SlideShare a Scribd company logo
1 of 9
Download to read offline
1
FERMAT’S LAST THEOREM PROVED BY INDUCTION
(accompanied by a philosophical comment)
Vasil Dinev Penchev,
Bulgarian Academy of Sciences: Institute for the Study of Societies and Knowledge:
Dept. of Logical Systems and Models
vasildinev@gmail.com
Abstract. A proof of Fermat’s last theorem is demonstrated. It is very brief, simple, elementary,
and absolutely arithmetical. The necessary premises for the proof are only: the three definitive
properties of the relation of equality (identity, symmetry, and transitivity), modus tollens, axiom
of induction, the proof of Fermat’s last theorem in the case of 𝑛𝑛 = 3 as well as the premises
necessary for the formulation of the theorem itself. It involves a modification of Fermat’s
approach of infinite descent. The infinite descent is linked to induction starting from 𝑛𝑛 = 3 by
modus tollens. An inductive series of modus tollens is constructed. The proof of the series by
induction is equivalent to Fermat’s last theorem. As far as Fermat had been proved the theorem
for 𝑛𝑛 = 4, one can suggest that the proof for 𝑛𝑛 ≥ 4 was accessible to him.
An idea for an elementary arithmetical proof of Fermat’s last theorem (FLT) by induction is
suggested. It would be accessible to Fermat unlike Wiles’s proof (1995), and would justify
Fermat’s claim (1637) for its proof. The inspiration for a simple proof would contradict to
Descartes’s dualism for appealing to merge “mind” and “body”, “words” and “things”, “terms” and
“propositions”, all orders of logic. A counterfactual course of history of mathematics and
philosophy may be admitted. The bifurcation happened in Descartes and Fermat’s age. FLT is
exceptionally difficult to be proved in our real branch rather than in the counterfactual one.
2
The theorem known as “Fermat’s last theorem” (FLT) was formulated by the French
mathematician in 1637 and proved by Andrew Wiles (1995). Fermat remained both its
statement and his claim for the proof “too long for the margin”. So, the challenge of a simple
proof accessible to Fermat is alive during centuries.
Andrew Wiles’s proof is too complicated. It is not only beyond arithmetic, but even the question
whether it is within set theory can be asked.
What follows is a simple and elementary proof by the axiom of induction applied to an
enumerated series of uniform recurrent arithmetical statements sharing the logical form of
modus tollens.
The necessary premises are only: the definition of equality in mathematics including the three
property: identity, symmetry, and transitivity; modus tollens; the axiom of induction, the proof of
FLT for 𝑛𝑛 = 3. All premises necessary for the theorem itself to be formulated should be added.
Thus, all Peano axioms of arithmetic are included. The set of all natural numbers, designated as
“N”, is the only set meant anywhere bellow. All variables (𝑥𝑥, 𝑦𝑦, 𝑧𝑧, 𝑤𝑤, 𝑛𝑛, 𝑎𝑎, 𝑏𝑏) and the constant “c”
are defined only on it: their values are its elements. However, the set “N” is not used. It is
utilized only for simplifying the notations.
The idea of proof is a modification of Fermat’s infinite descent, consisting in the following:
The modification is not directed to construct a false statement included in any proof by reductio
ad absurdum. Furthermore, it starts as if from infinity rather than from any finite natural number.
Anyway, the modification is able to be restricted only to arithmetic and the axiom of induction
(i.e. without the set-theory “actual infinity”) by means of an enumerated series of modus tollens.
Thus, Fermat’s infinite descent is seen and utilized as “reversed”: as an ascent by induction.
3
If one decomposes FLT to an enumerated series of statements, namely: FLT(3), FLT(4) FLT(5)
… FLT(n), FLT (n+1) , ..., the idea of the proof is:
∀(𝑥𝑥, 𝑦𝑦, 𝑧𝑧, 𝑛𝑛) 𝜖𝜖 𝑁𝑁: [(𝑎𝑎 = 𝑥𝑥 𝑛𝑛+1
) → (𝑏𝑏 = 𝑥𝑥 𝑛𝑛
)] ↔ [𝐹𝐹𝐹𝐹𝐹𝐹(𝑛𝑛) → 𝐹𝐹𝐹𝐹𝐹𝐹(𝑛𝑛 + 1)].
According to FLT, all FLT(n) are negative statements. If one considers the corresponding
positive statements, FLT*(n) = ¬FLT(n), the link to the series of modus tollens is obvious:
∀(𝑥𝑥, 𝑦𝑦, 𝑧𝑧, 𝑛𝑛)𝜖𝜖 𝑁𝑁: [(𝑎𝑎 = 𝑥𝑥 𝑛𝑛+1
) → (𝑏𝑏 = 𝑥𝑥 𝑛𝑛
) ↔ [¬FLT*(n) → ¬ FLT*(n+1)].
This is the core of proof. It needs a reflection even philosophical.
Two triple equalities ("𝑎𝑎 = 𝑥𝑥 𝑛𝑛+1
= 𝑦𝑦 𝑛𝑛+1
+ 𝑧𝑧 𝑛𝑛+1
”, and “𝑏𝑏 = 𝑥𝑥 𝑛𝑛
= 𝑦𝑦 𝑛𝑛
+ 𝑧𝑧 𝑛𝑛
”) are linked to each
other by modus tollens. What is valid for the left parts, (𝑎𝑎 = 𝑥𝑥 𝑛𝑛+1
) → (𝑏𝑏 = 𝑥𝑥 𝑛𝑛
), is transferred to
the right parts, ¬(𝑥𝑥 𝑛𝑛
= 𝑦𝑦 𝑛𝑛
+ 𝑧𝑧 𝑛𝑛
) → ¬(𝑥𝑥 𝑛𝑛+1
= 𝑦𝑦 𝑛𝑛+1
+ 𝑧𝑧 𝑛𝑛+1
), as an equivalence. The mediation of
each middle member in both triple equalities is crucial: it allows for the transition. An extended
description of “∀(𝑥𝑥, 𝑦𝑦, 𝑧𝑧, 𝑛𝑛)𝜖𝜖 𝑁𝑁: [(𝑎𝑎 = 𝑥𝑥 𝑛𝑛+1
) → (𝑏𝑏 = 𝑥𝑥 𝑛𝑛
) ↔ [¬FLT*(n) → ¬ FLT*(n+1)]” is:
∀(𝑥𝑥, 𝑦𝑦, 𝑧𝑧, 𝑛𝑛)𝜖𝜖 𝑁𝑁: [(𝑎𝑎 = 𝑥𝑥 𝑛𝑛+1
= 𝑦𝑦 𝑛𝑛+1
+ 𝑧𝑧 𝑛𝑛+1) → (𝑏𝑏 = 𝑥𝑥 𝑛𝑛
= 𝑦𝑦 𝑛𝑛
+ 𝑧𝑧 𝑛𝑛)] ↔
↔ [¬(𝑏𝑏 = 𝑥𝑥 𝑛𝑛
= 𝑦𝑦 𝑛𝑛
+ 𝑧𝑧 𝑛𝑛) → ¬(𝑎𝑎 = 𝑥𝑥 𝑛𝑛+1
= 𝑦𝑦 𝑛𝑛+1
+ 𝑧𝑧 𝑛𝑛+1)].
In fact, the equality (“=”) and logical equality “↔” are divided disjunctively. Their equivalence is
not necessary or used.
Anyway, their equivalence is valid as a mathematical isomorphism. Even more, the law of
identity in logic, “∀𝑎𝑎: 𝑎𝑎 ↔ 𝑎𝑎”, referring to the propositional logic, and the axiom of identity,
“∀𝑎𝑎: 𝑎𝑎 = 𝑎𝑎”, referring to any set of objects in a (first-order, second-order, …,
n-order, …) logic are isomorphic mathematically. The identity is a special kind of relation, in
which all orders are merged, and thus, indistinguishable from each other within it. Nonetheless,
any exemplification of that indistinguishability of identity due to mathematical isomorphism is not
used in the proof.
The proof in detail:
FLT: ∀(𝑥𝑥, 𝑦𝑦, 𝑧𝑧, 𝑛𝑛 ≥ 3) 𝜖𝜖 𝑁𝑁: ¬"𝑥𝑥 𝑛𝑛
= 𝑦𝑦 𝑛𝑛
+ 𝑧𝑧 𝑛𝑛
"
4
“FLT(c)” means: ¬"xc
=yc
+zc
" where “c” is a constant: 𝑐𝑐 ≥ 3, 𝑐𝑐 𝜖𝜖 𝑁𝑁. FLT will be proved as
FLT(c) will be proved for each “c” (∀𝑐𝑐) by induction. The equivalence of “FLT” and "∀c: FLT(c)”
is granted as obvious. The set of all “FLT(c)” is neither used nor involved in any way.
The relation of equality can be defined by its three properties: identity, symmetry, and
transitivity. They will be used to be proved a corollary from modus tollens, which is necessary to
be linked Fermat’s infinite descent to an inductive ascent.
Law (axiom) of identity [LI]: ∀𝐴𝐴: 𝐴𝐴 = 𝐴𝐴
It will be modified equivalently to “∀𝑥𝑥: 𝑥𝑥 ↔ 𝑥𝑥 = 𝑥𝑥” for the present utilization. Indeed:
∀𝑥𝑥: 𝑥𝑥 = 𝑥𝑥; ∀𝑥𝑥: 𝑥𝑥 → 𝑥𝑥; ∀𝑥𝑥: 𝑥𝑥 → 𝑥𝑥 = 𝑥𝑥; ∀𝑥𝑥: 𝑥𝑥 = 𝑥𝑥 → 𝑥𝑥; ∀𝑥𝑥: 𝑥𝑥 ↔ 𝑥𝑥 = 𝑥𝑥
Symmetry of equality [SE]: 𝐴𝐴 = 𝐵𝐵 ↔ 𝐵𝐵 = 𝐴𝐴.
It will be interpreted literally to the variables 𝑥𝑥, 𝑦𝑦, the values of which are elements of N.
∀𝑥𝑥, 𝑦𝑦: 𝑥𝑥 = 𝑦𝑦 ↔ 𝑦𝑦 = 𝑥𝑥
Transitivity of equality [TE]: 𝐴𝐴 = 𝐵𝐵 ∧ 𝐵𝐵 = 𝐶𝐶 ↔ 𝐴𝐴 = 𝐵𝐵 = 𝐶𝐶.
It will be interpreted literally to the variables 𝑥𝑥, 𝑦𝑦, 𝑧𝑧, the values of which are elements of N.
∀𝑥𝑥, 𝑦𝑦, 𝑧𝑧: [(𝑥𝑥 = 𝑦𝑦) ˄ (𝑦𝑦 = 𝑧𝑧)] ↔ (𝑥𝑥 = 𝑦𝑦 = 𝑧𝑧)
The definitive properties of the relation of equality imply: ∀𝑥𝑥, 𝑦𝑦: 𝑥𝑥 = (𝑥𝑥 = 𝑦𝑦). Indeed:
Let 𝑧𝑧 = 𝑥𝑥, then:
∀𝑥𝑥, 𝑦𝑦: [(𝑥𝑥 = 𝑦𝑦)˄ (𝑦𝑦 = 𝑥𝑥)] ↔ (𝑥𝑥 = 𝑦𝑦 = 𝑥𝑥) ↔ [𝑥𝑥 = (𝑦𝑦 = 𝑥𝑥)]
𝑆𝑆𝑆𝑆
↔ [𝑥𝑥 = (𝑥𝑥 = 𝑦𝑦)]
Modus tollens [MT]: (𝐴𝐴 → 𝐵𝐵) ↔ (¬𝐵𝐵 → ¬𝐴𝐴)
If one interprets MT as to the variables 𝑥𝑥, 𝑦𝑦, 𝑧𝑧, 𝑤𝑤 defined on N and means the proved statement
above (“∀𝑥𝑥, 𝑦𝑦: 𝑥𝑥 = (𝑥𝑥 = 𝑦𝑦)”) in order to substitute “𝑦𝑦” by “𝑦𝑦 = 𝑧𝑧” and “x” by “𝑥𝑥 = 𝑤𝑤”, the result is:
∀𝑥𝑥, 𝑦𝑦, 𝑧𝑧, 𝑤𝑤: [(𝑎𝑎 = 𝑥𝑥) → (𝑏𝑏 = 𝑦𝑦)] ↔ [¬(𝑦𝑦 = 𝑧𝑧) → ¬(𝑥𝑥 = 𝑤𝑤)]. Both “𝑎𝑎” and “𝑏𝑏” serve only to
transform the terms “𝑥𝑥” and “𝑦𝑦” into propositions and to allow for the implication. They mediate
5
and therefore divide disjunctively the equality of terms (“=”) from the logical equivalence of
propositions in modus tollens (“↔”).
Axiom of induction [AI]: ∀𝑝𝑝, 𝑛𝑛: 𝑝𝑝(1) ˄ [𝑝𝑝(𝑛𝑛) → 𝑝𝑝(𝑛𝑛 + 1)] → 𝑝𝑝 where “𝑝𝑝(𝑛𝑛)” is an arithmetical
proposition referring to the natural number “𝑛𝑛”, and “p” is the same proposition referring to all
natural numbers. “Arithmetical proposition” means a proposition in a first-order logic applied to
arithmetic. The axiom of induction is modified starting from 𝑛𝑛 = 3 rather than from 𝑛𝑛 = 1:
(∀𝑝𝑝, 𝑛𝑛: 𝑝𝑝(1) ˄ [𝑝𝑝(𝑛𝑛) → 𝑝𝑝(𝑛𝑛 + 1)] → 𝑝𝑝} → ∀𝑝𝑝, 𝑛𝑛 ≥ 3: 𝑝𝑝(3) ˄ [𝑝𝑝(𝑛𝑛) → 𝑝𝑝(𝑛𝑛 + 1)] → 𝑝𝑝
A modification of Fermat’s infinite descent [MFID]: MT modified as above is applied as starting
from 𝑛𝑛 = 3 as follows:
… 𝑛𝑛, 𝑛𝑛 − 1, … 5, 4, 3
The same descent is interpreted as a series of enumerated propositions:
… (𝑛𝑛), (𝑛𝑛 − 1), … (5), (4), (3)
A reverse chain of negations is implied:
¬(3), ¬(4), ¬(5), … , ¬(𝑛𝑛 − 1), ¬(𝑛𝑛), …
Both ascent of “negations” and infinite descent are constructed step by step following the
increasing number of the negative propositions (rather than the decreasing number of the
positive propositions):
[(4) → (3)] ↔ [¬(3) → ¬(4)], [(5) → (4)] ↔ [¬(4) → ¬(5)], [(6) → (5)] ↔ [¬(5) → ¬(6)], …
… [(𝑛𝑛 + 1) → (𝑛𝑛)] ↔ [¬(𝑛𝑛) → ¬(𝑛𝑛 + 1)], [(𝑛𝑛 + 2) → (𝑛𝑛 + 1)] ↔ [¬(𝑛𝑛 + 1) → ¬(𝑛𝑛 + 2)], … ….
So, one builds a series of modus tollens starting from 𝑛𝑛 = 3.
FLT(3): 𝑥𝑥, 𝑦𝑦, 𝑧𝑧 𝑎𝑎𝑎𝑎𝑎𝑎 𝑛𝑛𝑛𝑛𝑛𝑛𝑛𝑛𝑛𝑛𝑛𝑛𝑛𝑛 𝑛𝑛𝑛𝑛𝑛𝑛𝑛𝑛𝑛𝑛𝑛𝑛𝑛𝑛. 𝑇𝑇ℎ𝑒𝑒𝑒𝑒𝑒𝑒 𝑑𝑑𝑑𝑑 𝑛𝑛𝑛𝑛 𝑒𝑒𝑒𝑒𝑒𝑒𝑒𝑒𝑒𝑒 𝑎𝑎𝑎𝑎𝑎𝑎 𝑥𝑥, 𝑦𝑦, 𝑧𝑧:
𝑥𝑥3
+ 𝑦𝑦3
= 𝑧𝑧3
Many mathematicians beginning with Euler claimed its proof. Ernst Kummer’s proof (1847) will
be cited here for its absolute rigor. It refers to all cases of “regular prime numbers” defined by
Kummer, among which the case “𝑛𝑛 = 3” is.
Furthermore, the “n”-th member of the series of modus tollens, namely:
"[(𝑛𝑛 + 1) → (𝑛𝑛)] ↔ [¬(𝑛𝑛) → ¬(𝑛𝑛 + 1)]”, is valid as far as "(n+1)→(n)" is valid.
One interprets that "(n+1)→(n)" in the case of FLT:
∀𝑥𝑥, 𝑛𝑛: (𝑎𝑎 = 𝑥𝑥 𝑛𝑛+1
) → (𝑏𝑏 = 𝑥𝑥 𝑛𝑛
). This is true for 𝑥𝑥 𝑛𝑛+1
= 𝑥𝑥 𝑛𝑛
. 𝑥𝑥" . Thus, 𝑏𝑏 = 𝑥𝑥 𝑛𝑛
is a necessary
condition for 𝑎𝑎 = 𝑥𝑥 𝑛𝑛+1
and the former is implied by the latter. The expression "𝑥𝑥 𝑛𝑛+1
→ 𝑥𝑥 𝑛𝑛
" will
be used further as a brief notation for “∀𝑥𝑥, 𝑛𝑛: (𝑎𝑎 = 𝑥𝑥 𝑛𝑛+1
) → (𝑏𝑏 = 𝑥𝑥 𝑛𝑛
)” just as FLT(n) is a
corresponding brief notation.
6
The “a” and “b” transform the logical terms "𝑥𝑥 𝑛𝑛+1
" and “𝑥𝑥 𝑛𝑛
" into propositions correspondingly.
They serve to mediate between the relation of equality “=” referring to terms and the logical
equivalence “↔” referring to propositions therefore dividing them disjunctively.
The inspiration for the proof is the isomorphism of the law of identity in logic and the axiom of
identity in the definition of equality: “a” and “b” are necessary in order to remove that
isomorphism as a premise for the proof.
The series of modus tollens is interpreted in terms of FLT as the following series of implications:
[“𝑥𝑥4
→ 𝑥𝑥3
” ˄ “FLT(3)”] → “FLT(4)”; [“𝑥𝑥5
→ 𝑥𝑥4
” ˄ “FLT(4)”] → “FLT(5)”, [“𝑥𝑥6
→ 𝑥𝑥5
” ˄ “FLT(5)”] →
“FLT(6)”; … , [“𝑥𝑥 𝑛𝑛+1
→ 𝑥𝑥 𝑛𝑛
” ˄ “FLT(n)”] → “FLT(n+1)”; [“𝑥𝑥 𝑛𝑛+2
→ 𝑥𝑥 𝑛𝑛+1
” ˄ “FLT(n+1)”] → “FLT(n+2)”,
… …
The member of the series of implications is true for “n=3”, the validity for “n” implies the validity
for “n+1”. Thus, it is valid for “any member enumerated by a natural number greater than two” in
virtue of the axiom of induction.
FLT is proved.
If one accepts that Fermat (1670: 338-339) had proved FLT(4) and as far as the above proof
seems to be accessible to him, he might prove FLT for 𝑛𝑛 ≥ 4.
Literature:
Wiles, A. (1995) Modular Elliptic Curves and Fermat's Last Theorem. Annals of Mathematics,
Second Series, Vol. 141, No. 3 (May, 1995), pp. 443-55.
Kummer, E. (1847) Beweis des Fermat’schen Satzes der Unmöglichkeit von 𝑥𝑥 𝜆𝜆
+ 𝑦𝑦 𝜆𝜆
= 𝑧𝑧 𝜆𝜆
für
eine unendliche Anzahl Primzahlen λ. In: Kummer, Ernst Eduard. Collected papers (ed. Andre
Weil) Volume 1. Contributions to number theory. Berlin, Heidelberg, New York: Springer, 1975,
pp. 274-297.
Fermat, P. (1670) Diophanti Alexandrini Arithmeticorum libri sex, et De numeris multangulis liber
unus. Cum commentariis C.G. Bacheti v.c. & obseruationibus D.P. de Fermat .senatoris
Tolosani. Acessit Doctrinae analyticae inuentum nouum, collectum ex varijs eiusdem D. de
Fermat epistolis. Tolosae: Excudebat Bernardus Bosc, è regione Collegii Societatis lesu,
M. DC. LXX. (Source: http://books.google.com/books?id=yx9VIgeaCEYC&hl=&source=gbs_api
1670.)
7
A comment. The original proof of Fermat's las theorem: a philosophical reflection
Prehistory and background:
Fermat remained a statement (supposedly, in 1637) in the margin of his exemplar of Diophantus’s works
as well as the claim he had proved it, but the proof was too long to be recorded in the margin. The
statement is known as Fermat’s last theorem (FLT): the equation 𝑥𝑥 𝑛𝑛
+ 𝑦𝑦 𝑛𝑛
= 𝑧𝑧 𝑛𝑛
where x, y, z, n are
natural numbers does not have any solution for 𝑛𝑛 ≥ 3.
Fermat himself remained a proof for the case 𝑛𝑛 = 4. Euler proved it for 𝑛𝑛 = 3 in two different ways, but
both proofs met criticism. Gauss’s proof of the same particular case met criticism as well. Ernst
Kummer’s one (1847) refers to all “regular prime numbers” define by him, among which the case 𝑛𝑛 = 3
is. His proof is mathematically rigorous enough. The theorem has been proved for many particular cases
since then.
The statement in general was proved only in 1995 by Andrew Wiles as a corollary from the Taniyama-
Shimura-Weil conjecture known as the modularity theorem after his proof. It links the continuous (even
smooth) elliptic curves with the discrete modular forms. The proof is not arithmetical or accessible to
Fermat. It is even so complicated that the question whether it is within set theory rather than only
within arithmetic can be asked.
Anyway, Fermat’s challenge for an elementary arithmetical proof remains.
An idea for the inductive proof of FLT:
An idea for proving FLT might be the following. The statement is proved for 𝑛𝑛 = 3. If one proves that its
validity for 𝑛𝑛 implies its validity for 𝑛𝑛 + 1, the statement will be proved by virtue of the axiom of
induction in arithmetic, and thus: absolutely arithmetically.
Fermat’s “infinite descent” involving modus tollens might be modified for the purpose. The modification
would consists in the following. The infinite descent would not include in a reductio ad absurdum proof.
It would starts as if “from infinity” rather than from any finite natural number. The descent might be
transformed into a corresponding ascent, to which the axiom of induction would be applicable, by
means of modus tollens.
The inspiration of the inductive proof might be the mathematical isomorphism of the law of identity in
logic and the axiom of identity in the definition of the relation of equality axiomatically. It implies the
isomorphism of logical equivalence referring to propositions and the relation of equality referring to
objects or terms. Thus, identity in virtue of its definition is a special “singularity” where propositional
logic and any logic of an arbitrary order merge to each other.
The inspiration for merging can originate from a few philosophical doctrines such as Pythagoreanism,
Hegel’s panlogism, Husserl’s phenomenology, Heidegger’s doctrine(s). Furthermore, it can originate
from an experimental science such as quantum mechanics and its mathematical formalism grounded on
the separable complex Hilbert space.
However, it can originate from the absence or instability of Descartes’s dualism during Fermat’s life (as
far as he is almost Descartes’s contemporary). This together with some kind of naïve Pythagoreanism
admissible or even probable for a mathematician in number theory might inspire Fermat for a simple
arithmetical proof of FLT.
Fermat's accessibility to that kind of inductive proof:
The idea of inductive proof is relative to Fermat’s infinite descent. He himself had been prove FLT
8
for 𝑛𝑛 = 4. So, the conjecture that Fermat meant the proof for 𝑛𝑛 ≥ 4 is probable.
Furthermore, the one of Euler’s proof (the more correct one though containing gaps) was admissible to
Fermat at least in principle. So, the option for Fermat meant the case 𝑛𝑛 ≥ 3 might not be excluded
absolutely.
The meaning of identity in an eventual inductive proof:
The identity is able to inspire an elementary, simple, very brief, and absolutely arithmetical proof of FLT
by the method of mathematical induction. The philosophical essence of that identity is the identity of
anything (i.e. an object in any n-order logic) and the "word" designating the same thing (i.e. the
corresponding term in the (n-1)-order logic). In other words, this means the identity of any
mathematical structure and its interpretation of any kind. For example, meaning that identity, one
should erase the distinction between mathematical models and their material interpretation in physics.
The identity refers only to its scope: it does not imply mathematical models and their interpretations to
be identified at all. It states only the existence of a mathematical model identical to a given physical
system or vice versa: a given physical system identical to a given physical model.
This seems to be a philosophical postulate. On the contrary, Western philosophy (and particularly,
philosophy of science) as far as originates from Descartes's dualism postulates the opposite statement:
no mathematical model can be identical to the physical system interpreting it. Only a few, though the
most important, properties and relations of the system can be captured by the model, but there exist
always others, which are not, regardless of whether there exist property or relation of the system which
cannot be reflected in the model ever at all, in principle.
Thus, a difference whether absolute or historically relative justifies the distinction of "things" and
"words" in Western philosophy and philosophy of science. Its "blind spot" is all knowledge within the
opposite postulate allowing the identity of a mathematical model and a physical system. Thus, the
necessary inspiration for an elementary proof of FLT by induction turns out to be within the same 'blind
spot". The proof out of it, e.g. that of Andrew Wiles, is incredibly complicated, indirect, and mediated by
many, many chain links way to be seen the invisible being situated in the area corresponding to the
"blind spot". If one manages to reflect the existence of "blind spot", the change of position is much
simple as to observing what is located in the "blind spot" area. Abandoning the metaphor, this means to
be accepted the opposite postulate: mathematical model and reality can coincide and thus, be identical.
Once, that postulate is the case, the identity necessary for an elementary inductive proof of FLT is
admissible and the pathway to it is open. However, one can suggest that the actual pathway as a
"Wittgenstein ladder" might be removed in the final analysis. That is: the identity is necessary for the
inspiration to an elementary proof, but not within it actually, not within its text literally.
In facts, quantum mechanics was forced almost violently by the experimental results to see the area
corresponding to the "blind spot" of Western philosophy and science. The shocking theorems of the
"absence of hidden variables" in quantum mechanics were proved. They implied the absolute
coincidence of model and reality at least as to quantum mechanics, and thus, their identity.
Consequently, quantum mechanics might serve as an "inspiration" for an elementary, inductive proof of
FLT.
Identity in terms of Descartes's dualism:
However, Fermat's contemporary Descartes, his "older brother" by age, born, lived, and died about ten
years ago, ten years before Fermat, postulated the non-identity at issue by his doctrine of dualism.
9
Perhaps only God and belief might be the "key" to identity, otherwise inaccessible to human beings.
Thus, the direct pathway for an elementary inductive proof of FLT would turn out to be closed for
centuries, and a very, very round and indirect road would be walked exceptionally hard only at the end
of millennium by Andrew Wiles.
One can admit easily, that the direct pathway had not been closed ultimately in Fermat's age. So,
Fermat might prove his last theorem really, relying on that identity still possible and admissible in
science and mathematics.
Descartes remained his "analytic geometry" together with the "dualism": what is gapped in the latter is
linked in the former. Measuring the earth (i.e. "geometry") is identical to algebra generating
mathematical models only. Thus, a Foucault "episteme" of identities and distinctions has been
determined for centuries:
An identity (that of analytic geometry) has linked geometry to algebra and arithmetic, therefore
constituting mathematics. A distinction (that of dualism) has gapped mathematics from physics,
therefore constituting experimental science.
So, a plot about the “bystander – victim” Fermat, a "younger brother" of the “villain” Descartes can be
outlined. The original proof of FLT would be the symbol and title of that scenario.
Identity in terms of the modern western philosophy:
Descartes’s dualism underlay all Western philosophy after him. One of its main problems was how the
dualism might be overcome without God’s help. Kant’s transcendentalism and Hegel’s dialectic
panlogism can be considered as ones of the most successful solutions.
The fundamentally different is only Husserl’s phenomenology (as well as Heidegger’s doctrine(s)
influenced by it crucially). They considered the dualism as an axiom, and postulated its negation in their
doctrines.
Conclusion:
A counterfactual course of time in history of philosophy and in history of mathematics can be allowed.
The real branch of Descartes’s dualism and a lost original proof of FLT is ours. The counterfactual one
would suggest an elementary arithmetical proof and perhaps the absence of Descartes’s dualism and
the originating Western philosophy following it. The bifurcation happened in Descartes and Fermat’s
age.
One might attempt to write down those counterfactual histories of mathematics and philosophy.

More Related Content

What's hot

Recurrence relation of Bessel's and Legendre's function
Recurrence relation of Bessel's and Legendre's functionRecurrence relation of Bessel's and Legendre's function
Recurrence relation of Bessel's and Legendre's functionPartho Ghosh
 
Constraints on conformal field theories in d=3
Constraints on conformal field theories in d=3Constraints on conformal field theories in d=3
Constraints on conformal field theories in d=3Subham Dutta Chowdhury
 
It is known as two-valued logic because it have only two values
It is known as two-valued logic because it have only two values It is known as two-valued logic because it have only two values
It is known as two-valued logic because it have only two values Ramjeet Singh Yadav
 
Conformal field theories and three point functions
Conformal field theories and three point functionsConformal field theories and three point functions
Conformal field theories and three point functionsSubham Dutta Chowdhury
 
5.3 geometric sequences and sums
5.3 geometric sequences and sums5.3 geometric sequences and sums
5.3 geometric sequences and sumsmath260
 
Greek logic and mathematics
Greek logic and mathematicsGreek logic and mathematics
Greek logic and mathematicsBob Marcus
 
Geometric sequences
Geometric sequencesGeometric sequences
Geometric sequencesmooca76
 
Reading Testing a point-null hypothesis, by Jiahuan Li, Feb. 25, 2013
Reading Testing a point-null hypothesis, by Jiahuan Li, Feb. 25, 2013Reading Testing a point-null hypothesis, by Jiahuan Li, Feb. 25, 2013
Reading Testing a point-null hypothesis, by Jiahuan Li, Feb. 25, 2013Christian Robert
 
MAT-314 Relations and Functions
MAT-314 Relations and FunctionsMAT-314 Relations and Functions
MAT-314 Relations and FunctionsKevin Johnson
 
Introduction to Polynomial Functions
Introduction to Polynomial FunctionsIntroduction to Polynomial Functions
Introduction to Polynomial Functionskshoskey
 
13 1 arithmetic and geometric sequences
13 1 arithmetic and geometric sequences13 1 arithmetic and geometric sequences
13 1 arithmetic and geometric sequenceshisema01
 

What's hot (20)

Recurrence relation of Bessel's and Legendre's function
Recurrence relation of Bessel's and Legendre's functionRecurrence relation of Bessel's and Legendre's function
Recurrence relation of Bessel's and Legendre's function
 
Constraints on conformal field theories in d=3
Constraints on conformal field theories in d=3Constraints on conformal field theories in d=3
Constraints on conformal field theories in d=3
 
game (1)
game (1)game (1)
game (1)
 
MT102 Лекц 7
MT102 Лекц 7MT102 Лекц 7
MT102 Лекц 7
 
MT102 Лекц 15
MT102 Лекц 15MT102 Лекц 15
MT102 Лекц 15
 
It is known as two-valued logic because it have only two values
It is known as two-valued logic because it have only two values It is known as two-valued logic because it have only two values
It is known as two-valued logic because it have only two values
 
Conformal field theories and three point functions
Conformal field theories and three point functionsConformal field theories and three point functions
Conformal field theories and three point functions
 
Polynomials
PolynomialsPolynomials
Polynomials
 
5.3 geometric sequences and sums
5.3 geometric sequences and sums5.3 geometric sequences and sums
5.3 geometric sequences and sums
 
MT102 Лекц-2
MT102 Лекц-2MT102 Лекц-2
MT102 Лекц-2
 
Greek logic and mathematics
Greek logic and mathematicsGreek logic and mathematics
Greek logic and mathematics
 
Geometric sequences
Geometric sequencesGeometric sequences
Geometric sequences
 
Reading Testing a point-null hypothesis, by Jiahuan Li, Feb. 25, 2013
Reading Testing a point-null hypothesis, by Jiahuan Li, Feb. 25, 2013Reading Testing a point-null hypothesis, by Jiahuan Li, Feb. 25, 2013
Reading Testing a point-null hypothesis, by Jiahuan Li, Feb. 25, 2013
 
MT102 Лекц 10
MT102 Лекц 10MT102 Лекц 10
MT102 Лекц 10
 
MAT-314 Relations and Functions
MAT-314 Relations and FunctionsMAT-314 Relations and Functions
MAT-314 Relations and Functions
 
MT102 Лекц 13
MT102 Лекц 13MT102 Лекц 13
MT102 Лекц 13
 
Introduction to Polynomial Functions
Introduction to Polynomial FunctionsIntroduction to Polynomial Functions
Introduction to Polynomial Functions
 
MT102 Лекц 16
MT102 Лекц 16MT102 Лекц 16
MT102 Лекц 16
 
13 1 arithmetic and geometric sequences
13 1 arithmetic and geometric sequences13 1 arithmetic and geometric sequences
13 1 arithmetic and geometric sequences
 
MT102 Лекц 11
MT102 Лекц 11MT102 Лекц 11
MT102 Лекц 11
 

Similar to FERMAT’S LAST THEOREM PROVED BY INDUCTION (accompanied by a philosophical comment)

A disproof of the Riemann hypothesis
A disproof of the Riemann hypothesisA disproof of the Riemann hypothesis
A disproof of the Riemann hypothesisiosrjce
 
A Probabilistic Algorithm for Computation of Polynomial Greatest Common with ...
A Probabilistic Algorithm for Computation of Polynomial Greatest Common with ...A Probabilistic Algorithm for Computation of Polynomial Greatest Common with ...
A Probabilistic Algorithm for Computation of Polynomial Greatest Common with ...mathsjournal
 
Matrix Transformations on Paranormed Sequence Spaces Related To De La Vallée-...
Matrix Transformations on Paranormed Sequence Spaces Related To De La Vallée-...Matrix Transformations on Paranormed Sequence Spaces Related To De La Vallée-...
Matrix Transformations on Paranormed Sequence Spaces Related To De La Vallée-...inventionjournals
 
Section 9: Equivalence Relations & Cosets
Section 9: Equivalence Relations & CosetsSection 9: Equivalence Relations & Cosets
Section 9: Equivalence Relations & CosetsKevin Johnson
 
Chapter 2 Mathematical Language and Symbols.pdf
Chapter 2 Mathematical Language and Symbols.pdfChapter 2 Mathematical Language and Symbols.pdf
Chapter 2 Mathematical Language and Symbols.pdfRaRaRamirez
 
Lecture 1.2 quadratic functions
Lecture 1.2 quadratic functionsLecture 1.2 quadratic functions
Lecture 1.2 quadratic functionsnarayana dash
 
New Information on the Generalized Euler-Tricomi Equation
New Information on the Generalized Euler-Tricomi Equation New Information on the Generalized Euler-Tricomi Equation
New Information on the Generalized Euler-Tricomi Equation Lossian Barbosa Bacelar Miranda
 
published journals
published journalspublished journals
published journalshrithiksai2
 
journalism journals
journalism journalsjournalism journals
journalism journalsrikaseorika
 
journals to publish paper
journals to publish paperjournals to publish paper
journals to publish paperrikaseorika
 
Machine learning (9)
Machine learning (9)Machine learning (9)
Machine learning (9)NYversity
 
DIGITAL TEXT BOOK
DIGITAL TEXT BOOKDIGITAL TEXT BOOK
DIGITAL TEXT BOOKbintu55
 
Optimal Estimating Sequence for a Hilbert Space Valued Parameter
Optimal Estimating Sequence for a Hilbert Space Valued ParameterOptimal Estimating Sequence for a Hilbert Space Valued Parameter
Optimal Estimating Sequence for a Hilbert Space Valued ParameterIOSR Journals
 
Jensen's inequality, EM 알고리즘
Jensen's inequality, EM 알고리즘 Jensen's inequality, EM 알고리즘
Jensen's inequality, EM 알고리즘 Jungkyu Lee
 
Sistemas de ecuaciones lineales
Sistemas de ecuaciones linealesSistemas de ecuaciones lineales
Sistemas de ecuaciones linealesRokiFernandez1
 
Sequences 01
Sequences 01Sequences 01
Sequences 01kmfob
 

Similar to FERMAT’S LAST THEOREM PROVED BY INDUCTION (accompanied by a philosophical comment) (20)

A disproof of the Riemann hypothesis
A disproof of the Riemann hypothesisA disproof of the Riemann hypothesis
A disproof of the Riemann hypothesis
 
A Probabilistic Algorithm for Computation of Polynomial Greatest Common with ...
A Probabilistic Algorithm for Computation of Polynomial Greatest Common with ...A Probabilistic Algorithm for Computation of Polynomial Greatest Common with ...
A Probabilistic Algorithm for Computation of Polynomial Greatest Common with ...
 
Matrix Transformations on Paranormed Sequence Spaces Related To De La Vallée-...
Matrix Transformations on Paranormed Sequence Spaces Related To De La Vallée-...Matrix Transformations on Paranormed Sequence Spaces Related To De La Vallée-...
Matrix Transformations on Paranormed Sequence Spaces Related To De La Vallée-...
 
lec13.ppt
lec13.pptlec13.ppt
lec13.ppt
 
Section 9: Equivalence Relations & Cosets
Section 9: Equivalence Relations & CosetsSection 9: Equivalence Relations & Cosets
Section 9: Equivalence Relations & Cosets
 
Chapter 2 Mathematical Language and Symbols.pdf
Chapter 2 Mathematical Language and Symbols.pdfChapter 2 Mathematical Language and Symbols.pdf
Chapter 2 Mathematical Language and Symbols.pdf
 
Euler-Fermat theorem.pptx
Euler-Fermat theorem.pptxEuler-Fermat theorem.pptx
Euler-Fermat theorem.pptx
 
Lecture 1.2 quadratic functions
Lecture 1.2 quadratic functionsLecture 1.2 quadratic functions
Lecture 1.2 quadratic functions
 
New Information on the Generalized Euler-Tricomi Equation
New Information on the Generalized Euler-Tricomi Equation New Information on the Generalized Euler-Tricomi Equation
New Information on the Generalized Euler-Tricomi Equation
 
published journals
published journalspublished journals
published journals
 
journalism journals
journalism journalsjournalism journals
journalism journals
 
journals to publish paper
journals to publish paperjournals to publish paper
journals to publish paper
 
Machine learning (9)
Machine learning (9)Machine learning (9)
Machine learning (9)
 
5. Rania.pdf
5. Rania.pdf5. Rania.pdf
5. Rania.pdf
 
5. Rania.pdf
5. Rania.pdf5. Rania.pdf
5. Rania.pdf
 
DIGITAL TEXT BOOK
DIGITAL TEXT BOOKDIGITAL TEXT BOOK
DIGITAL TEXT BOOK
 
Optimal Estimating Sequence for a Hilbert Space Valued Parameter
Optimal Estimating Sequence for a Hilbert Space Valued ParameterOptimal Estimating Sequence for a Hilbert Space Valued Parameter
Optimal Estimating Sequence for a Hilbert Space Valued Parameter
 
Jensen's inequality, EM 알고리즘
Jensen's inequality, EM 알고리즘 Jensen's inequality, EM 알고리즘
Jensen's inequality, EM 알고리즘
 
Sistemas de ecuaciones lineales
Sistemas de ecuaciones linealesSistemas de ecuaciones lineales
Sistemas de ecuaciones lineales
 
Sequences 01
Sequences 01Sequences 01
Sequences 01
 

More from Vasil Penchev

The generalization of the Periodic table. The "Periodic table" of "dark matter"
The generalization of the Periodic table. The "Periodic table" of "dark matter"The generalization of the Periodic table. The "Periodic table" of "dark matter"
The generalization of the Periodic table. The "Periodic table" of "dark matter"Vasil Penchev
 
Modal History versus Counterfactual History: History as Intention
Modal History versus Counterfactual History: History as IntentionModal History versus Counterfactual History: History as Intention
Modal History versus Counterfactual History: History as IntentionVasil Penchev
 
Both classical and quantum information [autosaved]
Both classical and quantum information [autosaved]Both classical and quantum information [autosaved]
Both classical and quantum information [autosaved]Vasil Penchev
 
A CLASS OF EXEMPLES DEMONSTRATING THAT “푃푃≠푁푁푁 ” IN THE “P VS NP” PROBLEM
A CLASS OF EXEMPLES DEMONSTRATING THAT “푃푃≠푁푁푁 ” IN THE “P VS NP” PROBLEMA CLASS OF EXEMPLES DEMONSTRATING THAT “푃푃≠푁푁푁 ” IN THE “P VS NP” PROBLEM
A CLASS OF EXEMPLES DEMONSTRATING THAT “푃푃≠푁푁푁 ” IN THE “P VS NP” PROBLEMVasil Penchev
 
The space-time interpretation of Poincare’s conjecture proved by G. Perelman
The space-time interpretation of Poincare’s conjecture proved by G. Perelman The space-time interpretation of Poincare’s conjecture proved by G. Perelman
The space-time interpretation of Poincare’s conjecture proved by G. Perelman Vasil Penchev
 
FROM THE PRINCIPLE OF LEAST ACTION TO THE CONSERVATION OF QUANTUM INFORMATION...
FROM THE PRINCIPLE OF LEAST ACTION TO THE CONSERVATION OF QUANTUM INFORMATION...FROM THE PRINCIPLE OF LEAST ACTION TO THE CONSERVATION OF QUANTUM INFORMATION...
FROM THE PRINCIPLE OF LEAST ACTION TO THE CONSERVATION OF QUANTUM INFORMATION...Vasil Penchev
 
From the principle of least action to the conservation of quantum information...
From the principle of least action to the conservation of quantum information...From the principle of least action to the conservation of quantum information...
From the principle of least action to the conservation of quantum information...Vasil Penchev
 
Poincaré’s conjecture proved by G. Perelman by the isomorphism of Minkowski s...
Poincaré’s conjecture proved by G. Perelman by the isomorphism of Minkowski s...Poincaré’s conjecture proved by G. Perelman by the isomorphism of Minkowski s...
Poincaré’s conjecture proved by G. Perelman by the isomorphism of Minkowski s...Vasil Penchev
 
Why anything rather than nothing? The answer of quantum mechnaics
Why anything rather than nothing? The answer of quantum mechnaicsWhy anything rather than nothing? The answer of quantum mechnaics
Why anything rather than nothing? The answer of quantum mechnaicsVasil Penchev
 
The Square of Opposition & The Concept of Infinity: The shared information s...
The Square of Opposition &  The Concept of Infinity: The shared information s...The Square of Opposition &  The Concept of Infinity: The shared information s...
The Square of Opposition & The Concept of Infinity: The shared information s...Vasil Penchev
 
Mamardashvili, an Observer of the Totality. About “Symbol and Consciousness”,...
Mamardashvili, an Observer of the Totality. About “Symbol and Consciousness”,...Mamardashvili, an Observer of the Totality. About “Symbol and Consciousness”,...
Mamardashvili, an Observer of the Totality. About “Symbol and Consciousness”,...Vasil Penchev
 
Completeness: From henkin's Proposition to Quantum Computer
Completeness: From henkin's Proposition to Quantum ComputerCompleteness: From henkin's Proposition to Quantum Computer
Completeness: From henkin's Proposition to Quantum ComputerVasil Penchev
 
Why anything rather than nothing? The answer of quantum mechanics
Why anything rather than nothing? The answer of quantum mechanicsWhy anything rather than nothing? The answer of quantum mechanics
Why anything rather than nothing? The answer of quantum mechanicsVasil Penchev
 
Metaphor as entanglement
Metaphor as entanglementMetaphor as entanglement
Metaphor as entanglementVasil Penchev
 
Hilbert Space and pseudo-Riemannian Space: The Common Base of Quantum Informa...
Hilbert Space and pseudo-Riemannian Space: The Common Base of Quantum Informa...Hilbert Space and pseudo-Riemannian Space: The Common Base of Quantum Informa...
Hilbert Space and pseudo-Riemannian Space: The Common Base of Quantum Informa...Vasil Penchev
 
The formalized hodological methodology
The formalized hodological methodologyThe formalized hodological methodology
The formalized hodological methodologyVasil Penchev
 
The post-secular convergence of science and religion (a philosophical prognosis)
The post-secular convergence of science and religion (a philosophical prognosis)The post-secular convergence of science and religion (a philosophical prognosis)
The post-secular convergence of science and religion (a philosophical prognosis)Vasil Penchev
 
Analogia entis as analogy universalized and formalized rigorously and mathema...
Analogia entis as analogy universalized and formalized rigorously and mathema...Analogia entis as analogy universalized and formalized rigorously and mathema...
Analogia entis as analogy universalized and formalized rigorously and mathema...Vasil Penchev
 
Ontology as a formal one. The language of ontology as the ontology itself: th...
Ontology as a formal one. The language of ontology as the ontology itself: th...Ontology as a formal one. The language of ontology as the ontology itself: th...
Ontology as a formal one. The language of ontology as the ontology itself: th...Vasil Penchev
 

More from Vasil Penchev (20)

The generalization of the Periodic table. The "Periodic table" of "dark matter"
The generalization of the Periodic table. The "Periodic table" of "dark matter"The generalization of the Periodic table. The "Periodic table" of "dark matter"
The generalization of the Periodic table. The "Periodic table" of "dark matter"
 
Modal History versus Counterfactual History: History as Intention
Modal History versus Counterfactual History: History as IntentionModal History versus Counterfactual History: History as Intention
Modal History versus Counterfactual History: History as Intention
 
Both classical and quantum information [autosaved]
Both classical and quantum information [autosaved]Both classical and quantum information [autosaved]
Both classical and quantum information [autosaved]
 
A CLASS OF EXEMPLES DEMONSTRATING THAT “푃푃≠푁푁푁 ” IN THE “P VS NP” PROBLEM
A CLASS OF EXEMPLES DEMONSTRATING THAT “푃푃≠푁푁푁 ” IN THE “P VS NP” PROBLEMA CLASS OF EXEMPLES DEMONSTRATING THAT “푃푃≠푁푁푁 ” IN THE “P VS NP” PROBLEM
A CLASS OF EXEMPLES DEMONSTRATING THAT “푃푃≠푁푁푁 ” IN THE “P VS NP” PROBLEM
 
The space-time interpretation of Poincare’s conjecture proved by G. Perelman
The space-time interpretation of Poincare’s conjecture proved by G. Perelman The space-time interpretation of Poincare’s conjecture proved by G. Perelman
The space-time interpretation of Poincare’s conjecture proved by G. Perelman
 
FROM THE PRINCIPLE OF LEAST ACTION TO THE CONSERVATION OF QUANTUM INFORMATION...
FROM THE PRINCIPLE OF LEAST ACTION TO THE CONSERVATION OF QUANTUM INFORMATION...FROM THE PRINCIPLE OF LEAST ACTION TO THE CONSERVATION OF QUANTUM INFORMATION...
FROM THE PRINCIPLE OF LEAST ACTION TO THE CONSERVATION OF QUANTUM INFORMATION...
 
From the principle of least action to the conservation of quantum information...
From the principle of least action to the conservation of quantum information...From the principle of least action to the conservation of quantum information...
From the principle of least action to the conservation of quantum information...
 
Poincaré’s conjecture proved by G. Perelman by the isomorphism of Minkowski s...
Poincaré’s conjecture proved by G. Perelman by the isomorphism of Minkowski s...Poincaré’s conjecture proved by G. Perelman by the isomorphism of Minkowski s...
Poincaré’s conjecture proved by G. Perelman by the isomorphism of Minkowski s...
 
Why anything rather than nothing? The answer of quantum mechnaics
Why anything rather than nothing? The answer of quantum mechnaicsWhy anything rather than nothing? The answer of quantum mechnaics
Why anything rather than nothing? The answer of quantum mechnaics
 
The Square of Opposition & The Concept of Infinity: The shared information s...
The Square of Opposition &  The Concept of Infinity: The shared information s...The Square of Opposition &  The Concept of Infinity: The shared information s...
The Square of Opposition & The Concept of Infinity: The shared information s...
 
Mamardashvili, an Observer of the Totality. About “Symbol and Consciousness”,...
Mamardashvili, an Observer of the Totality. About “Symbol and Consciousness”,...Mamardashvili, an Observer of the Totality. About “Symbol and Consciousness”,...
Mamardashvili, an Observer of the Totality. About “Symbol and Consciousness”,...
 
Completeness: From henkin's Proposition to Quantum Computer
Completeness: From henkin's Proposition to Quantum ComputerCompleteness: From henkin's Proposition to Quantum Computer
Completeness: From henkin's Proposition to Quantum Computer
 
Why anything rather than nothing? The answer of quantum mechanics
Why anything rather than nothing? The answer of quantum mechanicsWhy anything rather than nothing? The answer of quantum mechanics
Why anything rather than nothing? The answer of quantum mechanics
 
Metaphor as entanglement
Metaphor as entanglementMetaphor as entanglement
Metaphor as entanglement
 
Hilbert Space and pseudo-Riemannian Space: The Common Base of Quantum Informa...
Hilbert Space and pseudo-Riemannian Space: The Common Base of Quantum Informa...Hilbert Space and pseudo-Riemannian Space: The Common Base of Quantum Informa...
Hilbert Space and pseudo-Riemannian Space: The Common Base of Quantum Informa...
 
The formalized hodological methodology
The formalized hodological methodologyThe formalized hodological methodology
The formalized hodological methodology
 
The post-secular convergence of science and religion (a philosophical prognosis)
The post-secular convergence of science and religion (a philosophical prognosis)The post-secular convergence of science and religion (a philosophical prognosis)
The post-secular convergence of science and religion (a philosophical prognosis)
 
Has AI a soul?
Has AI a soul?Has AI a soul?
Has AI a soul?
 
Analogia entis as analogy universalized and formalized rigorously and mathema...
Analogia entis as analogy universalized and formalized rigorously and mathema...Analogia entis as analogy universalized and formalized rigorously and mathema...
Analogia entis as analogy universalized and formalized rigorously and mathema...
 
Ontology as a formal one. The language of ontology as the ontology itself: th...
Ontology as a formal one. The language of ontology as the ontology itself: th...Ontology as a formal one. The language of ontology as the ontology itself: th...
Ontology as a formal one. The language of ontology as the ontology itself: th...
 

Recently uploaded

Scheme-of-Work-Science-Stage-4 cambridge science.docx
Scheme-of-Work-Science-Stage-4 cambridge science.docxScheme-of-Work-Science-Stage-4 cambridge science.docx
Scheme-of-Work-Science-Stage-4 cambridge science.docxyaramohamed343013
 
Behavioral Disorder: Schizophrenia & it's Case Study.pdf
Behavioral Disorder: Schizophrenia & it's Case Study.pdfBehavioral Disorder: Schizophrenia & it's Case Study.pdf
Behavioral Disorder: Schizophrenia & it's Case Study.pdfSELF-EXPLANATORY
 
Environmental Biotechnology Topic:- Microbial Biosensor
Environmental Biotechnology Topic:- Microbial BiosensorEnvironmental Biotechnology Topic:- Microbial Biosensor
Environmental Biotechnology Topic:- Microbial Biosensorsonawaneprad
 
Artificial Intelligence In Microbiology by Dr. Prince C P
Artificial Intelligence In Microbiology by Dr. Prince C PArtificial Intelligence In Microbiology by Dr. Prince C P
Artificial Intelligence In Microbiology by Dr. Prince C PPRINCE C P
 
Harmful and Useful Microorganisms Presentation
Harmful and Useful Microorganisms PresentationHarmful and Useful Microorganisms Presentation
Harmful and Useful Microorganisms Presentationtahreemzahra82
 
‏‏VIRUS - 123455555555555555555555555555555555555555
‏‏VIRUS -  123455555555555555555555555555555555555555‏‏VIRUS -  123455555555555555555555555555555555555555
‏‏VIRUS - 123455555555555555555555555555555555555555kikilily0909
 
RESPIRATORY ADAPTATIONS TO HYPOXIA IN HUMNAS.pptx
RESPIRATORY ADAPTATIONS TO HYPOXIA IN HUMNAS.pptxRESPIRATORY ADAPTATIONS TO HYPOXIA IN HUMNAS.pptx
RESPIRATORY ADAPTATIONS TO HYPOXIA IN HUMNAS.pptxFarihaAbdulRasheed
 
Evidences of Evolution General Biology 2
Evidences of Evolution General Biology 2Evidences of Evolution General Biology 2
Evidences of Evolution General Biology 2John Carlo Rollon
 
Bentham & Hooker's Classification. along with the merits and demerits of the ...
Bentham & Hooker's Classification. along with the merits and demerits of the ...Bentham & Hooker's Classification. along with the merits and demerits of the ...
Bentham & Hooker's Classification. along with the merits and demerits of the ...Nistarini College, Purulia (W.B) India
 
The dark energy paradox leads to a new structure of spacetime.pptx
The dark energy paradox leads to a new structure of spacetime.pptxThe dark energy paradox leads to a new structure of spacetime.pptx
The dark energy paradox leads to a new structure of spacetime.pptxEran Akiva Sinbar
 
Call Girls In Nihal Vihar Delhi ❤️8860477959 Looking Escorts In 24/7 Delhi NCR
Call Girls In Nihal Vihar Delhi ❤️8860477959 Looking Escorts In 24/7 Delhi NCRCall Girls In Nihal Vihar Delhi ❤️8860477959 Looking Escorts In 24/7 Delhi NCR
Call Girls In Nihal Vihar Delhi ❤️8860477959 Looking Escorts In 24/7 Delhi NCRlizamodels9
 
FREE NURSING BUNDLE FOR NURSES.PDF by na
FREE NURSING BUNDLE FOR NURSES.PDF by naFREE NURSING BUNDLE FOR NURSES.PDF by na
FREE NURSING BUNDLE FOR NURSES.PDF by naJASISJULIANOELYNV
 
Call Us ≽ 9953322196 ≼ Call Girls In Lajpat Nagar (Delhi) |
Call Us ≽ 9953322196 ≼ Call Girls In Lajpat Nagar (Delhi) |Call Us ≽ 9953322196 ≼ Call Girls In Lajpat Nagar (Delhi) |
Call Us ≽ 9953322196 ≼ Call Girls In Lajpat Nagar (Delhi) |aasikanpl
 
Pests of jatropha_Bionomics_identification_Dr.UPR.pdf
Pests of jatropha_Bionomics_identification_Dr.UPR.pdfPests of jatropha_Bionomics_identification_Dr.UPR.pdf
Pests of jatropha_Bionomics_identification_Dr.UPR.pdfPirithiRaju
 
zoogeography of pakistan.pptx fauna of Pakistan
zoogeography of pakistan.pptx fauna of Pakistanzoogeography of pakistan.pptx fauna of Pakistan
zoogeography of pakistan.pptx fauna of Pakistanzohaibmir069
 
THE ROLE OF PHARMACOGNOSY IN TRADITIONAL AND MODERN SYSTEM OF MEDICINE.pptx
THE ROLE OF PHARMACOGNOSY IN TRADITIONAL AND MODERN SYSTEM OF MEDICINE.pptxTHE ROLE OF PHARMACOGNOSY IN TRADITIONAL AND MODERN SYSTEM OF MEDICINE.pptx
THE ROLE OF PHARMACOGNOSY IN TRADITIONAL AND MODERN SYSTEM OF MEDICINE.pptxNandakishor Bhaurao Deshmukh
 
Call Girls in Mayapuri Delhi 💯Call Us 🔝9953322196🔝 💯Escort.
Call Girls in Mayapuri Delhi 💯Call Us 🔝9953322196🔝 💯Escort.Call Girls in Mayapuri Delhi 💯Call Us 🔝9953322196🔝 💯Escort.
Call Girls in Mayapuri Delhi 💯Call Us 🔝9953322196🔝 💯Escort.aasikanpl
 
Recombinant DNA technology( Transgenic plant and animal)
Recombinant DNA technology( Transgenic plant and animal)Recombinant DNA technology( Transgenic plant and animal)
Recombinant DNA technology( Transgenic plant and animal)DHURKADEVIBASKAR
 
Solution chemistry, Moral and Normal solutions
Solution chemistry, Moral and Normal solutionsSolution chemistry, Moral and Normal solutions
Solution chemistry, Moral and Normal solutionsHajira Mahmood
 
Grafana in space: Monitoring Japan's SLIM moon lander in real time
Grafana in space: Monitoring Japan's SLIM moon lander  in real timeGrafana in space: Monitoring Japan's SLIM moon lander  in real time
Grafana in space: Monitoring Japan's SLIM moon lander in real timeSatoshi NAKAHIRA
 

Recently uploaded (20)

Scheme-of-Work-Science-Stage-4 cambridge science.docx
Scheme-of-Work-Science-Stage-4 cambridge science.docxScheme-of-Work-Science-Stage-4 cambridge science.docx
Scheme-of-Work-Science-Stage-4 cambridge science.docx
 
Behavioral Disorder: Schizophrenia & it's Case Study.pdf
Behavioral Disorder: Schizophrenia & it's Case Study.pdfBehavioral Disorder: Schizophrenia & it's Case Study.pdf
Behavioral Disorder: Schizophrenia & it's Case Study.pdf
 
Environmental Biotechnology Topic:- Microbial Biosensor
Environmental Biotechnology Topic:- Microbial BiosensorEnvironmental Biotechnology Topic:- Microbial Biosensor
Environmental Biotechnology Topic:- Microbial Biosensor
 
Artificial Intelligence In Microbiology by Dr. Prince C P
Artificial Intelligence In Microbiology by Dr. Prince C PArtificial Intelligence In Microbiology by Dr. Prince C P
Artificial Intelligence In Microbiology by Dr. Prince C P
 
Harmful and Useful Microorganisms Presentation
Harmful and Useful Microorganisms PresentationHarmful and Useful Microorganisms Presentation
Harmful and Useful Microorganisms Presentation
 
‏‏VIRUS - 123455555555555555555555555555555555555555
‏‏VIRUS -  123455555555555555555555555555555555555555‏‏VIRUS -  123455555555555555555555555555555555555555
‏‏VIRUS - 123455555555555555555555555555555555555555
 
RESPIRATORY ADAPTATIONS TO HYPOXIA IN HUMNAS.pptx
RESPIRATORY ADAPTATIONS TO HYPOXIA IN HUMNAS.pptxRESPIRATORY ADAPTATIONS TO HYPOXIA IN HUMNAS.pptx
RESPIRATORY ADAPTATIONS TO HYPOXIA IN HUMNAS.pptx
 
Evidences of Evolution General Biology 2
Evidences of Evolution General Biology 2Evidences of Evolution General Biology 2
Evidences of Evolution General Biology 2
 
Bentham & Hooker's Classification. along with the merits and demerits of the ...
Bentham & Hooker's Classification. along with the merits and demerits of the ...Bentham & Hooker's Classification. along with the merits and demerits of the ...
Bentham & Hooker's Classification. along with the merits and demerits of the ...
 
The dark energy paradox leads to a new structure of spacetime.pptx
The dark energy paradox leads to a new structure of spacetime.pptxThe dark energy paradox leads to a new structure of spacetime.pptx
The dark energy paradox leads to a new structure of spacetime.pptx
 
Call Girls In Nihal Vihar Delhi ❤️8860477959 Looking Escorts In 24/7 Delhi NCR
Call Girls In Nihal Vihar Delhi ❤️8860477959 Looking Escorts In 24/7 Delhi NCRCall Girls In Nihal Vihar Delhi ❤️8860477959 Looking Escorts In 24/7 Delhi NCR
Call Girls In Nihal Vihar Delhi ❤️8860477959 Looking Escorts In 24/7 Delhi NCR
 
FREE NURSING BUNDLE FOR NURSES.PDF by na
FREE NURSING BUNDLE FOR NURSES.PDF by naFREE NURSING BUNDLE FOR NURSES.PDF by na
FREE NURSING BUNDLE FOR NURSES.PDF by na
 
Call Us ≽ 9953322196 ≼ Call Girls In Lajpat Nagar (Delhi) |
Call Us ≽ 9953322196 ≼ Call Girls In Lajpat Nagar (Delhi) |Call Us ≽ 9953322196 ≼ Call Girls In Lajpat Nagar (Delhi) |
Call Us ≽ 9953322196 ≼ Call Girls In Lajpat Nagar (Delhi) |
 
Pests of jatropha_Bionomics_identification_Dr.UPR.pdf
Pests of jatropha_Bionomics_identification_Dr.UPR.pdfPests of jatropha_Bionomics_identification_Dr.UPR.pdf
Pests of jatropha_Bionomics_identification_Dr.UPR.pdf
 
zoogeography of pakistan.pptx fauna of Pakistan
zoogeography of pakistan.pptx fauna of Pakistanzoogeography of pakistan.pptx fauna of Pakistan
zoogeography of pakistan.pptx fauna of Pakistan
 
THE ROLE OF PHARMACOGNOSY IN TRADITIONAL AND MODERN SYSTEM OF MEDICINE.pptx
THE ROLE OF PHARMACOGNOSY IN TRADITIONAL AND MODERN SYSTEM OF MEDICINE.pptxTHE ROLE OF PHARMACOGNOSY IN TRADITIONAL AND MODERN SYSTEM OF MEDICINE.pptx
THE ROLE OF PHARMACOGNOSY IN TRADITIONAL AND MODERN SYSTEM OF MEDICINE.pptx
 
Call Girls in Mayapuri Delhi 💯Call Us 🔝9953322196🔝 💯Escort.
Call Girls in Mayapuri Delhi 💯Call Us 🔝9953322196🔝 💯Escort.Call Girls in Mayapuri Delhi 💯Call Us 🔝9953322196🔝 💯Escort.
Call Girls in Mayapuri Delhi 💯Call Us 🔝9953322196🔝 💯Escort.
 
Recombinant DNA technology( Transgenic plant and animal)
Recombinant DNA technology( Transgenic plant and animal)Recombinant DNA technology( Transgenic plant and animal)
Recombinant DNA technology( Transgenic plant and animal)
 
Solution chemistry, Moral and Normal solutions
Solution chemistry, Moral and Normal solutionsSolution chemistry, Moral and Normal solutions
Solution chemistry, Moral and Normal solutions
 
Grafana in space: Monitoring Japan's SLIM moon lander in real time
Grafana in space: Monitoring Japan's SLIM moon lander  in real timeGrafana in space: Monitoring Japan's SLIM moon lander  in real time
Grafana in space: Monitoring Japan's SLIM moon lander in real time
 

FERMAT’S LAST THEOREM PROVED BY INDUCTION (accompanied by a philosophical comment)

  • 1. 1 FERMAT’S LAST THEOREM PROVED BY INDUCTION (accompanied by a philosophical comment) Vasil Dinev Penchev, Bulgarian Academy of Sciences: Institute for the Study of Societies and Knowledge: Dept. of Logical Systems and Models vasildinev@gmail.com Abstract. A proof of Fermat’s last theorem is demonstrated. It is very brief, simple, elementary, and absolutely arithmetical. The necessary premises for the proof are only: the three definitive properties of the relation of equality (identity, symmetry, and transitivity), modus tollens, axiom of induction, the proof of Fermat’s last theorem in the case of 𝑛𝑛 = 3 as well as the premises necessary for the formulation of the theorem itself. It involves a modification of Fermat’s approach of infinite descent. The infinite descent is linked to induction starting from 𝑛𝑛 = 3 by modus tollens. An inductive series of modus tollens is constructed. The proof of the series by induction is equivalent to Fermat’s last theorem. As far as Fermat had been proved the theorem for 𝑛𝑛 = 4, one can suggest that the proof for 𝑛𝑛 ≥ 4 was accessible to him. An idea for an elementary arithmetical proof of Fermat’s last theorem (FLT) by induction is suggested. It would be accessible to Fermat unlike Wiles’s proof (1995), and would justify Fermat’s claim (1637) for its proof. The inspiration for a simple proof would contradict to Descartes’s dualism for appealing to merge “mind” and “body”, “words” and “things”, “terms” and “propositions”, all orders of logic. A counterfactual course of history of mathematics and philosophy may be admitted. The bifurcation happened in Descartes and Fermat’s age. FLT is exceptionally difficult to be proved in our real branch rather than in the counterfactual one.
  • 2. 2 The theorem known as “Fermat’s last theorem” (FLT) was formulated by the French mathematician in 1637 and proved by Andrew Wiles (1995). Fermat remained both its statement and his claim for the proof “too long for the margin”. So, the challenge of a simple proof accessible to Fermat is alive during centuries. Andrew Wiles’s proof is too complicated. It is not only beyond arithmetic, but even the question whether it is within set theory can be asked. What follows is a simple and elementary proof by the axiom of induction applied to an enumerated series of uniform recurrent arithmetical statements sharing the logical form of modus tollens. The necessary premises are only: the definition of equality in mathematics including the three property: identity, symmetry, and transitivity; modus tollens; the axiom of induction, the proof of FLT for 𝑛𝑛 = 3. All premises necessary for the theorem itself to be formulated should be added. Thus, all Peano axioms of arithmetic are included. The set of all natural numbers, designated as “N”, is the only set meant anywhere bellow. All variables (𝑥𝑥, 𝑦𝑦, 𝑧𝑧, 𝑤𝑤, 𝑛𝑛, 𝑎𝑎, 𝑏𝑏) and the constant “c” are defined only on it: their values are its elements. However, the set “N” is not used. It is utilized only for simplifying the notations. The idea of proof is a modification of Fermat’s infinite descent, consisting in the following: The modification is not directed to construct a false statement included in any proof by reductio ad absurdum. Furthermore, it starts as if from infinity rather than from any finite natural number. Anyway, the modification is able to be restricted only to arithmetic and the axiom of induction (i.e. without the set-theory “actual infinity”) by means of an enumerated series of modus tollens. Thus, Fermat’s infinite descent is seen and utilized as “reversed”: as an ascent by induction.
  • 3. 3 If one decomposes FLT to an enumerated series of statements, namely: FLT(3), FLT(4) FLT(5) … FLT(n), FLT (n+1) , ..., the idea of the proof is: ∀(𝑥𝑥, 𝑦𝑦, 𝑧𝑧, 𝑛𝑛) 𝜖𝜖 𝑁𝑁: [(𝑎𝑎 = 𝑥𝑥 𝑛𝑛+1 ) → (𝑏𝑏 = 𝑥𝑥 𝑛𝑛 )] ↔ [𝐹𝐹𝐹𝐹𝐹𝐹(𝑛𝑛) → 𝐹𝐹𝐹𝐹𝐹𝐹(𝑛𝑛 + 1)]. According to FLT, all FLT(n) are negative statements. If one considers the corresponding positive statements, FLT*(n) = ¬FLT(n), the link to the series of modus tollens is obvious: ∀(𝑥𝑥, 𝑦𝑦, 𝑧𝑧, 𝑛𝑛)𝜖𝜖 𝑁𝑁: [(𝑎𝑎 = 𝑥𝑥 𝑛𝑛+1 ) → (𝑏𝑏 = 𝑥𝑥 𝑛𝑛 ) ↔ [¬FLT*(n) → ¬ FLT*(n+1)]. This is the core of proof. It needs a reflection even philosophical. Two triple equalities ("𝑎𝑎 = 𝑥𝑥 𝑛𝑛+1 = 𝑦𝑦 𝑛𝑛+1 + 𝑧𝑧 𝑛𝑛+1 ”, and “𝑏𝑏 = 𝑥𝑥 𝑛𝑛 = 𝑦𝑦 𝑛𝑛 + 𝑧𝑧 𝑛𝑛 ”) are linked to each other by modus tollens. What is valid for the left parts, (𝑎𝑎 = 𝑥𝑥 𝑛𝑛+1 ) → (𝑏𝑏 = 𝑥𝑥 𝑛𝑛 ), is transferred to the right parts, ¬(𝑥𝑥 𝑛𝑛 = 𝑦𝑦 𝑛𝑛 + 𝑧𝑧 𝑛𝑛 ) → ¬(𝑥𝑥 𝑛𝑛+1 = 𝑦𝑦 𝑛𝑛+1 + 𝑧𝑧 𝑛𝑛+1 ), as an equivalence. The mediation of each middle member in both triple equalities is crucial: it allows for the transition. An extended description of “∀(𝑥𝑥, 𝑦𝑦, 𝑧𝑧, 𝑛𝑛)𝜖𝜖 𝑁𝑁: [(𝑎𝑎 = 𝑥𝑥 𝑛𝑛+1 ) → (𝑏𝑏 = 𝑥𝑥 𝑛𝑛 ) ↔ [¬FLT*(n) → ¬ FLT*(n+1)]” is: ∀(𝑥𝑥, 𝑦𝑦, 𝑧𝑧, 𝑛𝑛)𝜖𝜖 𝑁𝑁: [(𝑎𝑎 = 𝑥𝑥 𝑛𝑛+1 = 𝑦𝑦 𝑛𝑛+1 + 𝑧𝑧 𝑛𝑛+1) → (𝑏𝑏 = 𝑥𝑥 𝑛𝑛 = 𝑦𝑦 𝑛𝑛 + 𝑧𝑧 𝑛𝑛)] ↔ ↔ [¬(𝑏𝑏 = 𝑥𝑥 𝑛𝑛 = 𝑦𝑦 𝑛𝑛 + 𝑧𝑧 𝑛𝑛) → ¬(𝑎𝑎 = 𝑥𝑥 𝑛𝑛+1 = 𝑦𝑦 𝑛𝑛+1 + 𝑧𝑧 𝑛𝑛+1)]. In fact, the equality (“=”) and logical equality “↔” are divided disjunctively. Their equivalence is not necessary or used. Anyway, their equivalence is valid as a mathematical isomorphism. Even more, the law of identity in logic, “∀𝑎𝑎: 𝑎𝑎 ↔ 𝑎𝑎”, referring to the propositional logic, and the axiom of identity, “∀𝑎𝑎: 𝑎𝑎 = 𝑎𝑎”, referring to any set of objects in a (first-order, second-order, …, n-order, …) logic are isomorphic mathematically. The identity is a special kind of relation, in which all orders are merged, and thus, indistinguishable from each other within it. Nonetheless, any exemplification of that indistinguishability of identity due to mathematical isomorphism is not used in the proof. The proof in detail: FLT: ∀(𝑥𝑥, 𝑦𝑦, 𝑧𝑧, 𝑛𝑛 ≥ 3) 𝜖𝜖 𝑁𝑁: ¬"𝑥𝑥 𝑛𝑛 = 𝑦𝑦 𝑛𝑛 + 𝑧𝑧 𝑛𝑛 "
  • 4. 4 “FLT(c)” means: ¬"xc =yc +zc " where “c” is a constant: 𝑐𝑐 ≥ 3, 𝑐𝑐 𝜖𝜖 𝑁𝑁. FLT will be proved as FLT(c) will be proved for each “c” (∀𝑐𝑐) by induction. The equivalence of “FLT” and "∀c: FLT(c)” is granted as obvious. The set of all “FLT(c)” is neither used nor involved in any way. The relation of equality can be defined by its three properties: identity, symmetry, and transitivity. They will be used to be proved a corollary from modus tollens, which is necessary to be linked Fermat’s infinite descent to an inductive ascent. Law (axiom) of identity [LI]: ∀𝐴𝐴: 𝐴𝐴 = 𝐴𝐴 It will be modified equivalently to “∀𝑥𝑥: 𝑥𝑥 ↔ 𝑥𝑥 = 𝑥𝑥” for the present utilization. Indeed: ∀𝑥𝑥: 𝑥𝑥 = 𝑥𝑥; ∀𝑥𝑥: 𝑥𝑥 → 𝑥𝑥; ∀𝑥𝑥: 𝑥𝑥 → 𝑥𝑥 = 𝑥𝑥; ∀𝑥𝑥: 𝑥𝑥 = 𝑥𝑥 → 𝑥𝑥; ∀𝑥𝑥: 𝑥𝑥 ↔ 𝑥𝑥 = 𝑥𝑥 Symmetry of equality [SE]: 𝐴𝐴 = 𝐵𝐵 ↔ 𝐵𝐵 = 𝐴𝐴. It will be interpreted literally to the variables 𝑥𝑥, 𝑦𝑦, the values of which are elements of N. ∀𝑥𝑥, 𝑦𝑦: 𝑥𝑥 = 𝑦𝑦 ↔ 𝑦𝑦 = 𝑥𝑥 Transitivity of equality [TE]: 𝐴𝐴 = 𝐵𝐵 ∧ 𝐵𝐵 = 𝐶𝐶 ↔ 𝐴𝐴 = 𝐵𝐵 = 𝐶𝐶. It will be interpreted literally to the variables 𝑥𝑥, 𝑦𝑦, 𝑧𝑧, the values of which are elements of N. ∀𝑥𝑥, 𝑦𝑦, 𝑧𝑧: [(𝑥𝑥 = 𝑦𝑦) ˄ (𝑦𝑦 = 𝑧𝑧)] ↔ (𝑥𝑥 = 𝑦𝑦 = 𝑧𝑧) The definitive properties of the relation of equality imply: ∀𝑥𝑥, 𝑦𝑦: 𝑥𝑥 = (𝑥𝑥 = 𝑦𝑦). Indeed: Let 𝑧𝑧 = 𝑥𝑥, then: ∀𝑥𝑥, 𝑦𝑦: [(𝑥𝑥 = 𝑦𝑦)˄ (𝑦𝑦 = 𝑥𝑥)] ↔ (𝑥𝑥 = 𝑦𝑦 = 𝑥𝑥) ↔ [𝑥𝑥 = (𝑦𝑦 = 𝑥𝑥)] 𝑆𝑆𝑆𝑆 ↔ [𝑥𝑥 = (𝑥𝑥 = 𝑦𝑦)] Modus tollens [MT]: (𝐴𝐴 → 𝐵𝐵) ↔ (¬𝐵𝐵 → ¬𝐴𝐴) If one interprets MT as to the variables 𝑥𝑥, 𝑦𝑦, 𝑧𝑧, 𝑤𝑤 defined on N and means the proved statement above (“∀𝑥𝑥, 𝑦𝑦: 𝑥𝑥 = (𝑥𝑥 = 𝑦𝑦)”) in order to substitute “𝑦𝑦” by “𝑦𝑦 = 𝑧𝑧” and “x” by “𝑥𝑥 = 𝑤𝑤”, the result is: ∀𝑥𝑥, 𝑦𝑦, 𝑧𝑧, 𝑤𝑤: [(𝑎𝑎 = 𝑥𝑥) → (𝑏𝑏 = 𝑦𝑦)] ↔ [¬(𝑦𝑦 = 𝑧𝑧) → ¬(𝑥𝑥 = 𝑤𝑤)]. Both “𝑎𝑎” and “𝑏𝑏” serve only to transform the terms “𝑥𝑥” and “𝑦𝑦” into propositions and to allow for the implication. They mediate
  • 5. 5 and therefore divide disjunctively the equality of terms (“=”) from the logical equivalence of propositions in modus tollens (“↔”). Axiom of induction [AI]: ∀𝑝𝑝, 𝑛𝑛: 𝑝𝑝(1) ˄ [𝑝𝑝(𝑛𝑛) → 𝑝𝑝(𝑛𝑛 + 1)] → 𝑝𝑝 where “𝑝𝑝(𝑛𝑛)” is an arithmetical proposition referring to the natural number “𝑛𝑛”, and “p” is the same proposition referring to all natural numbers. “Arithmetical proposition” means a proposition in a first-order logic applied to arithmetic. The axiom of induction is modified starting from 𝑛𝑛 = 3 rather than from 𝑛𝑛 = 1: (∀𝑝𝑝, 𝑛𝑛: 𝑝𝑝(1) ˄ [𝑝𝑝(𝑛𝑛) → 𝑝𝑝(𝑛𝑛 + 1)] → 𝑝𝑝} → ∀𝑝𝑝, 𝑛𝑛 ≥ 3: 𝑝𝑝(3) ˄ [𝑝𝑝(𝑛𝑛) → 𝑝𝑝(𝑛𝑛 + 1)] → 𝑝𝑝 A modification of Fermat’s infinite descent [MFID]: MT modified as above is applied as starting from 𝑛𝑛 = 3 as follows: … 𝑛𝑛, 𝑛𝑛 − 1, … 5, 4, 3 The same descent is interpreted as a series of enumerated propositions: … (𝑛𝑛), (𝑛𝑛 − 1), … (5), (4), (3) A reverse chain of negations is implied: ¬(3), ¬(4), ¬(5), … , ¬(𝑛𝑛 − 1), ¬(𝑛𝑛), … Both ascent of “negations” and infinite descent are constructed step by step following the increasing number of the negative propositions (rather than the decreasing number of the positive propositions): [(4) → (3)] ↔ [¬(3) → ¬(4)], [(5) → (4)] ↔ [¬(4) → ¬(5)], [(6) → (5)] ↔ [¬(5) → ¬(6)], … … [(𝑛𝑛 + 1) → (𝑛𝑛)] ↔ [¬(𝑛𝑛) → ¬(𝑛𝑛 + 1)], [(𝑛𝑛 + 2) → (𝑛𝑛 + 1)] ↔ [¬(𝑛𝑛 + 1) → ¬(𝑛𝑛 + 2)], … …. So, one builds a series of modus tollens starting from 𝑛𝑛 = 3. FLT(3): 𝑥𝑥, 𝑦𝑦, 𝑧𝑧 𝑎𝑎𝑎𝑎𝑎𝑎 𝑛𝑛𝑛𝑛𝑛𝑛𝑛𝑛𝑛𝑛𝑛𝑛𝑛𝑛 𝑛𝑛𝑛𝑛𝑛𝑛𝑛𝑛𝑛𝑛𝑛𝑛𝑛𝑛. 𝑇𝑇ℎ𝑒𝑒𝑒𝑒𝑒𝑒 𝑑𝑑𝑑𝑑 𝑛𝑛𝑛𝑛 𝑒𝑒𝑒𝑒𝑒𝑒𝑒𝑒𝑒𝑒 𝑎𝑎𝑎𝑎𝑎𝑎 𝑥𝑥, 𝑦𝑦, 𝑧𝑧: 𝑥𝑥3 + 𝑦𝑦3 = 𝑧𝑧3 Many mathematicians beginning with Euler claimed its proof. Ernst Kummer’s proof (1847) will be cited here for its absolute rigor. It refers to all cases of “regular prime numbers” defined by Kummer, among which the case “𝑛𝑛 = 3” is. Furthermore, the “n”-th member of the series of modus tollens, namely: "[(𝑛𝑛 + 1) → (𝑛𝑛)] ↔ [¬(𝑛𝑛) → ¬(𝑛𝑛 + 1)]”, is valid as far as "(n+1)→(n)" is valid. One interprets that "(n+1)→(n)" in the case of FLT: ∀𝑥𝑥, 𝑛𝑛: (𝑎𝑎 = 𝑥𝑥 𝑛𝑛+1 ) → (𝑏𝑏 = 𝑥𝑥 𝑛𝑛 ). This is true for 𝑥𝑥 𝑛𝑛+1 = 𝑥𝑥 𝑛𝑛 . 𝑥𝑥" . Thus, 𝑏𝑏 = 𝑥𝑥 𝑛𝑛 is a necessary condition for 𝑎𝑎 = 𝑥𝑥 𝑛𝑛+1 and the former is implied by the latter. The expression "𝑥𝑥 𝑛𝑛+1 → 𝑥𝑥 𝑛𝑛 " will be used further as a brief notation for “∀𝑥𝑥, 𝑛𝑛: (𝑎𝑎 = 𝑥𝑥 𝑛𝑛+1 ) → (𝑏𝑏 = 𝑥𝑥 𝑛𝑛 )” just as FLT(n) is a corresponding brief notation.
  • 6. 6 The “a” and “b” transform the logical terms "𝑥𝑥 𝑛𝑛+1 " and “𝑥𝑥 𝑛𝑛 " into propositions correspondingly. They serve to mediate between the relation of equality “=” referring to terms and the logical equivalence “↔” referring to propositions therefore dividing them disjunctively. The inspiration for the proof is the isomorphism of the law of identity in logic and the axiom of identity in the definition of equality: “a” and “b” are necessary in order to remove that isomorphism as a premise for the proof. The series of modus tollens is interpreted in terms of FLT as the following series of implications: [“𝑥𝑥4 → 𝑥𝑥3 ” ˄ “FLT(3)”] → “FLT(4)”; [“𝑥𝑥5 → 𝑥𝑥4 ” ˄ “FLT(4)”] → “FLT(5)”, [“𝑥𝑥6 → 𝑥𝑥5 ” ˄ “FLT(5)”] → “FLT(6)”; … , [“𝑥𝑥 𝑛𝑛+1 → 𝑥𝑥 𝑛𝑛 ” ˄ “FLT(n)”] → “FLT(n+1)”; [“𝑥𝑥 𝑛𝑛+2 → 𝑥𝑥 𝑛𝑛+1 ” ˄ “FLT(n+1)”] → “FLT(n+2)”, … … The member of the series of implications is true for “n=3”, the validity for “n” implies the validity for “n+1”. Thus, it is valid for “any member enumerated by a natural number greater than two” in virtue of the axiom of induction. FLT is proved. If one accepts that Fermat (1670: 338-339) had proved FLT(4) and as far as the above proof seems to be accessible to him, he might prove FLT for 𝑛𝑛 ≥ 4. Literature: Wiles, A. (1995) Modular Elliptic Curves and Fermat's Last Theorem. Annals of Mathematics, Second Series, Vol. 141, No. 3 (May, 1995), pp. 443-55. Kummer, E. (1847) Beweis des Fermat’schen Satzes der Unmöglichkeit von 𝑥𝑥 𝜆𝜆 + 𝑦𝑦 𝜆𝜆 = 𝑧𝑧 𝜆𝜆 für eine unendliche Anzahl Primzahlen λ. In: Kummer, Ernst Eduard. Collected papers (ed. Andre Weil) Volume 1. Contributions to number theory. Berlin, Heidelberg, New York: Springer, 1975, pp. 274-297. Fermat, P. (1670) Diophanti Alexandrini Arithmeticorum libri sex, et De numeris multangulis liber unus. Cum commentariis C.G. Bacheti v.c. & obseruationibus D.P. de Fermat .senatoris Tolosani. Acessit Doctrinae analyticae inuentum nouum, collectum ex varijs eiusdem D. de Fermat epistolis. Tolosae: Excudebat Bernardus Bosc, è regione Collegii Societatis lesu, M. DC. LXX. (Source: http://books.google.com/books?id=yx9VIgeaCEYC&hl=&source=gbs_api 1670.)
  • 7. 7 A comment. The original proof of Fermat's las theorem: a philosophical reflection Prehistory and background: Fermat remained a statement (supposedly, in 1637) in the margin of his exemplar of Diophantus’s works as well as the claim he had proved it, but the proof was too long to be recorded in the margin. The statement is known as Fermat’s last theorem (FLT): the equation 𝑥𝑥 𝑛𝑛 + 𝑦𝑦 𝑛𝑛 = 𝑧𝑧 𝑛𝑛 where x, y, z, n are natural numbers does not have any solution for 𝑛𝑛 ≥ 3. Fermat himself remained a proof for the case 𝑛𝑛 = 4. Euler proved it for 𝑛𝑛 = 3 in two different ways, but both proofs met criticism. Gauss’s proof of the same particular case met criticism as well. Ernst Kummer’s one (1847) refers to all “regular prime numbers” define by him, among which the case 𝑛𝑛 = 3 is. His proof is mathematically rigorous enough. The theorem has been proved for many particular cases since then. The statement in general was proved only in 1995 by Andrew Wiles as a corollary from the Taniyama- Shimura-Weil conjecture known as the modularity theorem after his proof. It links the continuous (even smooth) elliptic curves with the discrete modular forms. The proof is not arithmetical or accessible to Fermat. It is even so complicated that the question whether it is within set theory rather than only within arithmetic can be asked. Anyway, Fermat’s challenge for an elementary arithmetical proof remains. An idea for the inductive proof of FLT: An idea for proving FLT might be the following. The statement is proved for 𝑛𝑛 = 3. If one proves that its validity for 𝑛𝑛 implies its validity for 𝑛𝑛 + 1, the statement will be proved by virtue of the axiom of induction in arithmetic, and thus: absolutely arithmetically. Fermat’s “infinite descent” involving modus tollens might be modified for the purpose. The modification would consists in the following. The infinite descent would not include in a reductio ad absurdum proof. It would starts as if “from infinity” rather than from any finite natural number. The descent might be transformed into a corresponding ascent, to which the axiom of induction would be applicable, by means of modus tollens. The inspiration of the inductive proof might be the mathematical isomorphism of the law of identity in logic and the axiom of identity in the definition of the relation of equality axiomatically. It implies the isomorphism of logical equivalence referring to propositions and the relation of equality referring to objects or terms. Thus, identity in virtue of its definition is a special “singularity” where propositional logic and any logic of an arbitrary order merge to each other. The inspiration for merging can originate from a few philosophical doctrines such as Pythagoreanism, Hegel’s panlogism, Husserl’s phenomenology, Heidegger’s doctrine(s). Furthermore, it can originate from an experimental science such as quantum mechanics and its mathematical formalism grounded on the separable complex Hilbert space. However, it can originate from the absence or instability of Descartes’s dualism during Fermat’s life (as far as he is almost Descartes’s contemporary). This together with some kind of naïve Pythagoreanism admissible or even probable for a mathematician in number theory might inspire Fermat for a simple arithmetical proof of FLT. Fermat's accessibility to that kind of inductive proof: The idea of inductive proof is relative to Fermat’s infinite descent. He himself had been prove FLT
  • 8. 8 for 𝑛𝑛 = 4. So, the conjecture that Fermat meant the proof for 𝑛𝑛 ≥ 4 is probable. Furthermore, the one of Euler’s proof (the more correct one though containing gaps) was admissible to Fermat at least in principle. So, the option for Fermat meant the case 𝑛𝑛 ≥ 3 might not be excluded absolutely. The meaning of identity in an eventual inductive proof: The identity is able to inspire an elementary, simple, very brief, and absolutely arithmetical proof of FLT by the method of mathematical induction. The philosophical essence of that identity is the identity of anything (i.e. an object in any n-order logic) and the "word" designating the same thing (i.e. the corresponding term in the (n-1)-order logic). In other words, this means the identity of any mathematical structure and its interpretation of any kind. For example, meaning that identity, one should erase the distinction between mathematical models and their material interpretation in physics. The identity refers only to its scope: it does not imply mathematical models and their interpretations to be identified at all. It states only the existence of a mathematical model identical to a given physical system or vice versa: a given physical system identical to a given physical model. This seems to be a philosophical postulate. On the contrary, Western philosophy (and particularly, philosophy of science) as far as originates from Descartes's dualism postulates the opposite statement: no mathematical model can be identical to the physical system interpreting it. Only a few, though the most important, properties and relations of the system can be captured by the model, but there exist always others, which are not, regardless of whether there exist property or relation of the system which cannot be reflected in the model ever at all, in principle. Thus, a difference whether absolute or historically relative justifies the distinction of "things" and "words" in Western philosophy and philosophy of science. Its "blind spot" is all knowledge within the opposite postulate allowing the identity of a mathematical model and a physical system. Thus, the necessary inspiration for an elementary proof of FLT by induction turns out to be within the same 'blind spot". The proof out of it, e.g. that of Andrew Wiles, is incredibly complicated, indirect, and mediated by many, many chain links way to be seen the invisible being situated in the area corresponding to the "blind spot". If one manages to reflect the existence of "blind spot", the change of position is much simple as to observing what is located in the "blind spot" area. Abandoning the metaphor, this means to be accepted the opposite postulate: mathematical model and reality can coincide and thus, be identical. Once, that postulate is the case, the identity necessary for an elementary inductive proof of FLT is admissible and the pathway to it is open. However, one can suggest that the actual pathway as a "Wittgenstein ladder" might be removed in the final analysis. That is: the identity is necessary for the inspiration to an elementary proof, but not within it actually, not within its text literally. In facts, quantum mechanics was forced almost violently by the experimental results to see the area corresponding to the "blind spot" of Western philosophy and science. The shocking theorems of the "absence of hidden variables" in quantum mechanics were proved. They implied the absolute coincidence of model and reality at least as to quantum mechanics, and thus, their identity. Consequently, quantum mechanics might serve as an "inspiration" for an elementary, inductive proof of FLT. Identity in terms of Descartes's dualism: However, Fermat's contemporary Descartes, his "older brother" by age, born, lived, and died about ten years ago, ten years before Fermat, postulated the non-identity at issue by his doctrine of dualism.
  • 9. 9 Perhaps only God and belief might be the "key" to identity, otherwise inaccessible to human beings. Thus, the direct pathway for an elementary inductive proof of FLT would turn out to be closed for centuries, and a very, very round and indirect road would be walked exceptionally hard only at the end of millennium by Andrew Wiles. One can admit easily, that the direct pathway had not been closed ultimately in Fermat's age. So, Fermat might prove his last theorem really, relying on that identity still possible and admissible in science and mathematics. Descartes remained his "analytic geometry" together with the "dualism": what is gapped in the latter is linked in the former. Measuring the earth (i.e. "geometry") is identical to algebra generating mathematical models only. Thus, a Foucault "episteme" of identities and distinctions has been determined for centuries: An identity (that of analytic geometry) has linked geometry to algebra and arithmetic, therefore constituting mathematics. A distinction (that of dualism) has gapped mathematics from physics, therefore constituting experimental science. So, a plot about the “bystander – victim” Fermat, a "younger brother" of the “villain” Descartes can be outlined. The original proof of FLT would be the symbol and title of that scenario. Identity in terms of the modern western philosophy: Descartes’s dualism underlay all Western philosophy after him. One of its main problems was how the dualism might be overcome without God’s help. Kant’s transcendentalism and Hegel’s dialectic panlogism can be considered as ones of the most successful solutions. The fundamentally different is only Husserl’s phenomenology (as well as Heidegger’s doctrine(s) influenced by it crucially). They considered the dualism as an axiom, and postulated its negation in their doctrines. Conclusion: A counterfactual course of time in history of philosophy and in history of mathematics can be allowed. The real branch of Descartes’s dualism and a lost original proof of FLT is ours. The counterfactual one would suggest an elementary arithmetical proof and perhaps the absence of Descartes’s dualism and the originating Western philosophy following it. The bifurcation happened in Descartes and Fermat’s age. One might attempt to write down those counterfactual histories of mathematics and philosophy.