SlideShare a Scribd company logo
1 of 22
Download to read offline
University of Utah
Aristotle's Theory of Revolution: Looking at the Lockean Side
Author(s): Leslie Friedman Goldstein
Source: Political Research Quarterly, Vol. 54, No. 2 (Jun., 2001), pp. 311-331
Published by: Sage Publications, Inc. on behalf of the University of Utah
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/449159
Accessed: 21-08-2017 21:20 UTC
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
http://about.jstor.org/terms
Sage Publications, Inc., University of Utah are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize,
preserve and extend access to Political Research Quarterly
This content downloaded from 132.174.254.72 on Mon, 21 Aug 2017 21:20:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Aristotle's Theory of Revolution:
Looking at the Lockean Side
LESLIE FRIEDMAN GOLDSTEIN, UNIVERSITY OF DELAWARE
This article provides a detailed account of the theory of revolution pre-
sented in Books IV-VI of Aristotle's Politics and argues that despite impor-
tant differences of emphasis, rhetoric, and tone, there is a surprising
degree of similarity to the theory of revolution familiar to Americans from
John Locke's Second Treatise of Government. Aristotle and Locke share the
views that governments must avoid oppressing their subjects if they are
to avoid being overthrown, that revolution against oppressive rulers is
inevitable, that security for property would have a central place in the
avoidance of oppression, and that the succumbing to the temptations of
power on the part of ruling groups is the fundamental provocation of rev-
olution. This aspect of Aristotle's political thought has been little noticed,
but is an important dimension of it. Moreover, it provides a certain depth
of insight into that side of Locke's thought that most sharply contrasts
with Hobbes's thought, namely Locke's distrust of the corrupting force of
political power.
In Books IV-VI of Politics Aristotle supplemented the Socratic options for
stemming abuses of political power-the teaching of moderation and the luring
of potential tyrants toward philosophy-by invoking the low but solid ground of
the rulers' self-interest in staying in power. The core premises of the Aristotelian
teaching on sedition are essentially a "crime doesn't pay" story for rulers. These
premises were then available for Locke's much later elaboration when he-like
Aristotle suspicious of the corrupting force of political power-needed an alter-
native to Hobbes's absolutist political conclusions.
This claim about the core of Aristotle's teaching on sedition sheds significant
new light on Aristotle's maxim that the political theorist must elaborate not only
the best regime for an ideal situation but should also provide guidance for poli-
tics "based on a [given] presupposition" (Politics IV, 1, 1288b 28-30).1 Locke's
supposition is emphatically that what people want from politics is the preserva-
tion of their lives, liberties, and properties. Aristotle argues in Book III that
1 Translations generally follow Lord (1984). Where they differ, they are my own.
Poliitical Research Quarterly, Vol. 54 (June 2001): pp. 311-331
311
This content downloaded from 132.174.254.72 on Mon, 21 Aug 2017 21:20:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Political Research Quarterly
people form their political association for the good life, a life of happiness, or
human flourishing. Happiness requires that people of good character be formed.
But it turns out in Books IV-VI that, while a few are motivated by the desire for
honor, most people most of the time are motivated by concern for their property
and their physical dignity and security Genuinely good people, who have the
desire and capacity to serve the public good, rarely hold political power. Even
when they do hold power, their appetites and passions open them to being cor-
rupted if legal institutions are not structured in such a way as to check their
power (III, 3: 1287a 31-32). Consequently, the "given supposition" typically in
play in Aristotle's prescriptions for real-world politics may be not so far from the
world that Locke describes.
The argument here does not rely on a view that John Locke was some sort of
latter-day Thomist, who like St. Thomas took his bearings from a law of nature that
amounted to an adaptation of the concept of natural justice, or what was right
according to nature, found in Aristotle.2 To the contrary, one can take as a point of
departure that: "It is on the basis of Hobbes's view of the law of nature that Locke
opposes Hobbes's conclusions. He tries to show that Hobbes's principle-the right
of self-preservation-far from favoring absolute government, requires limited gov-
ernment" (Strauss 1953: 231-32; for a similar view see also Cox 1960 and 1982;
Macpherson 1962; Goldwin 1987; M. Zuckert 1994: 234-237 and 240; but cf.
Grant 1987; Simmons' 1993, and the preponderance of Locke scholarship cited
therein for the view that Locke's state of nature differs radically from that of
Hobbes). Whatever may be Locke's similarities with Hobbes, it is nonetheless clear
that those of Locke's "conclusions" that amount to his theory of revolution openly,
deliberately, and directly opposed Hobbes's view condemning revolutionary resist-
ance to oppressive government (as expressed, e.g., in Leviathan, ch. 20).
It is the argument of this article that most of the core premises of Locke's
theory of revolution are present in Aristotle's political writings. The sole exception
to this claim, albeit an important exception, is Locke's grounding of the right of
revolution in the rhetoric of pre-political inalienable rights; such rhetoric is absent
in Aristotle. The claim is not that Locke took his premises directly from Aristo-
tle-this article is not a biographical exercise.3 Rather it is an essay on Aristotle's
political thought, an essay in the spirit of the argument of Gadamer (1975: espe-
2 Cf. Barker (1962) lxi-lxii.
3 As a strictly historical matter, while Locke may in fact have adapted both his rhetorical approach
and the substance of his justification of revolution from some of the things Aristotle says, there are
numerous conceivable alternative sources of influence that intervened in the two thousand years
that separate the two men, which also may have helped to shape Locke's thinking on a popular
right of revolution. These range from Roman theories of popular control over the emperor, to feudal
theories of limits on kingship, to church governance theories of both the conciliarists and monar-
chomachs, to common law traditions (see, e.g., Procop? 1988; Nelson 1988; Dunbabin 1988;
Black 1988; Vincent 1987, ch.3; Myers 1982 and the numerous sources cited therein).
312
This content downloaded from 132.174.254.72 on Mon, 21 Aug 2017 21:20:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Aristotle's Theory of Revolution
cially 235-40, 258-67, 482-85; see also Yack 1993: 18-21) that one cannot help
but view the thought of philosophers of the past through a prism shaped by the
later philosophic tradition of which one is aware, and by which one's own thought
has to some degree been influenced. Locke depicted in stark and striking tones
the inevitability and justness of revolutionary resistance to tyranny; the clarity and
starkness of Locke's analysis rendered it more difficult, perhaps, for post-Locke
generations to discern the more muted statements along similar lines in Aristotle.
The argument here is that there is much more of the Lockean in Aristotle's
political thought, especially in Books IV through VI of Politics, than is generally
recognized.4 It is at least possible that Locke did find a large part of his inspira-
tion directly in Aristotle's writings, although that is not the point. The point is
that a highlighting of these rather muted Locken themes in Aristotle's theory of
revolution will help bring into clearer focus certain other important elements of
Aristotle's overall political philosophy.
Granted, the discussion of revolution as Aristotle presents it contrasts
sharply with Locke's approach, at least at first glance. Locke is seeking an answer
to the question whether reason, employed as a tool to serve the natural impulse
to comfortable self-preservation, suggests that there must be limits on the power
of government, and, if so, what mechanism can enforce those limits? Aristotle
addresses a different question: How can existing government stave off the sedi-
tion that is the prelude to revolution, and thereby revolution itself?5 Yet despite
the difference in the formal focus of their respective questions, there is a surpris-
ing degree of substantive similarity of content in the answers they generate.
As a prelude to this exercise of recovering Aristotle's teaching on revolution,
this essay, first, outlines the core premises of John Locke's theory of revolution.
Next it describes the sense and extent to which these premises are present in
Aristotle's Politics. The essay concludes with an elaboration of the claim that
attention to this under-explored aspect of Aristotle's thought enriches one's
understanding of both Aristotle and of Locke.
PRELUDE: LOCKE'S THEORY OF REVOLUTION
Summary
Locke's theory of revolution is at once normative and descriptive, and is a
story familiar to most Americans: Governments exist for the purpose of securing
4 This is not, however, a claim that Locke's notion of "rights" is rooted in Aristotle, cf. Miller 1995, 1996.
5 Aristotle also addresses broader questions of how to stave off political change generally-not just
sedition and revolution-but his answer to this general question is undercut by many of his rec-
ommendations concerning the specific question of how to stave off revolution. Specifically, he rec-
ommends that unjust regimes should be reformed (to stave off revolution). Since reform is a kind
of political change, this specific advice undercuts the purported advice against regime change in
general. This undercutting appears to be intentional.
313
This content downloaded from 132.174.254.72 on Mon, 21 Aug 2017 21:20:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Political Research Quarterly
to each member of society his6 life, liberty , and estate. Humans have the impulse
of self-preservation as a matter of nature and therefore the impulse is God-given.
Liberty and property as the means of preservation also belong to individuals,
therefore, as a matter of God-given natural rights. But humans-"the greater part
no strict observers of equity and justice"-have a way of being biased by self-
interest in judging conflicts over where their property ends and another's begins.
Therefore, without government, people would be exposed to "continual dan-
gers"; their lives, freedom and possessions, "very unsafe, very unsecure" (para.
123). So men compact, each with everyone, to form a society where they agree
to put all their forces together under a government whose form will be chosen
by the majority. This government will provide clear rules (a "settled, known
law"), independent judges for disputes, and an executive force to back up judg-
ments. The power of this government must logically be limited by the end for
which it was formed-preservation of the lives, liberties, and fortunes of the soci-
ety.7 If the people in government ever set out to attack these things, which Locke
likes to call collectively the "property" of the members of society, it no longer
makes sense to think of these people as the government. They have abandoned
the job with which they were entrusted, and they should, and will, be fought as
the public enemies they have shown themselves to be. They have introduced a
state of war against their former fellow-citizens by using "force without right"
(para. 232). Between such tyrannical rulers and the society they have attacked
there exists perforce a state of nature, because any two parties who do not share
an agreed-upon judge are in such a condition. And in this condition everyone
has the right of nature, which is to say, the right of self-defense. So revolution
against tyrannical government is by nature right, whether the government be a
single prince, a select few, or a legislature comprised of elected representatives of
the majority.8
6 Locke writes repeatedly of the "uniting into commonwealths" as something that "men" do. See, e.g.,
Second Treatise, para. 124. Hereafter, references to the Second Treatise will give simply the paragraph
number.
7 Individual members of society each join and consent to government with private goals, each to
secure his own comfortable self-preservation. But once society has been formed, the job of gov-
ernment becomes the securing of the lives, liberty and possessions of the society as a whole, in
peace and safety, and the protection of each individual member becomes a secondary consideration
(para. 129, 131, 134, 217). It is to be pursued only "as far as will consist with the public good"
(para. 134).
8 Locke does write that any form of government ("one or many") might behave tyrannically (para.
201). However, he-unlike Aristotle--does not really discuss the possibility that a direct democ-
racy would behave tyrannically toward those outside of government, i.e., outside the majority I
believe this is because Locke's theory of revolution has no solution for such tyranny. His theory
would define it as tyranny, but unlike all other versions of tyranny, it cannot be kept in check by
the fear of a successful revolution by the oppressed majority Without oppression of the "major
force" in a community, or at least a well-grounded fear that the oppression threatens to reach a
314
This content downloaded from 132.174.254.72 on Mon, 21 Aug 2017 21:20:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Aristotle's Theory of Revolution
Operational Premises
Locke's operational theory of revolution, that is, his theory as a matter of
observable practice, of how, when and why revolution occurs is as follows:
1. Inevitability: Human nature being what it is, if government engages in a
"long train" of actions that either attack the lives, freedom, or property of the
majority of the people, or are such that the "precedent and consequences seem
to threaten all," it is inevitable that the people will fight back against the govern-
ment that is attacking them (on long train of abuses, see para. 168, 205, 209,
210, 225, 230; on inevitability, see also para. 94, 149, 224; "First Letter on Tol-
eration," at pp. 53-54.) People threatened by severe misrule "cannot but feel
what they lie under" (para. 225), and the natural response to collective threat is
collective self-defense.
2. As a corollary to inevitability, it follows that attempts at deception of the
mass of the people about the fact of their oppression cannot succeed in staving off revo-
lution. "[T]alk ... hinders men not from feeling."
[W]hen the people are made miserable ... cry up their governors, as much as
you will for sons of Jupiter, let them be sacred and divine, descended or author-
ized from Heaven; give them out for whom or what you please the same will
happen. The people generally ill treated, and contrary to right, will be ready upon
any occasion to ease themselves of a burden that sits heavy upon them. ..
(para.224; Locke's italics).
3. As a general matter, oppressions of a few that are not seen as threats to the
many do not provoke revolution; revolutions are provoked only when the dominant force
in a community-the majority-feels threatened: Because revolution arises as an
expression of the natural impulse to self-preservation (which includes the natu-
ral impulse to retain the liberty and material acquisitions that facilitate preserva-
tion), an isolated, oppressed minority unable to persuade a majority that it too
faces the threat of oppression will not normally, i.e., not rationally, attempt an
overthrow of government, because to do so will be suicidal, and therefore con-
trary to their natural impulses (para. 208; see also 161, 168, 209, 223, 225, 230).
Indeed, even the majority is prone not to stir without substantial provoca-
tion; only a long train of abuses suffices to break through their inertia; revolution,
after all entails substantial risk-would-be perpetrators need to be convinced
that an attempt is worth the "trouble and cost" (para. 176).9
majority eventually, there cannot be rational hope for a victorious revolution, so the minority nor-
mally will simply endure their oppression. Locke's theory does not offer effectual protection for
minority rights (apart from the solace that God and nature are in principle on their side.)
9 My attention was drawn to this passage by Grant (1987: 167).
315
This content downloaded from 132.174.254.72 on Mon, 21 Aug 2017 21:20:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Political Research Quarterly
At this point a divergence arises between Locke's theory of what is right
according to nature and what happens as a matter of the normal patterns of what
might be called brute nature or mere nature. Many regimes that deprive minori-
ties of what is justly, or by nature, their right, will nonetheless, according to the
logic of brute nature, endure.10
Despite Premise 3, however, Locke does admit that some factious people on
occasion have behaved irrationally:
4. Contrary to the natural pattern, sometimes exceptions do occur, in which excep-
tionally ambitious or prideful men stir up sedition to the point of "great disorder" Locke
"grant[s] that the pride, ambition, and turbulency of private men have sometimes
caused great disorders in commonwealths, and factions have been fatal to states
and kingdoms" (para. 230). But he suggests that faction has more often been trig-
gered by "the rulers' insolence, and endeavors to get, and exercise an arbitrary
power over their people" than by a "desire in the people to cast off the lawful
authority of their rulers" (para. 226, 230; Locke's italics). Thus, two more prem-
ises are these:
5. Those who hold governmental power are more likely to provoke sedition and
revolution by tyrannical behavior than are the ruled to engage in unprovoked, or even
slightly provoked sedition. This is true because:
6. Power has a corrupting influence.
[T]hey who are in power (by the pretence they have to authority, the tempta-
tion of force they have in their hands, and the flattery of those about them) [are]
likeliest to [provoke revolution]; the properest way to prevent the evil is to show
them the danger and injustice of it who are under the greatest temptation to run
into it (para. 226; see also 91-93, 111, 137, 218).
7. The final clause of this quotation yields the next premise: The "best fence
against rebellion" that a political theorist can provide is to persuade rulers (not their
too-often put-upon subjects) to mend their ways, by warning them that oppressive gov-
ernment is what causes revolution (para. 226).11 Rulers need to temper their
insolence and greed, which are likely to be aggravated by the temptations of
power. The stimulus to such self-reform can be provided by an awareness,
offered by the political theorist, Locke, that such restraint will enable their rule
10 This would seem to be an utterly straightforward reading of the paragraphs cited at Premise 3, but
a number of Locke scholars dispute it. For a discussion of the debate, see citations and analysis
thereof in Simmons 1993: 172-77.
1 Cf. Tarcov (1981) who argues that the "best fence," in Locke's view, is an alert oppositional polit-
ical leadership who will alert the citizenry about a build-up of princely power tending toward
tyranny In my judgment, Tarcov's interpretation relies on reading more into para. 242 than is
really there and gives too little attention to Locke's actual description of the benefit of his teaching
on revolution in para. 226.
316
This content downloaded from 132.174.254.72 on Mon, 21 Aug 2017 21:20:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Aristotle's Theory of Revolution
to last (and peace and prosperity thereby to prevail). Locke is putting forth his
teaching on revolution, "this doctrine," as "the probablest means to hinder [rebel-
lion]." The "rebellion" in question is tyrannical behavior by the ruler that re-
introduces the state of war.
Locke's rhetorical emphasis is overwhelmingly addressed to the human pas-
sion of greed; thus he repeatedly warns that:
8. What rulers need to refrain from attacking is the "property" of their subjects.12
Moreover, he advises them that "the increase of lands and the right employing of
them [i.e., by developing an incentive structure that encourages industriousness]
is the great art of government" (para. 42). While Locke clearly indicates that he
uses the term "property" to include "life, liberty and estate," his choice of this dic-
tion inevitably underlines, as a practical matter, people's concerns with their own
material possessions.
9. Rulers heedful of Locke can easily avoid having seditious subjects, because a
populace contented by security for their lives and property will be the rulers' strongest
bulwark against the rare, ambitious minority faction. Misdeeds by rulers short of a
direct attack on the lives, liberty or estates of the general public are not likely to
provoke sedition. Indeed, even a minority justified in hostility to the government
"will not easily engage ... in a contest, wherein they are sure to perish; it being
as impossible for one or a few oppressed men to disturb the government, where
the body of the people do not think themselves concerned in it, as for a raving
madman, or a heady malcontent to overturn a well-settled state; the people being
as little apt to follow the one as the other" (para. 208; italics omitted).
The combination of Premises 3, 4, 5, 7, and 9 yields the following: Locke's
message concerning the occasional reality of factious behavior by "heady
malcontents" appears to be that, while such behavior can sometimes reach the
point of causing "great disorder" (the unfortunate reality being that some human
beings instead of following reason are "quarrelsome and contentious," para. 34),
the efforts of these ambitious few are not likely to prove "fatal" to "states and
kingdoms" unless the people at large have been seriously aggrieved by their gov-
ernment. Thus, Locke's overall message on revolution is that the primary cause
of rebellion is overreaching on the part of those in power. The temptations of
power and its corrupting force in unleashing the greed of rulers are the problems
that political theory can successfully address: The way to guard against depreda-
tions by governing authorities is to alert them to their own self-interest, with a
clear warning that severe mistreatment of the public will backfire by provoking
successful revolution.
12 The difficulty of figuring out how to keep rulers from using their political power to enrich them-
selves at the expense of their subjects is a problem as old as political philosophy itself. See Plato's
Republic 417a 6-b 3.
317
This content downloaded from 132.174.254.72 on Mon, 21 Aug 2017 21:20:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Political Research Quarterly
ARISTOTLE'S THEORY OF REVOLUTION
Aristotle's Premises
Although Aristotle makes the point in terms more measured than Locke's
rallying cry, "[The people] cannot but feel what they lie under," a premise close
to that of the inevitability of seditious overthrow of tyrannical regimes (Premise #1
above) does appear in Politics. Premise 1 in Aristotle's characteristically more cau-
tious rendition comes out as: "It is difficult for a regime to last if its constitution
is contrary to justice" (VII, 13: 1332b 28-29).13 He underlines this point by
insisting that the least just regimes-self-interested oligarchies and tyrannies-
are the shortest-lived. Those tyrannies that are believed to have lasted even as
long as seventeen years were, strictly speaking, not tyrannies. The so-called
tyrants in each of them (see examples at V, 12: 1315b 12-33) actually served
more as constitutional monarchs or popular leaders, either putting themselves
under the rule of law, or ruling in such a way as to please the populace in such
ways as exemplary public service in warfare, acts of concern for the public good,
and moderate rule. Thus, Aristotle is able to conclude, "Most [versions of] tyran-
nies [i.e., those that really warrant the label] have all been completely short-
lived" (V, 12: 1316b 38-39).
Like Locke, Aristotle also warns potentially oppressive rulers that they will
not be able to fool all of the people all of the time. While a genuinely well-man-
aged regime (in terms of the range of the practicable) would please all segments
of the community and thus would be altogether free of seditious faction (II,
9:1270b 21-22; II, 12: 1274a 15-21; III, 11: 1281b 28-34; IV, 9: 1294b 34-40;
VI, 5: 1320a 15-16), to survive in the sense of avoiding a successful sedition, a
regime must at least please the strongest elements of the community, its domi-
nant forces (IV, 13: 1297b 5-10; IV, 12: 1296b 14-16; V, 9: 1309b 16-18; VI, 7:
1320b 26-28). Strength, for Aristotle, is measured as a blend of the strength of
13 My case would be easier if this passage actually read as it is rendered in the Jonathan Barnes revi-
sion of Benjamin Jowett's translation of the Politics (Everson, ed. 1988: 176). There it is rendered:
"No government can stand which is not founded upon justice." But Aristotle does describe the sur-
vival chances of an unjust regime as "difficult" (chalepon) rather than literally impossible. In my
view, incidentally, this passage, together with the sentence that follows it, indicates Aristotle's view
that justice does prevail in the Bk. VII-VIII City According-to-Prayer, i.e., that city for which one
would wish once one understood what is best simply (III, 18; IV, 1; VII, 4: 1325b 37). (But cf. the
arguments of C. Zuckert [1983]; Nichols [1992: 144-45]; Yack [1993: 168-69]; and Annas
[1996].) Therefore, there are no un-natural slaves in it. All have citizen rights except resident
aliens plus natural slaves plus foreign serfs (presumably those lacking adequate thumos to object
to being ruled, and who would be working voluntarily in the City of Prayer, for rule over free
others who submit only involuntarily is tyrannical; see VII, 7: 1327b 25-30. These groups would
do all the vulgar necessary work. In this reading, I agree with Miller (1995: 240-41) and disagree
with the assertion of Cooper (1996: 867n.) that Aristotle "can hardly have seriously intended that
. all the native-born free persons. .. should exercise rights of citizenship."
318
This content downloaded from 132.174.254.72 on Mon, 21 Aug 2017 21:20:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Aristotle's Theory of Revolution
numbers and "quality" (Bk. IV, ch. 12). Numbers can be a source of political
power, but so can the political skills gained through "education," or the respect
accorded to some people because of their "good birth" into families revered for
having contributed to the public weal. Aristotle also includes "wealth" in his cal-
culus of political power. Owners of wealthy estates not only can afford the best
military equipment, but could also hire mercenaries (V, 6: 1306a 21-23) or (per-
haps more likely) acquire legions of followers by giving out jobs on their estates
(VI, 5: 1320b 8-9).
To be sure, Locke does not discuss at any length the relevance for revolution
of differences of political power attainable within civil society, and indeed down-
plays them by his frequent refrain, "The people shall be judge." However, a
recognition of differences of political influence within civil society does not con-
tradict anything in Locke's theory. Moreover, Aristotle himself, in a sense, warns
of the future appropriateness of thinking in terms of the people as the ultimate
judge, for he predicts (long before the universal prevalence of imperial or nation-
based states), "Now that it has happened that cities have become even larger, it
is perhaps [or alternatively, probably: isos] no longer easy for any regime to arise
other than a democracy" (III, 15: 1286b 19-20). But even outside of democracy,
government cannot afford to ignore the force of numbers; Even in an oligarchy,
if it treats the multitude unjustly, Aristotle warns, any leader would be adequate
to guide a successful revolt (V, 6: 1305a 38-41).
Aristotle, in considering how rulers should please the dominant elements of
the community, focuses more than Locke does on the question of who should
share the prerogatives of political office, as distinguished from policy outcomes
per se, although he does not entirely ignore the latter (e.g. VI, 5: 1320a 34-40).
This emphasis seems to be because he sees his audience as primarily "legislators,"
or founders who are devising a political framework after some regime has been
overthrown. (This concern is particularly apparent in Bk. IV, ch. 12, and in Bk. VI,
ch.5.) Still, it does make sense to expect that participation in rule will yield some
sharing of the benefits of rule, and the absence of participation, a consequent
absence of benefits. Indeed, Aristotle makes this point explicitly: Constitutions
that do not have an adequate amount of power-sharing in their initial structure,
he writes, are bound to produce bad [policy] in the end (V, 1: 1302a 5-8).
And Aristotle, like Locke, warns against governmental deception that aims
at exclusion of the general populace. He specifically singles out for criticism con-
stitutional devices that aim to give the illusion of a popular say in government
but are rigged to assure predominance by the wealthy, insisting that "in time from
things falsely good there must result a true evil" (IV, 12: 1297a12; the list of such
devices follows in IV, 13; he repeats the point at V, 8:1308a 2-3). This statement
that, sooner or later, the truth will out when it comes to government oppression,
amounts to Aristotle's endorsement of Premise 2: In the long run, deception of the
people cannot stave off revolution if government has become tyrannical.
319
This content downloaded from 132.174.254.72 on Mon, 21 Aug 2017 21:20:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Political Research Quarterly
Aristotle also agrees with Locke that if only a few are treated unjustly, they
will not be able to overthrow a government, as long as that government contin-
ues to please the preponderant elements in the community (V, 1:1301a 39-b2; V,
4: 1304b 2-5). Thus, Premise 3: Generally speaking, if the unjustly treated are a
tiny minority (without the backing of an aggrieved public) they will not revolt. Those
regimes last where the governing body treats well the people outside the ruling
group, for these regimes lack an aggrieved public (V, 8: 1308a 4-10).
Aristotle gives far more attention than does Locke to the 4th Premise: Excep-
tionally ambitious minorities can on occasion stir up sedition to the point of great dis-
order. In Book V especially, Aristotle dwells at great length upon the various
details of a grand variety of seditious overthrows or attempted overthrows of
rulers from prior history. The basic source of these was a perception of unfair-
ness. Sometimes, as in Locke's later theory, the felt grievance was on the part of
the common people, when their property was attacked (IV, 13: 1297b 5-8; V, 8:
1308a 8-9, 1308b 32-1309a 9; VI, 4: 1318b 14-20), but not always. Aristotle's
description and theory of revolution gives much greater prominence than does
Locke to the seditions triggered by a sentiment of frustrated ambition or of
offended dignity (including sexual dignity) on the part of would-be rulers-
those Locke dubbed "heady malcontents." These ambitious leaders, typically of
the wealthy classes, but sometimes from the military or naval ranks, can end up
strong enough to overpower the elements supportive of the regime partly
because the ruling groups treated segments of the population unjustly but also
partly because the tiny city-states of the ancient world were far less capable of
defending against coups than large nation-states came to be.14 It is conceivable
that the reason Locke's theory of revolution could look so different from Aristo-
tle's is that the largeness of kingdoms and even principalities in Locke's day ren-
dered much less frequent a viable threat of turbulence from an ambitious few, as
compared with the polis of fourth-century-BC Greece. Still, even in Aristotle's
description, Premise 3 is meant to convey the more general picture: if ambitious
leaders cannot tap into some degree of perceived injustice by powerful segments
of the community, they will not have enough followers to succeed in their coup
or revolution. (Incidentally, Aristotle shows more respect than Locke does for
those zealots for justice-"very few in number" but not unknown to history-
who, motivated primarily by a desire to do a noble thing, led lost causes against
bad government [V, 10: 1312a 4-39].)
14 Aristotle understood that bigness would enhance stability. He argued that this enhancement could
come about by expansion of the middle class, a group easier for rulers to keep satisfied than are
either the very rich or the very poor (Bk. IV). He argued, however, that the City of Prayer could
not be large in this way, for in a large city it is too difficult for the ruled and rulers (as they take
turns ruling) to recognize each other's particular talents for government and particular needs as
subjects being ruled (Bk. VII, ch.4).
320
This content downloaded from 132.174.254.72 on Mon, 21 Aug 2017 21:20:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Aristotle's Theory of Revolution
Aristotle's version of Premise 5, that revolution finds its source more often in
unjust provocation by rulers than in unprovoked sedition from the populace, or the ruled,
is thus not so prominent as in Locke, again because the problem of coups from
ambitious or outraged leaders was more pressing in Aristotle's day. Nonetheless, it
is clearly implied in his general advice for avoiding revolution: any regime that
wants stability needs to avoid the excesses that render it unjust. Oligarchies
should become somewhat democratic in governing structure so that they will be
less inclined to oppress the common people (VI, 6); democracies should adopt
laws that make more secure the property of the wealthy (VI, 5); tyrannies need to
become more kinglike, adopting the rule of law and a moderate way of life,
refraining from attacking either the common people or the elite (V, 11 and 12).
Aristotle's advice to tyrants is sometimes misread because he prefaces this
advice-the advice that he gives in his own name (viz., become more kinglike and
less tyrannical)-with an acknowledgment of the details of the "received wisdom"
on how to preserve tyranny--viz., be tyrannical: operate the kind of regime asso-
ciated with twentieth century totalitarianism, replete with spying on the subjects,
the constant stimulation of warfare, and prohibitions on voluntary organizations
or private meetings among the subjects. It is this "received wisdom" that Aristotle
is attempting to replace. Aristotle argues plainly that to follow the received wisdom
is to provoke revolution. "Indeed, what must be done is the opposite in nearly
every case of the things mentioned previously." Tyrannies that took the tyrannical
route were short-lived, while "tyrants" who behave in fact like benevolent kings,
appearing not as appropriators of their subjects' property but as stewards of it will
attain "longer-lasting" rule (V, 10: 1313a 1-V, 11: 1315b 10). These maxims about
how to avoid the excesses that amount to tyranny are the fenceposts of Aristotle's
"best fence against rebellion" argument (Premise 7).
One also finds in Aristotle an explanation for this "best fence" argument that
is similar to Locke's: (Premise 6) Power has a corrupting influence. In recommend-
ing a mix of democratic and aristocratic elements that check each other, such that
the common people would serve as electors of the most capable for political
office and as auditor of the elected officials, Aristotle offers the following expla-
nation: "[The officials] will rule justly by the fact that others have authority over
the audits. For to be under constraint and unable to do everything one might
resolve to do is beneficial. The license to do whatever one wishes cannot defend
against the base element in every human being" (VI, 4: 1318b 38-1319a 1; see
also IV, 14: 1298b 15-26; III, 16: 1287a 30-31).
Premise 8, what rulers need to refrain from attacking is the "property" of their
subjects, would seem to offer particular difficulty for the argument of this essay,
because Aristotle specifically criticized a competing political theorist, Phaleas, for
believing that solving the property problem would solve all political problems.
Aristotle pointed out in that discussion that there is a kind of person who cares
not just about bodily appetites, but who craves honor, societal respect, fame, a
321
This content downloaded from 132.174.254.72 on Mon, 21 Aug 2017 21:20:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Political Research Quarterly
"place in history."'5 Such people pose a much more serious threat than petty
crime, for they are the potential tyrants. What they need is not the right amount
of property, but rather proper education, which will teach moderation and phi-
losophy (Bk. II, ch. 7). Part of that education, however, is offered right here in Pol-
itics. To the extent that the education in the need for moderation is in part the
teaching on the proper limits of political power contained here, the Phaleas cri-
tique is not necessarily at odds with Premise 8.
And, indeed, Aristotle repeats more than once the importance of the advice
that links successful regime survival with refraining from attacks on people's
property. The many, he writes, "strive more for profits than for honor." They even
will tolerate oligarchies and used to tolerate tyrannies, so long as rulers do not
take their property or prevent them from working (VI, 4: 1318b1 6-19; see also
V, 8: 1308a 8-10). A slight variation on this warning appears in Bk. IV, ch.13: The
poor are willing to remain tranquil even when they have no share in political pre-
rogatives, provided no one acts "hubristically" toward them nor deprives them of
any of their property (IV, 13: 1297b 5-9; see also V, 11: 1315a 14-24)). The
Greek "hubris," generally translated "arrogance" (although Simpson [1997] and
Keyt [1999] offer the more apt, "insolence") involves, according to Aristotle's
Rhetoric, the deliberate taking of pleasure in acts of humiliation toward others
(Rh.1378b 23-29, as cited in Reeve 1998: 244). It may be that Machiavelli had
this passage in mind when he later wrote in The Prince that what ordinary people
want from their government is security for their property and protection against
the violation of their wives and daughters (referring to the latter as a loss of their
men's honor) (ch.17: 67 and ch.19: 72). Machiavelli's discussion is helpful, in
any case, for highlighting the linkage between Aristotle's warning against hubris-
tic behavior by the rulers and the security for life and limb that Locke clearly
includes under his umbrella term "property," for, per Locke, one's first natural
property is the property in one's own body (para. 27).
While it is true that Aristotle does advise rulers specifically against unjustly
depriving ambitious societal leaders of their prerogatives (V, 8: 1308a 8-9), he also
makes clear that it is not just the common people who want their property left
alone. He notes that the kinds of leaders who come to power in oligarchies, too,
care at least as much about the profits of office as they do about honor (VI, 7:
1321a 41-44). And Aristotle identifies governmental attacks on the property of
the well-off as a common provocation for elite-led seditions against democracies.
The matter of property is serious enough that Aristotle writes, "A very great
thing in every regime is to have the laws and management of the rest arranged in
such a way that it is impossible to profit from the [political] offices" (V, 8: 1308b
15 I realize that I am truncating Aristotle's argument here, blurring together the craving for fame or
honor (potentially including a desire for more than one's fair share of political offices) with the
desire for pure, or unmixed pleasure. I do so to avoid a lengthy tangent.
322
This content downloaded from 132.174.254.72 on Mon, 21 Aug 2017 21:20:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Aristotle's Theory of Revolution
32-1309a 14). He adds that preventing government officials from taking the
property of the people or treating them hubristically, however, is a difficult thing
to accomplish, "for it does not always turn out that those sharing in the govern-
ing body are the refined sort" (IV, 13: 1297b 8-10).
However unrefined rulers may turn out to be, they should at least under-
stand a frank appeal to their self-interest. For this reason, Aristotle has con-
structed the "best fence against rebellion argument," warning them that their best
safeguard against sedition lies in making their regime more just. And even if they
cannot have total assurance of having headed off sedition from every possible
ambitious leader, in light of the prevalence of concern for property among both
the wealthy and the common people, rulers who secure the lives, limbs, and prop-
erty of their subjects will have a substantial bulwark against sedition led by ambitious
competitors (Aristotle's version of Premise 9).
Limits of the Argument
Differences of Thematic Focus. Whereas the modem fame of Locke's Second
Treatise is as "a work principally designed to assert a right of resistance to unjust
authority, a right, in the last resort, of revolution" (Simmons 1993:147, citing
Dunn 1984: 28), no one would assert the same of Aristotle's Politics. Nonetheless
the core premises of Locke's operational theory of revolution, that is, of his theory
of when and why revolutions take place, are in fact present in Aristotle's earlier
work. It is true that Locke's Treatise is ostentatiously an essay that justifies revo-
lution. Such justification is not Aristotle's thematic focus. However, it is in fact
observably present in Politics, if one looks for it. The argument here-to reiter-
ate-is not a claim that Locke was in all important respects an Aristotelian. He
emphatically was not. Rather, the argument here is that Aristotle provides an
operational theory of revolution that contains most of the core premises of
Locke's later theory, including its prescriptive element: viz. revolutions against
tyrannical regimes are natural and virtually inevitable, and that the best fence
against rebellion is to alert would-be tyrants of this operational theory so that
they will mend their ways, and temper potential excesses of the regime. This fact
demarcates an underappreciated aspect of Aristotle's Politics, an underapprecia-
tion that this essay aspires to correct.16
16 It is perhaps a mark of this under-appreciation that scholars debate whether Aristotle was naively
over-optimistic to hope that tyrannical governments would heed this warning--compare Mulgan
1977: 134-35 with Polansky 1991: 331-32--but a comparable argument (so far as I have been
able to discover) does not appear in the Locke scholarship. Perhaps this view of Locke as more
hard-headed is attributable to his having discernibly inspired actual revolutions, such as the Amer-
ican. Thus, his warning to would-be tyrants took on "teeth" that were not so apparent in Aristo-
tle's more muted approach.
323
This content downloaded from 132.174.254.72 on Mon, 21 Aug 2017 21:20:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Political Research Quarterly
If this argument is correct, skeptics may wonder, why does Aristotle under-
play the theory, mute it, as it were, by emphasizing different concerns? No defin-
itive answer is available, but one can suggest the plausible hypothesis that Aris-
totle chose to emphasize the usefulness of his political science for rulers already
in power and for regimes already in place (e.g., in Politics, Book IV, ch. 1),
because of his consciousness of the relatively recent fate of Socrates."7
Moreover, if this argument is correct-if Aristotle's true concern, like
Locke's, is to prevent tyranny (in the general sense of oppressive government) by
warning that the closer government gets to tyranny, the more likely revolution-
ary overthrow becomes-then many of Aristotle's prescriptions take on new
meaning. For instance, his counsels that specific laws, type of citizen education,
and even the sense of justice appropriate in governing officials must be tailored
to the needs of the regime so as to preserve it (V, 9: 1309a 36-39; 1309b 14-17;
1310a 14-19), have an import that is the opposite of how they are generally
taken.'8 He is not saying that this means, for instance in an oligarchy, that the
laws and education adopted should be those closest to the wishes or inclinations
of the ruling oligarchs; on the contrary, they should be such as to temper or
restrain those inclinations: "But to be educated relative to the regime is not to do
the things that oligarchs or those who want democracy enjoy, but rather the
things by which the former will be able to run an oligarchy and the latter to have
a regime that is run democratically" (1310a 19-24). And what enables an oli-
garchy to continue in existence as an oligarchy, for instance, turns out to be that
it avoid the excesses characteristic of oligarchy, namely oppression of the
common people. Its rulers need to learn how to become "less oligarchical" in
order to stay in power. Some scholars take this fact as evidence that Aristotle
stumbled into an unwitting inconsistency (Mulgan 1977: 136; Rowe 1991: 67-
69; Reeve 1998: lxiii-lxiv), in that his prescription for making a regime endure is
to alter the regime for the better, which makes it a different regime.19 But one
17 Reportedly, Aristotle explained his departure from Athens, one year prior to his death from natu-
ral causes with the remark that he did not want Athens to sin a second time against philosophy
(Lord 1984: 6). Locke was free to endorse revolution against tyranny more openly because he
wrote under the cloak of anonymity (and perhaps, too, he chose this mode because he was intent
on fomenting a particular, immediate revolution [Ashcraft 19861). When Mulgan (1977: 136)
argues that Aristotle "should have admitted more openly that he considers the[] position [of tyran-
nical oligarchs, democrats or monarchs] untenable and that they must change the nature of their
rule or be overthrown," he writes as though the problem of Socrates was no problem. But the fact
is, Aristotle did openly admit these things; he simply did not stress them. He wrote them, as it
were, quietly, rather than shouting them from the rooftops, or the barricades.
18 Reeve (1998) seems at some points to agree with my reading (lxiv [describing a "stable but non-
rigid" regime] and lxvii) but at others to take these statements at their face value (liii, lxii, later on
lxvii).
19 Keyt, in an innovative reading, suggests that the real import of these passages is to render the
rulers of all regimes at least law-abiding; that Aristotle aims here to check each regime's potential
324
This content downloaded from 132.174.254.72 on Mon, 21 Aug 2017 21:20:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Aristotle's Theory of Revolution
could suggest that this is not an inconsistency. Aristotle is simply advising vari-
ous sovereign bodies that political power has limits; any sovereign who ignores
Aristotle's advice and uses political office to gratify every whim risks losing the
regime to seditious overthrow by aggrieved subjects.
Differences of Fundamental Premise: Irrespective of the evidence on the
authors' theories of revolution, one might also object that the differences between
the respective overall political philosophies of Locke and Aristotle are so over-
whelming that any similarity on revolution is insignificant and misleading.
Important points of contrast include, first, that for Aristotle it is of central signif-
icance that the political scientist identify the best regime, the City According-to-
Prayer, in order to have a standard by which to assess better and worse (Bk. III,
ch. 18; Bk. IV, ch. 1; Bks. VII-VIII). For Locke, by contrast, the type of regime that
will be legitimate in any particular society is a matter of original majority prefer-
ence-rule by one, by a select few, and by direct majority can equally be legiti-
mate as long as the government does not turn tyrannical. As long as it does not,
at least tacit consent can be assumed, and consent of the governed is what makes
for legitimate government. Locke's theory aims only to guard against the worst
excesses (Tarcov 1981: 214-17), while Aristotle orients his theory according to
the polestar of the best imaginable.
A second fundamental difference that might arguably render comparison
inappropriate is that for Locke (following Hobbes) the aims of the political
society concern the things of the body-security for life itself and freedom to
pursue a comfortable life. Aristotle, to the contrary, argues that real-life polit-
ical societies err in limiting their concerns to such things, when what politi-
cal societies should do is foster excellence of character or soul (psyche) among
the citizenry.20
However, despite these two massive differences of orientation, Aristotle
acknowledges that real-life societies typically-indeed universally in practice-
are not interested in hearing the good character message. People in government,
including the common people in direct democracies, are more interested in
deterioration into the extreme of lawlessness (1999: 136-142). While more attractive than those
readings that simply condemn Aristotle for inconsistency, Keyt's seems to pay insufficient heed to
the fact that Aristotle is giving advice that goes beyond law-abidingness to guide regime-design
itself. Moreover, Aristotle's approving description of so-called tyrants who in fact moderated their
tyrannies by putting themselves under law or by ruling in the public interest, thus rendering
themselves "monarchs" rather than tyrants, properly speaking, belies the notion that Aristotle
opposed all regime improvement (V, 12: 1315b 12-33).
20 Aristotle notes that even Sparta and similarly warlike political communities err in fostering only a
part of virtue, military courage, rather than the whole of it, and also because they value the goods
that are attainable through conquest more highly than the virtue involved in acquiring the goods
(Bk. II, ch.9: 1271a 42-1271b 11; see also VII, ch.2: 1324b 3-38; VII, 14: 1333a 37-1334a10;
VIII, 4: 1338b 9-38).
325
This content downloaded from 132.174.254.72 on Mon, 21 Aug 2017 21:20:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Political Research Quarterly
maintaining their own power than in any betterment of their souls (VI, 4: 1318b
2-5). And what people generally seek is property; the common many prefer
profits to honor (VI, 4: 1318b 17-18), and the wealthy few also "seek profits no
less than honor" (VI, 7: 1321a 41-43). Indeed there is no existing political soci-
ety where one can find even as many as one hundred men who have genuine
excellence of character (V, 1: 1302a 1-1302a 3).21 Thus, while the City of Prayer
for Aristotle provides a model for deciding what is better and worse legisla-
tion,22 his argument in Books IV-VI is that the political theorist must be able to
offer usable advice to real governments, and therefore must be able to address
the actual concerns of those governments. Here, therefore, Aristotle traverses
ground similar to Locke's.
Finally, the two theorists differ notoriously over the naturalness of human
equality. Locke maintains that no one has a natural right to rule another23 (since
all humans are one species) so legitimate ruling authority can come only from
consent. Aristotle argues that according to the nature of justice, some have a
more just claim to rule because they are people of moral excellence and practi-
cal wisdom, and for these reasons will do a better job. "The greatest factional
split is probably that between virtue and depravity" (V, 3: 1303b 14-15), but
this fact turns out to have little practical relevance because, although the people
of excellent character most deserve to rule, they are such a tiny minority that,
practically speaking, they would not dream of trying to come to power force-
fully (V, 1: 1301a 39-b2; V, 4: 1304b 4-6). Like Locke's outnumbered oppressed
minority, they simply have to endure the situation. Moreover, they would not be
able to persuade ordinary people to hand over power to them; such a thing
would be even more difficult than figuring out the perfect formula of distribu-
tive justice for a particular community. People in power will not heed claims
(however well-founded they might be) that justice requires them to turn over
their power to other people (VI, 3: 1318b 2-5). Thus, Aristotle, instead of
appealing directly to arguments based on justice, winds up, like Locke, warning
21 Aristotle says literally there are not 100 who are "good and well-born" and that "good birth and
excellence are in few." It is possible that his point in conjoining good birth with goodness is to
state that the conjunction of actual goodness with the societal influence that would come from
good birth is what is rare. I think it more likely, however, that his reference to good birth is as an
aspect of complete goodness, as in the expression "well brought-up." A youngster may start out
good but without good parents his or her chance of ending up good are far slimmer.
22 Not everyone agrees that Aristotle's City of Prayer, the city that is best simply, provides a standard
of justice that enables one to judge what is better and worse among actual regimes, cf. C. Zuckert
(1983); Nichols (1992: 144-45); Yack (1993: 168-69); Annas (1996). But see Miller (1995: 239-
45), Rowe (1991), and Bradley (1991) for examples of readings that accord with mine.
23 No one, that is, except someone who has been attacked without provocation. An attacker without
material motive has abandoned the human species and demoted himself to the ranks of vicious
beasts and thus may be executed or subjected to the lesser penalty of slavery
326
This content downloaded from 132.174.254.72 on Mon, 21 Aug 2017 21:20:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Aristotle's Theory of Revolution
ruling groups that if they wish to avoid being overthrown they must refrain from
tyrannical excesses.24
As for the matter of using consent of the governed to distinguish legitimate
from illegitimate government, Aristotle himself uses the voluntariness of submis-
sion to rule as a definitional marker that distinguishes tyrannical from healthy
rule (III, 14:1285a 27, b 3, b 5, b 8, b 21; IV, 10: 1295a 19-23; V, 10:1313a 3-
11). The three healthy-i.e., non-tyrannical-regimes had been defined as ones
that serve the public interest rather than simply the ruler's interest; in noting
three times that tyrannies are regimes where the public is being ruled involun-
tarily, Aristotle is indicating that the people do voluntarily submit when the
public interest is being served. Thus, voluntary submission to the rule of another
would appear to be the Aristotelian version of what Locke calls tacit consent to
government.
CONCLUSIONS
Aristotle's critique of Phaleas indicates that Aristotle understood that the
political problem of coping with people who want more than their fair share of
things is a problem too deep and too broad to solve by economic techniques
alone. Its ultimate solution would have to include the Socratic remedies
endorsed, for instance, in Plato's Republic, namely, teaching moderation and turn-
ing potential tyrants toward the pleasures offered by philosophy. Thus, Aristotl
strived to elevate political-life-as-he-found-it, by teaching that the polis properly
aims at the fostering of human excellence. (Indeed, Aristotle treats political life
per se as worthy of considerably more dignity than Socrates does. One does no
find in Aristotle the Socratic tendency to warn that the truly just person is bes
advised to stay away from politics [Apology 31d-32a; Republic 496c-e]).
Nonetheless, Aristotle also went beyond these remedies suggested by
Plato. Aristotle frankly acknowledged that no communities in fact provided
education in moderation. Consequently, he may have reasonably inferred tha
few were likely to do so in the future. Moreover, one may entertain legitimat
doubts about the likelihood that the lure of Socratic philosophy would pull a
large fraction of the world's potentially tyrannical rulers away from the temp-
tations of power. It is conceivable that Aristotle entertained these very doubts
He certainly stated clearly that once people have power, it is virtually impossi-
ble to succeed with purely justice-based arguments to persuade them to accept
checks on their own power (VI, 3: 1318b 2-5). And finally, Aristotle frankly
24 While Aristotle initially defines tyranny as the selfish rule of a monarch (III: 7), he later extend
the usage to cover self-aggrandizing rule by any group (included a popular majority) at the
expense of the rest of the public: extremist oligarchies and extremist democracies alike are prop-
erly regarded as tyrannies: "for these happen to be tyrannies [with the power] divided up" (V, 10
1312b 37-38).
327
This content downloaded from 132.174.254.72 on Mon, 21 Aug 2017 21:20:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Political Research Quarterly
acknowledged that what the vast majority of people want from government is
protection for their property
Thus, in Books IV-VI of Politics, Aristotle supplemented the Socratic options
for stemming abuses of political power by appealing to the low but solid ground
of the rulers' self-interest in staying in power. The core premises of the Aris-
totelian teaching on sedition-essentially a "crime doesn't pay" story for rulers-
were then available for Locke's much later elaboration. These in sum maintained
that governments must avoid oppressing their subjects if they were to avoid
being overthrown, that revolution against oppressive rulers is both inevitable and
natural,25 that security for property would have a central place in the avoidance
of oppression, and that the succumbing to the temptations of power on the part
of ruling groups is the fundamental provocation of revolution.
Locke (in direct contrast with Hobbes) agreed with Aristotle in distrusting
the corrupting influence of political power and thus re-worked Aristotle's basic
premises to provide an alternative to Hobbes's absolutist political conclusions.
Aristotle, for example, said of his recommended checking of the excesses that
amount to tyranny not only that it will render a monarch's rule "more noble and
more enviable" (because he will be ruling better people) and will render the ruler
himself, if not of "fine" character, at least "half-decent," but also that these
improvements will render his rule "longer-lasting" (V, 11: 1315b 4-10). Locke's
re-worked teaching on revolution holds onto the "longer-lasting" side of the
argument, and in effect drops the rest.
What this look at his "Lockean" side can teach us readers about Aristotle's
own political philosophy is the degree to which it paid heed to what might be
called the hard-headed realities. Most people want from their political commu-
nities protection for their physical security and for their property; persons of
genuinely excellent character are so exceedingly rare that they will hardly ever
be in power; the possessing of power has a way of corrupting those who rule.
While Aristotle did see the need to attend to these realities, he, in contrast to
Locke, refused to decomplicate his political theory, to focus almost exclusively
on the readily predictable. In Aristotle's theory (unlike Locke's) the human
yearning for nobility of character, the human desire to be a good and respect-
worthy person and to be surrounded by such people, and the craving for a
25 Keyt's explication astutely likens revolution to death of a regime and remarks that "death is some-
times a justly imposed penalty" (Keyt 1999: xiv-xv). Revolution, one could add, is the natural fate
of a regime in the extremely diseased condition of tyrannical excess. Both Locke and Aristotle
make a point of describing the naturalness of this outcome (natural in the sense that it is a ten-
dency intrinsic to the nature of tyranny) as a way of preventing the conditions of extreme disease
in the body politic. Locke is more outspoken than Aristotle in emphasizing that tyrants deserve
what they get (Since tyranny violates natural rights, it is by nature right to overthrow it). Still, Keyt
notes that in at least one passage Aristotle implies that resistance to tyranny is something worthy
of honor (V, 10: 1312a 21-39; Keyt 1999: xv).
328
This content downloaded from 132.174.254.72 on Mon, 21 Aug 2017 21:20:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Aristotles Theory of Revolution
social order characterized by justice, do not disappear. The tension between
these genuinely human but too-frail traits and the traits that characterize the
pursuit of comfortable self-preservation remains present in his political philos-
ophy, as do a variety of other tensions. These would include that between the
need for wisdom and the need for consent; the tensions among the needs for
freedom, for solidarity, and for ultimate meaning; and the tension between the
necessary conditions of political life-physical security and societal commu-
nity-and the highest goals of political life-the wisdom and human excellence
that are required for happiness (Salkever 1990: 84-89).
Nonetheless, despite these important differences, Aristotle's was a politics
attentive as well to the more base political tendencies on which Locke was later
to focus so emphatically. If governing authorities are to behave in even half-
decent ways, the political philosopher needs to develop an argument that is not
itself base but that can cope with the kind of base self-interest that is all too
prevalent in human affairs. Accomplishing this is a worthy enough task that Aris-
totle devoted the good part of three books of Politics to it.
REFERENCES
Annas, Julia. 1996. "Aristotle on Human Nature and Political Virtue," R
Metaphysics 49 (June): 731-54.
Ashcraft, Richard. 1986. Revolutionary Politics and Locke's Two Treatises of
ment. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Barker, Ernest. 1962. The Politics of Aristotle (Translation with Introdu
Appendices). New York: Oxford University Press.
Black, Antony. 1988. "The Conciliar Movement." In J. H. Burns, ed., Ca
History of Medieval Political Thought c. 350-c. 1450, pp. 573-87. Cam
MA: Cambridge University Press.
Bradley, A. C. 1991. "Aristotle's Conception of the State," in David Keyt
D. Miller, Jr., eds., A Companion to Aristotle's Politics, pp.13-56. Oxfor
Blackwell.
Burns, J. H., ed. 1988. Cambridge History of Medieval Political Though
c. 1450. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.
Cooper, John. 1996. "Justice and Rights in Aristotle's Politics." Review
physics 49 (June): 859-72.
Cox, Richard. 1960. Locke on War and Peace. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
1982, "Introduction." In Richard Cox, ed., Second Treatise of Govern
pp. vii-xlii. Arlington Heights, VA: Harlan Davidson.
Dunbabin, Jean. 1988. "Government." In Burns, op. cit., pp. 477-519.
Dunn, John. 1984. Locke. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Everson, Stephen, ed. 1988. The Politics (of Aristotle). Cambridge, MA
bridge University Press.
Gadamer, H. G. 1975. Truth and Method. New York: Seabury.
329
This content downloaded from 132.174.254.72 on Mon, 21 Aug 2017 21:20:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Political Research Quarterly
Goldwin, Robert. 1987. "John Locke." In Leo Strauss and Joseph Cropsey, eds.,
History of Political Philosophy, 3rd ed., pp. 476-511. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press.
Grant, Ruth. 1987. John Locke's Liberalism. Chicago; University of Chicago Press.
Keyt, David. 1999. Aristotle Politics Books V and VI (Translation with Commen-
tary). Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Locke, John. 1823. "First Letter on Toleration," in The Works ofJohn Locke, Vol.VI.
London: Tagg et al.
Locke, John. 1982. Second Treatise of Government, ed. Richard Cox. Arlington
Heights, VA: Harlan Davidson.
Lord, Carnes, trans. 1984. The Politics (of Aristotle). Chicago: University of
Chicago Press.
Machiavelli, Niccolo. 1985. The Prince. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Macpherson, C. B. 1962. The Political Theory of Possessive Individualism: Hobbes to
Locke. New York; Oxford University Press.
Meyers, Henry A., with Herwig Wolfram. 1982. Medieval Kingship. Chicago:
Nelson-Hall.
Miller, Fred D. 1995. Nature, Justice and Rights in Aristotle's Politics. Oxford:
Clarendon Press.
. 1996. "Aristotle and the Origins of Natural Rights," Review of Meta-
physics 49 (June): 873-907.
Mulgan, R. G. 1977. Aristotle's Political Theory. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Nelson, Janet. 1988. "Kingship and Empire." In Burns, op cit., pp. 211-51.
Nichols, Mary P 1992. Citizens and Statesmen: A Study of Aristotle's Politics.
Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.
Polansky, Ronald. 1991. "Aristotle on Political Change." In David Keyt and Fred
D. Miller, Jr., eds., A Companion to Aristotle's Politics, pp.323-45. Oxford:
Basil Blackwell.
Procope, John. 1988. "Greek and Roman Political Theory." In Burns, op. cit., pp.
21-36.
Reeve, C. D. C., trans. 1998. Politics (of Aristotle). Indianapolis, IN: Hackett.
Rowe, Christopher. 1991. "Aims and Methods in Aristotle's Politics." In David
Keyt and Fred D. Miller, Jr., eds., A Companion to Aristotle's Politics, pp. 57-
74. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Salkever, Stephen. 1990. Finding the Mean: Theory and Practice in Aristotelian Phi-
losophy. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Simmons, A. John. 1993. On the Edge of Anarchy: Locke, Consent, and the Limits of
Society. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Simpson, Peter L. Phillips, trans. 1997. The Politics of Aristotle. Chapel Hill: Uni-
versity of North Carolina Press.
Strauss, Leo. 1953. Natural Right and History. Chicago: University of Chicago
Press.
330
This content downloaded from 132.174.254.72 on Mon, 21 Aug 2017 21:20:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Aristotle's Theory of Revolution
Tarcov, Nathan. 1981. "Locke's Second Treatise and the 'Best Fence against Rebel-
lion.'" Review of Politics 43 (April): 198-217.
Vincent, Andrew. 1987. Theories of the State. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Yack, Bernard. 1993. The Problems of a Political Animal Community, Justice and
Conflict in Aristotelian Political Thought. Berkeley: University of California
Press.
Zuckert, Catherine H. 1983. "Aristotle on the Limits and Satisfactions of Politi-
cal Life." Interpretation 11: 185-206.
Zuckert, Michael. 1994. Natural Rights and the New Republicanism. Princeton Uni-
versity Press.
Received: March 7, 2000
Accepted for Publication: October 9, 2000
lesl@udel.edu
331
This content downloaded from 132.174.254.72 on Mon, 21 Aug 2017 21:20:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

More Related Content

Similar to Aristotle S Theory Of Revolution Looking At The Lockean Side

A brief introduction to the study of political philosophy
A brief introduction to the study of political philosophyA brief introduction to the study of political philosophy
A brief introduction to the study of political philosophyNoel Jopson
 
political_theory.pdf
political_theory.pdfpolitical_theory.pdf
political_theory.pdfWaniBasim
 
Totalitarianism Essay. Methodist University
Totalitarianism Essay. Methodist UniversityTotalitarianism Essay. Methodist University
Totalitarianism Essay. Methodist UniversityLisa Williams
 
151272423 certainties-undone
151272423 certainties-undone151272423 certainties-undone
151272423 certainties-undonehomeworkping4
 
Topic of discussion Uptopian IdeasRequired Textbook 
Topic of discussion  Uptopian IdeasRequired Textbook Topic of discussion  Uptopian IdeasRequired Textbook 
Topic of discussion Uptopian IdeasRequired Textbook curranalmeta
 
Coleman y leiter determinacy objectivity and authority
Coleman y leiter  determinacy objectivity and authorityColeman y leiter  determinacy objectivity and authority
Coleman y leiter determinacy objectivity and authorityrolomauris
 
Theories Of International Relations
Theories Of International RelationsTheories Of International Relations
Theories Of International RelationsJenny Smith
 
Administrative Theory & Praxis, 38 101–114, 2016 Copyright .docx
Administrative Theory & Praxis, 38 101–114, 2016 Copyright .docxAdministrative Theory & Praxis, 38 101–114, 2016 Copyright .docx
Administrative Theory & Praxis, 38 101–114, 2016 Copyright .docxcoubroughcosta
 
Topic Political SystemsInstructionsExplain how conservat
Topic Political SystemsInstructionsExplain how conservatTopic Political SystemsInstructionsExplain how conservat
Topic Political SystemsInstructionsExplain how conservatcurranalmeta
 
PLATO’S CRITICISMS OF DEMOCRACYIN THE REPUBLICBy Gerasi.docx
PLATO’S CRITICISMS OF DEMOCRACYIN THE REPUBLICBy Gerasi.docxPLATO’S CRITICISMS OF DEMOCRACYIN THE REPUBLICBy Gerasi.docx
PLATO’S CRITICISMS OF DEMOCRACYIN THE REPUBLICBy Gerasi.docxrandymartin91030
 
Unit 5 Comparative methods and Approaches
Unit 5 Comparative methods and ApproachesUnit 5 Comparative methods and Approaches
Unit 5 Comparative methods and ApproachesYash Agarwal
 
The truth is elsewhere: Critical History
The  truth is elsewhere: Critical HistoryThe  truth is elsewhere: Critical History
The truth is elsewhere: Critical HistoryAbubakar S. Mama
 

Similar to Aristotle S Theory Of Revolution Looking At The Lockean Side (15)

A brief introduction to the study of political philosophy
A brief introduction to the study of political philosophyA brief introduction to the study of political philosophy
A brief introduction to the study of political philosophy
 
political_theory.pdf
political_theory.pdfpolitical_theory.pdf
political_theory.pdf
 
Totalitarianism Essay. Methodist University
Totalitarianism Essay. Methodist UniversityTotalitarianism Essay. Methodist University
Totalitarianism Essay. Methodist University
 
Lesson 1.pptx
Lesson 1.pptxLesson 1.pptx
Lesson 1.pptx
 
Lesson 1.pptx
Lesson 1.pptxLesson 1.pptx
Lesson 1.pptx
 
151272423 certainties-undone
151272423 certainties-undone151272423 certainties-undone
151272423 certainties-undone
 
Topic of discussion Uptopian IdeasRequired Textbook 
Topic of discussion  Uptopian IdeasRequired Textbook Topic of discussion  Uptopian IdeasRequired Textbook 
Topic of discussion Uptopian IdeasRequired Textbook 
 
Coleman y leiter determinacy objectivity and authority
Coleman y leiter  determinacy objectivity and authorityColeman y leiter  determinacy objectivity and authority
Coleman y leiter determinacy objectivity and authority
 
Theories Of International Relations
Theories Of International RelationsTheories Of International Relations
Theories Of International Relations
 
Administrative Theory & Praxis, 38 101–114, 2016 Copyright .docx
Administrative Theory & Praxis, 38 101–114, 2016 Copyright .docxAdministrative Theory & Praxis, 38 101–114, 2016 Copyright .docx
Administrative Theory & Praxis, 38 101–114, 2016 Copyright .docx
 
Topic Political SystemsInstructionsExplain how conservat
Topic Political SystemsInstructionsExplain how conservatTopic Political SystemsInstructionsExplain how conservat
Topic Political SystemsInstructionsExplain how conservat
 
Ideology as constraint
Ideology as constraintIdeology as constraint
Ideology as constraint
 
PLATO’S CRITICISMS OF DEMOCRACYIN THE REPUBLICBy Gerasi.docx
PLATO’S CRITICISMS OF DEMOCRACYIN THE REPUBLICBy Gerasi.docxPLATO’S CRITICISMS OF DEMOCRACYIN THE REPUBLICBy Gerasi.docx
PLATO’S CRITICISMS OF DEMOCRACYIN THE REPUBLICBy Gerasi.docx
 
Unit 5 Comparative methods and Approaches
Unit 5 Comparative methods and ApproachesUnit 5 Comparative methods and Approaches
Unit 5 Comparative methods and Approaches
 
The truth is elsewhere: Critical History
The  truth is elsewhere: Critical HistoryThe  truth is elsewhere: Critical History
The truth is elsewhere: Critical History
 

More from Michele Thomas

Cara Menulis Angka Dengan Kata Dalam Bahasa Inggris L
Cara Menulis Angka Dengan Kata Dalam Bahasa Inggris LCara Menulis Angka Dengan Kata Dalam Bahasa Inggris L
Cara Menulis Angka Dengan Kata Dalam Bahasa Inggris LMichele Thomas
 
Critical Essay Short Persuasive Text Examples
Critical Essay Short Persuasive Text ExamplesCritical Essay Short Persuasive Text Examples
Critical Essay Short Persuasive Text ExamplesMichele Thomas
 
Samanthability - College Essay Writing Tips - Sama
Samanthability - College Essay Writing Tips - SamaSamanthability - College Essay Writing Tips - Sama
Samanthability - College Essay Writing Tips - SamaMichele Thomas
 
Prompt Assignment Help In The UK From Top Service WritingSquirrell
Prompt Assignment Help In The UK From Top Service WritingSquirrellPrompt Assignment Help In The UK From Top Service WritingSquirrell
Prompt Assignment Help In The UK From Top Service WritingSquirrellMichele Thomas
 
1 Buy Essays Papers. Pay F
1 Buy Essays Papers. Pay F1 Buy Essays Papers. Pay F
1 Buy Essays Papers. Pay FMichele Thomas
 
Example Of Essay About Life Experience
Example Of Essay About Life ExperienceExample Of Essay About Life Experience
Example Of Essay About Life ExperienceMichele Thomas
 
Pay For Essay Online Affordable Prices 247 Support - EssayVikings.Com
Pay For Essay Online Affordable Prices 247 Support - EssayVikings.ComPay For Essay Online Affordable Prices 247 Support - EssayVikings.Com
Pay For Essay Online Affordable Prices 247 Support - EssayVikings.ComMichele Thomas
 
Business Paper Essay On High School Experience
Business Paper Essay On High School ExperienceBusiness Paper Essay On High School Experience
Business Paper Essay On High School ExperienceMichele Thomas
 
Frog Writing Papers - Spring Writing Activiti
Frog Writing Papers - Spring Writing ActivitiFrog Writing Papers - Spring Writing Activiti
Frog Writing Papers - Spring Writing ActivitiMichele Thomas
 
Thesis Statement Practice Worksheet B
Thesis Statement Practice Worksheet BThesis Statement Practice Worksheet B
Thesis Statement Practice Worksheet BMichele Thomas
 
Example Of Position Paper Outline Position Paper D
Example Of Position Paper Outline Position Paper DExample Of Position Paper Outline Position Paper D
Example Of Position Paper Outline Position Paper DMichele Thomas
 
Benefits Of Professional Paper Writing Service By Su
Benefits Of Professional Paper Writing Service By SuBenefits Of Professional Paper Writing Service By Su
Benefits Of Professional Paper Writing Service By SuMichele Thomas
 
Thesis Statement Examples For Explanatory Essay - T
Thesis Statement Examples For Explanatory Essay - TThesis Statement Examples For Explanatory Essay - T
Thesis Statement Examples For Explanatory Essay - TMichele Thomas
 
Research Report Sample Template (8) - TEMPLATE
Research Report Sample Template (8) - TEMPLATEResearch Report Sample Template (8) - TEMPLATE
Research Report Sample Template (8) - TEMPLATEMichele Thomas
 
Free Printable Writing Paper Templates Page 23
Free Printable Writing Paper Templates Page 23Free Printable Writing Paper Templates Page 23
Free Printable Writing Paper Templates Page 23Michele Thomas
 
013 How To Write Good Biographical Essay Biogra
013 How To Write Good Biographical Essay Biogra013 How To Write Good Biographical Essay Biogra
013 How To Write Good Biographical Essay BiograMichele Thomas
 
How To Write An Assignment Introduction Sample. How To Struct
How To Write An Assignment Introduction Sample. How To StructHow To Write An Assignment Introduction Sample. How To Struct
How To Write An Assignment Introduction Sample. How To StructMichele Thomas
 
Manual For Writers Of Research Papers Resear
Manual For Writers Of Research Papers  ResearManual For Writers Of Research Papers  Resear
Manual For Writers Of Research Papers ResearMichele Thomas
 
Sports Writing Topics. Sports Persuasive Speech Topic
Sports Writing Topics. Sports Persuasive Speech TopicSports Writing Topics. Sports Persuasive Speech Topic
Sports Writing Topics. Sports Persuasive Speech TopicMichele Thomas
 
006 Examples Of Introductory Paragraphs For Expository Essays ...
006 Examples Of Introductory Paragraphs For Expository Essays ...006 Examples Of Introductory Paragraphs For Expository Essays ...
006 Examples Of Introductory Paragraphs For Expository Essays ...Michele Thomas
 

More from Michele Thomas (20)

Cara Menulis Angka Dengan Kata Dalam Bahasa Inggris L
Cara Menulis Angka Dengan Kata Dalam Bahasa Inggris LCara Menulis Angka Dengan Kata Dalam Bahasa Inggris L
Cara Menulis Angka Dengan Kata Dalam Bahasa Inggris L
 
Critical Essay Short Persuasive Text Examples
Critical Essay Short Persuasive Text ExamplesCritical Essay Short Persuasive Text Examples
Critical Essay Short Persuasive Text Examples
 
Samanthability - College Essay Writing Tips - Sama
Samanthability - College Essay Writing Tips - SamaSamanthability - College Essay Writing Tips - Sama
Samanthability - College Essay Writing Tips - Sama
 
Prompt Assignment Help In The UK From Top Service WritingSquirrell
Prompt Assignment Help In The UK From Top Service WritingSquirrellPrompt Assignment Help In The UK From Top Service WritingSquirrell
Prompt Assignment Help In The UK From Top Service WritingSquirrell
 
1 Buy Essays Papers. Pay F
1 Buy Essays Papers. Pay F1 Buy Essays Papers. Pay F
1 Buy Essays Papers. Pay F
 
Example Of Essay About Life Experience
Example Of Essay About Life ExperienceExample Of Essay About Life Experience
Example Of Essay About Life Experience
 
Pay For Essay Online Affordable Prices 247 Support - EssayVikings.Com
Pay For Essay Online Affordable Prices 247 Support - EssayVikings.ComPay For Essay Online Affordable Prices 247 Support - EssayVikings.Com
Pay For Essay Online Affordable Prices 247 Support - EssayVikings.Com
 
Business Paper Essay On High School Experience
Business Paper Essay On High School ExperienceBusiness Paper Essay On High School Experience
Business Paper Essay On High School Experience
 
Frog Writing Papers - Spring Writing Activiti
Frog Writing Papers - Spring Writing ActivitiFrog Writing Papers - Spring Writing Activiti
Frog Writing Papers - Spring Writing Activiti
 
Thesis Statement Practice Worksheet B
Thesis Statement Practice Worksheet BThesis Statement Practice Worksheet B
Thesis Statement Practice Worksheet B
 
Example Of Position Paper Outline Position Paper D
Example Of Position Paper Outline Position Paper DExample Of Position Paper Outline Position Paper D
Example Of Position Paper Outline Position Paper D
 
Benefits Of Professional Paper Writing Service By Su
Benefits Of Professional Paper Writing Service By SuBenefits Of Professional Paper Writing Service By Su
Benefits Of Professional Paper Writing Service By Su
 
Thesis Statement Examples For Explanatory Essay - T
Thesis Statement Examples For Explanatory Essay - TThesis Statement Examples For Explanatory Essay - T
Thesis Statement Examples For Explanatory Essay - T
 
Research Report Sample Template (8) - TEMPLATE
Research Report Sample Template (8) - TEMPLATEResearch Report Sample Template (8) - TEMPLATE
Research Report Sample Template (8) - TEMPLATE
 
Free Printable Writing Paper Templates Page 23
Free Printable Writing Paper Templates Page 23Free Printable Writing Paper Templates Page 23
Free Printable Writing Paper Templates Page 23
 
013 How To Write Good Biographical Essay Biogra
013 How To Write Good Biographical Essay Biogra013 How To Write Good Biographical Essay Biogra
013 How To Write Good Biographical Essay Biogra
 
How To Write An Assignment Introduction Sample. How To Struct
How To Write An Assignment Introduction Sample. How To StructHow To Write An Assignment Introduction Sample. How To Struct
How To Write An Assignment Introduction Sample. How To Struct
 
Manual For Writers Of Research Papers Resear
Manual For Writers Of Research Papers  ResearManual For Writers Of Research Papers  Resear
Manual For Writers Of Research Papers Resear
 
Sports Writing Topics. Sports Persuasive Speech Topic
Sports Writing Topics. Sports Persuasive Speech TopicSports Writing Topics. Sports Persuasive Speech Topic
Sports Writing Topics. Sports Persuasive Speech Topic
 
006 Examples Of Introductory Paragraphs For Expository Essays ...
006 Examples Of Introductory Paragraphs For Expository Essays ...006 Examples Of Introductory Paragraphs For Expository Essays ...
006 Examples Of Introductory Paragraphs For Expository Essays ...
 

Recently uploaded

Paris 2024 Olympic Geographies - an activity
Paris 2024 Olympic Geographies - an activityParis 2024 Olympic Geographies - an activity
Paris 2024 Olympic Geographies - an activityGeoBlogs
 
Organic Name Reactions for the students and aspirants of Chemistry12th.pptx
Organic Name Reactions  for the students and aspirants of Chemistry12th.pptxOrganic Name Reactions  for the students and aspirants of Chemistry12th.pptx
Organic Name Reactions for the students and aspirants of Chemistry12th.pptxVS Mahajan Coaching Centre
 
Contemporary philippine arts from the regions_PPT_Module_12 [Autosaved] (1).pptx
Contemporary philippine arts from the regions_PPT_Module_12 [Autosaved] (1).pptxContemporary philippine arts from the regions_PPT_Module_12 [Autosaved] (1).pptx
Contemporary philippine arts from the regions_PPT_Module_12 [Autosaved] (1).pptxRoyAbrique
 
Call Girls in Dwarka Mor Delhi Contact Us 9654467111
Call Girls in Dwarka Mor Delhi Contact Us 9654467111Call Girls in Dwarka Mor Delhi Contact Us 9654467111
Call Girls in Dwarka Mor Delhi Contact Us 9654467111Sapana Sha
 
Mastering the Unannounced Regulatory Inspection
Mastering the Unannounced Regulatory InspectionMastering the Unannounced Regulatory Inspection
Mastering the Unannounced Regulatory InspectionSafetyChain Software
 
1029 - Danh muc Sach Giao Khoa 10 . pdf
1029 -  Danh muc Sach Giao Khoa 10 . pdf1029 -  Danh muc Sach Giao Khoa 10 . pdf
1029 - Danh muc Sach Giao Khoa 10 . pdfQucHHunhnh
 
Arihant handbook biology for class 11 .pdf
Arihant handbook biology for class 11 .pdfArihant handbook biology for class 11 .pdf
Arihant handbook biology for class 11 .pdfchloefrazer622
 
Presentation by Andreas Schleicher Tackling the School Absenteeism Crisis 30 ...
Presentation by Andreas Schleicher Tackling the School Absenteeism Crisis 30 ...Presentation by Andreas Schleicher Tackling the School Absenteeism Crisis 30 ...
Presentation by Andreas Schleicher Tackling the School Absenteeism Crisis 30 ...EduSkills OECD
 
Sanyam Choudhary Chemistry practical.pdf
Sanyam Choudhary Chemistry practical.pdfSanyam Choudhary Chemistry practical.pdf
Sanyam Choudhary Chemistry practical.pdfsanyamsingh5019
 
18-04-UA_REPORT_MEDIALITERAСY_INDEX-DM_23-1-final-eng.pdf
18-04-UA_REPORT_MEDIALITERAСY_INDEX-DM_23-1-final-eng.pdf18-04-UA_REPORT_MEDIALITERAСY_INDEX-DM_23-1-final-eng.pdf
18-04-UA_REPORT_MEDIALITERAСY_INDEX-DM_23-1-final-eng.pdfssuser54595a
 
SOCIAL AND HISTORICAL CONTEXT - LFTVD.pptx
SOCIAL AND HISTORICAL CONTEXT - LFTVD.pptxSOCIAL AND HISTORICAL CONTEXT - LFTVD.pptx
SOCIAL AND HISTORICAL CONTEXT - LFTVD.pptxiammrhaywood
 
Z Score,T Score, Percential Rank and Box Plot Graph
Z Score,T Score, Percential Rank and Box Plot GraphZ Score,T Score, Percential Rank and Box Plot Graph
Z Score,T Score, Percential Rank and Box Plot GraphThiyagu K
 
“Oh GOSH! Reflecting on Hackteria's Collaborative Practices in a Global Do-It...
“Oh GOSH! Reflecting on Hackteria's Collaborative Practices in a Global Do-It...“Oh GOSH! Reflecting on Hackteria's Collaborative Practices in a Global Do-It...
“Oh GOSH! Reflecting on Hackteria's Collaborative Practices in a Global Do-It...Marc Dusseiller Dusjagr
 
A Critique of the Proposed National Education Policy Reform
A Critique of the Proposed National Education Policy ReformA Critique of the Proposed National Education Policy Reform
A Critique of the Proposed National Education Policy ReformChameera Dedduwage
 
POINT- BIOCHEMISTRY SEM 2 ENZYMES UNIT 5.pptx
POINT- BIOCHEMISTRY SEM 2 ENZYMES UNIT 5.pptxPOINT- BIOCHEMISTRY SEM 2 ENZYMES UNIT 5.pptx
POINT- BIOCHEMISTRY SEM 2 ENZYMES UNIT 5.pptxSayali Powar
 
Nutritional Needs Presentation - HLTH 104
Nutritional Needs Presentation - HLTH 104Nutritional Needs Presentation - HLTH 104
Nutritional Needs Presentation - HLTH 104misteraugie
 
BASLIQ CURRENT LOOKBOOK LOOKBOOK(1) (1).pdf
BASLIQ CURRENT LOOKBOOK  LOOKBOOK(1) (1).pdfBASLIQ CURRENT LOOKBOOK  LOOKBOOK(1) (1).pdf
BASLIQ CURRENT LOOKBOOK LOOKBOOK(1) (1).pdfSoniaTolstoy
 
Beyond the EU: DORA and NIS 2 Directive's Global Impact
Beyond the EU: DORA and NIS 2 Directive's Global ImpactBeyond the EU: DORA and NIS 2 Directive's Global Impact
Beyond the EU: DORA and NIS 2 Directive's Global ImpactPECB
 
URLs and Routing in the Odoo 17 Website App
URLs and Routing in the Odoo 17 Website AppURLs and Routing in the Odoo 17 Website App
URLs and Routing in the Odoo 17 Website AppCeline George
 

Recently uploaded (20)

Paris 2024 Olympic Geographies - an activity
Paris 2024 Olympic Geographies - an activityParis 2024 Olympic Geographies - an activity
Paris 2024 Olympic Geographies - an activity
 
Organic Name Reactions for the students and aspirants of Chemistry12th.pptx
Organic Name Reactions  for the students and aspirants of Chemistry12th.pptxOrganic Name Reactions  for the students and aspirants of Chemistry12th.pptx
Organic Name Reactions for the students and aspirants of Chemistry12th.pptx
 
Contemporary philippine arts from the regions_PPT_Module_12 [Autosaved] (1).pptx
Contemporary philippine arts from the regions_PPT_Module_12 [Autosaved] (1).pptxContemporary philippine arts from the regions_PPT_Module_12 [Autosaved] (1).pptx
Contemporary philippine arts from the regions_PPT_Module_12 [Autosaved] (1).pptx
 
Call Girls in Dwarka Mor Delhi Contact Us 9654467111
Call Girls in Dwarka Mor Delhi Contact Us 9654467111Call Girls in Dwarka Mor Delhi Contact Us 9654467111
Call Girls in Dwarka Mor Delhi Contact Us 9654467111
 
Mastering the Unannounced Regulatory Inspection
Mastering the Unannounced Regulatory InspectionMastering the Unannounced Regulatory Inspection
Mastering the Unannounced Regulatory Inspection
 
1029 - Danh muc Sach Giao Khoa 10 . pdf
1029 -  Danh muc Sach Giao Khoa 10 . pdf1029 -  Danh muc Sach Giao Khoa 10 . pdf
1029 - Danh muc Sach Giao Khoa 10 . pdf
 
Arihant handbook biology for class 11 .pdf
Arihant handbook biology for class 11 .pdfArihant handbook biology for class 11 .pdf
Arihant handbook biology for class 11 .pdf
 
Presentation by Andreas Schleicher Tackling the School Absenteeism Crisis 30 ...
Presentation by Andreas Schleicher Tackling the School Absenteeism Crisis 30 ...Presentation by Andreas Schleicher Tackling the School Absenteeism Crisis 30 ...
Presentation by Andreas Schleicher Tackling the School Absenteeism Crisis 30 ...
 
Sanyam Choudhary Chemistry practical.pdf
Sanyam Choudhary Chemistry practical.pdfSanyam Choudhary Chemistry practical.pdf
Sanyam Choudhary Chemistry practical.pdf
 
Mattingly "AI & Prompt Design: The Basics of Prompt Design"
Mattingly "AI & Prompt Design: The Basics of Prompt Design"Mattingly "AI & Prompt Design: The Basics of Prompt Design"
Mattingly "AI & Prompt Design: The Basics of Prompt Design"
 
18-04-UA_REPORT_MEDIALITERAСY_INDEX-DM_23-1-final-eng.pdf
18-04-UA_REPORT_MEDIALITERAСY_INDEX-DM_23-1-final-eng.pdf18-04-UA_REPORT_MEDIALITERAСY_INDEX-DM_23-1-final-eng.pdf
18-04-UA_REPORT_MEDIALITERAСY_INDEX-DM_23-1-final-eng.pdf
 
SOCIAL AND HISTORICAL CONTEXT - LFTVD.pptx
SOCIAL AND HISTORICAL CONTEXT - LFTVD.pptxSOCIAL AND HISTORICAL CONTEXT - LFTVD.pptx
SOCIAL AND HISTORICAL CONTEXT - LFTVD.pptx
 
Z Score,T Score, Percential Rank and Box Plot Graph
Z Score,T Score, Percential Rank and Box Plot GraphZ Score,T Score, Percential Rank and Box Plot Graph
Z Score,T Score, Percential Rank and Box Plot Graph
 
“Oh GOSH! Reflecting on Hackteria's Collaborative Practices in a Global Do-It...
“Oh GOSH! Reflecting on Hackteria's Collaborative Practices in a Global Do-It...“Oh GOSH! Reflecting on Hackteria's Collaborative Practices in a Global Do-It...
“Oh GOSH! Reflecting on Hackteria's Collaborative Practices in a Global Do-It...
 
A Critique of the Proposed National Education Policy Reform
A Critique of the Proposed National Education Policy ReformA Critique of the Proposed National Education Policy Reform
A Critique of the Proposed National Education Policy Reform
 
POINT- BIOCHEMISTRY SEM 2 ENZYMES UNIT 5.pptx
POINT- BIOCHEMISTRY SEM 2 ENZYMES UNIT 5.pptxPOINT- BIOCHEMISTRY SEM 2 ENZYMES UNIT 5.pptx
POINT- BIOCHEMISTRY SEM 2 ENZYMES UNIT 5.pptx
 
Nutritional Needs Presentation - HLTH 104
Nutritional Needs Presentation - HLTH 104Nutritional Needs Presentation - HLTH 104
Nutritional Needs Presentation - HLTH 104
 
BASLIQ CURRENT LOOKBOOK LOOKBOOK(1) (1).pdf
BASLIQ CURRENT LOOKBOOK  LOOKBOOK(1) (1).pdfBASLIQ CURRENT LOOKBOOK  LOOKBOOK(1) (1).pdf
BASLIQ CURRENT LOOKBOOK LOOKBOOK(1) (1).pdf
 
Beyond the EU: DORA and NIS 2 Directive's Global Impact
Beyond the EU: DORA and NIS 2 Directive's Global ImpactBeyond the EU: DORA and NIS 2 Directive's Global Impact
Beyond the EU: DORA and NIS 2 Directive's Global Impact
 
URLs and Routing in the Odoo 17 Website App
URLs and Routing in the Odoo 17 Website AppURLs and Routing in the Odoo 17 Website App
URLs and Routing in the Odoo 17 Website App
 

Aristotle S Theory Of Revolution Looking At The Lockean Side

  • 1. University of Utah Aristotle's Theory of Revolution: Looking at the Lockean Side Author(s): Leslie Friedman Goldstein Source: Political Research Quarterly, Vol. 54, No. 2 (Jun., 2001), pp. 311-331 Published by: Sage Publications, Inc. on behalf of the University of Utah Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/449159 Accessed: 21-08-2017 21:20 UTC JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org. Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at http://about.jstor.org/terms Sage Publications, Inc., University of Utah are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Political Research Quarterly This content downloaded from 132.174.254.72 on Mon, 21 Aug 2017 21:20:33 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
  • 2. Aristotle's Theory of Revolution: Looking at the Lockean Side LESLIE FRIEDMAN GOLDSTEIN, UNIVERSITY OF DELAWARE This article provides a detailed account of the theory of revolution pre- sented in Books IV-VI of Aristotle's Politics and argues that despite impor- tant differences of emphasis, rhetoric, and tone, there is a surprising degree of similarity to the theory of revolution familiar to Americans from John Locke's Second Treatise of Government. Aristotle and Locke share the views that governments must avoid oppressing their subjects if they are to avoid being overthrown, that revolution against oppressive rulers is inevitable, that security for property would have a central place in the avoidance of oppression, and that the succumbing to the temptations of power on the part of ruling groups is the fundamental provocation of rev- olution. This aspect of Aristotle's political thought has been little noticed, but is an important dimension of it. Moreover, it provides a certain depth of insight into that side of Locke's thought that most sharply contrasts with Hobbes's thought, namely Locke's distrust of the corrupting force of political power. In Books IV-VI of Politics Aristotle supplemented the Socratic options for stemming abuses of political power-the teaching of moderation and the luring of potential tyrants toward philosophy-by invoking the low but solid ground of the rulers' self-interest in staying in power. The core premises of the Aristotelian teaching on sedition are essentially a "crime doesn't pay" story for rulers. These premises were then available for Locke's much later elaboration when he-like Aristotle suspicious of the corrupting force of political power-needed an alter- native to Hobbes's absolutist political conclusions. This claim about the core of Aristotle's teaching on sedition sheds significant new light on Aristotle's maxim that the political theorist must elaborate not only the best regime for an ideal situation but should also provide guidance for poli- tics "based on a [given] presupposition" (Politics IV, 1, 1288b 28-30).1 Locke's supposition is emphatically that what people want from politics is the preserva- tion of their lives, liberties, and properties. Aristotle argues in Book III that 1 Translations generally follow Lord (1984). Where they differ, they are my own. Poliitical Research Quarterly, Vol. 54 (June 2001): pp. 311-331 311 This content downloaded from 132.174.254.72 on Mon, 21 Aug 2017 21:20:33 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
  • 3. Political Research Quarterly people form their political association for the good life, a life of happiness, or human flourishing. Happiness requires that people of good character be formed. But it turns out in Books IV-VI that, while a few are motivated by the desire for honor, most people most of the time are motivated by concern for their property and their physical dignity and security Genuinely good people, who have the desire and capacity to serve the public good, rarely hold political power. Even when they do hold power, their appetites and passions open them to being cor- rupted if legal institutions are not structured in such a way as to check their power (III, 3: 1287a 31-32). Consequently, the "given supposition" typically in play in Aristotle's prescriptions for real-world politics may be not so far from the world that Locke describes. The argument here does not rely on a view that John Locke was some sort of latter-day Thomist, who like St. Thomas took his bearings from a law of nature that amounted to an adaptation of the concept of natural justice, or what was right according to nature, found in Aristotle.2 To the contrary, one can take as a point of departure that: "It is on the basis of Hobbes's view of the law of nature that Locke opposes Hobbes's conclusions. He tries to show that Hobbes's principle-the right of self-preservation-far from favoring absolute government, requires limited gov- ernment" (Strauss 1953: 231-32; for a similar view see also Cox 1960 and 1982; Macpherson 1962; Goldwin 1987; M. Zuckert 1994: 234-237 and 240; but cf. Grant 1987; Simmons' 1993, and the preponderance of Locke scholarship cited therein for the view that Locke's state of nature differs radically from that of Hobbes). Whatever may be Locke's similarities with Hobbes, it is nonetheless clear that those of Locke's "conclusions" that amount to his theory of revolution openly, deliberately, and directly opposed Hobbes's view condemning revolutionary resist- ance to oppressive government (as expressed, e.g., in Leviathan, ch. 20). It is the argument of this article that most of the core premises of Locke's theory of revolution are present in Aristotle's political writings. The sole exception to this claim, albeit an important exception, is Locke's grounding of the right of revolution in the rhetoric of pre-political inalienable rights; such rhetoric is absent in Aristotle. The claim is not that Locke took his premises directly from Aristo- tle-this article is not a biographical exercise.3 Rather it is an essay on Aristotle's political thought, an essay in the spirit of the argument of Gadamer (1975: espe- 2 Cf. Barker (1962) lxi-lxii. 3 As a strictly historical matter, while Locke may in fact have adapted both his rhetorical approach and the substance of his justification of revolution from some of the things Aristotle says, there are numerous conceivable alternative sources of influence that intervened in the two thousand years that separate the two men, which also may have helped to shape Locke's thinking on a popular right of revolution. These range from Roman theories of popular control over the emperor, to feudal theories of limits on kingship, to church governance theories of both the conciliarists and monar- chomachs, to common law traditions (see, e.g., Procop? 1988; Nelson 1988; Dunbabin 1988; Black 1988; Vincent 1987, ch.3; Myers 1982 and the numerous sources cited therein). 312 This content downloaded from 132.174.254.72 on Mon, 21 Aug 2017 21:20:33 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
  • 4. Aristotle's Theory of Revolution cially 235-40, 258-67, 482-85; see also Yack 1993: 18-21) that one cannot help but view the thought of philosophers of the past through a prism shaped by the later philosophic tradition of which one is aware, and by which one's own thought has to some degree been influenced. Locke depicted in stark and striking tones the inevitability and justness of revolutionary resistance to tyranny; the clarity and starkness of Locke's analysis rendered it more difficult, perhaps, for post-Locke generations to discern the more muted statements along similar lines in Aristotle. The argument here is that there is much more of the Lockean in Aristotle's political thought, especially in Books IV through VI of Politics, than is generally recognized.4 It is at least possible that Locke did find a large part of his inspira- tion directly in Aristotle's writings, although that is not the point. The point is that a highlighting of these rather muted Locken themes in Aristotle's theory of revolution will help bring into clearer focus certain other important elements of Aristotle's overall political philosophy. Granted, the discussion of revolution as Aristotle presents it contrasts sharply with Locke's approach, at least at first glance. Locke is seeking an answer to the question whether reason, employed as a tool to serve the natural impulse to comfortable self-preservation, suggests that there must be limits on the power of government, and, if so, what mechanism can enforce those limits? Aristotle addresses a different question: How can existing government stave off the sedi- tion that is the prelude to revolution, and thereby revolution itself?5 Yet despite the difference in the formal focus of their respective questions, there is a surpris- ing degree of substantive similarity of content in the answers they generate. As a prelude to this exercise of recovering Aristotle's teaching on revolution, this essay, first, outlines the core premises of John Locke's theory of revolution. Next it describes the sense and extent to which these premises are present in Aristotle's Politics. The essay concludes with an elaboration of the claim that attention to this under-explored aspect of Aristotle's thought enriches one's understanding of both Aristotle and of Locke. PRELUDE: LOCKE'S THEORY OF REVOLUTION Summary Locke's theory of revolution is at once normative and descriptive, and is a story familiar to most Americans: Governments exist for the purpose of securing 4 This is not, however, a claim that Locke's notion of "rights" is rooted in Aristotle, cf. Miller 1995, 1996. 5 Aristotle also addresses broader questions of how to stave off political change generally-not just sedition and revolution-but his answer to this general question is undercut by many of his rec- ommendations concerning the specific question of how to stave off revolution. Specifically, he rec- ommends that unjust regimes should be reformed (to stave off revolution). Since reform is a kind of political change, this specific advice undercuts the purported advice against regime change in general. This undercutting appears to be intentional. 313 This content downloaded from 132.174.254.72 on Mon, 21 Aug 2017 21:20:33 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
  • 5. Political Research Quarterly to each member of society his6 life, liberty , and estate. Humans have the impulse of self-preservation as a matter of nature and therefore the impulse is God-given. Liberty and property as the means of preservation also belong to individuals, therefore, as a matter of God-given natural rights. But humans-"the greater part no strict observers of equity and justice"-have a way of being biased by self- interest in judging conflicts over where their property ends and another's begins. Therefore, without government, people would be exposed to "continual dan- gers"; their lives, freedom and possessions, "very unsafe, very unsecure" (para. 123). So men compact, each with everyone, to form a society where they agree to put all their forces together under a government whose form will be chosen by the majority. This government will provide clear rules (a "settled, known law"), independent judges for disputes, and an executive force to back up judg- ments. The power of this government must logically be limited by the end for which it was formed-preservation of the lives, liberties, and fortunes of the soci- ety.7 If the people in government ever set out to attack these things, which Locke likes to call collectively the "property" of the members of society, it no longer makes sense to think of these people as the government. They have abandoned the job with which they were entrusted, and they should, and will, be fought as the public enemies they have shown themselves to be. They have introduced a state of war against their former fellow-citizens by using "force without right" (para. 232). Between such tyrannical rulers and the society they have attacked there exists perforce a state of nature, because any two parties who do not share an agreed-upon judge are in such a condition. And in this condition everyone has the right of nature, which is to say, the right of self-defense. So revolution against tyrannical government is by nature right, whether the government be a single prince, a select few, or a legislature comprised of elected representatives of the majority.8 6 Locke writes repeatedly of the "uniting into commonwealths" as something that "men" do. See, e.g., Second Treatise, para. 124. Hereafter, references to the Second Treatise will give simply the paragraph number. 7 Individual members of society each join and consent to government with private goals, each to secure his own comfortable self-preservation. But once society has been formed, the job of gov- ernment becomes the securing of the lives, liberty and possessions of the society as a whole, in peace and safety, and the protection of each individual member becomes a secondary consideration (para. 129, 131, 134, 217). It is to be pursued only "as far as will consist with the public good" (para. 134). 8 Locke does write that any form of government ("one or many") might behave tyrannically (para. 201). However, he-unlike Aristotle--does not really discuss the possibility that a direct democ- racy would behave tyrannically toward those outside of government, i.e., outside the majority I believe this is because Locke's theory of revolution has no solution for such tyranny. His theory would define it as tyranny, but unlike all other versions of tyranny, it cannot be kept in check by the fear of a successful revolution by the oppressed majority Without oppression of the "major force" in a community, or at least a well-grounded fear that the oppression threatens to reach a 314 This content downloaded from 132.174.254.72 on Mon, 21 Aug 2017 21:20:33 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
  • 6. Aristotle's Theory of Revolution Operational Premises Locke's operational theory of revolution, that is, his theory as a matter of observable practice, of how, when and why revolution occurs is as follows: 1. Inevitability: Human nature being what it is, if government engages in a "long train" of actions that either attack the lives, freedom, or property of the majority of the people, or are such that the "precedent and consequences seem to threaten all," it is inevitable that the people will fight back against the govern- ment that is attacking them (on long train of abuses, see para. 168, 205, 209, 210, 225, 230; on inevitability, see also para. 94, 149, 224; "First Letter on Tol- eration," at pp. 53-54.) People threatened by severe misrule "cannot but feel what they lie under" (para. 225), and the natural response to collective threat is collective self-defense. 2. As a corollary to inevitability, it follows that attempts at deception of the mass of the people about the fact of their oppression cannot succeed in staving off revo- lution. "[T]alk ... hinders men not from feeling." [W]hen the people are made miserable ... cry up their governors, as much as you will for sons of Jupiter, let them be sacred and divine, descended or author- ized from Heaven; give them out for whom or what you please the same will happen. The people generally ill treated, and contrary to right, will be ready upon any occasion to ease themselves of a burden that sits heavy upon them. .. (para.224; Locke's italics). 3. As a general matter, oppressions of a few that are not seen as threats to the many do not provoke revolution; revolutions are provoked only when the dominant force in a community-the majority-feels threatened: Because revolution arises as an expression of the natural impulse to self-preservation (which includes the natu- ral impulse to retain the liberty and material acquisitions that facilitate preserva- tion), an isolated, oppressed minority unable to persuade a majority that it too faces the threat of oppression will not normally, i.e., not rationally, attempt an overthrow of government, because to do so will be suicidal, and therefore con- trary to their natural impulses (para. 208; see also 161, 168, 209, 223, 225, 230). Indeed, even the majority is prone not to stir without substantial provoca- tion; only a long train of abuses suffices to break through their inertia; revolution, after all entails substantial risk-would-be perpetrators need to be convinced that an attempt is worth the "trouble and cost" (para. 176).9 majority eventually, there cannot be rational hope for a victorious revolution, so the minority nor- mally will simply endure their oppression. Locke's theory does not offer effectual protection for minority rights (apart from the solace that God and nature are in principle on their side.) 9 My attention was drawn to this passage by Grant (1987: 167). 315 This content downloaded from 132.174.254.72 on Mon, 21 Aug 2017 21:20:33 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
  • 7. Political Research Quarterly At this point a divergence arises between Locke's theory of what is right according to nature and what happens as a matter of the normal patterns of what might be called brute nature or mere nature. Many regimes that deprive minori- ties of what is justly, or by nature, their right, will nonetheless, according to the logic of brute nature, endure.10 Despite Premise 3, however, Locke does admit that some factious people on occasion have behaved irrationally: 4. Contrary to the natural pattern, sometimes exceptions do occur, in which excep- tionally ambitious or prideful men stir up sedition to the point of "great disorder" Locke "grant[s] that the pride, ambition, and turbulency of private men have sometimes caused great disorders in commonwealths, and factions have been fatal to states and kingdoms" (para. 230). But he suggests that faction has more often been trig- gered by "the rulers' insolence, and endeavors to get, and exercise an arbitrary power over their people" than by a "desire in the people to cast off the lawful authority of their rulers" (para. 226, 230; Locke's italics). Thus, two more prem- ises are these: 5. Those who hold governmental power are more likely to provoke sedition and revolution by tyrannical behavior than are the ruled to engage in unprovoked, or even slightly provoked sedition. This is true because: 6. Power has a corrupting influence. [T]hey who are in power (by the pretence they have to authority, the tempta- tion of force they have in their hands, and the flattery of those about them) [are] likeliest to [provoke revolution]; the properest way to prevent the evil is to show them the danger and injustice of it who are under the greatest temptation to run into it (para. 226; see also 91-93, 111, 137, 218). 7. The final clause of this quotation yields the next premise: The "best fence against rebellion" that a political theorist can provide is to persuade rulers (not their too-often put-upon subjects) to mend their ways, by warning them that oppressive gov- ernment is what causes revolution (para. 226).11 Rulers need to temper their insolence and greed, which are likely to be aggravated by the temptations of power. The stimulus to such self-reform can be provided by an awareness, offered by the political theorist, Locke, that such restraint will enable their rule 10 This would seem to be an utterly straightforward reading of the paragraphs cited at Premise 3, but a number of Locke scholars dispute it. For a discussion of the debate, see citations and analysis thereof in Simmons 1993: 172-77. 1 Cf. Tarcov (1981) who argues that the "best fence," in Locke's view, is an alert oppositional polit- ical leadership who will alert the citizenry about a build-up of princely power tending toward tyranny In my judgment, Tarcov's interpretation relies on reading more into para. 242 than is really there and gives too little attention to Locke's actual description of the benefit of his teaching on revolution in para. 226. 316 This content downloaded from 132.174.254.72 on Mon, 21 Aug 2017 21:20:33 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
  • 8. Aristotle's Theory of Revolution to last (and peace and prosperity thereby to prevail). Locke is putting forth his teaching on revolution, "this doctrine," as "the probablest means to hinder [rebel- lion]." The "rebellion" in question is tyrannical behavior by the ruler that re- introduces the state of war. Locke's rhetorical emphasis is overwhelmingly addressed to the human pas- sion of greed; thus he repeatedly warns that: 8. What rulers need to refrain from attacking is the "property" of their subjects.12 Moreover, he advises them that "the increase of lands and the right employing of them [i.e., by developing an incentive structure that encourages industriousness] is the great art of government" (para. 42). While Locke clearly indicates that he uses the term "property" to include "life, liberty and estate," his choice of this dic- tion inevitably underlines, as a practical matter, people's concerns with their own material possessions. 9. Rulers heedful of Locke can easily avoid having seditious subjects, because a populace contented by security for their lives and property will be the rulers' strongest bulwark against the rare, ambitious minority faction. Misdeeds by rulers short of a direct attack on the lives, liberty or estates of the general public are not likely to provoke sedition. Indeed, even a minority justified in hostility to the government "will not easily engage ... in a contest, wherein they are sure to perish; it being as impossible for one or a few oppressed men to disturb the government, where the body of the people do not think themselves concerned in it, as for a raving madman, or a heady malcontent to overturn a well-settled state; the people being as little apt to follow the one as the other" (para. 208; italics omitted). The combination of Premises 3, 4, 5, 7, and 9 yields the following: Locke's message concerning the occasional reality of factious behavior by "heady malcontents" appears to be that, while such behavior can sometimes reach the point of causing "great disorder" (the unfortunate reality being that some human beings instead of following reason are "quarrelsome and contentious," para. 34), the efforts of these ambitious few are not likely to prove "fatal" to "states and kingdoms" unless the people at large have been seriously aggrieved by their gov- ernment. Thus, Locke's overall message on revolution is that the primary cause of rebellion is overreaching on the part of those in power. The temptations of power and its corrupting force in unleashing the greed of rulers are the problems that political theory can successfully address: The way to guard against depreda- tions by governing authorities is to alert them to their own self-interest, with a clear warning that severe mistreatment of the public will backfire by provoking successful revolution. 12 The difficulty of figuring out how to keep rulers from using their political power to enrich them- selves at the expense of their subjects is a problem as old as political philosophy itself. See Plato's Republic 417a 6-b 3. 317 This content downloaded from 132.174.254.72 on Mon, 21 Aug 2017 21:20:33 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
  • 9. Political Research Quarterly ARISTOTLE'S THEORY OF REVOLUTION Aristotle's Premises Although Aristotle makes the point in terms more measured than Locke's rallying cry, "[The people] cannot but feel what they lie under," a premise close to that of the inevitability of seditious overthrow of tyrannical regimes (Premise #1 above) does appear in Politics. Premise 1 in Aristotle's characteristically more cau- tious rendition comes out as: "It is difficult for a regime to last if its constitution is contrary to justice" (VII, 13: 1332b 28-29).13 He underlines this point by insisting that the least just regimes-self-interested oligarchies and tyrannies- are the shortest-lived. Those tyrannies that are believed to have lasted even as long as seventeen years were, strictly speaking, not tyrannies. The so-called tyrants in each of them (see examples at V, 12: 1315b 12-33) actually served more as constitutional monarchs or popular leaders, either putting themselves under the rule of law, or ruling in such a way as to please the populace in such ways as exemplary public service in warfare, acts of concern for the public good, and moderate rule. Thus, Aristotle is able to conclude, "Most [versions of] tyran- nies [i.e., those that really warrant the label] have all been completely short- lived" (V, 12: 1316b 38-39). Like Locke, Aristotle also warns potentially oppressive rulers that they will not be able to fool all of the people all of the time. While a genuinely well-man- aged regime (in terms of the range of the practicable) would please all segments of the community and thus would be altogether free of seditious faction (II, 9:1270b 21-22; II, 12: 1274a 15-21; III, 11: 1281b 28-34; IV, 9: 1294b 34-40; VI, 5: 1320a 15-16), to survive in the sense of avoiding a successful sedition, a regime must at least please the strongest elements of the community, its domi- nant forces (IV, 13: 1297b 5-10; IV, 12: 1296b 14-16; V, 9: 1309b 16-18; VI, 7: 1320b 26-28). Strength, for Aristotle, is measured as a blend of the strength of 13 My case would be easier if this passage actually read as it is rendered in the Jonathan Barnes revi- sion of Benjamin Jowett's translation of the Politics (Everson, ed. 1988: 176). There it is rendered: "No government can stand which is not founded upon justice." But Aristotle does describe the sur- vival chances of an unjust regime as "difficult" (chalepon) rather than literally impossible. In my view, incidentally, this passage, together with the sentence that follows it, indicates Aristotle's view that justice does prevail in the Bk. VII-VIII City According-to-Prayer, i.e., that city for which one would wish once one understood what is best simply (III, 18; IV, 1; VII, 4: 1325b 37). (But cf. the arguments of C. Zuckert [1983]; Nichols [1992: 144-45]; Yack [1993: 168-69]; and Annas [1996].) Therefore, there are no un-natural slaves in it. All have citizen rights except resident aliens plus natural slaves plus foreign serfs (presumably those lacking adequate thumos to object to being ruled, and who would be working voluntarily in the City of Prayer, for rule over free others who submit only involuntarily is tyrannical; see VII, 7: 1327b 25-30. These groups would do all the vulgar necessary work. In this reading, I agree with Miller (1995: 240-41) and disagree with the assertion of Cooper (1996: 867n.) that Aristotle "can hardly have seriously intended that . all the native-born free persons. .. should exercise rights of citizenship." 318 This content downloaded from 132.174.254.72 on Mon, 21 Aug 2017 21:20:33 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
  • 10. Aristotle's Theory of Revolution numbers and "quality" (Bk. IV, ch. 12). Numbers can be a source of political power, but so can the political skills gained through "education," or the respect accorded to some people because of their "good birth" into families revered for having contributed to the public weal. Aristotle also includes "wealth" in his cal- culus of political power. Owners of wealthy estates not only can afford the best military equipment, but could also hire mercenaries (V, 6: 1306a 21-23) or (per- haps more likely) acquire legions of followers by giving out jobs on their estates (VI, 5: 1320b 8-9). To be sure, Locke does not discuss at any length the relevance for revolution of differences of political power attainable within civil society, and indeed down- plays them by his frequent refrain, "The people shall be judge." However, a recognition of differences of political influence within civil society does not con- tradict anything in Locke's theory. Moreover, Aristotle himself, in a sense, warns of the future appropriateness of thinking in terms of the people as the ultimate judge, for he predicts (long before the universal prevalence of imperial or nation- based states), "Now that it has happened that cities have become even larger, it is perhaps [or alternatively, probably: isos] no longer easy for any regime to arise other than a democracy" (III, 15: 1286b 19-20). But even outside of democracy, government cannot afford to ignore the force of numbers; Even in an oligarchy, if it treats the multitude unjustly, Aristotle warns, any leader would be adequate to guide a successful revolt (V, 6: 1305a 38-41). Aristotle, in considering how rulers should please the dominant elements of the community, focuses more than Locke does on the question of who should share the prerogatives of political office, as distinguished from policy outcomes per se, although he does not entirely ignore the latter (e.g. VI, 5: 1320a 34-40). This emphasis seems to be because he sees his audience as primarily "legislators," or founders who are devising a political framework after some regime has been overthrown. (This concern is particularly apparent in Bk. IV, ch. 12, and in Bk. VI, ch.5.) Still, it does make sense to expect that participation in rule will yield some sharing of the benefits of rule, and the absence of participation, a consequent absence of benefits. Indeed, Aristotle makes this point explicitly: Constitutions that do not have an adequate amount of power-sharing in their initial structure, he writes, are bound to produce bad [policy] in the end (V, 1: 1302a 5-8). And Aristotle, like Locke, warns against governmental deception that aims at exclusion of the general populace. He specifically singles out for criticism con- stitutional devices that aim to give the illusion of a popular say in government but are rigged to assure predominance by the wealthy, insisting that "in time from things falsely good there must result a true evil" (IV, 12: 1297a12; the list of such devices follows in IV, 13; he repeats the point at V, 8:1308a 2-3). This statement that, sooner or later, the truth will out when it comes to government oppression, amounts to Aristotle's endorsement of Premise 2: In the long run, deception of the people cannot stave off revolution if government has become tyrannical. 319 This content downloaded from 132.174.254.72 on Mon, 21 Aug 2017 21:20:33 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
  • 11. Political Research Quarterly Aristotle also agrees with Locke that if only a few are treated unjustly, they will not be able to overthrow a government, as long as that government contin- ues to please the preponderant elements in the community (V, 1:1301a 39-b2; V, 4: 1304b 2-5). Thus, Premise 3: Generally speaking, if the unjustly treated are a tiny minority (without the backing of an aggrieved public) they will not revolt. Those regimes last where the governing body treats well the people outside the ruling group, for these regimes lack an aggrieved public (V, 8: 1308a 4-10). Aristotle gives far more attention than does Locke to the 4th Premise: Excep- tionally ambitious minorities can on occasion stir up sedition to the point of great dis- order. In Book V especially, Aristotle dwells at great length upon the various details of a grand variety of seditious overthrows or attempted overthrows of rulers from prior history. The basic source of these was a perception of unfair- ness. Sometimes, as in Locke's later theory, the felt grievance was on the part of the common people, when their property was attacked (IV, 13: 1297b 5-8; V, 8: 1308a 8-9, 1308b 32-1309a 9; VI, 4: 1318b 14-20), but not always. Aristotle's description and theory of revolution gives much greater prominence than does Locke to the seditions triggered by a sentiment of frustrated ambition or of offended dignity (including sexual dignity) on the part of would-be rulers- those Locke dubbed "heady malcontents." These ambitious leaders, typically of the wealthy classes, but sometimes from the military or naval ranks, can end up strong enough to overpower the elements supportive of the regime partly because the ruling groups treated segments of the population unjustly but also partly because the tiny city-states of the ancient world were far less capable of defending against coups than large nation-states came to be.14 It is conceivable that the reason Locke's theory of revolution could look so different from Aristo- tle's is that the largeness of kingdoms and even principalities in Locke's day ren- dered much less frequent a viable threat of turbulence from an ambitious few, as compared with the polis of fourth-century-BC Greece. Still, even in Aristotle's description, Premise 3 is meant to convey the more general picture: if ambitious leaders cannot tap into some degree of perceived injustice by powerful segments of the community, they will not have enough followers to succeed in their coup or revolution. (Incidentally, Aristotle shows more respect than Locke does for those zealots for justice-"very few in number" but not unknown to history- who, motivated primarily by a desire to do a noble thing, led lost causes against bad government [V, 10: 1312a 4-39].) 14 Aristotle understood that bigness would enhance stability. He argued that this enhancement could come about by expansion of the middle class, a group easier for rulers to keep satisfied than are either the very rich or the very poor (Bk. IV). He argued, however, that the City of Prayer could not be large in this way, for in a large city it is too difficult for the ruled and rulers (as they take turns ruling) to recognize each other's particular talents for government and particular needs as subjects being ruled (Bk. VII, ch.4). 320 This content downloaded from 132.174.254.72 on Mon, 21 Aug 2017 21:20:33 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
  • 12. Aristotle's Theory of Revolution Aristotle's version of Premise 5, that revolution finds its source more often in unjust provocation by rulers than in unprovoked sedition from the populace, or the ruled, is thus not so prominent as in Locke, again because the problem of coups from ambitious or outraged leaders was more pressing in Aristotle's day. Nonetheless, it is clearly implied in his general advice for avoiding revolution: any regime that wants stability needs to avoid the excesses that render it unjust. Oligarchies should become somewhat democratic in governing structure so that they will be less inclined to oppress the common people (VI, 6); democracies should adopt laws that make more secure the property of the wealthy (VI, 5); tyrannies need to become more kinglike, adopting the rule of law and a moderate way of life, refraining from attacking either the common people or the elite (V, 11 and 12). Aristotle's advice to tyrants is sometimes misread because he prefaces this advice-the advice that he gives in his own name (viz., become more kinglike and less tyrannical)-with an acknowledgment of the details of the "received wisdom" on how to preserve tyranny--viz., be tyrannical: operate the kind of regime asso- ciated with twentieth century totalitarianism, replete with spying on the subjects, the constant stimulation of warfare, and prohibitions on voluntary organizations or private meetings among the subjects. It is this "received wisdom" that Aristotle is attempting to replace. Aristotle argues plainly that to follow the received wisdom is to provoke revolution. "Indeed, what must be done is the opposite in nearly every case of the things mentioned previously." Tyrannies that took the tyrannical route were short-lived, while "tyrants" who behave in fact like benevolent kings, appearing not as appropriators of their subjects' property but as stewards of it will attain "longer-lasting" rule (V, 10: 1313a 1-V, 11: 1315b 10). These maxims about how to avoid the excesses that amount to tyranny are the fenceposts of Aristotle's "best fence against rebellion" argument (Premise 7). One also finds in Aristotle an explanation for this "best fence" argument that is similar to Locke's: (Premise 6) Power has a corrupting influence. In recommend- ing a mix of democratic and aristocratic elements that check each other, such that the common people would serve as electors of the most capable for political office and as auditor of the elected officials, Aristotle offers the following expla- nation: "[The officials] will rule justly by the fact that others have authority over the audits. For to be under constraint and unable to do everything one might resolve to do is beneficial. The license to do whatever one wishes cannot defend against the base element in every human being" (VI, 4: 1318b 38-1319a 1; see also IV, 14: 1298b 15-26; III, 16: 1287a 30-31). Premise 8, what rulers need to refrain from attacking is the "property" of their subjects, would seem to offer particular difficulty for the argument of this essay, because Aristotle specifically criticized a competing political theorist, Phaleas, for believing that solving the property problem would solve all political problems. Aristotle pointed out in that discussion that there is a kind of person who cares not just about bodily appetites, but who craves honor, societal respect, fame, a 321 This content downloaded from 132.174.254.72 on Mon, 21 Aug 2017 21:20:33 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
  • 13. Political Research Quarterly "place in history."'5 Such people pose a much more serious threat than petty crime, for they are the potential tyrants. What they need is not the right amount of property, but rather proper education, which will teach moderation and phi- losophy (Bk. II, ch. 7). Part of that education, however, is offered right here in Pol- itics. To the extent that the education in the need for moderation is in part the teaching on the proper limits of political power contained here, the Phaleas cri- tique is not necessarily at odds with Premise 8. And, indeed, Aristotle repeats more than once the importance of the advice that links successful regime survival with refraining from attacks on people's property. The many, he writes, "strive more for profits than for honor." They even will tolerate oligarchies and used to tolerate tyrannies, so long as rulers do not take their property or prevent them from working (VI, 4: 1318b1 6-19; see also V, 8: 1308a 8-10). A slight variation on this warning appears in Bk. IV, ch.13: The poor are willing to remain tranquil even when they have no share in political pre- rogatives, provided no one acts "hubristically" toward them nor deprives them of any of their property (IV, 13: 1297b 5-9; see also V, 11: 1315a 14-24)). The Greek "hubris," generally translated "arrogance" (although Simpson [1997] and Keyt [1999] offer the more apt, "insolence") involves, according to Aristotle's Rhetoric, the deliberate taking of pleasure in acts of humiliation toward others (Rh.1378b 23-29, as cited in Reeve 1998: 244). It may be that Machiavelli had this passage in mind when he later wrote in The Prince that what ordinary people want from their government is security for their property and protection against the violation of their wives and daughters (referring to the latter as a loss of their men's honor) (ch.17: 67 and ch.19: 72). Machiavelli's discussion is helpful, in any case, for highlighting the linkage between Aristotle's warning against hubris- tic behavior by the rulers and the security for life and limb that Locke clearly includes under his umbrella term "property," for, per Locke, one's first natural property is the property in one's own body (para. 27). While it is true that Aristotle does advise rulers specifically against unjustly depriving ambitious societal leaders of their prerogatives (V, 8: 1308a 8-9), he also makes clear that it is not just the common people who want their property left alone. He notes that the kinds of leaders who come to power in oligarchies, too, care at least as much about the profits of office as they do about honor (VI, 7: 1321a 41-44). And Aristotle identifies governmental attacks on the property of the well-off as a common provocation for elite-led seditions against democracies. The matter of property is serious enough that Aristotle writes, "A very great thing in every regime is to have the laws and management of the rest arranged in such a way that it is impossible to profit from the [political] offices" (V, 8: 1308b 15 I realize that I am truncating Aristotle's argument here, blurring together the craving for fame or honor (potentially including a desire for more than one's fair share of political offices) with the desire for pure, or unmixed pleasure. I do so to avoid a lengthy tangent. 322 This content downloaded from 132.174.254.72 on Mon, 21 Aug 2017 21:20:33 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
  • 14. Aristotle's Theory of Revolution 32-1309a 14). He adds that preventing government officials from taking the property of the people or treating them hubristically, however, is a difficult thing to accomplish, "for it does not always turn out that those sharing in the govern- ing body are the refined sort" (IV, 13: 1297b 8-10). However unrefined rulers may turn out to be, they should at least under- stand a frank appeal to their self-interest. For this reason, Aristotle has con- structed the "best fence against rebellion argument," warning them that their best safeguard against sedition lies in making their regime more just. And even if they cannot have total assurance of having headed off sedition from every possible ambitious leader, in light of the prevalence of concern for property among both the wealthy and the common people, rulers who secure the lives, limbs, and prop- erty of their subjects will have a substantial bulwark against sedition led by ambitious competitors (Aristotle's version of Premise 9). Limits of the Argument Differences of Thematic Focus. Whereas the modem fame of Locke's Second Treatise is as "a work principally designed to assert a right of resistance to unjust authority, a right, in the last resort, of revolution" (Simmons 1993:147, citing Dunn 1984: 28), no one would assert the same of Aristotle's Politics. Nonetheless the core premises of Locke's operational theory of revolution, that is, of his theory of when and why revolutions take place, are in fact present in Aristotle's earlier work. It is true that Locke's Treatise is ostentatiously an essay that justifies revo- lution. Such justification is not Aristotle's thematic focus. However, it is in fact observably present in Politics, if one looks for it. The argument here-to reiter- ate-is not a claim that Locke was in all important respects an Aristotelian. He emphatically was not. Rather, the argument here is that Aristotle provides an operational theory of revolution that contains most of the core premises of Locke's later theory, including its prescriptive element: viz. revolutions against tyrannical regimes are natural and virtually inevitable, and that the best fence against rebellion is to alert would-be tyrants of this operational theory so that they will mend their ways, and temper potential excesses of the regime. This fact demarcates an underappreciated aspect of Aristotle's Politics, an underapprecia- tion that this essay aspires to correct.16 16 It is perhaps a mark of this under-appreciation that scholars debate whether Aristotle was naively over-optimistic to hope that tyrannical governments would heed this warning--compare Mulgan 1977: 134-35 with Polansky 1991: 331-32--but a comparable argument (so far as I have been able to discover) does not appear in the Locke scholarship. Perhaps this view of Locke as more hard-headed is attributable to his having discernibly inspired actual revolutions, such as the Amer- ican. Thus, his warning to would-be tyrants took on "teeth" that were not so apparent in Aristo- tle's more muted approach. 323 This content downloaded from 132.174.254.72 on Mon, 21 Aug 2017 21:20:33 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
  • 15. Political Research Quarterly If this argument is correct, skeptics may wonder, why does Aristotle under- play the theory, mute it, as it were, by emphasizing different concerns? No defin- itive answer is available, but one can suggest the plausible hypothesis that Aris- totle chose to emphasize the usefulness of his political science for rulers already in power and for regimes already in place (e.g., in Politics, Book IV, ch. 1), because of his consciousness of the relatively recent fate of Socrates."7 Moreover, if this argument is correct-if Aristotle's true concern, like Locke's, is to prevent tyranny (in the general sense of oppressive government) by warning that the closer government gets to tyranny, the more likely revolution- ary overthrow becomes-then many of Aristotle's prescriptions take on new meaning. For instance, his counsels that specific laws, type of citizen education, and even the sense of justice appropriate in governing officials must be tailored to the needs of the regime so as to preserve it (V, 9: 1309a 36-39; 1309b 14-17; 1310a 14-19), have an import that is the opposite of how they are generally taken.'8 He is not saying that this means, for instance in an oligarchy, that the laws and education adopted should be those closest to the wishes or inclinations of the ruling oligarchs; on the contrary, they should be such as to temper or restrain those inclinations: "But to be educated relative to the regime is not to do the things that oligarchs or those who want democracy enjoy, but rather the things by which the former will be able to run an oligarchy and the latter to have a regime that is run democratically" (1310a 19-24). And what enables an oli- garchy to continue in existence as an oligarchy, for instance, turns out to be that it avoid the excesses characteristic of oligarchy, namely oppression of the common people. Its rulers need to learn how to become "less oligarchical" in order to stay in power. Some scholars take this fact as evidence that Aristotle stumbled into an unwitting inconsistency (Mulgan 1977: 136; Rowe 1991: 67- 69; Reeve 1998: lxiii-lxiv), in that his prescription for making a regime endure is to alter the regime for the better, which makes it a different regime.19 But one 17 Reportedly, Aristotle explained his departure from Athens, one year prior to his death from natu- ral causes with the remark that he did not want Athens to sin a second time against philosophy (Lord 1984: 6). Locke was free to endorse revolution against tyranny more openly because he wrote under the cloak of anonymity (and perhaps, too, he chose this mode because he was intent on fomenting a particular, immediate revolution [Ashcraft 19861). When Mulgan (1977: 136) argues that Aristotle "should have admitted more openly that he considers the[] position [of tyran- nical oligarchs, democrats or monarchs] untenable and that they must change the nature of their rule or be overthrown," he writes as though the problem of Socrates was no problem. But the fact is, Aristotle did openly admit these things; he simply did not stress them. He wrote them, as it were, quietly, rather than shouting them from the rooftops, or the barricades. 18 Reeve (1998) seems at some points to agree with my reading (lxiv [describing a "stable but non- rigid" regime] and lxvii) but at others to take these statements at their face value (liii, lxii, later on lxvii). 19 Keyt, in an innovative reading, suggests that the real import of these passages is to render the rulers of all regimes at least law-abiding; that Aristotle aims here to check each regime's potential 324 This content downloaded from 132.174.254.72 on Mon, 21 Aug 2017 21:20:33 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
  • 16. Aristotle's Theory of Revolution could suggest that this is not an inconsistency. Aristotle is simply advising vari- ous sovereign bodies that political power has limits; any sovereign who ignores Aristotle's advice and uses political office to gratify every whim risks losing the regime to seditious overthrow by aggrieved subjects. Differences of Fundamental Premise: Irrespective of the evidence on the authors' theories of revolution, one might also object that the differences between the respective overall political philosophies of Locke and Aristotle are so over- whelming that any similarity on revolution is insignificant and misleading. Important points of contrast include, first, that for Aristotle it is of central signif- icance that the political scientist identify the best regime, the City According-to- Prayer, in order to have a standard by which to assess better and worse (Bk. III, ch. 18; Bk. IV, ch. 1; Bks. VII-VIII). For Locke, by contrast, the type of regime that will be legitimate in any particular society is a matter of original majority prefer- ence-rule by one, by a select few, and by direct majority can equally be legiti- mate as long as the government does not turn tyrannical. As long as it does not, at least tacit consent can be assumed, and consent of the governed is what makes for legitimate government. Locke's theory aims only to guard against the worst excesses (Tarcov 1981: 214-17), while Aristotle orients his theory according to the polestar of the best imaginable. A second fundamental difference that might arguably render comparison inappropriate is that for Locke (following Hobbes) the aims of the political society concern the things of the body-security for life itself and freedom to pursue a comfortable life. Aristotle, to the contrary, argues that real-life polit- ical societies err in limiting their concerns to such things, when what politi- cal societies should do is foster excellence of character or soul (psyche) among the citizenry.20 However, despite these two massive differences of orientation, Aristotle acknowledges that real-life societies typically-indeed universally in practice- are not interested in hearing the good character message. People in government, including the common people in direct democracies, are more interested in deterioration into the extreme of lawlessness (1999: 136-142). While more attractive than those readings that simply condemn Aristotle for inconsistency, Keyt's seems to pay insufficient heed to the fact that Aristotle is giving advice that goes beyond law-abidingness to guide regime-design itself. Moreover, Aristotle's approving description of so-called tyrants who in fact moderated their tyrannies by putting themselves under law or by ruling in the public interest, thus rendering themselves "monarchs" rather than tyrants, properly speaking, belies the notion that Aristotle opposed all regime improvement (V, 12: 1315b 12-33). 20 Aristotle notes that even Sparta and similarly warlike political communities err in fostering only a part of virtue, military courage, rather than the whole of it, and also because they value the goods that are attainable through conquest more highly than the virtue involved in acquiring the goods (Bk. II, ch.9: 1271a 42-1271b 11; see also VII, ch.2: 1324b 3-38; VII, 14: 1333a 37-1334a10; VIII, 4: 1338b 9-38). 325 This content downloaded from 132.174.254.72 on Mon, 21 Aug 2017 21:20:33 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
  • 17. Political Research Quarterly maintaining their own power than in any betterment of their souls (VI, 4: 1318b 2-5). And what people generally seek is property; the common many prefer profits to honor (VI, 4: 1318b 17-18), and the wealthy few also "seek profits no less than honor" (VI, 7: 1321a 41-43). Indeed there is no existing political soci- ety where one can find even as many as one hundred men who have genuine excellence of character (V, 1: 1302a 1-1302a 3).21 Thus, while the City of Prayer for Aristotle provides a model for deciding what is better and worse legisla- tion,22 his argument in Books IV-VI is that the political theorist must be able to offer usable advice to real governments, and therefore must be able to address the actual concerns of those governments. Here, therefore, Aristotle traverses ground similar to Locke's. Finally, the two theorists differ notoriously over the naturalness of human equality. Locke maintains that no one has a natural right to rule another23 (since all humans are one species) so legitimate ruling authority can come only from consent. Aristotle argues that according to the nature of justice, some have a more just claim to rule because they are people of moral excellence and practi- cal wisdom, and for these reasons will do a better job. "The greatest factional split is probably that between virtue and depravity" (V, 3: 1303b 14-15), but this fact turns out to have little practical relevance because, although the people of excellent character most deserve to rule, they are such a tiny minority that, practically speaking, they would not dream of trying to come to power force- fully (V, 1: 1301a 39-b2; V, 4: 1304b 4-6). Like Locke's outnumbered oppressed minority, they simply have to endure the situation. Moreover, they would not be able to persuade ordinary people to hand over power to them; such a thing would be even more difficult than figuring out the perfect formula of distribu- tive justice for a particular community. People in power will not heed claims (however well-founded they might be) that justice requires them to turn over their power to other people (VI, 3: 1318b 2-5). Thus, Aristotle, instead of appealing directly to arguments based on justice, winds up, like Locke, warning 21 Aristotle says literally there are not 100 who are "good and well-born" and that "good birth and excellence are in few." It is possible that his point in conjoining good birth with goodness is to state that the conjunction of actual goodness with the societal influence that would come from good birth is what is rare. I think it more likely, however, that his reference to good birth is as an aspect of complete goodness, as in the expression "well brought-up." A youngster may start out good but without good parents his or her chance of ending up good are far slimmer. 22 Not everyone agrees that Aristotle's City of Prayer, the city that is best simply, provides a standard of justice that enables one to judge what is better and worse among actual regimes, cf. C. Zuckert (1983); Nichols (1992: 144-45); Yack (1993: 168-69); Annas (1996). But see Miller (1995: 239- 45), Rowe (1991), and Bradley (1991) for examples of readings that accord with mine. 23 No one, that is, except someone who has been attacked without provocation. An attacker without material motive has abandoned the human species and demoted himself to the ranks of vicious beasts and thus may be executed or subjected to the lesser penalty of slavery 326 This content downloaded from 132.174.254.72 on Mon, 21 Aug 2017 21:20:33 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
  • 18. Aristotle's Theory of Revolution ruling groups that if they wish to avoid being overthrown they must refrain from tyrannical excesses.24 As for the matter of using consent of the governed to distinguish legitimate from illegitimate government, Aristotle himself uses the voluntariness of submis- sion to rule as a definitional marker that distinguishes tyrannical from healthy rule (III, 14:1285a 27, b 3, b 5, b 8, b 21; IV, 10: 1295a 19-23; V, 10:1313a 3- 11). The three healthy-i.e., non-tyrannical-regimes had been defined as ones that serve the public interest rather than simply the ruler's interest; in noting three times that tyrannies are regimes where the public is being ruled involun- tarily, Aristotle is indicating that the people do voluntarily submit when the public interest is being served. Thus, voluntary submission to the rule of another would appear to be the Aristotelian version of what Locke calls tacit consent to government. CONCLUSIONS Aristotle's critique of Phaleas indicates that Aristotle understood that the political problem of coping with people who want more than their fair share of things is a problem too deep and too broad to solve by economic techniques alone. Its ultimate solution would have to include the Socratic remedies endorsed, for instance, in Plato's Republic, namely, teaching moderation and turn- ing potential tyrants toward the pleasures offered by philosophy. Thus, Aristotl strived to elevate political-life-as-he-found-it, by teaching that the polis properly aims at the fostering of human excellence. (Indeed, Aristotle treats political life per se as worthy of considerably more dignity than Socrates does. One does no find in Aristotle the Socratic tendency to warn that the truly just person is bes advised to stay away from politics [Apology 31d-32a; Republic 496c-e]). Nonetheless, Aristotle also went beyond these remedies suggested by Plato. Aristotle frankly acknowledged that no communities in fact provided education in moderation. Consequently, he may have reasonably inferred tha few were likely to do so in the future. Moreover, one may entertain legitimat doubts about the likelihood that the lure of Socratic philosophy would pull a large fraction of the world's potentially tyrannical rulers away from the temp- tations of power. It is conceivable that Aristotle entertained these very doubts He certainly stated clearly that once people have power, it is virtually impossi- ble to succeed with purely justice-based arguments to persuade them to accept checks on their own power (VI, 3: 1318b 2-5). And finally, Aristotle frankly 24 While Aristotle initially defines tyranny as the selfish rule of a monarch (III: 7), he later extend the usage to cover self-aggrandizing rule by any group (included a popular majority) at the expense of the rest of the public: extremist oligarchies and extremist democracies alike are prop- erly regarded as tyrannies: "for these happen to be tyrannies [with the power] divided up" (V, 10 1312b 37-38). 327 This content downloaded from 132.174.254.72 on Mon, 21 Aug 2017 21:20:33 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
  • 19. Political Research Quarterly acknowledged that what the vast majority of people want from government is protection for their property Thus, in Books IV-VI of Politics, Aristotle supplemented the Socratic options for stemming abuses of political power by appealing to the low but solid ground of the rulers' self-interest in staying in power. The core premises of the Aris- totelian teaching on sedition-essentially a "crime doesn't pay" story for rulers- were then available for Locke's much later elaboration. These in sum maintained that governments must avoid oppressing their subjects if they were to avoid being overthrown, that revolution against oppressive rulers is both inevitable and natural,25 that security for property would have a central place in the avoidance of oppression, and that the succumbing to the temptations of power on the part of ruling groups is the fundamental provocation of revolution. Locke (in direct contrast with Hobbes) agreed with Aristotle in distrusting the corrupting influence of political power and thus re-worked Aristotle's basic premises to provide an alternative to Hobbes's absolutist political conclusions. Aristotle, for example, said of his recommended checking of the excesses that amount to tyranny not only that it will render a monarch's rule "more noble and more enviable" (because he will be ruling better people) and will render the ruler himself, if not of "fine" character, at least "half-decent," but also that these improvements will render his rule "longer-lasting" (V, 11: 1315b 4-10). Locke's re-worked teaching on revolution holds onto the "longer-lasting" side of the argument, and in effect drops the rest. What this look at his "Lockean" side can teach us readers about Aristotle's own political philosophy is the degree to which it paid heed to what might be called the hard-headed realities. Most people want from their political commu- nities protection for their physical security and for their property; persons of genuinely excellent character are so exceedingly rare that they will hardly ever be in power; the possessing of power has a way of corrupting those who rule. While Aristotle did see the need to attend to these realities, he, in contrast to Locke, refused to decomplicate his political theory, to focus almost exclusively on the readily predictable. In Aristotle's theory (unlike Locke's) the human yearning for nobility of character, the human desire to be a good and respect- worthy person and to be surrounded by such people, and the craving for a 25 Keyt's explication astutely likens revolution to death of a regime and remarks that "death is some- times a justly imposed penalty" (Keyt 1999: xiv-xv). Revolution, one could add, is the natural fate of a regime in the extremely diseased condition of tyrannical excess. Both Locke and Aristotle make a point of describing the naturalness of this outcome (natural in the sense that it is a ten- dency intrinsic to the nature of tyranny) as a way of preventing the conditions of extreme disease in the body politic. Locke is more outspoken than Aristotle in emphasizing that tyrants deserve what they get (Since tyranny violates natural rights, it is by nature right to overthrow it). Still, Keyt notes that in at least one passage Aristotle implies that resistance to tyranny is something worthy of honor (V, 10: 1312a 21-39; Keyt 1999: xv). 328 This content downloaded from 132.174.254.72 on Mon, 21 Aug 2017 21:20:33 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
  • 20. Aristotles Theory of Revolution social order characterized by justice, do not disappear. The tension between these genuinely human but too-frail traits and the traits that characterize the pursuit of comfortable self-preservation remains present in his political philos- ophy, as do a variety of other tensions. These would include that between the need for wisdom and the need for consent; the tensions among the needs for freedom, for solidarity, and for ultimate meaning; and the tension between the necessary conditions of political life-physical security and societal commu- nity-and the highest goals of political life-the wisdom and human excellence that are required for happiness (Salkever 1990: 84-89). Nonetheless, despite these important differences, Aristotle's was a politics attentive as well to the more base political tendencies on which Locke was later to focus so emphatically. If governing authorities are to behave in even half- decent ways, the political philosopher needs to develop an argument that is not itself base but that can cope with the kind of base self-interest that is all too prevalent in human affairs. Accomplishing this is a worthy enough task that Aris- totle devoted the good part of three books of Politics to it. REFERENCES Annas, Julia. 1996. "Aristotle on Human Nature and Political Virtue," R Metaphysics 49 (June): 731-54. Ashcraft, Richard. 1986. Revolutionary Politics and Locke's Two Treatises of ment. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Barker, Ernest. 1962. The Politics of Aristotle (Translation with Introdu Appendices). New York: Oxford University Press. Black, Antony. 1988. "The Conciliar Movement." In J. H. Burns, ed., Ca History of Medieval Political Thought c. 350-c. 1450, pp. 573-87. Cam MA: Cambridge University Press. Bradley, A. C. 1991. "Aristotle's Conception of the State," in David Keyt D. Miller, Jr., eds., A Companion to Aristotle's Politics, pp.13-56. Oxfor Blackwell. Burns, J. H., ed. 1988. Cambridge History of Medieval Political Though c. 1450. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press. Cooper, John. 1996. "Justice and Rights in Aristotle's Politics." Review physics 49 (June): 859-72. Cox, Richard. 1960. Locke on War and Peace. Oxford: Clarendon Press. 1982, "Introduction." In Richard Cox, ed., Second Treatise of Govern pp. vii-xlii. Arlington Heights, VA: Harlan Davidson. Dunbabin, Jean. 1988. "Government." In Burns, op. cit., pp. 477-519. Dunn, John. 1984. Locke. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Everson, Stephen, ed. 1988. The Politics (of Aristotle). Cambridge, MA bridge University Press. Gadamer, H. G. 1975. Truth and Method. New York: Seabury. 329 This content downloaded from 132.174.254.72 on Mon, 21 Aug 2017 21:20:33 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
  • 21. Political Research Quarterly Goldwin, Robert. 1987. "John Locke." In Leo Strauss and Joseph Cropsey, eds., History of Political Philosophy, 3rd ed., pp. 476-511. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Grant, Ruth. 1987. John Locke's Liberalism. Chicago; University of Chicago Press. Keyt, David. 1999. Aristotle Politics Books V and VI (Translation with Commen- tary). Oxford: Clarendon Press. Locke, John. 1823. "First Letter on Toleration," in The Works ofJohn Locke, Vol.VI. London: Tagg et al. Locke, John. 1982. Second Treatise of Government, ed. Richard Cox. Arlington Heights, VA: Harlan Davidson. Lord, Carnes, trans. 1984. The Politics (of Aristotle). Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Machiavelli, Niccolo. 1985. The Prince. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Macpherson, C. B. 1962. The Political Theory of Possessive Individualism: Hobbes to Locke. New York; Oxford University Press. Meyers, Henry A., with Herwig Wolfram. 1982. Medieval Kingship. Chicago: Nelson-Hall. Miller, Fred D. 1995. Nature, Justice and Rights in Aristotle's Politics. Oxford: Clarendon Press. . 1996. "Aristotle and the Origins of Natural Rights," Review of Meta- physics 49 (June): 873-907. Mulgan, R. G. 1977. Aristotle's Political Theory. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Nelson, Janet. 1988. "Kingship and Empire." In Burns, op cit., pp. 211-51. Nichols, Mary P 1992. Citizens and Statesmen: A Study of Aristotle's Politics. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield. Polansky, Ronald. 1991. "Aristotle on Political Change." In David Keyt and Fred D. Miller, Jr., eds., A Companion to Aristotle's Politics, pp.323-45. Oxford: Basil Blackwell. Procope, John. 1988. "Greek and Roman Political Theory." In Burns, op. cit., pp. 21-36. Reeve, C. D. C., trans. 1998. Politics (of Aristotle). Indianapolis, IN: Hackett. Rowe, Christopher. 1991. "Aims and Methods in Aristotle's Politics." In David Keyt and Fred D. Miller, Jr., eds., A Companion to Aristotle's Politics, pp. 57- 74. Oxford: Basil Blackwell. Salkever, Stephen. 1990. Finding the Mean: Theory and Practice in Aristotelian Phi- losophy. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Simmons, A. John. 1993. On the Edge of Anarchy: Locke, Consent, and the Limits of Society. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Simpson, Peter L. Phillips, trans. 1997. The Politics of Aristotle. Chapel Hill: Uni- versity of North Carolina Press. Strauss, Leo. 1953. Natural Right and History. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. 330 This content downloaded from 132.174.254.72 on Mon, 21 Aug 2017 21:20:33 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
  • 22. Aristotle's Theory of Revolution Tarcov, Nathan. 1981. "Locke's Second Treatise and the 'Best Fence against Rebel- lion.'" Review of Politics 43 (April): 198-217. Vincent, Andrew. 1987. Theories of the State. Oxford: Basil Blackwell. Yack, Bernard. 1993. The Problems of a Political Animal Community, Justice and Conflict in Aristotelian Political Thought. Berkeley: University of California Press. Zuckert, Catherine H. 1983. "Aristotle on the Limits and Satisfactions of Politi- cal Life." Interpretation 11: 185-206. Zuckert, Michael. 1994. Natural Rights and the New Republicanism. Princeton Uni- versity Press. Received: March 7, 2000 Accepted for Publication: October 9, 2000 lesl@udel.edu 331 This content downloaded from 132.174.254.72 on Mon, 21 Aug 2017 21:20:33 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms