SlideShare a Scribd company logo
History of African Philosophy
This article traces the history of systematic African philosophy from the early 1920s to
date. In Plato’s Theaetetus, Socrates suggests that philosophy begins with wonder.
Aristotle agreed. However, recent research shows that wonder may have different subsets.
If that is the case, which specific subset of wonder inspired the beginning of the systematic
African philosophy? In the history of Western philosophy, there is the one
called thaumazein interpreted as awe and the other called miraculum interpreted as
curiosity. History shows that these two subsets manifest in the African place as well, even
during the pre-systematic era. However, there is now an idea appearing in recent African
philosophy literature called onuma interpreted as frustration which is regarded as the
subset of wonder that jump started the systematic African philosophy. In the 1920s, a host
of Africans who went to study in the West were just returning. They had experienced
terrible racism and discrimination while in the West. They were referred to as
descendants of slaves; as people from the slave colony, as sub-humans, and so on. On
return to their native lands, they met the same maltreatment by the colonial officials.
‘Frustrated’ by colonialism and racialism as well as the legacies of slavery, they were jolted
onto the path of philosophy—African philosophy—by what can be called onuma.
These ugly episodes of slavery, colonialism and racialism not only shaped the world’s
perception of Africa; they also instigated a form of intellectual revolt from the African
intelligentsias. The frustration with the colonial order eventually led to angry questions
and reactions out of which African philosophy emerged, first in the form of nationalisms
and then in the form ideological theorizations. But the frustration was borne out of
colonial caricature of Africa as culturally naïve, intellectually docile and rationally inept.
This caricature was created by European scholars such as Kant, Hegel and, much later,
Levy-Bruhl to name just a few. It was the reaction to this caricature that led some African
scholars returning from the West into the type of philosophizing one may describe as
systematic beginning with the identity of the African people, their place in history, and
their contributions to civilization. To dethrone the colonially-built episteme became a
ready attraction for African scholars’ vexed frustrations. Thus began the history of
systematic African philosophy with the likes of Aime Cisaire, Leopold Senghor, Kwame
Nkrumah, Julius Nyerere, William Abraham, John Mbiti and expatriates such as Placid
Tempels, Janheinz Jahn and George James, to name a few.
Table of Contents
1. Introduction
2. Criteria of African Philosophy
3. Methods of African Philosophy
a. The Communitarian Method
b. The Complementarity Method
c. The Conversational Method
4. Schools of African Philosophy
. Ethnophilosophy School
a. Nationalist/Ideological School
b. Philosophic Sagacity
c. Hermeneutical School
d. Literary School
e. Professional School
f. Conversational School
5. The Movements in African Philosophy
. Excavationism
a. Afro-Constructionism/Afro-Deconstructionism
b. Critical Reconstructionism/Afro-Eclecticism
c. Conversationalism
6. Periods of African Philosophy
. Early Period
a. Middle Period
b. Later Period
c. New Era
7. Conclusion
8. References and Further Reading
1. Introduction
African philosophy as a systematic study has a very short history. This history is also a
very dense one, since actors sought to do in a few decades what would have been better
done in many centuries. As a result, they also did in later years what ought to have been
done earlier and vice versa, thus making the early and the middle epochs overlap
considerably. The reason for this overtime endeavor is not far-fetched. Soon after
colonialism, actors realized that Africa had been sucked into the global matrix
unprepared. During colonial times, the identity of the African was European, his thought
system, standard and even his perception of reality were structured by the colonial
shadow which stood towering behind him. It was easy for the African to position himself
within these Western cultural appurtenances even though they had no real-time
connection with his being.
The vanity of this presupposition and the emptiness of colonial assurances manifested
soon after the towering colonial shadow vanished. Now, in the global matrix, it became
shameful for the African to continue to identify himself within the European colonialist
milieu. For one, he had just rejected colonialism and for another, the deposed European
colonialist made it clear that the identity of the African was no longer covered and insured
by the European medium. So, actors realized suddenly that they had been disillusioned
and had suffered severe self-deceit under colonial temper. The question which trailed
every African was, “Who are you?” Of course, the answers from European perspective
were savage, primitive, less than human, etc. It was the urgent, sudden need to contradict
these European positions that led some post-colonial Africans in search of African
identity. So, to discover or rediscover African identity in order to initiate a non-colonial
or original history for Africa in the global matrix and start a course of viable economic,
political and social progress that is entirely African became one of the focal points of
African philosophy.
Placid Tempels, the European missionary, elected to help and in his controversial
book, Bantu Philosophy, sought to create Africa’s own philosophy as proof that Africa has
its own peculiar identity and thought system. However, it was George James, another
concerned European who attempted a much more ambitious project in his work, Stolen
Legacy. In this work, there were strong suggestions not only that Africa has philosophy
but that the so-called Western philosophy, the very bastion of European identity, was
stolen from Africa. This claim was intended to make the proud European colonialists feel
indebted to the humiliated Africans, but it was unsuccessful. That Greek philosophy had
roots in Egypt does not imply, as some Europeans claim, that Egyptians were dark nor
that dark complexioned Africans had philosophy. The use of the term “Africans” in this
work is in keeping with George James’ demarcation which precludes the light
complexioned people of North Africa and refers to the dark complexioned people of
southern Sahara.
After these two Europeans, Africans began to attain maturation. Aime Cesaire, John
Mbiti, Odera Oruka, Julius Nyerere, Leopold Senghor, Nnamdi Azikiwe, Kwame
Nkrumah, Obafemi Awolowo, Alexis Kegame, Uzodinma Nwala, Emmanuel Edeh,
Innocent Onyewuenyi, and Henry Olela, to name just a few, opened the doors of ideas. A
few of the works produced sought to prove and establish the philosophical basis of
African, unique identity in the history of humankind, while others sought to chart a course
of Africa’s true identity through unique political and economic ideologies. It can be stated
that much of these endeavors fall under the early period.
For its concerns, the middle period of African philosophy is characterized by the great
debate. Those who seek to clarify and justify the position held in the early epoch and those
who seek to criticize and deny the viability of such position entangled themselves in a
great debate. Some of the actors on this front include, C. S. Momoh, Robin Horton, Henri
Maurier, Lacinay Keita, Peter Bodunrin, Kwasi Wiredu, Kwame Gyekye, Richard Wright,
Barry Halen, Joseph Omoregbe, C. B. Okolo, Theophilus Okere, Paulin Hountondji,
Gordon Hunnings, Odera Oruka and Sophie Oluwole to name a few.
The preceding epoch eventually gave way to the later period which has as its focus the
construction of an African episteme. Two camps rivaled each other namely; the Critical
Reconstructionists who are the evolved Universalists/Deconstructionists and the
Eclectics who are the evolved Traditionalists/Excavators. The former seek to build an
African episteme untainted by ethnophilosophy; whereas, the latter seek to do the same
by a delicate fusion of relevant ideals of the two camps. In the end, Critical
Reconstructionism ran into a brick wall when it became clear that whatever it produced
cannot truly be called African philosophy if it is all Western without African marks. The
mere claim that it would be African philosophy simply because it was produced by
Africans (Hountondji 1996 and Oruka 1975) would collapse like a house of cards under
any argument. For this great failure, the influence of Critical Reconstructionism in the
later period whittled down and it was latter absorbed by its rival—Eclecticism.
The works of the Eclectics heralded the emergence of the New Era in African philosophy.
The focus becomes the Conversational philosophizing, in which the production of
philosophically rigorous and original African episteme better than what the Eclectics
produced occupied the center stage.
The sum of what historians of African philosophy have done can be presented in the
following two broad categorizations to wit; Pre-systematic Era and the Systematic era.
The former refers to Africa’s philosophical culture, thoughts of the anonymous African
thinkers and may include the problems of Egyptian legacy. The latter refers to the periods
marking the return of Africa’s first eleven, Western-tutored philosophers from the 1920’s
to date. This latter category could further be delineated into four periods:
1.
a. Early period 1920s - 1960s
b. Middle period 1960s - 1980s
c. Later period 1980s - 1990s
d. New (Contemporary) Era since 1990s
Note, of course, that this does not commit us to saying that, before the early period, people
in Africa never philosophized—they did. But one fact that must not be denied is that they
did not document their thoughts and, as such, scholars cannot attest to their systematicity
or sources. In other words, what this periodization shows is that African philosophy as a
system first began in the late 1920s.
Because there are credible objections among African philosophers with regards to the
inclusion of it in the historical chart of African philosophy, the Egyptian question will be
ignored for now. The main objection is that even if the philosophers of stolen legacy were
able to prove a connection between Greece and Egypt, they could not prove in concrete
terms that Egyptians were dark complexioned Africans or that dark complexioned
Africans were Egyptians. It is understandable the frustration and desperation that
motivated such ambitious effort in the ugly colonial era which was captured above, but
any reasonable person, judging by the responses of time and events in the last few decades
knows it was high time Africans abandoned that unproven legacy and let go of that, now
helpless propaganda. If however, some would want to retain it as part of African
philosophy, it would carefully fall within the pre-literate or the pre-systematic era.
In this essay, discussion will focus on the history of systematic or literate African
philosophy touching prominently on the criteria, schools, movements and periods in
African philosophy. As much as the philosophers of a given era may disagree, they are
inevitably united by the problem of their epoch. That is to say, it is orthodoxy that each
epoch is defined by a common focus or problem. Therefore, the approach of the study of
the history of philosophy can be done either through personality periscope or through the
periods, but whichever approach one chooses, he unavoidably runs into the person who
had chosen the other. This is a sign of unity of focus. Thus philosophers are those who
seek to solve the problem of their time. In this presentation, the study of the history of
African philosophy will be approached principally through the periods, schools,
movements and the personalities will be discussed within these purviews.
2. Criteria of African Philosophy
To start with, more than three decades debate on the status of philosophy ended with the
affirmation that African philosophy exists. But what is it that makes a philosophy African?
Answers to this question polarized actors into two main groups, namely the
Traditionalists and Universalists. Whereas the Traditionalists aver that the studies of the
philosophical elements in world-view of the people constitute African philosophy, the
Universalists insist that it has to be a body of analytic and critical reflections of individual
African philosophers. Further probing of the question was done during the debate by the
end of which the question of what makes a philosophy “African” produced two contrasting
criteria. First, as a racial criterion; a philosophy would be African if it is produced by
Africans. This is the view held by people like Paulin Hountondji, Odera Oruka (in part),
and early Peter Bodunrin, derived from the two constituting terms—“African” and
“philosophy”. African philosophy following this criterion is the philosophy done by
Africans. This has been criticized as pejorative, incorrect and exclusivist. Second, as a
tradition criterion; a philosophy is “African” if it designates a non-racial-bound
philosophy tradition where the predicate “African” is treated as a solidarity term of no
racial import and where the approach derives inspiration from African cultural
background or system of thought. It does not matter whether the issues addressed are
African or that the philosophy is done by an African insofar as it has universal
applicability and emerged from the purview of African system of thought. African
philosophy would then be that rigorous discourse of African issues or any issues
whatsoever from the critical eye of African system of thought. Actors like Odera Oruka (in
part), Meinrad Hebga, C. S. Momoh, Udo Etuk, Joseph Omoregbe, the later Peter
Bodunrin, Jonathan Chimakonam can be grouped here. This criterion has also been
criticized as courting uncritical elements of the past when it makes reference to the
controversial idea of African logic tradition. Further discussion on this is well beyond the
scope of this essay. What is however common in the two criteria is that African philosophy
is a critical discourse on issues that may or may not affect Africa by African philosophers—
the purview of this discourse remains unsettled.
3. Methods of African Philosophy
a. The Communitarian Method
This method speaks to the idea of mutuality, the type found in the classic expression of
ubuntu: “a person is a person through other person” or that which is credited to John
Mbiti, “ I am because we are, since we are, therefore I am”. Those who employ this method
wish to demonstrate the idea of mutual interdependence of variables. You find this most
prominent in the works of researchers working in ubuntu and communalism. Some of the
thinkers who employ this method include; Ifeanyi Menkiti, Mogobe Ramose, Kwame
Gyekye, Thaddeus Metz, Fainos Mangena, Leonhard Praeg, Bernard Matolino, Michael
Eze, and so forth.
b. The Complementarity Method
This method was propounded by Innocent Asouzu and it harps on the idea of missing
link. No variable is useless. The system of reality is like a network in which each variable
has an important role to play i.e. it complements and is in return complemented because
no variable is self sufficient. Other scholars whose works have followed this method
include Mesembe Edet, Ada Agada, Jonathan Chimakonam and a host of others.
c. The Conversational Method
This is a formal procedure for assessing the relationships of opposed variables in which
thoughts are shuffled through disjunctive and conjunctive modes to constantly recreate
fresh thesis and anti-thesis each time at a higher level of discourse without the expectation
of the synthesis. It is an encounter between philosophers of rival schools of thought and
between different philosophical traditions or cultures in which one party called nwa-nsa
(the defender or proponent) holds up a position and another party called nwa-nju (the
doubter or opponent) doubts or questions the accuracy of the position. On the whole, this
method points to the idea of relationships among interdependent, interrelated and
interconnected realities existing in a network whose peculiar truth conditions can more
accurately and broadly be determined within specific contexts. This method was first
proposed by Jonathan Chimakonam and endorsed by the The Conversational School of
Philosophy. Other thinkers that now employ this method include, Victor Nweke,
Mesembe Edet, Fayemi Ademola Kazeem, Ada Agada, Pius Mosima, and a host of others.
4. Schools of African Philosophy
a. Ethnophilosophy School
This is the foremost school in systematic African philosophy which equated African
philosophy with culture-bound systems of thought. For this, their enterprise was
scornfully described as substandard hence the term “ethnophilosophy.” Thoughts of the
members of the Excavationism movement like Tempels Placid and Alexis Kagame
properly belong here and their high point was in the early period of African philosophy.
b. Nationalist/Ideological School
The concern of this school was nationalist philosophical jingoism to combat colonialism
and to create political philosophy and ideology for Africa from the indigenous traditional
system as a project of decolonization. Thoughts of members of the Excavationism
movement like Kwame Nkrumah, Leopold Sedar Senghor and Julius Nyerere in the early
period can be brought under this school.
c. Philosophic Sagacity
There is also the philosophic sagacity school whose main focus is to show that standard
philosophical discourse existed and still exists in traditional Africa and can only be
discovered through sage conversations. The chief proponent of this school was the
brilliant Kenyan philosopher Odera Oruka who took time to emphasize that Marcel
Gruaile’s similar programme is less sophisticated than his. Other adherents of this school
include Gail Presbey, Anke Graness and the Cameroonian philosopher Pius Mosima. But
since philosophical sagacity thrives on the method of oral interview of presumed sages
whose authenticity cannot be independently verified, what is produced distances itself
from the sages and becomes the fruits of the interviewing philosopher. So the sage
connection and the tradition became defeated. Their enterprise falls within the movement
of Critical Reconstructionism of the later period.
d. Hermeneutical School
Another prominent school is the hermeneutical school. Its focus is that the best approach
to studying African philosophy is through interpretations of oral traditions and emerging
philosophical texts. Theophilus Okere, Okonda Okolo, Tsenay Serequeberhan and
Ademola Fayemi Kazeem are some of the major proponents and members of this school.
The confusion however is that they reject ethnophilosophy whereas the oral tradition and
most of the texts available for interpretation are ethnophilosophical in nature. The works
of Okere and Okolo feasted on ethno-philosophy. This school exemplifies the movement
called Afro-constructionism of the middle period.
e. Literary School
The literary school’s main concern is to make a philosophical presentation of African
cultural values through literary/fictional ways. Proponents like Chinua Achebe, Cheik
Anta Diop, Ngugi wa Thiong’o, Wole Soyinka to name a few have been outstanding. Yet
critics have found it convenient to identify their discourse with ethnophilosophy from
literary angle thereby denigrating it as sub-standard. Their enterprise remarks the
movement of Afro-constructionism of the middle period.
f. Professional School
Perhaps the most controversial is the one variously described as professional, universalist
or modernist school. It contends that all the other schools are engaged in one form of
ethnophilosophy or the other, that standard African philosophy is critical, individual
discourse and that what qualifies as African philosophy must have universal merit and
thrive on the method of critical analysis and individual discursive enterprise. It is not
about talking, it is about doing. Some staunch unrepentant members of this school
include Kwasi Wiredu, Paulin Hountondji, Peter Bodunrin to name a few. They
demolished all that has been built in African philosophy and built nothing as an
alternative episteme. This school champions the movement of Afro-deconstructionism
and the abortive Critical Reconstructionism of the middle and later periods respectively.
Perhaps, one of the deeper criticisms that can be leveled against the position of the
professional school comes from C. S. Momoh’s scornful description of the school as
African logical neo-positivism. They agitate that (1) there is nothing as yet in African
traditional philosophy that qualifies as philosophy and (2) that critical analysis should be
the focus of African philosophy; so what then is there to be critically analyzed?
Professional school adherents are said to forget in their overt copying of European
philosophy that analysis is a recent development in European philosophy which attained
saturation in the 19th
century after over 2000 years of historical evolution thereby
requiring some downsizing. Would they also grant that philosophy in Europe before
19th
century was not philosophy? The aim of this essay is not to offer criticisms of the
schools but to present historical journey of philosophy in the African tradition. It is in
opposition to and the need to fill the lacuna in the enterprise of the professional school
that the new school which can be called conversational school has recently emerged in
African philosophy.
g. Conversational School
This emerging school thrives on fulfilling the yearning of the professional/modernist
school to have a robust individual discourse as well as fulfilling the conviction of the
traditionalists that a thorough-going African philosophy has to be erected on the
foundation of African thought systems. They make the most of the criterion which
presents African philosophy as a critical tradition that prioritizes engagements between
philosophers and cultures and projects individual discourses from the thought system of
Africa. Those whose writings fit into this school include Pantaleon Iroegbu, Innocent
Asouzu, Bruce Janz, Jennifer Vest, Jonathan Chimakonam and Ada Agada to name a few.
Their projects promote partly the movements of Afro-eclecticism and fully the
conversationalism of the later and the new periods respectively.
5. The Movements in African Philosophy
There are four main movements that can be identified in the history of African
philosophy, they include: Excavationism, Afro-constructionism/Afro-deconstructionism,
Critical Reconstructionism/Afro-Eclecticism and Conversationalism.
a. Excavationism
The Excavators are all those who sought to erect the edifice of African philosophy by
systematizing the African cultural world-views. Some of them aimed at retrieving and
reconstructing presumably lost African identity from the raw materials of African culture,
while others sought to develop compatible political ideologies for Africa from the native
political systems of African peoples. Members of this movement have all been grouped
under the school known as ethnophilosophy, and they thrived in the early period of
African philosophy. Their concern was to build and demonstrate unique African identify
in various forms. A few of them include Placid Tempels, Julius Nyerere, John Mbiti, Alexis
Kagame, Leopold Senghor, Kwame Nkrumah and Aime Cesaire.
b. Afro-Constructionism/Afro-Deconstructionism
The Afro-deconstructionists sometimes called the Modernists or the Universalists are
those who sought to demote such edifice erected by the Excavators on the ground that
their raw materials are substandard cultural paraphernalia. They are opposed to the idea
of unique African identity or culture-bound philosophy and preferred a philosophy that
will integrate African identity with the identity of all other races. They never built this
philosophy. Some members of this movement include Paulin Hountondji, Kwasi Wiredu,
Peter Bodunrin, Macien Towa, Fabien Ebousi Boulaga, Richard Wright and Henri
Maurier. Their opponents are the Afro-constructionists, sometimes called the
Traditionalists or Particularists who sought to add rigor and promote the works of the
Excavators as true African philosophy. Some prominent actors in this movement include
Innocent Onyewuenyi, Henry Olela, Lansana Keita, C. S. Momoh, Joseph Omoregbe,
Janheinz Jahn, George James, Sophie Oluwole and, in some ways, Kwame Gyekye.
Members of this twin-movement have variously been grouped under ethnophilosophy,
philosophic sagacity, professional, hermeneutical and literary schools and they thrived in
the middle period of African philosophy. This is also known as the period of the Great
Debate.
c. Critical Reconstructionism/Afro-Eclecticism
A few Afro-deconstructionists of the middle period evolved into Critical
Reconstructionists hoping to reconstruct from the scratch the edifice of authentic African
philosophy that would be critical, individualistic and universal. They hold that the edifice
of ethnophilosophy, which they had demolished in the middle period, contained no
critical rigor. Some of the members of this movement include, Kwasi Wiredu, Olusegun
Oladipo, V. Y. Mudimbe, D. A. Masolo, Odera Oruka and, in some ways, Barry Hallen and
J. O. Sodipo. Their opponents are the Afro-Eclectics who evolved from Afro-
constructionism of the middle period. Unable to sustain their advocacy and the structure
of ethnophilosophy they had constructed, they stepped down a little bit to say, “Maybe we
can combine meaningfully, some of the non-conflicting concerns of the Traditionalists
and the Modernists.” They say (1) that African traditional philosophy is not rigorous
enough as claimed by the Modernists is a fact (2) that the deconstructionist program of
the Modernists did not offer and is incapable of offering an alternative episteme is also a
fact (3) maybe the rigor of the Modernists can be applied on the usable and relevant
elements produced by the Traditionalists to produce the much elusive, authentic African
philosophy. African philosophy for this movement therefore becomes a product of
synthesis resulting from the application of tools of critical reasoning on the relevant
traditions of African life-world. A. F. Uduigwomen, Kwame Gyekye, Ifeanyi Menkiti and
Kwame Appiah are some of the members of this movement. This movement played a vital
reconciliatory role, the importance of which was not fully realized in African philosophy.
Most importantly, they found a way out and laid the foundation for the emergence of
Conversationalism. Members of this twin-movement thrived in the later period of African
philosophy.
d. Conversationalism
The Conversationalists are those who seek to create an enduring corpus in African
philosophy by engaging elements of tradition and individual thinkers in critical
conversations. They emphasize originality, creativity, innovation, peer-criticism and
cross-pollination of ideas in prescribing and evaluating their ideas. They hold that new
episteme in African philosophy can only be created by individual African philosophers
who make use of the “usable past” and the depth of individual originality in finding
solutions to contemporary demands. They do not lay emphasis on analysis alone but also
on critical rigor and what is now called arumaristics—a creative reshuffling of thesis and
anti-thesis that spins out new concepts and thoughts. Members of this movement thrive
in this contemporary period and their school can be called the conversational school.
Some of the philosophers that have demonstrated this trait include Pantaleon Iroegbu,
Innocent Asouzu, Bruce Janz, Jonathan Chimakonam, Ada Agada, Jennifer Lisa Vest, and
so forth.
6. Periods of African Philosophy
a. Early Period
The early period of African philosophy is an era of the movement called
cultural/ideological excavation aimed at retrieving and reconstructing African identity.
The schools that emerged and thrived in this period were ethnophilosophy and
ideological/nationalist schools. The Sub-Saharan Africans, Hegel wrote, had no high
cultures and had made no contributions to world history and civilization (1975: 190).
Lucien Levy Bruhl also added that they are pre-logical and two-third of human (1947: 17).
The summary of these two positions, which represent the colonial mindset, is that
Africans have no dignified identity like their European counterpart. This could be
deciphered in the British colonial system which sought to erode the native thought system
in the constitution of social systems in their colonies and also in the French policy of
assimilation. Assimilation is a concept credited to the French philosopher Chris Talbot
(1837) which rests on the idea of expanding French culture to the colonies outside of
France in the 19th
and 20th
centuries. According to Betts (2005: 8), the natives of these
colonies were considered French citizens as long as the French culture and customs were
adopted to replace the indigenous system. The purpose of the theory of assimilation, for
Michael Lambert, therefore, was to turn African natives into French men by educating
them in the French language and culture (1993: 239-262).
During colonial times, the British, for example, educated their colonies in the British
language and culture, strictly undermining the native languages and cultures. The
products of this new social system were then given the impression that they were British,
though second class, the king was their king, and the empire was also theirs. Suddenly,
however, colonialism ended and they found, to their chagrin, that they were treated as
slave countries in the new post-colonial order. Their native identity had been destroyed
and their fake British identity had also been taken from them; what was left was
amorphous and corrupt. It was in the heat of this confusion and frustration that the
African philosophers sought to retrieve and recreate the original African identity lost in
the event of colonization. Ruch and Anyanwu, therefore, ask, “What is this debate about
African identity concerned with and what led to it? In other words, why should Africans
search for their identity?” Their response to the questions is as follows:
The simple answer to these questions is this: Africans of the first half of this (20th
century)
century have begun to search for their identity, because they had, rightly or wrongly, the
feeling that they had lost it or that they were being deprived of it. The three main factors
which led to this feeling were: slavery, colonialism and racialism. (1981: 184-85)
Racialism, as Ruch and Anyanwu believed, may have sparked it off and slavery may have
dealt the heaviest blow, but it was colonialism that entrenched it. Ironically, it was the
same colonialism at its stylistic conclusion that opened the eyes of the African by stirring
the hornet’s nest. An African can never be a British or French even with the colonially
imposed language and culture. With this shock, the post colonial African philosophers of
the early period set out in search of Africa’s lost identity.
James in 1954 published his monumental work Stolen Legacy. In it, he attempted to prove
that the Egyptians were the true authors of Western philosophy; that Pythagoras,
Socrates, Plato and Aristotle plagiarized the Egyptians; that the authorship of the
individual doctrines of Greek philosophers is a mere speculation perpetuated chiefly by
Aristotle and executed by his school; and that the African continent gave the world its
civilization, knowledge, arts and sciences, religion and philosophy, a fact that is destined
to produce a change in the mentality both of the European and African peoples. In G. M.
James’ words:
In this way, the Greeks stole the legacy of the African continent and called it their own.
And as has already been pointed out, the result of this dishonesty had been the creation
of an enormous world opinion; that the African continent has made no contribution to
civilization, because her people are backward and low in intelligence and culture…This
erroneous opinion about the Black people has seriously injured them through the
centuries up to modern times in which it appears to have reached a climax in the history
of human relations. (1954: 54)
These rugged intellectual positions supported by evidential and well thought-out proofs
quickly heralded a shift in the intellectual culture of the world. But there was one problem
George James could not fix; he could not prove that the people of North Africa (Egyptians)
who were the true authors of ancient art, sciences, religion and philosophy were dark
complexioned Africans, as can be seen in his hopeful but inconsistent conclusions:
This is going to mean a tremendous change in world opinion, and attitude, for all people
and races who accept the new philosophy of Africa redemption, i.e. the truth that the
Greeks were not the authors of Greek philosophy; but the people of North Africa; would
change their opinion from one of disrespect to one of respect for the black people
throughout the world and treat them accordingly. (1954: 153)
It is inconsistent how the achievements of North Africans (Egyptians) can redeem the
black Africans. This is also the problem with Henri Olela’s article “The African
Foundations of Greek Philosophy”.
In Onyewuenyi’s The African Origin of Greek Philosophy however, an ambitious attempt
emerges to fill this lacuna in the argument of new philosophy of African redemption. In
the first part of chapter two, he reduced the Greek philosophy to Egyptian philosophy,
and in the second part, he attempted to further reduce the Egyptians of the time to dark
complexioned Africans. There are, however, two holes he could not fill. First, Egypt is the
world’s oldest standing country who also told their own story by themselves in different
forms. At no point did they or other historians describe them as dark complexioned
people. Second, if the Egyptians were at a time wholly dark complexioned, why are they
now wholly light complexioned? For the failure of this group of scholars to prove that dark
complexioned Africans were the authors of Egyptian philosophy, one must abandon the
Egyptian legacy.
There are however other scholars of the early period who tried in more reliable ways to
assert African identity by establishing native African philosophical heritage. One of such
is Tempels who authored Bantu Philosophy (1949). He proved that rationality was an
important feature of the traditional African culture. By systematizing Bantu philosophical
ideas he confronted the racist orientation of the West which depicted Africa as a continent
of semi-humans. In fact, Tempels showed the latent similarities in the spiritual
inclinations of the Europeans and their African counterpart. In the opening passage of his
work he observed that the European who has taken to atheism quickly returns to a
Christian viewpoint when suffering or pain threatens his survival. In much the same way,
he says the civilized or Christian Bantu returns to the ways of his ancestors when
confronted by suffering and death. So, spiritual orientation or thinking is not found only
in Africa.
In his attempt to explain the Bantu understanding of being, Tempels admits that this
might not be the same with the understanding of the European. Instead, he argues that
the Bantu construction is as much rational as that of the European. In his words:
So the criteriology of the Bantu rests upon external evidence, upon the authority and
dominating life force of the ancestors. It rests at the same time upon the internal evidence
of experience of nature and of living phenomena, observed from their point of view. No
doubt, anyone can show the error of their reasoning; but it must none the less be admitted
that their notions are based on reason, that their criteriology and their wisdom belong to
rational knowledge. (1949/2006: 51)
Tempels obviously believes that the Bantu, like the rest of the African tribes, posses
rationality which undergird their philosophical enterprise. The error in their reasoning is
only obvious in the light of European logic. The Bantu categories only differ from those of
the Europeans, which is why a first-time European on-looker would misinterpret them to
be irrational or spiritual. This effort clearly makes a case for Africa’s true identity, which,
for him, could be found in African religion within which African philosophy (ontology) is
subsumed. In his words, “being is force, force is being”. And the same could be said of
Alexis Kagame’s work The Bantu-Rwandan Philosophy(1956), which offers similar proofs
and arguments thus further strengthening the claims of Tempels, especially from an
African’s perspective. The major criticism against their industry remains the association
of their thoughts with ethnophilosophy, where ethnophilosophy is seen pejoratively. A
much more studded criticism is offered recently by Innocent Asouzu in his
workIbuanyidanda: New Complementary Ontology (2007). His criticism was not directed at
the validity of the thoughts they expressed or whether Africa could boast of a rational
enterprise such as philosophy but at the logical foundation of their thoughts. Asouzu
seems to quarrel with Tempels for allowing his native Aristotelian orientation to influence
his construction of African philosophy and lambasts Kagame for following suit instead of
correcting Tempels’ mistake. The principle of bivalence as evidenced in the Western
thought system was at the background of their construction.
Another important philosopher in this period is John Mbiti. His work African Religions
and Philosophy (1969) avidly educated those who doubted Africans’ possession of their
own identities before the arrival of the European by excavating and demonstrating the
rationality in the religious and philosophical enterprises in African cultures. He boldly
declared: “We shall use the singular, ‘philosophy’ to refer to the philosophical
understanding of African peoples concerning different issues of life” (1969: 2). His
presentation of time in African thought shows off the pattern of excavation in his African
philosophy. Although his studies focus primarily on the Kikamba and Gikuyu tribes of
Africa, he observes that there are similarities in many African cultures just as Tempels did
earlier. He subsumes African philosophy in African religion on the assumption that
African peoples do not know how to exist without religion. This idea is also shared by
William Abraham in his book The Mind of Africa as well as Tempels’ Bantu Philosophy.
African philosophy, from Mbiti’s treatment, could be likened to Tempels’ vital force, of
which African religion is its outer cloak. The obvious focus of this book is on African views
about God, political thought, afterlife, culture or world-view and creation, the
philosophical aspects lie within these religious over-coats. Thus, Mbiti establishes that
the true, and lost, identity of the African could be found within his religion. Another
important observation Mbiti made was that this identity is communal and not
individualistic. Hence, he states, “I am because we are and since we are therefore I am”
(1969: 108). Therefore, the African has to re-enter his religion to find his philosophy and
the community to find his identity.
This is a view shared by William Abraham in his The Mind of Africa (1962). He shares
Tempels’ and Mbiti’s views that the dark complexioned African tribes have many
similarities in their culture, though his studies focus on the culture and political thought
of the Akan of present day Ghana. Another important aspect of Abraham’s work is that he
subsumed African philosophical thought in African culture taking, as Barry Hallen
described, “an essentialist interpretation of African culture” (2002: 15). Thus for
Abraham, like Tempels and Mbiti, the lost African identity could be found in the seabed
of African indigenous culture in which religion features prominently.
On the other hand, there were those who sought to retrieve and establish once again
Africa’s lost identity through economic and political ways. Some names discussed here
include Kwame Nkrumah, Leopold Senghor and Julius Nyerere. These actors felt that the
African could never be truly decolonized unless he found his own system of living and
social organization. One cannot be African living like the European. The question that
guided their study therefore became, “What system of economic and social engineering
will suit us and project our true identity?” Nkrumah advocates African socialism, which,
according to Barry Hallen, is an original, social, political and philosophical theory of
African origin and orientation. This system is forged from the traditional, communal
structure of African society, a view strongly projected by Mbiti. Nkrumah says that a
return to African cultural system with its astute moral values, communal ownership of
land and a humanitarian social and political engineering holds the key to Africa
rediscovering her lost identity. Systematizing this process, will yield what he calls the
African brand of socialism. In most of his books, he projects the idea that Africa’s lost
identity is to be found in African native culture within which is African philosophical
thought and identity shaped by communal orientation. Some of his works include, Neo-
colonialism: The Last Stage of Imperialism (1965), I Speak of Freedom: A Statement of African
Ideology (1961), Africa Must Unite (1970), and Consciencism (1954).
Leopold Sedar Senghor of Senegal charted a course similar to that of Nkrumah. In his
works Negritude et Humanisme (1964) and Negritude and the Germans (1967), Senghor traced
Africa’s philosophy of social engineering down to African culture, which he said is
communal and laden with brotherly emotion. This is different from the European system,
which he says is individualistic, having been marshaled purely by reason. He opposed the
French colonial principle of assimilation aimed at turning Africans into Frenchmen by
eroding and replacing African culture with French culture. African culture and languages
are the bastions of African identity, and it is in this culture that he found the pedestal for
constructing a political ideology that would project African lost identity. Senghor is in
agreement with Nkrumah, Mbiti, Abraham and Tempels in many ways, especially with
regards to the basis for Africa’s true identity.
Julius Nyerere of Tanzania is another philosopher of note in the early period of African
philosophy. In his books Uhuru na Ujamaa: Freedom and Socialism (1964) and Ujamaa: The
Basis of African Socialism (1968), he sought to retrieve and establish African true identity
through economic and political ways. For him, Africans cannot regain their identity
unless they are first free and freedom (Uhuru) transcends independence. Cultural
imperialism has to be overcome. And what is the best way to achieve this if not by
developing a socio-political and economic ideology from the petals of African native
culture, and traditional values of togetherness and brotherliness? Hence, Nyerere
proposes Ujamaa, meaning familyhood—the “being-with” philosophy or the “we” instead
of the “I—spirit” (Okoro 2004: 96). In the words of Barry Hallen, “Nyerere argued that
there was a form of life and system of values indigenous to the culture of pre-colonial
Africa, Tanzania in particular, that was distinctive if not unique and that had survived the
onslaughts of colonialism sufficiently intact to be regenerated as the basis for an African
polity” (2002: 74). Thus for Nyerere, the basis of African identity is the African culture,
which is communal rather than individualistic. Nyerere was in agreement with other
actors of this period on the path to full recovery of Africa’s lost identity. Other
philosophers of this era not treated here include Nnamdi Azikiwe, Obafemi Awolowo,
Amilcar Cabral, and the two foreigners, Janheinz Jahn and Marcel Griaule.
b. Middle Period
The middle period of African philosophy is also an era of the twin-movement called Afro-
constructionism and afro-deconstructionism, otherwise called the Great Debate, when
two rival schools—Traditionalists and Universalists clashed. While the Traditionalists
sought to construct an African identity based on excavated African cultural elements, the
Universalists sought to demolish such architectonic structure by associating it with
ethnophilosophy. The schools that thrived in this era include Philosophic Sagacity,
Professional/Modernist/Universalist, hermeneutical and Literary schools.
An important factor of the early period is that the thoughts on the basis for Africa’s true
identity generated arguments that fostered the emergence of the Middle Period of African
philosophy. These arguments result from questions that could be summarized as follows:
(1) Is it proper to take for granted the sweeping assertion that all of Africa’s cultures share
a few basic elements in common? It was this assumption that had necessitated the favorite
phrase in the early period, “African philosophy,” rather than “African philosophies”. (2)
Does Africa or African culture contain a philosophy in the strict sense of the term? (3) Can
African philosophy emerge from the womb of African religion, world-view and culture?
Answers and objections to answers soon took the shape of a debate, characterizing the
middle period as the era of the Great Debate in African philosophy.
This debate was between members of Africa’s new crop of intellectual radicals. On one
hand, are the demoters and, on the other, are the promoters of African philosophy
established by the league of early period intellectuals. The former sought to criticize this
new philosophy of redemption, gave it a derogatory tag “ethnophilosophy” and
consequently denigrated the African Identity that was founded on it as savage and
primitive identity. At the other end, the promoters sought to clarify and defend this
philosophy and justify the African identity that was rooted in it as true and original.
For clarity, the assessment of the debate era will begin from the middle instead of the
beginning. In 1978 Odera Oruka a Kenyan philosopher presented a paper at the William
Amo Symposium held in Accra, Ghana on the topic “Four Trends in Current African
Philosophy” in which he identified or grouped voices on African philosophy into four
schools, namely ethnophilosophy, philosophic sagacity, nationalistic-ideological school
and professional philosophy. In 1990 he wrote another work, Sage Philosophy: Indigenous
Thinker and the Modern Debate on African Philosophy in which he further added two schools
to bring the number to six schools in African philosophy. Those two additions are the
hermeneutic and the artistic/literary schools.
Those who uphold philosophy in African culture are the ethnophilosophers and these
include the actors treated as members of the early period of African philosophy and their
followers or supporters in the Middle Period. These would include C. S. Momoh, Joseph
Omoregbe, Lansana Keita, Olusegun Oladipo, Gordon Hunnings, Kwame Gyekye, M. A.
Makinde, Emmanuel Edeh, Uzodinma Nwala, K. C. Anyanwu and later E. A. Ruch, to
name a few. The philosophic sagacity school, to which Oruka belongs, also accommodates
C. S. Momoh, C. B. Nze, J. I. Omoregbe, C. B. Okolo and T. F. Mason. The nationalist-
ideological school consists of those who sought to develop indigenous socio-political and
economic ideologies for Africa. Prominent members include Julius Nyerere, Leopold
Senghor, Kwame Nkrumah, Amilcar Cabral, Nnamdi Azikiwe and Obafemi Awolowo. The
professional philosophy school insists that African philosophy must be done with
professional philosophical methods such as analysis, critical reflection and logical
coherence as it is in Western philosophy. Members of this school include: Henri Maurier,
Richard Wright, Peter Bodunrin, Kwasi Wiredu, early E. A. Ruch, R. Horton, and later C.
B. Okolo. The hermeneutic school recommends linguistic analysis as a method of doing
African philosophy. A few of its members include Theophilus Okere, Okonda Okolo,
Tsenay Serequeberhan, Godwin Sogolo and partly J. Sodipo and B. Hallen. The
Artistic/Literary school philosophically discusses the core of African norms, and includes
Chinua Achebe, Okot P’Bitek, Ngugi wa Thiong’o, Wole Soyinka, Elechi Amadi and F. C.
Ogbalu.
Also, in 1989, C. S. Momoh in his The Substance of African Philosophy outlined five schools,
namely African logical neo-positivism, the colonial/missionary school of thought, the
Egyptological school, the ideological school and the purist school. The article was titled
“Nature, Issues and Substance of African Philosophy” and was reproduced in Jim
Unah’s Metaphysics, Phenomenology and African Philosophy (1996).
In comparing Momoh’s delineations with Oruka’s, it can be said that the purist school
encompasses Oruka’s ethnophilosophy, artistic/literary school and philosophic sagacity;
The African logical neo-positivism encompasses professional philosophy and the
hermeneutical schools; and the ideological and colonial/missionary schools correspond
to Oruka’s nationalistic-ideological school. The Egyptological school, therefore, remains
outstanding. Momoh sees it as a school which sees African philosophy as synonymous
with Egyptian philosophy or at least, as originating from it. Also, Egyptian philosophy as
a product of African philosophy is also expressed in the writings of George James, I. C.
Onyewuenyi and Henry Olela.
Welding all these divisions together are the perspectives of Peter Bodunrin and Kwasi
Wiredu. In the introduction to his 1985 edited volume Philosophy in Africa: Trends and
Perspectives, Bodunrin created two broad schools for all the subdivisions in both Oruka
and Momoh, namely the Traditionalist and Modernist schools. While the former includes
Africa’s rich culture and past, the latter excludes them from the mainstream of African
philosophy. Kwasi Wiredu also made this type of division, specifically Traditional and
Modernist, in his paper “On Defining African Philosophy” in C. S. Momoh’s (1989) edited
volume. Also, A. F. Uduigwomen created two broad schools, namely the Universalists and
the Particularists, in his “Philosophy and the Place of African Philosophy” (1995). These
can be equated to Bodunrin’s Modernist and Traditionalist schools respectively. The
significance of his contribution to the Great Debate rests on the new school he evolved
from the compromise of the Universalist and the Particularist schools (1995/2009: 2-7).
As Uduigwomen defines it, the Eclectic school accommodates discourses pertaining to
African experiences, culture and world-view as parts of African philosophy. Those
discourses must be critical, argumentative and rational. In other words, the so-called
ethnophilosophy can comply with the analytic and argumentative standards that people
like Bodunrin, Hountondji, and Wiredu insist upon. Many later African philosophers
revived Uduigwomen’s Eclectic school as a much more decisive approach to African
philosophy (Kanu 2013: 275-87). It is the era dominated by Eclecticism and meta-
philosophy that is tagged the ‘Later period’ in the history of African philosophy. For
perspicuity therefore, the debate from these two broad schools shall be addressed as the
perspectives of the Traditionalist or Particularist and the Modernist or Universalist.
The reader must now have understood the perspectives on which the individual
philosophers of the middle period debated. Hence, when Richard Wright published his
critical essay “Investigating African Philosophy” and Henri Maurier published his “Do we
have an African Philosophy?” denying the existence of African philosophy at least, as yet,
the reader understands why Lansana Keita’s “The African Philosophical Tradition”, C. S.
Momoh’s African Philosophy … does it exist?” or J. I. Omoregbe’s “African Philosophy:
Yesterday and Today” are offered as critical responses. When Wright arrived at the
conclusion that the problems surrounding the study of African philosophy are so great
that others are effectively prevented from any worthwhile work until their resolution,
Henri Maurier responded to the question, “Do we have an African Philosophy?” with “No!
Not Yet!” (1984: 25). One would understand why Lansana Keita took it up to provide
concrete evidence that Africa had and still has a philosophical tradition. In his words:
It is the purpose of this paper to present evidence that a sufficiently firm literate
philosophical tradition has existed in Africa since ancient times, and that this tradition is
of sufficient intellectual sophistication to warrant serious analysis…it is rather…an
attempt to offer a defensible idea of African philosophy. (1984: 58)
Keita went on in that paper to excavate intellectual resources to prove his case, but it was
J. I. Omoregbe who tackled the demoters on every front. Of particular interest are his
critical commentaries on the position of Kwasi Wiredu and others who share Wiredu’s
opinion that what is called African philosophy is not philosophy but community thought
at best. Omoregbe alludes that the logic and method of African philosophy need not be
the same as those of Western philosophy, which the demoters cling to. In his words:
It is not necessary to employ Aristotelian or the Russellian logic in this reflective activity
before one can be deemed to be philosophizing. It is not necessary to carry out this
reflective activity in the same way that the Western thinkers did. Ability to reason logically
and coherently is an integral part of man’s rationality. The power of logical thinking is
identical with the power of rationality. It is therefore false to say that people cannot think
logically or reason coherently unless they employ Aristotle’s or Russell’s form of logic or
even the Western-type argumentation. (1998: 4-5)
Omoregbe was addressing the position of most members of the Modernist school who
believed that African philosophy must follow the pattern of Western philosophy if it were
to exist. As he cautions:
Some people, trained in Western philosophy and its method, assert that there is no
philosophy and no philosophizing outside the Western type of philosophy or the Western
method of philosophizing (which they call “scientific” or “technical”. (1998: 5)
Philosophers like E. A. Ruch in some of his earlier writings,, Peter Bodunrin, C. B. Okolo,
and Robin Horton were direct recipients of Omoregbe’s sledge hammer. Robin Horton’s
“African Traditional Thought and Western Science” is a two part essay that sought in the
long run to expose the rational ineptitude in African thought. On the question of logic in
African philosophy, Robin Horton’s “Traditional Thought and the emerging African
Philosophy Department: A Comment on the Current Debate” first stirred the hornet’s nest
and was ably challenged by Godorn Hunnings’ “Logic, Language and Culture”, as well as
by Omoregbe’s “African Philosophy: Yesterday and Today”. Earlier, Meinrad Hebga’s
“Logic in Africa” had made insightful ground clearing on the matter. Recently, C.S.
Momoh’s “The Logic Question in African Philosophy” and Udo Etuk’s “The Possibility of
an African Logic” as well as Jonathan C. Okeke’s “Why can’t there be an African Logic”
made impressions. However, this logic question is gathering new momentum in African
philosophical discourse.
On the philosophical angle, Kwasi Wiredu’s “How not to Compare African Traditional
Thought with Western Thought” responded to the lopsided earlier effort of Robin Horton
but ended up making its own criticisms of the status of African philosophy which, for
Wiredu, is yet to attain maturation. In his words, “[M]any traditional African institutions
and cultural practices, such as the ones just mentioned, are based on superstition. By
‘superstition’ I mean a rationally unsupported belief in entities of any sort (1976: 4-8 and
1995: 194).” In his Philosophy and an African Culture, Wiredu was more pungent. He
caricatured much of the discourse on African philosophy as community thought or folk
thought unqualified to be called philosophy. For him, there had to be a practiced
distinction between “African philosophy as folk thought preserved in oral traditions and
African philosophy as critical, individual reflection, using modern logical and conceptual
techniques” (1980: 14). Olusegun Oladipo supports this in his Philosophy and the African
Experience. As he puts it:
But this kind of attitude is mistaken. In Africa we are engaged in the task of the
improvement of “the condition of men”. There can be no successful execution of this task
without a reasonable knowledge of, and control over, nature. But essential to the quest
for knowledge of, and control over, nature are “logical, mathematical and analytical
procedures” which are products of modern intellectual practices. The glorification of the
“unanalytical cast of mind” which a conception of African philosophy as African folk
thought encourages would not avail us the opportunity of taking advantage of the
theoretical and practical benefits offered by these intellectual procedures. It thus can only
succeed in making the task of improving the condition of man in Africa a daunting
one.(1996: 15)
Oladipo also shares similar thoughts in his The Idea of African Philosophy. African
philosophy for some of the Modernists is practiced in a debased sense. This position is
considered opinionated by the Traditionalists. Later E. A. Ruch and K. C. Anyanwu in
their African Philosophy: An Introduction to the Main Philosophical Trends in Contemporary
Africa attempt to excavate the philosophical elements in folklore and myth. C. S. Momoh’s
“The Mythological Question in African Philosophy” and K. C. Anyanwu’s “Philosophical
Significance of Myth and Symbol in Dogon World-View” further reinforced the position
of the Traditionalists.(cf. Momoh 1989 and Anyanwu 1989)
However, it took Paulin Hountondji in his African Philosophy: Myth and Reality to drive a
long nail in the coffin. African philosophy, for him, must be done in the same frame as
Western philosophy, including its principles, methodologies, methods and all. K. C.
Anyanwu again admitted that Western philosophy is one of the challenges facing African
philosophy but that only calls for systematization of African philosophy not its
decimation. He made these arguments in his paper “The Problem of Method in African
philosophy”.
Other arguments set Greek standards for authentic African philosophy as can be found in
Odera Oruka’s “The Fundamental Principles in the Question of ‘African Philosophy’ (I)”
and Hountondji’s “African Wisdom and Modern Philosophy.” They readily met with
Lansana Keita’s “African Philosophical Systems: A Rational Reconstruction”, J.
Kinyongo’s “Philosophy in Africa: An Existence” and even P. K. Roy’s “African Theory of
Knowledge”. For every step the Modernists took, the Traditionalists replied with two, a
response that lingered till the early 1990’s when a certain phase of disillusionment began
to set in to quell the debate. Actors on both fronts had only then begun to reach a new
consciousness, realizing that a new step had to be taken beyond the debate. Even Kwasi
Wiredu who had earlier justified the debate by his insistence that “without argument and
clarification, there is strictly no philosophy” (1980: 47) had to admit that it was time to
do something else. For him, African philosophers had to go beyond talking about African
philosophy and get down to actually doing it.
It was with this sort of new orientation which emerged from the disillusionment of the
protracted debate that the later period of African philosophy was born in the 1980’s. As it
is said in the Igbo proverb, “The music makers almost unanimously were changing the
rhythm and the dancers had to change their dance steps.” One of the high points of the
disillusionment was the emergence of the Eclectic school in the next period called ‘the
Later Period’ of African philosophy.
c. Later Period
This period of African philosophy heralds the emergence of the movements which can be
called Critical Reconstructionism and Afro-Eclecticism. For the Deconstructionists of the
middle period, the focus shifted from deconstruction to reconstruction of African
episteme in a universally integrated way; whereas, for the eclectics, finding a reconcilable
middle path between traditional African philosophy and the modern African philosophy
should be paramount. Thus they advocate a shift from entrenched ethnophilosophy and
universal hue to the reconstruction of African episteme if somewhat different from the
imposed Westernism and the uncritical ethnophilosophy. So, both the Critical
Reconstructionists and the Eclectics advocate one form of reconstruction or the other.
The former desire a new episteme untainted by ethnophilosophy while the later sue for
reconciled central and relevant ideals.
Not knowing how to proceed to this sort of task was a telling problem on all advocates of
critical reconstruction in African philosophy such as V. Y. Mudimbe, Ebousi Boulaga,
Olusegun Oladipo, Franz Crahey and Marcien Towa to name a few. At the dawn of the
era, these African legionnaires pointed out, in different terms, that reconstructing African
episteme was imperative. But more urgent was the need to first analyse the haggard
philosophical structure patched into existence with the cement of perverse dialogues. It
appeared inexorable to these thinkers and others of the time that none of these can be
successful outside the shadow of Westernism. For whatever one writes which is effectively
free from ethnophilosophy is either contained in Western discourse or in the very least
proceeds from its logic. If it is already contained in Western narrative or proceeds from
its logic, what then makes it African? This became a something of a dead-end for this
illustrious group, which struggled against evolutions in their positions.
Intuitively, almost every analyst knows that discussing what has been discussed in
Western philosophy or taking a lead from Western philosophy does not absolutely negate
or vitiate what is produced as African philosophy. But how is this to be effectively
justified? This appears to be the Achilles heel of the Critical Reconstructionists of the later
period in African philosophy. The massive failure of these Critical Reconstructionists to
go beyond the lines of recommendation and actually engage in reconstructing delayed
their emergence as a school of thought in African philosophy. The diversionary matrix
which occurred at this point ensured that the later period, which began with the two rival
camps of Critical Reconstructionists and Eclectics, ended with only the Eclectics left
standing. Thus dying in its embryo, Critical Reconstructionism became absorbed in
Eclecticism.
The campaign for Afro-reconstructionism had first emerged in the late 1980‘s in the
writings of Peter Bodunrin, Kwasi Wiredu, V. Y. Mudimbe and Olusegun Oladipo, even
though principals like Marcien Towa and Franz Crahey had hinted at it much earlier. The
insights of the latter two never rang bells beyond the ear-shot of identity reconstruction,
which was the echo of their time. Wiredu’s cry for conceptual decolonization and
Hountondji’s call for the abandonment of the ship of ethnophilosophy were in the spirit
of Afro-reconstructionism of the episteme. None of the Afro-reconstructionists except for
Wiredu was able to truly chart a course for reconstruction. His was linguistic even though
the significance of his campaign was never truly appreciated. His 1998 work “Toward
Decolonizing African Philosophy and Religion,” was a clearer recapitulation of his works of
preceding years.
Beyond this modest line, no other reconstructionist crusader of the time actually went
beyond deconstruction and problem identification. Almost spontaneously, Afro-
reconstructionism evolved into Afro-eclecticism in the early 1990’s when the emerging
Critical Reconstructionism ran into a brick wall of inactivity. The argument seems to say,
“If it is not philosophically permissible to employ alternative logic different from the one
in the West or methods, perhaps we can make do with the merger of the approaches we
have identified in African philosophy following the deconstructions.” These approaches
are the various schools of thought from ethnophilosophy, philosophic sagacity,
ideological school, universal, literary to hermeneutic schools which were deconstructed
into two broad approaches namely: The traditionalist school and the modernist school
also called the particularist and the universalist schools.
Eclectics, therefore, are those who think that the effective integration or complementation
of the African native system and the Western system could produce a viable synthesis that
is first African and then modern. Andrew Uduigwomen, the Nigerian philosopher could
be regarded as the founder of this school in African philosophy. In his 1995
work “Philosophy and the Place of African Philosophy,” he gave official birth to the Afro-
eclecticism. Identifying the Traditionalist and Modernist schools as the Particularist and
Universalist schools, he created the eclectic school by carefully unifying their goals from
the ruins of the deconstructed past.
Uduigwomen states that the eclectic school holds that an intellectual romance between
the Universalist conception and the Particularist conception will give rise to an authentic
African philosophy. The Universalist approach will provide the necessary analytic and
conceptual framework for the Particularist school. Since, according to Uduigwomen, this
framework cannot thrive in a vacuum, the Particularist approach will in turn supply the
raw materials or indigenous data needed by the Universalist approach. From the
submission of Uduigwomen above, one easily detects that Eclecticism for him entails
employing Western methods in analyzing African cultural paraphernalia.
However, Afro-Eclecticism is not without problems. The first problem though, is that he
did not supply the yardstick for determining what is to be admitted and what must be left
out of the corpus of African tradition. Everything cannot meet the standard of genuine
philosophy, nor should the philosophical selection be arbitrary. Hountondji, a chronic
critic of traditional efforts once called Tempels’ Bantu philosophy a sham. For him, it was
not African or Bantu philosophy but Tempels’ philosophy with African paraphernalia.
This could be extended to the vision of Afro-eclecticism. On the contrary, it could be
argued that if Hountondji agrees that the synthesis contains as little as African
paraphernalia, then it is something new and in this respect can claim the tag of African
philosophy. However, it leaves to be proven how philosophical that little African
paraphernalia is.
Other notable eclectics include Batholomew Abanuka, Udobata Onunwa, C. C. Ekwealor
and much later Chris Ijiomah. Abanuka posits in his 1994 work that a veritable way to
doing authentic African philosophy would be to recognize the unity of individual things
and, by extension, theories in ontology, epistemology or ethics. There is a basic identity
among these because they are connected and can be unified. Following C. S. Momoh
(1985: 12), Abanuka went on in A History of African Philosophy to argue that synthesis
should be the ultimate approach to doing African Philosophy. This position is shared by
Onunwa on a micro level. He says that realities in African world-view are inter-connected
and inter-dependent (1991: 66-71). Ekwealor and Ijiomah also believe in synthesis, noting
that these realities are broadly dualistic, being physical and spiritual (cf. Ekwalor 1990:
30 and Ijiomah 2005: 76 and 84). So, it would be an anomaly to think of African
philosophy as chiefly an exercise in analysis rather than synthesis. The ultimate
methodological approach to doing African philosophy, therefore, has to reflect unity of
methods above all else.
Eclecticism survived in the New Era of African philosophy in conversational forms.
Godfrey Ozumba and Jonathan Chimakonam on Njikoka philosophy, E. G. Ekwuru and
later Innocent Egwutuorah on Afrizealotism and even Innocent Asouzu on Ibuanyidanda
ontology are all various forms of eclectic thinking. However, these theories are grouped
in the New Era specifically for the time of their emergence and the conversational
structure they have.
The purest development of eclectic thinking in the later period could be found in
Pantaleon Iroegbu’s Uwa Ontology. He posits uwa (worlds) as an abstract generic concept
with fifteen connotations and six zones. Everything is uwa, in uwa and can be known
through uwa. For him, while the fifteen connotations are the different senses and aspects
which uwa concept carries in Igbo-African thought, the six zones are the spatio-temporal
locations of the worlds in terms of their inhabitants. He adds that these six zones are
dualistic and comprise of the earthly and the spiritual. They are also dynamic and
mutually related. Thus, Iroegbu suggests that the approach to doing authentic African
philosophy could consist in the conglomeration of uwa. This demonstrates a veritable
Eclectic method in African philosophy.
However, one of the major hindrances of Eclecticism of the later period is that it leads
straight to applied philosophy. Following this approach in this period almost makes it
impossible for second readers to do original and abstract philosophizing for its own sake.
Eclectic theories and methods confine one to their internal dynamics believing that for a
work to be regarded as authentic African philosophy, it must follow the rules of
Eclecticism. The wider implication is that while creativity might blossom, innovation and
originality are stifled. Because of pertinent problems such as these, further evolutions in
African philosophy became inevitable. The Kenyan philosopher Odera Oruka had
magnified the thoughts concerning individual rather than group philosophizing, thoughts
that had been variously expressed earlier by Peter Bodunrin, Paulin Hountondji and
Kwasi Wiredu, who further admonished African philosophers to stop talking and start
doing African philosophy. And V. Y. Mudimbe, in his The Invention of Africa…, suggested
the development of an African conversational philosophy, and the reinvention of Africa
by its philosophers, to undermine the Africa that Europe invented. The content of Lewis
Gordon’s essay “African Philosophy’s search for Identity: Existential consideration of a
recent effort” suggests a craving for a new line of development for African philosophy—a
new approach which is to be critical, engaging and universal while still being African. This,
in particular, is the spirit of the conversational African philosophy beginning to grip
African philosophers in late 1990’s when Gordon wrote his paper. Influences from these
thoughts by the turn of the millennium year crystallized into a new mode of thinking,
which then metamorphosed into conversational philosophy. The New Era in African
philosophy was thus heralded. The focus of this New Era and the orientation became the
conversational philosophy.
d. New Era
This period of African philosophy began in the late 1990’s and took shape by the turn of
the millennium years. The orientation of this period is conversational philosophy, so,
conversationalism is the movement that thrives in this period. The University of Calabar
has emerged as the international headquarters of this new movement hosting various
workshops, colloquia and conferences in African philosophy under the auspices of a
radical forum called The Conversational/Calabar School of Philosophy. In the Calabar
School of Philosophy, some prominent theories have emerged, namely ibuanyidanda
(complementary reflection) (Innocent Asouzu), harmonious monism (Chris Ijiomah),
Njikoka philosophy (Godfrey Ozumba and Jonathan Chimakonam) and conversational
philosophy (Jonathan Chimakonam). All these theories speak to the method of
conversational philosophy. Conversational philosophy is defined by the active
engagement between individual African philosophers in the creation of critical narratives
either by engaging the elements of tradition or straight-forwardly by producing new
thoughts or by engaging other individual thinkers. It thrives on incessant questioning
geared toward the production of new concepts, opening up new vistas and sustaining the
conversation.
Some of the African philosophers whose works follow this trajectory ironically have
emerged in the Western world, notably in America. The American philosopher Jennifer
Lisa Vest is one of them. Another one is Bruce Janz. These two, to name a few, suggest
that the highest purification of African philosophy is to be realized in the conversational-
styled philosophizing. However, it was the Nigerian philosopher Innocent Asouzu who
went beyond the earlier botched attempt of Leopold Senghor and transcended the
foundations of Pantaleon Iroegbu to erect a new model of African philosophy that is
conversational. The New Era, therefore, is the beginning of conversational philosophy.
Iroegbu in his Metaphysics: The Kpim of Philosophy inaugurated the reconstructive and
conversational approach in African philosophy. He engaged previous writers in a critical
conversation out of which he produced his own thought, (Uwa ontology) bearing the stain
of African tradition and thought systems but remarkably different in approach and
method of ethnophilosophy. Franz Fanon has highlighted the importance of sourcing
African philosophical paraphernalia from African indigenous culture. This is
corroborated in a way by Lucius Outlaw in his African Philosophy: Deconstructive and
Reconstructive Challenges. In it, Outlaw advocates the deconstruction of the European-
invented Africa to be replaced by a reconstruction to be done by conscientious Africans
free from the grip of colonial mentality (1996: 11). Whereas the Wiredu’s crusade sought
to deconstruct the invented Africa, actors in the New Era of African philosophy seek to
reconstruct through conversational approach.
Iroegbu inaugurated this drive but it was Asouzu who has made the most of it. His theory
of Ibuanyidanda ontology or complementary reflection maintains that “to be” simply
means to be in a mutual, complementary relationship (2007: 251-55). Every being,
therefore, is a variable with capacity to join a mutual interaction. In this capacity every
being alone is seen as a missing link and serving a missing link of reality in the network
of realities. One immediately suspects the apparent contradiction that might arise from
the fusion of two opposed variables when considered logically. But the logic of this theory
is not the two-valued classical logic but the three-valued system of logic developed in
Africa (cf. Chimakonam 2012, 2013 and 2014a). In this, the two standard values are sub-
contraries rather than contradictories thereby facilitating effective complementation of
variables. The possibility of the two standard values merging to form the third value in
the complementary mode is what makes Ezumezu logic a powerful tool of thought.
A good number of African philosophers are tuning their works into the pattern of
conversational philosophy. In the southern Africa, Mogobe Ramose, Michael Eze, Fainos
Mangena, Thaddeus Metz and Leonhard Praeg are doing this when they engage with the
idea of ubuntu ethics and ontology. Like all these thinkers, the champions of the new
conversational orientation are building the new edifice by reconstructing the
deconstructed domain of thought in the later period of African philosophy. The central
approach is conversation. By engaging other African philosophers or tradition in critical
and positive discourses, they hope to reconstruct the deconstructed edifice of African
philosophy. Hence, the New Era of African philosophy is safe from the retrogressive,
perverse dialogues which characterized the early and middle periods.
Also, with the critical deconstruction that occurred in the later part of the middle period
and the attendant eclecticism that emerged in the later period, the stage was set for the
formidable reconstructions and conversational encounters that marked the arrival of the
New Era of African philosophy.
7. Conclusion
The development of African philosophy through the periods yields two vital conceptions
for African philosophy, namely that African philosophy is a critical engagement of
tradition and individual thinkers on one hand, and on the other hand it is also a critical
construction of futurity. When individual African philosophers engage tradition critically
in order to ascertain its logical coherency and universal validity, they are doing African
philosophy. And when they employ the tools of logic in doing this, they are doing African
philosophy. On the second conception, when African philosophers engage in critical
conversations with one another and in construction of new thoughts in matters that
concern Africa but which are nonetheless universal and projected from African native
thought systems, they are doing African philosophy. So, the authentic African philosophy
is not just a future project, it can also continue from the past.
On the whole, this essay discussed the journey of African philosophy from the beginning
and focused on the criteria, schools and movements in African philosophical tradition.
The historical account of the periods in African philosophy began with the early period
through to the middle, the later and finally the new periods of African philosophy have
also been covered taking particular interest in the robust, individual contributions. There
are still some questions which trail the development of African philosophy, many of which
include, “Must African philosophy be tailored to the pattern of Western philosophy, even
in less definitive issues? If African philosophy is found to be different in approach from
Western philosophy, — so what? Are logical issues likely to play any major roles in the
structure and future of African philosophy? What is the future direction of African
philosophy? Is the problem of the language of African philosophy pregnant? Would
conversations in contemporary African philosophy totally eschew perverse dialogue?
What shall be the rules of engagement in African philosophy?” These questions are likely
to shape the next lines of thought in African philosophy.
8. References and Further Reading
 Abanuka, Batholomew. A History of African Philosophy. Enugu: Snaap Press, 2011.
 An epochal discussion of African philosophy.
 Abraham, William. The Mind of Africa. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1962.
 A philosophical discussion of culture, African thought and colonial times.
 Achebe, Chinua. Morning yet on Creation Day. London: Heinemann, 1975.
 A philosophical treatment of African tradition and colonial burden.
 Anyanwu, K. C. “Philosophical Significance of Myth and Symbol in Dogon World-view”. C. S. Momoh
ed. The Substance of African Philosophy. Auchi: APP Publications, 1989
 A discussion of the philosophical elements in an African culture.
 Aristotle. Metaphysica, Translated into English under the editorship of W. D. Ross, M.A., Hon. LL.D (Edin.)
Oxford. Vol. VIII, Second Edition, OXFORD at the Clarendon Press 1926. Online Edition. 982b.
 A translation of Aristotle’s treatise on metaphysics.
 Asouzu I. Innocent. Ibuanyidanda: New Complementary Ontology Beyond World-Immanentism, Ethnocentric
Reduction and Impositions. Litverlag, Münster, Zurich, New Brunswick, London, 2007
 An African perspective treatment of metaphysics or the theory of complementarity of beings.
 Babalola, Yai. “Theory and Practice in African Philosophy: The Poverty of Speculative Philosophy. A Review
of the Work of P. Hountondji, M. Towa, et al.” Second Order, 2. 2. 1977
 A Critical review of Hountondji and Towa.
 Betts, Raymond. Assimilation and Association in French Colonial Territory 1890 to 1915. (First ed. 1961),
Reprinted. Nebraska: University of Nebraska Press, 2005
 A discourse on French colonial policies.
 Bodunrin, Peter. “The Question of African Philosophy”. Richard Wright (ed) African Philosophy: An
Introduction 3rd
ed. Lanham: UPA, 1984.
 A discourse on the nature and universal conception of African philosophy.
 Cesaire Aimer. Return to My Native Land. London: Penguin Books, 1969
 A presentation of colonial impact on the mind of the colonized.
 Chimakonam, O. Jonathan. “Ezumezu: A Variant of Three-valued Logic—Insights and Controversies”. Paper
presented at the Annual Conference of the Philosophical Society of Southern Africa. Free State University,
Bloemfontein, South Africa. Jan. 20-22, 2014.
 An articulation of the structure of Ezumezu/African logic tradition.
 Chimakonam, O. Jonathan.“Principles of Indigenous African Logic: Toward Africa’s Development and
Restoration of African Identity” Paper presented at the 19th
Annual Conference of International Society for
African Philosophy and Studies [ISAPS], ‘50 Years of OAU/AU: Revisiting the Questions of African Unity,
Identity and Development’. Department of Philosophy, Nnamdi Azikiwe University, Awka. 27th
– 29th
May,
2013
 A presentation of the principles of Ezumezu/African logic tradition.
 Chimakonam, O. Jonathan.“Integrative Humanism: Extensions and Clarifications”. Integrative Humanism
Journal. 3.1, 2013.
 Further discussions on the theory of integrative humanism.
 Du Bois, W. E. B. The Souls of Black Folk. (1903). New York: Bantam Classic edition, 1989
 A discourse on race and cultural imperialism.
 Edeh, Emmanuel. Igbo Metaphysics. Chicago: Loyola University Press, 1985.
 An Igbo-African discourse on the nature being.
 Ekwealor, C. “The Igbo World-View: A General Survey”. The Humanities and All of Us.
 Emeka Oguegbu (ed) Onitsha: Watchword, 1990.
 A philosophical presentation of Igbo life-world.
 Etuk, Udo. “The Possibility of African logic”. The Third Way in African Philosophy, Olusegun Oladipo (ed).
Ibadan: Hope Publications, 2002
 A discussion of the nature and possibility of African logic.
 Franz, Fanon. The Wretched of the Earth. London: The Chaucer Press, 1965.
 A critical discourse on race and colonialism.
 Graiule, Marcel. Conversations with Ogotemmêli, London: Oxford University Press for the International
African Institute, 1965.
 An interlocutory presentation of African philosophy.
 Gyekye, Kwame. An Essay in African Philosophical Thought: The Akan Conceptual Scheme. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1987.
 A discussion of philosophy from an African cultural view point.
 Hallen, Barry. A Short History of African Philosophy. Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 2002.
 A presentation of the history of African philosophy from thematic and personality
perspectives.
 Hallen, B. and J. O. Sodipo. Knowledge, Belief and Witchcraft: Analytic Experiments in
African Philosophy. Palo Alto, CA: Stanford University Press, 1997.
 An analytic discourse of the universal nature of themes and terms in African philosophy.
 Hebga, Meinrad. “Logic in Africa”. Philosophy Today, Vol.11 No.4/4 (1958).
 An extrapolation on the structure of African logical tradition.
 Hegel, Georg. Lectures on the Philosophy of World History. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, reprint
1975
 Hegel’s discussion of his philosophy of world history.
 Horton, Robin. “African Traditional Religion and Western Science” in Africa 37: 1 and 2, 1967.
 A comparison of African and Western thought.
 Horton, Robin.
"Traditional Thought and the Emerging African Philosophy Department: A Comment on the Current Debate”
in Second Order: An African Journal of Philosophy vol. III No. 1, 1977.
 A logical critique of the idea of African philosophy.
 Hountondji, Paulin. African Philosophy: Myth and Reality. Second Revised ed. Bloomington, Indiana:
University Press, 1996.
 A critique of ethnophilosophy and an affirmation of African philosophy as a universal
discourse.
 Hunnings, Gordon. “Logic, Language and Culture”. Second Order: An African Journal of Philosophy, Vol.4,
No.1. (1975).
 A critique of classical logic and its laws in African thought and a suggestion of African logical
tradition.
 Ijiomah, Chris. “An Excavation of a Logic in African World-view”. African Journal of Religion, Culture and
Society. 1. 1. (August, 2006): pp.29-35.
 An extrapolation on a possible African logic tradition.
 Iroegbu, Pantaleon. Metaphysics: The Kpim of Philosophy. Owerri: International Universities Press, 1995.
 A conversational presentation of theory of being in African philosophy.
 Jacques, Tomaz. “Philosophy in Black: African Philosophy as a Negritude”. Discursos
 Postcoloniales Entorno Africa. CIEA7, No. 17, 7th
Congress of African Studies.
 A critique of the rigor of African philosophy as a discipline.
 James, George . Stolen Legacy: Greek Philosophy is Stolen Egyptian Philosophy. New York: Philosophical
Library, 1954.
 A philosophical discourse on race, culture, imperialism and colonial deceit.
 Jahn, Janheinz. Muntu: An Outline of Neo-African Culture. New York: Grove Press, 1961.
 A presentation of a new African culture as a synthesis and as philosophical relevant and
rational.
 Jewsiewicki, Bogumil. “African Historical Studies: Academic Knowledge as ‘usable past’ and Radical
Scholarship”. The African Studies Review. Vol. 32. No. 3, December, 1989.
 A discourse on the value of African tradition to modern scholarship.
 Keita, Lansana. “The African Philosophical Tradition”. Wright, Richard A., ed. African Philosophy: An
Introduction. 3rd ed. Lanham, Md.: University Press of America, 1984.
 An examination of African philosophical heritage.
 Keita, Lansana. “Contemporary African Philosophy: The Search for a Method”. Tsanay Serequeberhan
(ed) African Philosophy: The Essential Readings. New York: Paragon House, 1991.
 An analysis of methodological issues in and basis of African philosophy.
 Lambert, Michael. “From Citizenship to Négritude: Making a Difference in Elite Ideologies of Colonized
Francophone West Africa”. Comparative Studies in Society and History, Vol. 35, No. 2. (Apr., 1993), pp. 239–
262.
 A discourse on the problems of colonial policies in Francophone West Africa.
 Lewis Gordon. “African Philosophy’s Search for Identity: Existential Considerations of a recent Effort”. The
CLR James Journal, Winter 1997, pp. 98-117.
 A survey of the identity crisis of African philosophical tradition.
 Leo Apostel. African Philosophy. Belgium: Scientific Publishers, 1981.
 An Afrocentrist presentation of African philosophy.
 Levy-Bruhl, Lucien. Primitive Mentality. Paris: University of France Press, 1947.
 A Eurocentrist presentation of non-European world.
 Makinde, M.A. Philosophy in Africa. The Substance of African philosophy. C.S. Momoh. Ed. Auchi: African
Philosophy Projects’ Publications. 2000.
 A discourse on the practise and relevance of philosophy in Africa.
 Masolo, D. A. African Philosophy in Search of Identity. Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1994.
 An individual-based presentation of the history of African philosophy.
 Maurier, Henri. “Do We have an African Philosophy?”. Wright, Richard A., ed. 1984. African Philosophy: An
Introduction. 3rd ed. Lanham, Md.: University Press of America, 1984.
 A critique of Ethnophilosophy as authentic African philosophy.
 Mbiti, John. African Religions and Philosophy. London: Heinemann,1969.
 A discourse on African philosophical culture.
 Momoh, Campbell. “Canons of African Philosophy”. Paper presented at the 6th
Congress of the Nigerian
Philosophical Association. University of Ife, July 31- August 3, 1985.
 A presentation of the major schools of thought in African philosophy.
 Momoh, Campbell .ed. The Substance of African Philosophy. Auchi: APP Publications, 1989.
 A collection of essays on different issues in African philosophy.
 Momoh, Campbell. “The Logic Question in African Philosophy”. C. S. Momoh ed. The Substance of African
Philosophy. Auchi: APP Publications, 1989.
 A defense of the thesis of a possible African logic tradition.
 Mudimbe, V. Y. The Invention of Africa: Gnosis, Philosophy and the Order of Knowledge (African Systems of
Thought). Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1988.
 A discourse on culture, race, Eurocentrism and modern Africa as an invention of Western
scholarship.
 Ngugi wa Thiong’o. 1986. Decolonizing the Mind: The Politics of Language in African Literature. London: J.
Curry and Portsmouth, N. H: Heinemann, 1986.
 A discourse on Eurocentrism, Africa’s decolonization and cultural imperialism.
 Nkrumah, Kwame. I Speak of Freedom: A Statement of African Ideology. London: Mercury Books, 1961.
 A discourse on political ideology for Africa.
 Nkrumah, Kwame. Towards Colonial Freedom. London: Heinemann. (First published in 1945), 1962.
 A discussion of colonialism and its negative impact on Africa.
 Nwala, Uzodinma. Igbo Philosophy. London: Lantern Books, 1985.
 An Afrocentrist presentation of Igbo-African philosophical culture.
 Nyerere, Julius. Freedom and Unity. Dares Salaam: Oxford University Press, 1986.
 A discussion of a postcolonial Africa that should thrive on freedom and unity.
 Nyerere, Julius. Freedom and Socialism. Dares Salaam: Oxford University Press, 1986.
 A discourse on the fundamental traits of African socialism.
 Nyerere, Julius. Ujamaa—Essays on Socialism. Dar-es-Salaam, Tanzania: Oxford University Press, 1986.
 A collection of essays detailing the characteristics of African brand of socialism.
 Ogbalu, F.C. Ilu Igbo: The Book of Igbo Proverbs. Onitsha: University Publishing Company, 1965.
 A philosophical presentation of Igbo-African proverbs.
 Okeke, J. Chimakonam. “Why Can’t There be an African logic?”. Journal of Integrative Humanism. 1. 2.
(2011). 141-152.
 A defense of a possible African logic tradition and a critique of critics.
 Okere, Theophilus. “The Relation between Culture and Philosophy,” in Uche 2 1976.
 A discourse on the differences and similarities between culture and philosophy.
 Okere, Theophilus. African Philosophy: A Historico-Hermeneutical Investigation of the Conditions of Its
Possibility. Lanham, Md.: University Press of America, 1983.
 A hermeneutical discourse on the basis of African philosophy.
 Okolo, Chukwudum B. Problems of African Philosophy. Enugu: Cecta Nigeria Press, 1990.
 An x-ray of the major hindrances facing African philosophy as a discipline.
 Okoro, C. M. African Philosophy: Question and Debate, A Historical Study. Enugu: Paqon Press, 2004.
 A historical presentation of the great debate in African philosophy.
 Oladipo, Olusegun. (ed) The Third Way in African Philosophy. Ibadan: Hope, 2002.
 A collection of essays on the topical issues in African philosophy of the time.
 Oladipo, Olusegun. Core Issues in African Philosophy. Ibadan: Hope Publications, 2006.
 A discussion of central issues of African philosophy.
 Olela, Henry. “The African Foundations of Greek Philosophy”. Wright, Richard A., ed. African Philosophy:
An Introduction. 3rd ed. Lanham, Md.: University Press of America, 1984.
 An Afrocentrist presentation of African philosophy as the source of Greek philosophy.
 Oluwole, Sophie. Philosophy and Oral Tradition. Lagos: Ark Publications, 1999.
 A cultural excavationist programme in African philosophy.
 Omoregbe, Joseph. “African Philosophy: Yesterday and Today”. African Philosophy: An Anthology.
Emmanuel Eze (ed.), Massachusetts: Blackwell, 1998.
 A survey of major issues in the debate and a critique of the Universalist school.
 Onunwa, Udobata. “Humanism: The Bedrock of African Traditional Religion and Culture”. Religious
Humanism. Vol. XXV, No. 2, Spring 1991, Pp 66 – 71.
 A presentation of Humanism as the basis for African religion and culture.
 Onyewuenyi, Innocent. African Origin of Greek Philosophy: An Exercise in Afrocentrism. Enugu: SNAAP
Press, 1993.
 An Afrocentrist presentation of philosophy as a child of African thought.
 Oruka, H. Odera. “The Fundamental Principles in the Question of ‘African Philosophy,’ I.” Second Order 4,
no. 1: 44–55, 1975.
 A discussion of the main issues in the debate on African philosophy.
 Oruka, H. Odera.“Four Trends in African Philosophy.” In Philosophy in the Present Situation of Africa, edited
by Alwin Diemer. Weisbaden, Germany: Franz Steiner Erlagh. (First published in 1978), 1981; Ed.
 A breakdown of the major schools of thought in the debate on African philosophy.
 Oruka, H. Odera. Sage Philosophy: Indigenous Thinkers and the Modern Debate on African
Philosophy. Leiden: E. J. Brill. 1990.
 A survey of the journey so far in African philosophy and the identification of two additional
schools of thought.
 Outlaw, Lucius. “African ‘Philosophy’? Deconstructive and Reconstructive Challenges.” In his On Race and
Philosophy. New York and London: Routledge. 1996.
 A presentation of African philosophy as a tool for cultural renaissance.
 Plato. Theætetus,155d, p.37.
 Contains Plato’s theory of knowledge.
 Ruch, E. A. and Anyawnu, K. C. African Philosophy: An Introduction to the Main Philosophical Trends in
Contemporary Africa. Rome: Catholic Book Agency, 1981.
 A discussion on racialism, slavery, colonialism and their influence on the emergence of African
philosophy, in addition to current issues in the discipline.
 Sogolo, Godwin. Foundations of African Philosophy. Ibadan: Ibadan University Press, 1993.
 A discussion of the logical, epistemological and metaphysical grounds for African philosophy
project.
 Towa, Marcien. “Conditions for the Affirmation of a Modern African Philosophical Thought”. Tsanay
Serequeberhan (ed) African Philosophy: The Essential Readings. New York: Paragon House, 1991.
 A presentation of important factors required for the emergence of African philosophy as a
discipline.
 Uduigwomen, F. Andrew. “Philosophy and the Place of African Philosophy”. A. F. Uduigwomen ed. From
Footmarks to Landmarks on African Philosophy. 1995, 2nd
Ed. 1995/2009. Lagos: O. O. P. 2009.
 A collection of essays on different issues in African philosophy.
 Uduma Orji. “Can there be an African Logic” in A. F. Uduigwomen(ed.) From Footmarks to Landmarks on
African Philosophy Lagos: O. O. P. Ltd, 2009.
 A critique of a culture-bound logic in African thought.
 Uduma Orji. “Between Universalism and Cultural Identity: Revisiting the Motivation for an African Logic”. A
Paper delivered at an International Conference of the Council for Research in Values and Philosophy
Washington D.C., USA at University of Cape Coast, Cape Coast Ghana 3–5 February, 2010.
 A critique of a culture-bound logic in African thought and a presentation of logic as universal.
 Vest, J. L. 2009. ‘Perverse and necessary dialogues in African philosophy’, in: Thought and practice: a journal
of the philosophical association of Kenya. New series, Vol.1 No.2, December, pp. 1-23.
 An discussion of the proper direction and focus of African philosophy in the new Age.
 Wamba-ia Wamba, E. "Philosophy in Africa: Challenges of the African Philosopher,” in African Philosophy:
The Essential Readings. New York: Paragon House, 1991.
 A discussions of the technical problems of African philosophy as a discipline.
 Winch, Peter. “Understanding a Primitive Society”. American Philosophical Quarterly. No. 1, 1964.
 A discussion and a defense of the rationality of primitive people.
 Wiredu, Kwasi. Philosophy and an African Culture. Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press,
1980.
 A discussion of the philosophical elements in an African culture and a call for a universalizable
episteme for African philosophy.
 Wiredu, Kwasi. “How Not to Compare African Thought with Western Thought.”Ch’Indaba no. 2 ( July–
December): 1976. 4–8. Reprinted in African Philosophy: An Introduction, edited by R. Wright. Washington,
D.C.: University Press of America, 1977; and in African Philosophy: Selected Readings, edited by Albert G.
Mosley. Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice Hall, 1995.
 A critique of Robin Horton’s comparison of African and Western thought.
 Wiredu, Kwasi.“Our Problem of Knowledge: Brief Reflections on Knowledge and Development in
Africa”. African Philosophy as Cultural Inquiry. Ivan Karp and D. A. Masolo (ed). Bloomington, Indiana:
Indiana University Press, 2000.
 A discussion on the role of knowledge in the development of Africa.
 Wiredu, Kwasi. Cultural Universals and Particulars: An African Perspective. Bloomington: Indiana
University Press, 1996.
 A collection of essays on sundry philosophical issues pertaining to comparative and cross-
cultural philosophy.
 Wiredu, Kwasi. Conceptual Decolonization in African Philosophy. Ed. Olusegun Oladipo. Ibadan: Hope
Publications, 1995.
 A discussion of the importance and relevance of the theory of conceptual decolonization in
African philosophy.
 Wiredu, Kwasi. “On Defining African Philosophy”. C. S. Momoh ed. The Substance of African Philosophy.
Auchi: APP Publications, 1989.
 A discourse on the parameters of the discipline of African philosophy.
 Wright, Richard A., ed. “Investigating African Philosophy”. African Philosophy: An Introduction. 3rd ed.
Lanham, Md.: University Press of America, 1984.
 A critique of the existence of African philosophy as a discipline.
Author Information
Leopatra mutazu
Email leomutazu@gmail.com
GREAT ZIMBABWE UNIVERSITY

More Related Content

What's hot

Branches of philosophy
Branches of philosophyBranches of philosophy
Branches of philosophy
Arma_Sheikh
 
What is philosophy of science?
What is philosophy of science?What is philosophy of science?
What is philosophy of science?
John Wilkins
 
Introduction to philosophy
Introduction to philosophyIntroduction to philosophy
Introduction to philosophy
Syed Noman Ali
 
Ethics
EthicsEthics
Ethics
satu12
 
Modern philosophy by RPC
Modern philosophy by RPCModern philosophy by RPC
Ethics
EthicsEthics
Enlightenment Ch 9
Enlightenment Ch 9Enlightenment Ch 9
Enlightenment Ch 9
grieffel
 
Introduction to philosophy
Introduction to philosophyIntroduction to philosophy
Introduction to philosophyNoel Jopson
 
Confucianism and Taoism
Confucianism and TaoismConfucianism and Taoism
Confucianism and Taoism
reach
 
Scholasticism
ScholasticismScholasticism
Scholasticism
Beberly Fabayos
 
Lao tzu
Lao tzuLao tzu
The beginnings of philosophy
The beginnings of philosophyThe beginnings of philosophy
The beginnings of philosophy
Danilo Siquig Jr.
 
Ontology, epistimology and axiology
Ontology, epistimology and axiologyOntology, epistimology and axiology
Ontology, epistimology and axiologyMuhammad Absor
 
Philosophy of man(modern, ancient, contemporary)
Philosophy of man(modern, ancient, contemporary)Philosophy of man(modern, ancient, contemporary)
Philosophy of man(modern, ancient, contemporary)
EsOr Naujnas
 
Introduction: Philosophy of Science
Introduction: Philosophy of ScienceIntroduction: Philosophy of Science
Introduction: Philosophy of Science
Nadia Gabriela Dresscher
 
CONFUCIANISM
CONFUCIANISMCONFUCIANISM
CONFUCIANISM
MARVIN DY
 
Continental philosophy
Continental philosophyContinental philosophy
Continental philosophytjmartin72768
 

What's hot (20)

Branches of philosophy
Branches of philosophyBranches of philosophy
Branches of philosophy
 
What is philosophy of science?
What is philosophy of science?What is philosophy of science?
What is philosophy of science?
 
Contemporary Philosophy: Philosophy in current era
Contemporary Philosophy: Philosophy in current eraContemporary Philosophy: Philosophy in current era
Contemporary Philosophy: Philosophy in current era
 
L3 empiricism
L3 empiricismL3 empiricism
L3 empiricism
 
Introduction to philosophy
Introduction to philosophyIntroduction to philosophy
Introduction to philosophy
 
Ethics
EthicsEthics
Ethics
 
Modern philosophy by RPC
Modern philosophy by RPCModern philosophy by RPC
Modern philosophy by RPC
 
Ethics
EthicsEthics
Ethics
 
Enlightenment Ch 9
Enlightenment Ch 9Enlightenment Ch 9
Enlightenment Ch 9
 
Introduction to philosophy
Introduction to philosophyIntroduction to philosophy
Introduction to philosophy
 
Confucianism and Taoism
Confucianism and TaoismConfucianism and Taoism
Confucianism and Taoism
 
Scholasticism
ScholasticismScholasticism
Scholasticism
 
Greek philosophy
Greek philosophyGreek philosophy
Greek philosophy
 
Lao tzu
Lao tzuLao tzu
Lao tzu
 
The beginnings of philosophy
The beginnings of philosophyThe beginnings of philosophy
The beginnings of philosophy
 
Ontology, epistimology and axiology
Ontology, epistimology and axiologyOntology, epistimology and axiology
Ontology, epistimology and axiology
 
Philosophy of man(modern, ancient, contemporary)
Philosophy of man(modern, ancient, contemporary)Philosophy of man(modern, ancient, contemporary)
Philosophy of man(modern, ancient, contemporary)
 
Introduction: Philosophy of Science
Introduction: Philosophy of ScienceIntroduction: Philosophy of Science
Introduction: Philosophy of Science
 
CONFUCIANISM
CONFUCIANISMCONFUCIANISM
CONFUCIANISM
 
Continental philosophy
Continental philosophyContinental philosophy
Continental philosophy
 

Similar to History of african philosophy

PERIDIZATION OF AFRICAN PILOSOPHY presentation.pptx
PERIDIZATION OF AFRICAN PILOSOPHY presentation.pptxPERIDIZATION OF AFRICAN PILOSOPHY presentation.pptx
PERIDIZATION OF AFRICAN PILOSOPHY presentation.pptx
FreD61137
 
Decolonizing the African Mind: Further Analysis and Strategy by Dr. Uhuru Hotep
Decolonizing the African Mind: Further Analysis and Strategy by Dr. Uhuru Hotep Decolonizing the African Mind: Further Analysis and Strategy by Dr. Uhuru Hotep
Decolonizing the African Mind: Further Analysis and Strategy by Dr. Uhuru Hotep
RBG Communiversity
 
Decolonizing the African Mind: Further Analysis and Strategy_Dr. Uhuru Hotep
Decolonizing the African Mind: Further Analysis and Strategy_Dr. Uhuru HotepDecolonizing the African Mind: Further Analysis and Strategy_Dr. Uhuru Hotep
Decolonizing the African Mind: Further Analysis and Strategy_Dr. Uhuru Hotep
RBG Communiversity
 
Liu Zhao 1 Liu Zh.docx
Liu Zhao 1                                              Liu Zh.docxLiu Zhao 1                                              Liu Zh.docx
Liu Zhao 1 Liu Zh.docx
manningchassidy
 
African Philosophy
African PhilosophyAfrican Philosophy
African Philosophy
Don Dooley
 
Scientific Racism
Scientific RacismScientific Racism
Scientific Racism
Obadele Kambon
 
AFRICAN POLITICAL THOUGHT.pptx
AFRICAN POLITICAL THOUGHT.pptxAFRICAN POLITICAL THOUGHT.pptx
AFRICAN POLITICAL THOUGHT.pptx
DalitsoChama1
 
Anthropology 310 Research Paper
Anthropology 310 Research PaperAnthropology 310 Research Paper
Anthropology 310 Research PaperDanny Lubbe
 
Liu Zhao 1 Liu Zh.docx
Liu Zhao 1                                              Liu Zh.docxLiu Zhao 1                                              Liu Zh.docx
Liu Zhao 1 Liu Zh.docx
jesssueann
 
The African Philosophical Conflicts and Development
The African Philosophical Conflicts and DevelopmentThe African Philosophical Conflicts and Development
The African Philosophical Conflicts and Development
iosrjce
 
Beyond Afrocentrism: Prerequisites for Somalia to lead African de-colonizatio...
Beyond Afrocentrism: Prerequisites for Somalia to lead African de-colonizatio...Beyond Afrocentrism: Prerequisites for Somalia to lead African de-colonizatio...
Beyond Afrocentrism: Prerequisites for Somalia to lead African de-colonizatio...
Muhammad Shamsaddin Megalommatis
 
AFRICA AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS THEORY ACQUIESCENCE AND RESPONSES.pdf
AFRICA AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS THEORY  ACQUIESCENCE AND RESPONSES.pdfAFRICA AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS THEORY  ACQUIESCENCE AND RESPONSES.pdf
AFRICA AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS THEORY ACQUIESCENCE AND RESPONSES.pdf
Tiffany Daniels
 
Orientalism maimoona
Orientalism maimoonaOrientalism maimoona
Orientalism maimoonaHameel Khan
 
AFRICAN PHILOSOPHY.pptx
AFRICAN PHILOSOPHY.pptxAFRICAN PHILOSOPHY.pptx
AFRICAN PHILOSOPHY.pptx
ToyyibAmusa
 
Kemetic Roots of Library and Information Science, by Itibari M. Zulu
Kemetic Roots of Library and Information Science, by Itibari M. ZuluKemetic Roots of Library and Information Science, by Itibari M. Zulu
Kemetic Roots of Library and Information Science, by Itibari M. Zulu
RBG Communiversity
 
DEL MONTE eng pres 02/27/19 - talking points
DEL MONTE eng pres 02/27/19 - talking pointsDEL MONTE eng pres 02/27/19 - talking points
DEL MONTE eng pres 02/27/19 - talking points
LoanniDelMonte
 
Anthropology Of Africa
Anthropology Of AfricaAnthropology Of Africa
Anthropology Of Africa
Steven Wallach
 
En gl 308 intro & achebe
En gl 308 intro & achebeEn gl 308 intro & achebe
En gl 308 intro & achebeemmyrobertson
 
Major contribution to postcolonial theory and their work.pptx
Major contribution to postcolonial theory and their work.pptxMajor contribution to postcolonial theory and their work.pptx
Major contribution to postcolonial theory and their work.pptx
Nazish Malik
 

Similar to History of african philosophy (20)

PERIDIZATION OF AFRICAN PILOSOPHY presentation.pptx
PERIDIZATION OF AFRICAN PILOSOPHY presentation.pptxPERIDIZATION OF AFRICAN PILOSOPHY presentation.pptx
PERIDIZATION OF AFRICAN PILOSOPHY presentation.pptx
 
Decolonizing the African Mind: Further Analysis and Strategy by Dr. Uhuru Hotep
Decolonizing the African Mind: Further Analysis and Strategy by Dr. Uhuru Hotep Decolonizing the African Mind: Further Analysis and Strategy by Dr. Uhuru Hotep
Decolonizing the African Mind: Further Analysis and Strategy by Dr. Uhuru Hotep
 
Decolonizing the African Mind: Further Analysis and Strategy_Dr. Uhuru Hotep
Decolonizing the African Mind: Further Analysis and Strategy_Dr. Uhuru HotepDecolonizing the African Mind: Further Analysis and Strategy_Dr. Uhuru Hotep
Decolonizing the African Mind: Further Analysis and Strategy_Dr. Uhuru Hotep
 
Liu Zhao 1 Liu Zh.docx
Liu Zhao 1                                              Liu Zh.docxLiu Zhao 1                                              Liu Zh.docx
Liu Zhao 1 Liu Zh.docx
 
African Philosophy
African PhilosophyAfrican Philosophy
African Philosophy
 
Scientific Racism
Scientific RacismScientific Racism
Scientific Racism
 
AFRICAN POLITICAL THOUGHT.pptx
AFRICAN POLITICAL THOUGHT.pptxAFRICAN POLITICAL THOUGHT.pptx
AFRICAN POLITICAL THOUGHT.pptx
 
Anthropology 310 Research Paper
Anthropology 310 Research PaperAnthropology 310 Research Paper
Anthropology 310 Research Paper
 
Liu Zhao 1 Liu Zh.docx
Liu Zhao 1                                              Liu Zh.docxLiu Zhao 1                                              Liu Zh.docx
Liu Zhao 1 Liu Zh.docx
 
The African Philosophical Conflicts and Development
The African Philosophical Conflicts and DevelopmentThe African Philosophical Conflicts and Development
The African Philosophical Conflicts and Development
 
Beyond Afrocentrism: Prerequisites for Somalia to lead African de-colonizatio...
Beyond Afrocentrism: Prerequisites for Somalia to lead African de-colonizatio...Beyond Afrocentrism: Prerequisites for Somalia to lead African de-colonizatio...
Beyond Afrocentrism: Prerequisites for Somalia to lead African de-colonizatio...
 
AFRICA AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS THEORY ACQUIESCENCE AND RESPONSES.pdf
AFRICA AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS THEORY  ACQUIESCENCE AND RESPONSES.pdfAFRICA AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS THEORY  ACQUIESCENCE AND RESPONSES.pdf
AFRICA AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS THEORY ACQUIESCENCE AND RESPONSES.pdf
 
Orientalism maimoona
Orientalism maimoonaOrientalism maimoona
Orientalism maimoona
 
Orientalism
Orientalism Orientalism
Orientalism
 
AFRICAN PHILOSOPHY.pptx
AFRICAN PHILOSOPHY.pptxAFRICAN PHILOSOPHY.pptx
AFRICAN PHILOSOPHY.pptx
 
Kemetic Roots of Library and Information Science, by Itibari M. Zulu
Kemetic Roots of Library and Information Science, by Itibari M. ZuluKemetic Roots of Library and Information Science, by Itibari M. Zulu
Kemetic Roots of Library and Information Science, by Itibari M. Zulu
 
DEL MONTE eng pres 02/27/19 - talking points
DEL MONTE eng pres 02/27/19 - talking pointsDEL MONTE eng pres 02/27/19 - talking points
DEL MONTE eng pres 02/27/19 - talking points
 
Anthropology Of Africa
Anthropology Of AfricaAnthropology Of Africa
Anthropology Of Africa
 
En gl 308 intro & achebe
En gl 308 intro & achebeEn gl 308 intro & achebe
En gl 308 intro & achebe
 
Major contribution to postcolonial theory and their work.pptx
Major contribution to postcolonial theory and their work.pptxMajor contribution to postcolonial theory and their work.pptx
Major contribution to postcolonial theory and their work.pptx
 

Recently uploaded

Azure Interview Questions and Answers PDF By ScholarHat
Azure Interview Questions and Answers PDF By ScholarHatAzure Interview Questions and Answers PDF By ScholarHat
Azure Interview Questions and Answers PDF By ScholarHat
Scholarhat
 
2024.06.01 Introducing a competency framework for languag learning materials ...
2024.06.01 Introducing a competency framework for languag learning materials ...2024.06.01 Introducing a competency framework for languag learning materials ...
2024.06.01 Introducing a competency framework for languag learning materials ...
Sandy Millin
 
Francesca Gottschalk - How can education support child empowerment.pptx
Francesca Gottschalk - How can education support child empowerment.pptxFrancesca Gottschalk - How can education support child empowerment.pptx
Francesca Gottschalk - How can education support child empowerment.pptx
EduSkills OECD
 
1.4 modern child centered education - mahatma gandhi-2.pptx
1.4 modern child centered education - mahatma gandhi-2.pptx1.4 modern child centered education - mahatma gandhi-2.pptx
1.4 modern child centered education - mahatma gandhi-2.pptx
JosvitaDsouza2
 
Operation Blue Star - Saka Neela Tara
Operation Blue Star   -  Saka Neela TaraOperation Blue Star   -  Saka Neela Tara
Operation Blue Star - Saka Neela Tara
Balvir Singh
 
A Strategic Approach: GenAI in Education
A Strategic Approach: GenAI in EducationA Strategic Approach: GenAI in Education
A Strategic Approach: GenAI in Education
Peter Windle
 
How libraries can support authors with open access requirements for UKRI fund...
How libraries can support authors with open access requirements for UKRI fund...How libraries can support authors with open access requirements for UKRI fund...
How libraries can support authors with open access requirements for UKRI fund...
Jisc
 
Acetabularia Information For Class 9 .docx
Acetabularia Information For Class 9  .docxAcetabularia Information For Class 9  .docx
Acetabularia Information For Class 9 .docx
vaibhavrinwa19
 
Welcome to TechSoup New Member Orientation and Q&A (May 2024).pdf
Welcome to TechSoup   New Member Orientation and Q&A (May 2024).pdfWelcome to TechSoup   New Member Orientation and Q&A (May 2024).pdf
Welcome to TechSoup New Member Orientation and Q&A (May 2024).pdf
TechSoup
 
Language Across the Curriculm LAC B.Ed.
Language Across the  Curriculm LAC B.Ed.Language Across the  Curriculm LAC B.Ed.
Language Across the Curriculm LAC B.Ed.
Atul Kumar Singh
 
The Accursed House by Émile Gaboriau.pptx
The Accursed House by Émile Gaboriau.pptxThe Accursed House by Émile Gaboriau.pptx
The Accursed House by Émile Gaboriau.pptx
DhatriParmar
 
Overview on Edible Vaccine: Pros & Cons with Mechanism
Overview on Edible Vaccine: Pros & Cons with MechanismOverview on Edible Vaccine: Pros & Cons with Mechanism
Overview on Edible Vaccine: Pros & Cons with Mechanism
DeeptiGupta154
 
The basics of sentences session 5pptx.pptx
The basics of sentences session 5pptx.pptxThe basics of sentences session 5pptx.pptx
The basics of sentences session 5pptx.pptx
heathfieldcps1
 
Unit 2- Research Aptitude (UGC NET Paper I).pdf
Unit 2- Research Aptitude (UGC NET Paper I).pdfUnit 2- Research Aptitude (UGC NET Paper I).pdf
Unit 2- Research Aptitude (UGC NET Paper I).pdf
Thiyagu K
 
Embracing GenAI - A Strategic Imperative
Embracing GenAI - A Strategic ImperativeEmbracing GenAI - A Strategic Imperative
Embracing GenAI - A Strategic Imperative
Peter Windle
 
Biological Screening of Herbal Drugs in detailed.
Biological Screening of Herbal Drugs in detailed.Biological Screening of Herbal Drugs in detailed.
Biological Screening of Herbal Drugs in detailed.
Ashokrao Mane college of Pharmacy Peth-Vadgaon
 
Normal Labour/ Stages of Labour/ Mechanism of Labour
Normal Labour/ Stages of Labour/ Mechanism of LabourNormal Labour/ Stages of Labour/ Mechanism of Labour
Normal Labour/ Stages of Labour/ Mechanism of Labour
Wasim Ak
 
Marketing internship report file for MBA
Marketing internship report file for MBAMarketing internship report file for MBA
Marketing internship report file for MBA
gb193092
 
Honest Reviews of Tim Han LMA Course Program.pptx
Honest Reviews of Tim Han LMA Course Program.pptxHonest Reviews of Tim Han LMA Course Program.pptx
Honest Reviews of Tim Han LMA Course Program.pptx
timhan337
 
Model Attribute Check Company Auto Property
Model Attribute  Check Company Auto PropertyModel Attribute  Check Company Auto Property
Model Attribute Check Company Auto Property
Celine George
 

Recently uploaded (20)

Azure Interview Questions and Answers PDF By ScholarHat
Azure Interview Questions and Answers PDF By ScholarHatAzure Interview Questions and Answers PDF By ScholarHat
Azure Interview Questions and Answers PDF By ScholarHat
 
2024.06.01 Introducing a competency framework for languag learning materials ...
2024.06.01 Introducing a competency framework for languag learning materials ...2024.06.01 Introducing a competency framework for languag learning materials ...
2024.06.01 Introducing a competency framework for languag learning materials ...
 
Francesca Gottschalk - How can education support child empowerment.pptx
Francesca Gottschalk - How can education support child empowerment.pptxFrancesca Gottschalk - How can education support child empowerment.pptx
Francesca Gottschalk - How can education support child empowerment.pptx
 
1.4 modern child centered education - mahatma gandhi-2.pptx
1.4 modern child centered education - mahatma gandhi-2.pptx1.4 modern child centered education - mahatma gandhi-2.pptx
1.4 modern child centered education - mahatma gandhi-2.pptx
 
Operation Blue Star - Saka Neela Tara
Operation Blue Star   -  Saka Neela TaraOperation Blue Star   -  Saka Neela Tara
Operation Blue Star - Saka Neela Tara
 
A Strategic Approach: GenAI in Education
A Strategic Approach: GenAI in EducationA Strategic Approach: GenAI in Education
A Strategic Approach: GenAI in Education
 
How libraries can support authors with open access requirements for UKRI fund...
How libraries can support authors with open access requirements for UKRI fund...How libraries can support authors with open access requirements for UKRI fund...
How libraries can support authors with open access requirements for UKRI fund...
 
Acetabularia Information For Class 9 .docx
Acetabularia Information For Class 9  .docxAcetabularia Information For Class 9  .docx
Acetabularia Information For Class 9 .docx
 
Welcome to TechSoup New Member Orientation and Q&A (May 2024).pdf
Welcome to TechSoup   New Member Orientation and Q&A (May 2024).pdfWelcome to TechSoup   New Member Orientation and Q&A (May 2024).pdf
Welcome to TechSoup New Member Orientation and Q&A (May 2024).pdf
 
Language Across the Curriculm LAC B.Ed.
Language Across the  Curriculm LAC B.Ed.Language Across the  Curriculm LAC B.Ed.
Language Across the Curriculm LAC B.Ed.
 
The Accursed House by Émile Gaboriau.pptx
The Accursed House by Émile Gaboriau.pptxThe Accursed House by Émile Gaboriau.pptx
The Accursed House by Émile Gaboriau.pptx
 
Overview on Edible Vaccine: Pros & Cons with Mechanism
Overview on Edible Vaccine: Pros & Cons with MechanismOverview on Edible Vaccine: Pros & Cons with Mechanism
Overview on Edible Vaccine: Pros & Cons with Mechanism
 
The basics of sentences session 5pptx.pptx
The basics of sentences session 5pptx.pptxThe basics of sentences session 5pptx.pptx
The basics of sentences session 5pptx.pptx
 
Unit 2- Research Aptitude (UGC NET Paper I).pdf
Unit 2- Research Aptitude (UGC NET Paper I).pdfUnit 2- Research Aptitude (UGC NET Paper I).pdf
Unit 2- Research Aptitude (UGC NET Paper I).pdf
 
Embracing GenAI - A Strategic Imperative
Embracing GenAI - A Strategic ImperativeEmbracing GenAI - A Strategic Imperative
Embracing GenAI - A Strategic Imperative
 
Biological Screening of Herbal Drugs in detailed.
Biological Screening of Herbal Drugs in detailed.Biological Screening of Herbal Drugs in detailed.
Biological Screening of Herbal Drugs in detailed.
 
Normal Labour/ Stages of Labour/ Mechanism of Labour
Normal Labour/ Stages of Labour/ Mechanism of LabourNormal Labour/ Stages of Labour/ Mechanism of Labour
Normal Labour/ Stages of Labour/ Mechanism of Labour
 
Marketing internship report file for MBA
Marketing internship report file for MBAMarketing internship report file for MBA
Marketing internship report file for MBA
 
Honest Reviews of Tim Han LMA Course Program.pptx
Honest Reviews of Tim Han LMA Course Program.pptxHonest Reviews of Tim Han LMA Course Program.pptx
Honest Reviews of Tim Han LMA Course Program.pptx
 
Model Attribute Check Company Auto Property
Model Attribute  Check Company Auto PropertyModel Attribute  Check Company Auto Property
Model Attribute Check Company Auto Property
 

History of african philosophy

  • 1. History of African Philosophy This article traces the history of systematic African philosophy from the early 1920s to date. In Plato’s Theaetetus, Socrates suggests that philosophy begins with wonder. Aristotle agreed. However, recent research shows that wonder may have different subsets. If that is the case, which specific subset of wonder inspired the beginning of the systematic African philosophy? In the history of Western philosophy, there is the one called thaumazein interpreted as awe and the other called miraculum interpreted as curiosity. History shows that these two subsets manifest in the African place as well, even during the pre-systematic era. However, there is now an idea appearing in recent African philosophy literature called onuma interpreted as frustration which is regarded as the subset of wonder that jump started the systematic African philosophy. In the 1920s, a host of Africans who went to study in the West were just returning. They had experienced terrible racism and discrimination while in the West. They were referred to as descendants of slaves; as people from the slave colony, as sub-humans, and so on. On return to their native lands, they met the same maltreatment by the colonial officials. ‘Frustrated’ by colonialism and racialism as well as the legacies of slavery, they were jolted onto the path of philosophy—African philosophy—by what can be called onuma. These ugly episodes of slavery, colonialism and racialism not only shaped the world’s perception of Africa; they also instigated a form of intellectual revolt from the African intelligentsias. The frustration with the colonial order eventually led to angry questions and reactions out of which African philosophy emerged, first in the form of nationalisms and then in the form ideological theorizations. But the frustration was borne out of colonial caricature of Africa as culturally naïve, intellectually docile and rationally inept. This caricature was created by European scholars such as Kant, Hegel and, much later, Levy-Bruhl to name just a few. It was the reaction to this caricature that led some African scholars returning from the West into the type of philosophizing one may describe as systematic beginning with the identity of the African people, their place in history, and their contributions to civilization. To dethrone the colonially-built episteme became a ready attraction for African scholars’ vexed frustrations. Thus began the history of systematic African philosophy with the likes of Aime Cisaire, Leopold Senghor, Kwame Nkrumah, Julius Nyerere, William Abraham, John Mbiti and expatriates such as Placid Tempels, Janheinz Jahn and George James, to name a few.
  • 2. Table of Contents 1. Introduction 2. Criteria of African Philosophy 3. Methods of African Philosophy a. The Communitarian Method b. The Complementarity Method c. The Conversational Method 4. Schools of African Philosophy . Ethnophilosophy School a. Nationalist/Ideological School b. Philosophic Sagacity c. Hermeneutical School d. Literary School e. Professional School f. Conversational School 5. The Movements in African Philosophy . Excavationism a. Afro-Constructionism/Afro-Deconstructionism b. Critical Reconstructionism/Afro-Eclecticism c. Conversationalism 6. Periods of African Philosophy . Early Period a. Middle Period b. Later Period c. New Era 7. Conclusion 8. References and Further Reading
  • 3. 1. Introduction African philosophy as a systematic study has a very short history. This history is also a very dense one, since actors sought to do in a few decades what would have been better done in many centuries. As a result, they also did in later years what ought to have been done earlier and vice versa, thus making the early and the middle epochs overlap considerably. The reason for this overtime endeavor is not far-fetched. Soon after colonialism, actors realized that Africa had been sucked into the global matrix unprepared. During colonial times, the identity of the African was European, his thought system, standard and even his perception of reality were structured by the colonial shadow which stood towering behind him. It was easy for the African to position himself within these Western cultural appurtenances even though they had no real-time connection with his being. The vanity of this presupposition and the emptiness of colonial assurances manifested soon after the towering colonial shadow vanished. Now, in the global matrix, it became shameful for the African to continue to identify himself within the European colonialist milieu. For one, he had just rejected colonialism and for another, the deposed European colonialist made it clear that the identity of the African was no longer covered and insured by the European medium. So, actors realized suddenly that they had been disillusioned and had suffered severe self-deceit under colonial temper. The question which trailed every African was, “Who are you?” Of course, the answers from European perspective were savage, primitive, less than human, etc. It was the urgent, sudden need to contradict these European positions that led some post-colonial Africans in search of African identity. So, to discover or rediscover African identity in order to initiate a non-colonial or original history for Africa in the global matrix and start a course of viable economic, political and social progress that is entirely African became one of the focal points of African philosophy. Placid Tempels, the European missionary, elected to help and in his controversial book, Bantu Philosophy, sought to create Africa’s own philosophy as proof that Africa has its own peculiar identity and thought system. However, it was George James, another concerned European who attempted a much more ambitious project in his work, Stolen Legacy. In this work, there were strong suggestions not only that Africa has philosophy but that the so-called Western philosophy, the very bastion of European identity, was stolen from Africa. This claim was intended to make the proud European colonialists feel indebted to the humiliated Africans, but it was unsuccessful. That Greek philosophy had roots in Egypt does not imply, as some Europeans claim, that Egyptians were dark nor that dark complexioned Africans had philosophy. The use of the term “Africans” in this work is in keeping with George James’ demarcation which precludes the light complexioned people of North Africa and refers to the dark complexioned people of southern Sahara. After these two Europeans, Africans began to attain maturation. Aime Cesaire, John Mbiti, Odera Oruka, Julius Nyerere, Leopold Senghor, Nnamdi Azikiwe, Kwame Nkrumah, Obafemi Awolowo, Alexis Kegame, Uzodinma Nwala, Emmanuel Edeh, Innocent Onyewuenyi, and Henry Olela, to name just a few, opened the doors of ideas. A few of the works produced sought to prove and establish the philosophical basis of
  • 4. African, unique identity in the history of humankind, while others sought to chart a course of Africa’s true identity through unique political and economic ideologies. It can be stated that much of these endeavors fall under the early period. For its concerns, the middle period of African philosophy is characterized by the great debate. Those who seek to clarify and justify the position held in the early epoch and those who seek to criticize and deny the viability of such position entangled themselves in a great debate. Some of the actors on this front include, C. S. Momoh, Robin Horton, Henri Maurier, Lacinay Keita, Peter Bodunrin, Kwasi Wiredu, Kwame Gyekye, Richard Wright, Barry Halen, Joseph Omoregbe, C. B. Okolo, Theophilus Okere, Paulin Hountondji, Gordon Hunnings, Odera Oruka and Sophie Oluwole to name a few. The preceding epoch eventually gave way to the later period which has as its focus the construction of an African episteme. Two camps rivaled each other namely; the Critical Reconstructionists who are the evolved Universalists/Deconstructionists and the Eclectics who are the evolved Traditionalists/Excavators. The former seek to build an African episteme untainted by ethnophilosophy; whereas, the latter seek to do the same by a delicate fusion of relevant ideals of the two camps. In the end, Critical Reconstructionism ran into a brick wall when it became clear that whatever it produced cannot truly be called African philosophy if it is all Western without African marks. The mere claim that it would be African philosophy simply because it was produced by Africans (Hountondji 1996 and Oruka 1975) would collapse like a house of cards under any argument. For this great failure, the influence of Critical Reconstructionism in the later period whittled down and it was latter absorbed by its rival—Eclecticism. The works of the Eclectics heralded the emergence of the New Era in African philosophy. The focus becomes the Conversational philosophizing, in which the production of philosophically rigorous and original African episteme better than what the Eclectics produced occupied the center stage. The sum of what historians of African philosophy have done can be presented in the following two broad categorizations to wit; Pre-systematic Era and the Systematic era. The former refers to Africa’s philosophical culture, thoughts of the anonymous African thinkers and may include the problems of Egyptian legacy. The latter refers to the periods marking the return of Africa’s first eleven, Western-tutored philosophers from the 1920’s to date. This latter category could further be delineated into four periods: 1. a. Early period 1920s - 1960s b. Middle period 1960s - 1980s c. Later period 1980s - 1990s d. New (Contemporary) Era since 1990s Note, of course, that this does not commit us to saying that, before the early period, people in Africa never philosophized—they did. But one fact that must not be denied is that they did not document their thoughts and, as such, scholars cannot attest to their systematicity
  • 5. or sources. In other words, what this periodization shows is that African philosophy as a system first began in the late 1920s. Because there are credible objections among African philosophers with regards to the inclusion of it in the historical chart of African philosophy, the Egyptian question will be ignored for now. The main objection is that even if the philosophers of stolen legacy were able to prove a connection between Greece and Egypt, they could not prove in concrete terms that Egyptians were dark complexioned Africans or that dark complexioned Africans were Egyptians. It is understandable the frustration and desperation that motivated such ambitious effort in the ugly colonial era which was captured above, but any reasonable person, judging by the responses of time and events in the last few decades knows it was high time Africans abandoned that unproven legacy and let go of that, now helpless propaganda. If however, some would want to retain it as part of African philosophy, it would carefully fall within the pre-literate or the pre-systematic era. In this essay, discussion will focus on the history of systematic or literate African philosophy touching prominently on the criteria, schools, movements and periods in African philosophy. As much as the philosophers of a given era may disagree, they are inevitably united by the problem of their epoch. That is to say, it is orthodoxy that each epoch is defined by a common focus or problem. Therefore, the approach of the study of the history of philosophy can be done either through personality periscope or through the periods, but whichever approach one chooses, he unavoidably runs into the person who had chosen the other. This is a sign of unity of focus. Thus philosophers are those who seek to solve the problem of their time. In this presentation, the study of the history of African philosophy will be approached principally through the periods, schools, movements and the personalities will be discussed within these purviews. 2. Criteria of African Philosophy To start with, more than three decades debate on the status of philosophy ended with the affirmation that African philosophy exists. But what is it that makes a philosophy African? Answers to this question polarized actors into two main groups, namely the Traditionalists and Universalists. Whereas the Traditionalists aver that the studies of the philosophical elements in world-view of the people constitute African philosophy, the Universalists insist that it has to be a body of analytic and critical reflections of individual African philosophers. Further probing of the question was done during the debate by the end of which the question of what makes a philosophy “African” produced two contrasting criteria. First, as a racial criterion; a philosophy would be African if it is produced by Africans. This is the view held by people like Paulin Hountondji, Odera Oruka (in part), and early Peter Bodunrin, derived from the two constituting terms—“African” and “philosophy”. African philosophy following this criterion is the philosophy done by Africans. This has been criticized as pejorative, incorrect and exclusivist. Second, as a tradition criterion; a philosophy is “African” if it designates a non-racial-bound philosophy tradition where the predicate “African” is treated as a solidarity term of no racial import and where the approach derives inspiration from African cultural background or system of thought. It does not matter whether the issues addressed are African or that the philosophy is done by an African insofar as it has universal
  • 6. applicability and emerged from the purview of African system of thought. African philosophy would then be that rigorous discourse of African issues or any issues whatsoever from the critical eye of African system of thought. Actors like Odera Oruka (in part), Meinrad Hebga, C. S. Momoh, Udo Etuk, Joseph Omoregbe, the later Peter Bodunrin, Jonathan Chimakonam can be grouped here. This criterion has also been criticized as courting uncritical elements of the past when it makes reference to the controversial idea of African logic tradition. Further discussion on this is well beyond the scope of this essay. What is however common in the two criteria is that African philosophy is a critical discourse on issues that may or may not affect Africa by African philosophers— the purview of this discourse remains unsettled. 3. Methods of African Philosophy a. The Communitarian Method This method speaks to the idea of mutuality, the type found in the classic expression of ubuntu: “a person is a person through other person” or that which is credited to John Mbiti, “ I am because we are, since we are, therefore I am”. Those who employ this method wish to demonstrate the idea of mutual interdependence of variables. You find this most prominent in the works of researchers working in ubuntu and communalism. Some of the thinkers who employ this method include; Ifeanyi Menkiti, Mogobe Ramose, Kwame Gyekye, Thaddeus Metz, Fainos Mangena, Leonhard Praeg, Bernard Matolino, Michael Eze, and so forth. b. The Complementarity Method This method was propounded by Innocent Asouzu and it harps on the idea of missing link. No variable is useless. The system of reality is like a network in which each variable has an important role to play i.e. it complements and is in return complemented because no variable is self sufficient. Other scholars whose works have followed this method include Mesembe Edet, Ada Agada, Jonathan Chimakonam and a host of others. c. The Conversational Method This is a formal procedure for assessing the relationships of opposed variables in which thoughts are shuffled through disjunctive and conjunctive modes to constantly recreate fresh thesis and anti-thesis each time at a higher level of discourse without the expectation of the synthesis. It is an encounter between philosophers of rival schools of thought and between different philosophical traditions or cultures in which one party called nwa-nsa (the defender or proponent) holds up a position and another party called nwa-nju (the doubter or opponent) doubts or questions the accuracy of the position. On the whole, this method points to the idea of relationships among interdependent, interrelated and interconnected realities existing in a network whose peculiar truth conditions can more accurately and broadly be determined within specific contexts. This method was first proposed by Jonathan Chimakonam and endorsed by the The Conversational School of Philosophy. Other thinkers that now employ this method include, Victor Nweke, Mesembe Edet, Fayemi Ademola Kazeem, Ada Agada, Pius Mosima, and a host of others.
  • 7. 4. Schools of African Philosophy a. Ethnophilosophy School This is the foremost school in systematic African philosophy which equated African philosophy with culture-bound systems of thought. For this, their enterprise was scornfully described as substandard hence the term “ethnophilosophy.” Thoughts of the members of the Excavationism movement like Tempels Placid and Alexis Kagame properly belong here and their high point was in the early period of African philosophy. b. Nationalist/Ideological School The concern of this school was nationalist philosophical jingoism to combat colonialism and to create political philosophy and ideology for Africa from the indigenous traditional system as a project of decolonization. Thoughts of members of the Excavationism movement like Kwame Nkrumah, Leopold Sedar Senghor and Julius Nyerere in the early period can be brought under this school. c. Philosophic Sagacity There is also the philosophic sagacity school whose main focus is to show that standard philosophical discourse existed and still exists in traditional Africa and can only be discovered through sage conversations. The chief proponent of this school was the brilliant Kenyan philosopher Odera Oruka who took time to emphasize that Marcel Gruaile’s similar programme is less sophisticated than his. Other adherents of this school include Gail Presbey, Anke Graness and the Cameroonian philosopher Pius Mosima. But since philosophical sagacity thrives on the method of oral interview of presumed sages whose authenticity cannot be independently verified, what is produced distances itself from the sages and becomes the fruits of the interviewing philosopher. So the sage connection and the tradition became defeated. Their enterprise falls within the movement of Critical Reconstructionism of the later period. d. Hermeneutical School Another prominent school is the hermeneutical school. Its focus is that the best approach to studying African philosophy is through interpretations of oral traditions and emerging philosophical texts. Theophilus Okere, Okonda Okolo, Tsenay Serequeberhan and Ademola Fayemi Kazeem are some of the major proponents and members of this school. The confusion however is that they reject ethnophilosophy whereas the oral tradition and most of the texts available for interpretation are ethnophilosophical in nature. The works of Okere and Okolo feasted on ethno-philosophy. This school exemplifies the movement called Afro-constructionism of the middle period. e. Literary School The literary school’s main concern is to make a philosophical presentation of African cultural values through literary/fictional ways. Proponents like Chinua Achebe, Cheik Anta Diop, Ngugi wa Thiong’o, Wole Soyinka to name a few have been outstanding. Yet critics have found it convenient to identify their discourse with ethnophilosophy from literary angle thereby denigrating it as sub-standard. Their enterprise remarks the movement of Afro-constructionism of the middle period.
  • 8. f. Professional School Perhaps the most controversial is the one variously described as professional, universalist or modernist school. It contends that all the other schools are engaged in one form of ethnophilosophy or the other, that standard African philosophy is critical, individual discourse and that what qualifies as African philosophy must have universal merit and thrive on the method of critical analysis and individual discursive enterprise. It is not about talking, it is about doing. Some staunch unrepentant members of this school include Kwasi Wiredu, Paulin Hountondji, Peter Bodunrin to name a few. They demolished all that has been built in African philosophy and built nothing as an alternative episteme. This school champions the movement of Afro-deconstructionism and the abortive Critical Reconstructionism of the middle and later periods respectively. Perhaps, one of the deeper criticisms that can be leveled against the position of the professional school comes from C. S. Momoh’s scornful description of the school as African logical neo-positivism. They agitate that (1) there is nothing as yet in African traditional philosophy that qualifies as philosophy and (2) that critical analysis should be the focus of African philosophy; so what then is there to be critically analyzed? Professional school adherents are said to forget in their overt copying of European philosophy that analysis is a recent development in European philosophy which attained saturation in the 19th century after over 2000 years of historical evolution thereby requiring some downsizing. Would they also grant that philosophy in Europe before 19th century was not philosophy? The aim of this essay is not to offer criticisms of the schools but to present historical journey of philosophy in the African tradition. It is in opposition to and the need to fill the lacuna in the enterprise of the professional school that the new school which can be called conversational school has recently emerged in African philosophy. g. Conversational School This emerging school thrives on fulfilling the yearning of the professional/modernist school to have a robust individual discourse as well as fulfilling the conviction of the traditionalists that a thorough-going African philosophy has to be erected on the foundation of African thought systems. They make the most of the criterion which presents African philosophy as a critical tradition that prioritizes engagements between philosophers and cultures and projects individual discourses from the thought system of Africa. Those whose writings fit into this school include Pantaleon Iroegbu, Innocent Asouzu, Bruce Janz, Jennifer Vest, Jonathan Chimakonam and Ada Agada to name a few. Their projects promote partly the movements of Afro-eclecticism and fully the conversationalism of the later and the new periods respectively. 5. The Movements in African Philosophy There are four main movements that can be identified in the history of African philosophy, they include: Excavationism, Afro-constructionism/Afro-deconstructionism, Critical Reconstructionism/Afro-Eclecticism and Conversationalism. a. Excavationism The Excavators are all those who sought to erect the edifice of African philosophy by systematizing the African cultural world-views. Some of them aimed at retrieving and reconstructing presumably lost African identity from the raw materials of African culture, while others sought to develop compatible political ideologies for Africa from the native
  • 9. political systems of African peoples. Members of this movement have all been grouped under the school known as ethnophilosophy, and they thrived in the early period of African philosophy. Their concern was to build and demonstrate unique African identify in various forms. A few of them include Placid Tempels, Julius Nyerere, John Mbiti, Alexis Kagame, Leopold Senghor, Kwame Nkrumah and Aime Cesaire. b. Afro-Constructionism/Afro-Deconstructionism The Afro-deconstructionists sometimes called the Modernists or the Universalists are those who sought to demote such edifice erected by the Excavators on the ground that their raw materials are substandard cultural paraphernalia. They are opposed to the idea of unique African identity or culture-bound philosophy and preferred a philosophy that will integrate African identity with the identity of all other races. They never built this philosophy. Some members of this movement include Paulin Hountondji, Kwasi Wiredu, Peter Bodunrin, Macien Towa, Fabien Ebousi Boulaga, Richard Wright and Henri Maurier. Their opponents are the Afro-constructionists, sometimes called the Traditionalists or Particularists who sought to add rigor and promote the works of the Excavators as true African philosophy. Some prominent actors in this movement include Innocent Onyewuenyi, Henry Olela, Lansana Keita, C. S. Momoh, Joseph Omoregbe, Janheinz Jahn, George James, Sophie Oluwole and, in some ways, Kwame Gyekye. Members of this twin-movement have variously been grouped under ethnophilosophy, philosophic sagacity, professional, hermeneutical and literary schools and they thrived in the middle period of African philosophy. This is also known as the period of the Great Debate. c. Critical Reconstructionism/Afro-Eclecticism A few Afro-deconstructionists of the middle period evolved into Critical Reconstructionists hoping to reconstruct from the scratch the edifice of authentic African philosophy that would be critical, individualistic and universal. They hold that the edifice of ethnophilosophy, which they had demolished in the middle period, contained no critical rigor. Some of the members of this movement include, Kwasi Wiredu, Olusegun Oladipo, V. Y. Mudimbe, D. A. Masolo, Odera Oruka and, in some ways, Barry Hallen and J. O. Sodipo. Their opponents are the Afro-Eclectics who evolved from Afro- constructionism of the middle period. Unable to sustain their advocacy and the structure of ethnophilosophy they had constructed, they stepped down a little bit to say, “Maybe we can combine meaningfully, some of the non-conflicting concerns of the Traditionalists and the Modernists.” They say (1) that African traditional philosophy is not rigorous enough as claimed by the Modernists is a fact (2) that the deconstructionist program of the Modernists did not offer and is incapable of offering an alternative episteme is also a fact (3) maybe the rigor of the Modernists can be applied on the usable and relevant elements produced by the Traditionalists to produce the much elusive, authentic African philosophy. African philosophy for this movement therefore becomes a product of synthesis resulting from the application of tools of critical reasoning on the relevant traditions of African life-world. A. F. Uduigwomen, Kwame Gyekye, Ifeanyi Menkiti and Kwame Appiah are some of the members of this movement. This movement played a vital reconciliatory role, the importance of which was not fully realized in African philosophy. Most importantly, they found a way out and laid the foundation for the emergence of Conversationalism. Members of this twin-movement thrived in the later period of African philosophy.
  • 10. d. Conversationalism The Conversationalists are those who seek to create an enduring corpus in African philosophy by engaging elements of tradition and individual thinkers in critical conversations. They emphasize originality, creativity, innovation, peer-criticism and cross-pollination of ideas in prescribing and evaluating their ideas. They hold that new episteme in African philosophy can only be created by individual African philosophers who make use of the “usable past” and the depth of individual originality in finding solutions to contemporary demands. They do not lay emphasis on analysis alone but also on critical rigor and what is now called arumaristics—a creative reshuffling of thesis and anti-thesis that spins out new concepts and thoughts. Members of this movement thrive in this contemporary period and their school can be called the conversational school. Some of the philosophers that have demonstrated this trait include Pantaleon Iroegbu, Innocent Asouzu, Bruce Janz, Jonathan Chimakonam, Ada Agada, Jennifer Lisa Vest, and so forth. 6. Periods of African Philosophy a. Early Period The early period of African philosophy is an era of the movement called cultural/ideological excavation aimed at retrieving and reconstructing African identity. The schools that emerged and thrived in this period were ethnophilosophy and ideological/nationalist schools. The Sub-Saharan Africans, Hegel wrote, had no high cultures and had made no contributions to world history and civilization (1975: 190). Lucien Levy Bruhl also added that they are pre-logical and two-third of human (1947: 17). The summary of these two positions, which represent the colonial mindset, is that Africans have no dignified identity like their European counterpart. This could be deciphered in the British colonial system which sought to erode the native thought system in the constitution of social systems in their colonies and also in the French policy of assimilation. Assimilation is a concept credited to the French philosopher Chris Talbot (1837) which rests on the idea of expanding French culture to the colonies outside of France in the 19th and 20th centuries. According to Betts (2005: 8), the natives of these colonies were considered French citizens as long as the French culture and customs were adopted to replace the indigenous system. The purpose of the theory of assimilation, for Michael Lambert, therefore, was to turn African natives into French men by educating them in the French language and culture (1993: 239-262). During colonial times, the British, for example, educated their colonies in the British language and culture, strictly undermining the native languages and cultures. The products of this new social system were then given the impression that they were British, though second class, the king was their king, and the empire was also theirs. Suddenly, however, colonialism ended and they found, to their chagrin, that they were treated as slave countries in the new post-colonial order. Their native identity had been destroyed and their fake British identity had also been taken from them; what was left was amorphous and corrupt. It was in the heat of this confusion and frustration that the African philosophers sought to retrieve and recreate the original African identity lost in the event of colonization. Ruch and Anyanwu, therefore, ask, “What is this debate about
  • 11. African identity concerned with and what led to it? In other words, why should Africans search for their identity?” Their response to the questions is as follows: The simple answer to these questions is this: Africans of the first half of this (20th century) century have begun to search for their identity, because they had, rightly or wrongly, the feeling that they had lost it or that they were being deprived of it. The three main factors which led to this feeling were: slavery, colonialism and racialism. (1981: 184-85) Racialism, as Ruch and Anyanwu believed, may have sparked it off and slavery may have dealt the heaviest blow, but it was colonialism that entrenched it. Ironically, it was the same colonialism at its stylistic conclusion that opened the eyes of the African by stirring the hornet’s nest. An African can never be a British or French even with the colonially imposed language and culture. With this shock, the post colonial African philosophers of the early period set out in search of Africa’s lost identity. James in 1954 published his monumental work Stolen Legacy. In it, he attempted to prove that the Egyptians were the true authors of Western philosophy; that Pythagoras, Socrates, Plato and Aristotle plagiarized the Egyptians; that the authorship of the individual doctrines of Greek philosophers is a mere speculation perpetuated chiefly by Aristotle and executed by his school; and that the African continent gave the world its civilization, knowledge, arts and sciences, religion and philosophy, a fact that is destined to produce a change in the mentality both of the European and African peoples. In G. M. James’ words: In this way, the Greeks stole the legacy of the African continent and called it their own. And as has already been pointed out, the result of this dishonesty had been the creation of an enormous world opinion; that the African continent has made no contribution to civilization, because her people are backward and low in intelligence and culture…This erroneous opinion about the Black people has seriously injured them through the centuries up to modern times in which it appears to have reached a climax in the history of human relations. (1954: 54) These rugged intellectual positions supported by evidential and well thought-out proofs quickly heralded a shift in the intellectual culture of the world. But there was one problem George James could not fix; he could not prove that the people of North Africa (Egyptians) who were the true authors of ancient art, sciences, religion and philosophy were dark complexioned Africans, as can be seen in his hopeful but inconsistent conclusions: This is going to mean a tremendous change in world opinion, and attitude, for all people and races who accept the new philosophy of Africa redemption, i.e. the truth that the Greeks were not the authors of Greek philosophy; but the people of North Africa; would change their opinion from one of disrespect to one of respect for the black people throughout the world and treat them accordingly. (1954: 153) It is inconsistent how the achievements of North Africans (Egyptians) can redeem the black Africans. This is also the problem with Henri Olela’s article “The African Foundations of Greek Philosophy”.
  • 12. In Onyewuenyi’s The African Origin of Greek Philosophy however, an ambitious attempt emerges to fill this lacuna in the argument of new philosophy of African redemption. In the first part of chapter two, he reduced the Greek philosophy to Egyptian philosophy, and in the second part, he attempted to further reduce the Egyptians of the time to dark complexioned Africans. There are, however, two holes he could not fill. First, Egypt is the world’s oldest standing country who also told their own story by themselves in different forms. At no point did they or other historians describe them as dark complexioned people. Second, if the Egyptians were at a time wholly dark complexioned, why are they now wholly light complexioned? For the failure of this group of scholars to prove that dark complexioned Africans were the authors of Egyptian philosophy, one must abandon the Egyptian legacy. There are however other scholars of the early period who tried in more reliable ways to assert African identity by establishing native African philosophical heritage. One of such is Tempels who authored Bantu Philosophy (1949). He proved that rationality was an important feature of the traditional African culture. By systematizing Bantu philosophical ideas he confronted the racist orientation of the West which depicted Africa as a continent of semi-humans. In fact, Tempels showed the latent similarities in the spiritual inclinations of the Europeans and their African counterpart. In the opening passage of his work he observed that the European who has taken to atheism quickly returns to a Christian viewpoint when suffering or pain threatens his survival. In much the same way, he says the civilized or Christian Bantu returns to the ways of his ancestors when confronted by suffering and death. So, spiritual orientation or thinking is not found only in Africa. In his attempt to explain the Bantu understanding of being, Tempels admits that this might not be the same with the understanding of the European. Instead, he argues that the Bantu construction is as much rational as that of the European. In his words: So the criteriology of the Bantu rests upon external evidence, upon the authority and dominating life force of the ancestors. It rests at the same time upon the internal evidence of experience of nature and of living phenomena, observed from their point of view. No doubt, anyone can show the error of their reasoning; but it must none the less be admitted that their notions are based on reason, that their criteriology and their wisdom belong to rational knowledge. (1949/2006: 51) Tempels obviously believes that the Bantu, like the rest of the African tribes, posses rationality which undergird their philosophical enterprise. The error in their reasoning is only obvious in the light of European logic. The Bantu categories only differ from those of the Europeans, which is why a first-time European on-looker would misinterpret them to be irrational or spiritual. This effort clearly makes a case for Africa’s true identity, which, for him, could be found in African religion within which African philosophy (ontology) is subsumed. In his words, “being is force, force is being”. And the same could be said of Alexis Kagame’s work The Bantu-Rwandan Philosophy(1956), which offers similar proofs and arguments thus further strengthening the claims of Tempels, especially from an African’s perspective. The major criticism against their industry remains the association of their thoughts with ethnophilosophy, where ethnophilosophy is seen pejoratively. A much more studded criticism is offered recently by Innocent Asouzu in his
  • 13. workIbuanyidanda: New Complementary Ontology (2007). His criticism was not directed at the validity of the thoughts they expressed or whether Africa could boast of a rational enterprise such as philosophy but at the logical foundation of their thoughts. Asouzu seems to quarrel with Tempels for allowing his native Aristotelian orientation to influence his construction of African philosophy and lambasts Kagame for following suit instead of correcting Tempels’ mistake. The principle of bivalence as evidenced in the Western thought system was at the background of their construction. Another important philosopher in this period is John Mbiti. His work African Religions and Philosophy (1969) avidly educated those who doubted Africans’ possession of their own identities before the arrival of the European by excavating and demonstrating the rationality in the religious and philosophical enterprises in African cultures. He boldly declared: “We shall use the singular, ‘philosophy’ to refer to the philosophical understanding of African peoples concerning different issues of life” (1969: 2). His presentation of time in African thought shows off the pattern of excavation in his African philosophy. Although his studies focus primarily on the Kikamba and Gikuyu tribes of Africa, he observes that there are similarities in many African cultures just as Tempels did earlier. He subsumes African philosophy in African religion on the assumption that African peoples do not know how to exist without religion. This idea is also shared by William Abraham in his book The Mind of Africa as well as Tempels’ Bantu Philosophy. African philosophy, from Mbiti’s treatment, could be likened to Tempels’ vital force, of which African religion is its outer cloak. The obvious focus of this book is on African views about God, political thought, afterlife, culture or world-view and creation, the philosophical aspects lie within these religious over-coats. Thus, Mbiti establishes that the true, and lost, identity of the African could be found within his religion. Another important observation Mbiti made was that this identity is communal and not individualistic. Hence, he states, “I am because we are and since we are therefore I am” (1969: 108). Therefore, the African has to re-enter his religion to find his philosophy and the community to find his identity. This is a view shared by William Abraham in his The Mind of Africa (1962). He shares Tempels’ and Mbiti’s views that the dark complexioned African tribes have many similarities in their culture, though his studies focus on the culture and political thought of the Akan of present day Ghana. Another important aspect of Abraham’s work is that he subsumed African philosophical thought in African culture taking, as Barry Hallen described, “an essentialist interpretation of African culture” (2002: 15). Thus for Abraham, like Tempels and Mbiti, the lost African identity could be found in the seabed of African indigenous culture in which religion features prominently. On the other hand, there were those who sought to retrieve and establish once again Africa’s lost identity through economic and political ways. Some names discussed here include Kwame Nkrumah, Leopold Senghor and Julius Nyerere. These actors felt that the African could never be truly decolonized unless he found his own system of living and social organization. One cannot be African living like the European. The question that guided their study therefore became, “What system of economic and social engineering will suit us and project our true identity?” Nkrumah advocates African socialism, which, according to Barry Hallen, is an original, social, political and philosophical theory of African origin and orientation. This system is forged from the traditional, communal structure of African society, a view strongly projected by Mbiti. Nkrumah says that a return to African cultural system with its astute moral values, communal ownership of
  • 14. land and a humanitarian social and political engineering holds the key to Africa rediscovering her lost identity. Systematizing this process, will yield what he calls the African brand of socialism. In most of his books, he projects the idea that Africa’s lost identity is to be found in African native culture within which is African philosophical thought and identity shaped by communal orientation. Some of his works include, Neo- colonialism: The Last Stage of Imperialism (1965), I Speak of Freedom: A Statement of African Ideology (1961), Africa Must Unite (1970), and Consciencism (1954). Leopold Sedar Senghor of Senegal charted a course similar to that of Nkrumah. In his works Negritude et Humanisme (1964) and Negritude and the Germans (1967), Senghor traced Africa’s philosophy of social engineering down to African culture, which he said is communal and laden with brotherly emotion. This is different from the European system, which he says is individualistic, having been marshaled purely by reason. He opposed the French colonial principle of assimilation aimed at turning Africans into Frenchmen by eroding and replacing African culture with French culture. African culture and languages are the bastions of African identity, and it is in this culture that he found the pedestal for constructing a political ideology that would project African lost identity. Senghor is in agreement with Nkrumah, Mbiti, Abraham and Tempels in many ways, especially with regards to the basis for Africa’s true identity. Julius Nyerere of Tanzania is another philosopher of note in the early period of African philosophy. In his books Uhuru na Ujamaa: Freedom and Socialism (1964) and Ujamaa: The Basis of African Socialism (1968), he sought to retrieve and establish African true identity through economic and political ways. For him, Africans cannot regain their identity unless they are first free and freedom (Uhuru) transcends independence. Cultural imperialism has to be overcome. And what is the best way to achieve this if not by developing a socio-political and economic ideology from the petals of African native culture, and traditional values of togetherness and brotherliness? Hence, Nyerere proposes Ujamaa, meaning familyhood—the “being-with” philosophy or the “we” instead of the “I—spirit” (Okoro 2004: 96). In the words of Barry Hallen, “Nyerere argued that there was a form of life and system of values indigenous to the culture of pre-colonial Africa, Tanzania in particular, that was distinctive if not unique and that had survived the onslaughts of colonialism sufficiently intact to be regenerated as the basis for an African polity” (2002: 74). Thus for Nyerere, the basis of African identity is the African culture, which is communal rather than individualistic. Nyerere was in agreement with other actors of this period on the path to full recovery of Africa’s lost identity. Other philosophers of this era not treated here include Nnamdi Azikiwe, Obafemi Awolowo, Amilcar Cabral, and the two foreigners, Janheinz Jahn and Marcel Griaule. b. Middle Period The middle period of African philosophy is also an era of the twin-movement called Afro- constructionism and afro-deconstructionism, otherwise called the Great Debate, when two rival schools—Traditionalists and Universalists clashed. While the Traditionalists sought to construct an African identity based on excavated African cultural elements, the Universalists sought to demolish such architectonic structure by associating it with ethnophilosophy. The schools that thrived in this era include Philosophic Sagacity, Professional/Modernist/Universalist, hermeneutical and Literary schools.
  • 15. An important factor of the early period is that the thoughts on the basis for Africa’s true identity generated arguments that fostered the emergence of the Middle Period of African philosophy. These arguments result from questions that could be summarized as follows: (1) Is it proper to take for granted the sweeping assertion that all of Africa’s cultures share a few basic elements in common? It was this assumption that had necessitated the favorite phrase in the early period, “African philosophy,” rather than “African philosophies”. (2) Does Africa or African culture contain a philosophy in the strict sense of the term? (3) Can African philosophy emerge from the womb of African religion, world-view and culture? Answers and objections to answers soon took the shape of a debate, characterizing the middle period as the era of the Great Debate in African philosophy. This debate was between members of Africa’s new crop of intellectual radicals. On one hand, are the demoters and, on the other, are the promoters of African philosophy established by the league of early period intellectuals. The former sought to criticize this new philosophy of redemption, gave it a derogatory tag “ethnophilosophy” and consequently denigrated the African Identity that was founded on it as savage and primitive identity. At the other end, the promoters sought to clarify and defend this philosophy and justify the African identity that was rooted in it as true and original. For clarity, the assessment of the debate era will begin from the middle instead of the beginning. In 1978 Odera Oruka a Kenyan philosopher presented a paper at the William Amo Symposium held in Accra, Ghana on the topic “Four Trends in Current African Philosophy” in which he identified or grouped voices on African philosophy into four schools, namely ethnophilosophy, philosophic sagacity, nationalistic-ideological school and professional philosophy. In 1990 he wrote another work, Sage Philosophy: Indigenous Thinker and the Modern Debate on African Philosophy in which he further added two schools to bring the number to six schools in African philosophy. Those two additions are the hermeneutic and the artistic/literary schools. Those who uphold philosophy in African culture are the ethnophilosophers and these include the actors treated as members of the early period of African philosophy and their followers or supporters in the Middle Period. These would include C. S. Momoh, Joseph Omoregbe, Lansana Keita, Olusegun Oladipo, Gordon Hunnings, Kwame Gyekye, M. A. Makinde, Emmanuel Edeh, Uzodinma Nwala, K. C. Anyanwu and later E. A. Ruch, to name a few. The philosophic sagacity school, to which Oruka belongs, also accommodates C. S. Momoh, C. B. Nze, J. I. Omoregbe, C. B. Okolo and T. F. Mason. The nationalist- ideological school consists of those who sought to develop indigenous socio-political and economic ideologies for Africa. Prominent members include Julius Nyerere, Leopold Senghor, Kwame Nkrumah, Amilcar Cabral, Nnamdi Azikiwe and Obafemi Awolowo. The professional philosophy school insists that African philosophy must be done with professional philosophical methods such as analysis, critical reflection and logical coherence as it is in Western philosophy. Members of this school include: Henri Maurier, Richard Wright, Peter Bodunrin, Kwasi Wiredu, early E. A. Ruch, R. Horton, and later C. B. Okolo. The hermeneutic school recommends linguistic analysis as a method of doing African philosophy. A few of its members include Theophilus Okere, Okonda Okolo, Tsenay Serequeberhan, Godwin Sogolo and partly J. Sodipo and B. Hallen. The Artistic/Literary school philosophically discusses the core of African norms, and includes Chinua Achebe, Okot P’Bitek, Ngugi wa Thiong’o, Wole Soyinka, Elechi Amadi and F. C. Ogbalu.
  • 16. Also, in 1989, C. S. Momoh in his The Substance of African Philosophy outlined five schools, namely African logical neo-positivism, the colonial/missionary school of thought, the Egyptological school, the ideological school and the purist school. The article was titled “Nature, Issues and Substance of African Philosophy” and was reproduced in Jim Unah’s Metaphysics, Phenomenology and African Philosophy (1996). In comparing Momoh’s delineations with Oruka’s, it can be said that the purist school encompasses Oruka’s ethnophilosophy, artistic/literary school and philosophic sagacity; The African logical neo-positivism encompasses professional philosophy and the hermeneutical schools; and the ideological and colonial/missionary schools correspond to Oruka’s nationalistic-ideological school. The Egyptological school, therefore, remains outstanding. Momoh sees it as a school which sees African philosophy as synonymous with Egyptian philosophy or at least, as originating from it. Also, Egyptian philosophy as a product of African philosophy is also expressed in the writings of George James, I. C. Onyewuenyi and Henry Olela. Welding all these divisions together are the perspectives of Peter Bodunrin and Kwasi Wiredu. In the introduction to his 1985 edited volume Philosophy in Africa: Trends and Perspectives, Bodunrin created two broad schools for all the subdivisions in both Oruka and Momoh, namely the Traditionalist and Modernist schools. While the former includes Africa’s rich culture and past, the latter excludes them from the mainstream of African philosophy. Kwasi Wiredu also made this type of division, specifically Traditional and Modernist, in his paper “On Defining African Philosophy” in C. S. Momoh’s (1989) edited volume. Also, A. F. Uduigwomen created two broad schools, namely the Universalists and the Particularists, in his “Philosophy and the Place of African Philosophy” (1995). These can be equated to Bodunrin’s Modernist and Traditionalist schools respectively. The significance of his contribution to the Great Debate rests on the new school he evolved from the compromise of the Universalist and the Particularist schools (1995/2009: 2-7). As Uduigwomen defines it, the Eclectic school accommodates discourses pertaining to African experiences, culture and world-view as parts of African philosophy. Those discourses must be critical, argumentative and rational. In other words, the so-called ethnophilosophy can comply with the analytic and argumentative standards that people like Bodunrin, Hountondji, and Wiredu insist upon. Many later African philosophers revived Uduigwomen’s Eclectic school as a much more decisive approach to African philosophy (Kanu 2013: 275-87). It is the era dominated by Eclecticism and meta- philosophy that is tagged the ‘Later period’ in the history of African philosophy. For perspicuity therefore, the debate from these two broad schools shall be addressed as the perspectives of the Traditionalist or Particularist and the Modernist or Universalist. The reader must now have understood the perspectives on which the individual philosophers of the middle period debated. Hence, when Richard Wright published his critical essay “Investigating African Philosophy” and Henri Maurier published his “Do we have an African Philosophy?” denying the existence of African philosophy at least, as yet, the reader understands why Lansana Keita’s “The African Philosophical Tradition”, C. S. Momoh’s African Philosophy … does it exist?” or J. I. Omoregbe’s “African Philosophy: Yesterday and Today” are offered as critical responses. When Wright arrived at the conclusion that the problems surrounding the study of African philosophy are so great that others are effectively prevented from any worthwhile work until their resolution, Henri Maurier responded to the question, “Do we have an African Philosophy?” with “No!
  • 17. Not Yet!” (1984: 25). One would understand why Lansana Keita took it up to provide concrete evidence that Africa had and still has a philosophical tradition. In his words: It is the purpose of this paper to present evidence that a sufficiently firm literate philosophical tradition has existed in Africa since ancient times, and that this tradition is of sufficient intellectual sophistication to warrant serious analysis…it is rather…an attempt to offer a defensible idea of African philosophy. (1984: 58) Keita went on in that paper to excavate intellectual resources to prove his case, but it was J. I. Omoregbe who tackled the demoters on every front. Of particular interest are his critical commentaries on the position of Kwasi Wiredu and others who share Wiredu’s opinion that what is called African philosophy is not philosophy but community thought at best. Omoregbe alludes that the logic and method of African philosophy need not be the same as those of Western philosophy, which the demoters cling to. In his words: It is not necessary to employ Aristotelian or the Russellian logic in this reflective activity before one can be deemed to be philosophizing. It is not necessary to carry out this reflective activity in the same way that the Western thinkers did. Ability to reason logically and coherently is an integral part of man’s rationality. The power of logical thinking is identical with the power of rationality. It is therefore false to say that people cannot think logically or reason coherently unless they employ Aristotle’s or Russell’s form of logic or even the Western-type argumentation. (1998: 4-5) Omoregbe was addressing the position of most members of the Modernist school who believed that African philosophy must follow the pattern of Western philosophy if it were to exist. As he cautions: Some people, trained in Western philosophy and its method, assert that there is no philosophy and no philosophizing outside the Western type of philosophy or the Western method of philosophizing (which they call “scientific” or “technical”. (1998: 5) Philosophers like E. A. Ruch in some of his earlier writings,, Peter Bodunrin, C. B. Okolo, and Robin Horton were direct recipients of Omoregbe’s sledge hammer. Robin Horton’s “African Traditional Thought and Western Science” is a two part essay that sought in the long run to expose the rational ineptitude in African thought. On the question of logic in African philosophy, Robin Horton’s “Traditional Thought and the emerging African Philosophy Department: A Comment on the Current Debate” first stirred the hornet’s nest and was ably challenged by Godorn Hunnings’ “Logic, Language and Culture”, as well as by Omoregbe’s “African Philosophy: Yesterday and Today”. Earlier, Meinrad Hebga’s “Logic in Africa” had made insightful ground clearing on the matter. Recently, C.S. Momoh’s “The Logic Question in African Philosophy” and Udo Etuk’s “The Possibility of an African Logic” as well as Jonathan C. Okeke’s “Why can’t there be an African Logic” made impressions. However, this logic question is gathering new momentum in African philosophical discourse.
  • 18. On the philosophical angle, Kwasi Wiredu’s “How not to Compare African Traditional Thought with Western Thought” responded to the lopsided earlier effort of Robin Horton but ended up making its own criticisms of the status of African philosophy which, for Wiredu, is yet to attain maturation. In his words, “[M]any traditional African institutions and cultural practices, such as the ones just mentioned, are based on superstition. By ‘superstition’ I mean a rationally unsupported belief in entities of any sort (1976: 4-8 and 1995: 194).” In his Philosophy and an African Culture, Wiredu was more pungent. He caricatured much of the discourse on African philosophy as community thought or folk thought unqualified to be called philosophy. For him, there had to be a practiced distinction between “African philosophy as folk thought preserved in oral traditions and African philosophy as critical, individual reflection, using modern logical and conceptual techniques” (1980: 14). Olusegun Oladipo supports this in his Philosophy and the African Experience. As he puts it: But this kind of attitude is mistaken. In Africa we are engaged in the task of the improvement of “the condition of men”. There can be no successful execution of this task without a reasonable knowledge of, and control over, nature. But essential to the quest for knowledge of, and control over, nature are “logical, mathematical and analytical procedures” which are products of modern intellectual practices. The glorification of the “unanalytical cast of mind” which a conception of African philosophy as African folk thought encourages would not avail us the opportunity of taking advantage of the theoretical and practical benefits offered by these intellectual procedures. It thus can only succeed in making the task of improving the condition of man in Africa a daunting one.(1996: 15) Oladipo also shares similar thoughts in his The Idea of African Philosophy. African philosophy for some of the Modernists is practiced in a debased sense. This position is considered opinionated by the Traditionalists. Later E. A. Ruch and K. C. Anyanwu in their African Philosophy: An Introduction to the Main Philosophical Trends in Contemporary Africa attempt to excavate the philosophical elements in folklore and myth. C. S. Momoh’s “The Mythological Question in African Philosophy” and K. C. Anyanwu’s “Philosophical Significance of Myth and Symbol in Dogon World-View” further reinforced the position of the Traditionalists.(cf. Momoh 1989 and Anyanwu 1989) However, it took Paulin Hountondji in his African Philosophy: Myth and Reality to drive a long nail in the coffin. African philosophy, for him, must be done in the same frame as Western philosophy, including its principles, methodologies, methods and all. K. C. Anyanwu again admitted that Western philosophy is one of the challenges facing African philosophy but that only calls for systematization of African philosophy not its decimation. He made these arguments in his paper “The Problem of Method in African philosophy”. Other arguments set Greek standards for authentic African philosophy as can be found in Odera Oruka’s “The Fundamental Principles in the Question of ‘African Philosophy’ (I)” and Hountondji’s “African Wisdom and Modern Philosophy.” They readily met with Lansana Keita’s “African Philosophical Systems: A Rational Reconstruction”, J. Kinyongo’s “Philosophy in Africa: An Existence” and even P. K. Roy’s “African Theory of Knowledge”. For every step the Modernists took, the Traditionalists replied with two, a response that lingered till the early 1990’s when a certain phase of disillusionment began to set in to quell the debate. Actors on both fronts had only then begun to reach a new
  • 19. consciousness, realizing that a new step had to be taken beyond the debate. Even Kwasi Wiredu who had earlier justified the debate by his insistence that “without argument and clarification, there is strictly no philosophy” (1980: 47) had to admit that it was time to do something else. For him, African philosophers had to go beyond talking about African philosophy and get down to actually doing it. It was with this sort of new orientation which emerged from the disillusionment of the protracted debate that the later period of African philosophy was born in the 1980’s. As it is said in the Igbo proverb, “The music makers almost unanimously were changing the rhythm and the dancers had to change their dance steps.” One of the high points of the disillusionment was the emergence of the Eclectic school in the next period called ‘the Later Period’ of African philosophy. c. Later Period This period of African philosophy heralds the emergence of the movements which can be called Critical Reconstructionism and Afro-Eclecticism. For the Deconstructionists of the middle period, the focus shifted from deconstruction to reconstruction of African episteme in a universally integrated way; whereas, for the eclectics, finding a reconcilable middle path between traditional African philosophy and the modern African philosophy should be paramount. Thus they advocate a shift from entrenched ethnophilosophy and universal hue to the reconstruction of African episteme if somewhat different from the imposed Westernism and the uncritical ethnophilosophy. So, both the Critical Reconstructionists and the Eclectics advocate one form of reconstruction or the other. The former desire a new episteme untainted by ethnophilosophy while the later sue for reconciled central and relevant ideals. Not knowing how to proceed to this sort of task was a telling problem on all advocates of critical reconstruction in African philosophy such as V. Y. Mudimbe, Ebousi Boulaga, Olusegun Oladipo, Franz Crahey and Marcien Towa to name a few. At the dawn of the era, these African legionnaires pointed out, in different terms, that reconstructing African episteme was imperative. But more urgent was the need to first analyse the haggard philosophical structure patched into existence with the cement of perverse dialogues. It appeared inexorable to these thinkers and others of the time that none of these can be successful outside the shadow of Westernism. For whatever one writes which is effectively free from ethnophilosophy is either contained in Western discourse or in the very least proceeds from its logic. If it is already contained in Western narrative or proceeds from its logic, what then makes it African? This became a something of a dead-end for this illustrious group, which struggled against evolutions in their positions. Intuitively, almost every analyst knows that discussing what has been discussed in Western philosophy or taking a lead from Western philosophy does not absolutely negate or vitiate what is produced as African philosophy. But how is this to be effectively justified? This appears to be the Achilles heel of the Critical Reconstructionists of the later period in African philosophy. The massive failure of these Critical Reconstructionists to go beyond the lines of recommendation and actually engage in reconstructing delayed
  • 20. their emergence as a school of thought in African philosophy. The diversionary matrix which occurred at this point ensured that the later period, which began with the two rival camps of Critical Reconstructionists and Eclectics, ended with only the Eclectics left standing. Thus dying in its embryo, Critical Reconstructionism became absorbed in Eclecticism. The campaign for Afro-reconstructionism had first emerged in the late 1980‘s in the writings of Peter Bodunrin, Kwasi Wiredu, V. Y. Mudimbe and Olusegun Oladipo, even though principals like Marcien Towa and Franz Crahey had hinted at it much earlier. The insights of the latter two never rang bells beyond the ear-shot of identity reconstruction, which was the echo of their time. Wiredu’s cry for conceptual decolonization and Hountondji’s call for the abandonment of the ship of ethnophilosophy were in the spirit of Afro-reconstructionism of the episteme. None of the Afro-reconstructionists except for Wiredu was able to truly chart a course for reconstruction. His was linguistic even though the significance of his campaign was never truly appreciated. His 1998 work “Toward Decolonizing African Philosophy and Religion,” was a clearer recapitulation of his works of preceding years. Beyond this modest line, no other reconstructionist crusader of the time actually went beyond deconstruction and problem identification. Almost spontaneously, Afro- reconstructionism evolved into Afro-eclecticism in the early 1990’s when the emerging Critical Reconstructionism ran into a brick wall of inactivity. The argument seems to say, “If it is not philosophically permissible to employ alternative logic different from the one in the West or methods, perhaps we can make do with the merger of the approaches we have identified in African philosophy following the deconstructions.” These approaches are the various schools of thought from ethnophilosophy, philosophic sagacity, ideological school, universal, literary to hermeneutic schools which were deconstructed into two broad approaches namely: The traditionalist school and the modernist school also called the particularist and the universalist schools. Eclectics, therefore, are those who think that the effective integration or complementation of the African native system and the Western system could produce a viable synthesis that is first African and then modern. Andrew Uduigwomen, the Nigerian philosopher could be regarded as the founder of this school in African philosophy. In his 1995 work “Philosophy and the Place of African Philosophy,” he gave official birth to the Afro- eclecticism. Identifying the Traditionalist and Modernist schools as the Particularist and Universalist schools, he created the eclectic school by carefully unifying their goals from the ruins of the deconstructed past. Uduigwomen states that the eclectic school holds that an intellectual romance between the Universalist conception and the Particularist conception will give rise to an authentic African philosophy. The Universalist approach will provide the necessary analytic and conceptual framework for the Particularist school. Since, according to Uduigwomen, this framework cannot thrive in a vacuum, the Particularist approach will in turn supply the raw materials or indigenous data needed by the Universalist approach. From the submission of Uduigwomen above, one easily detects that Eclecticism for him entails employing Western methods in analyzing African cultural paraphernalia.
  • 21. However, Afro-Eclecticism is not without problems. The first problem though, is that he did not supply the yardstick for determining what is to be admitted and what must be left out of the corpus of African tradition. Everything cannot meet the standard of genuine philosophy, nor should the philosophical selection be arbitrary. Hountondji, a chronic critic of traditional efforts once called Tempels’ Bantu philosophy a sham. For him, it was not African or Bantu philosophy but Tempels’ philosophy with African paraphernalia. This could be extended to the vision of Afro-eclecticism. On the contrary, it could be argued that if Hountondji agrees that the synthesis contains as little as African paraphernalia, then it is something new and in this respect can claim the tag of African philosophy. However, it leaves to be proven how philosophical that little African paraphernalia is. Other notable eclectics include Batholomew Abanuka, Udobata Onunwa, C. C. Ekwealor and much later Chris Ijiomah. Abanuka posits in his 1994 work that a veritable way to doing authentic African philosophy would be to recognize the unity of individual things and, by extension, theories in ontology, epistemology or ethics. There is a basic identity among these because they are connected and can be unified. Following C. S. Momoh (1985: 12), Abanuka went on in A History of African Philosophy to argue that synthesis should be the ultimate approach to doing African Philosophy. This position is shared by Onunwa on a micro level. He says that realities in African world-view are inter-connected and inter-dependent (1991: 66-71). Ekwealor and Ijiomah also believe in synthesis, noting that these realities are broadly dualistic, being physical and spiritual (cf. Ekwalor 1990: 30 and Ijiomah 2005: 76 and 84). So, it would be an anomaly to think of African philosophy as chiefly an exercise in analysis rather than synthesis. The ultimate methodological approach to doing African philosophy, therefore, has to reflect unity of methods above all else. Eclecticism survived in the New Era of African philosophy in conversational forms. Godfrey Ozumba and Jonathan Chimakonam on Njikoka philosophy, E. G. Ekwuru and later Innocent Egwutuorah on Afrizealotism and even Innocent Asouzu on Ibuanyidanda ontology are all various forms of eclectic thinking. However, these theories are grouped in the New Era specifically for the time of their emergence and the conversational structure they have. The purest development of eclectic thinking in the later period could be found in Pantaleon Iroegbu’s Uwa Ontology. He posits uwa (worlds) as an abstract generic concept with fifteen connotations and six zones. Everything is uwa, in uwa and can be known through uwa. For him, while the fifteen connotations are the different senses and aspects which uwa concept carries in Igbo-African thought, the six zones are the spatio-temporal locations of the worlds in terms of their inhabitants. He adds that these six zones are dualistic and comprise of the earthly and the spiritual. They are also dynamic and mutually related. Thus, Iroegbu suggests that the approach to doing authentic African philosophy could consist in the conglomeration of uwa. This demonstrates a veritable Eclectic method in African philosophy. However, one of the major hindrances of Eclecticism of the later period is that it leads straight to applied philosophy. Following this approach in this period almost makes it impossible for second readers to do original and abstract philosophizing for its own sake.
  • 22. Eclectic theories and methods confine one to their internal dynamics believing that for a work to be regarded as authentic African philosophy, it must follow the rules of Eclecticism. The wider implication is that while creativity might blossom, innovation and originality are stifled. Because of pertinent problems such as these, further evolutions in African philosophy became inevitable. The Kenyan philosopher Odera Oruka had magnified the thoughts concerning individual rather than group philosophizing, thoughts that had been variously expressed earlier by Peter Bodunrin, Paulin Hountondji and Kwasi Wiredu, who further admonished African philosophers to stop talking and start doing African philosophy. And V. Y. Mudimbe, in his The Invention of Africa…, suggested the development of an African conversational philosophy, and the reinvention of Africa by its philosophers, to undermine the Africa that Europe invented. The content of Lewis Gordon’s essay “African Philosophy’s search for Identity: Existential consideration of a recent effort” suggests a craving for a new line of development for African philosophy—a new approach which is to be critical, engaging and universal while still being African. This, in particular, is the spirit of the conversational African philosophy beginning to grip African philosophers in late 1990’s when Gordon wrote his paper. Influences from these thoughts by the turn of the millennium year crystallized into a new mode of thinking, which then metamorphosed into conversational philosophy. The New Era in African philosophy was thus heralded. The focus of this New Era and the orientation became the conversational philosophy. d. New Era This period of African philosophy began in the late 1990’s and took shape by the turn of the millennium years. The orientation of this period is conversational philosophy, so, conversationalism is the movement that thrives in this period. The University of Calabar has emerged as the international headquarters of this new movement hosting various workshops, colloquia and conferences in African philosophy under the auspices of a radical forum called The Conversational/Calabar School of Philosophy. In the Calabar School of Philosophy, some prominent theories have emerged, namely ibuanyidanda (complementary reflection) (Innocent Asouzu), harmonious monism (Chris Ijiomah), Njikoka philosophy (Godfrey Ozumba and Jonathan Chimakonam) and conversational philosophy (Jonathan Chimakonam). All these theories speak to the method of conversational philosophy. Conversational philosophy is defined by the active engagement between individual African philosophers in the creation of critical narratives either by engaging the elements of tradition or straight-forwardly by producing new thoughts or by engaging other individual thinkers. It thrives on incessant questioning geared toward the production of new concepts, opening up new vistas and sustaining the conversation. Some of the African philosophers whose works follow this trajectory ironically have emerged in the Western world, notably in America. The American philosopher Jennifer Lisa Vest is one of them. Another one is Bruce Janz. These two, to name a few, suggest that the highest purification of African philosophy is to be realized in the conversational- styled philosophizing. However, it was the Nigerian philosopher Innocent Asouzu who went beyond the earlier botched attempt of Leopold Senghor and transcended the foundations of Pantaleon Iroegbu to erect a new model of African philosophy that is conversational. The New Era, therefore, is the beginning of conversational philosophy.
  • 23. Iroegbu in his Metaphysics: The Kpim of Philosophy inaugurated the reconstructive and conversational approach in African philosophy. He engaged previous writers in a critical conversation out of which he produced his own thought, (Uwa ontology) bearing the stain of African tradition and thought systems but remarkably different in approach and method of ethnophilosophy. Franz Fanon has highlighted the importance of sourcing African philosophical paraphernalia from African indigenous culture. This is corroborated in a way by Lucius Outlaw in his African Philosophy: Deconstructive and Reconstructive Challenges. In it, Outlaw advocates the deconstruction of the European- invented Africa to be replaced by a reconstruction to be done by conscientious Africans free from the grip of colonial mentality (1996: 11). Whereas the Wiredu’s crusade sought to deconstruct the invented Africa, actors in the New Era of African philosophy seek to reconstruct through conversational approach. Iroegbu inaugurated this drive but it was Asouzu who has made the most of it. His theory of Ibuanyidanda ontology or complementary reflection maintains that “to be” simply means to be in a mutual, complementary relationship (2007: 251-55). Every being, therefore, is a variable with capacity to join a mutual interaction. In this capacity every being alone is seen as a missing link and serving a missing link of reality in the network of realities. One immediately suspects the apparent contradiction that might arise from the fusion of two opposed variables when considered logically. But the logic of this theory is not the two-valued classical logic but the three-valued system of logic developed in Africa (cf. Chimakonam 2012, 2013 and 2014a). In this, the two standard values are sub- contraries rather than contradictories thereby facilitating effective complementation of variables. The possibility of the two standard values merging to form the third value in the complementary mode is what makes Ezumezu logic a powerful tool of thought. A good number of African philosophers are tuning their works into the pattern of conversational philosophy. In the southern Africa, Mogobe Ramose, Michael Eze, Fainos Mangena, Thaddeus Metz and Leonhard Praeg are doing this when they engage with the idea of ubuntu ethics and ontology. Like all these thinkers, the champions of the new conversational orientation are building the new edifice by reconstructing the deconstructed domain of thought in the later period of African philosophy. The central approach is conversation. By engaging other African philosophers or tradition in critical and positive discourses, they hope to reconstruct the deconstructed edifice of African philosophy. Hence, the New Era of African philosophy is safe from the retrogressive, perverse dialogues which characterized the early and middle periods. Also, with the critical deconstruction that occurred in the later part of the middle period and the attendant eclecticism that emerged in the later period, the stage was set for the formidable reconstructions and conversational encounters that marked the arrival of the New Era of African philosophy. 7. Conclusion The development of African philosophy through the periods yields two vital conceptions for African philosophy, namely that African philosophy is a critical engagement of tradition and individual thinkers on one hand, and on the other hand it is also a critical construction of futurity. When individual African philosophers engage tradition critically
  • 24. in order to ascertain its logical coherency and universal validity, they are doing African philosophy. And when they employ the tools of logic in doing this, they are doing African philosophy. On the second conception, when African philosophers engage in critical conversations with one another and in construction of new thoughts in matters that concern Africa but which are nonetheless universal and projected from African native thought systems, they are doing African philosophy. So, the authentic African philosophy is not just a future project, it can also continue from the past. On the whole, this essay discussed the journey of African philosophy from the beginning and focused on the criteria, schools and movements in African philosophical tradition. The historical account of the periods in African philosophy began with the early period through to the middle, the later and finally the new periods of African philosophy have also been covered taking particular interest in the robust, individual contributions. There are still some questions which trail the development of African philosophy, many of which include, “Must African philosophy be tailored to the pattern of Western philosophy, even in less definitive issues? If African philosophy is found to be different in approach from Western philosophy, — so what? Are logical issues likely to play any major roles in the structure and future of African philosophy? What is the future direction of African philosophy? Is the problem of the language of African philosophy pregnant? Would conversations in contemporary African philosophy totally eschew perverse dialogue? What shall be the rules of engagement in African philosophy?” These questions are likely to shape the next lines of thought in African philosophy.
  • 25. 8. References and Further Reading  Abanuka, Batholomew. A History of African Philosophy. Enugu: Snaap Press, 2011.  An epochal discussion of African philosophy.  Abraham, William. The Mind of Africa. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1962.  A philosophical discussion of culture, African thought and colonial times.  Achebe, Chinua. Morning yet on Creation Day. London: Heinemann, 1975.  A philosophical treatment of African tradition and colonial burden.  Anyanwu, K. C. “Philosophical Significance of Myth and Symbol in Dogon World-view”. C. S. Momoh ed. The Substance of African Philosophy. Auchi: APP Publications, 1989  A discussion of the philosophical elements in an African culture.  Aristotle. Metaphysica, Translated into English under the editorship of W. D. Ross, M.A., Hon. LL.D (Edin.) Oxford. Vol. VIII, Second Edition, OXFORD at the Clarendon Press 1926. Online Edition. 982b.  A translation of Aristotle’s treatise on metaphysics.  Asouzu I. Innocent. Ibuanyidanda: New Complementary Ontology Beyond World-Immanentism, Ethnocentric Reduction and Impositions. Litverlag, Münster, Zurich, New Brunswick, London, 2007  An African perspective treatment of metaphysics or the theory of complementarity of beings.  Babalola, Yai. “Theory and Practice in African Philosophy: The Poverty of Speculative Philosophy. A Review of the Work of P. Hountondji, M. Towa, et al.” Second Order, 2. 2. 1977  A Critical review of Hountondji and Towa.  Betts, Raymond. Assimilation and Association in French Colonial Territory 1890 to 1915. (First ed. 1961), Reprinted. Nebraska: University of Nebraska Press, 2005  A discourse on French colonial policies.  Bodunrin, Peter. “The Question of African Philosophy”. Richard Wright (ed) African Philosophy: An Introduction 3rd ed. Lanham: UPA, 1984.  A discourse on the nature and universal conception of African philosophy.  Cesaire Aimer. Return to My Native Land. London: Penguin Books, 1969  A presentation of colonial impact on the mind of the colonized.  Chimakonam, O. Jonathan. “Ezumezu: A Variant of Three-valued Logic—Insights and Controversies”. Paper presented at the Annual Conference of the Philosophical Society of Southern Africa. Free State University, Bloemfontein, South Africa. Jan. 20-22, 2014.  An articulation of the structure of Ezumezu/African logic tradition.  Chimakonam, O. Jonathan.“Principles of Indigenous African Logic: Toward Africa’s Development and Restoration of African Identity” Paper presented at the 19th Annual Conference of International Society for African Philosophy and Studies [ISAPS], ‘50 Years of OAU/AU: Revisiting the Questions of African Unity, Identity and Development’. Department of Philosophy, Nnamdi Azikiwe University, Awka. 27th – 29th May, 2013  A presentation of the principles of Ezumezu/African logic tradition.  Chimakonam, O. Jonathan.“Integrative Humanism: Extensions and Clarifications”. Integrative Humanism Journal. 3.1, 2013.  Further discussions on the theory of integrative humanism.  Du Bois, W. E. B. The Souls of Black Folk. (1903). New York: Bantam Classic edition, 1989  A discourse on race and cultural imperialism.  Edeh, Emmanuel. Igbo Metaphysics. Chicago: Loyola University Press, 1985.  An Igbo-African discourse on the nature being.  Ekwealor, C. “The Igbo World-View: A General Survey”. The Humanities and All of Us.  Emeka Oguegbu (ed) Onitsha: Watchword, 1990.  A philosophical presentation of Igbo life-world.  Etuk, Udo. “The Possibility of African logic”. The Third Way in African Philosophy, Olusegun Oladipo (ed). Ibadan: Hope Publications, 2002  A discussion of the nature and possibility of African logic.  Franz, Fanon. The Wretched of the Earth. London: The Chaucer Press, 1965.  A critical discourse on race and colonialism.
  • 26.  Graiule, Marcel. Conversations with Ogotemmêli, London: Oxford University Press for the International African Institute, 1965.  An interlocutory presentation of African philosophy.  Gyekye, Kwame. An Essay in African Philosophical Thought: The Akan Conceptual Scheme. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1987.  A discussion of philosophy from an African cultural view point.  Hallen, Barry. A Short History of African Philosophy. Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 2002.  A presentation of the history of African philosophy from thematic and personality perspectives.  Hallen, B. and J. O. Sodipo. Knowledge, Belief and Witchcraft: Analytic Experiments in African Philosophy. Palo Alto, CA: Stanford University Press, 1997.  An analytic discourse of the universal nature of themes and terms in African philosophy.  Hebga, Meinrad. “Logic in Africa”. Philosophy Today, Vol.11 No.4/4 (1958).  An extrapolation on the structure of African logical tradition.  Hegel, Georg. Lectures on the Philosophy of World History. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, reprint 1975  Hegel’s discussion of his philosophy of world history.  Horton, Robin. “African Traditional Religion and Western Science” in Africa 37: 1 and 2, 1967.  A comparison of African and Western thought.  Horton, Robin. "Traditional Thought and the Emerging African Philosophy Department: A Comment on the Current Debate” in Second Order: An African Journal of Philosophy vol. III No. 1, 1977.  A logical critique of the idea of African philosophy.  Hountondji, Paulin. African Philosophy: Myth and Reality. Second Revised ed. Bloomington, Indiana: University Press, 1996.  A critique of ethnophilosophy and an affirmation of African philosophy as a universal discourse.  Hunnings, Gordon. “Logic, Language and Culture”. Second Order: An African Journal of Philosophy, Vol.4, No.1. (1975).  A critique of classical logic and its laws in African thought and a suggestion of African logical tradition.  Ijiomah, Chris. “An Excavation of a Logic in African World-view”. African Journal of Religion, Culture and Society. 1. 1. (August, 2006): pp.29-35.  An extrapolation on a possible African logic tradition.  Iroegbu, Pantaleon. Metaphysics: The Kpim of Philosophy. Owerri: International Universities Press, 1995.  A conversational presentation of theory of being in African philosophy.  Jacques, Tomaz. “Philosophy in Black: African Philosophy as a Negritude”. Discursos  Postcoloniales Entorno Africa. CIEA7, No. 17, 7th Congress of African Studies.  A critique of the rigor of African philosophy as a discipline.  James, George . Stolen Legacy: Greek Philosophy is Stolen Egyptian Philosophy. New York: Philosophical Library, 1954.  A philosophical discourse on race, culture, imperialism and colonial deceit.  Jahn, Janheinz. Muntu: An Outline of Neo-African Culture. New York: Grove Press, 1961.  A presentation of a new African culture as a synthesis and as philosophical relevant and rational.  Jewsiewicki, Bogumil. “African Historical Studies: Academic Knowledge as ‘usable past’ and Radical Scholarship”. The African Studies Review. Vol. 32. No. 3, December, 1989.  A discourse on the value of African tradition to modern scholarship.  Keita, Lansana. “The African Philosophical Tradition”. Wright, Richard A., ed. African Philosophy: An Introduction. 3rd ed. Lanham, Md.: University Press of America, 1984.  An examination of African philosophical heritage.  Keita, Lansana. “Contemporary African Philosophy: The Search for a Method”. Tsanay Serequeberhan (ed) African Philosophy: The Essential Readings. New York: Paragon House, 1991.  An analysis of methodological issues in and basis of African philosophy.
  • 27.  Lambert, Michael. “From Citizenship to Négritude: Making a Difference in Elite Ideologies of Colonized Francophone West Africa”. Comparative Studies in Society and History, Vol. 35, No. 2. (Apr., 1993), pp. 239– 262.  A discourse on the problems of colonial policies in Francophone West Africa.  Lewis Gordon. “African Philosophy’s Search for Identity: Existential Considerations of a recent Effort”. The CLR James Journal, Winter 1997, pp. 98-117.  A survey of the identity crisis of African philosophical tradition.  Leo Apostel. African Philosophy. Belgium: Scientific Publishers, 1981.  An Afrocentrist presentation of African philosophy.  Levy-Bruhl, Lucien. Primitive Mentality. Paris: University of France Press, 1947.  A Eurocentrist presentation of non-European world.  Makinde, M.A. Philosophy in Africa. The Substance of African philosophy. C.S. Momoh. Ed. Auchi: African Philosophy Projects’ Publications. 2000.  A discourse on the practise and relevance of philosophy in Africa.  Masolo, D. A. African Philosophy in Search of Identity. Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1994.  An individual-based presentation of the history of African philosophy.  Maurier, Henri. “Do We have an African Philosophy?”. Wright, Richard A., ed. 1984. African Philosophy: An Introduction. 3rd ed. Lanham, Md.: University Press of America, 1984.  A critique of Ethnophilosophy as authentic African philosophy.  Mbiti, John. African Religions and Philosophy. London: Heinemann,1969.  A discourse on African philosophical culture.  Momoh, Campbell. “Canons of African Philosophy”. Paper presented at the 6th Congress of the Nigerian Philosophical Association. University of Ife, July 31- August 3, 1985.  A presentation of the major schools of thought in African philosophy.  Momoh, Campbell .ed. The Substance of African Philosophy. Auchi: APP Publications, 1989.  A collection of essays on different issues in African philosophy.  Momoh, Campbell. “The Logic Question in African Philosophy”. C. S. Momoh ed. The Substance of African Philosophy. Auchi: APP Publications, 1989.  A defense of the thesis of a possible African logic tradition.  Mudimbe, V. Y. The Invention of Africa: Gnosis, Philosophy and the Order of Knowledge (African Systems of Thought). Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1988.  A discourse on culture, race, Eurocentrism and modern Africa as an invention of Western scholarship.  Ngugi wa Thiong’o. 1986. Decolonizing the Mind: The Politics of Language in African Literature. London: J. Curry and Portsmouth, N. H: Heinemann, 1986.  A discourse on Eurocentrism, Africa’s decolonization and cultural imperialism.  Nkrumah, Kwame. I Speak of Freedom: A Statement of African Ideology. London: Mercury Books, 1961.  A discourse on political ideology for Africa.  Nkrumah, Kwame. Towards Colonial Freedom. London: Heinemann. (First published in 1945), 1962.  A discussion of colonialism and its negative impact on Africa.  Nwala, Uzodinma. Igbo Philosophy. London: Lantern Books, 1985.  An Afrocentrist presentation of Igbo-African philosophical culture.  Nyerere, Julius. Freedom and Unity. Dares Salaam: Oxford University Press, 1986.  A discussion of a postcolonial Africa that should thrive on freedom and unity.  Nyerere, Julius. Freedom and Socialism. Dares Salaam: Oxford University Press, 1986.  A discourse on the fundamental traits of African socialism.  Nyerere, Julius. Ujamaa—Essays on Socialism. Dar-es-Salaam, Tanzania: Oxford University Press, 1986.  A collection of essays detailing the characteristics of African brand of socialism.  Ogbalu, F.C. Ilu Igbo: The Book of Igbo Proverbs. Onitsha: University Publishing Company, 1965.  A philosophical presentation of Igbo-African proverbs.  Okeke, J. Chimakonam. “Why Can’t There be an African logic?”. Journal of Integrative Humanism. 1. 2. (2011). 141-152.  A defense of a possible African logic tradition and a critique of critics.
  • 28.  Okere, Theophilus. “The Relation between Culture and Philosophy,” in Uche 2 1976.  A discourse on the differences and similarities between culture and philosophy.  Okere, Theophilus. African Philosophy: A Historico-Hermeneutical Investigation of the Conditions of Its Possibility. Lanham, Md.: University Press of America, 1983.  A hermeneutical discourse on the basis of African philosophy.  Okolo, Chukwudum B. Problems of African Philosophy. Enugu: Cecta Nigeria Press, 1990.  An x-ray of the major hindrances facing African philosophy as a discipline.  Okoro, C. M. African Philosophy: Question and Debate, A Historical Study. Enugu: Paqon Press, 2004.  A historical presentation of the great debate in African philosophy.  Oladipo, Olusegun. (ed) The Third Way in African Philosophy. Ibadan: Hope, 2002.  A collection of essays on the topical issues in African philosophy of the time.  Oladipo, Olusegun. Core Issues in African Philosophy. Ibadan: Hope Publications, 2006.  A discussion of central issues of African philosophy.  Olela, Henry. “The African Foundations of Greek Philosophy”. Wright, Richard A., ed. African Philosophy: An Introduction. 3rd ed. Lanham, Md.: University Press of America, 1984.  An Afrocentrist presentation of African philosophy as the source of Greek philosophy.  Oluwole, Sophie. Philosophy and Oral Tradition. Lagos: Ark Publications, 1999.  A cultural excavationist programme in African philosophy.  Omoregbe, Joseph. “African Philosophy: Yesterday and Today”. African Philosophy: An Anthology. Emmanuel Eze (ed.), Massachusetts: Blackwell, 1998.  A survey of major issues in the debate and a critique of the Universalist school.  Onunwa, Udobata. “Humanism: The Bedrock of African Traditional Religion and Culture”. Religious Humanism. Vol. XXV, No. 2, Spring 1991, Pp 66 – 71.  A presentation of Humanism as the basis for African religion and culture.  Onyewuenyi, Innocent. African Origin of Greek Philosophy: An Exercise in Afrocentrism. Enugu: SNAAP Press, 1993.  An Afrocentrist presentation of philosophy as a child of African thought.  Oruka, H. Odera. “The Fundamental Principles in the Question of ‘African Philosophy,’ I.” Second Order 4, no. 1: 44–55, 1975.  A discussion of the main issues in the debate on African philosophy.  Oruka, H. Odera.“Four Trends in African Philosophy.” In Philosophy in the Present Situation of Africa, edited by Alwin Diemer. Weisbaden, Germany: Franz Steiner Erlagh. (First published in 1978), 1981; Ed.  A breakdown of the major schools of thought in the debate on African philosophy.  Oruka, H. Odera. Sage Philosophy: Indigenous Thinkers and the Modern Debate on African Philosophy. Leiden: E. J. Brill. 1990.  A survey of the journey so far in African philosophy and the identification of two additional schools of thought.  Outlaw, Lucius. “African ‘Philosophy’? Deconstructive and Reconstructive Challenges.” In his On Race and Philosophy. New York and London: Routledge. 1996.  A presentation of African philosophy as a tool for cultural renaissance.  Plato. Theætetus,155d, p.37.  Contains Plato’s theory of knowledge.  Ruch, E. A. and Anyawnu, K. C. African Philosophy: An Introduction to the Main Philosophical Trends in Contemporary Africa. Rome: Catholic Book Agency, 1981.  A discussion on racialism, slavery, colonialism and their influence on the emergence of African philosophy, in addition to current issues in the discipline.  Sogolo, Godwin. Foundations of African Philosophy. Ibadan: Ibadan University Press, 1993.  A discussion of the logical, epistemological and metaphysical grounds for African philosophy project.  Towa, Marcien. “Conditions for the Affirmation of a Modern African Philosophical Thought”. Tsanay Serequeberhan (ed) African Philosophy: The Essential Readings. New York: Paragon House, 1991.  A presentation of important factors required for the emergence of African philosophy as a discipline.
  • 29.  Uduigwomen, F. Andrew. “Philosophy and the Place of African Philosophy”. A. F. Uduigwomen ed. From Footmarks to Landmarks on African Philosophy. 1995, 2nd Ed. 1995/2009. Lagos: O. O. P. 2009.  A collection of essays on different issues in African philosophy.  Uduma Orji. “Can there be an African Logic” in A. F. Uduigwomen(ed.) From Footmarks to Landmarks on African Philosophy Lagos: O. O. P. Ltd, 2009.  A critique of a culture-bound logic in African thought.  Uduma Orji. “Between Universalism and Cultural Identity: Revisiting the Motivation for an African Logic”. A Paper delivered at an International Conference of the Council for Research in Values and Philosophy Washington D.C., USA at University of Cape Coast, Cape Coast Ghana 3–5 February, 2010.  A critique of a culture-bound logic in African thought and a presentation of logic as universal.  Vest, J. L. 2009. ‘Perverse and necessary dialogues in African philosophy’, in: Thought and practice: a journal of the philosophical association of Kenya. New series, Vol.1 No.2, December, pp. 1-23.  An discussion of the proper direction and focus of African philosophy in the new Age.  Wamba-ia Wamba, E. "Philosophy in Africa: Challenges of the African Philosopher,” in African Philosophy: The Essential Readings. New York: Paragon House, 1991.  A discussions of the technical problems of African philosophy as a discipline.  Winch, Peter. “Understanding a Primitive Society”. American Philosophical Quarterly. No. 1, 1964.  A discussion and a defense of the rationality of primitive people.  Wiredu, Kwasi. Philosophy and an African Culture. Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press, 1980.  A discussion of the philosophical elements in an African culture and a call for a universalizable episteme for African philosophy.  Wiredu, Kwasi. “How Not to Compare African Thought with Western Thought.”Ch’Indaba no. 2 ( July– December): 1976. 4–8. Reprinted in African Philosophy: An Introduction, edited by R. Wright. Washington, D.C.: University Press of America, 1977; and in African Philosophy: Selected Readings, edited by Albert G. Mosley. Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice Hall, 1995.  A critique of Robin Horton’s comparison of African and Western thought.  Wiredu, Kwasi.“Our Problem of Knowledge: Brief Reflections on Knowledge and Development in Africa”. African Philosophy as Cultural Inquiry. Ivan Karp and D. A. Masolo (ed). Bloomington, Indiana: Indiana University Press, 2000.  A discussion on the role of knowledge in the development of Africa.  Wiredu, Kwasi. Cultural Universals and Particulars: An African Perspective. Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1996.  A collection of essays on sundry philosophical issues pertaining to comparative and cross- cultural philosophy.  Wiredu, Kwasi. Conceptual Decolonization in African Philosophy. Ed. Olusegun Oladipo. Ibadan: Hope Publications, 1995.  A discussion of the importance and relevance of the theory of conceptual decolonization in African philosophy.  Wiredu, Kwasi. “On Defining African Philosophy”. C. S. Momoh ed. The Substance of African Philosophy. Auchi: APP Publications, 1989.  A discourse on the parameters of the discipline of African philosophy.  Wright, Richard A., ed. “Investigating African Philosophy”. African Philosophy: An Introduction. 3rd ed. Lanham, Md.: University Press of America, 1984.  A critique of the existence of African philosophy as a discipline.
  • 30. Author Information Leopatra mutazu Email leomutazu@gmail.com GREAT ZIMBABWE UNIVERSITY