SlideShare a Scribd company logo
1 of 13
Download to read offline
University of Oregon



Aristotle, Frye, and the Theory of Tragedy
Author(s): Leon Golden
Reviewed work(s):
Source: Comparative Literature, Vol. 27, No. 1 (Winter, 1975), pp. 47-58
Published by: Duke University Press on behalf of the University of Oregon
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/1769727 .
Accessed: 23/09/2012 12:17

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of
content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms
of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

.




                University of Oregon and Duke University Press are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend
                access to Comparative Literature.




http://www.jstor.org
LEON GOLDEN




                  Aristotle,                 Frye,
                 And            the
                 Theory                 of     Tragedy

N      ORTHROP FRYE has recognized a basic kinship between his
        Anatomy of Criticism and Aristotle's Poetics. After noting with
 regret the parochialismof many contemporarycritics, he warmly alludes
to Aristotle's conception of a "totally intelligible structure of knowledge
attainable about poetry which is not poetry itself, or the experience of it,
but poetics."' This conception, reflected concisely in the opening lines
of the Poetics, becomes the program of the Anatomy. Frye, however,
aspires to improve on his model by making use of all the relevant doc-
trines and techniques of criticism developed since Aristotle wrote.
   Tragedy is the central theme of the Poetics and a subject of major
importancein the Anatomy as well. In comparing the two approachesto
this genre we are struck by their wide divergence in method and con-
clusions. Clearly both Aristotle and Frye make profound contributions
to our understanding of tragedy but neither succeeds in providing a
definitive statement that clarifies the nature of the genre as it has
emerged and developed in the western literary tradition. I propose in
this paper to assess our current understanding of the nature of tragedy
based on the contributions made by Aristotle and Frye and then to sug-
gest a method by which these important theoretical statements can be
harmonized to lead us to a fuller understanding of the potentialities and
boundaries of the genre.
   The major tenets of Aristotle's theory of tragedy are well known. I
summarize them here for later comparison with Frye. For Aristotle
tragedy is an imitation (mimesis) of actions involving the pitiable and
fearful dimensions of human existence. This form of imitation repre-
    1 Anatomy of Criticism (Princeton, N.J., 1957), p. 14.
                                                                         47
COMPARATIVE            LITERATURE



 sents a noble (spoudaios) hero as its object; it uses artistically enhanced
 language as its means; and its manner of presentation is dramatic rather
 than narrative. The representation of pity (the feeling we have toward
 the undeserved misfortune of others) and fear (the same feeling when
 directed at our own vulnerability to such misfortune) requires that the
 tragic hero fall from happiness to misery because of some intellectual,
 not moral, error (hamartia). The effectiveness of any given tragedy is
 dependent upon its possessing a plot that is complete, is of the proper
 magnitude, and is developed in accordance with the laws of necessity
 and probability.The ultimate goal and essential pleasure associated with
tragis mimesis is catharsis. Catharsis, a much disputed term, has been
 interpreted in four principal ways: (1) as a form of medical purgation
 in which the pathological elements of pity and fear are purged from the
 spectator; (2) as a form of moral purification in which the spectator
achieves the proper mean between excess and deficiency in experiencing
pity and fear; (3) as a structuralprocess by which the tragic deed of the
hero is, in the course of the play, purified of its moral pollution; and (4)
as the process of intellectual clarificationby which the spectator comes to
understand, under a universal heading, the nature of the particular
pitiable and fearful events that have been depicted.2
   The ultimate thrust of the Aristotelian theory of tragedy will, of
course, depend on which interpretation of catharsis we accept but the
basic nature of Aristotle's approach to tragedy is clear even without a
final decision about this important term. Aristotle's goal is to set forth
the conditions under which the essential tragic effect and pleasure will be
most fully achieved. His definition of tragedy is thus a prescription for
the creation of an ideal work of art rather than a general statement
applicable to all works traditionally included within the limits of the
genre. Most of the plays cited for one reason or another in the Poetics
cannot be dealt with effectively in terms of the definition of tragedy set
forth in Chapter VI and few of the tragedies written since Aristotle's
time will fit snugly within the confines of that definition. Recognizing
that Aristotle's definition of tragedy is a statement of the ideal conditions
    2 For a discussion of the various theories of catharsis see the following: J.
Bernays, Zwei Abhandlungen iiber die aristotelische Theorie des Dramas (Berlin,
1880); I. Bywater, Aristotle on the Art of Poetry (Oxford, 1909), p. 160; G. F.
Else, Aristotle's Poetics: The Argument (Cambridge, Mass., 1957), pp. 221-32,
436-44; Leon Golden, "Catharsis," Transactions of the American Philological
Association, 93 (1962), 51-60 and "Mimesis and Katharsis," Classical Philology,
64 (1969), 145-53; D. W. Lucas, Aristotle; Poetics: Introduction, Commentary,
and Appendixes (Oxford, 1968), pp. 282-86; H. Otte, Neue Beitriige zur aristo-
telischen Begriffsbestimmung der Tragidie (Berlin, 1928), p. 10; Kurt von Fritz,
Antike und moderne Tragidie (Berlin, 1962), p. xxvi.


48
ARISTOTLE        AND FRYE



for the fulfillment of the tragic form prepares us for understanding
Frye's widely divergent approach.
   Frye identifies five modes and six phases of tragedy at different
stages of his argument but he does not treat these in any systematic form.
The modes do relate to a development downward from stories about
heroes who are superior in kind to other men and their environment to
stories about heroes who are inferior in degree both to other men and to
their environment. Frye identifies salient features characteristic of each
level of development from the Dionysiac to the elegiac, high mimetic,
low mimetic, and ironic modes. Pity and fear (not necessarily in the
Aristotelian sense), hamartia (without moral coloring), and catharsis
(in the sense of purgation) are attributed to some of the modes but they
do not form a system of central, unifying ideas that establishes the
essential meaning of the concept of tragedy. The six phases of tragedy
represent a development from the heroic to the ironic world view. Here,
too, however we do not have so much a systematic theory as a citation
and analysis of particularexamples. Frye does assert that two commonly
held "reductive formulas" for tragedy are partially but not completely
valid: (1) that tragedy exhibits the omnipotence of an external fate
and (2) that the tragic process is primarily a violation of moral law.
Frye cites a number of examples which clash with these formulas.
   We see that Frye, unlike Aristotle, is concerned with establishing a
critical position that will be relevant to the tremendous variety of works
traditionally included within the genre of tragedy. His discussion of five
modes and six phases recognizes the full range of manifestations tragedy
has taken in its historical development. Unfortunately, Frye's analysis
remains mostly on the level of a perceptive description of the salient
features of each mode and phase and does not establish a systematic
argument that would demonstrate the organic relationship among these
modes and phases. The major Aristotelian concepts of pity and fear,
hamartia, and catharsis are judged to occur in some dimensions of the
tragic experience but not in others and Frye supplies no substitutions
for them which would organize tragedy as a clearly unified territory
within the wide landscape of artistic mimesis.
   The strength of Aristotle's theory is that it identifies with precision a
central, perhaps the central theme of the genre; its weakness is that it
fails to account for the great body of works which have historically
been designated as tragedies. Frye's approach to tragedy makes a
significant contribution toward overcoming this limitation but he, in
turn, fails to provide us with a rigorous system of standards and criteria
through which the boundaries of the genre can be fixed and its constitu-
ent elements analyzed. It thus appears that a major contribution to the

                                                                         49
COMPARATIVE          LITERATURE



theory of tragedy could be made if it were possible to follow Frye in his
attempt to do justice to the entire range of tragedies without abandon-
ing Aristotelian rigor in establishing the definition of the genre. Such
a compromise between the two approachesis not impossible; indeed, the
mechanism for attaining it is implicit in the Aristotelian system itself. It
is possible to isolate four parameters in the Aristotelian analysis of
tragedy: (1) the moral stature of the hero: whether he is noble
 (spoudaios) or ignoble (phaulos); (2) the nature of the error (ha-
martia) committed by the hero: whether it is intellectual or moral; (3)
the destiny of the hero: whether he moves from happiness to misery or
the reverse; and (4) the response of the audience: whether pity and fear
are evoked and subjected to the process of catharsis in any of its possible
interpretations.
   When we apply these categories to the data provided by the history
of tragedy, we find four distinct patterns of tragic action. We shall now
analyze these patterns in detail and suggest that, as a system, they repre-
sent a rigorous approach to the phenomenon of tragedy that is fully
adequate to deal with the diverse elements historically united in this
genre.
   We shall begin with the pattern of tragic action which Aristotle
specifically identifies as ideal in the Poetics and which, in my view, is
represented in Greek tragedy only by the Oedipus Tyrannus. In this
pattern a spoudaios hero, that is, one of moral nobility and integrity,
makes an intellectual rather than a moral mistake (hamartia) which
triggers a fall from happiness to misery and evokes the response of pity
and fear from the audience. For Aristotle the evocation of pity and
fear is the proper goal of tragedy and it is only by this pattern of tragic
action that the goal can be achieved. To see the reason for this we must
understandclearly the meaning of pity and fear for Aristotle. In Chapter
XIII of the Poetics he defines these terms as follows: ".. . for pity is
aroused by someone who undeservedly falls into misfortune, and fear is
evoked by our recognizing that it is someone like ourselves who en-
counters this misfortune (pity, as I say, arising for the former reason,
fear for the latter)." Thus for Aristotle pity refers to our sympathetic
response to the undeserved misfortune of someone else and fear indi-
cates, narrowly and specifically, the anxiety we feel that such misfor-
tune can befall those who have the same degree of intelligence and moral
stature as ourselves. In order for the emotions of pity and fear to be
evoked we must have a tragic hero of sufficient moral stature to
deserve our respect and one with whom it is easy for us to identify.
Moreover, this hero must commit a significant error (hamartia) or else
the events of the drama would not be motivated and would not be linked

50
ARISTOTLE         AND     FRYE



by necessity and probability; nevertheless the error must be intellectual
rather than moral or else the undeserved quality of the misfortune would
be destroyed and with it the necessary preconditions for the evocation of
pity and fear.
   The Oedipus Tyrannus offers a good example of this pattern of tragic
action.3 Oedipus is clearly spoudaios because he always strives to ac-
complish morally justifiable goals: he flees from Corinth when it seems
possible that he might commit terrible crimes against those he assumes
to be his parents; he exerts himself without limit in seeking to lift the
plague from the people of Thebes; and, with total integrity, he brings
to light the truth about himself despite all efforts by others to prevent
his terrible moment of self-discovery. Some critics have seen Oedipus'
rashness and quickness to anger as signs of a moral flaw in his character.
They have failed to notice that such episodes occur when Oedipus' life
is in danger or when a citizen of great reputation and authority appears
to be withholding significant information that is necessary for the safety
of the state. Oedipus' very human response in these situations is not his
flaw; rather, his essential hamartia is his failure to understand the true
relationship between his own, finite human existence and the infinitely
powerful and mysterious nature of Apollo. Oedipus' attempt to avoid
committing incest and parricide and his efforts to free Thebes from its
suffering are the very virtues out of which his profound misunder-
standing of Apollo arises. In the Oedipus Tyrannus we observe the
evocation of both pity and fear because we are led to respect the moral
stature of the hero, to understand and pardon the intellectual mistake
which triggers his downfall, and to recognize ourselves as vulnerable to
the same fate.
   The second pattern of tragic action is observed in those situations
where pity alone is evoked without any concomitant fear in the technical
Aristotelian senses of those terms. In this pattern the hero is no longer
fully spoudaios but has only a hint of this quality and the mistake he
makes is essentially a moral one. The fall from happiness to misery
occurs with the same intensity as in the first pattern. Works that illus-
trate the second pattern of tragic action must have a hero who at least
aspires to act in accordance with moral virtue but is too weak to resist
the external pressures that drive him to commit a debased or criminal
act. The fact that the hero did not initially will his act but succumbed to
external pressure makes it possible for us to feel some measure of
   3 The view presented here of Oedipus as a noble hero is widely held today. See,
for example, the perceptive discussion by Bernard Knox, Oedipus at Thebes (New
Haven, Conn., 1957), pp. 194-96. An eloquent refutation of those who still wish
to fix moral blame on Oedipus is provided by Kurt von Fritz, Antike und moderne
Tragidie (Berlin, 1962), pp. 7-8.

                                                                                51
COMPARATIVE           LITERATURE



sympathy and anguish for an undeserved element in his fate. The moral-
ly debased quality of his actions, however, interferes with the recogni-
tion of our own vulnerability to a similar destiny and thus frustrates
the evocation of Aristotelian "fear."
   Euripides' Medea is a clear example.4 Medea tells us how totally she
had devoted herself to Jason's interests when he cunningly won her
affection as part of his strategy for obtaining the golden fleece. She
committed heinous crimes and cut all ties to her home and country to
serve his needs. Her anger at her betrayal by the always pragmatic
Jason drives her to seek revenge against him. She discovers the appro-
priate means in a plan that requires her to murder her own children
because only in this way can she hurt Jason as much as he has hurt her.
From the moment she adopts the plan to the moment she completes it,
we see Medea in an anguished and ambivalent state of mind toward the
children. In feigning compliance with Jason's recommendations for her
future life, she is brought to the verge of tears when she mentions the
children to him and thinks of the terrible destiny she has designed for
them. Her torment is intensified when she learns that Creon's daughter
has accepted the fatal gifts from her children for now she knows that
there can be no turning back from her decision. She agonizingly vacil-
lates before taking the final, irrevocable step toward killing them as she
sees how much they mean to her and how much she will suffer after
she has murdered them. Nevertheless, the injury Jason has done to her
pride threatens her existence so seriously that it must be redressed at
any cost. In a poignant soliloquy, marked by passages of deep maternal
love and flashes of angry indignation, Medea sees clearly that an evil
passion for revenge will dominate all her rational misgivings about the
act she is going to perform. It is possible to censure Medea for her
inability to control her passions and her refusal to place the children's
interests above her own but it is also clear that her fury is not willed by
her but caused by Jason's callous treatment. Medea herself clearly is
capable of the most intense love and loyalty as well as the most violent
anger and vengeance.
   Because Medea realizes that the murder of her children is an evil and
irrational act she cannot be a spoudaios hero like Oedipus in the Oedipus
Tyrannus. We can, however, still pity her fate as not being fully de-
served because she did not hate her children or desire to harm them. She
acted in response to the pressure exerted by Jason's cruel and cynical
abandonmentand committed an act she did not will and struggled hard
not to perform. Aristotelian "fear"is largely absent here, however, since
  4 An excellent insight into Medea'smood and characteris given by D. J. Cona-
cher, EuripideanDrama: Myth, Theme and Structure (Toronto, 1967), p. 196.

.52
ARISTOTLE          AND     FRYE



very few of us can imagine making the same decision as Medea under
any sort of external duress. Thus the second pattern of tragic action
shows some palpable differences from the pattern identified as ideal by
Aristotle. The spoudaios quality of the hero is greatly diminished, he
commits a serious moral error rather than simply an intellectual one,
and he falls from happiness to misery in such a way as to elicit only pity,
not fear, in the technical Aristotelian senses of those terms.
   The third pattern of tragic action involves the complete obliteration
of pity and fear. In it a depraved rather than spoudaios hero commits
the gravest moral errors and moves, because or in spite of them, not
from happiness to misery but from misery to happiness. In this type of
tragedy a profound flaw is usually uncovered in the order and govern-
ance of the universe.
   Euripides' Orestes offers an excellent example of this type of
tragedy.5Although the entire play is permeatedwith absurdist elements,
a discussion of the ending will be sufficient for our present purposes.
Orestes and Electra, having been betrayed by Menelaus, find themselves
facing a death sentence in Argos. With their friend Pylades they plot to
take appropriate vengeance on Menelaus by killing Menelaus' wife,
Helen, before their own death sentence can be carried out. In addition,
Electra urges that they seize Helen's daughter, Hermione, as a hostage.
She notes that if Menelaus wants to take vengeance for Helen's death,
they need only to threaten to cut Hermione's throat and Menelaus, who
is a coward, will think better of it and allow them to escape. The plan is
enthusiastically agreed upon, and Pylades and Orestes enter the palace
to take their joyous revenge on Helen who is murderously attacked
while Electra shouts encouragement from in front of the palace.
   The grim absurdity of human existence pictured in this play is under-
scored when Hermione appears and, taken in by Electra's cunning,
agrees with kindly human decency to intercede for Orestes and Electra
with Helen. When Hermione has been seized, Electra is proud of this
"heroic" action which will teach Menelaus to respect his formidable
adversaries. In place of the awesome confrontations found in Homer,
Aeschylus, and Sophocles we have here a competition in cunning, deceit,
and cowardice which emphasizes the absurdity of the human condition.
Before, however, the murder of Helen can be consummated, we are told
by a servant that she has mysteriously disappearedinto the sky.
   The climax of the play brings Menelaus onto the.scene to discover the
fate of Helen and take vengeance on those who may have harmed her.
   5 Significant assistance in understanding this unusual play is given by Kurt von
Fritz, op cit., pp. 312-16 and by William Arrowsmith in the introduction to his
translation of this play in The Complete Greek Tragedies, ed. D. Grene and R.
Lattimore, Vol. IV (Chicago, 1958), 186-91.
                                                                                 53
COMPARATIVE           LITERATURE



In a sardonic debate Orestes regrets that Helen disappeared before he
could kill her, and Menelaus, who believes that Orestes actually has
murdered his wife, threatens vengeance if he attempts to enhance his
reputation as a matricide by the additional slaughter of Hermione.
Orestes trades insults with Menelaus as he holds his sword to Her-
mione's throat and orders Pylades and Electra to set the palace afire. At
this moment the greatest absurdity of all takes place as Apollo appears
in the role of deus ex machina and suddenly reverses the action of the
play. He announces that he has transported Helen to live in the heavens
for ever, that Menelaus is to remarry, that Orestes is to take his sword
away from Hermione's throat and marry her instead, and that Pylades
and Electra are also to be married. Orestes welcomes and obeys the
injunctions of Apollo but notes a threatening and fearful quality in the
god's voice. So this "tragedy" comes to an end.
   In this pattern of tragic action pity and fear are destroyed since the
necessary conditions for them are not present. In order to have pity and
fear we need a spoudaios hero who makes an intellectual (not moral)
error which triggers but does not fully cause his fall from happiness to
misery. In the Orestes instead of a spoudaios hero we have a morally
depraved one who moves from misery to happiness under divine sanc-
tion in a way that defies both reason and justice. We respond to this
revelation of profound irrationality in the universe not with pity and
fear but rather with emotional shock, mirthless laughter, and a sense
of spiritual desolation over the mockery and meaninglessness of human
existence.
   The fourth pattern of tragic action stands in polar opposition to the
third. Instead of pity and fear being obliterated by an explosion of
cosmic evil they are transcended by an impressive manifestation of
divine love for man. A clear example of this rather unusual dimension
of tragedy is found in Sophocles' Oedipus at Colonus.6
   The Oedipus of the Oedipus at Colonus has undergone the purifying
fire of suffering and, though not purged of his human passions, has
attained a deeper understanding of the human condition. He clearly
perceives that he has been punished far too severely for any crime he has
committed, that he has been betrayed and manipulated by his sons and
Creon, and that he has benefitedfrom the love and kindness of Antigone,
Ismene, and Theseus. As in the Oedipus Tyrannus, divine purpose is
an ever-present controlling factor, but in this play it changes from a
painfully mysterious force to a benign and affirmativeone.
   The action of the Oedipus at Colonus provides several dramatic
   6 A good discussionof the characterof Oedipusas it is developedin this play is
found in CedricWhitman,Sophocles: A Study of Heroic Humanism (Cambridge,
Mass., 1951), p. 214.
54
ARISTOTLE          AND FRYE



occasions for revealing the aspects of Oedipus' character and destiny
which determine the play's specific tragic form. Oedipus' essential inno-
cence is expressed in his argument with Creon when the latter cruelly
attempts to take him back to Thebes against his will. Oedipus declares
that no evil or sin within himself drove him to commit the terrible deeds
whose source lay in a fearful ignorance over which he had no control. He
would not willingly or knowingly have married Jocasta, nor would he
willingly and knowingly have slain his father, but when attacked by
apparent strangers, in a desolate area, he defended his own life and he
poignantly calls upon his dead father's spirit to bear witness for him.
Most important, however, is the manifestation of the benign interest
which the gods now take in Oedipus. In the climactic scene of the play
the blind Oedipus is suddenly given mysterious powers and guides his
sighted companions to a sacred place where a divine voice summons him
to his ultimate destiny and reward. Mystically, the heavens open and
receive Oedipus who at the end of a troubled life is the recipient of infi-
nite divine grace.
   Divine intervention has raised Oedipus above the human condition.
As a result of that intervention he makes no mistake that leads him from
happiness to misery but is instead led by divine grace from suffering to
supreme happiness. His stature is now far above our own and since we
cannot view him as someone like ourselves who has incurred undeserved
misfortune because of an intellectual error, we do not respond with the
emotions of pity and fear, but must rather view his final triumph with
awe. Thus the Oedipus at Colonus as a tragedy directly contradicts the
 experience we have of the Oedipus Tyrannus as a tragedy. In place of a
spoudaios hero who makes an intellectual mistake, it offers us a divinely
protected hero who makes no essential error; in place of a fall from hap-
 piness to misery, it describes the reverse movement from misery to
 happiness; in place of pity and fear, it evokes awe and wonder.
   We have now identified four patterns of tragic action and provided
 an example from Greek tragedy to illustrate each of them. Similar
 examples can be found in Shakespearean and modern tragedy.7 The
   7 An analogous descending movement from high tragedy to pathetic tragedy to
absurd tragedy can be traced in Othello, Macbeth, and Richard III. In these plays
we move from a spoudaios hero such as Othello (Iago himself refers to the Moor's
"noble nature"), to one like Macbeth who is pressed by an external force to commit
a crime he would not undertake by himself, to one, finally, like Richard III who is
utterly depraved and rejoices in the evil he accomplishes. For a discussion of
Othello's character see A. C. Bradley, Shakespearean Tragedy (London, 1929),
pp. 189-91. Bradley also provides us with a perceptive analysis of the characters
of Macbeth and Lady Macbeth, op. cit., pp. 351 ff. A good discussion of the impact
of Richard III is provided by H. B. Charlton, Shakespearian Tragedy (Cambridge,
1952), p. 39. It should be noted that because of the death of Richard this play does
not attain to the consummate absurdity of the Orestes. I know of no Shakespearean
                                                                                  55
COMPARATIVE            LITERATURE



first form of tragedy we shall call high tragedy: it is the form specifically
defined by Aristotle in the Poetics and involves a spoudaios hero who
makes an intellectual mistake and whose fall from happiness to misery
evokes from the audience the emotions of pity and fear (in the technical
Aristotelian senses of those terms). The second form we shall call
pathetic tragedy: it portrays a hero who is not fully spoudaios but who
manifests at least a trace or hint of nobility and who, under the pressure
of some external force, makes both moral and intellectual errors that
lead to his downfall from happiness to misery. The fate of the hero of
pathetic tragedy evokes only pity, not fear, from the audience. The third
form we shall call absurd tragedy: it depicts a depraved or ignoble hero
who commits a combination of moral and intelectual errors that are
terrifyingly complemented by grim flaws in the universe itself. In its
extreme form, this type of tragedy presents its depraved or ignoble hero
as moving triumphantly from misery to happiness although a number
of works stop just short of this radicalmanifestation of cosmic absurdity.
Instead of evoking pity and fear, absurd tragedy obliterates those emo-
tions by creating a mood of spiritual desolation and a sense of the mean-
inglessness and mockery of human existence. The fourth form of trag-
edy we shall call heroic tragedy: it presents a hero who is superior to
ordinary standards of human nobility because he has been granted
divine interest and protection. The hero commits no essential error,
moves from misery or relative misery to supreme happiness, and evokes
awe from the audience. Absurd tragedy destroys pity and fear; heroic
tragedy completely transcends them.
   The analysis of tragedy given above is based on an extrapolation from
the criteria set down by Aristotle in the Poetics. We have noted that
Aristotle's specific and literal discussion of tragedy centers on the ideal
conditions for the evocation of pity and fear which are seen to be the
truly tragic emotions. Aristotle's concern with these ideal conditions
is reflected in his famous definition of tragedy which applies fully to only
a small number of works. The history of tragedy provides us with many
more examples of pathetic tragedy than of Aristotelian high tragedy.
The attempt to make a literal application of Aristotle's definition to
tragedy, in general, results in a distortion either of the definition or of
empirical reality. The expansion of the Aristotelian system provided in
our analysis overcomes the narrowness inherent in the original defini-
drama that fits easily within the boundaries of what we have called heroic tragedy
but this concept precisely fits works which we today designate as "Christian trag-
edy." For discussions of Christian tragedy which will illuminate its articulation
with the pattern of tragic action we have called heroic see Karl Jaspers, Tragedy
Is Not Enough, trans. H. A. T. Reiche, H. T. Moore, and K. W. Deutsch (Boston,
1952), pp. 28-87, and Reinhold Niebuhr, Beyond Tragedy: Essays on the Christian
Interpretation of History (New York, 1965), pp. 155-69.
56
ARISTOTLE AND FRYE


 tion and makes the Aristotelian approach truly viable in terms of the
history of tragedy.
    Frye does attempt to deal with the greatly varied forms which tragedy
has manifested throughout its historical development, but he does not
provide firm and specific criteria by which the related forms of tragedy
can be compared and analyzed. Thus in his discussion of the five modes
of tragedy we learn that there is a Dionysiac mode that deals with
"stories of dying gods"; an elegiac mode that "presents a heroism un-
spoiled by irony"; a high mimetic mode which "mingles the heroic with
the ironic" and in which "pity and fear become, respectively, favorable
and adverse moral judgment, which are relevant to tragedy but not
central to it"; a low mimetic mode in which "pity and fear are neither
purged nor absorbed into pleasures, but are communicated externally,
as sensation" and whose root idea "is the exclusion of an individual on
our own level from a social group to which he is trying to belong": and
an ironic mode in which pity and fear are not "raised" but rather "re-
flected" to the reader and which represents "simply the study of tragic
isolation as such" inasmuch as its tragic hero "does not necessarily have
any tragic hamartiaor pathetic obsession: he is only somebody who gets
isolated from his society."8
    I find a similar problem in Frye's subsequent discussion of six phases
of tragedy. His first phase is one "in which the central character is
given the greatest possible dignity in contrast to the other characters,
so that we get the perspective of a stag pulled down by wolves"; his
second phase "is in one way or another the tragedy of innocence in the
sense of inexperience, usually involving young people"; his third phase
is one "in which a strong emphasis is thrown on the success or com-
pleteness of the hero's achievement"; his fourth phase involves "the
typical fall of the hero through hybris and hamartia"; his fifth phase is
an ironic perspective of tragedy which "presents for the most part the
tragedy of lost direction and lack of knowledge, not unlike the second
phase except that the context is the world of adult experience";
his sixth plhaserepresents "a world of shock and horror in which the
central images are images of sparagmos, that is, cannibalism, mutilation,
and torture."9
    Frye's discussion of tragedy thus provides some perceptive descrip-
tive statements about possible kinds of tragic experience but it does not
provide us with firm and objective criteria by which the various modes
and phases of tragedy can be compared and understood.
    In place of Aristotle's rigorous but very narrow prescription for the
  8 Frye, pp. 35-43.
  9 Frye, pp.219-23.

                                                                       57
COMPARATIVE           LITERATURE



attainment of the ideal form of tragedy and Frye's comprehensive but
too subjective description of the varieties of tragic experience, we have
presented a system of analysis rooted in an expansion of, and extrapola-
tion from, the objective criteria utilized by Aristotle in the Poetics. This
system provides a means of making an objective analysis and compari-
son of all the various patterns of tragedy and of observing the unity that
underlies their diversity.
     Florida State University




58

More Related Content

What's hot

SEP-FEP-abstract-booklet-2012
SEP-FEP-abstract-booklet-2012SEP-FEP-abstract-booklet-2012
SEP-FEP-abstract-booklet-2012Ellie Harper
 
My presentaion on theory of catharsis
My presentaion on theory of catharsisMy presentaion on theory of catharsis
My presentaion on theory of catharsiskklewade
 
Being becoming narrative
Being becoming narrativeBeing becoming narrative
Being becoming narrativebrobaker
 
58 284-1-pb
58 284-1-pb58 284-1-pb
58 284-1-pbandre_mm
 
Aristotle's Politics by Professor Steve Smith
Aristotle's Politics by Professor Steve SmithAristotle's Politics by Professor Steve Smith
Aristotle's Politics by Professor Steve SmithNoel Jopson
 
Aristotle definition of poetry, by robert j. yanal
Aristotle definition of poetry, by robert j. yanalAristotle definition of poetry, by robert j. yanal
Aristotle definition of poetry, by robert j. yanalMariane Farias
 
Writing Sample Nietzsche
Writing Sample NietzscheWriting Sample Nietzsche
Writing Sample NietzscheLewis Channing
 
Postdeconstructive necrophilia, by floyd dunphy
Postdeconstructive necrophilia, by floyd dunphyPostdeconstructive necrophilia, by floyd dunphy
Postdeconstructive necrophilia, by floyd dunphyMariane Farias
 
(2008) Martin Heidegger's pallid lack of Love: answering Nihilism
(2008) Martin Heidegger's pallid lack of Love: answering Nihilism(2008) Martin Heidegger's pallid lack of Love: answering Nihilism
(2008) Martin Heidegger's pallid lack of Love: answering NihilismSonja Grussendorf
 
Theory of conflict: toward the psychological explanation
Theory of conflict: toward the psychological explanationTheory of conflict: toward the psychological explanation
Theory of conflict: toward the psychological explanationviktor_pushkar
 
Sartre presentatIN wESTERN pHILOSOPHICAL AND pOLITICAL THOUGHT
Sartre presentatIN wESTERN pHILOSOPHICAL AND pOLITICAL THOUGHTSartre presentatIN wESTERN pHILOSOPHICAL AND pOLITICAL THOUGHT
Sartre presentatIN wESTERN pHILOSOPHICAL AND pOLITICAL THOUGHTAgnes Fernandez
 
International Journal of Humanities and Social Science Invention (IJHSSI)
International Journal of Humanities and Social Science Invention (IJHSSI)International Journal of Humanities and Social Science Invention (IJHSSI)
International Journal of Humanities and Social Science Invention (IJHSSI)inventionjournals
 

What's hot (20)

Aristotle's Poetics
Aristotle's Poetics Aristotle's Poetics
Aristotle's Poetics
 
Catharsis
CatharsisCatharsis
Catharsis
 
Theory of catharsis
Theory of  catharsis Theory of  catharsis
Theory of catharsis
 
Catharsis
Catharsis Catharsis
Catharsis
 
Historiographic Metafiction - Linda Hutcheon
Historiographic Metafiction - Linda HutcheonHistoriographic Metafiction - Linda Hutcheon
Historiographic Metafiction - Linda Hutcheon
 
SEP-FEP-abstract-booklet-2012
SEP-FEP-abstract-booklet-2012SEP-FEP-abstract-booklet-2012
SEP-FEP-abstract-booklet-2012
 
My presentaion on theory of catharsis
My presentaion on theory of catharsisMy presentaion on theory of catharsis
My presentaion on theory of catharsis
 
Being becoming narrative
Being becoming narrativeBeing becoming narrative
Being becoming narrative
 
58 284-1-pb
58 284-1-pb58 284-1-pb
58 284-1-pb
 
Aristotle's Politics by Professor Steve Smith
Aristotle's Politics by Professor Steve SmithAristotle's Politics by Professor Steve Smith
Aristotle's Politics by Professor Steve Smith
 
Aristotle definition of poetry, by robert j. yanal
Aristotle definition of poetry, by robert j. yanalAristotle definition of poetry, by robert j. yanal
Aristotle definition of poetry, by robert j. yanal
 
Writing Sample Nietzsche
Writing Sample NietzscheWriting Sample Nietzsche
Writing Sample Nietzsche
 
Postdeconstructive necrophilia, by floyd dunphy
Postdeconstructive necrophilia, by floyd dunphyPostdeconstructive necrophilia, by floyd dunphy
Postdeconstructive necrophilia, by floyd dunphy
 
Sense nonsense-merleau-ponty
Sense nonsense-merleau-pontySense nonsense-merleau-ponty
Sense nonsense-merleau-ponty
 
(2008) Martin Heidegger's pallid lack of Love: answering Nihilism
(2008) Martin Heidegger's pallid lack of Love: answering Nihilism(2008) Martin Heidegger's pallid lack of Love: answering Nihilism
(2008) Martin Heidegger's pallid lack of Love: answering Nihilism
 
Martin Amis Time's Arrow Study Guide
Martin Amis Time's Arrow Study GuideMartin Amis Time's Arrow Study Guide
Martin Amis Time's Arrow Study Guide
 
Theory of conflict: toward the psychological explanation
Theory of conflict: toward the psychological explanationTheory of conflict: toward the psychological explanation
Theory of conflict: toward the psychological explanation
 
Sartre presentatIN wESTERN pHILOSOPHICAL AND pOLITICAL THOUGHT
Sartre presentatIN wESTERN pHILOSOPHICAL AND pOLITICAL THOUGHTSartre presentatIN wESTERN pHILOSOPHICAL AND pOLITICAL THOUGHT
Sartre presentatIN wESTERN pHILOSOPHICAL AND pOLITICAL THOUGHT
 
International Journal of Humanities and Social Science Invention (IJHSSI)
International Journal of Humanities and Social Science Invention (IJHSSI)International Journal of Humanities and Social Science Invention (IJHSSI)
International Journal of Humanities and Social Science Invention (IJHSSI)
 
Coleridge
ColeridgeColeridge
Coleridge
 

Viewers also liked

Mozambique independence explainer
Mozambique independence explainerMozambique independence explainer
Mozambique independence explainerLloydCoutts1
 
3D-objektumfelismeres-LIDAR-Dolgozat-1-6-6
3D-objektumfelismeres-LIDAR-Dolgozat-1-6-63D-objektumfelismeres-LIDAR-Dolgozat-1-6-6
3D-objektumfelismeres-LIDAR-Dolgozat-1-6-6Zoltán Czirják
 
Engaging Mass Media in Communicating SRH Research in sub-Saharan Africa
Engaging Mass Media in Communicating SRH Research in sub-Saharan AfricaEngaging Mass Media in Communicating SRH Research in sub-Saharan Africa
Engaging Mass Media in Communicating SRH Research in sub-Saharan AfricaIDS
 
UCLA Mar2013_Presentation_FINAL[1]
UCLA Mar2013_Presentation_FINAL[1]UCLA Mar2013_Presentation_FINAL[1]
UCLA Mar2013_Presentation_FINAL[1]Valeria Sasser
 
African Origins of African Americans
African Origins of African AmericansAfrican Origins of African Americans
African Origins of African AmericansChristina Barnett
 
Northrop Frye's Archetype of Literature
Northrop Frye's Archetype of LiteratureNorthrop Frye's Archetype of Literature
Northrop Frye's Archetype of LiteratureDilip Barad
 
Aristotle's concept of tragedy
Aristotle's concept of tragedyAristotle's concept of tragedy
Aristotle's concept of tragedyMaria Aleem
 
History and Literature of Africa
History and Literature of AfricaHistory and Literature of Africa
History and Literature of AfricaJenny Reyes
 
The African Literature
The African Literature The African Literature
The African Literature NEHA00MENTA
 
African Literature
African LiteratureAfrican Literature
African LiteratureCj Punsalang
 

Viewers also liked (15)

Mozambique independence explainer
Mozambique independence explainerMozambique independence explainer
Mozambique independence explainer
 
Famous poets of amroha , shayar of amroha
Famous poets of amroha , shayar of amroha Famous poets of amroha , shayar of amroha
Famous poets of amroha , shayar of amroha
 
Lusophone world
Lusophone worldLusophone world
Lusophone world
 
3D-objektumfelismeres-LIDAR-Dolgozat-1-6-6
3D-objektumfelismeres-LIDAR-Dolgozat-1-6-63D-objektumfelismeres-LIDAR-Dolgozat-1-6-6
3D-objektumfelismeres-LIDAR-Dolgozat-1-6-6
 
Engaging Mass Media in Communicating SRH Research in sub-Saharan Africa
Engaging Mass Media in Communicating SRH Research in sub-Saharan AfricaEngaging Mass Media in Communicating SRH Research in sub-Saharan Africa
Engaging Mass Media in Communicating SRH Research in sub-Saharan Africa
 
UCLA Mar2013_Presentation_FINAL[1]
UCLA Mar2013_Presentation_FINAL[1]UCLA Mar2013_Presentation_FINAL[1]
UCLA Mar2013_Presentation_FINAL[1]
 
African Origins of African Americans
African Origins of African AmericansAfrican Origins of African Americans
African Origins of African Americans
 
Northrop Frye's Archetype of Literature
Northrop Frye's Archetype of LiteratureNorthrop Frye's Archetype of Literature
Northrop Frye's Archetype of Literature
 
Aristotle's concept of tragedy
Aristotle's concept of tragedyAristotle's concept of tragedy
Aristotle's concept of tragedy
 
History and Literature of Africa
History and Literature of AfricaHistory and Literature of Africa
History and Literature of Africa
 
African Lit
African LitAfrican Lit
African Lit
 
Pooja.trivedi
Pooja.trivediPooja.trivedi
Pooja.trivedi
 
The African Literature
The African Literature The African Literature
The African Literature
 
African Literature
African LiteratureAfrican Literature
African Literature
 
African Literature
African LiteratureAfrican Literature
African Literature
 

Similar to Aristotle, frye, and the theory of tragedy, by leon golden

Aristotles study of tragedy, by henry alonzo
Aristotles study of tragedy, by henry alonzoAristotles study of tragedy, by henry alonzo
Aristotles study of tragedy, by henry alonzoMariane Farias
 
AN ECLECTIC OVERVIEW OF LITERATURE AS AN ACT OF LANGUAGE AND THE LANGUAGE OF ART
AN ECLECTIC OVERVIEW OF LITERATURE AS AN ACT OF LANGUAGE AND THE LANGUAGE OF ARTAN ECLECTIC OVERVIEW OF LITERATURE AS AN ACT OF LANGUAGE AND THE LANGUAGE OF ART
AN ECLECTIC OVERVIEW OF LITERATURE AS AN ACT OF LANGUAGE AND THE LANGUAGE OF ARTDustin Pytko
 
Bridging the Abyss and Becoming the Work of Art- Aristotle, Socrates and Poet...
Bridging the Abyss and Becoming the Work of Art- Aristotle, Socrates and Poet...Bridging the Abyss and Becoming the Work of Art- Aristotle, Socrates and Poet...
Bridging the Abyss and Becoming the Work of Art- Aristotle, Socrates and Poet...Tristan Wicks
 
Memory, mimeses, tragedy
Memory, mimeses, tragedyMemory, mimeses, tragedy
Memory, mimeses, tragedyMariane Farias
 
Theory in anthropology since the sixties sherry ortner
Theory in anthropology since the sixties sherry ortnerTheory in anthropology since the sixties sherry ortner
Theory in anthropology since the sixties sherry ortnerLaura Calle
 
The_Cyclical_Pattern_of_the_Four_Mythos_of_Northrop_Frye_.pptx
The_Cyclical_Pattern_of_the_Four_Mythos_of_Northrop_Frye_.pptxThe_Cyclical_Pattern_of_the_Four_Mythos_of_Northrop_Frye_.pptx
The_Cyclical_Pattern_of_the_Four_Mythos_of_Northrop_Frye_.pptxGayatri Nimavat
 
Essay On Health And Fitness
Essay On Health And FitnessEssay On Health And Fitness
Essay On Health And FitnessJessica Hurt
 
Essay On Tragedy.pdf
Essay On Tragedy.pdfEssay On Tragedy.pdf
Essay On Tragedy.pdfAmanda Dahya
 
Aristotle S Theory Of Tragedy
Aristotle S Theory Of TragedyAristotle S Theory Of Tragedy
Aristotle S Theory Of TragedyJoaquin Hamad
 
Major Themes and analysis of Aristotle Poetics
Major Themes and analysis of Aristotle PoeticsMajor Themes and analysis of Aristotle Poetics
Major Themes and analysis of Aristotle Poeticssaba rai
 
Art as Narrative Recounting Trauma through Literature.pdf
Art as Narrative  Recounting Trauma through Literature.pdfArt as Narrative  Recounting Trauma through Literature.pdf
Art as Narrative Recounting Trauma through Literature.pdfSara Parker
 
Classical criticism in eng lit. presentation
Classical criticism in eng lit. presentationClassical criticism in eng lit. presentation
Classical criticism in eng lit. presentationPatrick Dave
 
Only Project Management Expert I need the answers.docx
Only Project Management Expert   I need the answers.docxOnly Project Management Expert   I need the answers.docx
Only Project Management Expert I need the answers.docxAASTHA76
 
Archetypal Literary Theory In The Postmodern Era
Archetypal Literary Theory In The Postmodern EraArchetypal Literary Theory In The Postmodern Era
Archetypal Literary Theory In The Postmodern EraNancy Rinehart
 
Analysis of sophocles_oedipus_the_king_a
Analysis of sophocles_oedipus_the_king_aAnalysis of sophocles_oedipus_the_king_a
Analysis of sophocles_oedipus_the_king_asaimaPerveen4
 

Similar to Aristotle, frye, and the theory of tragedy, by leon golden (20)

Aristotles study of tragedy, by henry alonzo
Aristotles study of tragedy, by henry alonzoAristotles study of tragedy, by henry alonzo
Aristotles study of tragedy, by henry alonzo
 
Plato.Freud.Nietzsche.pdf
Plato.Freud.Nietzsche.pdfPlato.Freud.Nietzsche.pdf
Plato.Freud.Nietzsche.pdf
 
AN ECLECTIC OVERVIEW OF LITERATURE AS AN ACT OF LANGUAGE AND THE LANGUAGE OF ART
AN ECLECTIC OVERVIEW OF LITERATURE AS AN ACT OF LANGUAGE AND THE LANGUAGE OF ARTAN ECLECTIC OVERVIEW OF LITERATURE AS AN ACT OF LANGUAGE AND THE LANGUAGE OF ART
AN ECLECTIC OVERVIEW OF LITERATURE AS AN ACT OF LANGUAGE AND THE LANGUAGE OF ART
 
Bridging the Abyss and Becoming the Work of Art- Aristotle, Socrates and Poet...
Bridging the Abyss and Becoming the Work of Art- Aristotle, Socrates and Poet...Bridging the Abyss and Becoming the Work of Art- Aristotle, Socrates and Poet...
Bridging the Abyss and Becoming the Work of Art- Aristotle, Socrates and Poet...
 
Narrative theories
Narrative theoriesNarrative theories
Narrative theories
 
Memory, mimeses, tragedy
Memory, mimeses, tragedyMemory, mimeses, tragedy
Memory, mimeses, tragedy
 
Literary theory
Literary theoryLiterary theory
Literary theory
 
Review of On Beauty
Review of On BeautyReview of On Beauty
Review of On Beauty
 
Theory in anthropology since the sixties sherry ortner
Theory in anthropology since the sixties sherry ortnerTheory in anthropology since the sixties sherry ortner
Theory in anthropology since the sixties sherry ortner
 
Aristotle
AristotleAristotle
Aristotle
 
The_Cyclical_Pattern_of_the_Four_Mythos_of_Northrop_Frye_.pptx
The_Cyclical_Pattern_of_the_Four_Mythos_of_Northrop_Frye_.pptxThe_Cyclical_Pattern_of_the_Four_Mythos_of_Northrop_Frye_.pptx
The_Cyclical_Pattern_of_the_Four_Mythos_of_Northrop_Frye_.pptx
 
Essay On Health And Fitness
Essay On Health And FitnessEssay On Health And Fitness
Essay On Health And Fitness
 
Essay On Tragedy.pdf
Essay On Tragedy.pdfEssay On Tragedy.pdf
Essay On Tragedy.pdf
 
Aristotle S Theory Of Tragedy
Aristotle S Theory Of TragedyAristotle S Theory Of Tragedy
Aristotle S Theory Of Tragedy
 
Major Themes and analysis of Aristotle Poetics
Major Themes and analysis of Aristotle PoeticsMajor Themes and analysis of Aristotle Poetics
Major Themes and analysis of Aristotle Poetics
 
Art as Narrative Recounting Trauma through Literature.pdf
Art as Narrative  Recounting Trauma through Literature.pdfArt as Narrative  Recounting Trauma through Literature.pdf
Art as Narrative Recounting Trauma through Literature.pdf
 
Classical criticism in eng lit. presentation
Classical criticism in eng lit. presentationClassical criticism in eng lit. presentation
Classical criticism in eng lit. presentation
 
Only Project Management Expert I need the answers.docx
Only Project Management Expert   I need the answers.docxOnly Project Management Expert   I need the answers.docx
Only Project Management Expert I need the answers.docx
 
Archetypal Literary Theory In The Postmodern Era
Archetypal Literary Theory In The Postmodern EraArchetypal Literary Theory In The Postmodern Era
Archetypal Literary Theory In The Postmodern Era
 
Analysis of sophocles_oedipus_the_king_a
Analysis of sophocles_oedipus_the_king_aAnalysis of sophocles_oedipus_the_king_a
Analysis of sophocles_oedipus_the_king_a
 

More from Mariane Farias

Robert Musil's other postmodernism, by M. Freed
Robert Musil's other postmodernism, by M. FreedRobert Musil's other postmodernism, by M. Freed
Robert Musil's other postmodernism, by M. FreedMariane Farias
 
Mecanismos internos (ensaios sobre literatura), Coetzee
Mecanismos internos (ensaios sobre literatura), CoetzeeMecanismos internos (ensaios sobre literatura), Coetzee
Mecanismos internos (ensaios sobre literatura), CoetzeeMariane Farias
 
A Educação Estética do Homem, Friedrich Schiller
A Educação Estética do Homem, Friedrich SchillerA Educação Estética do Homem, Friedrich Schiller
A Educação Estética do Homem, Friedrich SchillerMariane Farias
 
Introdução à leitura de Hegel, Alexandre Kojève
Introdução à leitura de Hegel, Alexandre KojèveIntrodução à leitura de Hegel, Alexandre Kojève
Introdução à leitura de Hegel, Alexandre KojèveMariane Farias
 
Aesthetic imitation and imitators in aristotle, by katherine e. gilbert
Aesthetic imitation and imitators in aristotle, by katherine e. gilbertAesthetic imitation and imitators in aristotle, by katherine e. gilbert
Aesthetic imitation and imitators in aristotle, by katherine e. gilbertMariane Farias
 
Poetics as system, by claudio guillen
Poetics as system, by claudio guillenPoetics as system, by claudio guillen
Poetics as system, by claudio guillenMariane Farias
 
What is poetics, by stein haugom
What is poetics, by stein haugomWhat is poetics, by stein haugom
What is poetics, by stein haugomMariane Farias
 
Myth and philosophy, by rui zhu
Myth and philosophy, by rui zhuMyth and philosophy, by rui zhu
Myth and philosophy, by rui zhuMariane Farias
 
Hume and the theory of tragedy, by j. frederick doering
Hume and the theory of tragedy, by j. frederick doeringHume and the theory of tragedy, by j. frederick doering
Hume and the theory of tragedy, by j. frederick doeringMariane Farias
 
The lost dimension of greek tragedy, by peter d. arnott
The lost dimension of greek tragedy, by peter d. arnottThe lost dimension of greek tragedy, by peter d. arnott
The lost dimension of greek tragedy, by peter d. arnottMariane Farias
 
Tragedy, pessimism, nietzsche, by joshua foa dienstag
Tragedy, pessimism, nietzsche, by joshua foa dienstagTragedy, pessimism, nietzsche, by joshua foa dienstag
Tragedy, pessimism, nietzsche, by joshua foa dienstagMariane Farias
 
Tragedy reconsidered, by george steiner
Tragedy reconsidered, by george steinerTragedy reconsidered, by george steiner
Tragedy reconsidered, by george steinerMariane Farias
 
The performative basis of modern literary theory, by henry mc donald
The performative basis of modern literary theory, by henry mc donaldThe performative basis of modern literary theory, by henry mc donald
The performative basis of modern literary theory, by henry mc donaldMariane Farias
 
The poetics of aristotle, by r. p hardie
The poetics of aristotle, by r. p hardieThe poetics of aristotle, by r. p hardie
The poetics of aristotle, by r. p hardieMariane Farias
 
The doleful airs of euripides, by blair hoxby
The doleful airs of euripides, by blair hoxbyThe doleful airs of euripides, by blair hoxby
The doleful airs of euripides, by blair hoxbyMariane Farias
 
Pity, fear, and catharsis in aristotles poetics, by charles b. daniels and sa...
Pity, fear, and catharsis in aristotles poetics, by charles b. daniels and sa...Pity, fear, and catharsis in aristotles poetics, by charles b. daniels and sa...
Pity, fear, and catharsis in aristotles poetics, by charles b. daniels and sa...Mariane Farias
 
Nietzsche's idea of myth, by benjamin bennett
Nietzsche's idea of myth, by benjamin bennettNietzsche's idea of myth, by benjamin bennett
Nietzsche's idea of myth, by benjamin bennettMariane Farias
 
Heidegger and tragedy, by michael gelven
Heidegger and tragedy, by michael gelvenHeidegger and tragedy, by michael gelven
Heidegger and tragedy, by michael gelvenMariane Farias
 
French scenes in greek tragedy, by mark damen
French scenes in greek tragedy, by mark damenFrench scenes in greek tragedy, by mark damen
French scenes in greek tragedy, by mark damenMariane Farias
 
Borges, averroes, aristotle, by daniel balderston
Borges, averroes, aristotle, by daniel balderstonBorges, averroes, aristotle, by daniel balderston
Borges, averroes, aristotle, by daniel balderstonMariane Farias
 

More from Mariane Farias (20)

Robert Musil's other postmodernism, by M. Freed
Robert Musil's other postmodernism, by M. FreedRobert Musil's other postmodernism, by M. Freed
Robert Musil's other postmodernism, by M. Freed
 
Mecanismos internos (ensaios sobre literatura), Coetzee
Mecanismos internos (ensaios sobre literatura), CoetzeeMecanismos internos (ensaios sobre literatura), Coetzee
Mecanismos internos (ensaios sobre literatura), Coetzee
 
A Educação Estética do Homem, Friedrich Schiller
A Educação Estética do Homem, Friedrich SchillerA Educação Estética do Homem, Friedrich Schiller
A Educação Estética do Homem, Friedrich Schiller
 
Introdução à leitura de Hegel, Alexandre Kojève
Introdução à leitura de Hegel, Alexandre KojèveIntrodução à leitura de Hegel, Alexandre Kojève
Introdução à leitura de Hegel, Alexandre Kojève
 
Aesthetic imitation and imitators in aristotle, by katherine e. gilbert
Aesthetic imitation and imitators in aristotle, by katherine e. gilbertAesthetic imitation and imitators in aristotle, by katherine e. gilbert
Aesthetic imitation and imitators in aristotle, by katherine e. gilbert
 
Poetics as system, by claudio guillen
Poetics as system, by claudio guillenPoetics as system, by claudio guillen
Poetics as system, by claudio guillen
 
What is poetics, by stein haugom
What is poetics, by stein haugomWhat is poetics, by stein haugom
What is poetics, by stein haugom
 
Myth and philosophy, by rui zhu
Myth and philosophy, by rui zhuMyth and philosophy, by rui zhu
Myth and philosophy, by rui zhu
 
Hume and the theory of tragedy, by j. frederick doering
Hume and the theory of tragedy, by j. frederick doeringHume and the theory of tragedy, by j. frederick doering
Hume and the theory of tragedy, by j. frederick doering
 
The lost dimension of greek tragedy, by peter d. arnott
The lost dimension of greek tragedy, by peter d. arnottThe lost dimension of greek tragedy, by peter d. arnott
The lost dimension of greek tragedy, by peter d. arnott
 
Tragedy, pessimism, nietzsche, by joshua foa dienstag
Tragedy, pessimism, nietzsche, by joshua foa dienstagTragedy, pessimism, nietzsche, by joshua foa dienstag
Tragedy, pessimism, nietzsche, by joshua foa dienstag
 
Tragedy reconsidered, by george steiner
Tragedy reconsidered, by george steinerTragedy reconsidered, by george steiner
Tragedy reconsidered, by george steiner
 
The performative basis of modern literary theory, by henry mc donald
The performative basis of modern literary theory, by henry mc donaldThe performative basis of modern literary theory, by henry mc donald
The performative basis of modern literary theory, by henry mc donald
 
The poetics of aristotle, by r. p hardie
The poetics of aristotle, by r. p hardieThe poetics of aristotle, by r. p hardie
The poetics of aristotle, by r. p hardie
 
The doleful airs of euripides, by blair hoxby
The doleful airs of euripides, by blair hoxbyThe doleful airs of euripides, by blair hoxby
The doleful airs of euripides, by blair hoxby
 
Pity, fear, and catharsis in aristotles poetics, by charles b. daniels and sa...
Pity, fear, and catharsis in aristotles poetics, by charles b. daniels and sa...Pity, fear, and catharsis in aristotles poetics, by charles b. daniels and sa...
Pity, fear, and catharsis in aristotles poetics, by charles b. daniels and sa...
 
Nietzsche's idea of myth, by benjamin bennett
Nietzsche's idea of myth, by benjamin bennettNietzsche's idea of myth, by benjamin bennett
Nietzsche's idea of myth, by benjamin bennett
 
Heidegger and tragedy, by michael gelven
Heidegger and tragedy, by michael gelvenHeidegger and tragedy, by michael gelven
Heidegger and tragedy, by michael gelven
 
French scenes in greek tragedy, by mark damen
French scenes in greek tragedy, by mark damenFrench scenes in greek tragedy, by mark damen
French scenes in greek tragedy, by mark damen
 
Borges, averroes, aristotle, by daniel balderston
Borges, averroes, aristotle, by daniel balderstonBorges, averroes, aristotle, by daniel balderston
Borges, averroes, aristotle, by daniel balderston
 

Recently uploaded

1029-Danh muc Sach Giao Khoa khoi 6.pdf
1029-Danh muc Sach Giao Khoa khoi  6.pdf1029-Danh muc Sach Giao Khoa khoi  6.pdf
1029-Danh muc Sach Giao Khoa khoi 6.pdfQucHHunhnh
 
Russian Escort Service in Delhi 11k Hotel Foreigner Russian Call Girls in Delhi
Russian Escort Service in Delhi 11k Hotel Foreigner Russian Call Girls in DelhiRussian Escort Service in Delhi 11k Hotel Foreigner Russian Call Girls in Delhi
Russian Escort Service in Delhi 11k Hotel Foreigner Russian Call Girls in Delhikauryashika82
 
Class 11th Physics NEET formula sheet pdf
Class 11th Physics NEET formula sheet pdfClass 11th Physics NEET formula sheet pdf
Class 11th Physics NEET formula sheet pdfAyushMahapatra5
 
APM Welcome, APM North West Network Conference, Synergies Across Sectors
APM Welcome, APM North West Network Conference, Synergies Across SectorsAPM Welcome, APM North West Network Conference, Synergies Across Sectors
APM Welcome, APM North West Network Conference, Synergies Across SectorsAssociation for Project Management
 
Introduction to Nonprofit Accounting: The Basics
Introduction to Nonprofit Accounting: The BasicsIntroduction to Nonprofit Accounting: The Basics
Introduction to Nonprofit Accounting: The BasicsTechSoup
 
Kisan Call Centre - To harness potential of ICT in Agriculture by answer farm...
Kisan Call Centre - To harness potential of ICT in Agriculture by answer farm...Kisan Call Centre - To harness potential of ICT in Agriculture by answer farm...
Kisan Call Centre - To harness potential of ICT in Agriculture by answer farm...Krashi Coaching
 
Holdier Curriculum Vitae (April 2024).pdf
Holdier Curriculum Vitae (April 2024).pdfHoldier Curriculum Vitae (April 2024).pdf
Holdier Curriculum Vitae (April 2024).pdfagholdier
 
Call Girls in Dwarka Mor Delhi Contact Us 9654467111
Call Girls in Dwarka Mor Delhi Contact Us 9654467111Call Girls in Dwarka Mor Delhi Contact Us 9654467111
Call Girls in Dwarka Mor Delhi Contact Us 9654467111Sapana Sha
 
Disha NEET Physics Guide for classes 11 and 12.pdf
Disha NEET Physics Guide for classes 11 and 12.pdfDisha NEET Physics Guide for classes 11 and 12.pdf
Disha NEET Physics Guide for classes 11 and 12.pdfchloefrazer622
 
General AI for Medical Educators April 2024
General AI for Medical Educators April 2024General AI for Medical Educators April 2024
General AI for Medical Educators April 2024Janet Corral
 
Paris 2024 Olympic Geographies - an activity
Paris 2024 Olympic Geographies - an activityParis 2024 Olympic Geographies - an activity
Paris 2024 Olympic Geographies - an activityGeoBlogs
 
Advanced Views - Calendar View in Odoo 17
Advanced Views - Calendar View in Odoo 17Advanced Views - Calendar View in Odoo 17
Advanced Views - Calendar View in Odoo 17Celine George
 
BASLIQ CURRENT LOOKBOOK LOOKBOOK(1) (1).pdf
BASLIQ CURRENT LOOKBOOK  LOOKBOOK(1) (1).pdfBASLIQ CURRENT LOOKBOOK  LOOKBOOK(1) (1).pdf
BASLIQ CURRENT LOOKBOOK LOOKBOOK(1) (1).pdfSoniaTolstoy
 
fourth grading exam for kindergarten in writing
fourth grading exam for kindergarten in writingfourth grading exam for kindergarten in writing
fourth grading exam for kindergarten in writingTeacherCyreneCayanan
 
Accessible design: Minimum effort, maximum impact
Accessible design: Minimum effort, maximum impactAccessible design: Minimum effort, maximum impact
Accessible design: Minimum effort, maximum impactdawncurless
 
Interactive Powerpoint_How to Master effective communication
Interactive Powerpoint_How to Master effective communicationInteractive Powerpoint_How to Master effective communication
Interactive Powerpoint_How to Master effective communicationnomboosow
 
social pharmacy d-pharm 1st year by Pragati K. Mahajan
social pharmacy d-pharm 1st year by Pragati K. Mahajansocial pharmacy d-pharm 1st year by Pragati K. Mahajan
social pharmacy d-pharm 1st year by Pragati K. Mahajanpragatimahajan3
 
Key note speaker Neum_Admir Softic_ENG.pdf
Key note speaker Neum_Admir Softic_ENG.pdfKey note speaker Neum_Admir Softic_ENG.pdf
Key note speaker Neum_Admir Softic_ENG.pdfAdmir Softic
 

Recently uploaded (20)

1029-Danh muc Sach Giao Khoa khoi 6.pdf
1029-Danh muc Sach Giao Khoa khoi  6.pdf1029-Danh muc Sach Giao Khoa khoi  6.pdf
1029-Danh muc Sach Giao Khoa khoi 6.pdf
 
Russian Escort Service in Delhi 11k Hotel Foreigner Russian Call Girls in Delhi
Russian Escort Service in Delhi 11k Hotel Foreigner Russian Call Girls in DelhiRussian Escort Service in Delhi 11k Hotel Foreigner Russian Call Girls in Delhi
Russian Escort Service in Delhi 11k Hotel Foreigner Russian Call Girls in Delhi
 
Class 11th Physics NEET formula sheet pdf
Class 11th Physics NEET formula sheet pdfClass 11th Physics NEET formula sheet pdf
Class 11th Physics NEET formula sheet pdf
 
APM Welcome, APM North West Network Conference, Synergies Across Sectors
APM Welcome, APM North West Network Conference, Synergies Across SectorsAPM Welcome, APM North West Network Conference, Synergies Across Sectors
APM Welcome, APM North West Network Conference, Synergies Across Sectors
 
Introduction to Nonprofit Accounting: The Basics
Introduction to Nonprofit Accounting: The BasicsIntroduction to Nonprofit Accounting: The Basics
Introduction to Nonprofit Accounting: The Basics
 
Kisan Call Centre - To harness potential of ICT in Agriculture by answer farm...
Kisan Call Centre - To harness potential of ICT in Agriculture by answer farm...Kisan Call Centre - To harness potential of ICT in Agriculture by answer farm...
Kisan Call Centre - To harness potential of ICT in Agriculture by answer farm...
 
Holdier Curriculum Vitae (April 2024).pdf
Holdier Curriculum Vitae (April 2024).pdfHoldier Curriculum Vitae (April 2024).pdf
Holdier Curriculum Vitae (April 2024).pdf
 
Call Girls in Dwarka Mor Delhi Contact Us 9654467111
Call Girls in Dwarka Mor Delhi Contact Us 9654467111Call Girls in Dwarka Mor Delhi Contact Us 9654467111
Call Girls in Dwarka Mor Delhi Contact Us 9654467111
 
Disha NEET Physics Guide for classes 11 and 12.pdf
Disha NEET Physics Guide for classes 11 and 12.pdfDisha NEET Physics Guide for classes 11 and 12.pdf
Disha NEET Physics Guide for classes 11 and 12.pdf
 
General AI for Medical Educators April 2024
General AI for Medical Educators April 2024General AI for Medical Educators April 2024
General AI for Medical Educators April 2024
 
Paris 2024 Olympic Geographies - an activity
Paris 2024 Olympic Geographies - an activityParis 2024 Olympic Geographies - an activity
Paris 2024 Olympic Geographies - an activity
 
Mattingly "AI & Prompt Design: Structured Data, Assistants, & RAG"
Mattingly "AI & Prompt Design: Structured Data, Assistants, & RAG"Mattingly "AI & Prompt Design: Structured Data, Assistants, & RAG"
Mattingly "AI & Prompt Design: Structured Data, Assistants, & RAG"
 
Advanced Views - Calendar View in Odoo 17
Advanced Views - Calendar View in Odoo 17Advanced Views - Calendar View in Odoo 17
Advanced Views - Calendar View in Odoo 17
 
BASLIQ CURRENT LOOKBOOK LOOKBOOK(1) (1).pdf
BASLIQ CURRENT LOOKBOOK  LOOKBOOK(1) (1).pdfBASLIQ CURRENT LOOKBOOK  LOOKBOOK(1) (1).pdf
BASLIQ CURRENT LOOKBOOK LOOKBOOK(1) (1).pdf
 
fourth grading exam for kindergarten in writing
fourth grading exam for kindergarten in writingfourth grading exam for kindergarten in writing
fourth grading exam for kindergarten in writing
 
Accessible design: Minimum effort, maximum impact
Accessible design: Minimum effort, maximum impactAccessible design: Minimum effort, maximum impact
Accessible design: Minimum effort, maximum impact
 
Interactive Powerpoint_How to Master effective communication
Interactive Powerpoint_How to Master effective communicationInteractive Powerpoint_How to Master effective communication
Interactive Powerpoint_How to Master effective communication
 
social pharmacy d-pharm 1st year by Pragati K. Mahajan
social pharmacy d-pharm 1st year by Pragati K. Mahajansocial pharmacy d-pharm 1st year by Pragati K. Mahajan
social pharmacy d-pharm 1st year by Pragati K. Mahajan
 
Código Creativo y Arte de Software | Unidad 1
Código Creativo y Arte de Software | Unidad 1Código Creativo y Arte de Software | Unidad 1
Código Creativo y Arte de Software | Unidad 1
 
Key note speaker Neum_Admir Softic_ENG.pdf
Key note speaker Neum_Admir Softic_ENG.pdfKey note speaker Neum_Admir Softic_ENG.pdf
Key note speaker Neum_Admir Softic_ENG.pdf
 

Aristotle, frye, and the theory of tragedy, by leon golden

  • 1. University of Oregon Aristotle, Frye, and the Theory of Tragedy Author(s): Leon Golden Reviewed work(s): Source: Comparative Literature, Vol. 27, No. 1 (Winter, 1975), pp. 47-58 Published by: Duke University Press on behalf of the University of Oregon Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/1769727 . Accessed: 23/09/2012 12:17 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp . JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org. . University of Oregon and Duke University Press are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Comparative Literature. http://www.jstor.org
  • 2. LEON GOLDEN Aristotle, Frye, And the Theory of Tragedy N ORTHROP FRYE has recognized a basic kinship between his Anatomy of Criticism and Aristotle's Poetics. After noting with regret the parochialismof many contemporarycritics, he warmly alludes to Aristotle's conception of a "totally intelligible structure of knowledge attainable about poetry which is not poetry itself, or the experience of it, but poetics."' This conception, reflected concisely in the opening lines of the Poetics, becomes the program of the Anatomy. Frye, however, aspires to improve on his model by making use of all the relevant doc- trines and techniques of criticism developed since Aristotle wrote. Tragedy is the central theme of the Poetics and a subject of major importancein the Anatomy as well. In comparing the two approachesto this genre we are struck by their wide divergence in method and con- clusions. Clearly both Aristotle and Frye make profound contributions to our understanding of tragedy but neither succeeds in providing a definitive statement that clarifies the nature of the genre as it has emerged and developed in the western literary tradition. I propose in this paper to assess our current understanding of the nature of tragedy based on the contributions made by Aristotle and Frye and then to sug- gest a method by which these important theoretical statements can be harmonized to lead us to a fuller understanding of the potentialities and boundaries of the genre. The major tenets of Aristotle's theory of tragedy are well known. I summarize them here for later comparison with Frye. For Aristotle tragedy is an imitation (mimesis) of actions involving the pitiable and fearful dimensions of human existence. This form of imitation repre- 1 Anatomy of Criticism (Princeton, N.J., 1957), p. 14. 47
  • 3. COMPARATIVE LITERATURE sents a noble (spoudaios) hero as its object; it uses artistically enhanced language as its means; and its manner of presentation is dramatic rather than narrative. The representation of pity (the feeling we have toward the undeserved misfortune of others) and fear (the same feeling when directed at our own vulnerability to such misfortune) requires that the tragic hero fall from happiness to misery because of some intellectual, not moral, error (hamartia). The effectiveness of any given tragedy is dependent upon its possessing a plot that is complete, is of the proper magnitude, and is developed in accordance with the laws of necessity and probability.The ultimate goal and essential pleasure associated with tragis mimesis is catharsis. Catharsis, a much disputed term, has been interpreted in four principal ways: (1) as a form of medical purgation in which the pathological elements of pity and fear are purged from the spectator; (2) as a form of moral purification in which the spectator achieves the proper mean between excess and deficiency in experiencing pity and fear; (3) as a structuralprocess by which the tragic deed of the hero is, in the course of the play, purified of its moral pollution; and (4) as the process of intellectual clarificationby which the spectator comes to understand, under a universal heading, the nature of the particular pitiable and fearful events that have been depicted.2 The ultimate thrust of the Aristotelian theory of tragedy will, of course, depend on which interpretation of catharsis we accept but the basic nature of Aristotle's approach to tragedy is clear even without a final decision about this important term. Aristotle's goal is to set forth the conditions under which the essential tragic effect and pleasure will be most fully achieved. His definition of tragedy is thus a prescription for the creation of an ideal work of art rather than a general statement applicable to all works traditionally included within the limits of the genre. Most of the plays cited for one reason or another in the Poetics cannot be dealt with effectively in terms of the definition of tragedy set forth in Chapter VI and few of the tragedies written since Aristotle's time will fit snugly within the confines of that definition. Recognizing that Aristotle's definition of tragedy is a statement of the ideal conditions 2 For a discussion of the various theories of catharsis see the following: J. Bernays, Zwei Abhandlungen iiber die aristotelische Theorie des Dramas (Berlin, 1880); I. Bywater, Aristotle on the Art of Poetry (Oxford, 1909), p. 160; G. F. Else, Aristotle's Poetics: The Argument (Cambridge, Mass., 1957), pp. 221-32, 436-44; Leon Golden, "Catharsis," Transactions of the American Philological Association, 93 (1962), 51-60 and "Mimesis and Katharsis," Classical Philology, 64 (1969), 145-53; D. W. Lucas, Aristotle; Poetics: Introduction, Commentary, and Appendixes (Oxford, 1968), pp. 282-86; H. Otte, Neue Beitriige zur aristo- telischen Begriffsbestimmung der Tragidie (Berlin, 1928), p. 10; Kurt von Fritz, Antike und moderne Tragidie (Berlin, 1962), p. xxvi. 48
  • 4. ARISTOTLE AND FRYE for the fulfillment of the tragic form prepares us for understanding Frye's widely divergent approach. Frye identifies five modes and six phases of tragedy at different stages of his argument but he does not treat these in any systematic form. The modes do relate to a development downward from stories about heroes who are superior in kind to other men and their environment to stories about heroes who are inferior in degree both to other men and to their environment. Frye identifies salient features characteristic of each level of development from the Dionysiac to the elegiac, high mimetic, low mimetic, and ironic modes. Pity and fear (not necessarily in the Aristotelian sense), hamartia (without moral coloring), and catharsis (in the sense of purgation) are attributed to some of the modes but they do not form a system of central, unifying ideas that establishes the essential meaning of the concept of tragedy. The six phases of tragedy represent a development from the heroic to the ironic world view. Here, too, however we do not have so much a systematic theory as a citation and analysis of particularexamples. Frye does assert that two commonly held "reductive formulas" for tragedy are partially but not completely valid: (1) that tragedy exhibits the omnipotence of an external fate and (2) that the tragic process is primarily a violation of moral law. Frye cites a number of examples which clash with these formulas. We see that Frye, unlike Aristotle, is concerned with establishing a critical position that will be relevant to the tremendous variety of works traditionally included within the genre of tragedy. His discussion of five modes and six phases recognizes the full range of manifestations tragedy has taken in its historical development. Unfortunately, Frye's analysis remains mostly on the level of a perceptive description of the salient features of each mode and phase and does not establish a systematic argument that would demonstrate the organic relationship among these modes and phases. The major Aristotelian concepts of pity and fear, hamartia, and catharsis are judged to occur in some dimensions of the tragic experience but not in others and Frye supplies no substitutions for them which would organize tragedy as a clearly unified territory within the wide landscape of artistic mimesis. The strength of Aristotle's theory is that it identifies with precision a central, perhaps the central theme of the genre; its weakness is that it fails to account for the great body of works which have historically been designated as tragedies. Frye's approach to tragedy makes a significant contribution toward overcoming this limitation but he, in turn, fails to provide us with a rigorous system of standards and criteria through which the boundaries of the genre can be fixed and its constitu- ent elements analyzed. It thus appears that a major contribution to the 49
  • 5. COMPARATIVE LITERATURE theory of tragedy could be made if it were possible to follow Frye in his attempt to do justice to the entire range of tragedies without abandon- ing Aristotelian rigor in establishing the definition of the genre. Such a compromise between the two approachesis not impossible; indeed, the mechanism for attaining it is implicit in the Aristotelian system itself. It is possible to isolate four parameters in the Aristotelian analysis of tragedy: (1) the moral stature of the hero: whether he is noble (spoudaios) or ignoble (phaulos); (2) the nature of the error (ha- martia) committed by the hero: whether it is intellectual or moral; (3) the destiny of the hero: whether he moves from happiness to misery or the reverse; and (4) the response of the audience: whether pity and fear are evoked and subjected to the process of catharsis in any of its possible interpretations. When we apply these categories to the data provided by the history of tragedy, we find four distinct patterns of tragic action. We shall now analyze these patterns in detail and suggest that, as a system, they repre- sent a rigorous approach to the phenomenon of tragedy that is fully adequate to deal with the diverse elements historically united in this genre. We shall begin with the pattern of tragic action which Aristotle specifically identifies as ideal in the Poetics and which, in my view, is represented in Greek tragedy only by the Oedipus Tyrannus. In this pattern a spoudaios hero, that is, one of moral nobility and integrity, makes an intellectual rather than a moral mistake (hamartia) which triggers a fall from happiness to misery and evokes the response of pity and fear from the audience. For Aristotle the evocation of pity and fear is the proper goal of tragedy and it is only by this pattern of tragic action that the goal can be achieved. To see the reason for this we must understandclearly the meaning of pity and fear for Aristotle. In Chapter XIII of the Poetics he defines these terms as follows: ".. . for pity is aroused by someone who undeservedly falls into misfortune, and fear is evoked by our recognizing that it is someone like ourselves who en- counters this misfortune (pity, as I say, arising for the former reason, fear for the latter)." Thus for Aristotle pity refers to our sympathetic response to the undeserved misfortune of someone else and fear indi- cates, narrowly and specifically, the anxiety we feel that such misfor- tune can befall those who have the same degree of intelligence and moral stature as ourselves. In order for the emotions of pity and fear to be evoked we must have a tragic hero of sufficient moral stature to deserve our respect and one with whom it is easy for us to identify. Moreover, this hero must commit a significant error (hamartia) or else the events of the drama would not be motivated and would not be linked 50
  • 6. ARISTOTLE AND FRYE by necessity and probability; nevertheless the error must be intellectual rather than moral or else the undeserved quality of the misfortune would be destroyed and with it the necessary preconditions for the evocation of pity and fear. The Oedipus Tyrannus offers a good example of this pattern of tragic action.3 Oedipus is clearly spoudaios because he always strives to ac- complish morally justifiable goals: he flees from Corinth when it seems possible that he might commit terrible crimes against those he assumes to be his parents; he exerts himself without limit in seeking to lift the plague from the people of Thebes; and, with total integrity, he brings to light the truth about himself despite all efforts by others to prevent his terrible moment of self-discovery. Some critics have seen Oedipus' rashness and quickness to anger as signs of a moral flaw in his character. They have failed to notice that such episodes occur when Oedipus' life is in danger or when a citizen of great reputation and authority appears to be withholding significant information that is necessary for the safety of the state. Oedipus' very human response in these situations is not his flaw; rather, his essential hamartia is his failure to understand the true relationship between his own, finite human existence and the infinitely powerful and mysterious nature of Apollo. Oedipus' attempt to avoid committing incest and parricide and his efforts to free Thebes from its suffering are the very virtues out of which his profound misunder- standing of Apollo arises. In the Oedipus Tyrannus we observe the evocation of both pity and fear because we are led to respect the moral stature of the hero, to understand and pardon the intellectual mistake which triggers his downfall, and to recognize ourselves as vulnerable to the same fate. The second pattern of tragic action is observed in those situations where pity alone is evoked without any concomitant fear in the technical Aristotelian senses of those terms. In this pattern the hero is no longer fully spoudaios but has only a hint of this quality and the mistake he makes is essentially a moral one. The fall from happiness to misery occurs with the same intensity as in the first pattern. Works that illus- trate the second pattern of tragic action must have a hero who at least aspires to act in accordance with moral virtue but is too weak to resist the external pressures that drive him to commit a debased or criminal act. The fact that the hero did not initially will his act but succumbed to external pressure makes it possible for us to feel some measure of 3 The view presented here of Oedipus as a noble hero is widely held today. See, for example, the perceptive discussion by Bernard Knox, Oedipus at Thebes (New Haven, Conn., 1957), pp. 194-96. An eloquent refutation of those who still wish to fix moral blame on Oedipus is provided by Kurt von Fritz, Antike und moderne Tragidie (Berlin, 1962), pp. 7-8. 51
  • 7. COMPARATIVE LITERATURE sympathy and anguish for an undeserved element in his fate. The moral- ly debased quality of his actions, however, interferes with the recogni- tion of our own vulnerability to a similar destiny and thus frustrates the evocation of Aristotelian "fear." Euripides' Medea is a clear example.4 Medea tells us how totally she had devoted herself to Jason's interests when he cunningly won her affection as part of his strategy for obtaining the golden fleece. She committed heinous crimes and cut all ties to her home and country to serve his needs. Her anger at her betrayal by the always pragmatic Jason drives her to seek revenge against him. She discovers the appro- priate means in a plan that requires her to murder her own children because only in this way can she hurt Jason as much as he has hurt her. From the moment she adopts the plan to the moment she completes it, we see Medea in an anguished and ambivalent state of mind toward the children. In feigning compliance with Jason's recommendations for her future life, she is brought to the verge of tears when she mentions the children to him and thinks of the terrible destiny she has designed for them. Her torment is intensified when she learns that Creon's daughter has accepted the fatal gifts from her children for now she knows that there can be no turning back from her decision. She agonizingly vacil- lates before taking the final, irrevocable step toward killing them as she sees how much they mean to her and how much she will suffer after she has murdered them. Nevertheless, the injury Jason has done to her pride threatens her existence so seriously that it must be redressed at any cost. In a poignant soliloquy, marked by passages of deep maternal love and flashes of angry indignation, Medea sees clearly that an evil passion for revenge will dominate all her rational misgivings about the act she is going to perform. It is possible to censure Medea for her inability to control her passions and her refusal to place the children's interests above her own but it is also clear that her fury is not willed by her but caused by Jason's callous treatment. Medea herself clearly is capable of the most intense love and loyalty as well as the most violent anger and vengeance. Because Medea realizes that the murder of her children is an evil and irrational act she cannot be a spoudaios hero like Oedipus in the Oedipus Tyrannus. We can, however, still pity her fate as not being fully de- served because she did not hate her children or desire to harm them. She acted in response to the pressure exerted by Jason's cruel and cynical abandonmentand committed an act she did not will and struggled hard not to perform. Aristotelian "fear"is largely absent here, however, since 4 An excellent insight into Medea'smood and characteris given by D. J. Cona- cher, EuripideanDrama: Myth, Theme and Structure (Toronto, 1967), p. 196. .52
  • 8. ARISTOTLE AND FRYE very few of us can imagine making the same decision as Medea under any sort of external duress. Thus the second pattern of tragic action shows some palpable differences from the pattern identified as ideal by Aristotle. The spoudaios quality of the hero is greatly diminished, he commits a serious moral error rather than simply an intellectual one, and he falls from happiness to misery in such a way as to elicit only pity, not fear, in the technical Aristotelian senses of those terms. The third pattern of tragic action involves the complete obliteration of pity and fear. In it a depraved rather than spoudaios hero commits the gravest moral errors and moves, because or in spite of them, not from happiness to misery but from misery to happiness. In this type of tragedy a profound flaw is usually uncovered in the order and govern- ance of the universe. Euripides' Orestes offers an excellent example of this type of tragedy.5Although the entire play is permeatedwith absurdist elements, a discussion of the ending will be sufficient for our present purposes. Orestes and Electra, having been betrayed by Menelaus, find themselves facing a death sentence in Argos. With their friend Pylades they plot to take appropriate vengeance on Menelaus by killing Menelaus' wife, Helen, before their own death sentence can be carried out. In addition, Electra urges that they seize Helen's daughter, Hermione, as a hostage. She notes that if Menelaus wants to take vengeance for Helen's death, they need only to threaten to cut Hermione's throat and Menelaus, who is a coward, will think better of it and allow them to escape. The plan is enthusiastically agreed upon, and Pylades and Orestes enter the palace to take their joyous revenge on Helen who is murderously attacked while Electra shouts encouragement from in front of the palace. The grim absurdity of human existence pictured in this play is under- scored when Hermione appears and, taken in by Electra's cunning, agrees with kindly human decency to intercede for Orestes and Electra with Helen. When Hermione has been seized, Electra is proud of this "heroic" action which will teach Menelaus to respect his formidable adversaries. In place of the awesome confrontations found in Homer, Aeschylus, and Sophocles we have here a competition in cunning, deceit, and cowardice which emphasizes the absurdity of the human condition. Before, however, the murder of Helen can be consummated, we are told by a servant that she has mysteriously disappearedinto the sky. The climax of the play brings Menelaus onto the.scene to discover the fate of Helen and take vengeance on those who may have harmed her. 5 Significant assistance in understanding this unusual play is given by Kurt von Fritz, op cit., pp. 312-16 and by William Arrowsmith in the introduction to his translation of this play in The Complete Greek Tragedies, ed. D. Grene and R. Lattimore, Vol. IV (Chicago, 1958), 186-91. 53
  • 9. COMPARATIVE LITERATURE In a sardonic debate Orestes regrets that Helen disappeared before he could kill her, and Menelaus, who believes that Orestes actually has murdered his wife, threatens vengeance if he attempts to enhance his reputation as a matricide by the additional slaughter of Hermione. Orestes trades insults with Menelaus as he holds his sword to Her- mione's throat and orders Pylades and Electra to set the palace afire. At this moment the greatest absurdity of all takes place as Apollo appears in the role of deus ex machina and suddenly reverses the action of the play. He announces that he has transported Helen to live in the heavens for ever, that Menelaus is to remarry, that Orestes is to take his sword away from Hermione's throat and marry her instead, and that Pylades and Electra are also to be married. Orestes welcomes and obeys the injunctions of Apollo but notes a threatening and fearful quality in the god's voice. So this "tragedy" comes to an end. In this pattern of tragic action pity and fear are destroyed since the necessary conditions for them are not present. In order to have pity and fear we need a spoudaios hero who makes an intellectual (not moral) error which triggers but does not fully cause his fall from happiness to misery. In the Orestes instead of a spoudaios hero we have a morally depraved one who moves from misery to happiness under divine sanc- tion in a way that defies both reason and justice. We respond to this revelation of profound irrationality in the universe not with pity and fear but rather with emotional shock, mirthless laughter, and a sense of spiritual desolation over the mockery and meaninglessness of human existence. The fourth pattern of tragic action stands in polar opposition to the third. Instead of pity and fear being obliterated by an explosion of cosmic evil they are transcended by an impressive manifestation of divine love for man. A clear example of this rather unusual dimension of tragedy is found in Sophocles' Oedipus at Colonus.6 The Oedipus of the Oedipus at Colonus has undergone the purifying fire of suffering and, though not purged of his human passions, has attained a deeper understanding of the human condition. He clearly perceives that he has been punished far too severely for any crime he has committed, that he has been betrayed and manipulated by his sons and Creon, and that he has benefitedfrom the love and kindness of Antigone, Ismene, and Theseus. As in the Oedipus Tyrannus, divine purpose is an ever-present controlling factor, but in this play it changes from a painfully mysterious force to a benign and affirmativeone. The action of the Oedipus at Colonus provides several dramatic 6 A good discussionof the characterof Oedipusas it is developedin this play is found in CedricWhitman,Sophocles: A Study of Heroic Humanism (Cambridge, Mass., 1951), p. 214. 54
  • 10. ARISTOTLE AND FRYE occasions for revealing the aspects of Oedipus' character and destiny which determine the play's specific tragic form. Oedipus' essential inno- cence is expressed in his argument with Creon when the latter cruelly attempts to take him back to Thebes against his will. Oedipus declares that no evil or sin within himself drove him to commit the terrible deeds whose source lay in a fearful ignorance over which he had no control. He would not willingly or knowingly have married Jocasta, nor would he willingly and knowingly have slain his father, but when attacked by apparent strangers, in a desolate area, he defended his own life and he poignantly calls upon his dead father's spirit to bear witness for him. Most important, however, is the manifestation of the benign interest which the gods now take in Oedipus. In the climactic scene of the play the blind Oedipus is suddenly given mysterious powers and guides his sighted companions to a sacred place where a divine voice summons him to his ultimate destiny and reward. Mystically, the heavens open and receive Oedipus who at the end of a troubled life is the recipient of infi- nite divine grace. Divine intervention has raised Oedipus above the human condition. As a result of that intervention he makes no mistake that leads him from happiness to misery but is instead led by divine grace from suffering to supreme happiness. His stature is now far above our own and since we cannot view him as someone like ourselves who has incurred undeserved misfortune because of an intellectual error, we do not respond with the emotions of pity and fear, but must rather view his final triumph with awe. Thus the Oedipus at Colonus as a tragedy directly contradicts the experience we have of the Oedipus Tyrannus as a tragedy. In place of a spoudaios hero who makes an intellectual mistake, it offers us a divinely protected hero who makes no essential error; in place of a fall from hap- piness to misery, it describes the reverse movement from misery to happiness; in place of pity and fear, it evokes awe and wonder. We have now identified four patterns of tragic action and provided an example from Greek tragedy to illustrate each of them. Similar examples can be found in Shakespearean and modern tragedy.7 The 7 An analogous descending movement from high tragedy to pathetic tragedy to absurd tragedy can be traced in Othello, Macbeth, and Richard III. In these plays we move from a spoudaios hero such as Othello (Iago himself refers to the Moor's "noble nature"), to one like Macbeth who is pressed by an external force to commit a crime he would not undertake by himself, to one, finally, like Richard III who is utterly depraved and rejoices in the evil he accomplishes. For a discussion of Othello's character see A. C. Bradley, Shakespearean Tragedy (London, 1929), pp. 189-91. Bradley also provides us with a perceptive analysis of the characters of Macbeth and Lady Macbeth, op. cit., pp. 351 ff. A good discussion of the impact of Richard III is provided by H. B. Charlton, Shakespearian Tragedy (Cambridge, 1952), p. 39. It should be noted that because of the death of Richard this play does not attain to the consummate absurdity of the Orestes. I know of no Shakespearean 55
  • 11. COMPARATIVE LITERATURE first form of tragedy we shall call high tragedy: it is the form specifically defined by Aristotle in the Poetics and involves a spoudaios hero who makes an intellectual mistake and whose fall from happiness to misery evokes from the audience the emotions of pity and fear (in the technical Aristotelian senses of those terms). The second form we shall call pathetic tragedy: it portrays a hero who is not fully spoudaios but who manifests at least a trace or hint of nobility and who, under the pressure of some external force, makes both moral and intellectual errors that lead to his downfall from happiness to misery. The fate of the hero of pathetic tragedy evokes only pity, not fear, from the audience. The third form we shall call absurd tragedy: it depicts a depraved or ignoble hero who commits a combination of moral and intelectual errors that are terrifyingly complemented by grim flaws in the universe itself. In its extreme form, this type of tragedy presents its depraved or ignoble hero as moving triumphantly from misery to happiness although a number of works stop just short of this radicalmanifestation of cosmic absurdity. Instead of evoking pity and fear, absurd tragedy obliterates those emo- tions by creating a mood of spiritual desolation and a sense of the mean- inglessness and mockery of human existence. The fourth form of trag- edy we shall call heroic tragedy: it presents a hero who is superior to ordinary standards of human nobility because he has been granted divine interest and protection. The hero commits no essential error, moves from misery or relative misery to supreme happiness, and evokes awe from the audience. Absurd tragedy destroys pity and fear; heroic tragedy completely transcends them. The analysis of tragedy given above is based on an extrapolation from the criteria set down by Aristotle in the Poetics. We have noted that Aristotle's specific and literal discussion of tragedy centers on the ideal conditions for the evocation of pity and fear which are seen to be the truly tragic emotions. Aristotle's concern with these ideal conditions is reflected in his famous definition of tragedy which applies fully to only a small number of works. The history of tragedy provides us with many more examples of pathetic tragedy than of Aristotelian high tragedy. The attempt to make a literal application of Aristotle's definition to tragedy, in general, results in a distortion either of the definition or of empirical reality. The expansion of the Aristotelian system provided in our analysis overcomes the narrowness inherent in the original defini- drama that fits easily within the boundaries of what we have called heroic tragedy but this concept precisely fits works which we today designate as "Christian trag- edy." For discussions of Christian tragedy which will illuminate its articulation with the pattern of tragic action we have called heroic see Karl Jaspers, Tragedy Is Not Enough, trans. H. A. T. Reiche, H. T. Moore, and K. W. Deutsch (Boston, 1952), pp. 28-87, and Reinhold Niebuhr, Beyond Tragedy: Essays on the Christian Interpretation of History (New York, 1965), pp. 155-69. 56
  • 12. ARISTOTLE AND FRYE tion and makes the Aristotelian approach truly viable in terms of the history of tragedy. Frye does attempt to deal with the greatly varied forms which tragedy has manifested throughout its historical development, but he does not provide firm and specific criteria by which the related forms of tragedy can be compared and analyzed. Thus in his discussion of the five modes of tragedy we learn that there is a Dionysiac mode that deals with "stories of dying gods"; an elegiac mode that "presents a heroism un- spoiled by irony"; a high mimetic mode which "mingles the heroic with the ironic" and in which "pity and fear become, respectively, favorable and adverse moral judgment, which are relevant to tragedy but not central to it"; a low mimetic mode in which "pity and fear are neither purged nor absorbed into pleasures, but are communicated externally, as sensation" and whose root idea "is the exclusion of an individual on our own level from a social group to which he is trying to belong": and an ironic mode in which pity and fear are not "raised" but rather "re- flected" to the reader and which represents "simply the study of tragic isolation as such" inasmuch as its tragic hero "does not necessarily have any tragic hamartiaor pathetic obsession: he is only somebody who gets isolated from his society."8 I find a similar problem in Frye's subsequent discussion of six phases of tragedy. His first phase is one "in which the central character is given the greatest possible dignity in contrast to the other characters, so that we get the perspective of a stag pulled down by wolves"; his second phase "is in one way or another the tragedy of innocence in the sense of inexperience, usually involving young people"; his third phase is one "in which a strong emphasis is thrown on the success or com- pleteness of the hero's achievement"; his fourth phase involves "the typical fall of the hero through hybris and hamartia"; his fifth phase is an ironic perspective of tragedy which "presents for the most part the tragedy of lost direction and lack of knowledge, not unlike the second phase except that the context is the world of adult experience"; his sixth plhaserepresents "a world of shock and horror in which the central images are images of sparagmos, that is, cannibalism, mutilation, and torture."9 Frye's discussion of tragedy thus provides some perceptive descrip- tive statements about possible kinds of tragic experience but it does not provide us with firm and objective criteria by which the various modes and phases of tragedy can be compared and understood. In place of Aristotle's rigorous but very narrow prescription for the 8 Frye, pp. 35-43. 9 Frye, pp.219-23. 57
  • 13. COMPARATIVE LITERATURE attainment of the ideal form of tragedy and Frye's comprehensive but too subjective description of the varieties of tragic experience, we have presented a system of analysis rooted in an expansion of, and extrapola- tion from, the objective criteria utilized by Aristotle in the Poetics. This system provides a means of making an objective analysis and compari- son of all the various patterns of tragedy and of observing the unity that underlies their diversity. Florida State University 58