SlideShare a Scribd company logo
1 of 108
Journal of Theoretical and Philosophical
Psychology
What Is a Person? What Is the Self? Formulations for a
Science of Psychology
Raymond M. Bergner
Online First Publication, February 9, 2017.
http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/teo0000057
CITATION
Bergner, R. M. (2017, February 9). What Is a Person? What Is
the Self? Formulations for a Science
of Psychology. Journal of Theoretical and Philosophical
Psychology. Advance online publication.
http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/teo0000057
What Is a Person? What Is the Self? Formulations for a
Science of Psychology
Raymond M. Bergner
Illinois State University
This article offers solutions to two historically unresolved
subject matter problems in
psychology: (a) What is a “person”? And, (b) what is the “self”?
Part 1 of the article
presents Peter Ossorio’s (2006) Descriptive Psychologically
based answer to the first of
these questions, an answer that comprises a paradigm case
formulation of the concept
“person” itself, as well as a parametric analysis for describing
individual persons. Part
2 of the article presents a new solution to the second question.
The solution is a
disarmingly simple one in which “self” or “I,” consistent with
actual usage, means
simply and essentially “this person”—this holistically
considered, embodied, con-
scious, deliberate actor that I intend when I use the terms “I” or
“me” or “myself”—as
opposed to “that person,” the specific individual I intend when I
say “he” or “she” or
“herself.” The ways in which this formulation (a) uniquely
possesses an empirical
grounding, (b) avoids many historical problems that have arisen
in trying to delineate
the nature of the self, and (c) integrates the field of self
psychology, are all demon-
strated. The article provides logical and empirical arguments in
support of both of its
formulations, as well as for the importance of the science of
psychology possessing
such formulations of its core subject matter.
Keywords: person, self, Descriptive Psychology, conceptual
formulation, philosophy of
behavioral science
For a large class of cases—though not for all—in
which we employ the word “meaning” it can be de-
fined thus: the meaning of a word is its use in the
language.
—Ludwig Wittgenstein, 1953, #43
Imagine a biology instructor, on the opening
day of class, addressing her students as follows:
Welcome to vertebrate biology. In this class, we will
be discussing the biology of vertebrate organisms. Un-
fortunately, however, our field has so far come to no
consensus in the matter of how to define the term
“vertebrate.” So, in essence, we cannot articulate pre-
cisely and definitively the nature of our subject matter.
In other words, we cannot state the conceptual criteria
for correctly identifying one organism as a vertebrate
and another as an invertebrate. So, procedurally, as we
study the findings of different authorities in this area,
we will in each case just go along with the concep-
tion that each has explicitly or implicitly adopted,
even though these may differ one from another, and
even though the result could be that they are actually
investigating different subject matter. A few people
in our field seem bothered by this problem, but most
of us are not.
The situation described in this vignette, one
in which an individual with presumed expertise
in a scientific domain cannot even articulate the
nature of the subject matter of that domain, is
sadly one that characterizes the field of psychol-
ogy where many of its core concepts such as
‘behavior,’ ‘person,’ ‘self,’ ‘personality,’ and
‘mental disorder’ are concerned (Bergner, 2006,
2011, 2016; Harri & Tissaw, 2005; Martin, Sug-
arman, & Hickinbottom, 2010; Ossorio, 2006).
It is a situation of scientific imprecision and
confusion, as well as indifference to the prob-
lem of conceptualizing our subject matter itself,
a situation in which our field is in effect repeat-
edly saying to its practitioners, “We scientifi-
cally study the set of phenomena X; unfortu-
nately we cannot tell you the criteria for
membership in that set.”
The purpose of this article is to present solu-
tions to two of these historically unresolved
subject matter problems in psychology: (a)
What is a “person”? And, (b) what is the “self”?
Correspondence concerning this article should be ad-
dressed to Raymond M. Bergner, Department of Psychol-
ogy, Illinois State University, Normal, IL 61790-4620. E-
mail: [email protected]
T
hi
s
do
cu
m
en
t
is
co
py
ri
gh
te
d
by
th
e
A
m
er
ic
an
P
sy
ch
ol
og
ic
al
A
ss
oc
ia
ti
on
or
on
e
of
it
s
al
li
ed
pu
bl
is
he
rs
.
T
hi
s
ar
ti
cl
e
is
in
te
nd
ed
so
le
ly
fo
r
th
e
pe
rs
on
al
us
e
of
th
e
in
di
vi
du
al
us
er
an
d
is
no
t
to
be
di
ss
em
in
at
ed
br
oa
dl
y.
Journal of Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology © 2017
American Psychological Association
2017, Vol. 37, No. 1, 000 1068-8471/17/$12.00
http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/teo0000057
1
mailto:[email protected]
http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/teo0000057
To address the first of these, I will present Peter
Ossorio’s formulation of the concept “person”
within the broader conceptual schema of De-
scriptive Psychology (Ossorio, 1966/1995,
2006). To address the second, building upon
Ossorio’s formulation, I will propose a new
solution. Logical and empirical arguments in
support of both formulations, as well as for the
importance of a science of psychology possess-
ing such formulations of its core subject matter,
will also be presented.
The Concept of a “Person”
As just noted, psychology has to date arrived
at no consensus definition or other conceptual
formulation (e.g., Roschian prototype analysis)
of the concept “person” (Bergner, 2016; Martin
et al., 2010; Ossorio, 2006). Although the pri-
mary focus of the entire field is that of describ-
ing and explaining persons: their behavior, de-
velopment, neural processes, psychopathology,
personalities, and more, scientific psychologists
have largely ignored the question of just what
sort of being it is that is the subject of all their
theoretical and empirical attention. When dis-
cussing persons, the usual approach is not to
define it at all. For example, the term does not
even appear in the APA Dictionary of Psychol-
ogy (VandenBos, 2007), the Oxford Dictionary
of Psychology (Colman, 2006), or the glossaries
(as well as indexes) of every 1 of 7 current
personality texts that I examined (e.g., Engler,
2009; Feist, Feist, & Roberts, 2013; Hergen-
hahn & Olson, 2007).
The Proposed Formulation
Ossorio has proposed a conceptual formula-
tion of a “person” as “. . . an individual whose
history is paradigmatically a history of deliber-
ate action” (Ossorio, 2006, p. 69). A person is
an individual, in other words, that (paradigmati-
cally) has a history of, and thus an ability to,
behave deliberately; that is, to engage in some
behavior B, knowing that he or she is doing B
rather than other behaviors that he or she dis-
tinguishes, and having chosen B as being the
thing to do from among a set of distinguished
behavioral alternatives. In the vernacular, such
behavior may be characterized as “knowing
what you’re doing and doing it on purpose.”
Behaviors such as making a carefully consid-
ered move in a board game, ordering from a
restaurant menu, or phrasing a verbal reply so as
not to offend another represent clear, everyday
examples of deliberate actions. This formula-
tion is consistent with those of Baumeister
(2008, 2010); Chisholm (1982); Martin et al.
(2010), and Taylor (1985, 1989), all of whom
view agency—the ability to genuinely choose
one’s actions—as essential to personhood.
A Paradigm Case, Not a Definition
This formulation of “person” is not a defini-
tion. It is instead a paradigm case formulation
(“PCF”; Ossorio, 2006). Paradigm case meth-
odology, like its first cousin, prototype analysis
(Fehr, 2006; Mervis & Rosch, 1981; Rosch,
1973), represents an alternative to definition as
a way to demarcate an empirical domain (or
set). PCF methodology involves a two-pronged
strategy. The first prong is that of selecting a
certain case to represent the paradigm case. This
is usually an archetypal, indubitable one that
captures central or core features of the concept.
For example, the selected paradigm case of the
concept “family” might be a grouping of per-
sons living together composed of a mother, a
father, and their biological children. Because, in
many instances, we have strong reason to in-
clude other than the paradigm cases as instances
of a concept under investigation, the second
step in PCF methodology involves specifying
nonparadigm cases that represent transforma-
tions of the paradigm case. Thus, in the case of
“family,” single parent families (transforma-
tion: change number of parents), step-families
(transformation: one parent not a biological par-
ent), and blended families (transformation: at
least one parent has children from a previous
relationship), would all be regarded as instances
of the concept “family” by virtue of their re-
semblance to the paradigmatic one (Ossorio,
2006; cf. Fehr, 2006; Mervis & Rosch, 1981;
Rosch, 1973).
Used in the present context, our paradigm
case formulation of “person” gets at the point
that, while deliberate action is central to the
concept of a paradigm case person, we custom-
arily extend the concept to transformations of
this paradigm case in which individuals, for
example, (a) will only acquire the ability to
behave deliberately at a later time (e.g., infants);
(b) have suffered damage to this ability through
2 BERGNER
T
hi
s
do
cu
m
en
t
is
co
py
ri
gh
te
d
by
th
e
A
m
er
ic
an
P
sy
ch
ol
og
ic
al
A
ss
oc
ia
ti
on
or
on
e
of
it
s
al
li
ed
pu
bl
is
he
rs
.
T
hi
s
ar
ti
cl
e
is
in
te
nd
ed
so
le
ly
fo
r
th
e
pe
rs
on
al
us
e
of
th
e
in
di
vi
du
al
us
er
an
d
is
no
t
to
be
di
ss
em
in
at
ed
br
oa
dl
y.
such misfortunes as autism, brain damage, or
dementia; or (c) are in comas or vegetative
states. Further, while currently our only entirely
clear example of a paradigm case person is
homo sapiens embodied human beings, PCF
methodology allows for the possibility that with
future developments, other nonparadigm cases
may emerge such as silicon-embodied extrater-
restrials, highly developed computers, chimpan-
zees, or dolphins. (NB: Procedurally, using PCF
methodology here permits us to avoid the po-
litically and humanely questionable alternatives
of characterizing certain individuals as “lesser
persons” or as possessing “lesser degrees of
personhood.”)
No Consciousness, No Persons
That deliberate action is a central requirement
for an individual to qualify as a (paradigm case)
person implies further that the presence of con-
sciousness is also necessary. The explication of
the concept of deliberate action above stated
that a person is an individual that has the ability
to “engage in some behavior B, knowing that he
or she is doing B rather than other behaviors
that he or she distinguishes. . . .” It stated further
that such behavior can be characterized as
“knowing what you’re doing and doing it on
purpose.” Deliberate action implies conscious-
ness—implies awareness or comprehension of
what one is doing and of the distinction between
it and other behavioral options. If some entity,
in a situation permitting logically possible al-
ternatives, cannot ever do other than automati-
cally and nonconsciously enact one of them, we
do not count this as deliberate action—as a case
of choosing—and we do not count this entity a
person. A computer, for example, is pro-
grammed to do X (e.g., purchase a stock) if state
of affairs Y obtains (the stock hits a certain
price point); or, as in the case of IBMs trivia
quiz “contestant” “Watson,” to sort through a
myriad of key words and phrases to find statis-
tically associated ones, generate the highest
probability confluence of them using hundreds
of algorithms, and generate this as a product
(Thompson, 2010). In such cases, there is noth-
ing we could call “awareness” or “comprehen-
sion” or “consciousness” of alternatives; or of
genuinely “choosing” or “selecting” one of
them from among the others; thus, no deliberate
action, and thus, no person.
Persons Not Always Behaving Deliberately
A computer may be defined functionally as a
device for accomplishing various computational
tasks, and an airplane one for transporting peo-
ple and/or goods above the ground from one
place to another. They are defined by their func-
tions in human affairs, by what they do, but not
necessarily by what they are doing one hundred
percent of the time. To define them as we do, for
example, we do not need to believe that the
airplane is always in the air flying from one
place to another or that the computer is always
in operation. In the same way, to conceptualize
a person as an individual capable of deliberate
action does not imply that persons are always so
engaged. We recognize trivially that they are
sometimes asleep, sometimes seriously ill, and
sometimes engaged in activities (e.g., brushing
hair away from their eyes or typing the next
letter on the keyboard) with no conscious
awareness (Baumeister, 2008). As in the case of
the computer and airplane, it is the central func-
tion or capability that is at issue in conceptually
capturing what a person is.
Implication
The proposed formulation of “person,” if (as
I will argue below) it captures the core condi-
tion for correct application of this term, carries
the implication that wherever and whenever we
encounter a being that exemplifies it, whether it
be a homo sapiens embodied human being, a
member of a now extinct species of the genus
homo, a silicon extraterrestrial, a future com-
puter, a chimpanzee, or a dolphin, this being
should be counted a person.
Kinds of Persons
A familiar and very simple conceptual sys-
tem comprising three parameters, hue, satura-
tion, and brightness, is able to capture and to
distinguish every actual and possible instance of
the phenomenon color (Munsell, 1946). In the
same way, a (vastly more complex) conceptual
system for the science of psychology must be
able to provide conceptual resources for articu-
lating every fact and possible fact about persons
(qua persons, vs., e.g., as biological organisms).
If it is to do so, it must not merely capture the
concept of “person” in general, but must also
3PERSON AND SELF
T
hi
s
do
cu
m
en
t
is
co
py
ri
gh
te
d
by
th
e
A
m
er
ic
an
P
sy
ch
ol
og
ic
al
A
ss
oc
ia
ti
on
or
on
e
of
it
s
al
li
ed
pu
bl
is
he
rs
.
T
hi
s
ar
ti
cl
e
is
in
te
nd
ed
so
le
ly
fo
r
th
e
pe
rs
on
al
us
e
of
th
e
in
di
vi
du
al
us
er
an
d
is
no
t
to
be
di
ss
em
in
at
ed
br
oa
dl
y.
provide resources for capturing and distinguish-
ing what kinds of persons there are. Whether we
are psychologists, historians, biographers, nov-
elists, or just individuals leading our everyday
social lives, we do and we must distinguish
persons, not merely on the basis of identity
(“that’s John Smith”), but on basis of the kinds
of persons they are. The following parametric
analysis, adapted from Ossorio (2006), provides
the conceptual resources for doing so:
�PC� � �Ds, P, Dr�, Where . . .
PC � Person Characteristics
Ds � Dispositions, the various personal tendencies or
inclinations, ordinarily observable in a person by virtue
of a pattern of frequency in his or her behavior. These
include Traits (dispositions to engage in a certain kind
of behavior such as shy, aggressive, or generous be-
havior); Styles (dispositions having to do, not with
what a person does, but with how he or she does it
[e.g., in a sophisticated, graceful, or awkward fash-
ion]); Attitudes (dispositions to regard and treat differ-
ent objects [e.g., a religious text or a political candi-
date] or certain classes of object [e.g., liberals or
conservatives] in certain characteristic ways [e.g., con-
temptuously or reverently]); Interests (dispositions to
find certain topics [e.g., world affairs, sports, or music]
absorbing or captivating).
P � Powers, concepts having to do with what is
possible and not possible for a given person. These
include the person’s Abilities (i.e., capabilities with
reference to some kind of achievement such as speak-
ing a language, playing the piano, or shooting a bas-
ketball); Knowledge (the set of facts the person has the
ability to act on, such as the multiplication times tables,
the rules of baseball, or the information necessary to
repair an automobile engine); and Values (the set of
motivational priorities that the person is routinely able
to act on, such as a value for honesty, for accumulating
wealth, or for an adventurous way of life).
Dr � Derivatives, concepts that, unlike the two previ-
ous categories, do not have a direct connection to
behavior but are defined instead by their reference to
Dispositions and Powers. These include States (states
of affairs in which there is a systematic difference in
the ordinary powers or dispositions of a person, such as
being sick, exhausted, or drunk); Capacities (the po-
tential to acquire personal characteristics, such as ones
to acquire musical skills, learn languages, or play soc-
cer); and Embodiment (the physical characteristics of a
person, such as being six feet tall, weighing 170
pounds, or having blue eyes; adapted from Ossorio,
2006, pp. 70 –71).
In essence, we describe what kind of person
John is by giving values to these parameters.
As a psychotherapist, organizational person-
nel selector, psychological researcher, and
more, I might have reason to do this in a
highly formalized and rigorous fashion. As a
prospective life partner, business associate,
friend, or voter, I might do so less formally
but, depending on the particulars, no less
carefully. In either case, what I am doing is
making commitments to some number of
these parameters pertaining to the kind of
person John is. When I describe him as “ex-
traverted,” I commit to (one value of) the
Trait parameter; when “flamboyant” to the
Style parameter; when “obsessed with making
money” to the Values parameter; when “very
good with numbers” to the Ability parameter
(of course, all of these parameters will have
multiple values and will exist in some de-
gree— extraversion will not be John’s only
trait and he may be somewhat or very outgo-
ing). And I am saying in essence that, relative
to what can be termed a “standard normal
person” (Ossorio, 1983) in his culture, this is
the kind of behavior, style, motivational pri-
ority, ability, and so forth, that you can expect
to find in greater frequency and/or degree
when you observe John; this is the kind of
person John is.
Lest there be confusion, it should be noted
that this analysis is not about personality. It is
about persons. As such, it extends consider-
ably beyond what, if we are faithful to con-
sensual English usage, we understand by an
individual’s “personality.” Of the above list-
ing of 10 person characteristics, only two
(traits and styles) clearly pertain to an indi-
vidual’s personality (it may be noted, e.g.,
that every one of the currently popular “big
five” personality characteristics [Goldberg,
1993; McAdams & Pals, 2006] is a trait).
Two other characteristics, interests and val-
ues, could (more arguably) be seen as pertain-
ing to personality. However, facts about an
individual’s embodiment (“John is six feet
tall”), capacities (“Mary has a capacity for
learning languages”), states (“Jack has been
depressed lately”), abilities (“Jill is capable
of writing computer programs”), attitudes
(“Scott has a negative attitude toward immi-
grants”), and knowledge (“Suzie knows the
capitol of every state”) are not personality
facts. While personality facts are important
ones about persons, they are far from being
the only facts, much less the only important
facts, about what kind of person a person is.
4 BERGNER
T
hi
s
do
cu
m
en
t
is
co
py
ri
gh
te
d
by
th
e
A
m
er
ic
an
P
sy
ch
ol
og
ic
al
A
ss
oc
ia
ti
on
or
on
e
of
it
s
al
li
ed
pu
bl
is
he
rs
.
T
hi
s
ar
ti
cl
e
is
in
te
nd
ed
so
le
ly
fo
r
th
e
pe
rs
on
al
us
e
of
th
e
in
di
vi
du
al
us
er
an
d
is
no
t
to
be
di
ss
em
in
at
ed
br
oa
dl
y.
Empirical Foundation: Conceptions
Capture Meaning in Actual Usage
The formulations of “person” and the para-
metric analysis of persons were created for the
purpose of demarcating the domain of persons
for a science of psychology (Ossorio, 1966/
1995, 2006); that is, for articulating both what a
person is and all of the ways in which one
person can be the same as, or different from,
another person (cf. hue, saturation, and bright-
ness for color). In this section, I will attempt to
show that these conceptions, though formulated
for such usage, have the advantage of success-
fully capturing what amounts to a refined and
disambiguated meaning in use of these concepts
in ordinary lay usage. In capturing this usage, I
will argue further that, per Wittgenstein’s fa-
mous dictum that “. . . the meaning of a word is
its use in the language” (Wittgenstein, 1953,
#43), they in effect become strong candidates
for what should be considered the meaning of
these person concepts in a science of psychol-
ogy. This is based on the contention that, if
shown to be coherent, the concept in actual use
by people, the distinction they are actually
drawing and acting upon, serves better than any
other as the premier “expert concept” and
should not be disregarded or violated with im-
punity in favor of one’s own invented private
meaning (Austin, 1956; Hegi & Bergner, 2010;
Kelley, 1983; Wittgenstein, 1953). Further, as
the concepts in actual use, they enjoy the unique
advantage of having an actual empirical basis
upon which to ground claims about their mean-
ing.
Beverley Fehr has observed that, when called
upon to define or otherwise explicate the mean-
ings of concepts, “. . . people may not necessar-
ily produce the full range of important features
when asked (a recall task), but ‘know them
when they see them’ (. . . a recognition task)”
(Fehr, 2006, p. 242). It is an observational com-
monplace that people use concepts that embody
criteria they are unable to articulate. Asked
what time it is, they correctly respond by telling
us the time. Asked to describe their mother’s
personality, they inform us that she is outgoing,
generous, and considerate of others. Asked to
give an example of humor, they tell us a joke.
However, asked to define or otherwise expli-
cate the concepts of “time,” “personality,” or
“humor,” they are for the most part at a loss.
They possess the correct distinctions, they use
the terms correctly, but they cannot articulate
well the conceptual criteria they are using in
doing so.
With this in mind, the question can be raised
regarding whether or not the person formula-
tions above do in fact capture, not what people
can verbally articulate if asked, but how people
actually use these conceptions; that is, what
distinctions they actually draw and act upon.
First, with respect to the definition of “person”
stated, many everyday, commonplace observa-
tions reveal that people regard and treat persons,
both themselves and others, as deliberate actors.
That is, they regard and treat them as individu-
als who can and do consider behavioral alterna-
tives that they understand, choose from among
these the one that they enact, and genuinely
possess the power to do otherwise. A few rep-
resentative examples: (a) Both as individuals
and as representatives of institutions (e.g., the
legal system), they hold themselves and others
responsible for their behavior, implying that
these individuals had a choice and could have
done otherwise (e.g., they blame others when
they are negligent, laud them when they engage
in altruistic behavior, or render a guilty verdict
as jurors in a court of law). (b) They react
differently to unfortunate bodily movements of
others (e.g., someone bumping into them) seen
as “accidents” than to ones seen as done “de-
liberately” or “on purpose.” (c) They routinely
enjoin others to entertain certain considerations
(e.g., to think about the consequences of a cer-
tain action) to influence the choices of these
others. (NB: It should perhaps be underscored
that this point, as well as the following one,
pertain to the meaning in use of a concept, and
not to the perennially unsettled issue of the
ontological merits of free will vs. deterministic
positions.)
Further, when entities are known or believed
not to possess the ability to engage in deliberate
action, even those entities most likely to pass
the Turing test and, thus, to be seen as most
person-like, we characteristically do not regard
them as persons. For example, in a media search
of articles on contemporary chess playing and
trivia identifying computer programs, I have
been unable to find a single claim to the effect
that either of them qualified as persons. “If not
deliberate action, then not person” seems to be
the criterion in use here: if there is no perceived
5PERSON AND SELF
T
hi
s
do
cu
m
en
t
is
co
py
ri
gh
te
d
by
th
e
A
m
er
ic
an
P
sy
ch
ol
og
ic
al
A
ss
oc
ia
ti
on
or
on
e
of
it
s
al
li
ed
pu
bl
is
he
rs
.
T
hi
s
ar
ti
cl
e
is
in
te
nd
ed
so
le
ly
fo
r
th
e
pe
rs
on
al
us
e
of
th
e
in
di
vi
du
al
us
er
an
d
is
no
t
to
be
di
ss
em
in
at
ed
br
oa
dl
y.
reason to believe that an entity is capable of
considering understood behavioral options and
genuinely choosing from among them, then that
individual is not seen as an instance of the
concept “person.”
Describing Persons
With regard to the second matter, that of how
people describe what kinds of persons they and
others are, it is again a matter of everyday
observation that, in the face of requests for what
kind of person a given individual is, describers
invariably respond by making commitments to
one or more of the PC parameters listed above.
Whether with single labels (e.g., “shy” “consci-
entious”) or more protracted descriptions
(“He’s the kind of person who, when confronted
with difficult situations, enjoys rising to the
challenge”), they offer information about the
individual’s traits, attitudes, interests, styles,
values, capacities, embodiment and so forth
(and often descriptions of the degree to which
these are the case). Ana is “somewhat shy, very
unassuming, places great value on her integrity,
wants very much to have children, is interested
in and possesses extensive knowledge of pre-
Colombian art, has a talent for music, is five
feet, six inches tall,” and so forth.
Some Relations to Other Formulations
As noted above, few explicit formulations of
the concept “person” have arisen within psy-
chology. The present conceptualization, how-
ever, is consistent with a small number of pre-
vious ones that have given a central role to
choice or agency as the core criterion for per-
sonhood. For example, Martin et al. (2010) state
that “. . . the ability to make choices and act on
these choices to impact one’s own life and the
lives of others is the most distinctive feature of
personhood . . .” (p. v). Other psychologists
who have viewed choice as central to person-
hood include Baumeister (2008, 2010), Frankl
(1969/2014); Rychlak (1981), and Yalom
(1980). Within philosophy, authors whose for-
mulations are consistent with the present one in
this regard include Chisholm (1982), Hacker
(2007), Kierkegaard (1834/1992), and Sartre
and Mairet (1948). Also consistent are a number
of views approaching the question of person-
hood from moral (e.g., Anderson, 2000; Kant,
1797/1996; Taylor, 1989) and from legal (e.g.,
Taylor, 1985) perspectives, all of which em-
body views of persons as choice-making indi-
viduals who are responsible for their morally
and legally relevant behaviors.
In its contention that choice or agency is a
core characteristic of what the concept “person”
means to people, the present account is incon-
sistent with many others that, while not explic-
itly addressing the question conceptually, pres-
ent us with views of persons at distinct odds
with it. The authors of these accounts come both
from psychology (e.g., Freud, 1949; Skinner,
1971; Wegner, 2002) and from philosophy
(e.g., Honderich, 2002; Smilanski, 2000; G.
Strawson, 1994). In one form or another, these
authors all view persons as a kind of organism
whose behavior is entirely determined by bio-
logical, environmental, psychological, and/or
social determinants. On the present view, given
its conceptual requirement of genuine choice or
agency, such “persons” would be regarded pre-
cisely as nonpersons. (NB: In a position known
as “compatibilism,” which asserts a compatibil-
ity between free will and determinism, authors
[e.g., Dennett, 2003; Nahmias, 2011] maintain
both (a) that persons do in fact engage in activ-
ities such as mulling over behavioral alterna-
tives, arriving at decisions, and acting in accord
with those decisions, implying free will; and (b)
that these activities are themselves the inevita-
ble products of antecedent causal forces, imply-
ing determinism. However, it is very difficult,
all behavior remaining in the end the ineluctable
outcome of deterministic forces, to see this po-
sition as other than a deterministic one [com-
pare Honderich, 2002; Hood, 2012].)
One other relevant focus in the literature per-
tains to the classical distinction between mind
and body. In the present context, this becomes
the issue of whether a person is essentially a
mind (Berkeley, 1710/1970), a body (or even a
brain; Churchland, 2013), or a combination of
the two that somehow interact (Descartes, 1649/
1998). With respect to this issue, the present
position is essentially identical to that of P. F.
Strawson when he famously stated that,
What I mean by the concept of a person is the concept
of a type of entity such that both predicates ascribing
states of consciousness and predicates ascribing corpo-
real characteristics, a physical situation, and so forth,
are equally applicable to a single individual of that
6 BERGNER
T
hi
s
do
cu
m
en
t
is
co
py
ri
gh
te
d
by
th
e
A
m
er
ic
an
P
sy
ch
ol
og
ic
al
A
ss
oc
ia
ti
on
or
on
e
of
it
s
al
li
ed
pu
bl
is
he
rs
.
T
hi
s
ar
ti
cl
e
is
in
te
nd
ed
so
le
ly
fo
r
th
e
pe
rs
on
al
us
e
of
th
e
in
di
vi
du
al
us
er
an
d
is
no
t
to
be
di
ss
em
in
at
ed
br
oa
dl
y.
single type. (Strawson, 1959, p. 102; cf. Hacker, 2007;
Harré, 1998)
Why Should We Care About the Concept
of “Person”?
So what? Why should we care about having
an optimally formulated concept of “person”?
What differences would it make (a) for psychol-
ogy as a science, and (b) for individual mem-
bers of society, as well as for society at large?
Consequences for Psychology as a Science
The term “person,” it might be argued, is the
central concept in psychology (Bergner, 2010,
2013; Martin et al., 2010; Ossorio, 2006). Why
central? The primary focus of the entire field of
psychology is persons: their behavior, develop-
ment, neural functioning, personality, emotion,
intelligence, and more. What integrates the en-
tire field, what integrates, all of these apparently
so disparate topics, is that they all have refer-
ence to the single complex being that is a per-
son. They are all about various aspects of per-
sons. Thus, having a formulation of what a
person is, as well as a system for describing and
distinguishing kinds of persons, are, in Natalie
Angier’s phrase, “at the heart of the discipline”
(Angier, 2009, p. D1).
Despite this, we seem little better off than 50
plus years ago when Sigmund Koch “described
psychology as singular among scholarly and
scientific pursuits in having decided on a set of
methods before it defined its proper subject
matter” (Robinson, 2001, p. 421). At the outset
of this article, I presented a sketch of a hypo-
thetical biology teacher who relates to her class
on the first day that she cannot define or other-
wise formulate the nature of the subject matter
of her course. She states that she cannot even
tell them what that subject matter is—that is,
what the criteria are for inclusion in the set of
phenomena under study and thus cannot, strictly
speaking, tell them how to identify from the
outset what is even to count as a case of that
subject matter! This polemic illustrates a num-
ber of problems with psychology’s historical
failure to settle upon consensus formulations of
seminal concepts such as “person”: its failure to
articulate the nature of its subject matter, its
allowance of differing and inconsistent formu-
lations of this (as well as other) core concepts,
and its creation thereby of an untenable situa-
tion in which researchers claiming to be inves-
tigating the same thing might not in fact be
doing so. As stated previously, it is a situation
of scientific imprecision and confusion, as well
as indifference to the problem itself.
Social Consequences
Martin et al. (2010) have argued that, while
psychology has failed by and large to formulate
the concept “person,” it has settled on an im-
plicit default view of persons that is biologically
reductionistic and deterministic in nature, and
that this view has very significant social conse-
quences (cf. Bergner, 2004). The field and the
broader society is being presented with a view
that persons are organisms whose behavior is
biologically determined; in effect, that a person
is, in E.O. Wilson’s phrase, a “marvelous robot
. . . wired (neuronally) with awesome precision”
(Wilson, 1999, p. 53). The social impact of such
a view of persons being presented to society is
a matter of considerable importance (Baumeis-
ter, 2008; Bergner, 2004; Martin et al., 2010).
As Martin et al. express the matter,
By reducing persons to their physical or biological
constituents in an attempt to meet the demands of a
naturalist paradigm, psychologists strip humans of
what matters to them most and render explanations of
human action and experience that are distorted and
malformed, if not wholly alien. (p. 8)
Among the features so reduced and distorted,
these authors contend, are moral accountability,
human rights and responsibilities, and any no-
tions of praise- or blameworthiness.
Further, a growing empirical literature on the
effects of belief in free will versus determinism
attests that the disbelief in free will inherent in
viewing persons as nonagents is associated with
a wide variety of antisocial outcomes. These
include (a) an increased likelihood that people
will act in socially irresponsible ways such as
cheating and refusing to help others (Baumeis-
ter, Masicampo, & DeWall, 2009); (b) lower
moral standards, disbelief in the legitimacy of
moral rules, and decreased levels of both mean-
ing and satisfaction in life (Bergner & Ramon,
2013); (c) greater levels of aggressive behavior
and a reduced willingness to help others
(Baumeister, 2008); and (d) higher rates of
cheating and of overpaying oneself for perfor-
mance on a task (Vohs & Schooler, 2008).
7PERSON AND SELF
T
hi
s
do
cu
m
en
t
is
co
py
ri
gh
te
d
by
th
e
A
m
er
ic
an
P
sy
ch
ol
og
ic
al
A
ss
oc
ia
ti
on
or
on
e
of
it
s
al
li
ed
pu
bl
is
he
rs
.
T
hi
s
ar
ti
cl
e
is
in
te
nd
ed
so
le
ly
fo
r
th
e
pe
rs
on
al
us
e
of
th
e
in
di
vi
du
al
us
er
an
d
is
no
t
to
be
di
ss
em
in
at
ed
br
oa
dl
y.
Thus, the presentation to the public of a con-
ception of persons as choice-making deliberate
actors is to the advantage both of individual
persons and of society in general.
Finally, both Bergner (2004) and Martin et al.
(2010) have argued that biologically reduction-
istic and deterministic views of persons under-
mine critical social institutions and academic
disciplines (including psychology). The former
author expresses this as follows:
With the disappearance of the concept of a person (as
a choice-making agent) must come a corresponding
disappearance of the conceptual apparatuses of our
current seminal social institutions (e.g., the family, the
judicial system, religion, and the educational system)
and many other disciplines aside from psychology
(e.g., ethics, law, sociology, economics, history, and
political science). . . . If we dismiss the categories of
‘choosing,’ ‘intending,’ ‘acting for a reason,’ ‘acting
deliberately,’ and so forth, as designating legitimate,
scientifically acceptable states of affairs, then consider
the following statements. From law: ‘Murder in the
first degree, implying the planned, premeditated act of
killing another, ought to be punished more severely
than manslaughter.’ From ethics and religion: ‘The
concepts of moral ‘right’ and ‘wrong’ (as well as the
latter’s religious counterpart, ‘sin’), conceptually im-
ply the ability of an individual to choose from among
understood behavioral options; a completely deter-
mined movement on the part of a person . . . is ineli-
gible for such attributions.’ . . . If we accept the reduc-
tive views, the concept of a (choice-making) person
and its logical sequelae become inherently defective
attempts to account for what can only legitimately be
accounted for biologically (2004, p. 7).
The Concept of “Self”
When philosophers use a word—“knowledge,” “be-
ing,” “object,” “I,” “proposition,” and “name”—and
try to grasp the essence of the thing, one must ask
oneself: is the word ever actually used in this way in
the language game which is its original home? What
we do is to bring words back from their metaphysical
to their everyday use.—Ludwig Wittgenstein, 1953,
#116
. . . it is, rather, of the essence of our investigation that
. . . we want to understand something that is already in
plain view. For this is what we seem in some sense not
to understand.—Ludwig Wittgenstein, 1953, # 89
A second longstanding and thus far unre-
solved problem in both psychology and philos-
ophy concerns the nature of the self (Baumeis-
ter, 2008, 2010; Guenther & Alicke, 2013;
Harré, 1998; Martin et al., 2010; McGinn, 2004;
VandenBos, 2007). In its entry on this term,
VandenBos (2007) states that “. . . the term’s
use in psychology is extremely wide ranging
and lacks uniformity” (p. 827), while Harré
(1998) asserts that, “The study of no aspect of
humanity is so marked by muddled thinking and
confusion of thought as this one” (p. 2). In the
same vein, Martin et al. (2010) attest that,
With all of this publishing on the topic (of self), it
might be supposed that psychologists have come to an
agreed understanding of what the self is or, at the very
least, have given considerable attention to conceptual
issues of this kind. Unfortunately, for the most part,
nothing could be further from the truth. (p. 7)
When they take up matters pertaining to the
self, theorists and researchers approach it from a
myriad of directions. Thus, we have literatures
on the self-concept, self-esteem, self-regulation,
self-presentation, self-actualization, self-
knowledge, self-deception, the socially con-
structed self, and much more (Baumeister,
2010; Guenther & Alicke, 2013). Given this
diversity, and given the “muddle” just alluded
to, it becomes difficult to see what might be at
the heart of all of these topics by virtue of which
each calls itself a topic “about the self.”
So just what if anything at all is this entity
that we call the “self” or the “I”? Historically,
on most accounts, authors have been inclined to
see this term as designating an “inner” entity,
one that is deep, mysterious, ineffable, and per-
haps ineluctably hidden from view. This has
been so whether the author wished to endorse
the existence of such an entity or to deny it (e.g.,
Harré, 1998). So, to take up some of the histor-
ically most prominent answers given, is the self
an immaterial Cartesian thinking substance akin
to the traditional notion of the “soul” (Des-
cartes, 1649/1998)? Is it an inferable but itself
not directly observable entity, perhaps transcen-
dental in nature (Kant, 1781–1787/1999), that is
the inner source of consciousness, thought,
memory, feeling, and instigation of action (e.g.,
James’ [1890] “I” or “pure ego”)? On negative,
“no such entity” accounts, is the so-called self
merely a Humean “bundle” of associated mem-
ories, thoughts, and experiences that, given our
inability to observe some inner “I” at their
source, must collectively be considered the to-
tality of what constitutes the self (Hume, 1739 –
1740/2003); compare Dennett, 1986; Hood,
2012, on self as a convenient fiction)? Is it
essentially a social construction; that is, an “in-
ventory of self-attributes or conceptions” ac-
quired “through social observation, interaction,
8 BERGNER
T
hi
s
do
cu
m
en
t
is
co
py
ri
gh
te
d
by
th
e
A
m
er
ic
an
P
sy
ch
ol
og
ic
al
A
ss
oc
ia
ti
on
or
on
e
of
it
s
al
li
ed
pu
bl
is
he
rs
.
T
hi
s
ar
ti
cl
e
is
in
te
nd
ed
so
le
ly
fo
r
th
e
pe
rs
on
al
us
e
of
th
e
in
di
vi
du
al
us
er
an
d
is
no
t
to
be
di
ss
em
in
at
ed
br
oa
dl
y.
and language acquisition” (Gergen, 1977, p.
143; Gergen, 2011; McAdams, 2013; Mead,
1934)? Is it the individual’s body, or perhaps
just his or her brain (Churchland, 2013; Hood,
2012; Olson, 1997)? The consensus at the pres-
ent time seems to be that this is one of those
perennially intractable problems, or even mys-
teries (McGinn, 1993, 2004), on which we have
not been able to come to any broadly accepted
agreement (Baumeister, 2010; Guenther & Al-
icke, 2013; Harré, 1998; Martin et al., 2010;
VandenBos, 2007).
If we turn to the Wittgensteinian “original
home” of the words “self” and “I,” however, we
find that their use in everyday affairs is entirely
clear and unproblematic. In such use, no one
seems to have a problem understanding what is
meant by these terms. With respect to “I,” or-
dinary people and geniuses alike exhibit this
understanding when they say such things as “I
think that X,” “I am intending to do Y,” “I see
myself as Z,” and so forth. The very young child
proclaims, “I want candy,” while Albert Ein-
stein asserts, “As I have said so many times,
God doesn’t play dice with the world” (Her-
manns, 1983, p. 58). With respect to “self,”
much the same is true. When used in common
usage, it is usually as a prefix (as in “self-
taught” or “self-effacing”) or in conjunction
with another syllable (as in “myself” or “her-
self”). Again, such use (e.g., if I say, “I did it
myself”) is generally clear and unproblematic,
and raises few questions regarding what is
meant.
If our conception be granted that a person is,
paradigmatically, an embodied, conscious indi-
vidual whose history is a history of deliberate
action; and if what can be said about the char-
acteristics of persons can be captured by artic-
ulating any given person’s dispositions (traits,
attitudes, interests, and styles), powers (abili-
ties, knowledge, and values), and derivatives
(states, capacities, and embodiments), a certain
formulation of what “I” (or “self”) means is
suggested. “I” means simply and essentially
“this person”; that is, the holistically consid-
ered, flesh and blood individual I intend when I
use the terms “I” or “me” or “myself,” as op-
posed to “that person,” the specific person I
intend when I say “he” or “you” or “herself.”
When I say “I” or “me”—when I refer to my
self—I am merely designating a certain person,
a certain embodied, conscious, deliberate actor
of whom both mental (“I think”) and physical
(“I walk”) actions are aptly predicated (cf. P.
Strawson, 1959), and I am distinguishing this
person from other persons. In particular, I (or
any person making this utterance) am designat-
ing the person who is the author of the utter-
ance. What I am not designating is an immate-
rial substance, a certain body, a certain brain, a
certain social construction, a certain bundle of
associated memories, thoughts, and experi-
ences, or some alleged but never observed inner
entity at their source. Just me, the guy who is
writing this sentence, the one with this embodi-
ment, this history of deliberate action, this per-
sonal world, this consciousness, these beliefs,
these values, and so forth. And when I say
“him” or “her”—let us say, “Abraham Lin-
coln”—I simply intend that person, the one
with that embodiment, that history of deliberate
action, that world, those beliefs, and so forth.
The proposed formulations of “person” and
“person characteristics” here allow for a star-
tlingly simple answer to a question that has long
perplexed, and continues to perplex, psycholo-
gists, philosophers, and thinking persons gener-
ally. This answer, it must be said, often comes
as a disappointing one to those with whom I
have shared it. Given the nature of much his-
torical thought on the concept, something
deeper, more profound, and more arcane seems
called for. However, my primary task here is
that of determining what, if we respect the
meaning in use of this concept in the “language
game which is its original home” (Wittgenstein,
1953, #116), the term actually means. (NB: the
term’s etymology is “old English self, seolf, sylf
‘one’s own person’” [www.etymonline.com/
index.php?term�self]). My second task is that
of demonstrating how, if we simply adopt this
meaning in use, so many historical problems are
avoided and so much falls into place in the
study of the self. Let me explain.
Problems Avoided
The formulation of self as “this person” not
only provides a positive answer to the question
of the meaning of this term, but in doing so does
not get us into the kinds of problems in the first
place that previous formulations have encoun-
tered. (a) Unlike the immaterial soul/transcen-
dental ego accounts, it does not require belief in
an unobservable immaterial entity, nor does it
9PERSON AND SELF
T
hi
s
do
cu
m
en
t
is
co
py
ri
gh
te
d
by
th
e
A
m
er
ic
an
P
sy
ch
ol
og
ic
al
A
ss
oc
ia
ti
on
or
on
e
of
it
s
al
li
ed
pu
bl
is
he
rs
.
T
hi
s
ar
ti
cl
e
is
in
te
nd
ed
so
le
ly
fo
r
th
e
pe
rs
on
al
us
e
of
th
e
in
di
vi
du
al
us
er
an
d
is
no
t
to
be
di
ss
em
in
at
ed
br
oa
dl
y.
http://www.etymonline.com/index.php?term=self
http://www.etymonline.com/index.php?term=self
generate the attendant mystery of how such an
entity could interact with a physical body. (b)
Unlike the inner experiential and agentic self,
the present account does not send one on an
introspective search for some underlying entity
which is the source of these experiences and
actions, which search, as many have attested
(e.g., Harré, 1998; Hood, 2012; Hume, 1739 –
1740/2003), has always proven futile. (c) Un-
like Hume’s (1739 –1740/2003) notion that the
so-called “self” is a fictional entity consisting
of nothing over and above a bundle of asso-
ciated memories, thoughts, feelings, and other
experiences, or Dennett’s (1986) assertion
that the self, like the notion of “center of
gravity,” is merely a convenient fiction, the
present account does not posit the seemingly
absurd notions that there are free floating
thoughts and experiences that have no actual
author or owner (Reid, 1785/1986; P. Straw-
son, 1959), or that there is no such thing as
the self. Instead, it simply identifies this
owner and this self with this person (“I”), this
quite observable, embodied individual with
this history of deliberate action (both mental
and physical) and this collectivity of person
characteristics. (d) Unlike the self as a social
construction, the present formulation does not
confuse one’s conception of oneself, which
admittedly consists of socially acquired lin-
guistic descriptors, with the self itself; in-
stead, it identifies the latter, a flesh and blood
person, with the subject or the “haver” of
these descriptors, thereby avoiding a problem
curiously similar to the no-ownership one en-
countered by Hume.
Further, (e) unlike the self-as-brain or self-
as-body solutions, the present one does not do
radical violence to the meaning of the concept
“I” in actual usage (e.g., when I say, “I went
to the store,” I do not mean that my brain
went to the store; or when I say, “I’m im-
pressed with the work of my graduate assis-
tant,” I do not mean that my body is im-
pressed with his work). (f) The present
account passes many of the bizarre, yet tell-
ing, thought experiments that philosophers
are so fond of posing. For example, McGinn
(2004) proposes one in which, in the future,
brain reprogramming becomes a possibility.
One day I am seized, my brain is stripped of
its current contents, and new content pro-
grammed in from the brain of Adolf Hitler.
Upon awakening from the operation, I (or
somebody?) find that I now have all the mem-
ories, knowledge, personality traits, and sense
of identity of Adolf Hitler. Is it still me? On
the self-as-brain account, where same brain is
equivalent to same person, the answer would
have to be “yes.” However, both intuitively
and on the present account, where self is
equated with this person with this history of
deliberate action and these person character-
istics (traits, attitudes, interests, values,
knowledge, etc.), the answer would clearly be
“no.” (g) Finally, the present formulation ac-
commodates the observation of William
James (1890) and many others since (e.g.,
Guenther & Alicke, 2013; McAdams, 2013)
that self can be regarded both as subject (as in
“I memorized the poem.”) and as object (as in
“I like how I look in my new suit.”); however,
no special distinction is required on the pres-
ent account to capture the simple fact that I
sometimes describe the person who is me as
an actor, thinker, or experiencer, and other
times as the object of my own thoughts and
observations.
The concept of “I” or “self” is almost ev-
erywhere conflated with the matter of per-
sonal identity (Olson, 2016). The notion of
“I” as this person, however, permits a discon-
nection of the two notions. For example, to
cite a famous fictional invention from the TV
series Star Trek, a man named “Kirk” enters a
device known as a “transporter” that demate-
rializes him and subsequently rematerializes
him (or somebody?) in a distant location. On
the present account, when either of these (one
or two) individuals utters the word “I” to refer
to himself (e.g., “I am expecting an attack
from the Klingons”), in each case he means
“this person”—the specific person who is the
author of the utterance. Whether the two are
or are not the same person is a separate ques-
tion. While the issue of identity is an impor-
tant one in its own right, the present concep-
tion of “I” or “self” separates the matter of
what these terms mean from the matter of
what it means to say that A and B are the
same person. (NB: The present formulation,
however, may also be useful, as in the brain
reprogramming thought experiment above, in
discussions of the latter topic.)
10 BERGNER
T
hi
s
do
cu
m
en
t
is
co
py
ri
gh
te
d
by
th
e
A
m
er
ic
an
P
sy
ch
ol
og
ic
al
A
ss
oc
ia
ti
on
or
on
e
of
it
s
al
li
ed
pu
bl
is
he
rs
.
T
hi
s
ar
ti
cl
e
is
in
te
nd
ed
so
le
ly
fo
r
th
e
pe
rs
on
al
us
e
of
th
e
in
di
vi
du
al
us
er
an
d
is
no
t
to
be
di
ss
em
in
at
ed
br
oa
dl
y.
Integrates the Field of Self Psychology
Finally, the formulation of self as “this
person,” aside from representing a clearer,
simpler, and more empirically grounded for-
mulation of this concept, easily and common-
sensically integrates the many phenomena
that have been investigated historically in
connection with the notion of self. It does so
by identifying and conceptualizing the central
entity around which this entire area is orga-
nized. For example, my “self-concept” as
commonly understood can be formulated as
my conception of this person—my culturally,
socially, and linguistically constructed formu-
lation of who I am in the social scheme of
things (“male,” “Caucasian,” “married,” “fa-
ther,” “college professor,” “clinical psychol-
ogist,” “politically progressive,” etc.). My
“sense of self” can be conceptualized as my
phenomenological experiencing of this per-
son as a conscious being in matters such as
my feelings of agency, my sense of personal
identity through time, my ongoing awareness
of my own inner states, my experiencing and
acting upon the world from a certain location
vis-à-vis other persons and physical entities,
and much more (Baumeister, 2010; Harré,
1998; Heron, 1992; McAdams, 2013; Taylor,
1989). My “self-esteem” can be formulated as
the overall worth or value that I appraise this
person as having (cf. Baumeister, Campbell,
Krueger, & Vohs, 2003). Finding my “real
self” or “authentic self,” and actualizing this
self can be formulated as this person discov-
ering and pursuing a set of possibilities in life
(vocations, relationships, interests, activities,
and ways of life) to which I discover that I
have strong intrinsic positive relationships
(e.g., that I love certain persons, that I find
pursuing certain intellectual questions highly
meaningful, and that I find coaching youth
soccer enormously engrossing; cf. Rogers
[1964] on “organismic valuing process”;
Campbell [2004] on “finding one’s bliss”).
Without further multiplying examples, it is
easy to see how the “this person” conception
of self coordinates readily with, and serves to
integrate, other prominent research topics
such as self-regulation, self-presentation,
self-enhancement, self-awareness, self-
deception, and more. And it is easy to see how
almost nothing is lost in doing so. Strong
research programs on all of the topics just
listed remain important and viable enter-
prises. The only things lost are the conceptual
muddle in which many of these things (espe-
cially self-concept and sense of self) are con-
fused with the self itself and our historically
futile search for some unobservable, mysteri-
ous, inner entity that we have always seemed
to feel must somehow be there.
Conclusion
In this article, I have attempted to provide
sound, rigorous Descriptive Psychologically
based solutions to two conceptual problems in
psychology and philosophy. Building upon
Ossorio’s (1966/1995, 2006) solution to the
first of these, that of formulating the concept
of a “person,” I have proceeded to provide a
new formulation of the second, that of “self.”
The first purpose in doing so has been to offer
some hopefully useful contributions to re-
dressing the much larger critical problem in
psychology that, unlike other mature sci-
ences, it has still after many years largely
failed to arrive at consensus formulations of
its core subject matter. The second purpose
has been to articulate some important benefits
that are gained by having adequate formula-
tions of “person” and “self.”
References
Anderson, D. L. (2000). What is a person? Consor-
tium on Cognitive Science Instruction, Illinois
State University. Retrieved from http://www.mind
.ilstu.edu/curriculum/what_is_a_person/what_is_a_
person.php
Angier, N. (2009, July, 21). When ‘what animals do’
doesn’t seem to cover it’. New York Times, D1.
Austin, J. (1956). A plea for excuses. Proceedings of
the Aristotelian Society, 57, 130. http://dx.doi.org/
10.1093/aristotelian/57.1.1
Baumeister, R. F. (2008). Free will in scientific psy-
chology. Perspectives on Psychological Science,
3, 14 –19. http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/j.1745-6916
.2008.00057.x
Baumeister, R. F. (2010). The self. In R. Baumeister
& E. Finkel (Eds.), Advanced social psychology:
The state of the science (pp. 139 –175). New York,
NY: Oxford University Press.
Baumeister, R. F., Campbell, J. D., Krueger, J. I., &
Vohs, K. D. (2003). Does high self-esteem cause
better performance, interpersonal success, happi-
11PERSON AND SELF
T
hi
s
do
cu
m
en
t
is
co
py
ri
gh
te
d
by
th
e
A
m
er
ic
an
P
sy
ch
ol
og
ic
al
A
ss
oc
ia
ti
on
or
on
e
of
it
s
al
li
ed
pu
bl
is
he
rs
.
T
hi
s
ar
ti
cl
e
is
in
te
nd
ed
so
le
ly
fo
r
th
e
pe
rs
on
al
us
e
of
th
e
in
di
vi
du
al
us
er
an
d
is
no
t
to
be
di
ss
em
in
at
ed
br
oa
dl
y.
http://www.mind.ilstu.edu/curriculum/what_is_a_person/what_i
s_a_person.php
http://www.mind.ilstu.edu/curriculum/what_is_a_person/what_i
s_a_person.php
http://www.mind.ilstu.edu/curriculum/what_is_a_person/what_i
s_a_person.php
http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/aristotelian/57.1.1
http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/aristotelian/57.1.1
http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/j.1745-6916.2008.00057.x
http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/j.1745-6916.2008.00057.x
ness, or healthier lifestyles? Psychological Science
in the Public Interest, 4, 144. http://dx.doi.org/10
.1111/1529-1006.01431.ISSN1529-1006
Baumeister, R. F., Masicampo, E. J., & Dewall, C. N.
(2009). Prosocial benefits of feeling free: Disbelief
in free will increases aggression and reduces help-
fulness. Personality and Social Psychology Bulle-
tin, 35, 260 –268. http://dx.doi.org/10.1177/
0146167208327217
Bergner, R. (2004). Is it all really biological? Journal
of Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology, 24,
3049. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/h0091236
Bergner, R. (2006). An open letter from Isaac New-
ton to the field of psychology. In K. Davis & R.
Bergner (Eds.), Advances in descriptive psychol-
ogy (Vol. 8, pp. 69 – 80). Ann Arbor, MI: Descrip-
tive Psychology Press.
Bergner, R. (2010). What is descriptive psychology?
An introduction. In K. Davis, F. Lubuguin, & W.
Schwartz (Eds.), Advances in descriptive psychol-
ogy (Vol. 9, pp. 325–360). Ann Arbor, MI: De-
scriptive Psychology Press.
Bergner, R. (2011). What is behavior? And so what?
New Ideas in Psychology, 29, 147–155. http://dx
.doi.org/10.1016/j.newideapsych.2010.08.001
Bergner, R. (2013). All the world’s a stage: A person-
centered view of science. In R. Bergner, K. Davis,
F. Lubuguin, & W. Schwartz (Eds.), Advances in
descriptive psychology (Vol. 10, pp. 7–18). Ann
Arbor, MI: Descriptive Psychology Press.
Bergner, R. (2016). What is “behavior?” And why is
it not reducible to biological states of affairs?
Journal of Theoretical and Philosophical Psychol-
ogy, 36, 41–55. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/teo00
00026
Bergner, R., & Ramon, A. (2013). Some implications
of belief in love, free will, and non-reductionism.
The Journal of Social Psychology, 153, 598 – 618.
http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/00224545.2013.798249
Berkeley, G. (1970). Treatise concerning the princi-
ples of human knowledge. New York, NY: Bobbs-
Merrill. (Original work published 1710)
Campbell, J. (2004). Pathways to bliss: Mythology
and personal transformation. New York, NY:
New World Library.
Chisholm, R. (1982). Human freedom and the self. In
G. Watson (Ed.), Free will (pp. 24 –35). Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Churchland, P. (2013). Touching a nerve: The self as
brain. New York, NY: Norton.
Colman, A. M. (2006). Oxford dictionary of psychol-
ogy. Oxford, United Kingdom: Oxford University
Press.
Dennett, D. (1986). The self as a center of narrative
gravity. In F. Kessel, P. Cole, & D. Johnson (Eds.),
Self and consciousness: Multiple perspectives (pp.
103–115). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
Dennett, D. (2003). Freedom evolves. New York,
NY: Penguin.
Descartes, R. (1998). The passions of the soul (D. A.
Cress, Trans.). Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publish-
ing. (Original work published 1649)
Engler, B. (2009). Personality theories: An introduc-
tion. Boston, MA: Houghton Mifflin.
Fehr, B. (2006). The prototype approach to studying
love. In R. Sternberg & K. Weis (Eds.), The new
psychology of love (pp. 225–248). New Haven,
CT: Yale University Press.
Feist, J., Feist, G., & Roberts, T. (2013). Theories of
personality (8th ed.). New York, NY: McGraw-
Hill.
Frankl, V. (2014). The will to meaning. New York,
NY: Meridian. (Original work published 1969)
Freud, S. (1949). An outline of psychoanalysis. New
York, NY: Norton.
Gergen, K. (1977). The social construction of self-
knowledge. In T. Mischel (Ed.), The self, psycho-
logical and philosophical issues (pp. 139 –l69).
Oxford, United Kingdom: Blackwell.
Gergen, K. (2011). The self as social construction.
Psychological Studies, 58, 108116. http://dx.doi
.org/10.1007/s12646-011-0066-1
Goldberg, L. R. (1993). The structure of phenotypic
personality traits. American Psychologist, 48, 26 –
34. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/0003-066X.48.1.26
Guenther, C., & Alicke, M. (2013). The psychology
of the self. Psychology. http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/
obo/9780199828340-0093
Hacker, P. M. S. (2007). Human nature: The catego-
rial framework. Malden, MA: Blackwell. http://dx
.doi.org/10.1002/9780470692165
Harré, H. R. (1998) The singular self. Los Angeles,
CA: Sage.
Harri, R., & Tissaw, M. (2005). Wittgenstein and
psychology: A practical guide. Aldershott, Hamp-
shire, United Kingdom: Ashgate.
Hegi, K., & Bergner, R. (2010). What is love? An
empirically-based essentialist account. Journal of
Social and Personal Relationships, 27, 620 – 636.
http://dx.doi.org/10.1177/0265407510369605
Hergenhahn, B., & Olson, M. (2007). An introduc-
tion to theories of personality (7th ed.). Upper
Saddle River, NJ: Prentice Hall.
Hermanns, W. (1983). Einstein and the poet. Welles-
ley, MA: Branden Books.
Heron, J. (1992). Feeling and personhood: Psychol-
ogy in another key. London, United Kingdom:
Sage.
Honderich, T. (2002). How free are you? The deter-
minism problem (2nd ed.). Oxford, United King-
dom: Oxford University Press.
Hood, B. (2012). The self illusion: How the social
brain creates identity. New York, NY: Oxford
University Press.
12 BERGNER
T
hi
s
do
cu
m
en
t
is
co
py
ri
gh
te
d
by
th
e
A
m
er
ic
an
P
sy
ch
ol
og
ic
al
A
ss
oc
ia
ti
on
or
on
e
of
it
s
al
li
ed
pu
bl
is
he
rs
.
T
hi
s
ar
ti
cl
e
is
in
te
nd
ed
so
le
ly
fo
r
th
e
pe
rs
on
al
us
e
of
th
e
in
di
vi
du
al
us
er
an
d
is
no
t
to
be
di
ss
em
in
at
ed
br
oa
dl
y.
http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/1529-1006.01431.ISSN1529-1006
http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/1529-1006.01431.ISSN1529-1006
http://dx.doi.org/10.1177/0146167208327217
http://dx.doi.org/10.1177/0146167208327217
http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/h0091236
http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.newideapsych.2010.08.001
http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.newideapsych.2010.08.001
http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/teo0000026
http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/teo0000026
http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/00224545.2013.798249
http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/s12646-011-0066-1
http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/s12646-011-0066-1
http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/0003-066X.48.1.26
http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/obo/9780199828340-0093
http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/obo/9780199828340-0093
http://dx.doi.org/10.1002/9780470692165
http://dx.doi.org/10.1002/9780470692165
http://dx.doi.org/10.1177/0265407510369605
Hume, D. (2003). A treatise of human nature. Mine-
ola, NY: Dover Publications. (Original work pub-
lished 1739 –1740)
James, W. (1890). The principles of psychology. New
York, NY: Holt. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/11059-
000
Kant, I. (1996). The metaphysics of morals. Cam-
bridge, United Kingdom: Cambridge University
Press. (Original work published 1797) http://dx.doi
.org/10.1017/CBO9780511809644
Kant, I. (1999). Critique of pure reason. Cambridge,
United Kingdom: Cambridge University Press.
(Original work published 1781–1787)
Kelley, H. H. (1983). Love and commitment. In E.
Berscheid, A. Christensen, J. H. Harvey, T. L.
Huston, G. Levinger, . . . D. R. Peterson (Eds.),
Close relationships (pp. 265–314). New York,
NY: Freeman.
Kierkegaard, S. (1992). Either/or. London: Penguin.
(Original work published 1834)
Martin, J., Sugarman, J., & Hickinbottom, S. (2010).
Persons: Understanding psychological selfhood
and agency. New York, NY: Springer. http://dx
.doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4419-1065-3
McAdams, D. (2013). The psychological self as ac-
tor, agent, and author. Perspectives in Psycholog-
ical Science, 8, 272–295. http://dx.doi.org/10
.1177/1745691612464657
McAdams, D. P., & Pals, J. L. (2006). A new Big
Five: Fundamental principles for an integrative
science of personality. American Psychologist, 61,
204 –217. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/0003-066X.61
.3.204
McGinn, C. (1993). Problems in philosophy: The
limits of inquiry. Oxford, United Kingdom: Black-
well Publishers.
McGinn, C. (2004). Eternal question, timeless ap-
proaches. Lectures in the Barnes and Noble Audio
Series.
Mead, G. (1934). Mind, self, and society. Chicago,
IL: University of Chicago Press.
Mervis, C., & Rosch, E. (1981). Categorization of
natural objects. Annual Review of Psychology, 32,
89 –113. http://dx.doi.org/10.1146/annurev.ps.32
.020181.000513
Munsell, A. H. (1946). A Color Notation: An illus-
trated system defining all colors and their relations
by measured scales of hue, value and chroma (15th
ed.). Baltimore, MD: Munsell Color Co.
Nahmias, E. (2011). Intuitions about free will, deter-
minism, and bypassing. In R. Kane (Ed.), The
Oxford handbook of free will (pp. 555–576). Ox-
ford, United Kingdom: Oxford University Press.
http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/oxfordhb/97801953
99691.003.0029
Olson, E. (1997). The human animal: Personal iden-
tity without psychology. New York, NY: Oxford
University Press.
Olson, E. T. (2016). Personal identity. In E. N. Zalta
(Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy
(Spring 2016 ed.). Retrieved from http://plato
.stanford.edu/archives/spr2016/entries/identity-
personal/;10.1002/9781118922590.ch7
Ossorio, P. G. (1983). A multicultural psychology. In
K. Davis & R. Bergner (Eds.), Advances in de-
scriptive psychology (Vol. 3, pp. 13– 44). Green-
wich, CT: JAI Press.
Ossorio, P. G. (1995). Persons. Ann Arbor, MI:
Descriptive Psychology Press. (Original work pub-
lished 1966)
Ossorio, P. G. (2006). The behavior of persons. Ann
Arbor, MI: Descriptive Psychology Press.
Reid, T. (1986). Essays on the intellectual powers of
man. Charlottesville, VA: Lincoln Rembrandt
Publishers. (Original work published 1785)
Robinson, D. N. (2001). Sigmund Kochphilosophi-
cally speaking. American Psychologist, 56, 420 –
424. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/0003-066X.56.5
.420
Rogers, C. R. (1964). Toward a modern approach to
values: The valuing process in the mature person.
The Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology,
68, 160 –167. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/h0046419
Rosch, E. H. (1973). Natural categories. Cognitive
Psychology, 4, 328 –350. http://dx.doi.org/10
.1016/0010-0285(73)90017-0
Rychlak, J. (1981). Introduction to personality and
personality theory. Boston, MA: Houghton Mif-
flin.
Sartre, J.-P., & Mairet, P. (1948). Existentialism and
humanism. London: Methuen.
Skinner, B. F. (1971). Beyond freedom and dignity.
New York, NY: Knopf.
Smilanski, S. (2000). Free will and illusion. Oxford,
United Kingdom: Oxford University Press.
Strawson, G. (1994). The impossibility of moral re-
sponsibility. Philosophical Studies, 75, 524. http://
dx.doi.org/10.1007/BF00989879
Strawson, P. F. (1959). Individuals: An essay in
descriptive metaphysics. London, United King-
dom: Routledge. http://dx.doi.org/10.4324/
9780203221303
Taylor, C. (1985). The concept of a person. Philo-
sophical papers (Vol. 1). Cambridge, United
Kingdom: Cambridge University Press.
Taylor, C. (1989). Sources of the self: The making of
the modern identity. Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press.
Thompson, C. (2010, June, 16). Smarter than you
think: What is I. B. M.’s Watson? The New York
Times Magazine.
VandenBos, G. R. (2007). APA dictionary of psy-
chology. Washington, DC: American Psychologi-
cal Association.
Vohs, K. D., & Schooler, J. W. (2008). The value of
believing in free will: Encouraging a belief in
13PERSON AND SELF
T
hi
s
do
cu
m
en
t
is
co
py
ri
gh
te
d
by
th
e
A
m
er
ic
an
P
sy
ch
ol
og
ic
al
A
ss
oc
ia
ti
on
or
on
e
of
it
s
al
li
ed
pu
bl
is
he
rs
.
T
hi
s
ar
ti
cl
e
is
in
te
nd
ed
so
le
ly
fo
r
th
e
pe
rs
on
al
us
e
of
th
e
in
di
vi
du
al
us
er
an
d
is
no
t
to
be
di
ss
em
in
at
ed
br
oa
dl
y.
http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/11059-000
http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/11059-000
http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511809644
http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511809644
http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4419-1065-3
http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4419-1065-3
http://dx.doi.org/10.1177/1745691612464657
http://dx.doi.org/10.1177/1745691612464657
http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/0003-066X.61.3.204
http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/0003-066X.61.3.204
http://dx.doi.org/10.1146/annurev.ps.32.020181.000513
http://dx.doi.org/10.1146/annurev.ps.32.020181.000513
http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/oxfordhb/9780195399691.003.0029
http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/oxfordhb/9780195399691.003.0029
http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2016/entries/identity-
personal/;10.1002/9781118922590.ch7
http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2016/entries/identity-
personal/;10.1002/9781118922590.ch7
http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2016/entries/identity-
personal/;10.1002/9781118922590.ch7
http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/0003-066X.56.5.420
http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/0003-066X.56.5.420
http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/h0046419
http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/0010-0285%2873%2990017-0
http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/0010-0285%2873%2990017-0
http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/BF00989879
http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/BF00989879
http://dx.doi.org/10.4324/9780203221303
http://dx.doi.org/10.4324/9780203221303
determinism increases cheating. Psychological
Science, 19, 4954. http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/j
.1467-9280.2008.02045.x
Wegner, D. (2002). The illusion of conscious will.
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Wilson, E. O. (1999). The biological basis of moral-
ity. Atlantic Monthly Online, 1–11.
Wittgenstein, L. (1953). Philosophical Investiga-
tions. New York, NY: Macmillan.
Yalom, I. (1980). Existential psychotherapy. New
York, NY: Basic Books.
Received May 25, 2016
Revision received December 12, 2016
Accepted December 15, 2016 �
14 BERGNER
T
hi
s
do
cu
m
en
t
is
co
py
ri
gh
te
d
by
th
e
A
m
er
ic
an
P
sy
ch
ol
og
ic
al
A
ss
oc
ia
ti
on
or
on
e
of
it
s
al
li
ed
pu
bl
is
he
rs
.
T
hi
s
ar
ti
cl
e
is
in
te
nd
ed
so
le
ly
fo
r
th
e
pe
rs
on
al
us
e
of
th
e
in
di
vi
du
al
us
er
an
d
is
no
t
to
be
di
ss
em
in
at
ed
br
oa
dl
y.
http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9280.2008.02045.x
http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9280.2008.02045.xWhat Is a
Person? What Is the Self? Formulations for a Science of
PsychologyThe Concept of a “Person”The Proposed
FormulationA Paradigm Case, Not a DefinitionNo
Consciousness, No PersonsPersons Not Always Behaving
DeliberatelyImplicationKinds of PersonsEmpirical Foundation:
Conceptions Capture Meaning in Actual UsageDescribing
PersonsSome Relations to Other FormulationsWhy Should We
Care About the Concept of “Person”?Consequences for
Psychology as a ScienceSocial ConsequencesThe Concept of
“Self”Problems AvoidedIntegrates the Field of Self
PsychologyConclusionReferences

More Related Content

Similar to Journal of Theoretical and PhilosophicalPsychologyWhat Is .docx

Note Please cover the introduction (origins of behaviorism and it.docx
Note Please cover the introduction (origins of behaviorism and it.docxNote Please cover the introduction (origins of behaviorism and it.docx
Note Please cover the introduction (origins of behaviorism and it.docxcurwenmichaela
 
SW 411 HBSE MIDTERM RUBRICINTRODUCTIONIntroduce your t.docx
SW 411 HBSE MIDTERM RUBRICINTRODUCTIONIntroduce your t.docxSW 411 HBSE MIDTERM RUBRICINTRODUCTIONIntroduce your t.docx
SW 411 HBSE MIDTERM RUBRICINTRODUCTIONIntroduce your t.docxssuserf9c51d
 
Sources of my IdentityIntroduction My personal identity deal.docx
Sources of my IdentityIntroduction My personal identity deal.docxSources of my IdentityIntroduction My personal identity deal.docx
Sources of my IdentityIntroduction My personal identity deal.docxrafbolet0
 
PSY 330 Effective Communication - snaptutorial.com
PSY 330 Effective Communication - snaptutorial.comPSY 330 Effective Communication - snaptutorial.com
PSY 330 Effective Communication - snaptutorial.comdonaldzs39
 
Psy 330 Education Organization-snaptutorial.com
Psy 330 Education Organization-snaptutorial.comPsy 330 Education Organization-snaptutorial.com
Psy 330 Education Organization-snaptutorial.comrobertlesew35
 
Essay on the embryonic field of language
Essay on the embryonic field of languageEssay on the embryonic field of language
Essay on the embryonic field of languageKen Ewell
 
1 Assessment 4 Context Five Qualitative Methodologies .docx
1 Assessment 4 Context Five Qualitative Methodologies .docx1 Assessment 4 Context Five Qualitative Methodologies .docx
1 Assessment 4 Context Five Qualitative Methodologies .docxoswald1horne84988
 

Similar to Journal of Theoretical and PhilosophicalPsychologyWhat Is .docx (8)

Note Please cover the introduction (origins of behaviorism and it.docx
Note Please cover the introduction (origins of behaviorism and it.docxNote Please cover the introduction (origins of behaviorism and it.docx
Note Please cover the introduction (origins of behaviorism and it.docx
 
SW 411 HBSE MIDTERM RUBRICINTRODUCTIONIntroduce your t.docx
SW 411 HBSE MIDTERM RUBRICINTRODUCTIONIntroduce your t.docxSW 411 HBSE MIDTERM RUBRICINTRODUCTIONIntroduce your t.docx
SW 411 HBSE MIDTERM RUBRICINTRODUCTIONIntroduce your t.docx
 
Sources of my IdentityIntroduction My personal identity deal.docx
Sources of my IdentityIntroduction My personal identity deal.docxSources of my IdentityIntroduction My personal identity deal.docx
Sources of my IdentityIntroduction My personal identity deal.docx
 
PSY 330 Effective Communication - snaptutorial.com
PSY 330 Effective Communication - snaptutorial.comPSY 330 Effective Communication - snaptutorial.com
PSY 330 Effective Communication - snaptutorial.com
 
Psy 330 Education Organization-snaptutorial.com
Psy 330 Education Organization-snaptutorial.comPsy 330 Education Organization-snaptutorial.com
Psy 330 Education Organization-snaptutorial.com
 
Essay on the embryonic field of language
Essay on the embryonic field of languageEssay on the embryonic field of language
Essay on the embryonic field of language
 
1 Assessment 4 Context Five Qualitative Methodologies .docx
1 Assessment 4 Context Five Qualitative Methodologies .docx1 Assessment 4 Context Five Qualitative Methodologies .docx
1 Assessment 4 Context Five Qualitative Methodologies .docx
 
Bigfive
BigfiveBigfive
Bigfive
 

More from tawnyataylor528

•Reflective Log•Your reflective log should include the.docx
•Reflective Log•Your reflective log should include the.docx•Reflective Log•Your reflective log should include the.docx
•Reflective Log•Your reflective log should include the.docxtawnyataylor528
 
•The philosophers Thomas Hobbes and John Locke disagreed on the un.docx
•The philosophers Thomas Hobbes and John Locke disagreed on the un.docx•The philosophers Thomas Hobbes and John Locke disagreed on the un.docx
•The philosophers Thomas Hobbes and John Locke disagreed on the un.docxtawnyataylor528
 
•From the first e-Activity, examine two (2) economic effects that yo.docx
•From the first e-Activity, examine two (2) economic effects that yo.docx•From the first e-Activity, examine two (2) economic effects that yo.docx
•From the first e-Activity, examine two (2) economic effects that yo.docxtawnyataylor528
 
• What are the NYS Physical Education Standards, and how do they ali.docx
• What are the NYS Physical Education Standards, and how do they ali.docx• What are the NYS Physical Education Standards, and how do they ali.docx
• What are the NYS Physical Education Standards, and how do they ali.docxtawnyataylor528
 
• Choose a health problem in the human population. Some examples i.docx
• Choose a health problem in the human population. Some examples i.docx• Choose a health problem in the human population. Some examples i.docx
• Choose a health problem in the human population. Some examples i.docxtawnyataylor528
 
•Key elements to GE’s learning culture include active experimentat.docx
•Key elements to GE’s learning culture include active experimentat.docx•Key elements to GE’s learning culture include active experimentat.docx
•Key elements to GE’s learning culture include active experimentat.docxtawnyataylor528
 
• This summative assessment can be completed in class or at any .docx
• This summative assessment can be completed in class or at any .docx• This summative assessment can be completed in class or at any .docx
• This summative assessment can be completed in class or at any .docxtawnyataylor528
 
• 2 pages• APA• how the airport uses sustainability at the o.docx
• 2 pages• APA• how the airport uses sustainability at the o.docx• 2 pages• APA• how the airport uses sustainability at the o.docx
• 2 pages• APA• how the airport uses sustainability at the o.docxtawnyataylor528
 
¿Lógico o ilógicoIndicate whether each of the doctors statemen.docx
¿Lógico o ilógicoIndicate whether each of the doctors statemen.docx¿Lógico o ilógicoIndicate whether each of the doctors statemen.docx
¿Lógico o ilógicoIndicate whether each of the doctors statemen.docxtawnyataylor528
 
·Which of the following is considered a hybrid organizational fo.docx
·Which of the following is considered a hybrid organizational fo.docx·Which of the following is considered a hybrid organizational fo.docx
·Which of the following is considered a hybrid organizational fo.docxtawnyataylor528
 
·Write aresearch paper of three (3) body pages on a narrow aspec.docx
·Write aresearch paper of three (3) body pages on a narrow aspec.docx·Write aresearch paper of three (3) body pages on a narrow aspec.docx
·Write aresearch paper of three (3) body pages on a narrow aspec.docxtawnyataylor528
 
·InterviewConduct an interview and document it.During this c.docx
·InterviewConduct an interview and document it.During this c.docx·InterviewConduct an interview and document it.During this c.docx
·InterviewConduct an interview and document it.During this c.docxtawnyataylor528
 
·Submit a 50- to 100-word response to each of the followin.docx
·Submit a 50- to 100-word response to each of the followin.docx·Submit a 50- to 100-word response to each of the followin.docx
·Submit a 50- to 100-word response to each of the followin.docxtawnyataylor528
 
·Section 3·Financial management, quality and marketing asp.docx
·Section 3·Financial management, quality and marketing asp.docx·Section 3·Financial management, quality and marketing asp.docx
·Section 3·Financial management, quality and marketing asp.docxtawnyataylor528
 
·Why is the effort to standardize the language used in reporti.docx
·Why is the effort to standardize the language used in reporti.docx·Why is the effort to standardize the language used in reporti.docx
·Why is the effort to standardize the language used in reporti.docxtawnyataylor528
 
·Humans belong to the genus Homo and chimpanzees to the genus .docx
·Humans belong to the genus Homo and chimpanzees to the genus .docx·Humans belong to the genus Homo and chimpanzees to the genus .docx
·Humans belong to the genus Homo and chimpanzees to the genus .docxtawnyataylor528
 
·Crash House II and add resources and costs—remember, only crash.docx
·Crash House II and add resources and costs—remember, only crash.docx·Crash House II and add resources and costs—remember, only crash.docx
·Crash House II and add resources and costs—remember, only crash.docxtawnyataylor528
 
·What is the main difference between the approaches of CONFLICT .docx
·What is the main difference between the approaches of CONFLICT .docx·What is the main difference between the approaches of CONFLICT .docx
·What is the main difference between the approaches of CONFLICT .docxtawnyataylor528
 
·What is the work of art’s historical and cultural context·.docx
·What is the work of art’s historical and cultural context·.docx·What is the work of art’s historical and cultural context·.docx
·What is the work of art’s historical and cultural context·.docxtawnyataylor528
 
·Review the steps of the SDLC. Explain why quality service deliv.docx
·Review the steps of the SDLC. Explain why quality service deliv.docx·Review the steps of the SDLC. Explain why quality service deliv.docx
·Review the steps of the SDLC. Explain why quality service deliv.docxtawnyataylor528
 

More from tawnyataylor528 (20)

•Reflective Log•Your reflective log should include the.docx
•Reflective Log•Your reflective log should include the.docx•Reflective Log•Your reflective log should include the.docx
•Reflective Log•Your reflective log should include the.docx
 
•The philosophers Thomas Hobbes and John Locke disagreed on the un.docx
•The philosophers Thomas Hobbes and John Locke disagreed on the un.docx•The philosophers Thomas Hobbes and John Locke disagreed on the un.docx
•The philosophers Thomas Hobbes and John Locke disagreed on the un.docx
 
•From the first e-Activity, examine two (2) economic effects that yo.docx
•From the first e-Activity, examine two (2) economic effects that yo.docx•From the first e-Activity, examine two (2) economic effects that yo.docx
•From the first e-Activity, examine two (2) economic effects that yo.docx
 
• What are the NYS Physical Education Standards, and how do they ali.docx
• What are the NYS Physical Education Standards, and how do they ali.docx• What are the NYS Physical Education Standards, and how do they ali.docx
• What are the NYS Physical Education Standards, and how do they ali.docx
 
• Choose a health problem in the human population. Some examples i.docx
• Choose a health problem in the human population. Some examples i.docx• Choose a health problem in the human population. Some examples i.docx
• Choose a health problem in the human population. Some examples i.docx
 
•Key elements to GE’s learning culture include active experimentat.docx
•Key elements to GE’s learning culture include active experimentat.docx•Key elements to GE’s learning culture include active experimentat.docx
•Key elements to GE’s learning culture include active experimentat.docx
 
• This summative assessment can be completed in class or at any .docx
• This summative assessment can be completed in class or at any .docx• This summative assessment can be completed in class or at any .docx
• This summative assessment can be completed in class or at any .docx
 
• 2 pages• APA• how the airport uses sustainability at the o.docx
• 2 pages• APA• how the airport uses sustainability at the o.docx• 2 pages• APA• how the airport uses sustainability at the o.docx
• 2 pages• APA• how the airport uses sustainability at the o.docx
 
¿Lógico o ilógicoIndicate whether each of the doctors statemen.docx
¿Lógico o ilógicoIndicate whether each of the doctors statemen.docx¿Lógico o ilógicoIndicate whether each of the doctors statemen.docx
¿Lógico o ilógicoIndicate whether each of the doctors statemen.docx
 
·Which of the following is considered a hybrid organizational fo.docx
·Which of the following is considered a hybrid organizational fo.docx·Which of the following is considered a hybrid organizational fo.docx
·Which of the following is considered a hybrid organizational fo.docx
 
·Write aresearch paper of three (3) body pages on a narrow aspec.docx
·Write aresearch paper of three (3) body pages on a narrow aspec.docx·Write aresearch paper of three (3) body pages on a narrow aspec.docx
·Write aresearch paper of three (3) body pages on a narrow aspec.docx
 
·InterviewConduct an interview and document it.During this c.docx
·InterviewConduct an interview and document it.During this c.docx·InterviewConduct an interview and document it.During this c.docx
·InterviewConduct an interview and document it.During this c.docx
 
·Submit a 50- to 100-word response to each of the followin.docx
·Submit a 50- to 100-word response to each of the followin.docx·Submit a 50- to 100-word response to each of the followin.docx
·Submit a 50- to 100-word response to each of the followin.docx
 
·Section 3·Financial management, quality and marketing asp.docx
·Section 3·Financial management, quality and marketing asp.docx·Section 3·Financial management, quality and marketing asp.docx
·Section 3·Financial management, quality and marketing asp.docx
 
·Why is the effort to standardize the language used in reporti.docx
·Why is the effort to standardize the language used in reporti.docx·Why is the effort to standardize the language used in reporti.docx
·Why is the effort to standardize the language used in reporti.docx
 
·Humans belong to the genus Homo and chimpanzees to the genus .docx
·Humans belong to the genus Homo and chimpanzees to the genus .docx·Humans belong to the genus Homo and chimpanzees to the genus .docx
·Humans belong to the genus Homo and chimpanzees to the genus .docx
 
·Crash House II and add resources and costs—remember, only crash.docx
·Crash House II and add resources and costs—remember, only crash.docx·Crash House II and add resources and costs—remember, only crash.docx
·Crash House II and add resources and costs—remember, only crash.docx
 
·What is the main difference between the approaches of CONFLICT .docx
·What is the main difference between the approaches of CONFLICT .docx·What is the main difference between the approaches of CONFLICT .docx
·What is the main difference between the approaches of CONFLICT .docx
 
·What is the work of art’s historical and cultural context·.docx
·What is the work of art’s historical and cultural context·.docx·What is the work of art’s historical and cultural context·.docx
·What is the work of art’s historical and cultural context·.docx
 
·Review the steps of the SDLC. Explain why quality service deliv.docx
·Review the steps of the SDLC. Explain why quality service deliv.docx·Review the steps of the SDLC. Explain why quality service deliv.docx
·Review the steps of the SDLC. Explain why quality service deliv.docx
 

Recently uploaded

Accessible Digital Futures project (20/03/2024)
Accessible Digital Futures project (20/03/2024)Accessible Digital Futures project (20/03/2024)
Accessible Digital Futures project (20/03/2024)Jisc
 
Transparency, Recognition and the role of eSealing - Ildiko Mazar and Koen No...
Transparency, Recognition and the role of eSealing - Ildiko Mazar and Koen No...Transparency, Recognition and the role of eSealing - Ildiko Mazar and Koen No...
Transparency, Recognition and the role of eSealing - Ildiko Mazar and Koen No...EADTU
 
TỔNG HỢP HƠN 100 ĐỀ THI THỬ TỐT NGHIỆP THPT TOÁN 2024 - TỪ CÁC TRƯỜNG, TRƯỜNG...
TỔNG HỢP HƠN 100 ĐỀ THI THỬ TỐT NGHIỆP THPT TOÁN 2024 - TỪ CÁC TRƯỜNG, TRƯỜNG...TỔNG HỢP HƠN 100 ĐỀ THI THỬ TỐT NGHIỆP THPT TOÁN 2024 - TỪ CÁC TRƯỜNG, TRƯỜNG...
TỔNG HỢP HƠN 100 ĐỀ THI THỬ TỐT NGHIỆP THPT TOÁN 2024 - TỪ CÁC TRƯỜNG, TRƯỜNG...Nguyen Thanh Tu Collection
 
AIM of Education-Teachers Training-2024.ppt
AIM of Education-Teachers Training-2024.pptAIM of Education-Teachers Training-2024.ppt
AIM of Education-Teachers Training-2024.pptNishitharanjan Rout
 
Diuretic, Hypoglycemic and Limit test of Heavy metals and Arsenic.-1.pdf
Diuretic, Hypoglycemic and Limit test of Heavy metals and Arsenic.-1.pdfDiuretic, Hypoglycemic and Limit test of Heavy metals and Arsenic.-1.pdf
Diuretic, Hypoglycemic and Limit test of Heavy metals and Arsenic.-1.pdfKartik Tiwari
 
Jamworks pilot and AI at Jisc (20/03/2024)
Jamworks pilot and AI at Jisc (20/03/2024)Jamworks pilot and AI at Jisc (20/03/2024)
Jamworks pilot and AI at Jisc (20/03/2024)Jisc
 
Unit 3 Emotional Intelligence and Spiritual Intelligence.pdf
Unit 3 Emotional Intelligence and Spiritual Intelligence.pdfUnit 3 Emotional Intelligence and Spiritual Intelligence.pdf
Unit 3 Emotional Intelligence and Spiritual Intelligence.pdfDr Vijay Vishwakarma
 
PANDITA RAMABAI- Indian political thought GENDER.pptx
PANDITA RAMABAI- Indian political thought GENDER.pptxPANDITA RAMABAI- Indian political thought GENDER.pptx
PANDITA RAMABAI- Indian political thought GENDER.pptxakanksha16arora
 
SPLICE Working Group: Reusable Code Examples
SPLICE Working Group:Reusable Code ExamplesSPLICE Working Group:Reusable Code Examples
SPLICE Working Group: Reusable Code ExamplesPeter Brusilovsky
 
Introduction to TechSoup’s Digital Marketing Services and Use Cases
Introduction to TechSoup’s Digital Marketing  Services and Use CasesIntroduction to TechSoup’s Digital Marketing  Services and Use Cases
Introduction to TechSoup’s Digital Marketing Services and Use CasesTechSoup
 
REMIFENTANIL: An Ultra short acting opioid.pptx
REMIFENTANIL: An Ultra short acting opioid.pptxREMIFENTANIL: An Ultra short acting opioid.pptx
REMIFENTANIL: An Ultra short acting opioid.pptxDr. Ravikiran H M Gowda
 
OSCM Unit 2_Operations Processes & Systems
OSCM Unit 2_Operations Processes & SystemsOSCM Unit 2_Operations Processes & Systems
OSCM Unit 2_Operations Processes & SystemsSandeep D Chaudhary
 
What is 3 Way Matching Process in Odoo 17.pptx
What is 3 Way Matching Process in Odoo 17.pptxWhat is 3 Way Matching Process in Odoo 17.pptx
What is 3 Way Matching Process in Odoo 17.pptxCeline George
 
Observing-Correct-Grammar-in-Making-Definitions.pptx
Observing-Correct-Grammar-in-Making-Definitions.pptxObserving-Correct-Grammar-in-Making-Definitions.pptx
Observing-Correct-Grammar-in-Making-Definitions.pptxAdelaideRefugio
 
COMMUNICATING NEGATIVE NEWS - APPROACHES .pptx
COMMUNICATING NEGATIVE NEWS - APPROACHES .pptxCOMMUNICATING NEGATIVE NEWS - APPROACHES .pptx
COMMUNICATING NEGATIVE NEWS - APPROACHES .pptxannathomasp01
 
MuleSoft Integration with AWS Textract | Calling AWS Textract API |AWS - Clou...
MuleSoft Integration with AWS Textract | Calling AWS Textract API |AWS - Clou...MuleSoft Integration with AWS Textract | Calling AWS Textract API |AWS - Clou...
MuleSoft Integration with AWS Textract | Calling AWS Textract API |AWS - Clou...MysoreMuleSoftMeetup
 
Michaelis Menten Equation and Estimation Of Vmax and Tmax.pptx
Michaelis Menten Equation and Estimation Of Vmax and Tmax.pptxMichaelis Menten Equation and Estimation Of Vmax and Tmax.pptx
Michaelis Menten Equation and Estimation Of Vmax and Tmax.pptxRugvedSathawane
 
UGC NET Paper 1 Unit 7 DATA INTERPRETATION.pdf
UGC NET Paper 1 Unit 7 DATA INTERPRETATION.pdfUGC NET Paper 1 Unit 7 DATA INTERPRETATION.pdf
UGC NET Paper 1 Unit 7 DATA INTERPRETATION.pdfNirmal Dwivedi
 
Play hard learn harder: The Serious Business of Play
Play hard learn harder:  The Serious Business of PlayPlay hard learn harder:  The Serious Business of Play
Play hard learn harder: The Serious Business of PlayPooky Knightsmith
 

Recently uploaded (20)

Accessible Digital Futures project (20/03/2024)
Accessible Digital Futures project (20/03/2024)Accessible Digital Futures project (20/03/2024)
Accessible Digital Futures project (20/03/2024)
 
Transparency, Recognition and the role of eSealing - Ildiko Mazar and Koen No...
Transparency, Recognition and the role of eSealing - Ildiko Mazar and Koen No...Transparency, Recognition and the role of eSealing - Ildiko Mazar and Koen No...
Transparency, Recognition and the role of eSealing - Ildiko Mazar and Koen No...
 
TỔNG HỢP HƠN 100 ĐỀ THI THỬ TỐT NGHIỆP THPT TOÁN 2024 - TỪ CÁC TRƯỜNG, TRƯỜNG...
TỔNG HỢP HƠN 100 ĐỀ THI THỬ TỐT NGHIỆP THPT TOÁN 2024 - TỪ CÁC TRƯỜNG, TRƯỜNG...TỔNG HỢP HƠN 100 ĐỀ THI THỬ TỐT NGHIỆP THPT TOÁN 2024 - TỪ CÁC TRƯỜNG, TRƯỜNG...
TỔNG HỢP HƠN 100 ĐỀ THI THỬ TỐT NGHIỆP THPT TOÁN 2024 - TỪ CÁC TRƯỜNG, TRƯỜNG...
 
AIM of Education-Teachers Training-2024.ppt
AIM of Education-Teachers Training-2024.pptAIM of Education-Teachers Training-2024.ppt
AIM of Education-Teachers Training-2024.ppt
 
Diuretic, Hypoglycemic and Limit test of Heavy metals and Arsenic.-1.pdf
Diuretic, Hypoglycemic and Limit test of Heavy metals and Arsenic.-1.pdfDiuretic, Hypoglycemic and Limit test of Heavy metals and Arsenic.-1.pdf
Diuretic, Hypoglycemic and Limit test of Heavy metals and Arsenic.-1.pdf
 
Jamworks pilot and AI at Jisc (20/03/2024)
Jamworks pilot and AI at Jisc (20/03/2024)Jamworks pilot and AI at Jisc (20/03/2024)
Jamworks pilot and AI at Jisc (20/03/2024)
 
Unit 3 Emotional Intelligence and Spiritual Intelligence.pdf
Unit 3 Emotional Intelligence and Spiritual Intelligence.pdfUnit 3 Emotional Intelligence and Spiritual Intelligence.pdf
Unit 3 Emotional Intelligence and Spiritual Intelligence.pdf
 
PANDITA RAMABAI- Indian political thought GENDER.pptx
PANDITA RAMABAI- Indian political thought GENDER.pptxPANDITA RAMABAI- Indian political thought GENDER.pptx
PANDITA RAMABAI- Indian political thought GENDER.pptx
 
SPLICE Working Group: Reusable Code Examples
SPLICE Working Group:Reusable Code ExamplesSPLICE Working Group:Reusable Code Examples
SPLICE Working Group: Reusable Code Examples
 
Introduction to TechSoup’s Digital Marketing Services and Use Cases
Introduction to TechSoup’s Digital Marketing  Services and Use CasesIntroduction to TechSoup’s Digital Marketing  Services and Use Cases
Introduction to TechSoup’s Digital Marketing Services and Use Cases
 
REMIFENTANIL: An Ultra short acting opioid.pptx
REMIFENTANIL: An Ultra short acting opioid.pptxREMIFENTANIL: An Ultra short acting opioid.pptx
REMIFENTANIL: An Ultra short acting opioid.pptx
 
OSCM Unit 2_Operations Processes & Systems
OSCM Unit 2_Operations Processes & SystemsOSCM Unit 2_Operations Processes & Systems
OSCM Unit 2_Operations Processes & Systems
 
What is 3 Way Matching Process in Odoo 17.pptx
What is 3 Way Matching Process in Odoo 17.pptxWhat is 3 Way Matching Process in Odoo 17.pptx
What is 3 Way Matching Process in Odoo 17.pptx
 
VAMOS CUIDAR DO NOSSO PLANETA! .
VAMOS CUIDAR DO NOSSO PLANETA!                    .VAMOS CUIDAR DO NOSSO PLANETA!                    .
VAMOS CUIDAR DO NOSSO PLANETA! .
 
Observing-Correct-Grammar-in-Making-Definitions.pptx
Observing-Correct-Grammar-in-Making-Definitions.pptxObserving-Correct-Grammar-in-Making-Definitions.pptx
Observing-Correct-Grammar-in-Making-Definitions.pptx
 
COMMUNICATING NEGATIVE NEWS - APPROACHES .pptx
COMMUNICATING NEGATIVE NEWS - APPROACHES .pptxCOMMUNICATING NEGATIVE NEWS - APPROACHES .pptx
COMMUNICATING NEGATIVE NEWS - APPROACHES .pptx
 
MuleSoft Integration with AWS Textract | Calling AWS Textract API |AWS - Clou...
MuleSoft Integration with AWS Textract | Calling AWS Textract API |AWS - Clou...MuleSoft Integration with AWS Textract | Calling AWS Textract API |AWS - Clou...
MuleSoft Integration with AWS Textract | Calling AWS Textract API |AWS - Clou...
 
Michaelis Menten Equation and Estimation Of Vmax and Tmax.pptx
Michaelis Menten Equation and Estimation Of Vmax and Tmax.pptxMichaelis Menten Equation and Estimation Of Vmax and Tmax.pptx
Michaelis Menten Equation and Estimation Of Vmax and Tmax.pptx
 
UGC NET Paper 1 Unit 7 DATA INTERPRETATION.pdf
UGC NET Paper 1 Unit 7 DATA INTERPRETATION.pdfUGC NET Paper 1 Unit 7 DATA INTERPRETATION.pdf
UGC NET Paper 1 Unit 7 DATA INTERPRETATION.pdf
 
Play hard learn harder: The Serious Business of Play
Play hard learn harder:  The Serious Business of PlayPlay hard learn harder:  The Serious Business of Play
Play hard learn harder: The Serious Business of Play
 

Journal of Theoretical and PhilosophicalPsychologyWhat Is .docx

  • 1. Journal of Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology What Is a Person? What Is the Self? Formulations for a Science of Psychology Raymond M. Bergner Online First Publication, February 9, 2017. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/teo0000057 CITATION Bergner, R. M. (2017, February 9). What Is a Person? What Is the Self? Formulations for a Science of Psychology. Journal of Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology. Advance online publication. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/teo0000057 What Is a Person? What Is the Self? Formulations for a Science of Psychology Raymond M. Bergner Illinois State University This article offers solutions to two historically unresolved subject matter problems in psychology: (a) What is a “person”? And, (b) what is the “self”? Part 1 of the article presents Peter Ossorio’s (2006) Descriptive Psychologically based answer to the first of these questions, an answer that comprises a paradigm case formulation of the concept “person” itself, as well as a parametric analysis for describing
  • 2. individual persons. Part 2 of the article presents a new solution to the second question. The solution is a disarmingly simple one in which “self” or “I,” consistent with actual usage, means simply and essentially “this person”—this holistically considered, embodied, con- scious, deliberate actor that I intend when I use the terms “I” or “me” or “myself”—as opposed to “that person,” the specific individual I intend when I say “he” or “she” or “herself.” The ways in which this formulation (a) uniquely possesses an empirical grounding, (b) avoids many historical problems that have arisen in trying to delineate the nature of the self, and (c) integrates the field of self psychology, are all demon- strated. The article provides logical and empirical arguments in support of both of its formulations, as well as for the importance of the science of psychology possessing such formulations of its core subject matter. Keywords: person, self, Descriptive Psychology, conceptual formulation, philosophy of behavioral science For a large class of cases—though not for all—in which we employ the word “meaning” it can be de- fined thus: the meaning of a word is its use in the language. —Ludwig Wittgenstein, 1953, #43 Imagine a biology instructor, on the opening day of class, addressing her students as follows:
  • 3. Welcome to vertebrate biology. In this class, we will be discussing the biology of vertebrate organisms. Un- fortunately, however, our field has so far come to no consensus in the matter of how to define the term “vertebrate.” So, in essence, we cannot articulate pre- cisely and definitively the nature of our subject matter. In other words, we cannot state the conceptual criteria for correctly identifying one organism as a vertebrate and another as an invertebrate. So, procedurally, as we study the findings of different authorities in this area, we will in each case just go along with the concep- tion that each has explicitly or implicitly adopted, even though these may differ one from another, and even though the result could be that they are actually investigating different subject matter. A few people in our field seem bothered by this problem, but most of us are not. The situation described in this vignette, one in which an individual with presumed expertise in a scientific domain cannot even articulate the nature of the subject matter of that domain, is sadly one that characterizes the field of psychol- ogy where many of its core concepts such as ‘behavior,’ ‘person,’ ‘self,’ ‘personality,’ and ‘mental disorder’ are concerned (Bergner, 2006, 2011, 2016; Harri & Tissaw, 2005; Martin, Sug- arman, & Hickinbottom, 2010; Ossorio, 2006). It is a situation of scientific imprecision and confusion, as well as indifference to the prob- lem of conceptualizing our subject matter itself, a situation in which our field is in effect repeat- edly saying to its practitioners, “We scientifi- cally study the set of phenomena X; unfortu-
  • 4. nately we cannot tell you the criteria for membership in that set.” The purpose of this article is to present solu- tions to two of these historically unresolved subject matter problems in psychology: (a) What is a “person”? And, (b) what is the “self”? Correspondence concerning this article should be ad- dressed to Raymond M. Bergner, Department of Psychol- ogy, Illinois State University, Normal, IL 61790-4620. E- mail: [email protected] T hi s do cu m en t is co py ri gh te d by
  • 8. is no t to be di ss em in at ed br oa dl y. Journal of Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology © 2017 American Psychological Association 2017, Vol. 37, No. 1, 000 1068-8471/17/$12.00 http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/teo0000057 1 mailto:[email protected] http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/teo0000057 To address the first of these, I will present Peter Ossorio’s formulation of the concept “person”
  • 9. within the broader conceptual schema of De- scriptive Psychology (Ossorio, 1966/1995, 2006). To address the second, building upon Ossorio’s formulation, I will propose a new solution. Logical and empirical arguments in support of both formulations, as well as for the importance of a science of psychology possess- ing such formulations of its core subject matter, will also be presented. The Concept of a “Person” As just noted, psychology has to date arrived at no consensus definition or other conceptual formulation (e.g., Roschian prototype analysis) of the concept “person” (Bergner, 2016; Martin et al., 2010; Ossorio, 2006). Although the pri- mary focus of the entire field is that of describ- ing and explaining persons: their behavior, de- velopment, neural processes, psychopathology, personalities, and more, scientific psychologists have largely ignored the question of just what sort of being it is that is the subject of all their theoretical and empirical attention. When dis- cussing persons, the usual approach is not to define it at all. For example, the term does not even appear in the APA Dictionary of Psychol- ogy (VandenBos, 2007), the Oxford Dictionary of Psychology (Colman, 2006), or the glossaries (as well as indexes) of every 1 of 7 current personality texts that I examined (e.g., Engler, 2009; Feist, Feist, & Roberts, 2013; Hergen- hahn & Olson, 2007). The Proposed Formulation
  • 10. Ossorio has proposed a conceptual formula- tion of a “person” as “. . . an individual whose history is paradigmatically a history of deliber- ate action” (Ossorio, 2006, p. 69). A person is an individual, in other words, that (paradigmati- cally) has a history of, and thus an ability to, behave deliberately; that is, to engage in some behavior B, knowing that he or she is doing B rather than other behaviors that he or she dis- tinguishes, and having chosen B as being the thing to do from among a set of distinguished behavioral alternatives. In the vernacular, such behavior may be characterized as “knowing what you’re doing and doing it on purpose.” Behaviors such as making a carefully consid- ered move in a board game, ordering from a restaurant menu, or phrasing a verbal reply so as not to offend another represent clear, everyday examples of deliberate actions. This formula- tion is consistent with those of Baumeister (2008, 2010); Chisholm (1982); Martin et al. (2010), and Taylor (1985, 1989), all of whom view agency—the ability to genuinely choose one’s actions—as essential to personhood. A Paradigm Case, Not a Definition This formulation of “person” is not a defini- tion. It is instead a paradigm case formulation (“PCF”; Ossorio, 2006). Paradigm case meth- odology, like its first cousin, prototype analysis (Fehr, 2006; Mervis & Rosch, 1981; Rosch, 1973), represents an alternative to definition as a way to demarcate an empirical domain (or set). PCF methodology involves a two-pronged
  • 11. strategy. The first prong is that of selecting a certain case to represent the paradigm case. This is usually an archetypal, indubitable one that captures central or core features of the concept. For example, the selected paradigm case of the concept “family” might be a grouping of per- sons living together composed of a mother, a father, and their biological children. Because, in many instances, we have strong reason to in- clude other than the paradigm cases as instances of a concept under investigation, the second step in PCF methodology involves specifying nonparadigm cases that represent transforma- tions of the paradigm case. Thus, in the case of “family,” single parent families (transforma- tion: change number of parents), step-families (transformation: one parent not a biological par- ent), and blended families (transformation: at least one parent has children from a previous relationship), would all be regarded as instances of the concept “family” by virtue of their re- semblance to the paradigmatic one (Ossorio, 2006; cf. Fehr, 2006; Mervis & Rosch, 1981; Rosch, 1973). Used in the present context, our paradigm case formulation of “person” gets at the point that, while deliberate action is central to the concept of a paradigm case person, we custom- arily extend the concept to transformations of this paradigm case in which individuals, for example, (a) will only acquire the ability to behave deliberately at a later time (e.g., infants); (b) have suffered damage to this ability through 2 BERGNER
  • 16. in at ed br oa dl y. such misfortunes as autism, brain damage, or dementia; or (c) are in comas or vegetative states. Further, while currently our only entirely clear example of a paradigm case person is homo sapiens embodied human beings, PCF methodology allows for the possibility that with future developments, other nonparadigm cases may emerge such as silicon-embodied extrater- restrials, highly developed computers, chimpan- zees, or dolphins. (NB: Procedurally, using PCF methodology here permits us to avoid the po- litically and humanely questionable alternatives of characterizing certain individuals as “lesser persons” or as possessing “lesser degrees of personhood.”) No Consciousness, No Persons That deliberate action is a central requirement for an individual to qualify as a (paradigm case) person implies further that the presence of con- sciousness is also necessary. The explication of
  • 17. the concept of deliberate action above stated that a person is an individual that has the ability to “engage in some behavior B, knowing that he or she is doing B rather than other behaviors that he or she distinguishes. . . .” It stated further that such behavior can be characterized as “knowing what you’re doing and doing it on purpose.” Deliberate action implies conscious- ness—implies awareness or comprehension of what one is doing and of the distinction between it and other behavioral options. If some entity, in a situation permitting logically possible al- ternatives, cannot ever do other than automati- cally and nonconsciously enact one of them, we do not count this as deliberate action—as a case of choosing—and we do not count this entity a person. A computer, for example, is pro- grammed to do X (e.g., purchase a stock) if state of affairs Y obtains (the stock hits a certain price point); or, as in the case of IBMs trivia quiz “contestant” “Watson,” to sort through a myriad of key words and phrases to find statis- tically associated ones, generate the highest probability confluence of them using hundreds of algorithms, and generate this as a product (Thompson, 2010). In such cases, there is noth- ing we could call “awareness” or “comprehen- sion” or “consciousness” of alternatives; or of genuinely “choosing” or “selecting” one of them from among the others; thus, no deliberate action, and thus, no person. Persons Not Always Behaving Deliberately A computer may be defined functionally as a device for accomplishing various computational
  • 18. tasks, and an airplane one for transporting peo- ple and/or goods above the ground from one place to another. They are defined by their func- tions in human affairs, by what they do, but not necessarily by what they are doing one hundred percent of the time. To define them as we do, for example, we do not need to believe that the airplane is always in the air flying from one place to another or that the computer is always in operation. In the same way, to conceptualize a person as an individual capable of deliberate action does not imply that persons are always so engaged. We recognize trivially that they are sometimes asleep, sometimes seriously ill, and sometimes engaged in activities (e.g., brushing hair away from their eyes or typing the next letter on the keyboard) with no conscious awareness (Baumeister, 2008). As in the case of the computer and airplane, it is the central func- tion or capability that is at issue in conceptually capturing what a person is. Implication The proposed formulation of “person,” if (as I will argue below) it captures the core condi- tion for correct application of this term, carries the implication that wherever and whenever we encounter a being that exemplifies it, whether it be a homo sapiens embodied human being, a member of a now extinct species of the genus homo, a silicon extraterrestrial, a future com- puter, a chimpanzee, or a dolphin, this being should be counted a person. Kinds of Persons
  • 19. A familiar and very simple conceptual sys- tem comprising three parameters, hue, satura- tion, and brightness, is able to capture and to distinguish every actual and possible instance of the phenomenon color (Munsell, 1946). In the same way, a (vastly more complex) conceptual system for the science of psychology must be able to provide conceptual resources for articu- lating every fact and possible fact about persons (qua persons, vs., e.g., as biological organisms). If it is to do so, it must not merely capture the concept of “person” in general, but must also 3PERSON AND SELF T hi s do cu m en t is co py ri gh te
  • 23. an d is no t to be di ss em in at ed br oa dl y. provide resources for capturing and distinguish- ing what kinds of persons there are. Whether we are psychologists, historians, biographers, nov- elists, or just individuals leading our everyday social lives, we do and we must distinguish persons, not merely on the basis of identity (“that’s John Smith”), but on basis of the kinds
  • 24. of persons they are. The following parametric analysis, adapted from Ossorio (2006), provides the conceptual resources for doing so: �PC� � �Ds, P, Dr�, Where . . . PC � Person Characteristics Ds � Dispositions, the various personal tendencies or inclinations, ordinarily observable in a person by virtue of a pattern of frequency in his or her behavior. These include Traits (dispositions to engage in a certain kind of behavior such as shy, aggressive, or generous be- havior); Styles (dispositions having to do, not with what a person does, but with how he or she does it [e.g., in a sophisticated, graceful, or awkward fash- ion]); Attitudes (dispositions to regard and treat differ- ent objects [e.g., a religious text or a political candi- date] or certain classes of object [e.g., liberals or conservatives] in certain characteristic ways [e.g., con- temptuously or reverently]); Interests (dispositions to find certain topics [e.g., world affairs, sports, or music] absorbing or captivating). P � Powers, concepts having to do with what is possible and not possible for a given person. These include the person’s Abilities (i.e., capabilities with reference to some kind of achievement such as speak- ing a language, playing the piano, or shooting a bas- ketball); Knowledge (the set of facts the person has the ability to act on, such as the multiplication times tables, the rules of baseball, or the information necessary to repair an automobile engine); and Values (the set of motivational priorities that the person is routinely able to act on, such as a value for honesty, for accumulating wealth, or for an adventurous way of life).
  • 25. Dr � Derivatives, concepts that, unlike the two previ- ous categories, do not have a direct connection to behavior but are defined instead by their reference to Dispositions and Powers. These include States (states of affairs in which there is a systematic difference in the ordinary powers or dispositions of a person, such as being sick, exhausted, or drunk); Capacities (the po- tential to acquire personal characteristics, such as ones to acquire musical skills, learn languages, or play soc- cer); and Embodiment (the physical characteristics of a person, such as being six feet tall, weighing 170 pounds, or having blue eyes; adapted from Ossorio, 2006, pp. 70 –71). In essence, we describe what kind of person John is by giving values to these parameters. As a psychotherapist, organizational person- nel selector, psychological researcher, and more, I might have reason to do this in a highly formalized and rigorous fashion. As a prospective life partner, business associate, friend, or voter, I might do so less formally but, depending on the particulars, no less carefully. In either case, what I am doing is making commitments to some number of these parameters pertaining to the kind of person John is. When I describe him as “ex- traverted,” I commit to (one value of) the Trait parameter; when “flamboyant” to the Style parameter; when “obsessed with making money” to the Values parameter; when “very good with numbers” to the Ability parameter (of course, all of these parameters will have multiple values and will exist in some de-
  • 26. gree— extraversion will not be John’s only trait and he may be somewhat or very outgo- ing). And I am saying in essence that, relative to what can be termed a “standard normal person” (Ossorio, 1983) in his culture, this is the kind of behavior, style, motivational pri- ority, ability, and so forth, that you can expect to find in greater frequency and/or degree when you observe John; this is the kind of person John is. Lest there be confusion, it should be noted that this analysis is not about personality. It is about persons. As such, it extends consider- ably beyond what, if we are faithful to con- sensual English usage, we understand by an individual’s “personality.” Of the above list- ing of 10 person characteristics, only two (traits and styles) clearly pertain to an indi- vidual’s personality (it may be noted, e.g., that every one of the currently popular “big five” personality characteristics [Goldberg, 1993; McAdams & Pals, 2006] is a trait). Two other characteristics, interests and val- ues, could (more arguably) be seen as pertain- ing to personality. However, facts about an individual’s embodiment (“John is six feet tall”), capacities (“Mary has a capacity for learning languages”), states (“Jack has been depressed lately”), abilities (“Jill is capable of writing computer programs”), attitudes (“Scott has a negative attitude toward immi- grants”), and knowledge (“Suzie knows the capitol of every state”) are not personality facts. While personality facts are important ones about persons, they are far from being
  • 27. the only facts, much less the only important facts, about what kind of person a person is. 4 BERGNER T hi s do cu m en t is co py ri gh te d by th e A m er
  • 31. di ss em in at ed br oa dl y. Empirical Foundation: Conceptions Capture Meaning in Actual Usage The formulations of “person” and the para- metric analysis of persons were created for the purpose of demarcating the domain of persons for a science of psychology (Ossorio, 1966/ 1995, 2006); that is, for articulating both what a person is and all of the ways in which one person can be the same as, or different from, another person (cf. hue, saturation, and bright- ness for color). In this section, I will attempt to show that these conceptions, though formulated for such usage, have the advantage of success- fully capturing what amounts to a refined and disambiguated meaning in use of these concepts in ordinary lay usage. In capturing this usage, I will argue further that, per Wittgenstein’s fa-
  • 32. mous dictum that “. . . the meaning of a word is its use in the language” (Wittgenstein, 1953, #43), they in effect become strong candidates for what should be considered the meaning of these person concepts in a science of psychol- ogy. This is based on the contention that, if shown to be coherent, the concept in actual use by people, the distinction they are actually drawing and acting upon, serves better than any other as the premier “expert concept” and should not be disregarded or violated with im- punity in favor of one’s own invented private meaning (Austin, 1956; Hegi & Bergner, 2010; Kelley, 1983; Wittgenstein, 1953). Further, as the concepts in actual use, they enjoy the unique advantage of having an actual empirical basis upon which to ground claims about their mean- ing. Beverley Fehr has observed that, when called upon to define or otherwise explicate the mean- ings of concepts, “. . . people may not necessar- ily produce the full range of important features when asked (a recall task), but ‘know them when they see them’ (. . . a recognition task)” (Fehr, 2006, p. 242). It is an observational com- monplace that people use concepts that embody criteria they are unable to articulate. Asked what time it is, they correctly respond by telling us the time. Asked to describe their mother’s personality, they inform us that she is outgoing, generous, and considerate of others. Asked to give an example of humor, they tell us a joke. However, asked to define or otherwise expli- cate the concepts of “time,” “personality,” or “humor,” they are for the most part at a loss.
  • 33. They possess the correct distinctions, they use the terms correctly, but they cannot articulate well the conceptual criteria they are using in doing so. With this in mind, the question can be raised regarding whether or not the person formula- tions above do in fact capture, not what people can verbally articulate if asked, but how people actually use these conceptions; that is, what distinctions they actually draw and act upon. First, with respect to the definition of “person” stated, many everyday, commonplace observa- tions reveal that people regard and treat persons, both themselves and others, as deliberate actors. That is, they regard and treat them as individu- als who can and do consider behavioral alterna- tives that they understand, choose from among these the one that they enact, and genuinely possess the power to do otherwise. A few rep- resentative examples: (a) Both as individuals and as representatives of institutions (e.g., the legal system), they hold themselves and others responsible for their behavior, implying that these individuals had a choice and could have done otherwise (e.g., they blame others when they are negligent, laud them when they engage in altruistic behavior, or render a guilty verdict as jurors in a court of law). (b) They react differently to unfortunate bodily movements of others (e.g., someone bumping into them) seen as “accidents” than to ones seen as done “de- liberately” or “on purpose.” (c) They routinely enjoin others to entertain certain considerations (e.g., to think about the consequences of a cer-
  • 34. tain action) to influence the choices of these others. (NB: It should perhaps be underscored that this point, as well as the following one, pertain to the meaning in use of a concept, and not to the perennially unsettled issue of the ontological merits of free will vs. deterministic positions.) Further, when entities are known or believed not to possess the ability to engage in deliberate action, even those entities most likely to pass the Turing test and, thus, to be seen as most person-like, we characteristically do not regard them as persons. For example, in a media search of articles on contemporary chess playing and trivia identifying computer programs, I have been unable to find a single claim to the effect that either of them qualified as persons. “If not deliberate action, then not person” seems to be the criterion in use here: if there is no perceived 5PERSON AND SELF T hi s do cu m en t is
  • 39. reason to believe that an entity is capable of considering understood behavioral options and genuinely choosing from among them, then that individual is not seen as an instance of the concept “person.” Describing Persons With regard to the second matter, that of how people describe what kinds of persons they and others are, it is again a matter of everyday observation that, in the face of requests for what kind of person a given individual is, describers invariably respond by making commitments to one or more of the PC parameters listed above. Whether with single labels (e.g., “shy” “consci- entious”) or more protracted descriptions (“He’s the kind of person who, when confronted with difficult situations, enjoys rising to the challenge”), they offer information about the individual’s traits, attitudes, interests, styles, values, capacities, embodiment and so forth (and often descriptions of the degree to which these are the case). Ana is “somewhat shy, very unassuming, places great value on her integrity, wants very much to have children, is interested in and possesses extensive knowledge of pre- Colombian art, has a talent for music, is five feet, six inches tall,” and so forth. Some Relations to Other Formulations As noted above, few explicit formulations of the concept “person” have arisen within psy- chology. The present conceptualization, how- ever, is consistent with a small number of pre-
  • 40. vious ones that have given a central role to choice or agency as the core criterion for per- sonhood. For example, Martin et al. (2010) state that “. . . the ability to make choices and act on these choices to impact one’s own life and the lives of others is the most distinctive feature of personhood . . .” (p. v). Other psychologists who have viewed choice as central to person- hood include Baumeister (2008, 2010), Frankl (1969/2014); Rychlak (1981), and Yalom (1980). Within philosophy, authors whose for- mulations are consistent with the present one in this regard include Chisholm (1982), Hacker (2007), Kierkegaard (1834/1992), and Sartre and Mairet (1948). Also consistent are a number of views approaching the question of person- hood from moral (e.g., Anderson, 2000; Kant, 1797/1996; Taylor, 1989) and from legal (e.g., Taylor, 1985) perspectives, all of which em- body views of persons as choice-making indi- viduals who are responsible for their morally and legally relevant behaviors. In its contention that choice or agency is a core characteristic of what the concept “person” means to people, the present account is incon- sistent with many others that, while not explic- itly addressing the question conceptually, pres- ent us with views of persons at distinct odds with it. The authors of these accounts come both from psychology (e.g., Freud, 1949; Skinner, 1971; Wegner, 2002) and from philosophy (e.g., Honderich, 2002; Smilanski, 2000; G. Strawson, 1994). In one form or another, these authors all view persons as a kind of organism
  • 41. whose behavior is entirely determined by bio- logical, environmental, psychological, and/or social determinants. On the present view, given its conceptual requirement of genuine choice or agency, such “persons” would be regarded pre- cisely as nonpersons. (NB: In a position known as “compatibilism,” which asserts a compatibil- ity between free will and determinism, authors [e.g., Dennett, 2003; Nahmias, 2011] maintain both (a) that persons do in fact engage in activ- ities such as mulling over behavioral alterna- tives, arriving at decisions, and acting in accord with those decisions, implying free will; and (b) that these activities are themselves the inevita- ble products of antecedent causal forces, imply- ing determinism. However, it is very difficult, all behavior remaining in the end the ineluctable outcome of deterministic forces, to see this po- sition as other than a deterministic one [com- pare Honderich, 2002; Hood, 2012].) One other relevant focus in the literature per- tains to the classical distinction between mind and body. In the present context, this becomes the issue of whether a person is essentially a mind (Berkeley, 1710/1970), a body (or even a brain; Churchland, 2013), or a combination of the two that somehow interact (Descartes, 1649/ 1998). With respect to this issue, the present position is essentially identical to that of P. F. Strawson when he famously stated that, What I mean by the concept of a person is the concept of a type of entity such that both predicates ascribing states of consciousness and predicates ascribing corpo- real characteristics, a physical situation, and so forth,
  • 42. are equally applicable to a single individual of that 6 BERGNER T hi s do cu m en t is co py ri gh te d by th e A m er ic
  • 46. ss em in at ed br oa dl y. single type. (Strawson, 1959, p. 102; cf. Hacker, 2007; Harré, 1998) Why Should We Care About the Concept of “Person”? So what? Why should we care about having an optimally formulated concept of “person”? What differences would it make (a) for psychol- ogy as a science, and (b) for individual mem- bers of society, as well as for society at large? Consequences for Psychology as a Science The term “person,” it might be argued, is the central concept in psychology (Bergner, 2010, 2013; Martin et al., 2010; Ossorio, 2006). Why central? The primary focus of the entire field of psychology is persons: their behavior, develop-
  • 47. ment, neural functioning, personality, emotion, intelligence, and more. What integrates the en- tire field, what integrates, all of these apparently so disparate topics, is that they all have refer- ence to the single complex being that is a per- son. They are all about various aspects of per- sons. Thus, having a formulation of what a person is, as well as a system for describing and distinguishing kinds of persons, are, in Natalie Angier’s phrase, “at the heart of the discipline” (Angier, 2009, p. D1). Despite this, we seem little better off than 50 plus years ago when Sigmund Koch “described psychology as singular among scholarly and scientific pursuits in having decided on a set of methods before it defined its proper subject matter” (Robinson, 2001, p. 421). At the outset of this article, I presented a sketch of a hypo- thetical biology teacher who relates to her class on the first day that she cannot define or other- wise formulate the nature of the subject matter of her course. She states that she cannot even tell them what that subject matter is—that is, what the criteria are for inclusion in the set of phenomena under study and thus cannot, strictly speaking, tell them how to identify from the outset what is even to count as a case of that subject matter! This polemic illustrates a num- ber of problems with psychology’s historical failure to settle upon consensus formulations of seminal concepts such as “person”: its failure to articulate the nature of its subject matter, its allowance of differing and inconsistent formu- lations of this (as well as other) core concepts,
  • 48. and its creation thereby of an untenable situa- tion in which researchers claiming to be inves- tigating the same thing might not in fact be doing so. As stated previously, it is a situation of scientific imprecision and confusion, as well as indifference to the problem itself. Social Consequences Martin et al. (2010) have argued that, while psychology has failed by and large to formulate the concept “person,” it has settled on an im- plicit default view of persons that is biologically reductionistic and deterministic in nature, and that this view has very significant social conse- quences (cf. Bergner, 2004). The field and the broader society is being presented with a view that persons are organisms whose behavior is biologically determined; in effect, that a person is, in E.O. Wilson’s phrase, a “marvelous robot . . . wired (neuronally) with awesome precision” (Wilson, 1999, p. 53). The social impact of such a view of persons being presented to society is a matter of considerable importance (Baumeis- ter, 2008; Bergner, 2004; Martin et al., 2010). As Martin et al. express the matter, By reducing persons to their physical or biological constituents in an attempt to meet the demands of a naturalist paradigm, psychologists strip humans of what matters to them most and render explanations of human action and experience that are distorted and malformed, if not wholly alien. (p. 8) Among the features so reduced and distorted, these authors contend, are moral accountability,
  • 49. human rights and responsibilities, and any no- tions of praise- or blameworthiness. Further, a growing empirical literature on the effects of belief in free will versus determinism attests that the disbelief in free will inherent in viewing persons as nonagents is associated with a wide variety of antisocial outcomes. These include (a) an increased likelihood that people will act in socially irresponsible ways such as cheating and refusing to help others (Baumeis- ter, Masicampo, & DeWall, 2009); (b) lower moral standards, disbelief in the legitimacy of moral rules, and decreased levels of both mean- ing and satisfaction in life (Bergner & Ramon, 2013); (c) greater levels of aggressive behavior and a reduced willingness to help others (Baumeister, 2008); and (d) higher rates of cheating and of overpaying oneself for perfor- mance on a task (Vohs & Schooler, 2008). 7PERSON AND SELF T hi s do cu m en t is
  • 54. Thus, the presentation to the public of a con- ception of persons as choice-making deliberate actors is to the advantage both of individual persons and of society in general. Finally, both Bergner (2004) and Martin et al. (2010) have argued that biologically reduction- istic and deterministic views of persons under- mine critical social institutions and academic disciplines (including psychology). The former author expresses this as follows: With the disappearance of the concept of a person (as a choice-making agent) must come a corresponding disappearance of the conceptual apparatuses of our current seminal social institutions (e.g., the family, the judicial system, religion, and the educational system) and many other disciplines aside from psychology (e.g., ethics, law, sociology, economics, history, and political science). . . . If we dismiss the categories of ‘choosing,’ ‘intending,’ ‘acting for a reason,’ ‘acting deliberately,’ and so forth, as designating legitimate, scientifically acceptable states of affairs, then consider the following statements. From law: ‘Murder in the first degree, implying the planned, premeditated act of killing another, ought to be punished more severely than manslaughter.’ From ethics and religion: ‘The concepts of moral ‘right’ and ‘wrong’ (as well as the latter’s religious counterpart, ‘sin’), conceptually im- ply the ability of an individual to choose from among understood behavioral options; a completely deter- mined movement on the part of a person . . . is ineli- gible for such attributions.’ . . . If we accept the reduc- tive views, the concept of a (choice-making) person and its logical sequelae become inherently defective attempts to account for what can only legitimately be
  • 55. accounted for biologically (2004, p. 7). The Concept of “Self” When philosophers use a word—“knowledge,” “be- ing,” “object,” “I,” “proposition,” and “name”—and try to grasp the essence of the thing, one must ask oneself: is the word ever actually used in this way in the language game which is its original home? What we do is to bring words back from their metaphysical to their everyday use.—Ludwig Wittgenstein, 1953, #116 . . . it is, rather, of the essence of our investigation that . . . we want to understand something that is already in plain view. For this is what we seem in some sense not to understand.—Ludwig Wittgenstein, 1953, # 89 A second longstanding and thus far unre- solved problem in both psychology and philos- ophy concerns the nature of the self (Baumeis- ter, 2008, 2010; Guenther & Alicke, 2013; Harré, 1998; Martin et al., 2010; McGinn, 2004; VandenBos, 2007). In its entry on this term, VandenBos (2007) states that “. . . the term’s use in psychology is extremely wide ranging and lacks uniformity” (p. 827), while Harré (1998) asserts that, “The study of no aspect of humanity is so marked by muddled thinking and confusion of thought as this one” (p. 2). In the same vein, Martin et al. (2010) attest that, With all of this publishing on the topic (of self), it might be supposed that psychologists have come to an
  • 56. agreed understanding of what the self is or, at the very least, have given considerable attention to conceptual issues of this kind. Unfortunately, for the most part, nothing could be further from the truth. (p. 7) When they take up matters pertaining to the self, theorists and researchers approach it from a myriad of directions. Thus, we have literatures on the self-concept, self-esteem, self-regulation, self-presentation, self-actualization, self- knowledge, self-deception, the socially con- structed self, and much more (Baumeister, 2010; Guenther & Alicke, 2013). Given this diversity, and given the “muddle” just alluded to, it becomes difficult to see what might be at the heart of all of these topics by virtue of which each calls itself a topic “about the self.” So just what if anything at all is this entity that we call the “self” or the “I”? Historically, on most accounts, authors have been inclined to see this term as designating an “inner” entity, one that is deep, mysterious, ineffable, and per- haps ineluctably hidden from view. This has been so whether the author wished to endorse the existence of such an entity or to deny it (e.g., Harré, 1998). So, to take up some of the histor- ically most prominent answers given, is the self an immaterial Cartesian thinking substance akin to the traditional notion of the “soul” (Des- cartes, 1649/1998)? Is it an inferable but itself not directly observable entity, perhaps transcen- dental in nature (Kant, 1781–1787/1999), that is the inner source of consciousness, thought, memory, feeling, and instigation of action (e.g., James’ [1890] “I” or “pure ego”)? On negative,
  • 57. “no such entity” accounts, is the so-called self merely a Humean “bundle” of associated mem- ories, thoughts, and experiences that, given our inability to observe some inner “I” at their source, must collectively be considered the to- tality of what constitutes the self (Hume, 1739 – 1740/2003); compare Dennett, 1986; Hood, 2012, on self as a convenient fiction)? Is it essentially a social construction; that is, an “in- ventory of self-attributes or conceptions” ac- quired “through social observation, interaction, 8 BERGNER T hi s do cu m en t is co py ri gh te d
  • 61. d is no t to be di ss em in at ed br oa dl y. and language acquisition” (Gergen, 1977, p. 143; Gergen, 2011; McAdams, 2013; Mead, 1934)? Is it the individual’s body, or perhaps just his or her brain (Churchland, 2013; Hood, 2012; Olson, 1997)? The consensus at the pres- ent time seems to be that this is one of those perennially intractable problems, or even mys- teries (McGinn, 1993, 2004), on which we have not been able to come to any broadly accepted
  • 62. agreement (Baumeister, 2010; Guenther & Al- icke, 2013; Harré, 1998; Martin et al., 2010; VandenBos, 2007). If we turn to the Wittgensteinian “original home” of the words “self” and “I,” however, we find that their use in everyday affairs is entirely clear and unproblematic. In such use, no one seems to have a problem understanding what is meant by these terms. With respect to “I,” or- dinary people and geniuses alike exhibit this understanding when they say such things as “I think that X,” “I am intending to do Y,” “I see myself as Z,” and so forth. The very young child proclaims, “I want candy,” while Albert Ein- stein asserts, “As I have said so many times, God doesn’t play dice with the world” (Her- manns, 1983, p. 58). With respect to “self,” much the same is true. When used in common usage, it is usually as a prefix (as in “self- taught” or “self-effacing”) or in conjunction with another syllable (as in “myself” or “her- self”). Again, such use (e.g., if I say, “I did it myself”) is generally clear and unproblematic, and raises few questions regarding what is meant. If our conception be granted that a person is, paradigmatically, an embodied, conscious indi- vidual whose history is a history of deliberate action; and if what can be said about the char- acteristics of persons can be captured by artic- ulating any given person’s dispositions (traits, attitudes, interests, and styles), powers (abili- ties, knowledge, and values), and derivatives (states, capacities, and embodiments), a certain
  • 63. formulation of what “I” (or “self”) means is suggested. “I” means simply and essentially “this person”; that is, the holistically consid- ered, flesh and blood individual I intend when I use the terms “I” or “me” or “myself,” as op- posed to “that person,” the specific person I intend when I say “he” or “you” or “herself.” When I say “I” or “me”—when I refer to my self—I am merely designating a certain person, a certain embodied, conscious, deliberate actor of whom both mental (“I think”) and physical (“I walk”) actions are aptly predicated (cf. P. Strawson, 1959), and I am distinguishing this person from other persons. In particular, I (or any person making this utterance) am designat- ing the person who is the author of the utter- ance. What I am not designating is an immate- rial substance, a certain body, a certain brain, a certain social construction, a certain bundle of associated memories, thoughts, and experi- ences, or some alleged but never observed inner entity at their source. Just me, the guy who is writing this sentence, the one with this embodi- ment, this history of deliberate action, this per- sonal world, this consciousness, these beliefs, these values, and so forth. And when I say “him” or “her”—let us say, “Abraham Lin- coln”—I simply intend that person, the one with that embodiment, that history of deliberate action, that world, those beliefs, and so forth. The proposed formulations of “person” and “person characteristics” here allow for a star- tlingly simple answer to a question that has long perplexed, and continues to perplex, psycholo-
  • 64. gists, philosophers, and thinking persons gener- ally. This answer, it must be said, often comes as a disappointing one to those with whom I have shared it. Given the nature of much his- torical thought on the concept, something deeper, more profound, and more arcane seems called for. However, my primary task here is that of determining what, if we respect the meaning in use of this concept in the “language game which is its original home” (Wittgenstein, 1953, #116), the term actually means. (NB: the term’s etymology is “old English self, seolf, sylf ‘one’s own person’” [www.etymonline.com/ index.php?term�self]). My second task is that of demonstrating how, if we simply adopt this meaning in use, so many historical problems are avoided and so much falls into place in the study of the self. Let me explain. Problems Avoided The formulation of self as “this person” not only provides a positive answer to the question of the meaning of this term, but in doing so does not get us into the kinds of problems in the first place that previous formulations have encoun- tered. (a) Unlike the immaterial soul/transcen- dental ego accounts, it does not require belief in an unobservable immaterial entity, nor does it 9PERSON AND SELF T hi s
  • 69. br oa dl y. http://www.etymonline.com/index.php?term=self http://www.etymonline.com/index.php?term=self generate the attendant mystery of how such an entity could interact with a physical body. (b) Unlike the inner experiential and agentic self, the present account does not send one on an introspective search for some underlying entity which is the source of these experiences and actions, which search, as many have attested (e.g., Harré, 1998; Hood, 2012; Hume, 1739 – 1740/2003), has always proven futile. (c) Un- like Hume’s (1739 –1740/2003) notion that the so-called “self” is a fictional entity consisting of nothing over and above a bundle of asso- ciated memories, thoughts, feelings, and other experiences, or Dennett’s (1986) assertion that the self, like the notion of “center of gravity,” is merely a convenient fiction, the present account does not posit the seemingly absurd notions that there are free floating thoughts and experiences that have no actual author or owner (Reid, 1785/1986; P. Straw- son, 1959), or that there is no such thing as the self. Instead, it simply identifies this owner and this self with this person (“I”), this quite observable, embodied individual with this history of deliberate action (both mental
  • 70. and physical) and this collectivity of person characteristics. (d) Unlike the self as a social construction, the present formulation does not confuse one’s conception of oneself, which admittedly consists of socially acquired lin- guistic descriptors, with the self itself; in- stead, it identifies the latter, a flesh and blood person, with the subject or the “haver” of these descriptors, thereby avoiding a problem curiously similar to the no-ownership one en- countered by Hume. Further, (e) unlike the self-as-brain or self- as-body solutions, the present one does not do radical violence to the meaning of the concept “I” in actual usage (e.g., when I say, “I went to the store,” I do not mean that my brain went to the store; or when I say, “I’m im- pressed with the work of my graduate assis- tant,” I do not mean that my body is im- pressed with his work). (f) The present account passes many of the bizarre, yet tell- ing, thought experiments that philosophers are so fond of posing. For example, McGinn (2004) proposes one in which, in the future, brain reprogramming becomes a possibility. One day I am seized, my brain is stripped of its current contents, and new content pro- grammed in from the brain of Adolf Hitler. Upon awakening from the operation, I (or somebody?) find that I now have all the mem- ories, knowledge, personality traits, and sense of identity of Adolf Hitler. Is it still me? On the self-as-brain account, where same brain is equivalent to same person, the answer would
  • 71. have to be “yes.” However, both intuitively and on the present account, where self is equated with this person with this history of deliberate action and these person character- istics (traits, attitudes, interests, values, knowledge, etc.), the answer would clearly be “no.” (g) Finally, the present formulation ac- commodates the observation of William James (1890) and many others since (e.g., Guenther & Alicke, 2013; McAdams, 2013) that self can be regarded both as subject (as in “I memorized the poem.”) and as object (as in “I like how I look in my new suit.”); however, no special distinction is required on the pres- ent account to capture the simple fact that I sometimes describe the person who is me as an actor, thinker, or experiencer, and other times as the object of my own thoughts and observations. The concept of “I” or “self” is almost ev- erywhere conflated with the matter of per- sonal identity (Olson, 2016). The notion of “I” as this person, however, permits a discon- nection of the two notions. For example, to cite a famous fictional invention from the TV series Star Trek, a man named “Kirk” enters a device known as a “transporter” that demate- rializes him and subsequently rematerializes him (or somebody?) in a distant location. On the present account, when either of these (one or two) individuals utters the word “I” to refer to himself (e.g., “I am expecting an attack from the Klingons”), in each case he means “this person”—the specific person who is the author of the utterance. Whether the two are
  • 72. or are not the same person is a separate ques- tion. While the issue of identity is an impor- tant one in its own right, the present concep- tion of “I” or “self” separates the matter of what these terms mean from the matter of what it means to say that A and B are the same person. (NB: The present formulation, however, may also be useful, as in the brain reprogramming thought experiment above, in discussions of the latter topic.) 10 BERGNER T hi s do cu m en t is co py ri gh te d by
  • 76. is no t to be di ss em in at ed br oa dl y. Integrates the Field of Self Psychology Finally, the formulation of self as “this person,” aside from representing a clearer, simpler, and more empirically grounded for- mulation of this concept, easily and common- sensically integrates the many phenomena that have been investigated historically in connection with the notion of self. It does so by identifying and conceptualizing the central
  • 77. entity around which this entire area is orga- nized. For example, my “self-concept” as commonly understood can be formulated as my conception of this person—my culturally, socially, and linguistically constructed formu- lation of who I am in the social scheme of things (“male,” “Caucasian,” “married,” “fa- ther,” “college professor,” “clinical psychol- ogist,” “politically progressive,” etc.). My “sense of self” can be conceptualized as my phenomenological experiencing of this per- son as a conscious being in matters such as my feelings of agency, my sense of personal identity through time, my ongoing awareness of my own inner states, my experiencing and acting upon the world from a certain location vis-à-vis other persons and physical entities, and much more (Baumeister, 2010; Harré, 1998; Heron, 1992; McAdams, 2013; Taylor, 1989). My “self-esteem” can be formulated as the overall worth or value that I appraise this person as having (cf. Baumeister, Campbell, Krueger, & Vohs, 2003). Finding my “real self” or “authentic self,” and actualizing this self can be formulated as this person discov- ering and pursuing a set of possibilities in life (vocations, relationships, interests, activities, and ways of life) to which I discover that I have strong intrinsic positive relationships (e.g., that I love certain persons, that I find pursuing certain intellectual questions highly meaningful, and that I find coaching youth soccer enormously engrossing; cf. Rogers [1964] on “organismic valuing process”; Campbell [2004] on “finding one’s bliss”). Without further multiplying examples, it is
  • 78. easy to see how the “this person” conception of self coordinates readily with, and serves to integrate, other prominent research topics such as self-regulation, self-presentation, self-enhancement, self-awareness, self- deception, and more. And it is easy to see how almost nothing is lost in doing so. Strong research programs on all of the topics just listed remain important and viable enter- prises. The only things lost are the conceptual muddle in which many of these things (espe- cially self-concept and sense of self) are con- fused with the self itself and our historically futile search for some unobservable, mysteri- ous, inner entity that we have always seemed to feel must somehow be there. Conclusion In this article, I have attempted to provide sound, rigorous Descriptive Psychologically based solutions to two conceptual problems in psychology and philosophy. Building upon Ossorio’s (1966/1995, 2006) solution to the first of these, that of formulating the concept of a “person,” I have proceeded to provide a new formulation of the second, that of “self.” The first purpose in doing so has been to offer some hopefully useful contributions to re- dressing the much larger critical problem in psychology that, unlike other mature sci- ences, it has still after many years largely failed to arrive at consensus formulations of its core subject matter. The second purpose has been to articulate some important benefits
  • 79. that are gained by having adequate formula- tions of “person” and “self.” References Anderson, D. L. (2000). What is a person? Consor- tium on Cognitive Science Instruction, Illinois State University. Retrieved from http://www.mind .ilstu.edu/curriculum/what_is_a_person/what_is_a_ person.php Angier, N. (2009, July, 21). When ‘what animals do’ doesn’t seem to cover it’. New York Times, D1. Austin, J. (1956). A plea for excuses. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 57, 130. http://dx.doi.org/ 10.1093/aristotelian/57.1.1 Baumeister, R. F. (2008). Free will in scientific psy- chology. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 3, 14 –19. http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/j.1745-6916 .2008.00057.x Baumeister, R. F. (2010). The self. In R. Baumeister & E. Finkel (Eds.), Advanced social psychology: The state of the science (pp. 139 –175). New York, NY: Oxford University Press. Baumeister, R. F., Campbell, J. D., Krueger, J. I., & Vohs, K. D. (2003). Does high self-esteem cause better performance, interpersonal success, happi- 11PERSON AND SELF T hi
  • 84. ed br oa dl y. http://www.mind.ilstu.edu/curriculum/what_is_a_person/what_i s_a_person.php http://www.mind.ilstu.edu/curriculum/what_is_a_person/what_i s_a_person.php http://www.mind.ilstu.edu/curriculum/what_is_a_person/what_i s_a_person.php http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/aristotelian/57.1.1 http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/aristotelian/57.1.1 http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/j.1745-6916.2008.00057.x http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/j.1745-6916.2008.00057.x ness, or healthier lifestyles? Psychological Science in the Public Interest, 4, 144. http://dx.doi.org/10 .1111/1529-1006.01431.ISSN1529-1006 Baumeister, R. F., Masicampo, E. J., & Dewall, C. N. (2009). Prosocial benefits of feeling free: Disbelief in free will increases aggression and reduces help- fulness. Personality and Social Psychology Bulle- tin, 35, 260 –268. http://dx.doi.org/10.1177/ 0146167208327217 Bergner, R. (2004). Is it all really biological? Journal of Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology, 24, 3049. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/h0091236
  • 85. Bergner, R. (2006). An open letter from Isaac New- ton to the field of psychology. In K. Davis & R. Bergner (Eds.), Advances in descriptive psychol- ogy (Vol. 8, pp. 69 – 80). Ann Arbor, MI: Descrip- tive Psychology Press. Bergner, R. (2010). What is descriptive psychology? An introduction. In K. Davis, F. Lubuguin, & W. Schwartz (Eds.), Advances in descriptive psychol- ogy (Vol. 9, pp. 325–360). Ann Arbor, MI: De- scriptive Psychology Press. Bergner, R. (2011). What is behavior? And so what? New Ideas in Psychology, 29, 147–155. http://dx .doi.org/10.1016/j.newideapsych.2010.08.001 Bergner, R. (2013). All the world’s a stage: A person- centered view of science. In R. Bergner, K. Davis, F. Lubuguin, & W. Schwartz (Eds.), Advances in descriptive psychology (Vol. 10, pp. 7–18). Ann Arbor, MI: Descriptive Psychology Press. Bergner, R. (2016). What is “behavior?” And why is it not reducible to biological states of affairs? Journal of Theoretical and Philosophical Psychol- ogy, 36, 41–55. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/teo00 00026 Bergner, R., & Ramon, A. (2013). Some implications of belief in love, free will, and non-reductionism. The Journal of Social Psychology, 153, 598 – 618. http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/00224545.2013.798249 Berkeley, G. (1970). Treatise concerning the princi- ples of human knowledge. New York, NY: Bobbs- Merrill. (Original work published 1710)
  • 86. Campbell, J. (2004). Pathways to bliss: Mythology and personal transformation. New York, NY: New World Library. Chisholm, R. (1982). Human freedom and the self. In G. Watson (Ed.), Free will (pp. 24 –35). Oxford: Oxford University Press. Churchland, P. (2013). Touching a nerve: The self as brain. New York, NY: Norton. Colman, A. M. (2006). Oxford dictionary of psychol- ogy. Oxford, United Kingdom: Oxford University Press. Dennett, D. (1986). The self as a center of narrative gravity. In F. Kessel, P. Cole, & D. Johnson (Eds.), Self and consciousness: Multiple perspectives (pp. 103–115). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum. Dennett, D. (2003). Freedom evolves. New York, NY: Penguin. Descartes, R. (1998). The passions of the soul (D. A. Cress, Trans.). Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publish- ing. (Original work published 1649) Engler, B. (2009). Personality theories: An introduc- tion. Boston, MA: Houghton Mifflin. Fehr, B. (2006). The prototype approach to studying love. In R. Sternberg & K. Weis (Eds.), The new psychology of love (pp. 225–248). New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
  • 87. Feist, J., Feist, G., & Roberts, T. (2013). Theories of personality (8th ed.). New York, NY: McGraw- Hill. Frankl, V. (2014). The will to meaning. New York, NY: Meridian. (Original work published 1969) Freud, S. (1949). An outline of psychoanalysis. New York, NY: Norton. Gergen, K. (1977). The social construction of self- knowledge. In T. Mischel (Ed.), The self, psycho- logical and philosophical issues (pp. 139 –l69). Oxford, United Kingdom: Blackwell. Gergen, K. (2011). The self as social construction. Psychological Studies, 58, 108116. http://dx.doi .org/10.1007/s12646-011-0066-1 Goldberg, L. R. (1993). The structure of phenotypic personality traits. American Psychologist, 48, 26 – 34. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/0003-066X.48.1.26 Guenther, C., & Alicke, M. (2013). The psychology of the self. Psychology. http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/ obo/9780199828340-0093 Hacker, P. M. S. (2007). Human nature: The catego- rial framework. Malden, MA: Blackwell. http://dx .doi.org/10.1002/9780470692165 Harré, H. R. (1998) The singular self. Los Angeles, CA: Sage. Harri, R., & Tissaw, M. (2005). Wittgenstein and psychology: A practical guide. Aldershott, Hamp-
  • 88. shire, United Kingdom: Ashgate. Hegi, K., & Bergner, R. (2010). What is love? An empirically-based essentialist account. Journal of Social and Personal Relationships, 27, 620 – 636. http://dx.doi.org/10.1177/0265407510369605 Hergenhahn, B., & Olson, M. (2007). An introduc- tion to theories of personality (7th ed.). Upper Saddle River, NJ: Prentice Hall. Hermanns, W. (1983). Einstein and the poet. Welles- ley, MA: Branden Books. Heron, J. (1992). Feeling and personhood: Psychol- ogy in another key. London, United Kingdom: Sage. Honderich, T. (2002). How free are you? The deter- minism problem (2nd ed.). Oxford, United King- dom: Oxford University Press. Hood, B. (2012). The self illusion: How the social brain creates identity. New York, NY: Oxford University Press. 12 BERGNER T hi s do cu m
  • 93. y. http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/1529-1006.01431.ISSN1529-1006 http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/1529-1006.01431.ISSN1529-1006 http://dx.doi.org/10.1177/0146167208327217 http://dx.doi.org/10.1177/0146167208327217 http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/h0091236 http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.newideapsych.2010.08.001 http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.newideapsych.2010.08.001 http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/teo0000026 http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/teo0000026 http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/00224545.2013.798249 http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/s12646-011-0066-1 http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/s12646-011-0066-1 http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/0003-066X.48.1.26 http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/obo/9780199828340-0093 http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/obo/9780199828340-0093 http://dx.doi.org/10.1002/9780470692165 http://dx.doi.org/10.1002/9780470692165 http://dx.doi.org/10.1177/0265407510369605 Hume, D. (2003). A treatise of human nature. Mine- ola, NY: Dover Publications. (Original work pub- lished 1739 –1740) James, W. (1890). The principles of psychology. New York, NY: Holt. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/11059- 000 Kant, I. (1996). The metaphysics of morals. Cam- bridge, United Kingdom: Cambridge University Press. (Original work published 1797) http://dx.doi .org/10.1017/CBO9780511809644
  • 94. Kant, I. (1999). Critique of pure reason. Cambridge, United Kingdom: Cambridge University Press. (Original work published 1781–1787) Kelley, H. H. (1983). Love and commitment. In E. Berscheid, A. Christensen, J. H. Harvey, T. L. Huston, G. Levinger, . . . D. R. Peterson (Eds.), Close relationships (pp. 265–314). New York, NY: Freeman. Kierkegaard, S. (1992). Either/or. London: Penguin. (Original work published 1834) Martin, J., Sugarman, J., & Hickinbottom, S. (2010). Persons: Understanding psychological selfhood and agency. New York, NY: Springer. http://dx .doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4419-1065-3 McAdams, D. (2013). The psychological self as ac- tor, agent, and author. Perspectives in Psycholog- ical Science, 8, 272–295. http://dx.doi.org/10 .1177/1745691612464657 McAdams, D. P., & Pals, J. L. (2006). A new Big Five: Fundamental principles for an integrative science of personality. American Psychologist, 61, 204 –217. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/0003-066X.61 .3.204 McGinn, C. (1993). Problems in philosophy: The limits of inquiry. Oxford, United Kingdom: Black- well Publishers. McGinn, C. (2004). Eternal question, timeless ap- proaches. Lectures in the Barnes and Noble Audio Series.
  • 95. Mead, G. (1934). Mind, self, and society. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press. Mervis, C., & Rosch, E. (1981). Categorization of natural objects. Annual Review of Psychology, 32, 89 –113. http://dx.doi.org/10.1146/annurev.ps.32 .020181.000513 Munsell, A. H. (1946). A Color Notation: An illus- trated system defining all colors and their relations by measured scales of hue, value and chroma (15th ed.). Baltimore, MD: Munsell Color Co. Nahmias, E. (2011). Intuitions about free will, deter- minism, and bypassing. In R. Kane (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of free will (pp. 555–576). Ox- ford, United Kingdom: Oxford University Press. http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/oxfordhb/97801953 99691.003.0029 Olson, E. (1997). The human animal: Personal iden- tity without psychology. New York, NY: Oxford University Press. Olson, E. T. (2016). Personal identity. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Spring 2016 ed.). Retrieved from http://plato .stanford.edu/archives/spr2016/entries/identity- personal/;10.1002/9781118922590.ch7 Ossorio, P. G. (1983). A multicultural psychology. In K. Davis & R. Bergner (Eds.), Advances in de- scriptive psychology (Vol. 3, pp. 13– 44). Green- wich, CT: JAI Press.
  • 96. Ossorio, P. G. (1995). Persons. Ann Arbor, MI: Descriptive Psychology Press. (Original work pub- lished 1966) Ossorio, P. G. (2006). The behavior of persons. Ann Arbor, MI: Descriptive Psychology Press. Reid, T. (1986). Essays on the intellectual powers of man. Charlottesville, VA: Lincoln Rembrandt Publishers. (Original work published 1785) Robinson, D. N. (2001). Sigmund Kochphilosophi- cally speaking. American Psychologist, 56, 420 – 424. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/0003-066X.56.5 .420 Rogers, C. R. (1964). Toward a modern approach to values: The valuing process in the mature person. The Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology, 68, 160 –167. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/h0046419 Rosch, E. H. (1973). Natural categories. Cognitive Psychology, 4, 328 –350. http://dx.doi.org/10 .1016/0010-0285(73)90017-0 Rychlak, J. (1981). Introduction to personality and personality theory. Boston, MA: Houghton Mif- flin. Sartre, J.-P., & Mairet, P. (1948). Existentialism and humanism. London: Methuen. Skinner, B. F. (1971). Beyond freedom and dignity. New York, NY: Knopf. Smilanski, S. (2000). Free will and illusion. Oxford,
  • 97. United Kingdom: Oxford University Press. Strawson, G. (1994). The impossibility of moral re- sponsibility. Philosophical Studies, 75, 524. http:// dx.doi.org/10.1007/BF00989879 Strawson, P. F. (1959). Individuals: An essay in descriptive metaphysics. London, United King- dom: Routledge. http://dx.doi.org/10.4324/ 9780203221303 Taylor, C. (1985). The concept of a person. Philo- sophical papers (Vol. 1). Cambridge, United Kingdom: Cambridge University Press. Taylor, C. (1989). Sources of the self: The making of the modern identity. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Thompson, C. (2010, June, 16). Smarter than you think: What is I. B. M.’s Watson? The New York Times Magazine. VandenBos, G. R. (2007). APA dictionary of psy- chology. Washington, DC: American Psychologi- cal Association. Vohs, K. D., & Schooler, J. W. (2008). The value of believing in free will: Encouraging a belief in 13PERSON AND SELF T hi s
  • 102. br oa dl y. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/11059-000 http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/11059-000 http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511809644 http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511809644 http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4419-1065-3 http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4419-1065-3 http://dx.doi.org/10.1177/1745691612464657 http://dx.doi.org/10.1177/1745691612464657 http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/0003-066X.61.3.204 http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/0003-066X.61.3.204 http://dx.doi.org/10.1146/annurev.ps.32.020181.000513 http://dx.doi.org/10.1146/annurev.ps.32.020181.000513 http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/oxfordhb/9780195399691.003.0029 http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/oxfordhb/9780195399691.003.0029 http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2016/entries/identity- personal/;10.1002/9781118922590.ch7 http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2016/entries/identity- personal/;10.1002/9781118922590.ch7 http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2016/entries/identity- personal/;10.1002/9781118922590.ch7 http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/0003-066X.56.5.420 http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/0003-066X.56.5.420 http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/h0046419 http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/0010-0285%2873%2990017-0 http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/0010-0285%2873%2990017-0 http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/BF00989879 http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/BF00989879 http://dx.doi.org/10.4324/9780203221303 http://dx.doi.org/10.4324/9780203221303
  • 103. determinism increases cheating. Psychological Science, 19, 4954. http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/j .1467-9280.2008.02045.x Wegner, D. (2002). The illusion of conscious will. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Wilson, E. O. (1999). The biological basis of moral- ity. Atlantic Monthly Online, 1–11. Wittgenstein, L. (1953). Philosophical Investiga- tions. New York, NY: Macmillan. Yalom, I. (1980). Existential psychotherapy. New York, NY: Basic Books. Received May 25, 2016 Revision received December 12, 2016 Accepted December 15, 2016 � 14 BERGNER T hi s do cu m en t
  • 108. http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9280.2008.02045.x http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9280.2008.02045.xWhat Is a Person? What Is the Self? Formulations for a Science of PsychologyThe Concept of a “Person”The Proposed FormulationA Paradigm Case, Not a DefinitionNo Consciousness, No PersonsPersons Not Always Behaving DeliberatelyImplicationKinds of PersonsEmpirical Foundation: Conceptions Capture Meaning in Actual UsageDescribing PersonsSome Relations to Other FormulationsWhy Should We Care About the Concept of “Person”?Consequences for Psychology as a ScienceSocial ConsequencesThe Concept of “Self”Problems AvoidedIntegrates the Field of Self PsychologyConclusionReferences