SlideShare a Scribd company logo
Educational Philosophy and Theory,Vol. 37, No. 4, 2005
© 2005 Philosophy of Education Society of Australasia
Published by Blackwell Publishing, 9600 Garsington Road, Oxford, OX4 2DQ, UK and
350 Main Street, Malden, MA 02148, USA
Blackwell Publishing, Ltd.
Oxford, UK
EPAT
Educational Philosophy and Theory
0013-1857
© 2005 Philosophy of Education Society of Australasia
September 2005
37
4
Original Article
A Field Guide to Heidegger
David I. Waddington
A Field Guide to Heidegger:
Understanding ‘The Question
Concerning Technology’
D I. W
Stanford University
Abstract
This essay serves as a guide for scholars, especially those in education, who want to gain
a better understanding of Heidegger’s essay,‘The Question ConcerningTechnology’.The paper
has three sections: an interpretive summary, a critical commentary, and some remarks on
Heidegger scholarship in education. Since Heidegger’s writing style is rather opaque, the
interpretive summary serves as a map with which to navigate the essay.The critical commentary
offers a careful analysis of some of the central concepts in the essay. These concepts, which
include bringing-forth, challenging-forth, and gestell, are intriguing but problematic.
The problems and possibilities of these ideas are analyzed, and an overall assessment of
Heidegger’s ideas on technology is offered. In the final section, the work of several scholars
in education is examined. Some of this work is excellent, but there is also a significant
amount of confused and confusing scholarship.
Keywords: Heidegger, technology, environment, craft, education
It is a clear statement of the power of Heidegger’s thought that even among
a group of people from a very different tradition [computer science] it has
evoked stirrings—inklings of a new way of going about the business of
technology.
—Terry Winograd (Professor of Computer Science, Stanford University),
Heidegger and the Design of Computer Systems, p. 108
Introduction
Reading Heidegger is a lot like trying to navigate a ship through a dense fog. His
language is sprinkled with German neologisms, and his lines of thought tend not
to be laid out in a straightforward manner. However, despite these difficulties,
philosophers of education have recently exhibited a heightened level of interest in
Heidegger’s thought. They seem especially interested in a short piece by Heidegger
entitled ‘The Question Concerning Technology’; in Michael Peters’ (2002) new
568 David I.Waddington
© 2005 Philosophy of Education Society of Australasia
collection, Heidegger, Education, and Modernity, eight of the eleven included essays
refer to ‘The Question Concerning Technology’. Academics working in technology
education have also expressed an interest in this particular essay.
Heidegger pioneered a new way of thinking about technology; ‘The Question
Concerning Technology’ contains exciting ideas that may have important implica-
tions in both technology education and environmental education. However, just as
one must set the table before sitting down to a meal, so too must one understand
Heidegger before trying to draw educational implications from his thought. Thus,
the primary role of this essay is to act as a field guide—to summarize, criticize and
interpret ‘The Question Concerning Technology’.
Some may think that is unnecessary to perform such a low-level task. Yet, there
are several reasons why a field guide is important:
1. Providing access. Many academics and educators would be interested in Heidegger’s
ideas, but lack the patience and time to decode Heidegger’s Byzantine formulations.
The first and second sections of my paper (the interpretive summary and the critical
commentary) will address this need for access.
2. Facilitating critical understanding. Although Heidegger’s ideas on technology have
received plenty of accolades, they have (as yet) received very little criticism within
the education literature. It is important to appreciate both the strengths and the
weaknesses of Heidegger’s thought, and the second section of my paper (the critical
commentary) will assist in this.
3. Clearing up confusion. Although some philosophers of education have written excellent
articles about Heidegger’s philosophy of technology, other authors have made signi-
ficant errors in their interpretations of Heidegger. The final section of the paper will
be dedicated to the task of pointing out these errors.
Part 1 An Interpretive Summary of ‘The Question Concerning Technology’
Most essays on technology focus primarily on practical issues surrounding the use
of particular technologies. Heidegger’s essay, however, does not—instead, it focuses
on the ways of thinking that lie behind technology. Heidegger (1977, p. 3) thinks that
by coming to understand these ways of thinking, humans can enter into a ‘free
relationship’ with technology.
After dismissing the conventional account of technology, which supposedly states
that technology is simply a means to an end, Heidegger commences a discussion on
ancient craftsmanship. He suggests that the ancient craftsmanship involves the four
Aristotelian causes: material, formal, final, and efficient. Intuitively, one might think
that the efficient cause of a given craft-item (the craftsman) was the most significant
of the four. However, although the craftsman has an important role in that she unites
the four causes by considering each of them carefully, each of the four causes is equally
co-responsible for the particular craft-item that is produced. Heidegger comments,
‘The four ways of being responsible bring something into appearance. They let it
come forth into presencing’ (1977, p. 9). Appropriately enough, Heidegger names
this process bringing-forth. Notably, bringing-forth is not merely a descriptive genus
A Field Guide to Heidegger 569
© 2005 Philosophy of Education Society of Australasia
under which the four causes are subsumed—rather, it is a unified process, ‘a single
leading-forth to which [each of the causes] is indebted’ (Lovitt, 1972, p. 46).
Heidegger writes that bringing-forth ‘comes to pass only insofar as something
concealed comes into unconcealment’ (1977, p. 11). Thus, instead of the craft-item
being created by the craftsman, as one would think, it was revealed or unconcealed.
In ‘The Thing’, Heidegger comments on the making of a jug,
The jug is not a vessel because it was made; rather, the jug had to be
made because it is this holding vessel. The making … lets the jug come
into its own. But that which in the jug’s nature is its own is never brought
about by its making. (1971, p. 168)
Clearly, revealing/unconcealing in the mode of bringing-forth contains strong hints
of Platonism.
Bringing-forth is the mode of revealing that corresponds to ancient craft. Modern
technology, however, has its own particular mode of revealing, which Heidegger
calls challenging-forth. Thinking in the mode of challenging-forth is very different
from thinking in the mode of bringing-forth: when challenging-forth, one sets upon
the elements of a situation both in the sense of ordering (i.e. setting a system upon)
and in a more rapacious sense (i.e. the wolves set upon the traveler and devoured
him). In bringing-forth, human beings were one important element among others
in the productive process; in challenging-forth, humans control the productive process.
Efficiency is an additional important element of thinking in the mode of challeng-
ing forth; the earth, for example, is set upon to yield the maximum amount of ore
with the minimum amount of effort. Essentially, challenging-forth changes the way
we see the world—as Michael Zimmerman pointedly remarks, ‘To be capable of
transforming a forest into packaging for cheeseburgers, man must see the forest not
as a display of the miracle of life, but as raw material, pure and simple’ (1977, p. 79).
Production in the mode of challenging-forth reveals objects that have the status
of standing-reserve. Objects that have been made standing-reserve have been
reduced to disposability in two different senses of the word: (1) They are disposable
in the technical sense; they are easily ordered and arranged. Trees that once stood
chaotically in the forest are now logs that can be easily counted, weighed, piled, and
shipped. (2) They are also disposable in the conventional sense; like diapers and
cheap razors, they are endlessly replaceable/interchangeable and have little value.
For the most part, challenging things forth into standing-reserve is not a laudable
activity, and thus it makes sense to wonder what drives human beings to think in
this way. Heidegger’s answer to this motivational question is unconventional—
instead of suggesting that the origins of this motivation are indigenous to human
beings, he postulates the existence of a phenomenon that ‘sets upon man to order
the real as standing-reserve’ (1977, p. 19). Heidegger calls this mysterious
phenomenon enframing (Ge-stell in German). The word ‘Ge-stell’ gathers together
several meanings of the -stellen family of German verbs: in Ge-stell, humans are
ordered (bestellen), commanded (bestellen), and entrapped (nachstellen) (Harries 1994,
p. 229). Heidegger thinks that our default state is that of being trapped by Ge-stell;
this is what he means when he writes, ‘As the one who is challenged forth in this
570 David I.Waddington
© 2005 Philosophy of Education Society of Australasia
way, man stands within the essential realm of [Ge-stell]. He can never take up a
relationship to it only subsequently’ (1977, p. 24; Sallis, 1971, p. 162).
According to Heidegger (1977, p. 25), there are different ‘ordainings of destining’
for human beings. Although the default destining is that of Ge-stell, it is possible
to choose an alternate road. Heidegger thinks that human beings have been granted
the special role of ‘Shepherds of Being’—we have been granted the power to reveal
the world in certain ways (Ballard, 1971, p. 60). Trapped in Ge-stell, we tend to
reveal things in the mode of challenging-forth, but we can also choose to reveal
things in the mode of bringing-forth. Heidegger comments, ‘Placed between these
possibilities, man is endangered from out of destining’ (1977, p. 26). However, by
carefully considering the ways of thinking that lie behind technology, we can grasp
the ‘saving power’. We can realize that we, the Shepherds of Being, have a choice:
we can bring-forth rather than challenge-forth. Thus, once we understand the
thinking behind technology, we become free to choose our fate—‘… we are already
sojourning in the open space of destining’ (Heidegger, 1977, p. 26).
Part 2 Critical Commentary on ‘The Question Concerning Technology’
2.0 Introduction
The following critical commentary will be organized in four sections; the first three
sections will analyze, in turn, the puzzles and weaknesses surrounding three pivotal
ideas in Heidegger’s essay: bringing-forth, challenging-forth-to-standing-reserve,
and Ge-stell. The final section of the analysis will synthesize the results of the first
three analyses to create an overall evaluation of Heidegger’s account.
2.1 Bringing-forth
If one were to draw conclusions about Plato and Aristotle solely from Heidegger’s
remarks in ‘The Question Concerning Technology’, one would think that crafts-
manship was a central issue for both of these ancient thinkers. Furthermore, from
the warm light in which Heidegger bathes the craftsman, one might also come to
believe that Plato and Aristotle have a certain reverence for craftsmen and the
process of craftsmanship. Plato and Aristotle’s attitudes toward craftsmanship,
however, can (at best) be described as ambivalent. In the Politics, Aristotle remarks,
‘… no man can practice excellence who is living the life of a mechanic or laborer’
(1995, 1278a20). Craftsmen and craftsmanship receive a more favorable treatment
in Plato, but Plato still makes the following unfriendly remark:
If an offspring of [the guardians] should be found to have a mixture of
iron or bronze, they must not pity him in any way, but give him the rank
appropriate to his nature and drive him out to join the craftsmen and
farmers. (1997, 415bc)
Indeed, lyrical prose having to do with craftsmanship is scarce in Plato and
Aristotle, but abundant in Heidegger.
A Field Guide to Heidegger 571
© 2005 Philosophy of Education Society of Australasia
Heidegger also claims that his account of the four causes is true to the spirit of
Greek thought. Heidegger’s notion of the co-responsibility of the four causes has
some support in Aristotle, who comments: ‘… the [causes other than the efficient
cause] are causes in the sense of the end or the good of the rest …’ (1995, 195a23)
Heidegger’s insistence on the non-primacy of the efficient cause, however, finds
less support: in Topics, Aristotle remarks, ‘Again, the primary source of the change
or rest [is] … generally what makes of what is made …’ (1995, 194b30) Aristotle’s
remarks on causation do not entirely rule out Heidegger’s somewhat romantic
interpretation, but neither do they provide much supporting evidence.
Heidegger’s strongest evidence in favor of bringing-forth consists of a quote from
Symposium [what follows is Heidegger’s translation]: ‘Every occasion for whatever
passes over and goes forward into presencing from that which is not presencing is
poiesis, is bringing-forth’ (1977, p. 10). Nehamas and Woodruff, in their translation
of the Symposium, offer a different rendition of the same passage:
After all, everything that is responsible for creating something out of
nothing is a kind of poetry, and so all the creations of every craft and
profession are themselves a kind of poetry, and everyone who practices a
craft is a poet. (1997, 205b)
Although this translation is significantly different from Heidegger’s, its content
(craftsmen as poets creating something out of nothing) and tone (romantic) offers
some historical support for the notion of bringing-forth. Yet, this is not enough to
authenticate the supposed historical status of bringing-forth. Although there is some
evidence linking bringing-forth to Greek thinking, a far more likely conclusion
is that the idea of bringing-forth had its primary origin in the mind of Martin
Heidegger.
A more serious problem with the notion of bringing-forth concerns the idea of
revealing/unconcealment. Recall Heidegger’s comment in ‘The Thing’:
The jug is not a vessel because it was made; rather, the jug had to be
made because it is this holding vessel. The making … lets the jug come
into its own. But that which in the jug’s nature is its own is never brought
about by its making. (1971, p. 168)
Clearly, there is some sort of Platonic pre-existence at work here—the jug, appar-
ently, pre-exists as concealed and is revealed through the co-responsible action of
the four causes. Perhaps one can see what Heidegger means here by recalling the
ubiquitous stories of wood carvers who somehow know, in advance, what shape a
particular piece of wood ‘wants to be’. However, no amount of idiosyncratic
accounts on the part of folk artists can reduce the implausibility of the idea of pre-
existence. The jug is a created object, and while it can be created through the loving
and careful process of bringing-forth, the jug’s created status cannot be eclipsed.
To sum up, the notion of bringing-forth is probably largely Heidegger’s arbitrary
creation, and the idea of revealing pre-existent objects is highly implausible. Does
this mean that these ideas should be thrown out? This essential question, which has
important implications for Heidegger’s philosophy, will be addressed in a later section.
572 David I.Waddington
© 2005 Philosophy of Education Society of Australasia
2.2 Challenging-forth and Standing-reserve
Heidegger comments, ‘It is said that modern technology is something incomparably
different from all earlier technologies …’ (1977, p. 14) Heidegger attributes this
‘incomparable difference’ to the ability of human beings to think in the mode of
challenging forth—an ability which, he maintains, only emerged recently. Apparently,
older technologies cannot involve or facilitate this sort of thinking:
The revealing that rules in modern technology is a challenging, which
puts to nature the unreasonable demand that it supply energy that can
be extracted and stored as such. But does this not hold true for the old
windmill as well? No. Its sails do indeed turn in the wind; they are left
entirely to the wind’s blowing. But the windmill does not unlock energy
from the air currents in order to store it. (Heidegger 1977, p. 14)
However, if I were an ambitious and avaricious miller living in the middle ages, I
might want to maximize flour production in my mill. To this end, I would make
sure that my windmill had enormous sails in order to maximize wind-catching effi-
ciency. By processing the grain, I would unlock its food energy in the form of flour
and hold it in reserve in my granary. I could then maximize profit by selling the flour
during the wintertime when the peasants were starving. The intuitive plausibility of
the hypothetical miller suggests that Heidegger is wrong to think that challenging-
forth is a phenomenon unique to modern times.
However, despite the fact that thinking in the mode of challenging-forth is not
limited solely to the reign of modern technology, there is certainly a link between
modern technology and challenging-forth. The forester of old with his horses and
chains could not even conceive of machines like the Caterpillar tree ‘harvester’, which
can liquidate a forest at ‘the highest level of productivity and efficiency’ using
‘extremely high levels of horsepower’ (Caterpillar 2003). Since modern technology
enables challenging-forth to achieve extraordinary results, thinking in the mode of
challenging-forth is more dangerous and alluring now than at any other time in history.
Tree ‘harvesters’ are a particularly unpleasant example of modern technology.
Yet, critics of Heidegger are quick to point out that modern technology has
improved our standard of living. Hydroelectric dams, for example, have allowed
power to be brought to the homes of many people around the world, thus improving
their lives immensely. Although there are some environmental problems associated
with hydroelectric dams, it is a relatively clean form of energy generation. Heidegger,
however, is outraged by the building of a hydroelectric dam on the Rhine:
In the context of the interlocking processes pertaining to the orderly
disposition of electrical energy, even the Rhine itself appears as something
at our command. The hydroelectric plant is not built into the Rhine
River, as was the old wooden bridge that joined bank with bank for
hundreds of years. Rather the river is dammed up into the power plant.
What the river is now, namely, a water power supplier, derives from out
of the essence of the power station. In order that we may even remotely
A Field Guide to Heidegger 573
© 2005 Philosophy of Education Society of Australasia
consider the monstrousness that reigns here, let us ponder for a moment
the contrast that speaks out of the two titles, ‘The Rhine’ as dammed up
into the power works, and ‘The Rhine’ as uttered out of the art work, in
Hölderlin’s hymn by that name. (1977, p. 16)
Even the most rabid capitalists may become uneasy when forced to watch a tree
‘harvester’ in the process of liquidating a forest; intuitively, one can see that there
is a certain monstrousness about this kind of wholesale destruction.Yet, although the
same kind of destruction is not taking place in the context of the dam on the Rhine,
Heidegger still asks us to ‘consider the monstrousness that reigns here’. (1977,
p. 16) In order to solve this puzzle in Heidegger’s thinking, let us clarify the terms
of the problem with some assumptions: assume that the dam has improved the
standard of living for many Germans and that no significant environmental damage
has resulted from its construction and operation. If these assumptions are made,
how can Heidegger still deem the dam monstrous?
In his polemic against the dam, Heidegger comments, ‘What the river is now,
namely a water power supplier, derives from out of the essence of the power station’
(1977, p. 16). Heidegger does not hate the dam because it physically damages the
river; instead, he hates it because it reduces the river. Subsumed under both the
idea and the material fact of the hydroelectric dam, the river no longer stands on
its own. Implicitly, Heidegger is using the following syllogism:
Premise: The building of the Rhine dam has compromised the standing-on-its-own
of the Rhine River.
Premise: All actions in which we compromise the standing-on-its-own of something
are monstrous actions.
Conclusion: The building of the Rhine dam is a monstrous action.
It is still unclear, however, what it means for something to stand on its own.
Aristotle may enlighten us in this regard with his description of what it is for a
human being not to stand on their own: ‘Hence we see what is the nature and office
of a slave; he who is … not his own but another’s man, is by nature a slave …’ (1995,
1254a13) The person whose nature is subsumed under that of another has been
reduced—reduced to slavery. No standing or dignity remain for the slave; ‘he’ or ‘she’
has been reduced to an ‘it’. The slave, regarded as slave, is a mere piece of property
that is disposable in both the technical and conventional senses of disposability
described in the summary.
Laboring under the material and conceptual mastery of the dam, the river has also
been reduced to slavery. It no longer stands on its own; it is merely a piece of property
to be manipulated by the various gigantic states and corporations of the world. The
Rhine and the Columbia, the Nile and the Yangtze—they were once the greatest
and most holy of rivers, but are now merely the most useful of our slave-objects.
Most of the countries of the world have signed agreements that grant that human
beings possess a certain inviolable dignity; humans cannot be reduced to slavery
and they must be treated with a measure of respect. Human beings, however, are
574 David I.Waddington
© 2005 Philosophy of Education Society of Australasia
not the only entities in the world that seem to possess dignity. For example, a
Sequoia in the forest stands on its own, and, as such, it seems to have some kind
of dignity. Once that tree has been cut down and reduced to a technically and
conventionally disposable log, whatever dignity it may once have had is lost.
Suppose it is true that all human beings possess a kind of inviolable dignity.
Animals differ from human beings only in the fact that they are not rational. Does
their lack of reason make animals unworthy of dignity? Surely not: when humans
lose their minds to Alzheimer’s disease, we all agree that their dignity remains
inviolable. We would not even consider consigning a witless Alzheimer’s patient to
a cage in a research laboratory.
One can expand the scope of this argument from animals to other living and
non-living entities. In each case one can ask, ‘Does their lack of property Z make
entity X less worthy of dignity than entity Y?’ Admittedly, as one traces the course
of this argument through the hierarchy of being—from animals all the way down
to manufactured objects—dignity becomes increasingly attenuated. Yet, I would
argue that dignity persists all the way down the hierarchy of being; even the plastic
soft-drink bottle possesses an extremely small amount of dignity. Heidegger would
probably concur with this view; he was fascinated by the work of Cezanne, who
thought that even inanimate objects had dignity:
People think that a sugar bowl has no physiognomy, no soul. But that also
changes from day to day. One has to know how to take them, flatter them,
these gentlemen. These glasses, these plates, they speak to each other, they
are always exchanging confidences. ( Jamme, 1994, p. 140)
In his essay, ‘The Thing’, Heidegger expresses views that are similar to those of
Cezanne. (1971, p. 182)
At one point, while discussing the reduction of objects to standing-reserve,
Heidegger remarks, ‘Whatever stands by in the sense of standing-reserve no longer
stands over against us as object’ (1977, p. 17). The notion of the dignity and
standing of objects can help us understand Heidegger’s cryptic remark. Objects like
the river lose their dignity by being subsumed under the material and conceptual
command of objects like the dam, which, for their part, are under the complete
control of human subjects. Therefore, in a sense, whatever is reduced to standing-
reserve is no longer an object because it has been completely subsumed under the
material and conceptual reign of the subject. A kind of objectlessness results—the only
significance these objects have is that they are the property of the subject. In light
of this view, another of Heidegger’s puzzling remarks begins to make sense:
Meanwhile man … exalts himself to the posture of lord of the earth. In
this way the impression comes to prevail that everything man encounters
exists only insofar as it is his construct. This illusion gives rise in turn to
one final delusion: It seems as though man everywhere and always encounters
only himself [italics mine]. (1977, p. 27)
Heidegger feels that we should not underestimate the importance of the dignity
of objects; once the objectlessness of standing-reserve prevails, the next target for
A Field Guide to Heidegger 575
© 2005 Philosophy of Education Society of Australasia
reduction to material/conceptual slavery is other subjects—human beings. Already,
says Heidegger (1977, p. 18), we can discern the beginnings of this trend in the talk
of ‘human resources’. As Michael Zimmerman ominously remarks, ‘While humanity
cannot yet manufacture itself in factories, it is moving in that direction’ (1990, p. 201).
2.3 Ge-stell
The phenomenon of Ge-stell is problematic for three reasons:
1. The non-human origin of the phenomenon of Ge-stell seems to entail serious
difficulties.
2. It is a significant challenge to understand what Heidegger means by Ge-stell.
3. One is puzzled as to why Heidegger introduces this phenomenon at all; it is not
clear how postulating the phenomenon of Ge-stell adds to the ideas that have already
been adumbrated in the essay.
In coming to a proper understanding of the phenomenon of Ge-stell, all of these
problems must be addressed.
In order to deal with the first two problems, one must understand the relationship
between Ge-stell and Heidegger’s notion of Being. Instead of accepting a conven-
tional conception of Being as sort of inert underlying substance, Heidegger thinks
of Being as energeia (Pöggeler, 1996, p. 208). Edward Ballard comments on this
conception: ‘We do not come to thinking; rather it comes to us’ (1971, p. 61). Thus,
in a sense, Being has a mind of its own—in different epochs, Being reveals itself
to man in different ways. In ‘The Word of Nietzsche’, Heidegger remarks, ‘In every
phase of metaphysics there has been visible at any particular time a portion of a
way that the destining of Being prepares as a path for itself …’ (1977, p. 54)
Essentially, Ge-stell is the dominant way in which Being is revealing itself to human
beings right now.
An example may bring to light some of the difficulties surrounding this conception:
once, on a Grade 5 class trip, a classmate of mine who could not swim fell into
the pool. After he was fished out, he explained that the Devil had pulled him into
the pool. Naturally, most of the class did not find this to be an adequate explana-
tion. The point of the story is as follows: if the Devil no longer suffices to explain
bad events to schoolchildren, how can the more mature readers of Heidegger
(1977, p. 24) possibly accept that Ge-stell happens ‘neither exclusively in man, nor
decisively through man’, but rather because of the inscrutable and mysterious
powers of Being?
Heidegger cannot be decisively extricated from this difficulty. However, puzzle-
ment on the part of readers over Heidegger’s strange position can be palliated
through an explanation of the nature of Ge-stell. In order to understand Ge-stell,
we must turn to a similar phenomenon that Heidegger outlines in Being and Time:
the they. Heidegger comments:
In utilizing public transportation, in the use of information services such
as the newspaper, every other is like the next … In this inconspicuousness
576 David I.Waddington
© 2005 Philosophy of Education Society of Australasia
and unascertainability, the they unfolds its true dictatorship. We enjoy
ourselves and have fun the way they enjoy themselves. We read, see, and
judge literature the way they see and judge. (1996, p. 119)
In non-Heideggerian parlance, the they is the consciousness (Heidegger thinks it is
a false consciousness) of society. Simply by virtue of being in society, human beings
are always already lost in the they; we always already see things through their eyes.
Ge-stell is, essentially, an element (perhaps even the dominant element) of the
contemporary they.
The dominant consciousness of society always already ensnares us into thinking
in the mode of challenging-forth; it is as if we have had special challenging-forth
contact lenses permanently implanted in our eyes since birth. Heidegger remarks,
‘It is not the case that a Da-sein, untouched and unseduced by this way of inter-
preting, was ever confronted by the free land of a ‘world’ merely to look at what
it encounters’ (1996, p. 159).
No one is to blame for the they; it is simply an inevitable element of the structure
of human existence. By understanding this inevitability and this blamelessness, we
can see why it might be said that the they and Ge-stell are both, in a sense, of non-
human origin. Neither the they nor Ge-stell are a plot by the government or the
ruling classes; the they and Ge-stell are simply part of the way Things are going—
the way Being is going.
The third problem that was posed at the beginning of this section—the question
of how Ge-stell adds to the ideas that have already been introduced in Heidegger’s
essay—must be answered very speculatively. When Heidegger postulates a non-
human origin for Ge-stell, he extricates human beings from blame. The logging
contractor cannot be blamed for using the Caterpillar tree ‘harvester’ to destroy
the forest. Thus, rather than responding to the logging contractor with hatred and
blame, those people who had extricated themselves from the destining of Ge-stell
would realize that the only fruitful path is to educate the logging contractor. Per-
haps, for example, one could gently pry the challenging-forth contact lenses away
from the contractor’s eyes through a peaceful debate about the relative merits of
bringing-forth and challenging-forth.
At this point, the three problems I posed concerning Ge-stell have all been
briefly addressed. This treatment, however, has not extricated the concept of
Ge-stell from its difficulties—if anything, I have uncovered a cornucopia of potential
new problems. Due to its many inadequacies, the question must be raised whether
the notion of Ge-stell should be thrown out. As in the case of bringing-forth, this
crucial question will have to be deferred for the time being.
2.4 The Overall Impact of ‘The Question Concerning Technology’
Most current articles on the value of technology are preoccupied with pieces of
technology. These articles are valuable; it is important both to observe how particular
technologies function in the world and to point out possible new directions for
these technologies. However, a significant dimension of technology goes unnoticed
A Field Guide to Heidegger 577
© 2005 Philosophy of Education Society of Australasia
by most commentators: the way of thinking that lies behind the creation and use of
technology. If more commentators on technology were able to wade through ‘The
Question Concerning Technology’, as well as some of Heidegger’s other writings,
they might discover some exciting new pathways for their thinking.
Heidegger’s account also has noteworthy implications for environmental ethics.
If all living things and inanimate objects have a measure of dignity, the various
entities that make up the world must be accorded more respect. If human beings
are gradually destroying the world (both in the conventional sense and in the
Heideggerian sense of reduction to standing-reserve) through their entrapment in
challenging-forth, systematic efforts must be made to free individuals from their
ideological prison. Redesigning certain aspects of the education system might serve
to further this goal.
The great breakthrough of ‘The Question Concerning Technology’ is that it shifts
the focus away from specific technologies and toward the modes of thinking that
lie behind these technologies. However, within this breakthrough lies a danger: it
is possible to focus on the thinking behind the technology to such an extent that
meaningful distinctions in the world are obscured. In a remark that was originally
a part of ‘The Question Concerning Technology’, but was later excised (Harries,
1994, p. 233), this danger manifests itself:
Agriculture is now a motorized food industry—in essence the same as the
manufacture of corpses in the gas chambers and extermination campus,
the same as the blockading and starvation of nations, the same as the
manufacture of hydrogen bombs. (Ferry & Renaut, 1990, p. 71) (Schirmacher,
1983, p. 25)
In this remark, Heidegger is trying to point out that challenging-forth into standing-
reserve is at work in both modern agriculture and the concentration camps. Clearly,
however, to say that modern agriculture and the death camps are ‘in essence the
same’ obviates meaningful empirical distinctions and trivializes the significance of
the extermination camps. Rorty notes, ‘Heidegger needed to see everything in our
century other than its technologism as mere transitory appearance’ (1994, p. 36).
Another significant failing of Heidegger’s philosophy of technology is that the
benefits of technology are not acknowledged. The hydroelectric dam across
the Rhine does improve people’s lives, and, as Rorty (1977, p. 302) points out, the
spread of modern technology across the planet has prevented many people from
dying of starvation. Yet, despite the fact that Heidegger never acknowledges the
benefits of technology, he does not urge giving it up:
We can say ‘yes’ to the unavoidable use of technological objects, and we
can at the same time say ‘no,’ insofar as we do not permit them to claim
us exclusively and thus to warp, confuse, and finally lay waste to our
essence. (1966, p. 54)
This smacks of having one’s cake and eating it too. Under Heidegger’s conception,
we conveniently say ‘yes’ to the modern technologies that make our lives so
comfortable, while somehow apparently saying ‘no’ to them as well.
578 David I.Waddington
© 2005 Philosophy of Education Society of Australasia
The greatest difficulties with ‘The Question Concerning Technology’, however,
are technical rather than ideological. Imagine, for example, what a careful, but not
particularly sympathetic, analyst might say about each of Heidegger’s three key
notions:
Bringing-forth—this is an arbitrary, nostalgic notion that involves an impossibility
(revealing from pre-existence) and has no grounding in historical fact.
Challenging-forth to standing-reserve—this is another arbitrary construction, which
demonizes technology wholesale and indulges in groundless speculation by asserting
that objects (even inanimate objects!) have some kind of mysterious dignity.
Ge-stell—this is the most preposterous idea of the three. In addition to being
nearly incomprehensible, it entails the ridiculous notion that inscrutable historical
determinations of Being are somehow responsible for human actions. Furthermore,
if one accepts the speculative connection between the they and Ge-stell, it appears
that human beings are trapped in a mindset of destruction—a mindset that, para-
doxically, absolves the perpetrators of any responsibility for the destruction!
In addition to the internal problems of the three notions, none of the three key
ideas is established through any systematic form of argument. For the most part,
Heidegger simply makes ex-cathedra pronouncements about these three ideas; he
might as well be saying, ‘Behold bringing-forth,’ and ‘Let there be the phenomenon
of Ge-stell’.
Clearly, we must face the recurrent question of whether Heidegger’s ideas should
be discarded. Most people would lean strongly in the direction of discarding the
ideas; our common-sense practice in situations like these is to discard ideas that do not
adequately correspond to the world. Heidegger’s theory of technology contains so many
implausible notions that it is very difficult to defend it on a correspondence basis.
Philosophers of a more post-modern bent might be inclined to defend Heidegger
using the criterion of coherence. Since even the most insane religious fanatics can
postulate a coherent system, this criterion is highly suspect. However, even if one
makes the questionable decision to accept the criterion of coherence, Heidegger’s
theory is not necessarily saved. Although I have interpreted ‘The Question
Concerning Technology’ in such a way as to present Heidegger’s theory as coherent,
Heidegger’s wandering formulations make other, less coherent, interpretations
possible.
The best criterion with which to defend Heidegger is neither correspondence nor
coherence, but usefulness. If people decided to think in the mode of bringing-forth,
and decided not to think in the mode of challenging-forth, much more beauty and
happiness might be brought into the world. If more people chose to think that living
things and inanimate objects had a certain dignity, the destruction of the earth
might begin to draw to a close. And, if people thought that the phenomenon of
Ge-stell was a possibility, they might be motivated to examine their own view of
the world with a critical eye. Rorty writes of Heidegger,
I see the toolbox we have inherited from [Heidegger] as containing a very
varied assortment, constructed for various different purposes—an
assortment in which only some items are still useful. (Rorty, 1994, p. 35)
A Field Guide to Heidegger 579
© 2005 Philosophy of Education Society of Australasia
‘The Question Concerning Technology’ is a toolbox containing three key tools:
bringing-forth, challenging-forth to standing-reserve, and Ge-stell. All of these
tools are useful: indeed, used properly, they might serve to repair the damaged
relationship between human beings and the world.
In Republic, Plato writes, ‘… if it is appropriate for anyone to use falsehoods for
the good of the city … it is the rulers’ (1997, 398b) Some might allege that the
preceding defense of Heidegger, on the grounds of usefulness, contains harbingers
of indoctrination—hints of the Platonic philosophical elite who tell the noble,
educational lie to the masses. Perhaps, however, it is time for philosophers to stop
apologizing for advocating the noble lie; a great many lies are already told to the
people by elites, and most of these lies are ignoble.
Part 3 Heidegger Scholarship in Education
When one reads a piece of secondary literature, one hopes to find clear writing and
accurate scholarship. Unfortunately, some of the articles on Heidegger by scholars
in education fall short in one or both of these areas. By pointing out the shortcom-
ings of these articles, I hope to offer a justification for the preceding summary and
critique. I also aim to provide a helpful guide for those interested in further
research in this area.
Richard Walton’s, ‘Heidegger in the Hands-on Science and Technology Center’,
is an example of an article with significant defects. Consider, for example, the
following excerpt:
This means that, in Heidegger’s terms, ‘technology’ is more than the
artifacts and activities that form the ontic. It can be spoken of in terms of
the mode of truth that is the framework of possibilities which forms the
essential nature of technology which is to be revealed and which gives
technology its ontological sense. Superficially, this ontology of technology
seems to bear some similarity with the platonic notion of the ideal form
yet, as Guignon (1993, p. 4) pointed out, a significant distinction can be
drawn between Heidegger’s ‘substance ontology’ and the traditional notion
of the ‘metaphysics of presence’. (Walton, 2000, p. 54)
In these three sentences, we see the words/phrases ‘ontic’ ‘ontological’ (to give
Walton credit, he defines ‘ontic’ and ‘ontological’ earlier on), ‘mode of truth’, ‘platonic
notion of the ideal form’, ‘substance ontology’, and ‘metaphysics of presence’, and
Walton is only on the second paragraph of his discussion of Heidegger! Walton’s
article was published in the Journal of Technology Education, which, presumably, has
an audience composed mostly of academics working in technology education.
One suspects that these academics might be puzzled by discussions of ‘substance
ontology’ and the ‘metaphysics of presence’.
Walton’s analyses are often somewhat confused—for example, consider Walton’s
account of an exhibit at a science center:
The exhibits found within such centers represent a special case or
category of technological artifact which is designed and built with the
580 David I.Waddington
© 2005 Philosophy of Education Society of Australasia
specific aim of encouraging reflection upon its own essence. Of course,
in most cases this is only true to a limited extent. An exhibit which
demonstrates chaotic motion reveals only a limited set of ideas relating to
the nature of the world and in so doing it shows only one way in which
technology can be used to frame this idea. But it does show that the idea
can be framed. Heidegger uses the term gestell to describe this act of
framing, or what he called ‘enframing’. (2000, p. 54)
I don’t think that Ge-stell, which is a sort of meta-phenomenon beyond human
control, appropriately describes what is happening when a person constructs an
exhibit about chaotic motion. Challenging-forth might be an appropriate descrip-
tion, but it is not clear that challenging-forth is necessarily at work during the
construction of an exhibit like this. This sort of confusion is representative of most
of Walton’s essay, which fails to give an adequate account of Heidegger.
Heidegger scholarship is significantly better within the philosophy of education
community. However, some analyses of Heidegger by members of the philosophy
of education community contain occasional flaws. For example, consider the fol-
lowing paragraph—an excerpt from James Marshall’s essay, ‘Electronic Writing and
the Wrapping of Language’:
To have a free relationship with technology we cannot come to it with any
presuppositions—for example, that it is neutral. … This involves an
initial response to technology, before any decision is made as to what it is and,
then, how we are to respond to it. For to respond to it we must have grasped
certain things about ourselves, about human being, so that we can ‘open’
ourselves to the essences of both human being and of technology. This must
be simultaneous and mutual opening up or recognition, and not a temporal
response, for human being and technology are in mutual interrelationship.
This is difficult to understand, given traditional philosophical, logicist,
positivist and Anglo-Saxon understandings of language and logic and a
traditional overt antipathy to metaphysics. (Marshall, 2000, p. 144)
There are two significant problems with this paragraph. First, in a Heideggerian
context, it doesn’t make sense to talk about approaching technology ‘without pre-
suppositions’ or ‘before any decision is made as to what it is’. The problem is not
one of how to make the decision about technology; Heidegger would say that the
decision has always already been made. We are already stuck in a particular under-
standing of technology; the challenge is to become aware of that understanding and
to extricate ourselves from it somehow. Second, it is not clear to me how a ‘mutual
opening up’ is possible. Although it is possible to understand Ge-stell as having
some kind of agency, I fail to see how the essence of technology can really ‘open
itself up’. Further to this point, Marshall says that this ‘mutual opening up’ is ‘not
a temporal response’. What would it mean for a response to be ‘non-temporal’? I do
not consider myself a positivist or a person with an ‘overt antipathy to metaphysics’—
in fact, I am deeply sympathetic to much of Heidegger’s account. Yet, I still find it
‘difficult to understand’ what Marshall is saying in this particular paragraph.
A Field Guide to Heidegger 581
© 2005 Philosophy of Education Society of Australasia
Ilan Gur-Ze’ev’s article ‘Martin Heidegger, Transcendence, and the Possibility of
Counter-Education’ also raises some questions. For example, in a discussion about how
things are leveled down to standing-reserve, Gur-Ze’ev makes the following remark:
Within this process, modern science and technology transform man
himself into a standing-reserve. Enframing and unconcealment as roads
to realizing human freedom are blocked in a manner that does not enable
the human to acknowledge and challenge it. (Gur-Ze’ev, 2002, p. 74)
There are several problems with this remark. First, Gur-Ze’ev introduces the word
‘enframing’ without any comment. Thus, any readers of Gur-Ze’ev, who have not
already read Heidegger, will be confused by this use of the word. Gur-Ze’ev com-
pounds this problem by misunderstanding enframing: obviously, enframing (Ge-stell)
is not a road to human freedom. Furthermore, since challenging-forth also involves
a kind of unconcealment, unconcealment is also not necessarily a ‘road to realizing
human freedom’.
Some of Gur-Ze’ev’s other remarks suffer from similar difficulties:
In modern Ge-stell, in the human’s being framed in modernity as
advanced by modern science and technology, human situateness ensures
the oblivion of the mission of the human, of life as something more than
mere life. But for Heidegger, framing has deeper roots and is not to be
reduced to a specific historical situation. It springs from the very fact of
situateness of human life, of always living enframed. (Gur-Ze’ev, 2002, p. 75)
Again, Gur-Ze’ev fails to explain either ‘Ge-stell’, ‘framing’, or ‘enframing’ to the
reader. And what exactly does it mean that ‘framing’ has ‘deeper roots’ and is ‘not
to be reduced to a specific historical situation’? Gur-Ze’ev might be making
an important point about Being here, but he does not explain this to the reader.
Furthermore, it is difficult to understand what Gur-Ze’ev means when he says
that enframing ‘springs from the very fact of situateness of human life’. In sum,
although Gur-Ze’ev appears to be quite knowledgeable about Heidegger, he does
not always explain Heidegger very well. Indeed, articles like Gur-Ze’ev’s highlight
the need for a clear, concise analysis of Heidegger’s philosophy of technology.
There is no denying, however, that there are many excellent essays written on
Heidegger by philosophers of education. Paul Standish, Bert Lambeir, and Michael
Bonnett have all written insightful articles that I recommend highly. In particular,
Bonnett’s article, ‘Education in a Destitute Time’, is a masterpiece. However,
despite the competence of these authors, there is something missing from all of
their articles: rigorous, systematic criticism of Heidegger. To give credit where it is
due, Standish, in ‘Only Connect’, devotes a paragraph to criticizing Heidegger’s
nostalgia (1999, p. 424). In a similar spirit, Bonnett makes the following remark:
Clearly, Heidegger here presents us with a critique of the traditional
Western metaphysical conception of thinking of a most radical kind, and
this itself stands in need of further exploration and critical evaluation.
(Bonnett, 1983, p. 26)
582 David I.Waddington
© 2005 Philosophy of Education Society of Australasia
Unfortunately, Bonnett, Lambeir, and Standish have not presented us with ‘further
exploration’ and ‘critical evaluation’ of this kind. They are in no way blameworthy
for this; they simply chose to focus on examining the educational implications of
Heidegger’s philosophy rather than examining its faults.
I have chosen the opposite path: I have not commented very much about the
educational implications of Heidegger’s philosophy, choosing instead to focus on
solving puzzles in his philosophy and pointing out its shortcomings. However, as
Bonnett’s comment points out, this is a task that needs to be done. Hopefully, this
field guide will also serve as a tool with which scholars in education, who may have
been scared off by Heidegger’s difficult prose, can now pry open the treasure box
of interesting ideas that is ‘The Question Concerning Technology’. Indeed, in the
introduction, I suggested that this field guide would ‘set the table’ for further
scholarship on Heidegger within the philosophy of education. Now that I have ‘set
the table’, readers of this field guide should make ready ‘the meal’ by conducting
further investigations of the educational implications of Heidegger’s philosophy of
technology.
References
Aristotle (1995) The Complete Works of Aristotle, J. Barnes (ed.) (Princeton, Princeton University
Press).
Ballard, E. (1971) Heidegger’s View and Evaluation of Nature and Natural Science, in: J. Sallis
(ed.), Heidegger and the Path of Thinking (Pittsburgh, Duquesne University Press), pp. 37–
64.
Bonnett, M. (1983), Education in a Destitute Time, Journal of Philosophy of Education, 17:1,
pp. 21–33.
Caterpillar Equipment (28 April 2003), Harvesters, http://cmms.cat.com/cmms/servlet/cat.dcs.
cmms.servlet.GetModelSummary?classid=406&langid=en&rgnid=NACD&view=html&
prdname=580&prdid=580&familyid=463&subfamilyid=331&dsfFlag=0&subfamilyheader=
Harvesters
Ferry, L. & Renaut, A. (1990), Heidegger and Modernity, F. Philip (trans.) (Chicago, University
of Chicago Press).
Guignon, C. B. (1993) Introduction, in: C. B. Guignon (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to
Heidegger (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press), pp. 1–42.
Gur-Ze’ev, I. (2002) Heidegger, Transcendence, and the Possibility of Counter-Education, in:
M. Peters (ed.), Heidegger, Education, and Modernity (Lanham, Rowman and Littlefield),
pp. 65–80.
Harries, K. (1994) Philosophy, Politics, Technology, in: K. Harries & C. Jamme (eds), Martin
Heidegger: Politics, Art, and Technology (New York, Holmes and Meier), pp. 225–245.
Heidegger, M. (1996) Being and Time, trans. J. Stambaugh (Albany, SUNY Press).
Heidegger, M. (1966) Discourse on Thinking, J. M. Anderson and E. H. Freund (trans.) (New
York, Harper and Row).
Heidegger, M. (1977) The Question Concerning Technology, in: The Question Concerning
Technology and Other Essays, W. Lovitt (trans.) (New York, Harper and Row), pp. 3–
35.
Heidegger, M. (1971) The Thing, in: Poetry, Language, Thought, A. Hofstadter (trans.)
(New York, Harper and Row), pp. 165–182.
Heidegger, M. (1977) The Word of Nietzsche, in: The Question Concerning Technology and Other
Essays, W. Lovitt (trans.) (New York, Harper and Row), pp. 53–112.
A Field Guide to Heidegger 583
© 2005 Philosophy of Education Society of Australasia
Jamme, C. (1994) The Loss of Things: Cezanne, Rilke, Heidegger, in: K. Harries & C. Jamme
(eds), Martin Heidegger: Politics, Art, and Technology (New York, Holmes and Meier),
pp. 139–153.
Lambeir, B. (2002) Comfortably Numb in the Digital Era: Man’s being as standing-reserve or
dwelling silently, in: M. Peters (ed.), Heidegger, Education, and Modernity (Lanham,
Rowman and Littlefield), pp. 103–122.
Lovitt, W. (1972) A Gesprach with Heidegger on Technology, Man and World, 6:1, pp. 44–62.
Marshall, J. (2000), Electronic Writing and the Wrapping of Language, Journal of Philosophy of
Education, 34:1, pp. 135–150.
Plato (1997) Complete Works, J. Cooper (ed.) (Indianapolis, Hackett).
Pöggeler, O. (1996) Does the Saving Power also grow? Heidegger’s last paths, in: C. McCann
(ed.), Critical Heidegger (London, Routledge), pp. 206–226.
Rorty, R. (1994) Another Possible World, in: K. Harries & C. Jamme (eds) Martin Heidegger:
Politics, Art, and Technology (New York: Holmes and Meier), pp. 34–40.
Rorty, R. (1977), Overcoming the Tradition: Heidegger and Dewey, Review of Metaphysics, 30:2,
pp. 280–305.
Sallis, J. (1971) Toward the Movement of Reversal: Science, technology, and the language of
homecoming, in: J. Sallis (ed.), Heidegger and the Path of Thinking (Pittsburgh, Duquesne
University Press), pp. 138–168.
Schirmacher, W. (1983) Technik und Gelassenheit (Freiburg, Alber).
Standish, P. (1999), Only Connect: Computer literacy from Heidegger to cyberfeminism,
Educational Theory, 49:4, pp. 417–435.
Walton, R. (2000), Heidegger in the Hands-On Science and Technology Center: Philosophical
reflections on learning in informal settings, Journal of Technology Education, 12:1, pp. 49–
60.
Winograd, T. (1995) Heidegger and the Design of Computer Systems, in: A. Feenberg &
A. Hanney (eds), Technology and the Politics of Knowledge (Bloomington, Indiana University
Press), pp. 108–127.
Zimmerman, M. (1977) Beyond Humanism: Heidegger’s understanding of technology, Listening,
12:3, pp. 74–83.
Zimmerman, M. (1990), Heidegger’s Confrontation with Modernity: Technology, politics, and art
(Bloomington, Indiana University Press).

More Related Content

Similar to A Field Guide To Heidegger Understanding The Question Concerning Technology

Group 4- Technology as a way of Revealing.pptx
Group 4- Technology as a way of Revealing.pptxGroup 4- Technology as a way of Revealing.pptx
Group 4- Technology as a way of Revealing.pptx
heatherlee640974
 
How To Write An Argument Essay.pdf
How To Write An Argument Essay.pdfHow To Write An Argument Essay.pdf
How To Write An Argument Essay.pdf
Lynn Bennett
 
Learning innovation
Learning innovationLearning innovation
Learning innovation
Vidensemergens
 
chapter4-STS.pptx
chapter4-STS.pptxchapter4-STS.pptx
chapter4-STS.pptx
KimberlyTemplonuevo
 
Hermenetutics in tertiary education
Hermenetutics in tertiary educationHermenetutics in tertiary education
Hermenetutics in tertiary education
Guangdong University of Foreign Studies
 
Advancement of scientific knowledge and complex thinking
Advancement of scientific knowledge and complex thinkingAdvancement of scientific knowledge and complex thinking
Advancement of scientific knowledge and complex thinking
Fernando Alcoforado
 
Creativity in tefl
Creativity in teflCreativity in tefl
Creativity in tefl
QamraSaud AlOtaibi
 
Why theory
Why theoryWhy theory
Mary midgely, background, philosophy
Mary midgely, background, philosophyMary midgely, background, philosophy
Mary midgely, background, philosophy
Leah Schade
 
Collaboration in the arts and humanities
Collaboration in the arts and humanitiesCollaboration in the arts and humanities
Collaboration in the arts and humanities
NomadWarMachine
 
Science, Technology and Society Modules 6-8 ppt.pptx
Science, Technology and Society Modules 6-8 ppt.pptxScience, Technology and Society Modules 6-8 ppt.pptx
Science, Technology and Society Modules 6-8 ppt.pptx
VonKenneth1
 
Sobre ortega dieguez
Sobre ortega dieguezSobre ortega dieguez
Sobre ortega dieguez
JORGE
 
Mind the Gap!
Mind the Gap!Mind the Gap!
Mind the Gap!
amuseevous
 
The Modernist State, Valania.pdf
The Modernist State, Valania.pdfThe Modernist State, Valania.pdf
The Modernist State, Valania.pdf
DrAndrewNyongesa
 
Discourse Analysis article shared by Azhar Khan ..1
Discourse Analysis article shared by Azhar Khan ..1Discourse Analysis article shared by Azhar Khan ..1
Discourse Analysis article shared by Azhar Khan ..1
Abdullah Saleem
 
Learning Theory
Learning TheoryLearning Theory
Learning Theory
George Roberts
 

Similar to A Field Guide To Heidegger Understanding The Question Concerning Technology (16)

Group 4- Technology as a way of Revealing.pptx
Group 4- Technology as a way of Revealing.pptxGroup 4- Technology as a way of Revealing.pptx
Group 4- Technology as a way of Revealing.pptx
 
How To Write An Argument Essay.pdf
How To Write An Argument Essay.pdfHow To Write An Argument Essay.pdf
How To Write An Argument Essay.pdf
 
Learning innovation
Learning innovationLearning innovation
Learning innovation
 
chapter4-STS.pptx
chapter4-STS.pptxchapter4-STS.pptx
chapter4-STS.pptx
 
Hermenetutics in tertiary education
Hermenetutics in tertiary educationHermenetutics in tertiary education
Hermenetutics in tertiary education
 
Advancement of scientific knowledge and complex thinking
Advancement of scientific knowledge and complex thinkingAdvancement of scientific knowledge and complex thinking
Advancement of scientific knowledge and complex thinking
 
Creativity in tefl
Creativity in teflCreativity in tefl
Creativity in tefl
 
Why theory
Why theoryWhy theory
Why theory
 
Mary midgely, background, philosophy
Mary midgely, background, philosophyMary midgely, background, philosophy
Mary midgely, background, philosophy
 
Collaboration in the arts and humanities
Collaboration in the arts and humanitiesCollaboration in the arts and humanities
Collaboration in the arts and humanities
 
Science, Technology and Society Modules 6-8 ppt.pptx
Science, Technology and Society Modules 6-8 ppt.pptxScience, Technology and Society Modules 6-8 ppt.pptx
Science, Technology and Society Modules 6-8 ppt.pptx
 
Sobre ortega dieguez
Sobre ortega dieguezSobre ortega dieguez
Sobre ortega dieguez
 
Mind the Gap!
Mind the Gap!Mind the Gap!
Mind the Gap!
 
The Modernist State, Valania.pdf
The Modernist State, Valania.pdfThe Modernist State, Valania.pdf
The Modernist State, Valania.pdf
 
Discourse Analysis article shared by Azhar Khan ..1
Discourse Analysis article shared by Azhar Khan ..1Discourse Analysis article shared by Azhar Khan ..1
Discourse Analysis article shared by Azhar Khan ..1
 
Learning Theory
Learning TheoryLearning Theory
Learning Theory
 

More from Renee Lewis

College Essay Writing An Academic Article
College Essay Writing An Academic ArticleCollege Essay Writing An Academic Article
College Essay Writing An Academic Article
Renee Lewis
 
Best Online Essay Writing Service - The Best Place To Buy Sam
Best Online Essay Writing Service - The Best Place To Buy SamBest Online Essay Writing Service - The Best Place To Buy Sam
Best Online Essay Writing Service - The Best Place To Buy Sam
Renee Lewis
 
Vocabulary For Ielts Writing Essays
Vocabulary For Ielts Writing EssaysVocabulary For Ielts Writing Essays
Vocabulary For Ielts Writing Essays
Renee Lewis
 
Common Mistakes To Avoid In Essay Writing - MakeMyAssignments Blog
Common Mistakes To Avoid In Essay Writing - MakeMyAssignments BlogCommon Mistakes To Avoid In Essay Writing - MakeMyAssignments Blog
Common Mistakes To Avoid In Essay Writing - MakeMyAssignments Blog
Renee Lewis
 
Pin On Academic Research Writing
Pin On Academic Research WritingPin On Academic Research Writing
Pin On Academic Research Writing
Renee Lewis
 
Compare And Contrast Essay
Compare And Contrast EssayCompare And Contrast Essay
Compare And Contrast Essay
Renee Lewis
 
Helping The Poor Essay. Helping The Poor And Needy. 2022-10-12
Helping The Poor Essay. Helping The Poor And Needy. 2022-10-12Helping The Poor Essay. Helping The Poor And Needy. 2022-10-12
Helping The Poor Essay. Helping The Poor And Needy. 2022-10-12
Renee Lewis
 
How Much Time Will It Decide To Use To Write Down A 150
How Much Time Will It Decide To Use To Write Down A 150How Much Time Will It Decide To Use To Write Down A 150
How Much Time Will It Decide To Use To Write Down A 150
Renee Lewis
 
Pearson - Along These Lines Writing Paragraphs
Pearson - Along These Lines Writing ParagraphsPearson - Along These Lines Writing Paragraphs
Pearson - Along These Lines Writing Paragraphs
Renee Lewis
 
Writing An Editorial
Writing An EditorialWriting An Editorial
Writing An Editorial
Renee Lewis
 
College Essay How Do I Write An Essay About Myself
College Essay How Do I Write An Essay About MyselfCollege Essay How Do I Write An Essay About Myself
College Essay How Do I Write An Essay About Myself
Renee Lewis
 
Travel Writing (500 Words) - PHDessay.Com
Travel Writing (500 Words) - PHDessay.ComTravel Writing (500 Words) - PHDessay.Com
Travel Writing (500 Words) - PHDessay.Com
Renee Lewis
 
Best Website For Essay By Customassignments - Issuu
Best Website For Essay By Customassignments - IssuuBest Website For Essay By Customassignments - Issuu
Best Website For Essay By Customassignments - Issuu
Renee Lewis
 
Critical Review Essay PDF Information Epistemology
Critical Review Essay  PDF  Information  EpistemologyCritical Review Essay  PDF  Information  Epistemology
Critical Review Essay PDF Information Epistemology
Renee Lewis
 
Papier Lettre Lign Stationary.PrimroseBorder
Papier  Lettre Lign  Stationary.PrimroseBorderPapier  Lettre Lign  Stationary.PrimroseBorder
Papier Lettre Lign Stationary.PrimroseBorder
Renee Lewis
 
Can I Pay Someone To Write A Paper For Me Write My Paper For Me
Can I Pay Someone To Write A Paper For Me Write My Paper For MeCan I Pay Someone To Write A Paper For Me Write My Paper For Me
Can I Pay Someone To Write A Paper For Me Write My Paper For Me
Renee Lewis
 
Best Research Paper Writing Services Revie
Best Research Paper Writing Services RevieBest Research Paper Writing Services Revie
Best Research Paper Writing Services Revie
Renee Lewis
 
History Essay Essays On Line
History Essay Essays On LineHistory Essay Essays On Line
History Essay Essays On Line
Renee Lewis
 
Home - Essay2209.Web.Fc2.Com
Home - Essay2209.Web.Fc2.ComHome - Essay2209.Web.Fc2.Com
Home - Essay2209.Web.Fc2.Com
Renee Lewis
 
How To Write An Essay Quickly.
How To Write An Essay Quickly.How To Write An Essay Quickly.
How To Write An Essay Quickly.
Renee Lewis
 

More from Renee Lewis (20)

College Essay Writing An Academic Article
College Essay Writing An Academic ArticleCollege Essay Writing An Academic Article
College Essay Writing An Academic Article
 
Best Online Essay Writing Service - The Best Place To Buy Sam
Best Online Essay Writing Service - The Best Place To Buy SamBest Online Essay Writing Service - The Best Place To Buy Sam
Best Online Essay Writing Service - The Best Place To Buy Sam
 
Vocabulary For Ielts Writing Essays
Vocabulary For Ielts Writing EssaysVocabulary For Ielts Writing Essays
Vocabulary For Ielts Writing Essays
 
Common Mistakes To Avoid In Essay Writing - MakeMyAssignments Blog
Common Mistakes To Avoid In Essay Writing - MakeMyAssignments BlogCommon Mistakes To Avoid In Essay Writing - MakeMyAssignments Blog
Common Mistakes To Avoid In Essay Writing - MakeMyAssignments Blog
 
Pin On Academic Research Writing
Pin On Academic Research WritingPin On Academic Research Writing
Pin On Academic Research Writing
 
Compare And Contrast Essay
Compare And Contrast EssayCompare And Contrast Essay
Compare And Contrast Essay
 
Helping The Poor Essay. Helping The Poor And Needy. 2022-10-12
Helping The Poor Essay. Helping The Poor And Needy. 2022-10-12Helping The Poor Essay. Helping The Poor And Needy. 2022-10-12
Helping The Poor Essay. Helping The Poor And Needy. 2022-10-12
 
How Much Time Will It Decide To Use To Write Down A 150
How Much Time Will It Decide To Use To Write Down A 150How Much Time Will It Decide To Use To Write Down A 150
How Much Time Will It Decide To Use To Write Down A 150
 
Pearson - Along These Lines Writing Paragraphs
Pearson - Along These Lines Writing ParagraphsPearson - Along These Lines Writing Paragraphs
Pearson - Along These Lines Writing Paragraphs
 
Writing An Editorial
Writing An EditorialWriting An Editorial
Writing An Editorial
 
College Essay How Do I Write An Essay About Myself
College Essay How Do I Write An Essay About MyselfCollege Essay How Do I Write An Essay About Myself
College Essay How Do I Write An Essay About Myself
 
Travel Writing (500 Words) - PHDessay.Com
Travel Writing (500 Words) - PHDessay.ComTravel Writing (500 Words) - PHDessay.Com
Travel Writing (500 Words) - PHDessay.Com
 
Best Website For Essay By Customassignments - Issuu
Best Website For Essay By Customassignments - IssuuBest Website For Essay By Customassignments - Issuu
Best Website For Essay By Customassignments - Issuu
 
Critical Review Essay PDF Information Epistemology
Critical Review Essay  PDF  Information  EpistemologyCritical Review Essay  PDF  Information  Epistemology
Critical Review Essay PDF Information Epistemology
 
Papier Lettre Lign Stationary.PrimroseBorder
Papier  Lettre Lign  Stationary.PrimroseBorderPapier  Lettre Lign  Stationary.PrimroseBorder
Papier Lettre Lign Stationary.PrimroseBorder
 
Can I Pay Someone To Write A Paper For Me Write My Paper For Me
Can I Pay Someone To Write A Paper For Me Write My Paper For MeCan I Pay Someone To Write A Paper For Me Write My Paper For Me
Can I Pay Someone To Write A Paper For Me Write My Paper For Me
 
Best Research Paper Writing Services Revie
Best Research Paper Writing Services RevieBest Research Paper Writing Services Revie
Best Research Paper Writing Services Revie
 
History Essay Essays On Line
History Essay Essays On LineHistory Essay Essays On Line
History Essay Essays On Line
 
Home - Essay2209.Web.Fc2.Com
Home - Essay2209.Web.Fc2.ComHome - Essay2209.Web.Fc2.Com
Home - Essay2209.Web.Fc2.Com
 
How To Write An Essay Quickly.
How To Write An Essay Quickly.How To Write An Essay Quickly.
How To Write An Essay Quickly.
 

Recently uploaded

Reimagining Your Library Space: How to Increase the Vibes in Your Library No ...
Reimagining Your Library Space: How to Increase the Vibes in Your Library No ...Reimagining Your Library Space: How to Increase the Vibes in Your Library No ...
Reimagining Your Library Space: How to Increase the Vibes in Your Library No ...
Diana Rendina
 
Hindi varnamala | hindi alphabet PPT.pdf
Hindi varnamala | hindi alphabet PPT.pdfHindi varnamala | hindi alphabet PPT.pdf
Hindi varnamala | hindi alphabet PPT.pdf
Dr. Mulla Adam Ali
 
MARY JANE WILSON, A “BOA MÃE” .
MARY JANE WILSON, A “BOA MÃE”           .MARY JANE WILSON, A “BOA MÃE”           .
MARY JANE WILSON, A “BOA MÃE” .
Colégio Santa Teresinha
 
Cognitive Development Adolescence Psychology
Cognitive Development Adolescence PsychologyCognitive Development Adolescence Psychology
Cognitive Development Adolescence Psychology
paigestewart1632
 
Advanced Java[Extra Concepts, Not Difficult].docx
Advanced Java[Extra Concepts, Not Difficult].docxAdvanced Java[Extra Concepts, Not Difficult].docx
Advanced Java[Extra Concepts, Not Difficult].docx
adhitya5119
 
clinical examination of hip joint (1).pdf
clinical examination of hip joint (1).pdfclinical examination of hip joint (1).pdf
clinical examination of hip joint (1).pdf
Priyankaranawat4
 
ISO/IEC 27001, ISO/IEC 42001, and GDPR: Best Practices for Implementation and...
ISO/IEC 27001, ISO/IEC 42001, and GDPR: Best Practices for Implementation and...ISO/IEC 27001, ISO/IEC 42001, and GDPR: Best Practices for Implementation and...
ISO/IEC 27001, ISO/IEC 42001, and GDPR: Best Practices for Implementation and...
PECB
 
Digital Artefact 1 - Tiny Home Environmental Design
Digital Artefact 1 - Tiny Home Environmental DesignDigital Artefact 1 - Tiny Home Environmental Design
Digital Artefact 1 - Tiny Home Environmental Design
amberjdewit93
 
The History of Stoke Newington Street Names
The History of Stoke Newington Street NamesThe History of Stoke Newington Street Names
The History of Stoke Newington Street Names
History of Stoke Newington
 
Walmart Business+ and Spark Good for Nonprofits.pdf
Walmart Business+ and Spark Good for Nonprofits.pdfWalmart Business+ and Spark Good for Nonprofits.pdf
Walmart Business+ and Spark Good for Nonprofits.pdf
TechSoup
 
NEWSPAPERS - QUESTION 1 - REVISION POWERPOINT.pptx
NEWSPAPERS - QUESTION 1 - REVISION POWERPOINT.pptxNEWSPAPERS - QUESTION 1 - REVISION POWERPOINT.pptx
NEWSPAPERS - QUESTION 1 - REVISION POWERPOINT.pptx
iammrhaywood
 
Liberal Approach to the Study of Indian Politics.pdf
Liberal Approach to the Study of Indian Politics.pdfLiberal Approach to the Study of Indian Politics.pdf
Liberal Approach to the Study of Indian Politics.pdf
WaniBasim
 
Traditional Musical Instruments of Arunachal Pradesh and Uttar Pradesh - RAYH...
Traditional Musical Instruments of Arunachal Pradesh and Uttar Pradesh - RAYH...Traditional Musical Instruments of Arunachal Pradesh and Uttar Pradesh - RAYH...
Traditional Musical Instruments of Arunachal Pradesh and Uttar Pradesh - RAYH...
imrankhan141184
 
Leveraging Generative AI to Drive Nonprofit Innovation
Leveraging Generative AI to Drive Nonprofit InnovationLeveraging Generative AI to Drive Nonprofit Innovation
Leveraging Generative AI to Drive Nonprofit Innovation
TechSoup
 
C1 Rubenstein AP HuG xxxxxxxxxxxxxx.pptx
C1 Rubenstein AP HuG xxxxxxxxxxxxxx.pptxC1 Rubenstein AP HuG xxxxxxxxxxxxxx.pptx
C1 Rubenstein AP HuG xxxxxxxxxxxxxx.pptx
mulvey2
 
How to Make a Field Mandatory in Odoo 17
How to Make a Field Mandatory in Odoo 17How to Make a Field Mandatory in Odoo 17
How to Make a Field Mandatory in Odoo 17
Celine George
 
Présentationvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvv2.pptx
Présentationvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvv2.pptxPrésentationvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvv2.pptx
Présentationvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvv2.pptx
siemaillard
 
How to Manage Your Lost Opportunities in Odoo 17 CRM
How to Manage Your Lost Opportunities in Odoo 17 CRMHow to Manage Your Lost Opportunities in Odoo 17 CRM
How to Manage Your Lost Opportunities in Odoo 17 CRM
Celine George
 
PCOS corelations and management through Ayurveda.
PCOS corelations and management through Ayurveda.PCOS corelations and management through Ayurveda.
PCOS corelations and management through Ayurveda.
Dr. Shivangi Singh Parihar
 
BÀI TẬP BỔ TRỢ TIẾNG ANH 8 CẢ NĂM - GLOBAL SUCCESS - NĂM HỌC 2023-2024 (CÓ FI...
BÀI TẬP BỔ TRỢ TIẾNG ANH 8 CẢ NĂM - GLOBAL SUCCESS - NĂM HỌC 2023-2024 (CÓ FI...BÀI TẬP BỔ TRỢ TIẾNG ANH 8 CẢ NĂM - GLOBAL SUCCESS - NĂM HỌC 2023-2024 (CÓ FI...
BÀI TẬP BỔ TRỢ TIẾNG ANH 8 CẢ NĂM - GLOBAL SUCCESS - NĂM HỌC 2023-2024 (CÓ FI...
Nguyen Thanh Tu Collection
 

Recently uploaded (20)

Reimagining Your Library Space: How to Increase the Vibes in Your Library No ...
Reimagining Your Library Space: How to Increase the Vibes in Your Library No ...Reimagining Your Library Space: How to Increase the Vibes in Your Library No ...
Reimagining Your Library Space: How to Increase the Vibes in Your Library No ...
 
Hindi varnamala | hindi alphabet PPT.pdf
Hindi varnamala | hindi alphabet PPT.pdfHindi varnamala | hindi alphabet PPT.pdf
Hindi varnamala | hindi alphabet PPT.pdf
 
MARY JANE WILSON, A “BOA MÃE” .
MARY JANE WILSON, A “BOA MÃE”           .MARY JANE WILSON, A “BOA MÃE”           .
MARY JANE WILSON, A “BOA MÃE” .
 
Cognitive Development Adolescence Psychology
Cognitive Development Adolescence PsychologyCognitive Development Adolescence Psychology
Cognitive Development Adolescence Psychology
 
Advanced Java[Extra Concepts, Not Difficult].docx
Advanced Java[Extra Concepts, Not Difficult].docxAdvanced Java[Extra Concepts, Not Difficult].docx
Advanced Java[Extra Concepts, Not Difficult].docx
 
clinical examination of hip joint (1).pdf
clinical examination of hip joint (1).pdfclinical examination of hip joint (1).pdf
clinical examination of hip joint (1).pdf
 
ISO/IEC 27001, ISO/IEC 42001, and GDPR: Best Practices for Implementation and...
ISO/IEC 27001, ISO/IEC 42001, and GDPR: Best Practices for Implementation and...ISO/IEC 27001, ISO/IEC 42001, and GDPR: Best Practices for Implementation and...
ISO/IEC 27001, ISO/IEC 42001, and GDPR: Best Practices for Implementation and...
 
Digital Artefact 1 - Tiny Home Environmental Design
Digital Artefact 1 - Tiny Home Environmental DesignDigital Artefact 1 - Tiny Home Environmental Design
Digital Artefact 1 - Tiny Home Environmental Design
 
The History of Stoke Newington Street Names
The History of Stoke Newington Street NamesThe History of Stoke Newington Street Names
The History of Stoke Newington Street Names
 
Walmart Business+ and Spark Good for Nonprofits.pdf
Walmart Business+ and Spark Good for Nonprofits.pdfWalmart Business+ and Spark Good for Nonprofits.pdf
Walmart Business+ and Spark Good for Nonprofits.pdf
 
NEWSPAPERS - QUESTION 1 - REVISION POWERPOINT.pptx
NEWSPAPERS - QUESTION 1 - REVISION POWERPOINT.pptxNEWSPAPERS - QUESTION 1 - REVISION POWERPOINT.pptx
NEWSPAPERS - QUESTION 1 - REVISION POWERPOINT.pptx
 
Liberal Approach to the Study of Indian Politics.pdf
Liberal Approach to the Study of Indian Politics.pdfLiberal Approach to the Study of Indian Politics.pdf
Liberal Approach to the Study of Indian Politics.pdf
 
Traditional Musical Instruments of Arunachal Pradesh and Uttar Pradesh - RAYH...
Traditional Musical Instruments of Arunachal Pradesh and Uttar Pradesh - RAYH...Traditional Musical Instruments of Arunachal Pradesh and Uttar Pradesh - RAYH...
Traditional Musical Instruments of Arunachal Pradesh and Uttar Pradesh - RAYH...
 
Leveraging Generative AI to Drive Nonprofit Innovation
Leveraging Generative AI to Drive Nonprofit InnovationLeveraging Generative AI to Drive Nonprofit Innovation
Leveraging Generative AI to Drive Nonprofit Innovation
 
C1 Rubenstein AP HuG xxxxxxxxxxxxxx.pptx
C1 Rubenstein AP HuG xxxxxxxxxxxxxx.pptxC1 Rubenstein AP HuG xxxxxxxxxxxxxx.pptx
C1 Rubenstein AP HuG xxxxxxxxxxxxxx.pptx
 
How to Make a Field Mandatory in Odoo 17
How to Make a Field Mandatory in Odoo 17How to Make a Field Mandatory in Odoo 17
How to Make a Field Mandatory in Odoo 17
 
Présentationvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvv2.pptx
Présentationvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvv2.pptxPrésentationvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvv2.pptx
Présentationvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvvv2.pptx
 
How to Manage Your Lost Opportunities in Odoo 17 CRM
How to Manage Your Lost Opportunities in Odoo 17 CRMHow to Manage Your Lost Opportunities in Odoo 17 CRM
How to Manage Your Lost Opportunities in Odoo 17 CRM
 
PCOS corelations and management through Ayurveda.
PCOS corelations and management through Ayurveda.PCOS corelations and management through Ayurveda.
PCOS corelations and management through Ayurveda.
 
BÀI TẬP BỔ TRỢ TIẾNG ANH 8 CẢ NĂM - GLOBAL SUCCESS - NĂM HỌC 2023-2024 (CÓ FI...
BÀI TẬP BỔ TRỢ TIẾNG ANH 8 CẢ NĂM - GLOBAL SUCCESS - NĂM HỌC 2023-2024 (CÓ FI...BÀI TẬP BỔ TRỢ TIẾNG ANH 8 CẢ NĂM - GLOBAL SUCCESS - NĂM HỌC 2023-2024 (CÓ FI...
BÀI TẬP BỔ TRỢ TIẾNG ANH 8 CẢ NĂM - GLOBAL SUCCESS - NĂM HỌC 2023-2024 (CÓ FI...
 

A Field Guide To Heidegger Understanding The Question Concerning Technology

  • 1. Educational Philosophy and Theory,Vol. 37, No. 4, 2005 © 2005 Philosophy of Education Society of Australasia Published by Blackwell Publishing, 9600 Garsington Road, Oxford, OX4 2DQ, UK and 350 Main Street, Malden, MA 02148, USA Blackwell Publishing, Ltd. Oxford, UK EPAT Educational Philosophy and Theory 0013-1857 © 2005 Philosophy of Education Society of Australasia September 2005 37 4 Original Article A Field Guide to Heidegger David I. Waddington A Field Guide to Heidegger: Understanding ‘The Question Concerning Technology’ D I. W Stanford University Abstract This essay serves as a guide for scholars, especially those in education, who want to gain a better understanding of Heidegger’s essay,‘The Question ConcerningTechnology’.The paper has three sections: an interpretive summary, a critical commentary, and some remarks on Heidegger scholarship in education. Since Heidegger’s writing style is rather opaque, the interpretive summary serves as a map with which to navigate the essay.The critical commentary offers a careful analysis of some of the central concepts in the essay. These concepts, which include bringing-forth, challenging-forth, and gestell, are intriguing but problematic. The problems and possibilities of these ideas are analyzed, and an overall assessment of Heidegger’s ideas on technology is offered. In the final section, the work of several scholars in education is examined. Some of this work is excellent, but there is also a significant amount of confused and confusing scholarship. Keywords: Heidegger, technology, environment, craft, education It is a clear statement of the power of Heidegger’s thought that even among a group of people from a very different tradition [computer science] it has evoked stirrings—inklings of a new way of going about the business of technology. —Terry Winograd (Professor of Computer Science, Stanford University), Heidegger and the Design of Computer Systems, p. 108 Introduction Reading Heidegger is a lot like trying to navigate a ship through a dense fog. His language is sprinkled with German neologisms, and his lines of thought tend not to be laid out in a straightforward manner. However, despite these difficulties, philosophers of education have recently exhibited a heightened level of interest in Heidegger’s thought. They seem especially interested in a short piece by Heidegger entitled ‘The Question Concerning Technology’; in Michael Peters’ (2002) new
  • 2. 568 David I.Waddington © 2005 Philosophy of Education Society of Australasia collection, Heidegger, Education, and Modernity, eight of the eleven included essays refer to ‘The Question Concerning Technology’. Academics working in technology education have also expressed an interest in this particular essay. Heidegger pioneered a new way of thinking about technology; ‘The Question Concerning Technology’ contains exciting ideas that may have important implica- tions in both technology education and environmental education. However, just as one must set the table before sitting down to a meal, so too must one understand Heidegger before trying to draw educational implications from his thought. Thus, the primary role of this essay is to act as a field guide—to summarize, criticize and interpret ‘The Question Concerning Technology’. Some may think that is unnecessary to perform such a low-level task. Yet, there are several reasons why a field guide is important: 1. Providing access. Many academics and educators would be interested in Heidegger’s ideas, but lack the patience and time to decode Heidegger’s Byzantine formulations. The first and second sections of my paper (the interpretive summary and the critical commentary) will address this need for access. 2. Facilitating critical understanding. Although Heidegger’s ideas on technology have received plenty of accolades, they have (as yet) received very little criticism within the education literature. It is important to appreciate both the strengths and the weaknesses of Heidegger’s thought, and the second section of my paper (the critical commentary) will assist in this. 3. Clearing up confusion. Although some philosophers of education have written excellent articles about Heidegger’s philosophy of technology, other authors have made signi- ficant errors in their interpretations of Heidegger. The final section of the paper will be dedicated to the task of pointing out these errors. Part 1 An Interpretive Summary of ‘The Question Concerning Technology’ Most essays on technology focus primarily on practical issues surrounding the use of particular technologies. Heidegger’s essay, however, does not—instead, it focuses on the ways of thinking that lie behind technology. Heidegger (1977, p. 3) thinks that by coming to understand these ways of thinking, humans can enter into a ‘free relationship’ with technology. After dismissing the conventional account of technology, which supposedly states that technology is simply a means to an end, Heidegger commences a discussion on ancient craftsmanship. He suggests that the ancient craftsmanship involves the four Aristotelian causes: material, formal, final, and efficient. Intuitively, one might think that the efficient cause of a given craft-item (the craftsman) was the most significant of the four. However, although the craftsman has an important role in that she unites the four causes by considering each of them carefully, each of the four causes is equally co-responsible for the particular craft-item that is produced. Heidegger comments, ‘The four ways of being responsible bring something into appearance. They let it come forth into presencing’ (1977, p. 9). Appropriately enough, Heidegger names this process bringing-forth. Notably, bringing-forth is not merely a descriptive genus
  • 3. A Field Guide to Heidegger 569 © 2005 Philosophy of Education Society of Australasia under which the four causes are subsumed—rather, it is a unified process, ‘a single leading-forth to which [each of the causes] is indebted’ (Lovitt, 1972, p. 46). Heidegger writes that bringing-forth ‘comes to pass only insofar as something concealed comes into unconcealment’ (1977, p. 11). Thus, instead of the craft-item being created by the craftsman, as one would think, it was revealed or unconcealed. In ‘The Thing’, Heidegger comments on the making of a jug, The jug is not a vessel because it was made; rather, the jug had to be made because it is this holding vessel. The making … lets the jug come into its own. But that which in the jug’s nature is its own is never brought about by its making. (1971, p. 168) Clearly, revealing/unconcealing in the mode of bringing-forth contains strong hints of Platonism. Bringing-forth is the mode of revealing that corresponds to ancient craft. Modern technology, however, has its own particular mode of revealing, which Heidegger calls challenging-forth. Thinking in the mode of challenging-forth is very different from thinking in the mode of bringing-forth: when challenging-forth, one sets upon the elements of a situation both in the sense of ordering (i.e. setting a system upon) and in a more rapacious sense (i.e. the wolves set upon the traveler and devoured him). In bringing-forth, human beings were one important element among others in the productive process; in challenging-forth, humans control the productive process. Efficiency is an additional important element of thinking in the mode of challeng- ing forth; the earth, for example, is set upon to yield the maximum amount of ore with the minimum amount of effort. Essentially, challenging-forth changes the way we see the world—as Michael Zimmerman pointedly remarks, ‘To be capable of transforming a forest into packaging for cheeseburgers, man must see the forest not as a display of the miracle of life, but as raw material, pure and simple’ (1977, p. 79). Production in the mode of challenging-forth reveals objects that have the status of standing-reserve. Objects that have been made standing-reserve have been reduced to disposability in two different senses of the word: (1) They are disposable in the technical sense; they are easily ordered and arranged. Trees that once stood chaotically in the forest are now logs that can be easily counted, weighed, piled, and shipped. (2) They are also disposable in the conventional sense; like diapers and cheap razors, they are endlessly replaceable/interchangeable and have little value. For the most part, challenging things forth into standing-reserve is not a laudable activity, and thus it makes sense to wonder what drives human beings to think in this way. Heidegger’s answer to this motivational question is unconventional— instead of suggesting that the origins of this motivation are indigenous to human beings, he postulates the existence of a phenomenon that ‘sets upon man to order the real as standing-reserve’ (1977, p. 19). Heidegger calls this mysterious phenomenon enframing (Ge-stell in German). The word ‘Ge-stell’ gathers together several meanings of the -stellen family of German verbs: in Ge-stell, humans are ordered (bestellen), commanded (bestellen), and entrapped (nachstellen) (Harries 1994, p. 229). Heidegger thinks that our default state is that of being trapped by Ge-stell; this is what he means when he writes, ‘As the one who is challenged forth in this
  • 4. 570 David I.Waddington © 2005 Philosophy of Education Society of Australasia way, man stands within the essential realm of [Ge-stell]. He can never take up a relationship to it only subsequently’ (1977, p. 24; Sallis, 1971, p. 162). According to Heidegger (1977, p. 25), there are different ‘ordainings of destining’ for human beings. Although the default destining is that of Ge-stell, it is possible to choose an alternate road. Heidegger thinks that human beings have been granted the special role of ‘Shepherds of Being’—we have been granted the power to reveal the world in certain ways (Ballard, 1971, p. 60). Trapped in Ge-stell, we tend to reveal things in the mode of challenging-forth, but we can also choose to reveal things in the mode of bringing-forth. Heidegger comments, ‘Placed between these possibilities, man is endangered from out of destining’ (1977, p. 26). However, by carefully considering the ways of thinking that lie behind technology, we can grasp the ‘saving power’. We can realize that we, the Shepherds of Being, have a choice: we can bring-forth rather than challenge-forth. Thus, once we understand the thinking behind technology, we become free to choose our fate—‘… we are already sojourning in the open space of destining’ (Heidegger, 1977, p. 26). Part 2 Critical Commentary on ‘The Question Concerning Technology’ 2.0 Introduction The following critical commentary will be organized in four sections; the first three sections will analyze, in turn, the puzzles and weaknesses surrounding three pivotal ideas in Heidegger’s essay: bringing-forth, challenging-forth-to-standing-reserve, and Ge-stell. The final section of the analysis will synthesize the results of the first three analyses to create an overall evaluation of Heidegger’s account. 2.1 Bringing-forth If one were to draw conclusions about Plato and Aristotle solely from Heidegger’s remarks in ‘The Question Concerning Technology’, one would think that crafts- manship was a central issue for both of these ancient thinkers. Furthermore, from the warm light in which Heidegger bathes the craftsman, one might also come to believe that Plato and Aristotle have a certain reverence for craftsmen and the process of craftsmanship. Plato and Aristotle’s attitudes toward craftsmanship, however, can (at best) be described as ambivalent. In the Politics, Aristotle remarks, ‘… no man can practice excellence who is living the life of a mechanic or laborer’ (1995, 1278a20). Craftsmen and craftsmanship receive a more favorable treatment in Plato, but Plato still makes the following unfriendly remark: If an offspring of [the guardians] should be found to have a mixture of iron or bronze, they must not pity him in any way, but give him the rank appropriate to his nature and drive him out to join the craftsmen and farmers. (1997, 415bc) Indeed, lyrical prose having to do with craftsmanship is scarce in Plato and Aristotle, but abundant in Heidegger.
  • 5. A Field Guide to Heidegger 571 © 2005 Philosophy of Education Society of Australasia Heidegger also claims that his account of the four causes is true to the spirit of Greek thought. Heidegger’s notion of the co-responsibility of the four causes has some support in Aristotle, who comments: ‘… the [causes other than the efficient cause] are causes in the sense of the end or the good of the rest …’ (1995, 195a23) Heidegger’s insistence on the non-primacy of the efficient cause, however, finds less support: in Topics, Aristotle remarks, ‘Again, the primary source of the change or rest [is] … generally what makes of what is made …’ (1995, 194b30) Aristotle’s remarks on causation do not entirely rule out Heidegger’s somewhat romantic interpretation, but neither do they provide much supporting evidence. Heidegger’s strongest evidence in favor of bringing-forth consists of a quote from Symposium [what follows is Heidegger’s translation]: ‘Every occasion for whatever passes over and goes forward into presencing from that which is not presencing is poiesis, is bringing-forth’ (1977, p. 10). Nehamas and Woodruff, in their translation of the Symposium, offer a different rendition of the same passage: After all, everything that is responsible for creating something out of nothing is a kind of poetry, and so all the creations of every craft and profession are themselves a kind of poetry, and everyone who practices a craft is a poet. (1997, 205b) Although this translation is significantly different from Heidegger’s, its content (craftsmen as poets creating something out of nothing) and tone (romantic) offers some historical support for the notion of bringing-forth. Yet, this is not enough to authenticate the supposed historical status of bringing-forth. Although there is some evidence linking bringing-forth to Greek thinking, a far more likely conclusion is that the idea of bringing-forth had its primary origin in the mind of Martin Heidegger. A more serious problem with the notion of bringing-forth concerns the idea of revealing/unconcealment. Recall Heidegger’s comment in ‘The Thing’: The jug is not a vessel because it was made; rather, the jug had to be made because it is this holding vessel. The making … lets the jug come into its own. But that which in the jug’s nature is its own is never brought about by its making. (1971, p. 168) Clearly, there is some sort of Platonic pre-existence at work here—the jug, appar- ently, pre-exists as concealed and is revealed through the co-responsible action of the four causes. Perhaps one can see what Heidegger means here by recalling the ubiquitous stories of wood carvers who somehow know, in advance, what shape a particular piece of wood ‘wants to be’. However, no amount of idiosyncratic accounts on the part of folk artists can reduce the implausibility of the idea of pre- existence. The jug is a created object, and while it can be created through the loving and careful process of bringing-forth, the jug’s created status cannot be eclipsed. To sum up, the notion of bringing-forth is probably largely Heidegger’s arbitrary creation, and the idea of revealing pre-existent objects is highly implausible. Does this mean that these ideas should be thrown out? This essential question, which has important implications for Heidegger’s philosophy, will be addressed in a later section.
  • 6. 572 David I.Waddington © 2005 Philosophy of Education Society of Australasia 2.2 Challenging-forth and Standing-reserve Heidegger comments, ‘It is said that modern technology is something incomparably different from all earlier technologies …’ (1977, p. 14) Heidegger attributes this ‘incomparable difference’ to the ability of human beings to think in the mode of challenging forth—an ability which, he maintains, only emerged recently. Apparently, older technologies cannot involve or facilitate this sort of thinking: The revealing that rules in modern technology is a challenging, which puts to nature the unreasonable demand that it supply energy that can be extracted and stored as such. But does this not hold true for the old windmill as well? No. Its sails do indeed turn in the wind; they are left entirely to the wind’s blowing. But the windmill does not unlock energy from the air currents in order to store it. (Heidegger 1977, p. 14) However, if I were an ambitious and avaricious miller living in the middle ages, I might want to maximize flour production in my mill. To this end, I would make sure that my windmill had enormous sails in order to maximize wind-catching effi- ciency. By processing the grain, I would unlock its food energy in the form of flour and hold it in reserve in my granary. I could then maximize profit by selling the flour during the wintertime when the peasants were starving. The intuitive plausibility of the hypothetical miller suggests that Heidegger is wrong to think that challenging- forth is a phenomenon unique to modern times. However, despite the fact that thinking in the mode of challenging-forth is not limited solely to the reign of modern technology, there is certainly a link between modern technology and challenging-forth. The forester of old with his horses and chains could not even conceive of machines like the Caterpillar tree ‘harvester’, which can liquidate a forest at ‘the highest level of productivity and efficiency’ using ‘extremely high levels of horsepower’ (Caterpillar 2003). Since modern technology enables challenging-forth to achieve extraordinary results, thinking in the mode of challenging-forth is more dangerous and alluring now than at any other time in history. Tree ‘harvesters’ are a particularly unpleasant example of modern technology. Yet, critics of Heidegger are quick to point out that modern technology has improved our standard of living. Hydroelectric dams, for example, have allowed power to be brought to the homes of many people around the world, thus improving their lives immensely. Although there are some environmental problems associated with hydroelectric dams, it is a relatively clean form of energy generation. Heidegger, however, is outraged by the building of a hydroelectric dam on the Rhine: In the context of the interlocking processes pertaining to the orderly disposition of electrical energy, even the Rhine itself appears as something at our command. The hydroelectric plant is not built into the Rhine River, as was the old wooden bridge that joined bank with bank for hundreds of years. Rather the river is dammed up into the power plant. What the river is now, namely, a water power supplier, derives from out of the essence of the power station. In order that we may even remotely
  • 7. A Field Guide to Heidegger 573 © 2005 Philosophy of Education Society of Australasia consider the monstrousness that reigns here, let us ponder for a moment the contrast that speaks out of the two titles, ‘The Rhine’ as dammed up into the power works, and ‘The Rhine’ as uttered out of the art work, in Hölderlin’s hymn by that name. (1977, p. 16) Even the most rabid capitalists may become uneasy when forced to watch a tree ‘harvester’ in the process of liquidating a forest; intuitively, one can see that there is a certain monstrousness about this kind of wholesale destruction.Yet, although the same kind of destruction is not taking place in the context of the dam on the Rhine, Heidegger still asks us to ‘consider the monstrousness that reigns here’. (1977, p. 16) In order to solve this puzzle in Heidegger’s thinking, let us clarify the terms of the problem with some assumptions: assume that the dam has improved the standard of living for many Germans and that no significant environmental damage has resulted from its construction and operation. If these assumptions are made, how can Heidegger still deem the dam monstrous? In his polemic against the dam, Heidegger comments, ‘What the river is now, namely a water power supplier, derives from out of the essence of the power station’ (1977, p. 16). Heidegger does not hate the dam because it physically damages the river; instead, he hates it because it reduces the river. Subsumed under both the idea and the material fact of the hydroelectric dam, the river no longer stands on its own. Implicitly, Heidegger is using the following syllogism: Premise: The building of the Rhine dam has compromised the standing-on-its-own of the Rhine River. Premise: All actions in which we compromise the standing-on-its-own of something are monstrous actions. Conclusion: The building of the Rhine dam is a monstrous action. It is still unclear, however, what it means for something to stand on its own. Aristotle may enlighten us in this regard with his description of what it is for a human being not to stand on their own: ‘Hence we see what is the nature and office of a slave; he who is … not his own but another’s man, is by nature a slave …’ (1995, 1254a13) The person whose nature is subsumed under that of another has been reduced—reduced to slavery. No standing or dignity remain for the slave; ‘he’ or ‘she’ has been reduced to an ‘it’. The slave, regarded as slave, is a mere piece of property that is disposable in both the technical and conventional senses of disposability described in the summary. Laboring under the material and conceptual mastery of the dam, the river has also been reduced to slavery. It no longer stands on its own; it is merely a piece of property to be manipulated by the various gigantic states and corporations of the world. The Rhine and the Columbia, the Nile and the Yangtze—they were once the greatest and most holy of rivers, but are now merely the most useful of our slave-objects. Most of the countries of the world have signed agreements that grant that human beings possess a certain inviolable dignity; humans cannot be reduced to slavery and they must be treated with a measure of respect. Human beings, however, are
  • 8. 574 David I.Waddington © 2005 Philosophy of Education Society of Australasia not the only entities in the world that seem to possess dignity. For example, a Sequoia in the forest stands on its own, and, as such, it seems to have some kind of dignity. Once that tree has been cut down and reduced to a technically and conventionally disposable log, whatever dignity it may once have had is lost. Suppose it is true that all human beings possess a kind of inviolable dignity. Animals differ from human beings only in the fact that they are not rational. Does their lack of reason make animals unworthy of dignity? Surely not: when humans lose their minds to Alzheimer’s disease, we all agree that their dignity remains inviolable. We would not even consider consigning a witless Alzheimer’s patient to a cage in a research laboratory. One can expand the scope of this argument from animals to other living and non-living entities. In each case one can ask, ‘Does their lack of property Z make entity X less worthy of dignity than entity Y?’ Admittedly, as one traces the course of this argument through the hierarchy of being—from animals all the way down to manufactured objects—dignity becomes increasingly attenuated. Yet, I would argue that dignity persists all the way down the hierarchy of being; even the plastic soft-drink bottle possesses an extremely small amount of dignity. Heidegger would probably concur with this view; he was fascinated by the work of Cezanne, who thought that even inanimate objects had dignity: People think that a sugar bowl has no physiognomy, no soul. But that also changes from day to day. One has to know how to take them, flatter them, these gentlemen. These glasses, these plates, they speak to each other, they are always exchanging confidences. ( Jamme, 1994, p. 140) In his essay, ‘The Thing’, Heidegger expresses views that are similar to those of Cezanne. (1971, p. 182) At one point, while discussing the reduction of objects to standing-reserve, Heidegger remarks, ‘Whatever stands by in the sense of standing-reserve no longer stands over against us as object’ (1977, p. 17). The notion of the dignity and standing of objects can help us understand Heidegger’s cryptic remark. Objects like the river lose their dignity by being subsumed under the material and conceptual command of objects like the dam, which, for their part, are under the complete control of human subjects. Therefore, in a sense, whatever is reduced to standing- reserve is no longer an object because it has been completely subsumed under the material and conceptual reign of the subject. A kind of objectlessness results—the only significance these objects have is that they are the property of the subject. In light of this view, another of Heidegger’s puzzling remarks begins to make sense: Meanwhile man … exalts himself to the posture of lord of the earth. In this way the impression comes to prevail that everything man encounters exists only insofar as it is his construct. This illusion gives rise in turn to one final delusion: It seems as though man everywhere and always encounters only himself [italics mine]. (1977, p. 27) Heidegger feels that we should not underestimate the importance of the dignity of objects; once the objectlessness of standing-reserve prevails, the next target for
  • 9. A Field Guide to Heidegger 575 © 2005 Philosophy of Education Society of Australasia reduction to material/conceptual slavery is other subjects—human beings. Already, says Heidegger (1977, p. 18), we can discern the beginnings of this trend in the talk of ‘human resources’. As Michael Zimmerman ominously remarks, ‘While humanity cannot yet manufacture itself in factories, it is moving in that direction’ (1990, p. 201). 2.3 Ge-stell The phenomenon of Ge-stell is problematic for three reasons: 1. The non-human origin of the phenomenon of Ge-stell seems to entail serious difficulties. 2. It is a significant challenge to understand what Heidegger means by Ge-stell. 3. One is puzzled as to why Heidegger introduces this phenomenon at all; it is not clear how postulating the phenomenon of Ge-stell adds to the ideas that have already been adumbrated in the essay. In coming to a proper understanding of the phenomenon of Ge-stell, all of these problems must be addressed. In order to deal with the first two problems, one must understand the relationship between Ge-stell and Heidegger’s notion of Being. Instead of accepting a conven- tional conception of Being as sort of inert underlying substance, Heidegger thinks of Being as energeia (Pöggeler, 1996, p. 208). Edward Ballard comments on this conception: ‘We do not come to thinking; rather it comes to us’ (1971, p. 61). Thus, in a sense, Being has a mind of its own—in different epochs, Being reveals itself to man in different ways. In ‘The Word of Nietzsche’, Heidegger remarks, ‘In every phase of metaphysics there has been visible at any particular time a portion of a way that the destining of Being prepares as a path for itself …’ (1977, p. 54) Essentially, Ge-stell is the dominant way in which Being is revealing itself to human beings right now. An example may bring to light some of the difficulties surrounding this conception: once, on a Grade 5 class trip, a classmate of mine who could not swim fell into the pool. After he was fished out, he explained that the Devil had pulled him into the pool. Naturally, most of the class did not find this to be an adequate explana- tion. The point of the story is as follows: if the Devil no longer suffices to explain bad events to schoolchildren, how can the more mature readers of Heidegger (1977, p. 24) possibly accept that Ge-stell happens ‘neither exclusively in man, nor decisively through man’, but rather because of the inscrutable and mysterious powers of Being? Heidegger cannot be decisively extricated from this difficulty. However, puzzle- ment on the part of readers over Heidegger’s strange position can be palliated through an explanation of the nature of Ge-stell. In order to understand Ge-stell, we must turn to a similar phenomenon that Heidegger outlines in Being and Time: the they. Heidegger comments: In utilizing public transportation, in the use of information services such as the newspaper, every other is like the next … In this inconspicuousness
  • 10. 576 David I.Waddington © 2005 Philosophy of Education Society of Australasia and unascertainability, the they unfolds its true dictatorship. We enjoy ourselves and have fun the way they enjoy themselves. We read, see, and judge literature the way they see and judge. (1996, p. 119) In non-Heideggerian parlance, the they is the consciousness (Heidegger thinks it is a false consciousness) of society. Simply by virtue of being in society, human beings are always already lost in the they; we always already see things through their eyes. Ge-stell is, essentially, an element (perhaps even the dominant element) of the contemporary they. The dominant consciousness of society always already ensnares us into thinking in the mode of challenging-forth; it is as if we have had special challenging-forth contact lenses permanently implanted in our eyes since birth. Heidegger remarks, ‘It is not the case that a Da-sein, untouched and unseduced by this way of inter- preting, was ever confronted by the free land of a ‘world’ merely to look at what it encounters’ (1996, p. 159). No one is to blame for the they; it is simply an inevitable element of the structure of human existence. By understanding this inevitability and this blamelessness, we can see why it might be said that the they and Ge-stell are both, in a sense, of non- human origin. Neither the they nor Ge-stell are a plot by the government or the ruling classes; the they and Ge-stell are simply part of the way Things are going— the way Being is going. The third problem that was posed at the beginning of this section—the question of how Ge-stell adds to the ideas that have already been introduced in Heidegger’s essay—must be answered very speculatively. When Heidegger postulates a non- human origin for Ge-stell, he extricates human beings from blame. The logging contractor cannot be blamed for using the Caterpillar tree ‘harvester’ to destroy the forest. Thus, rather than responding to the logging contractor with hatred and blame, those people who had extricated themselves from the destining of Ge-stell would realize that the only fruitful path is to educate the logging contractor. Per- haps, for example, one could gently pry the challenging-forth contact lenses away from the contractor’s eyes through a peaceful debate about the relative merits of bringing-forth and challenging-forth. At this point, the three problems I posed concerning Ge-stell have all been briefly addressed. This treatment, however, has not extricated the concept of Ge-stell from its difficulties—if anything, I have uncovered a cornucopia of potential new problems. Due to its many inadequacies, the question must be raised whether the notion of Ge-stell should be thrown out. As in the case of bringing-forth, this crucial question will have to be deferred for the time being. 2.4 The Overall Impact of ‘The Question Concerning Technology’ Most current articles on the value of technology are preoccupied with pieces of technology. These articles are valuable; it is important both to observe how particular technologies function in the world and to point out possible new directions for these technologies. However, a significant dimension of technology goes unnoticed
  • 11. A Field Guide to Heidegger 577 © 2005 Philosophy of Education Society of Australasia by most commentators: the way of thinking that lies behind the creation and use of technology. If more commentators on technology were able to wade through ‘The Question Concerning Technology’, as well as some of Heidegger’s other writings, they might discover some exciting new pathways for their thinking. Heidegger’s account also has noteworthy implications for environmental ethics. If all living things and inanimate objects have a measure of dignity, the various entities that make up the world must be accorded more respect. If human beings are gradually destroying the world (both in the conventional sense and in the Heideggerian sense of reduction to standing-reserve) through their entrapment in challenging-forth, systematic efforts must be made to free individuals from their ideological prison. Redesigning certain aspects of the education system might serve to further this goal. The great breakthrough of ‘The Question Concerning Technology’ is that it shifts the focus away from specific technologies and toward the modes of thinking that lie behind these technologies. However, within this breakthrough lies a danger: it is possible to focus on the thinking behind the technology to such an extent that meaningful distinctions in the world are obscured. In a remark that was originally a part of ‘The Question Concerning Technology’, but was later excised (Harries, 1994, p. 233), this danger manifests itself: Agriculture is now a motorized food industry—in essence the same as the manufacture of corpses in the gas chambers and extermination campus, the same as the blockading and starvation of nations, the same as the manufacture of hydrogen bombs. (Ferry & Renaut, 1990, p. 71) (Schirmacher, 1983, p. 25) In this remark, Heidegger is trying to point out that challenging-forth into standing- reserve is at work in both modern agriculture and the concentration camps. Clearly, however, to say that modern agriculture and the death camps are ‘in essence the same’ obviates meaningful empirical distinctions and trivializes the significance of the extermination camps. Rorty notes, ‘Heidegger needed to see everything in our century other than its technologism as mere transitory appearance’ (1994, p. 36). Another significant failing of Heidegger’s philosophy of technology is that the benefits of technology are not acknowledged. The hydroelectric dam across the Rhine does improve people’s lives, and, as Rorty (1977, p. 302) points out, the spread of modern technology across the planet has prevented many people from dying of starvation. Yet, despite the fact that Heidegger never acknowledges the benefits of technology, he does not urge giving it up: We can say ‘yes’ to the unavoidable use of technological objects, and we can at the same time say ‘no,’ insofar as we do not permit them to claim us exclusively and thus to warp, confuse, and finally lay waste to our essence. (1966, p. 54) This smacks of having one’s cake and eating it too. Under Heidegger’s conception, we conveniently say ‘yes’ to the modern technologies that make our lives so comfortable, while somehow apparently saying ‘no’ to them as well.
  • 12. 578 David I.Waddington © 2005 Philosophy of Education Society of Australasia The greatest difficulties with ‘The Question Concerning Technology’, however, are technical rather than ideological. Imagine, for example, what a careful, but not particularly sympathetic, analyst might say about each of Heidegger’s three key notions: Bringing-forth—this is an arbitrary, nostalgic notion that involves an impossibility (revealing from pre-existence) and has no grounding in historical fact. Challenging-forth to standing-reserve—this is another arbitrary construction, which demonizes technology wholesale and indulges in groundless speculation by asserting that objects (even inanimate objects!) have some kind of mysterious dignity. Ge-stell—this is the most preposterous idea of the three. In addition to being nearly incomprehensible, it entails the ridiculous notion that inscrutable historical determinations of Being are somehow responsible for human actions. Furthermore, if one accepts the speculative connection between the they and Ge-stell, it appears that human beings are trapped in a mindset of destruction—a mindset that, para- doxically, absolves the perpetrators of any responsibility for the destruction! In addition to the internal problems of the three notions, none of the three key ideas is established through any systematic form of argument. For the most part, Heidegger simply makes ex-cathedra pronouncements about these three ideas; he might as well be saying, ‘Behold bringing-forth,’ and ‘Let there be the phenomenon of Ge-stell’. Clearly, we must face the recurrent question of whether Heidegger’s ideas should be discarded. Most people would lean strongly in the direction of discarding the ideas; our common-sense practice in situations like these is to discard ideas that do not adequately correspond to the world. Heidegger’s theory of technology contains so many implausible notions that it is very difficult to defend it on a correspondence basis. Philosophers of a more post-modern bent might be inclined to defend Heidegger using the criterion of coherence. Since even the most insane religious fanatics can postulate a coherent system, this criterion is highly suspect. However, even if one makes the questionable decision to accept the criterion of coherence, Heidegger’s theory is not necessarily saved. Although I have interpreted ‘The Question Concerning Technology’ in such a way as to present Heidegger’s theory as coherent, Heidegger’s wandering formulations make other, less coherent, interpretations possible. The best criterion with which to defend Heidegger is neither correspondence nor coherence, but usefulness. If people decided to think in the mode of bringing-forth, and decided not to think in the mode of challenging-forth, much more beauty and happiness might be brought into the world. If more people chose to think that living things and inanimate objects had a certain dignity, the destruction of the earth might begin to draw to a close. And, if people thought that the phenomenon of Ge-stell was a possibility, they might be motivated to examine their own view of the world with a critical eye. Rorty writes of Heidegger, I see the toolbox we have inherited from [Heidegger] as containing a very varied assortment, constructed for various different purposes—an assortment in which only some items are still useful. (Rorty, 1994, p. 35)
  • 13. A Field Guide to Heidegger 579 © 2005 Philosophy of Education Society of Australasia ‘The Question Concerning Technology’ is a toolbox containing three key tools: bringing-forth, challenging-forth to standing-reserve, and Ge-stell. All of these tools are useful: indeed, used properly, they might serve to repair the damaged relationship between human beings and the world. In Republic, Plato writes, ‘… if it is appropriate for anyone to use falsehoods for the good of the city … it is the rulers’ (1997, 398b) Some might allege that the preceding defense of Heidegger, on the grounds of usefulness, contains harbingers of indoctrination—hints of the Platonic philosophical elite who tell the noble, educational lie to the masses. Perhaps, however, it is time for philosophers to stop apologizing for advocating the noble lie; a great many lies are already told to the people by elites, and most of these lies are ignoble. Part 3 Heidegger Scholarship in Education When one reads a piece of secondary literature, one hopes to find clear writing and accurate scholarship. Unfortunately, some of the articles on Heidegger by scholars in education fall short in one or both of these areas. By pointing out the shortcom- ings of these articles, I hope to offer a justification for the preceding summary and critique. I also aim to provide a helpful guide for those interested in further research in this area. Richard Walton’s, ‘Heidegger in the Hands-on Science and Technology Center’, is an example of an article with significant defects. Consider, for example, the following excerpt: This means that, in Heidegger’s terms, ‘technology’ is more than the artifacts and activities that form the ontic. It can be spoken of in terms of the mode of truth that is the framework of possibilities which forms the essential nature of technology which is to be revealed and which gives technology its ontological sense. Superficially, this ontology of technology seems to bear some similarity with the platonic notion of the ideal form yet, as Guignon (1993, p. 4) pointed out, a significant distinction can be drawn between Heidegger’s ‘substance ontology’ and the traditional notion of the ‘metaphysics of presence’. (Walton, 2000, p. 54) In these three sentences, we see the words/phrases ‘ontic’ ‘ontological’ (to give Walton credit, he defines ‘ontic’ and ‘ontological’ earlier on), ‘mode of truth’, ‘platonic notion of the ideal form’, ‘substance ontology’, and ‘metaphysics of presence’, and Walton is only on the second paragraph of his discussion of Heidegger! Walton’s article was published in the Journal of Technology Education, which, presumably, has an audience composed mostly of academics working in technology education. One suspects that these academics might be puzzled by discussions of ‘substance ontology’ and the ‘metaphysics of presence’. Walton’s analyses are often somewhat confused—for example, consider Walton’s account of an exhibit at a science center: The exhibits found within such centers represent a special case or category of technological artifact which is designed and built with the
  • 14. 580 David I.Waddington © 2005 Philosophy of Education Society of Australasia specific aim of encouraging reflection upon its own essence. Of course, in most cases this is only true to a limited extent. An exhibit which demonstrates chaotic motion reveals only a limited set of ideas relating to the nature of the world and in so doing it shows only one way in which technology can be used to frame this idea. But it does show that the idea can be framed. Heidegger uses the term gestell to describe this act of framing, or what he called ‘enframing’. (2000, p. 54) I don’t think that Ge-stell, which is a sort of meta-phenomenon beyond human control, appropriately describes what is happening when a person constructs an exhibit about chaotic motion. Challenging-forth might be an appropriate descrip- tion, but it is not clear that challenging-forth is necessarily at work during the construction of an exhibit like this. This sort of confusion is representative of most of Walton’s essay, which fails to give an adequate account of Heidegger. Heidegger scholarship is significantly better within the philosophy of education community. However, some analyses of Heidegger by members of the philosophy of education community contain occasional flaws. For example, consider the fol- lowing paragraph—an excerpt from James Marshall’s essay, ‘Electronic Writing and the Wrapping of Language’: To have a free relationship with technology we cannot come to it with any presuppositions—for example, that it is neutral. … This involves an initial response to technology, before any decision is made as to what it is and, then, how we are to respond to it. For to respond to it we must have grasped certain things about ourselves, about human being, so that we can ‘open’ ourselves to the essences of both human being and of technology. This must be simultaneous and mutual opening up or recognition, and not a temporal response, for human being and technology are in mutual interrelationship. This is difficult to understand, given traditional philosophical, logicist, positivist and Anglo-Saxon understandings of language and logic and a traditional overt antipathy to metaphysics. (Marshall, 2000, p. 144) There are two significant problems with this paragraph. First, in a Heideggerian context, it doesn’t make sense to talk about approaching technology ‘without pre- suppositions’ or ‘before any decision is made as to what it is’. The problem is not one of how to make the decision about technology; Heidegger would say that the decision has always already been made. We are already stuck in a particular under- standing of technology; the challenge is to become aware of that understanding and to extricate ourselves from it somehow. Second, it is not clear to me how a ‘mutual opening up’ is possible. Although it is possible to understand Ge-stell as having some kind of agency, I fail to see how the essence of technology can really ‘open itself up’. Further to this point, Marshall says that this ‘mutual opening up’ is ‘not a temporal response’. What would it mean for a response to be ‘non-temporal’? I do not consider myself a positivist or a person with an ‘overt antipathy to metaphysics’— in fact, I am deeply sympathetic to much of Heidegger’s account. Yet, I still find it ‘difficult to understand’ what Marshall is saying in this particular paragraph.
  • 15. A Field Guide to Heidegger 581 © 2005 Philosophy of Education Society of Australasia Ilan Gur-Ze’ev’s article ‘Martin Heidegger, Transcendence, and the Possibility of Counter-Education’ also raises some questions. For example, in a discussion about how things are leveled down to standing-reserve, Gur-Ze’ev makes the following remark: Within this process, modern science and technology transform man himself into a standing-reserve. Enframing and unconcealment as roads to realizing human freedom are blocked in a manner that does not enable the human to acknowledge and challenge it. (Gur-Ze’ev, 2002, p. 74) There are several problems with this remark. First, Gur-Ze’ev introduces the word ‘enframing’ without any comment. Thus, any readers of Gur-Ze’ev, who have not already read Heidegger, will be confused by this use of the word. Gur-Ze’ev com- pounds this problem by misunderstanding enframing: obviously, enframing (Ge-stell) is not a road to human freedom. Furthermore, since challenging-forth also involves a kind of unconcealment, unconcealment is also not necessarily a ‘road to realizing human freedom’. Some of Gur-Ze’ev’s other remarks suffer from similar difficulties: In modern Ge-stell, in the human’s being framed in modernity as advanced by modern science and technology, human situateness ensures the oblivion of the mission of the human, of life as something more than mere life. But for Heidegger, framing has deeper roots and is not to be reduced to a specific historical situation. It springs from the very fact of situateness of human life, of always living enframed. (Gur-Ze’ev, 2002, p. 75) Again, Gur-Ze’ev fails to explain either ‘Ge-stell’, ‘framing’, or ‘enframing’ to the reader. And what exactly does it mean that ‘framing’ has ‘deeper roots’ and is ‘not to be reduced to a specific historical situation’? Gur-Ze’ev might be making an important point about Being here, but he does not explain this to the reader. Furthermore, it is difficult to understand what Gur-Ze’ev means when he says that enframing ‘springs from the very fact of situateness of human life’. In sum, although Gur-Ze’ev appears to be quite knowledgeable about Heidegger, he does not always explain Heidegger very well. Indeed, articles like Gur-Ze’ev’s highlight the need for a clear, concise analysis of Heidegger’s philosophy of technology. There is no denying, however, that there are many excellent essays written on Heidegger by philosophers of education. Paul Standish, Bert Lambeir, and Michael Bonnett have all written insightful articles that I recommend highly. In particular, Bonnett’s article, ‘Education in a Destitute Time’, is a masterpiece. However, despite the competence of these authors, there is something missing from all of their articles: rigorous, systematic criticism of Heidegger. To give credit where it is due, Standish, in ‘Only Connect’, devotes a paragraph to criticizing Heidegger’s nostalgia (1999, p. 424). In a similar spirit, Bonnett makes the following remark: Clearly, Heidegger here presents us with a critique of the traditional Western metaphysical conception of thinking of a most radical kind, and this itself stands in need of further exploration and critical evaluation. (Bonnett, 1983, p. 26)
  • 16. 582 David I.Waddington © 2005 Philosophy of Education Society of Australasia Unfortunately, Bonnett, Lambeir, and Standish have not presented us with ‘further exploration’ and ‘critical evaluation’ of this kind. They are in no way blameworthy for this; they simply chose to focus on examining the educational implications of Heidegger’s philosophy rather than examining its faults. I have chosen the opposite path: I have not commented very much about the educational implications of Heidegger’s philosophy, choosing instead to focus on solving puzzles in his philosophy and pointing out its shortcomings. However, as Bonnett’s comment points out, this is a task that needs to be done. Hopefully, this field guide will also serve as a tool with which scholars in education, who may have been scared off by Heidegger’s difficult prose, can now pry open the treasure box of interesting ideas that is ‘The Question Concerning Technology’. Indeed, in the introduction, I suggested that this field guide would ‘set the table’ for further scholarship on Heidegger within the philosophy of education. Now that I have ‘set the table’, readers of this field guide should make ready ‘the meal’ by conducting further investigations of the educational implications of Heidegger’s philosophy of technology. References Aristotle (1995) The Complete Works of Aristotle, J. Barnes (ed.) (Princeton, Princeton University Press). Ballard, E. (1971) Heidegger’s View and Evaluation of Nature and Natural Science, in: J. Sallis (ed.), Heidegger and the Path of Thinking (Pittsburgh, Duquesne University Press), pp. 37– 64. Bonnett, M. (1983), Education in a Destitute Time, Journal of Philosophy of Education, 17:1, pp. 21–33. Caterpillar Equipment (28 April 2003), Harvesters, http://cmms.cat.com/cmms/servlet/cat.dcs. cmms.servlet.GetModelSummary?classid=406&langid=en&rgnid=NACD&view=html& prdname=580&prdid=580&familyid=463&subfamilyid=331&dsfFlag=0&subfamilyheader= Harvesters Ferry, L. & Renaut, A. (1990), Heidegger and Modernity, F. Philip (trans.) (Chicago, University of Chicago Press). Guignon, C. B. (1993) Introduction, in: C. B. Guignon (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Heidegger (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press), pp. 1–42. Gur-Ze’ev, I. (2002) Heidegger, Transcendence, and the Possibility of Counter-Education, in: M. Peters (ed.), Heidegger, Education, and Modernity (Lanham, Rowman and Littlefield), pp. 65–80. Harries, K. (1994) Philosophy, Politics, Technology, in: K. Harries & C. Jamme (eds), Martin Heidegger: Politics, Art, and Technology (New York, Holmes and Meier), pp. 225–245. Heidegger, M. (1996) Being and Time, trans. J. Stambaugh (Albany, SUNY Press). Heidegger, M. (1966) Discourse on Thinking, J. M. Anderson and E. H. Freund (trans.) (New York, Harper and Row). Heidegger, M. (1977) The Question Concerning Technology, in: The Question Concerning Technology and Other Essays, W. Lovitt (trans.) (New York, Harper and Row), pp. 3– 35. Heidegger, M. (1971) The Thing, in: Poetry, Language, Thought, A. Hofstadter (trans.) (New York, Harper and Row), pp. 165–182. Heidegger, M. (1977) The Word of Nietzsche, in: The Question Concerning Technology and Other Essays, W. Lovitt (trans.) (New York, Harper and Row), pp. 53–112.
  • 17. A Field Guide to Heidegger 583 © 2005 Philosophy of Education Society of Australasia Jamme, C. (1994) The Loss of Things: Cezanne, Rilke, Heidegger, in: K. Harries & C. Jamme (eds), Martin Heidegger: Politics, Art, and Technology (New York, Holmes and Meier), pp. 139–153. Lambeir, B. (2002) Comfortably Numb in the Digital Era: Man’s being as standing-reserve or dwelling silently, in: M. Peters (ed.), Heidegger, Education, and Modernity (Lanham, Rowman and Littlefield), pp. 103–122. Lovitt, W. (1972) A Gesprach with Heidegger on Technology, Man and World, 6:1, pp. 44–62. Marshall, J. (2000), Electronic Writing and the Wrapping of Language, Journal of Philosophy of Education, 34:1, pp. 135–150. Plato (1997) Complete Works, J. Cooper (ed.) (Indianapolis, Hackett). Pöggeler, O. (1996) Does the Saving Power also grow? Heidegger’s last paths, in: C. McCann (ed.), Critical Heidegger (London, Routledge), pp. 206–226. Rorty, R. (1994) Another Possible World, in: K. Harries & C. Jamme (eds) Martin Heidegger: Politics, Art, and Technology (New York: Holmes and Meier), pp. 34–40. Rorty, R. (1977), Overcoming the Tradition: Heidegger and Dewey, Review of Metaphysics, 30:2, pp. 280–305. Sallis, J. (1971) Toward the Movement of Reversal: Science, technology, and the language of homecoming, in: J. Sallis (ed.), Heidegger and the Path of Thinking (Pittsburgh, Duquesne University Press), pp. 138–168. Schirmacher, W. (1983) Technik und Gelassenheit (Freiburg, Alber). Standish, P. (1999), Only Connect: Computer literacy from Heidegger to cyberfeminism, Educational Theory, 49:4, pp. 417–435. Walton, R. (2000), Heidegger in the Hands-On Science and Technology Center: Philosophical reflections on learning in informal settings, Journal of Technology Education, 12:1, pp. 49– 60. Winograd, T. (1995) Heidegger and the Design of Computer Systems, in: A. Feenberg & A. Hanney (eds), Technology and the Politics of Knowledge (Bloomington, Indiana University Press), pp. 108–127. Zimmerman, M. (1977) Beyond Humanism: Heidegger’s understanding of technology, Listening, 12:3, pp. 74–83. Zimmerman, M. (1990), Heidegger’s Confrontation with Modernity: Technology, politics, and art (Bloomington, Indiana University Press).