SlideShare a Scribd company logo
1 of 15
Download to read offline
Entry ā€œArt Criticismā€ from the Grove (Oxford) Dictionary of Art
James Elkins
This material was originally posted on www.jameselkins.com.
Please write jameselkins@fastmail.cn with comments, or for an up-to-date version.
Art criticism can be provisionally deļ¬ned as writing that evaluates art. Yet
it has no formal deļ¬nition or agreedā€“upon meaning. The sense of the
concept is compromised by two fundamentally antithetical usages: on the
one hand, art criticism is understood as an historical practice, embracing
writers from Pliny or Vasari to the present; and on the other, it is taken to be
a way of writing that is potentially independent of historical conditions.
There is no reliable history or philosophy of art criticism, and virtually no
literature on its concept or nature. Some philosophers deny art criticism
exists as such, and others say it subsumes art historyā€”so that this entire
Dictionary would be an example of critical writing. Given that disparity, it is
best not to presuppose art criticism has a consensual meaning, but to take the
alternate deļ¬nitions seriously. This entry is divided into two sections:
1. Art criticism as a kind of writing
2. Art criticism as an historical practice
1. When art criticism has been treated as a kind of writing, it has
normally been considered as evaluative or judgmental rather than
descriptive. The traditions of judicative and philodoxic (ostensibly neutral,
ā€œknowledgeā€“lovingā€) discourse begin in ancient Greek texts, and are still
both distinct and mingled today (Trimpi, 1983). But this distinction between
art criticism and art history has been criticized on at least three grounds.
(a) Philosophically, each deļ¬nition of art criticism that opposes it to
the ostensibly more neutral, descriptive work of art history represses both
the inherent and continuous judgments in all historical writing, and the
philosophic arguments that description and evaluation are inevitably mixed
in all writing. Much of art history depends on such a refusal, and maintains
its philodoxic purpose in part by excluding art criticism and deļ¬ning it as
judicative (Preziosi, 1989). The complementary exclusion can be observed
in art criticism. Lionello Venturiā€™s History of Art Criticism calls the
distinction between art history and criticism a ā€œgrave error,ā€ and adds ā€œif a
fact referred to is not considered as a function of judgment, it is perfectly
uselessā€; but such observations could not be consistently carried through
without making the project of a history of art criticism incoherent (Gilbert,
1962; Venturi, 1964, 20). Similarly Luigi Grassi and Mario Pepeā€™s
Dizionario della critica dā€™arte contains a brief entry on art criticism noting
it is inseparable from historical writing (Grassi and Pepe, 1978, 135).
(b) Art criticism has also been distinguished from art history by noting
that criticism has a different rhetorical purpose, since it is intended to
persuade rather than inform. But this does not provide a stable deļ¬nition
since no art historical text leaves its reader unaffected by its implicit
judgments regarding value and signiļ¬cance (Fried, 1990). Some of the most
eloquent art historians, such as Roberto Longhi, create persuasive
2
revaluations of past art at least as much as they produce authoritative
compilations of facts. Although Heinrich Wƶlfļ¬‚in insists ā€œthere is no
questionā€ of judgment in his work, his descriptions are persuasive precisly
because they are such strong judgments (Wƶlfļ¬‚in, 1914, 1).
(c) The historiography of art history provides evidence that many of
the practices that gave rise to art history were conceived as critical
enterprises. Vasari is frequently cited as an example of mixed critical and
factual narrative (Alpers, 1960), and there is also the seventeenthā€“century
practice of ars critica, which laid the foundations for the higher biblical
criticism and furnished ā€œthe example for classical, and later modern,
philologyā€ (Borkowski, 1936; McKeon, 1944, 163) that in turn proved so
fruitful for the developing discipline of art history (Podro, 1982). For these
reasons it is philosophically, rhetorically, and historiographically untenable
to maintain the distinction between art history and art criticism on the
grounds that one evaluates and the other describes.
The problem is symmetrical: like most art history, some art criticism
is conceived as nonjudgmental and philodoxic. In particular criticism can be
understood as imaginative reā€“enactment of creation or perception, with no
determinate relation to evaluation. Ekphrasis can function this way, and has
from Pliny, Callistratus and Philostratus through Vasari (Bertrand, 1893;
Alpers, 1960; Mitchell, 1994, 151ā€“81). In turnā€“ofā€“theā€“century German
aesthetics, the doctrine of empathy provided a foundation for writing that
critically reimagined the bodily experience of artwork (Lipps and Vischer,
1994). In the United States, John Dewey proposed that criticism should not
appraise or judge but that ā€œwe lay hold of the full import of a work of art
only as we go through in our own vital processes the processes the artist
went through in producing the workā€ (Dewey, 1934, 325), and Benedetto
3
Croceā€™s slightly earlier concept of imaginative understanding is similar
(Croce, 1910, 42). Venturiā€™s History of Art Criticism can be read as a
secondā€“order work of this kind, since he aims in part to relive older critical
experiences without judging them (Gilbert, 1962, 59; Venturi, 1964, 8ā€“9).
When art criticism is imagined as an evaluative activity, it can be
conceived either as personal response without explicit purpose or thesis, or
else as measured judgment governed by premeditated principles. The two
provide divergent genealogies for the juridical aspect of art criticism. In
general the second strategy derives from Enlightenment philosophy and
results in texts that aim to present an ostensibly true, universal, or reliable
assessment of the value of an artwork, and the ļ¬rst comes from romantic
poetry, confession, and reverie, and yields texts that can be read as the
potentially idiosyncratic exercise of individual sensibility.
(a) As a deļ¬ning trait of the more personal sense of art criticism,
writers have pointed to the intimacy of writing about art, and they have
emphasized its dependence on the idea of sensibility or taste (Grassi, 1970,
47). Thus Charles Baudelaire called for criticism that would be ā€œpartial,
passionate, and politicalā€ (Baudelaire, 1923, 87), and Friedrich Nietzsche
practiced a personal and psychological criticism of philosophy and art
(Nietzsche, 1989). Ultimately these tendencies could be traced to Platoā€™s
dialectic criticism, where dialogue and opinions constitute the medium in
which critical judgments emerge, as opposed to Aristotleā€™s ā€œscientiļ¬cā€
criticism, which is based on expository description and the rational
unfolding of knowledge (McKeon, 1944, 162); but contemporary art
criticism that depends on sensibility, personal reļ¬‚ection and taste is more
often understood as a fundamentally romantic and postā€“romantic enterprise
(de Man, 1983).
4
A limitation of this approach is that it restricts the history of art
criticism to certain strains of nineteenthā€“ and twentiethā€“century writing,
excluding writers such as Winckelmann (Potts, 1982), Diderot, and even
Clement Greenberg, to the extent that each of them proposed to speak
according to explicit principles as much as from personal sensibility. In
addition, this way of construing art criticism risks blurring the line between
art criticism and any writing with strong personal content. In the twentieth
century there have been various attempts to question the distinction between
ā€œphilosophyā€ and ā€œwriting,ā€ and more speciļ¬cally to produce hybrids of art
criticism that are partly ā€œphilosophic,ā€ depending on the rational unfolding
of principles, and partly ā€œliteraryā€ in this sense (Deleuze, 1993; Deleuze and
Guattari, 1994). But it could be asked whether those forms of writing fail to
take seriously the conventional and institutional divisions that continue to
distinguish art criticism from art history.
(b) In the Enlightenment philosophic tradition, the word Kritik took
on a speciļ¬c meaning: it denoted the principled negotiation between
destructive skepticism and constructive systematics (Schneiders, 1985;
Ricoeur, 1992). A critique in this sense is neither purely critical nor merely
hortatory, but uses explicitly developed principles and assumptions in order
to achieve a moderated position. Argument takes the place of assertion, and
dubiety replaces dogma (Booth, 1974). This orientation produces texts that
are governed by ā€œthe philosophic principles assumed in the critical
judgments,ā€ the ā€œconception of artistic purposeā€ and of art, and the selection
and application of critical criteria and evidence (McKeon, 1944, 130): that
is, it produces texts where the rational examination of argument comprises
part of the structure and meaning of the text.
5
This form of inquiry continues to be common in philosophy, but
relatively little art criticism makes important or consistent use of named
principles, though there are contemporary counterexamples (McEvilley,
1993; Danto, 1992). Nor is such writing usually a continuation of the
Enlightenment tradition of critiques as measured negotiations between
conļ¬‚icting propositions, so that contemporary art criticism sometimes
becomes more dogmatic, excoriative, or symbuleutic (tending to give
advice) than exploratory, openā€“ended or elenctic (Socratic). Instead of
seeking to navigate between antinomies or conļ¬‚icting assumptions in order
to produce moderate solutions, such writing takes on the more rigid
rhetorical forms of dogmatic criticism (Kramer, 1985). For both these
reasons evaluative art criticism that proceeds from named principles is
uncommon, and criticism that works in a more intimate, personal way is
more frequent.
2. Attempts to deļ¬ne art criticism as a kind of writing have to contend
with historical deļ¬nitions that include a variety of practices under the name
ā€œart criticism.ā€ In the West, art criticism has been considered as an historical
practice in two potentially contradictory ways: (a) it has been described as a
collection of texts and passages without reference to any strong organizing
principle, and (b) it has been restricted to times and places when the term
ā€œart criticismā€ or its cognates were in use by the writers themselves.
In deļ¬nition (b), art criticism is a relatively recent practice, since the
distinction between criticism and history was not made in modern terms
until early in the eighteenth century (Richardson, 1715). But most histories
of art criticism pay only intermittent attention to that criterion, and in accord
with deļ¬nition (a), begin instead by assembling a wide variety of authors
6
from different periods in Western culture. By reading retrospectively, the
modern Western sense of art criticism can be partly or intermittently
discerned in ancient, medieval, Renaissance, and nonā€“Western texts. Thus
Luigi Grassi opens his history of art criticism with Plato (Grassi, 1970), and
Venturi begins his in the third c. BC with Xenocrates of Sikyon and
Antigones of Karystos (Venturi, 1964; Pliny, 1896; Kalkmann, 1898), and
continues through Roman authors including Vitruvius and Lucian, to St.
Augustine, Theophilus, the Polish student of optics Witelo, and Danteā€™s
observations about Cimabue and Giotto. A difļ¬culty with such an approach
is that critical writing about art can be found practically anywhere. The Latin
author Heraclius wondered how the Romans incorporated gold into their
glassware, and Venturi mentions him along with more philosophic questions
of expression raised by Theophilus, and Witeloā€™s preference for almond-
shaped eyes (Venturi, 1964, 65ā€“69).
For later periods this method becomes more cogent, since there is a
continuity of preferences among Renaissance writers from Ghiberti and
Filarete to Vasari (Krautheimer, 1956; Tigler, 1963; Boase, 1979). After the
Renaissance, critical literature becomes recognisable as a genre, especially
in the writings associated with the French Academy such as Le Brun,
Perrault, de Piles, and Denis Diderot (Mortier, 1982). In other words,
deļ¬nition (a) becomes more coherent as it approaches deļ¬nition (b).
The criticism of the salons in Paris forms a large resource for
historians of the late eighteenth and nineteenth centuries (Parson, 1986;
McWilliam 1991a, 1991b), and the reception of Impressionism helped
consolidate the practice into a profession. But the deļ¬nition begins to
weaken again when we move away from the later nineteenth century and
into the twentieth century (Dresdner, 1915; dā€™Ancona and Wittgens, 1927).
7
Even as early as the beginning of the nineteenth century, philosophers such
as Hegel and August Wilhelm von Schlegel had begun to challenge
distinctions between the criticism, philosophy, and history of art (Schlegel,
1801ā€“02; Hegel, 1844). The span from Jonathan Richardsonā€™s deļ¬nition of
art criticism to Schlegelā€™s revaluation is only eighty yearsā€”a short range in
which the term art criticism is both explicit and relatively unchallenged.
The problem is exacerbated in the twentieth century, not least because
contemporary art criticism no longer takes place within the nationalist,
academic and antiā€“academic discursive frames that ļ¬rst gave it meaning, but
is combined with cultural criticism in general and with pieces of formerly
unrelated kinds of writing. A contemporary art critic might write about
journalism or shopping as much as about art, and it can be difļ¬cult to see
how such writing can sensibly be described as a descendent of eighteenthā€“
or nineteenthā€“century practice.
In addition to this problem of historical focus, historical deļ¬nitions of
art criticism are also difļ¬cult to apply to nonā€“Western writing about art.
Several cultures developed aesthetic discourses about their own art
independent of Western inļ¬‚uence, but none have terms strictly comprable to
ā€œart criticism.ā€ Instead they present collections of critical practices. For
Africa, there is a large literature reporting the ways that sculptors judge their
work, but much of it either involves nonverbal judgments, as in a study of
BaKwele preferences (Child and Siroto, 1971), or linguistically simple
assessments requiring only comparative adjectives (Crowley, 1971). When
indigenous words are applied to the evaluation of art, as in the Yoruba
concept of iwa or the Fang concepts of opposition and vitality, they tend to
be common to various areas of nonā€“art experience, making it difļ¬cult to
assess whether their meanings are adequately reported by researchers who
8
necessarily bring other concepts to their research (Fernandez, 1971;
Abiodun, 1983, 1991; Vogel, 1986). Because art criticism does not constitute
a separate discourse in African traditions (Sieber, 1971), it can only be called
art criticism in the rudimentary sense of ā€œdiscourse about artā€ rather than for
any more coherent correspondence to Western aesthetics and criticism.
In China there has been writing about visual art since the ļ¬fth c. AD.
In treatises by Guo Hsi and Guo Ruoxu (both c. 1050 AD), terms that a
Western reader would call descriptive, critical, formal, and philosophic
coexist (SirƩn, 1936), so that it would be no less inappropriate to say that
they are writing amalgams of art history and criticism than to say Vasari was
writing in those genres without being fully aware of the fact. Several key
concepts, such as ā€œspirit consonanceā€ or ā€œspiritual communionā€ (shenhui)
have no adequate correlates in Western languages, making it difļ¬cult to ļ¬nd
common ground (Guo Ruoxu, 1951, 15). The Li dai ming hua ji [Record of
the Famous Painters of all the Dynasties] by Zhang Yanyuan (c. 847 AD)
begins with descriptions of paintingā€™s power to promote Confucian ethical
values, and its magical connection with the ā€œdivine permutationsā€ of nature
(Zhang Yanyuan, 1954, 61, 82): a double origin that places the remainder of
the authorā€™s critical terms, no matter how familiar they might appear, outside
the domain of Western aestheticsā€”even though Zhang distinguishes
between criticism and history in a Western manner (Zhang Yanyuan, 1954,
143).
In the Islamic tradition, texts such as Qadi Ahmadā€™s Calligraphers
and Painters (c. 1606 AD) also mingle theological concepts with graphical,
historical, and critical terms. The concept of the qalam (the calligrapherā€™s
pen and the painterā€™s brush) is at once a divine creation, since it was made
by Allah; a term in historical narrative, since it was passed on from one style
9
and one artist to the next; and a critical tool, because it enables the author to
speak about the particular beauties of each artistā€™s work (Ahmad, 1959, 48ā€“
51). In each of these cases, the speciļ¬c differences between the texts and
traditions militate against a parallel with Western art criticism, and the task
for a more reļ¬‚ective historiography would be to ļ¬nd other categories to put
in its place (Heidegger, 1971).
There is no single account of art criticism that is not counterintuitive,
anachronistic, ethnocentric, artiļ¬cial, or naĆÆve. The term exists in nearly
meaningless dispersion, and gains coherence as authors acknowledge the
disparate inļ¬‚uences of conļ¬‚icting deļ¬nitions, and demonstrate where they
harmonize or chafe with one another.
10
REFERENCES
Pliny, The Elder Plinyā€™s Chapters on the History of Art, trans by K. Jexā€“
Blake (London, 1896).
Zhang Yanyuan, Li dai ming hua ji [A Record of the Famous Painters of All
the Dynasties], abridged translation by William Acker (Leiden,
1954 [c. 847 AD]), pp. 59ā€“382.
Guo Hsi, An Essay on Landscape Painting, translated by Shio Sakanishi
(London, 1935 [c. 1050 AD]).
Guo Ruoxu, Tā€™uā€“hua chienā€“wen chih [Experiences in Painting], translated
by Alexander Soper (Washington, 1951 [c. 1070 AD]).
Qadi Ahmad, Calligraphers and Painters, trans. by V. Minorsky. Freer
Gallery of Art Occasional Papers vol. 3 (Washington, 1959 [c.
1606 AD]).
Jonathan Richardson, An Essay on the Theory of Painting (London, 1719).
August Wilhelm von Schlegel, Vorlesungen Ć¼ber schƶne Literatur und Kunst
(Berlin, 1801ā€“02).
Georg Wilhelm Freidrich Hegel, Vorlesungen Ć¼ber die Aesthetik (Mainz,
1844).
Friedrich Nietzsche, Ecce Homo, translated by Walter Kaufmann (New
York, 1989).
Eduard Bertrand, Etudes sur la peinture et la critique dans lā€™antiquitĆ© (Paris,
1893).
A. Kalkmann, Die Quellen der Kunstgeschichte des Plinius (Berlin, 1898).
Benedetto Croce, Problemi di estetica (Bari, 1910).
A. Dresdner, Die Kunstkritik (Munich, 1915).
11
Charles Baudelaire, CuriositĆ©s aesthĆ©tiques, in Œuvres complĆØtes (Paris,
1923).
P. dā€™Ancona and Fernanda Wittgens, La moderna critica dā€™arte (Milan,
1927).
John Dewey, Art as Experience (New York, 1934).
S. von Dunin Borkowski, Spinoza, vol. 4, Aus den Tagen Spinozas (MĆ¼nster,
1936).
Osvald SirƩn, The Chinese on the Art of Painting (Beijing, 1936).
Lionello Venturi, History of Art Criticism, trans. Charles Marriott (New
York: Dutton, 1964 [1945/1964]).
Richard McKeon, ā€œThe Philosophic Bases of Art and Criticism,ā€ part two,
Modern Philology 41 (1944), pp. 129ā€“71.
Martin Heidegger, ā€œA Dialogue on Language Between a Japanese and an
Inquirer,ā€ in On the Way to Language, trans. by Peter Hertz
(San Francisco, 1971).
Richard Krautheimer, Lorenzo Ghiberti (Princeton, 1956).
Svetlana Alpers, ā€œEkphrasis and Aesthetic Attitudes in Vasariā€™s Lives,ā€
Journal of the Warburg and Courtauld Institute 23 (1960), pp.
190ā€“215.
Creighton Gilbert, ā€œLionello Venturi,ā€ Arts Magazine 36 no. 5 (1962).
Peter Tigler, Die Architekturtheorie des Filarete (Berlin, 1963).
Luigi Grassi, Teorici e storia della critica dā€™arte, prima parte, Dallā€™AntichitĆ 
a tutto il Cinquecento con due saggi introduttivi (Rome, 1970).
Irwin Child and Leon Sirotto, ā€œBaKwele and American Aesthetic Evaluation
Compared,ā€ in Art and Aesthetics in Primitive Societies, edited
by Carol F. Jopling (New York, 1971), pp. 271ā€“89.
12
Daniel Crowley, ā€œAn African Aesthetic,ā€ in Art and Aesthetics in Primitive
Societies, edited by Carol F. Jopling (New York, 1971), pp.
315ā€“27.
James W. Fernandez, ā€œPrinciples of Opposition and Vitality in Fang
Aesthetics,ā€ in Art and Aesthetics in Primitive Societies, edited
by Carol F. Jopling (New York, 1971), pp. 356ā€“73.
Roy Sieber, ā€œThe Aesthetics of Traditional Aftrican Art,ā€ in Art and
Aesthetics in Primitive Societies, edited by Carol F. Jopling
(New York, 1971), pp. 127ā€“31.
Wayne Booth, Modern Dogma and the Rhetoric of Assent (Chicago, 1974).
Jerome Jordan Pollitt, The Ancient View of Greek Art: Criticism History, and
Terminology (New Haven, 1974).
Luigi Grassi and Mario Pepe, Dizionario della critica dā€™arte, 2 vols. (Torino,
1978), v. ā€œCritica dā€™arte,ā€ vol. 1, pp. 135ā€“36.
T. S. R. Boase, Giorgio Vasari: The Man and the Book (Princeton, 1979).
Roland Mortier, Diderot and the ā€œgrand gĆ“utā€ (Oxford, 1982).
Michael Podro, The Critical Historians of Art (New Haven, 1982).
Alex Potts, ā€œWinckelmannā€™s Construction of History,ā€ Art History 5 no. 4
(1982), pp. 377ā€“407.
Rowland Abiodun, ā€œIdentity and the Artistic Process in the Yoruba Aesthetic
Concept of Iwa,ā€ Journal of Cultures and Ideas 1 no. 1 (1983).
Paul de Man, Blindness and Insight, Essays in the Rhetoric of
Contemporary Fiction. Theory and History of Literature, edited
by Wlad Godzich and Jochen Schulteā€“Sasse, volume 7.
(Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1983).
Hilton Kramer, Revenge of the Philistines: Art and Culture, 1972ā€“1984
(New York, 1985).
13
W. Schneiders, ā€œVenĆ¼nftiger Zweifel und wahre Eklektik. Zur Entstehung
des modernen Kritikbegriffes,ā€ Studia Leibnitiana 17 no. 2
(1985), pp. 143ā€“61.
Christopher Parson, A Bibliography of Salon Criticism in Second Empire
Paris (Camnbridge, 1986).
Susan Vogel, African Aesthetics (New York, 1986).
Michael Fried, Coubetā€™s Realism (Chicago: University of Chicago Press,
1990).
Rowland Abiodun, Henry Drewal and John Pemberton, Yoruba Art and
Aesthetics (New York, 1991).
Neil McWilliam, A Bibliography of Salon Criticism in Paris from the ancien
rĆ©gime to the Restoration, 1699ā€“1827 (New York, 1991a).
ā€”ā€”, A Bibliography of Salon Criticism in Paris from the July Monarchy to
the Second Empire, 1831ā€“1851 (New York, 1991b).
Arthur Danto, Beyond the Brillo Box: The Visual Arts in Postā€“Historical
Perspective (New York, 1992).
Paul Ricoeur, Oneself as Another, translated by Kathleen Blamey (Chicago:
University of Chicago Press, 1992).
Gilles Deleuze, Critique et clinique (Paris: Minuit, 1993).
Theodor Lipps, in Empathy, Form, and Space: Problems in German
Aesthetics 1873ā€“1893, translated by Harry Francis Mallgrave
and Eleftherios Ikonomu (Santa Monica, CA: Getty Center for
the History of Art and Humanities, 1994).
Thomas McEvilley, The Exileā€™s Return: Toward a Refedinition of Painting
for the Post-Modern Era (New York, 1993).
W. J. T. Mitchell, Picture Theory, Essays on Verbal and Visual
Representation (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1994).
14
Gilles Deleuze and FĆ©lix Guattari, What is Philosophy? translated by Hugh
Tomlinson and Graham Burchell (New York: Columbia
University Press, 1994).
JAMES ELKINS
15

More Related Content

Similar to Art Criticism (Dictionary Essay)

Take the quiz to discover what poem you have been assigned to discus.docx
Take the quiz to discover what poem you have been assigned to discus.docxTake the quiz to discover what poem you have been assigned to discus.docx
Take the quiz to discover what poem you have been assigned to discus.docx
briankimberly26463
Ā 
Class, Gender, Pleasure, and CriticismAuthor(s) Norman.docx
Class, Gender, Pleasure, and CriticismAuthor(s) Norman.docxClass, Gender, Pleasure, and CriticismAuthor(s) Norman.docx
Class, Gender, Pleasure, and CriticismAuthor(s) Norman.docx
AASTHA76
Ā 
Review of The Mirror and the Lamp
Review of The Mirror and the LampReview of The Mirror and the Lamp
Review of The Mirror and the Lamp
Shiva Kumar Srinivasan
Ā 
The Short Guide SeriesUnder the Editorship ofSylvan Barn.docx
The Short Guide SeriesUnder the Editorship ofSylvan Barn.docxThe Short Guide SeriesUnder the Editorship ofSylvan Barn.docx
The Short Guide SeriesUnder the Editorship ofSylvan Barn.docx
arnoldmeredith47041
Ā 
Literary criticism 2016 additional material rev (2)
Literary criticism 2016 additional material rev (2)Literary criticism 2016 additional material rev (2)
Literary criticism 2016 additional material rev (2)
Jaypee010391
Ā 
Literary Theory And Criticism
Literary Theory And CriticismLiterary Theory And Criticism
Literary Theory And Criticism
Dr. Cupid Lucid
Ā 
The study of literary movements
The study of literary movementsThe study of literary movements
The study of literary movements
Abdel-Fattah Adel
Ā 
Poetics as system, by claudio guillen
Poetics as system, by claudio guillenPoetics as system, by claudio guillen
Poetics as system, by claudio guillen
Mariane Farias
Ā 

Similar to Art Criticism (Dictionary Essay) (20)

4
44
4
Ā 
2
22
2
Ā 
Art After Philosophy (1969) Joseph Kosuth
Art After Philosophy (1969) Joseph KosuthArt After Philosophy (1969) Joseph Kosuth
Art After Philosophy (1969) Joseph Kosuth
Ā 
A Short History of Literary Criticism.pdf
A Short History of Literary Criticism.pdfA Short History of Literary Criticism.pdf
A Short History of Literary Criticism.pdf
Ā 
Autofiction And New Realist Prose Jonathan Franzen S Quot Freedom Quot
Autofiction And New Realist Prose  Jonathan Franzen S  Quot Freedom QuotAutofiction And New Realist Prose  Jonathan Franzen S  Quot Freedom Quot
Autofiction And New Realist Prose Jonathan Franzen S Quot Freedom Quot
Ā 
Take the quiz to discover what poem you have been assigned to discus.docx
Take the quiz to discover what poem you have been assigned to discus.docxTake the quiz to discover what poem you have been assigned to discus.docx
Take the quiz to discover what poem you have been assigned to discus.docx
Ā 
10_Literary_Theory.ppt
10_Literary_Theory.ppt10_Literary_Theory.ppt
10_Literary_Theory.ppt
Ā 
Class, Gender, Pleasure, and CriticismAuthor(s) Norman.docx
Class, Gender, Pleasure, and CriticismAuthor(s) Norman.docxClass, Gender, Pleasure, and CriticismAuthor(s) Norman.docx
Class, Gender, Pleasure, and CriticismAuthor(s) Norman.docx
Ā 
comparative literature by Susan Bassnett
comparative literature by Susan Bassnett comparative literature by Susan Bassnett
comparative literature by Susan Bassnett
Ā 
Literary criticism
Literary criticism Literary criticism
Literary criticism
Ā 
New Criticism
New CriticismNew Criticism
New Criticism
Ā 
Review of The Mirror and the Lamp
Review of The Mirror and the LampReview of The Mirror and the Lamp
Review of The Mirror and the Lamp
Ā 
The Short Guide SeriesUnder the Editorship ofSylvan Barn.docx
The Short Guide SeriesUnder the Editorship ofSylvan Barn.docxThe Short Guide SeriesUnder the Editorship ofSylvan Barn.docx
The Short Guide SeriesUnder the Editorship ofSylvan Barn.docx
Ā 
Literary theory and schools of criticism
Literary theory and schools of criticismLiterary theory and schools of criticism
Literary theory and schools of criticism
Ā 
Literary criticism 2016 additional material rev (2)
Literary criticism 2016 additional material rev (2)Literary criticism 2016 additional material rev (2)
Literary criticism 2016 additional material rev (2)
Ā 
literary criticism.pdf
literary criticism.pdfliterary criticism.pdf
literary criticism.pdf
Ā 
Literary Theory And Criticism
Literary Theory And CriticismLiterary Theory And Criticism
Literary Theory And Criticism
Ā 
The study of literary movements
The study of literary movementsThe study of literary movements
The study of literary movements
Ā 
Criticism History
Criticism HistoryCriticism History
Criticism History
Ā 
Poetics as system, by claudio guillen
Poetics as system, by claudio guillenPoetics as system, by claudio guillen
Poetics as system, by claudio guillen
Ā 

More from Christine Williams

More from Christine Williams (20)

Why A College Education Is Important Essay.Docx - Wh
Why A College Education Is Important Essay.Docx - WhWhy A College Education Is Important Essay.Docx - Wh
Why A College Education Is Important Essay.Docx - Wh
Ā 
About Me Paper Example Awesom
About Me Paper Example AwesomAbout Me Paper Example Awesom
About Me Paper Example Awesom
Ā 
015 Guide English How To Write An Essay Perfect T
015 Guide English How To Write An Essay Perfect T015 Guide English How To Write An Essay Perfect T
015 Guide English How To Write An Essay Perfect T
Ā 
Great Essay Titles. Top 30
Great Essay Titles. Top 30Great Essay Titles. Top 30
Great Essay Titles. Top 30
Ā 
6 Basic Outline Templates - PDF
6 Basic Outline Templates - PDF6 Basic Outline Templates - PDF
6 Basic Outline Templates - PDF
Ā 
Essay On Empathy For Students - EnglishGramma
Essay On Empathy For Students - EnglishGrammaEssay On Empathy For Students - EnglishGramma
Essay On Empathy For Students - EnglishGramma
Ā 
4 Major Types Of Essays - Infographics Types Of Ess
4 Major Types Of Essays - Infographics Types Of Ess4 Major Types Of Essays - Infographics Types Of Ess
4 Major Types Of Essays - Infographics Types Of Ess
Ā 
Opinion Writing Graphic Organizer 4Th Grade
Opinion Writing Graphic Organizer 4Th GradeOpinion Writing Graphic Organizer 4Th Grade
Opinion Writing Graphic Organizer 4Th Grade
Ā 
45 Perfect Thesis Statement Template
45 Perfect Thesis Statement Template45 Perfect Thesis Statement Template
45 Perfect Thesis Statement Template
Ā 
Can You Help Me Write An Essay About How T
Can You Help Me Write An Essay About How TCan You Help Me Write An Essay About How T
Can You Help Me Write An Essay About How T
Ā 
Good Essay Editing Service
Good Essay Editing ServiceGood Essay Editing Service
Good Essay Editing Service
Ā 
Affordable Custom Paper Writing Services Prof
Affordable Custom Paper Writing Services ProfAffordable Custom Paper Writing Services Prof
Affordable Custom Paper Writing Services Prof
Ā 
Definition Essay Usc Dornsife Supplemental Ess
Definition Essay Usc Dornsife Supplemental EssDefinition Essay Usc Dornsife Supplemental Ess
Definition Essay Usc Dornsife Supplemental Ess
Ā 
Mrs. Jones - Free Worksheets And Printable
Mrs. Jones - Free Worksheets And PrintableMrs. Jones - Free Worksheets And Printable
Mrs. Jones - Free Worksheets And Printable
Ā 
Reflective Essay Examples Structure Great Tips Pr
Reflective Essay Examples Structure Great Tips PrReflective Essay Examples Structure Great Tips Pr
Reflective Essay Examples Structure Great Tips Pr
Ā 
Cheap Research Paper Writing Cheap Essay Writing Service From Page
Cheap Research Paper Writing Cheap Essay Writing Service From PageCheap Research Paper Writing Cheap Essay Writing Service From Page
Cheap Research Paper Writing Cheap Essay Writing Service From Page
Ā 
Practicing Writing An Argumentat
Practicing Writing An ArgumentatPracticing Writing An Argumentat
Practicing Writing An Argumentat
Ā 
How To Write A Narrative Essay Best Guide And To
How To Write A Narrative Essay Best Guide And ToHow To Write A Narrative Essay Best Guide And To
How To Write A Narrative Essay Best Guide And To
Ā 
How You Can Write A Great Narrative Essay Step-By-Step
How You Can Write A Great Narrative Essay Step-By-StepHow You Can Write A Great Narrative Essay Step-By-Step
How You Can Write A Great Narrative Essay Step-By-Step
Ā 
IR Argumentative Essay Graphic Organizer By Ren
IR Argumentative Essay Graphic Organizer By RenIR Argumentative Essay Graphic Organizer By Ren
IR Argumentative Essay Graphic Organizer By Ren
Ā 

Recently uploaded

Activity 01 - Artificial Culture (1).pdf
Activity 01 - Artificial Culture (1).pdfActivity 01 - Artificial Culture (1).pdf
Activity 01 - Artificial Culture (1).pdf
ciinovamais
Ā 
1029 - Danh muc Sach Giao Khoa 10 . pdf
1029 -  Danh muc Sach Giao Khoa 10 . pdf1029 -  Danh muc Sach Giao Khoa 10 . pdf
1029 - Danh muc Sach Giao Khoa 10 . pdf
QucHHunhnh
Ā 
Jual Obat Aborsi Hongkong ( Asli No.1 ) 085657271886 Obat Penggugur Kandungan...
Jual Obat Aborsi Hongkong ( Asli No.1 ) 085657271886 Obat Penggugur Kandungan...Jual Obat Aborsi Hongkong ( Asli No.1 ) 085657271886 Obat Penggugur Kandungan...
Jual Obat Aborsi Hongkong ( Asli No.1 ) 085657271886 Obat Penggugur Kandungan...
ZurliaSoop
Ā 
1029-Danh muc Sach Giao Khoa khoi 6.pdf
1029-Danh muc Sach Giao Khoa khoi  6.pdf1029-Danh muc Sach Giao Khoa khoi  6.pdf
1029-Danh muc Sach Giao Khoa khoi 6.pdf
QucHHunhnh
Ā 

Recently uploaded (20)

Unit-IV- Pharma. Marketing Channels.pptx
Unit-IV- Pharma. Marketing Channels.pptxUnit-IV- Pharma. Marketing Channels.pptx
Unit-IV- Pharma. Marketing Channels.pptx
Ā 
Holdier Curriculum Vitae (April 2024).pdf
Holdier Curriculum Vitae (April 2024).pdfHoldier Curriculum Vitae (April 2024).pdf
Holdier Curriculum Vitae (April 2024).pdf
Ā 
How to Give a Domain for a Field in Odoo 17
How to Give a Domain for a Field in Odoo 17How to Give a Domain for a Field in Odoo 17
How to Give a Domain for a Field in Odoo 17
Ā 
Activity 01 - Artificial Culture (1).pdf
Activity 01 - Artificial Culture (1).pdfActivity 01 - Artificial Culture (1).pdf
Activity 01 - Artificial Culture (1).pdf
Ā 
Unit-V; Pricing (Pharma Marketing Management).pptx
Unit-V; Pricing (Pharma Marketing Management).pptxUnit-V; Pricing (Pharma Marketing Management).pptx
Unit-V; Pricing (Pharma Marketing Management).pptx
Ā 
1029 - Danh muc Sach Giao Khoa 10 . pdf
1029 -  Danh muc Sach Giao Khoa 10 . pdf1029 -  Danh muc Sach Giao Khoa 10 . pdf
1029 - Danh muc Sach Giao Khoa 10 . pdf
Ā 
Micro-Scholarship, What it is, How can it help me.pdf
Micro-Scholarship, What it is, How can it help me.pdfMicro-Scholarship, What it is, How can it help me.pdf
Micro-Scholarship, What it is, How can it help me.pdf
Ā 
Unit-IV; Professional Sales Representative (PSR).pptx
Unit-IV; Professional Sales Representative (PSR).pptxUnit-IV; Professional Sales Representative (PSR).pptx
Unit-IV; Professional Sales Representative (PSR).pptx
Ā 
Jual Obat Aborsi Hongkong ( Asli No.1 ) 085657271886 Obat Penggugur Kandungan...
Jual Obat Aborsi Hongkong ( Asli No.1 ) 085657271886 Obat Penggugur Kandungan...Jual Obat Aborsi Hongkong ( Asli No.1 ) 085657271886 Obat Penggugur Kandungan...
Jual Obat Aborsi Hongkong ( Asli No.1 ) 085657271886 Obat Penggugur Kandungan...
Ā 
Kodo Millet PPT made by Ghanshyam bairwa college of Agriculture kumher bhara...
Kodo Millet  PPT made by Ghanshyam bairwa college of Agriculture kumher bhara...Kodo Millet  PPT made by Ghanshyam bairwa college of Agriculture kumher bhara...
Kodo Millet PPT made by Ghanshyam bairwa college of Agriculture kumher bhara...
Ā 
PROCESS RECORDING FORMAT.docx
PROCESS      RECORDING        FORMAT.docxPROCESS      RECORDING        FORMAT.docx
PROCESS RECORDING FORMAT.docx
Ā 
1029-Danh muc Sach Giao Khoa khoi 6.pdf
1029-Danh muc Sach Giao Khoa khoi  6.pdf1029-Danh muc Sach Giao Khoa khoi  6.pdf
1029-Danh muc Sach Giao Khoa khoi 6.pdf
Ā 
Third Battle of Panipat detailed notes.pptx
Third Battle of Panipat detailed notes.pptxThird Battle of Panipat detailed notes.pptx
Third Battle of Panipat detailed notes.pptx
Ā 
Making communications land - Are they received and understood as intended? we...
Making communications land - Are they received and understood as intended? we...Making communications land - Are they received and understood as intended? we...
Making communications land - Are they received and understood as intended? we...
Ā 
Asian American Pacific Islander Month DDSD 2024.pptx
Asian American Pacific Islander Month DDSD 2024.pptxAsian American Pacific Islander Month DDSD 2024.pptx
Asian American Pacific Islander Month DDSD 2024.pptx
Ā 
Spatium Project Simulation student brief
Spatium Project Simulation student briefSpatium Project Simulation student brief
Spatium Project Simulation student brief
Ā 
SOC 101 Demonstration of Learning Presentation
SOC 101 Demonstration of Learning PresentationSOC 101 Demonstration of Learning Presentation
SOC 101 Demonstration of Learning Presentation
Ā 
Mehran University Newsletter Vol-X, Issue-I, 2024
Mehran University Newsletter Vol-X, Issue-I, 2024Mehran University Newsletter Vol-X, Issue-I, 2024
Mehran University Newsletter Vol-X, Issue-I, 2024
Ā 
Food safety_Challenges food safety laboratories_.pdf
Food safety_Challenges food safety laboratories_.pdfFood safety_Challenges food safety laboratories_.pdf
Food safety_Challenges food safety laboratories_.pdf
Ā 
Basic Civil Engineering first year Notes- Chapter 4 Building.pptx
Basic Civil Engineering first year Notes- Chapter 4 Building.pptxBasic Civil Engineering first year Notes- Chapter 4 Building.pptx
Basic Civil Engineering first year Notes- Chapter 4 Building.pptx
Ā 

Art Criticism (Dictionary Essay)

  • 1. Entry ā€œArt Criticismā€ from the Grove (Oxford) Dictionary of Art James Elkins This material was originally posted on www.jameselkins.com. Please write jameselkins@fastmail.cn with comments, or for an up-to-date version. Art criticism can be provisionally deļ¬ned as writing that evaluates art. Yet it has no formal deļ¬nition or agreedā€“upon meaning. The sense of the concept is compromised by two fundamentally antithetical usages: on the one hand, art criticism is understood as an historical practice, embracing writers from Pliny or Vasari to the present; and on the other, it is taken to be a way of writing that is potentially independent of historical conditions. There is no reliable history or philosophy of art criticism, and virtually no literature on its concept or nature. Some philosophers deny art criticism exists as such, and others say it subsumes art historyā€”so that this entire Dictionary would be an example of critical writing. Given that disparity, it is best not to presuppose art criticism has a consensual meaning, but to take the alternate deļ¬nitions seriously. This entry is divided into two sections: 1. Art criticism as a kind of writing 2. Art criticism as an historical practice
  • 2. 1. When art criticism has been treated as a kind of writing, it has normally been considered as evaluative or judgmental rather than descriptive. The traditions of judicative and philodoxic (ostensibly neutral, ā€œknowledgeā€“lovingā€) discourse begin in ancient Greek texts, and are still both distinct and mingled today (Trimpi, 1983). But this distinction between art criticism and art history has been criticized on at least three grounds. (a) Philosophically, each deļ¬nition of art criticism that opposes it to the ostensibly more neutral, descriptive work of art history represses both the inherent and continuous judgments in all historical writing, and the philosophic arguments that description and evaluation are inevitably mixed in all writing. Much of art history depends on such a refusal, and maintains its philodoxic purpose in part by excluding art criticism and deļ¬ning it as judicative (Preziosi, 1989). The complementary exclusion can be observed in art criticism. Lionello Venturiā€™s History of Art Criticism calls the distinction between art history and criticism a ā€œgrave error,ā€ and adds ā€œif a fact referred to is not considered as a function of judgment, it is perfectly uselessā€; but such observations could not be consistently carried through without making the project of a history of art criticism incoherent (Gilbert, 1962; Venturi, 1964, 20). Similarly Luigi Grassi and Mario Pepeā€™s Dizionario della critica dā€™arte contains a brief entry on art criticism noting it is inseparable from historical writing (Grassi and Pepe, 1978, 135). (b) Art criticism has also been distinguished from art history by noting that criticism has a different rhetorical purpose, since it is intended to persuade rather than inform. But this does not provide a stable deļ¬nition since no art historical text leaves its reader unaffected by its implicit judgments regarding value and signiļ¬cance (Fried, 1990). Some of the most eloquent art historians, such as Roberto Longhi, create persuasive 2
  • 3. revaluations of past art at least as much as they produce authoritative compilations of facts. Although Heinrich Wƶlfļ¬‚in insists ā€œthere is no questionā€ of judgment in his work, his descriptions are persuasive precisly because they are such strong judgments (Wƶlfļ¬‚in, 1914, 1). (c) The historiography of art history provides evidence that many of the practices that gave rise to art history were conceived as critical enterprises. Vasari is frequently cited as an example of mixed critical and factual narrative (Alpers, 1960), and there is also the seventeenthā€“century practice of ars critica, which laid the foundations for the higher biblical criticism and furnished ā€œthe example for classical, and later modern, philologyā€ (Borkowski, 1936; McKeon, 1944, 163) that in turn proved so fruitful for the developing discipline of art history (Podro, 1982). For these reasons it is philosophically, rhetorically, and historiographically untenable to maintain the distinction between art history and art criticism on the grounds that one evaluates and the other describes. The problem is symmetrical: like most art history, some art criticism is conceived as nonjudgmental and philodoxic. In particular criticism can be understood as imaginative reā€“enactment of creation or perception, with no determinate relation to evaluation. Ekphrasis can function this way, and has from Pliny, Callistratus and Philostratus through Vasari (Bertrand, 1893; Alpers, 1960; Mitchell, 1994, 151ā€“81). In turnā€“ofā€“theā€“century German aesthetics, the doctrine of empathy provided a foundation for writing that critically reimagined the bodily experience of artwork (Lipps and Vischer, 1994). In the United States, John Dewey proposed that criticism should not appraise or judge but that ā€œwe lay hold of the full import of a work of art only as we go through in our own vital processes the processes the artist went through in producing the workā€ (Dewey, 1934, 325), and Benedetto 3
  • 4. Croceā€™s slightly earlier concept of imaginative understanding is similar (Croce, 1910, 42). Venturiā€™s History of Art Criticism can be read as a secondā€“order work of this kind, since he aims in part to relive older critical experiences without judging them (Gilbert, 1962, 59; Venturi, 1964, 8ā€“9). When art criticism is imagined as an evaluative activity, it can be conceived either as personal response without explicit purpose or thesis, or else as measured judgment governed by premeditated principles. The two provide divergent genealogies for the juridical aspect of art criticism. In general the second strategy derives from Enlightenment philosophy and results in texts that aim to present an ostensibly true, universal, or reliable assessment of the value of an artwork, and the ļ¬rst comes from romantic poetry, confession, and reverie, and yields texts that can be read as the potentially idiosyncratic exercise of individual sensibility. (a) As a deļ¬ning trait of the more personal sense of art criticism, writers have pointed to the intimacy of writing about art, and they have emphasized its dependence on the idea of sensibility or taste (Grassi, 1970, 47). Thus Charles Baudelaire called for criticism that would be ā€œpartial, passionate, and politicalā€ (Baudelaire, 1923, 87), and Friedrich Nietzsche practiced a personal and psychological criticism of philosophy and art (Nietzsche, 1989). Ultimately these tendencies could be traced to Platoā€™s dialectic criticism, where dialogue and opinions constitute the medium in which critical judgments emerge, as opposed to Aristotleā€™s ā€œscientiļ¬cā€ criticism, which is based on expository description and the rational unfolding of knowledge (McKeon, 1944, 162); but contemporary art criticism that depends on sensibility, personal reļ¬‚ection and taste is more often understood as a fundamentally romantic and postā€“romantic enterprise (de Man, 1983). 4
  • 5. A limitation of this approach is that it restricts the history of art criticism to certain strains of nineteenthā€“ and twentiethā€“century writing, excluding writers such as Winckelmann (Potts, 1982), Diderot, and even Clement Greenberg, to the extent that each of them proposed to speak according to explicit principles as much as from personal sensibility. In addition, this way of construing art criticism risks blurring the line between art criticism and any writing with strong personal content. In the twentieth century there have been various attempts to question the distinction between ā€œphilosophyā€ and ā€œwriting,ā€ and more speciļ¬cally to produce hybrids of art criticism that are partly ā€œphilosophic,ā€ depending on the rational unfolding of principles, and partly ā€œliteraryā€ in this sense (Deleuze, 1993; Deleuze and Guattari, 1994). But it could be asked whether those forms of writing fail to take seriously the conventional and institutional divisions that continue to distinguish art criticism from art history. (b) In the Enlightenment philosophic tradition, the word Kritik took on a speciļ¬c meaning: it denoted the principled negotiation between destructive skepticism and constructive systematics (Schneiders, 1985; Ricoeur, 1992). A critique in this sense is neither purely critical nor merely hortatory, but uses explicitly developed principles and assumptions in order to achieve a moderated position. Argument takes the place of assertion, and dubiety replaces dogma (Booth, 1974). This orientation produces texts that are governed by ā€œthe philosophic principles assumed in the critical judgments,ā€ the ā€œconception of artistic purposeā€ and of art, and the selection and application of critical criteria and evidence (McKeon, 1944, 130): that is, it produces texts where the rational examination of argument comprises part of the structure and meaning of the text. 5
  • 6. This form of inquiry continues to be common in philosophy, but relatively little art criticism makes important or consistent use of named principles, though there are contemporary counterexamples (McEvilley, 1993; Danto, 1992). Nor is such writing usually a continuation of the Enlightenment tradition of critiques as measured negotiations between conļ¬‚icting propositions, so that contemporary art criticism sometimes becomes more dogmatic, excoriative, or symbuleutic (tending to give advice) than exploratory, openā€“ended or elenctic (Socratic). Instead of seeking to navigate between antinomies or conļ¬‚icting assumptions in order to produce moderate solutions, such writing takes on the more rigid rhetorical forms of dogmatic criticism (Kramer, 1985). For both these reasons evaluative art criticism that proceeds from named principles is uncommon, and criticism that works in a more intimate, personal way is more frequent. 2. Attempts to deļ¬ne art criticism as a kind of writing have to contend with historical deļ¬nitions that include a variety of practices under the name ā€œart criticism.ā€ In the West, art criticism has been considered as an historical practice in two potentially contradictory ways: (a) it has been described as a collection of texts and passages without reference to any strong organizing principle, and (b) it has been restricted to times and places when the term ā€œart criticismā€ or its cognates were in use by the writers themselves. In deļ¬nition (b), art criticism is a relatively recent practice, since the distinction between criticism and history was not made in modern terms until early in the eighteenth century (Richardson, 1715). But most histories of art criticism pay only intermittent attention to that criterion, and in accord with deļ¬nition (a), begin instead by assembling a wide variety of authors 6
  • 7. from different periods in Western culture. By reading retrospectively, the modern Western sense of art criticism can be partly or intermittently discerned in ancient, medieval, Renaissance, and nonā€“Western texts. Thus Luigi Grassi opens his history of art criticism with Plato (Grassi, 1970), and Venturi begins his in the third c. BC with Xenocrates of Sikyon and Antigones of Karystos (Venturi, 1964; Pliny, 1896; Kalkmann, 1898), and continues through Roman authors including Vitruvius and Lucian, to St. Augustine, Theophilus, the Polish student of optics Witelo, and Danteā€™s observations about Cimabue and Giotto. A difļ¬culty with such an approach is that critical writing about art can be found practically anywhere. The Latin author Heraclius wondered how the Romans incorporated gold into their glassware, and Venturi mentions him along with more philosophic questions of expression raised by Theophilus, and Witeloā€™s preference for almond- shaped eyes (Venturi, 1964, 65ā€“69). For later periods this method becomes more cogent, since there is a continuity of preferences among Renaissance writers from Ghiberti and Filarete to Vasari (Krautheimer, 1956; Tigler, 1963; Boase, 1979). After the Renaissance, critical literature becomes recognisable as a genre, especially in the writings associated with the French Academy such as Le Brun, Perrault, de Piles, and Denis Diderot (Mortier, 1982). In other words, deļ¬nition (a) becomes more coherent as it approaches deļ¬nition (b). The criticism of the salons in Paris forms a large resource for historians of the late eighteenth and nineteenth centuries (Parson, 1986; McWilliam 1991a, 1991b), and the reception of Impressionism helped consolidate the practice into a profession. But the deļ¬nition begins to weaken again when we move away from the later nineteenth century and into the twentieth century (Dresdner, 1915; dā€™Ancona and Wittgens, 1927). 7
  • 8. Even as early as the beginning of the nineteenth century, philosophers such as Hegel and August Wilhelm von Schlegel had begun to challenge distinctions between the criticism, philosophy, and history of art (Schlegel, 1801ā€“02; Hegel, 1844). The span from Jonathan Richardsonā€™s deļ¬nition of art criticism to Schlegelā€™s revaluation is only eighty yearsā€”a short range in which the term art criticism is both explicit and relatively unchallenged. The problem is exacerbated in the twentieth century, not least because contemporary art criticism no longer takes place within the nationalist, academic and antiā€“academic discursive frames that ļ¬rst gave it meaning, but is combined with cultural criticism in general and with pieces of formerly unrelated kinds of writing. A contemporary art critic might write about journalism or shopping as much as about art, and it can be difļ¬cult to see how such writing can sensibly be described as a descendent of eighteenthā€“ or nineteenthā€“century practice. In addition to this problem of historical focus, historical deļ¬nitions of art criticism are also difļ¬cult to apply to nonā€“Western writing about art. Several cultures developed aesthetic discourses about their own art independent of Western inļ¬‚uence, but none have terms strictly comprable to ā€œart criticism.ā€ Instead they present collections of critical practices. For Africa, there is a large literature reporting the ways that sculptors judge their work, but much of it either involves nonverbal judgments, as in a study of BaKwele preferences (Child and Siroto, 1971), or linguistically simple assessments requiring only comparative adjectives (Crowley, 1971). When indigenous words are applied to the evaluation of art, as in the Yoruba concept of iwa or the Fang concepts of opposition and vitality, they tend to be common to various areas of nonā€“art experience, making it difļ¬cult to assess whether their meanings are adequately reported by researchers who 8
  • 9. necessarily bring other concepts to their research (Fernandez, 1971; Abiodun, 1983, 1991; Vogel, 1986). Because art criticism does not constitute a separate discourse in African traditions (Sieber, 1971), it can only be called art criticism in the rudimentary sense of ā€œdiscourse about artā€ rather than for any more coherent correspondence to Western aesthetics and criticism. In China there has been writing about visual art since the ļ¬fth c. AD. In treatises by Guo Hsi and Guo Ruoxu (both c. 1050 AD), terms that a Western reader would call descriptive, critical, formal, and philosophic coexist (SirĆ©n, 1936), so that it would be no less inappropriate to say that they are writing amalgams of art history and criticism than to say Vasari was writing in those genres without being fully aware of the fact. Several key concepts, such as ā€œspirit consonanceā€ or ā€œspiritual communionā€ (shenhui) have no adequate correlates in Western languages, making it difļ¬cult to ļ¬nd common ground (Guo Ruoxu, 1951, 15). The Li dai ming hua ji [Record of the Famous Painters of all the Dynasties] by Zhang Yanyuan (c. 847 AD) begins with descriptions of paintingā€™s power to promote Confucian ethical values, and its magical connection with the ā€œdivine permutationsā€ of nature (Zhang Yanyuan, 1954, 61, 82): a double origin that places the remainder of the authorā€™s critical terms, no matter how familiar they might appear, outside the domain of Western aestheticsā€”even though Zhang distinguishes between criticism and history in a Western manner (Zhang Yanyuan, 1954, 143). In the Islamic tradition, texts such as Qadi Ahmadā€™s Calligraphers and Painters (c. 1606 AD) also mingle theological concepts with graphical, historical, and critical terms. The concept of the qalam (the calligrapherā€™s pen and the painterā€™s brush) is at once a divine creation, since it was made by Allah; a term in historical narrative, since it was passed on from one style 9
  • 10. and one artist to the next; and a critical tool, because it enables the author to speak about the particular beauties of each artistā€™s work (Ahmad, 1959, 48ā€“ 51). In each of these cases, the speciļ¬c differences between the texts and traditions militate against a parallel with Western art criticism, and the task for a more reļ¬‚ective historiography would be to ļ¬nd other categories to put in its place (Heidegger, 1971). There is no single account of art criticism that is not counterintuitive, anachronistic, ethnocentric, artiļ¬cial, or naĆÆve. The term exists in nearly meaningless dispersion, and gains coherence as authors acknowledge the disparate inļ¬‚uences of conļ¬‚icting deļ¬nitions, and demonstrate where they harmonize or chafe with one another. 10
  • 11. REFERENCES Pliny, The Elder Plinyā€™s Chapters on the History of Art, trans by K. Jexā€“ Blake (London, 1896). Zhang Yanyuan, Li dai ming hua ji [A Record of the Famous Painters of All the Dynasties], abridged translation by William Acker (Leiden, 1954 [c. 847 AD]), pp. 59ā€“382. Guo Hsi, An Essay on Landscape Painting, translated by Shio Sakanishi (London, 1935 [c. 1050 AD]). Guo Ruoxu, Tā€™uā€“hua chienā€“wen chih [Experiences in Painting], translated by Alexander Soper (Washington, 1951 [c. 1070 AD]). Qadi Ahmad, Calligraphers and Painters, trans. by V. Minorsky. Freer Gallery of Art Occasional Papers vol. 3 (Washington, 1959 [c. 1606 AD]). Jonathan Richardson, An Essay on the Theory of Painting (London, 1719). August Wilhelm von Schlegel, Vorlesungen Ć¼ber schƶne Literatur und Kunst (Berlin, 1801ā€“02). Georg Wilhelm Freidrich Hegel, Vorlesungen Ć¼ber die Aesthetik (Mainz, 1844). Friedrich Nietzsche, Ecce Homo, translated by Walter Kaufmann (New York, 1989). Eduard Bertrand, Etudes sur la peinture et la critique dans lā€™antiquitĆ© (Paris, 1893). A. Kalkmann, Die Quellen der Kunstgeschichte des Plinius (Berlin, 1898). Benedetto Croce, Problemi di estetica (Bari, 1910). A. Dresdner, Die Kunstkritik (Munich, 1915). 11
  • 12. Charles Baudelaire, CuriositĆ©s aesthĆ©tiques, in Œuvres complĆØtes (Paris, 1923). P. dā€™Ancona and Fernanda Wittgens, La moderna critica dā€™arte (Milan, 1927). John Dewey, Art as Experience (New York, 1934). S. von Dunin Borkowski, Spinoza, vol. 4, Aus den Tagen Spinozas (MĆ¼nster, 1936). Osvald SirĆ©n, The Chinese on the Art of Painting (Beijing, 1936). Lionello Venturi, History of Art Criticism, trans. Charles Marriott (New York: Dutton, 1964 [1945/1964]). Richard McKeon, ā€œThe Philosophic Bases of Art and Criticism,ā€ part two, Modern Philology 41 (1944), pp. 129ā€“71. Martin Heidegger, ā€œA Dialogue on Language Between a Japanese and an Inquirer,ā€ in On the Way to Language, trans. by Peter Hertz (San Francisco, 1971). Richard Krautheimer, Lorenzo Ghiberti (Princeton, 1956). Svetlana Alpers, ā€œEkphrasis and Aesthetic Attitudes in Vasariā€™s Lives,ā€ Journal of the Warburg and Courtauld Institute 23 (1960), pp. 190ā€“215. Creighton Gilbert, ā€œLionello Venturi,ā€ Arts Magazine 36 no. 5 (1962). Peter Tigler, Die Architekturtheorie des Filarete (Berlin, 1963). Luigi Grassi, Teorici e storia della critica dā€™arte, prima parte, Dallā€™AntichitĆ  a tutto il Cinquecento con due saggi introduttivi (Rome, 1970). Irwin Child and Leon Sirotto, ā€œBaKwele and American Aesthetic Evaluation Compared,ā€ in Art and Aesthetics in Primitive Societies, edited by Carol F. Jopling (New York, 1971), pp. 271ā€“89. 12
  • 13. Daniel Crowley, ā€œAn African Aesthetic,ā€ in Art and Aesthetics in Primitive Societies, edited by Carol F. Jopling (New York, 1971), pp. 315ā€“27. James W. Fernandez, ā€œPrinciples of Opposition and Vitality in Fang Aesthetics,ā€ in Art and Aesthetics in Primitive Societies, edited by Carol F. Jopling (New York, 1971), pp. 356ā€“73. Roy Sieber, ā€œThe Aesthetics of Traditional Aftrican Art,ā€ in Art and Aesthetics in Primitive Societies, edited by Carol F. Jopling (New York, 1971), pp. 127ā€“31. Wayne Booth, Modern Dogma and the Rhetoric of Assent (Chicago, 1974). Jerome Jordan Pollitt, The Ancient View of Greek Art: Criticism History, and Terminology (New Haven, 1974). Luigi Grassi and Mario Pepe, Dizionario della critica dā€™arte, 2 vols. (Torino, 1978), v. ā€œCritica dā€™arte,ā€ vol. 1, pp. 135ā€“36. T. S. R. Boase, Giorgio Vasari: The Man and the Book (Princeton, 1979). Roland Mortier, Diderot and the ā€œgrand gĆ“utā€ (Oxford, 1982). Michael Podro, The Critical Historians of Art (New Haven, 1982). Alex Potts, ā€œWinckelmannā€™s Construction of History,ā€ Art History 5 no. 4 (1982), pp. 377ā€“407. Rowland Abiodun, ā€œIdentity and the Artistic Process in the Yoruba Aesthetic Concept of Iwa,ā€ Journal of Cultures and Ideas 1 no. 1 (1983). Paul de Man, Blindness and Insight, Essays in the Rhetoric of Contemporary Fiction. Theory and History of Literature, edited by Wlad Godzich and Jochen Schulteā€“Sasse, volume 7. (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1983). Hilton Kramer, Revenge of the Philistines: Art and Culture, 1972ā€“1984 (New York, 1985). 13
  • 14. W. Schneiders, ā€œVenĆ¼nftiger Zweifel und wahre Eklektik. Zur Entstehung des modernen Kritikbegriffes,ā€ Studia Leibnitiana 17 no. 2 (1985), pp. 143ā€“61. Christopher Parson, A Bibliography of Salon Criticism in Second Empire Paris (Camnbridge, 1986). Susan Vogel, African Aesthetics (New York, 1986). Michael Fried, Coubetā€™s Realism (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1990). Rowland Abiodun, Henry Drewal and John Pemberton, Yoruba Art and Aesthetics (New York, 1991). Neil McWilliam, A Bibliography of Salon Criticism in Paris from the ancien rĆ©gime to the Restoration, 1699ā€“1827 (New York, 1991a). ā€”ā€”, A Bibliography of Salon Criticism in Paris from the July Monarchy to the Second Empire, 1831ā€“1851 (New York, 1991b). Arthur Danto, Beyond the Brillo Box: The Visual Arts in Postā€“Historical Perspective (New York, 1992). Paul Ricoeur, Oneself as Another, translated by Kathleen Blamey (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1992). Gilles Deleuze, Critique et clinique (Paris: Minuit, 1993). Theodor Lipps, in Empathy, Form, and Space: Problems in German Aesthetics 1873ā€“1893, translated by Harry Francis Mallgrave and Eleftherios Ikonomu (Santa Monica, CA: Getty Center for the History of Art and Humanities, 1994). Thomas McEvilley, The Exileā€™s Return: Toward a Refedinition of Painting for the Post-Modern Era (New York, 1993). W. J. T. Mitchell, Picture Theory, Essays on Verbal and Visual Representation (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1994). 14
  • 15. Gilles Deleuze and FĆ©lix Guattari, What is Philosophy? translated by Hugh Tomlinson and Graham Burchell (New York: Columbia University Press, 1994). JAMES ELKINS 15