SlideShare a Scribd company logo
1 of 89
Revision of “Comparison of Theories”
At the doctoral level, writing is a continual process of revision
as individuals improve skills and build subject matter expertise.
This notion of writing, reflecting, and revising carries forward
through the dissertation process to the publication of
professional materials. In this assignment, you will reflect on
the written work you submitted in Topic 3 and the feedback
provided by your instructor to create a revised version of the
paper “Comparison of Theories.”
General Requirements:
Use the following information to ensure successful completion
of the assignment:
· This assignment uses a rubric. Please review the rubric prior
to beginning the assignment to become familiar with the
expectations for successful completion.
· Doctoral learners are required to use APA style for their
writing assignments. The APA Style Guide is located in the
Student Success Center.
· Refer to Chapters 2-4 of the Publication Manual of the
American Psychological Association (6th ed.) for specific
guidelines related to doctoral level writing. These chapters
contain essential information on manuscript structure and
content, clear and concise writing, and academic grammar and
usage.
· This assignment requires that at least two additional scholarly
research sources related to this topic, and at least one in-text
citation from each source be included.
· You are required to submit this assignment to LopesWrite.
Refer to the LopesWrite Technical Support articles for
assistance.
Directions:
Reflect on your writing and the feedback from your instructor
on the paper “Comparison of Theories” that you submitted in
Topic 3. What could you do to improve the academic quality of
the content and the writing of the submitted paper?
Write a revised version (1,500-1,800 words total) of the paper
“Comparison of Theories” that makes improvements in the
caliber of the writing and incorporates instructor feedback
regarding content and writing. Include the following in your
submission:
1. A reflection (250-300 words) that provides a bulleted list of
the changes you made to the paper and discusses your revision
process including how you incorporated your instructor's
feedback into the revised version. Similar to an abstract, this
section will receive its own page following the title page and
preceding the introduction to the paper.
2. The revised paper that incorporates instructor feedback;
clarifies the thesis statement and solidifies supporting
arguments; edits for grammar, spelling, and punctuation; adjusts
word choice to display professional and scholarly language; and
adjusts sentence structure for improved readability.
CHAPTER 2
MORAL EDUCATION, LIBERAL EDUCATION
AND THE VOICE OF THE INDIVIDUAL
Paul Standish
‘I want to break free.’ – Freddie Mercury
The words above, from Freddie Mercury’s hit song, Free, have,
so it seems, a guaran-
teed appeal to young (and older) people today. In fact, there are
many songs in which
one finds expressions of, or cries of, or demands for freedom.
We live in a world that,
in so many respects, offers freedom to people as never before.
But the word seems to
have an unstoppable emotive force. Don’t we all at times utter it
or think it – whether
we are thinking ‘Now at last I feel free’, or ‘If only I could be
free’, or ‘Once I get
away from here I shall be free’? Where does the emotive power
of the idea of freedom
come from and why does it seem so important to us?
For all the apparent impetus towards new possibilities of life,
however, there is in
some of these expressions more than a suggestion of the
ressentiment that Nietzsche
saw as a manifestation of nihilism. Nihilism of such kinds
involves a negativity
towards the way things are, in a never-ending, perhaps
compulsive longing for some
other world. If only things could be different, these thoughts
seem to say; they are the
opposite of the yea-saying, the intense absorption in experience,
that might otherwise
be associated with freedom. But, this is an essay about neither
Nietzsche nor nihilism.
What I propose to do is to consider the ways in which concerns
with freedom have
been played out in the philosophy of the curriculum. I shall do
this by tracing a story
that leads from the rise of progressivism to the reactions against
it.
Although there is, in a sense, something timeless about
questions concerning free-
dom, they acquire new dimensions in circumstances of
globalization. Whereas one
might, on a standard analysis, ask questions about what it can
mean for the individual
to be free when he or she is at the same time conditioned by
social, cultural, political
and religious circumstances within the nation-state, the very
terms of this question are
now challenged by globalization. It is not just that the nation-
state finds itself com-
promised by the power of multinationals or by the invasive
forms of new communi-
cations or by larger political forms of organization; it is that the
very space of the
political, the terms of the public and the private, is reconfigured
in new and sometimes
frenetic, sometimes tranquilized forms. Education systems now
routinely acknowl-
edge questions of globalization, but these rarely go beyond
gestures towards the
knowledge economy or the somewhat haphazard adoption of
web-based learning.
From country to country, however, the picture varies. A
dimension of the demise of
33
K. Roth and I. Gur-Ze’ev (eds.), Education in the Era of
Globalization, 33–50
© 2007 Springer.
34 PAUL STANDISH
the nation-state for many citizens in European countries, for
example, is precisely that
they now think of themselves as citizens of Europe. The ways in
which individual
identities are developed, and hence that the possibilities of
freedom are conceived, are
deeply conditioned by these changing political terms. In
countries, such as the UK or
Japan, however a relative isolation is maintained, with
correspondingly more intro-
spective conceptions of citizenship and its education. There are
obvious debates to be
had about how far public education should foster loyalty to the
nation-state and how
far cosmopolitan values, and about how far these are
incompatible. In other political
regimes, to be sure – say, in theocracies, in countries devastated
by poverty or in newly
formed democracies – the stakes of freedom are plainly very
different.
When one looks across this range of difference, and against the
in some respects
common background of global change, what is clear is that
Enlightenment ideals of
freedom are themselves challenged. While I do not propose to
foreground the
Nietzschean themes alluded to here, it is in the restoring of such
an inflection at
the end of the chapter that an alternative, richer conception of
freedom in relation to
the curriculum is sought.
It is in this context that concerns about freedom and schooling
have developed
in various ways and in diverse circumstances. In Japan, there is
concern about
drop-out rates from education, about the rebellious behaviour of
young people,
about classroom disruption, and lack of respect for tradition,
about hair dyed
blond . . . And, in this context, some argue that what is needed
is education of the
heart (kokoro no kyoiku). In the UK within recent decades,
debates about moral
education and citizenship have gained a new prominence. What
is needed, the
argument has been, is to get ‘back to basics’. What we need to
do is to teach
children the difference between right and wrong. In these and
other countries, it
has become a common wisdom that it is progressive (or child-
centred) ideas and
methods, that have given children too much freedom and so
deprived them of the
standards of behaviour and the discipline that is necessary in
their upbringing.
John Major went so far, in the early 1990s, as to say: ‘The
progressives have had
their say and they have had their day’. In fact, in the UK, during
the past 20 years,
no leading politician (of any of the parties) has been willing to
speak in favour of
progressivism because in the eyes of the public it has become so
much associated
with the image of self-indulgent teachers, who want to be
‘friends’ with the
children rather than to teach them, to let children do whatever
they want, and
because the one thing that the general public wants from
education is for it to
make sure that their children come out of school with the
necessary skills to find
decent jobs.
I want shortly to give a brief account of that development in the
UK and of reac-
tions against it. But, first, it is appropriate to say more about
the value of freedom
that is so close to its heart. For brevity, I shall not say anything
here about the
prominence of the idea in the world of Ancient Greece but shall
confine myself to
some remarks about the rise of the idea of freedom, principally
in Europe, over the
past 300 or so years. What does a consideration of that period
show?
MORAL EDUCATION, LIBERAL EDUCATION 35
The development of the idea of freedom
in the modern Western world
When people speak in history or philosophy of ‘the modern
world’, they typically
have in mind a period of time extending back to René Descartes
and the individual-
ism of disengaged rationality and to the political individualism
of John Locke. But
probably the most striking changes come with the political
upheavals of the late 18th
century and, in the UK especially, the massive social change
brought about by the
Industrial Revolution. Perhaps equally important during these
centuries is the rise of
science, which came with a new confidence in man’s reasoning
and a faith in progress.
(It was indeed thought of as ‘man’s’ reasoning at the time!)
Words such as ‘progress’
and ‘development’ have now become so commonplace in our
thinking that we
suppose them to be perfectly natural, almost as if progress were
built into the universe,
but really this is very much the result of these massive changes
in thought. With this
new confidence in human abilities, there was an unprecedented
questioning of estab-
lished religious and moral horizons, and also the growing belief
that, just as science
had brought about spectacular changes in technology, so too
rationality could be
applied to the organization of society.
The gradual move from a conception of the universe as God’s
creation towards a
placing of man at the centre of things (that is, the rise of
humanism) gave new promi-
nence to the idea of freedom. Immanuel Kant advanced the key
principle that, because
human beings were capable of free will, they should always be
treated as ends, never
simply as means. (In other words, they should never be treated
simply as slaves, but
should be recognized as beings with interests of their own, and
with the capacity ratio-
nally to reflect on those interests.) This has become a guiding
principle for the modern
world. Perhaps the most important figure in the change we are
considering, however,
is Jean-Jacques Rousseau. His radical ideas pointed to the ways
in which the contem-
porary world caused people to lead lives that were shaped by
mere convention and that
were unnatural. One can perhaps picture the extraordinary
costumes that were worn
by the aristocracy of that time – the long wigs, the make-up, the
brightly coloured
fancy clothing for women and men! – and think of these as
symbols of the falseness
of people’s values and behaviour. In fact, however, the very
ideas of what is natural
and of falseness here are themselves familiar to us very much
because of Rousseau’s
own work. For, in his rejection of the values of convention, he
argued that human
beings had lost touch with nature and with their true selves. The
way that today we
cherish the natural world – our delight in a beautiful mountain
range as well as our
current environmentalism – would probably have made little
sense in the Western
world before Rousseau’s time. And, when today we read in a
popular magazine such
as Cosmopolitan of the need to get in touch with your ‘real self’
(Are you in touch
with the real you?), this idea, which apparently comes so
naturally to us, is surely
partly attributable to Rousseau. The idea of what is real or true
to ourselves, which
connects with our notions of honesty, sincerity, integrity and
being ‘together’ as a per-
son, is sometimes spoken of as authenticity. In his book The
Ethics of Authenticity
36 PAUL STANDISH
(1991), Charles Taylor speaks of the massive inward turn that is
brought about by
Rousseau’s thinking: Rousseau gives us a sense of ourselves as
beings with inner
depths, for whom the morally good life must be one where we
feel in tune with our
own deepest commitments and feelings (as opposed to one
where we simply follow
what our religious or political leaders, or our parents, say). The
source of morality is
a voice within.
What Rousseau also offers, of course, in his conception of
nature is a new idea of
childhood – hence his enormous influence on thinking about
education. Against the
Christian idea that human beings are born in a state of ‘original
sin’, he enables us to
think of children as innocent (and pure and good, perhaps)
because they are closer to
nature. In contrast to the idea that the role of education was to
mould children into a
shape that would fit society, Rousseau’s view was that the
perverted forms that soci-
ety had come to assume must themselves change in accordance
with what was natural.
His description of Emile’s upbringing does indeed have an
important bearing on edu-
cation, but the book needs to be seen as part of his larger
political philosophy: his
vision of the good society and of citizenship. In the light of
Emile (Rousseau, 1911,
originally published 1762) and his other more obviously
political writings, there is a
clear connection between his thought and an event that was
profoundly to shape the
history of modern Europe and its understanding of itself – the
French Revolution
(1789). Its slogan of ‘liberty, equality, fraternity’ underlines the
point.
In the 19th century, the thinker who stands out for his
importance in the political
thinking of the English-speaking world is, of course, John
Stuart Mill. In Mill’s On
Liberty, originally published in 1859, he advances what has
become taken by people
in general to be a fundamental principle. He writes:
The object of this essay is to assert one very simple principle,
as entitled to govern
absolutely the dealings of society with the individual in the way
of compulsion and con-
trol, whether the means used be physical force in the form of
legal penalties or the moral
coercion of public opinion. That principle is that the sole end
for which mankind are war-
ranted, individually or collectively, in interfering with the
liberty of action of any of their
number is self-protection. That the only purpose for which
power can rightfully be exer-
cised over any member of a civilized community, against his
will, is to prevent harm to oth-
ers. His own good, either physical or moral, is not a sufficient
warrant (Mill, 1978, p. 9).
In other words, you should not prevent someone from doing
what they want to do
unless they are harming someone else. You should not interfere
with them because
they are harming themselves or because you think you know
what is best for them.
This principle encounters many problem cases, some of which
Mill and his critics
have addressed, but it remains an immensely powerful guiding
principle and a natural
reference point.
Although the ways of thinking sketched here have become
naturalized in the
Western world, they have undoubtedly brought problems,
problems that could not
easily have been anticipated. When the individual becomes the
ultimate reference point,
there is a loss of horizons of meaning that in the past had given
sense to much of what
he did; community ties are weakened, and the individual feels
rootless and purposeless;
there is a kind of ‘disenchantment’ of the world. Within the
democracies that have
MORAL EDUCATION, LIBERAL EDUCATION 37
developed, especially where the masses are not well educated,
there is some tendency
for values and policies to be determined by the ‘lowest common
denominator’, so that
societies are flattened and narrowed. And in these
circumstances morality can degen-
erate into crude utilitarianism, governed by a technical
rationality.
Of course, the history of the 20th century is marked by two
world wars. Amongst
the social consequences of these in the UK were a weakening of
the British class
system, which had been such a pronounced feature of the period
of the Empire, and a
change in the role of women (as they too became directly
involved in the war effort or
took over civilian jobs normally held by men). In the 15 or so
years immediately
following the Second World War, the UK faced a period of
austerity and at the same
time saw the closing decades of its empire, as colonized
countries moved towards
independence. But, in the 1960s, there was a new period of
economic prosperity and
suddenly the feeling that things could change. New universities
were built to meet the
needs of the children of the post-war baby boom who were now
passing through
adolescence, sex scandals in the government changed people’s
attitudes towards those
in power and authority, the Beatles made their first records and
‘flower-power’ (the
hippies) arrived! This was a new sense that one could question
the way things had
been done in the past, that one could, and one should, live one’s
life as one chose. One
must above all be authentic. It was in this context that
progressivism came to be intro-
duced in schools.
Progressive schooling and its introduction in the UK
While the advent of progressivism in state education in the UK
was later than it had
been in Germany and Scandinavia, for example, or for that
matter in the United States,
its development was perhaps more dramatic.1 The Primary
Memorandum in Scotland
(1965) and the Plowden Report (1967), two major government
reports, advocated a
radical change in the education of children in elementary
school. The following para-
graph from the Primary Memorandum is indicative:
It is now generally accepted that the primary school is much
more than a preparation for
secondary school: it is a stage of development in its own right .
. . [Schooling must] meet
the child’s needs and interests . . . [The teacher must] provide
the environment, experi-
ences and guidance which will stimulate growth along natural
lines . . . [The child is] not
an adult in miniature . . . [N]atural endowment of children is
not uniform . . . [G]rowth
and development . . . are continuous . . . The artificial nature of
school organisation
[needs to be compensated for] (SED, 1965, pp. 3–4).
To anyone familiar with the texts of progressive educators,
these ideas will be famil-
iar enough. It would be easy to match the phrases here to ideas
of John Dewey, espe-
cially in Democracy and Education (Dewey, 1925, originally
published in 1916). It
is undoubtedly the case that the ideas that were promoted in the
teacher education
1 There had been a number of influential experiments in private
education before this time. For a full
discussion of the development of progressivism, see Darling and
Nordenbo (2003).
38 PAUL STANDISH
colleges at this time were a watered-down, if not a distorted,
version of the thinking
of the philosophers whom they quoted (Rousseau and Dewey
above all). And even if
the new approaches that they advocated did not affect all
schools, there was neverthe-
less a sudden wave of interest in these innovations. Visitors
came from many coun-
tries to see the new ‘Plowden schools’.
It is worth pausing for a moment to think what one might have
seen in a visit to a
progressive elementary school classroom in England at that
time. In contrast to the
plain, rather forbidding room with high windows (so that the
children would look up
towards God) and straight rows of desks (so that would work
silently and attend only
to the teacher) that had been the experience of the previous
generation, the new class-
room would be a colourful and comfortable place: there would
be large windows, let-
ting the light in and encouraging children to look out at the
garden outside; tables
would be arranged in ‘family’ groups, encouraging children to
work with one another;
the walls would be decorated with the brightly coloured art
work of the children; there
would be a ‘quiet corner’ with a carpet and cushions, and
picture-books for children
to browse; there would be pet animals (such as guinea pigs) for
the children to care
for, and plants for them to tend; and there would be a variety of
activity, with children
writing, drawing, making things, playing, talking and laughing
excitedly; the teacher
would not generally have spoken to the class as a whole, but
would move around the
room, attending to one child then another as the need arose. The
children would up to
a point be free to pursue the activities in whatever order they
chose – in other words,
to follow their interests. The principles and values governing
this scene can be
summed up in the following set of precepts:
• children learn best through doing, through experience;
• learning takes place in a process of discovery;
• creativity should be developed;
• imagination should be developed;
• children learn through play;
• they learn best when they are happy;
• learning should begin with the interests of the child;
• children must not become bored;
• children must learn things in meaningful contexts (not just
isolated facts or
mindless drills);
• learning should be organized on the basis of themes or topics,
not according to
abstract academic subjects;
• education is a process of growth from within;
• the role of the teacher is to provide conditions that will assist
that growth;
• all children are different and they have their individual needs
and rates of
growth;
• the teacher must respond to the child’s needs, not present them
with what she
wants to teach;
• the emphasis should be on encouragement and praise, not
punishment;
• the teacher should not be an authoritarian figure but more like
a friend to the
children.
MORAL EDUCATION, LIBERAL EDUCATION 39
These then were the values promoted by many of those training
teachers at the time
and to some extent they became a kind of ideology. It is not the
case that all schools
adopted them entirely, but the general climate in the primary
school undoubtedly went
through a period of major change.
Economic change and conservative reactions
In the 1970s, however, events outside the school came to have
an important bearing
on the country’s development and on how education and
teachers were seen. In 1972,
a world crisis was occasioned when some of the main oil-
producing countries in the
Middle East made the decision to act collectively to raise
prices. In the UK, one effect
was a doubling in the cost of petrol overnight. Inevitably, this
put severe pressure on
the economy. This occurred following a time of prosperity when
the major trade
unions had succeeded, through collective bargaining, in gaining
wage increases for
their members. Now, with higher prices in the shops, they
understandably pressed for
more. Through the 1970s, there was a series of strikes against a
background of rising
inflation (to over 20%). Social problems appeared to be on the
increase, with crime
rising, and there was a general air of unrest. In 1979, Margaret
Thatcher came to
power, with a radical agenda for reform, one that involved high
levels of unemploy-
ment, new kinds of poverty and a squeeze on the funding of
public services, welfare
and education. Inevitably, progressive education was blamed for
much that was wrong
in society. Her first Minister of Education, Keith Joseph, even
went so far as to say
that it was teacher educators who were to blame because they
had introduced teach-
ers to Dewey!
In or around the 1970s, a number of publications had been
produced under the
ominous title of ‘Black Papers in Education’2 (see Boyson,
1975; Cox, 1992; Cox
and Boyson, 1975, 1977; Cox and Dyson, 1969). At the time
these reactionary texts
struck many teachers as the ranting of conservative extremists,
and they were
assumed simply to be wildly out of touch. It was striking,
however, that a decade
later, with the reforms that Margaret Thatcher was to introduce,
they had come closer
to the mainstream. What Thatcher picked up on and skilfully
exploited was suspi-
cions amongst ordinary people that all was not well with
education. For many peo-
ple, the challenge to conventional notions of discipline and
authority that had come
with progressivism had seemed threatening, and the emphasis
on creativity, play, and
happiness in the elementary classroom appeared to involve a
neglect of the knowl-
edge and values that children needed. Not surprisingly, this laid
the way for the idea
that we needed to ‘get back to basics’ and that children must
learn the difference
between right and wrong.
2 The term ‘Black Paper’ borrows from the normal use of the
phrase ‘White Paper’ for a government policy
document.
40 PAUL STANDISH
This widespread reaction to progressivism may have been
justified in some ways,
but it was generally based on very crude and limited ideas about
education. It needs
to be contrasted with the serious and careful work of a number
of critics who, from
the 1960s onwards, raised questions of a predominantly
philosophical kind about
some of the assumptions of progressivism. These criticisms
were advanced in the
name of liberal education, and it is to this that I now turn.
The idea of a liberal education
The views in Question are particularly interesting because,
unlike those of the reactionary
critics above, they also were committed to the idea that
education was fundamentally con-
nected with freedom. But they disagreed about what this
freedom consisted in. The lead-
ing figure in this in the UK was R. S. Peters, although in many
respects his work related
to ideas being developed around the same time by Israel
Scheffler in the United States.
In collaboration with his colleagues, Paul Hirst and Robert
Dearden, Peters attempted to
restate the idea of a liberal education. The importance of this
idea and its influence on
Anglophone philosophy of education can scarcely be
questioned. It is a conception of
education with ancient roots that presents us with cogent
criticisms of progressivism.
Criticism of progressivism from liberal education
Like the reactionary critics mentioned above, these thinkers
were concerned about vari-
ous aspects of the wave of progressivism that was changing
education. Within the child-
centred preoccupations with play, happiness, creativity, learning
by discovery (or
experiential learning) and growth, they detected a somewhat
sentimental view of the
child. They identified also a failure to think through what these
terms really implied. To
take an example, progressive educators tended to think that
children must above all be
happy and that only the happy child would learn well, and this
came to mean that a class-
room in which children were smiling and laughing was a good
classroom. But, as
Dearden in particular pointed out, happiness is a much more
elusive notion than this sug-
gests. Sometimes we can be laughing but not be happy or only
happy in a superficial way.
Sometimes a greater degree of happiness comes because of
struggling and then feeling
that one has really achieved something. Some kinds of
happiness bring satisfactions that
are more profound. If smiling and laughing were the ultimate
satisfaction, we should put
scientists to work on a drug that would produce this state
reliably and without difficulty.
But surely we want more from our lives than this. At least,
surely we should!
This connects very much with what is perhaps the most
pervasive criticism of pro-
gressive education that these philosophers made. This was, in R.
S. Peters’ words, that
child-centred education was concerned too much with the
manner and insufficiently with
the matter of education. In other words, it was too concerned
with questions about the
methods of learning and insufficiently concerned with what was
learned. From the point
of view of liberal education, the question of what is to be
learned is the fundamental ques-
tion of education. Let us consider how they set about answering
that question.
MORAL EDUCATION, LIBERAL EDUCATION 41
What is worthwhile?
There are obviously some things that we learn to do that we
need more or less for our
survival and some that are really a matter of training for the
jobs that we take up in
society. For example, in the comparatively recent past, many
young women were
trained in typing skills. With the development of voice-
recognition, these skills will
perhaps eventually become obsolete, and it is not obvious why
anyone would then
what to acquire them. So they are useful skills but nothing
more. On the contrary,
there are some things we learn that are not obsolescent in this
way. It is noticeable that
these are things that, unlike typing, have often been pursued by
people who have not
had to find jobs to support themselves (the aristocracy, for
example). They seem to be
things that, whether or not they are useful, are intrinsically
worthwhile. The idea of
what is worthwhile in itself is at the heart of this account of
education. So we must
ask what it is that people find worthwhile. What do they find
most satisfaction in?
In addressing this question in his book Ethics and Education,
Peters considers the
things that people enjoy in a series of ascending stages. In the
first place, they enjoy
physical pleasures such as eating and drinking, sex, and lying in
the sun. These are
genuine sources of satisfaction for human beings, and they are
activities that allow
scope for care, refinement and sophistication. (Think for a
moment of the remarkable
difference between the way in which even the higher animals
eat and a simple meal
shared amongst friends or family.) But these activities also have
their limitations.
They depend on cyclical appetites – for example, there is only
so much that one can
eat at one time. And each time you eat, even where this is a
gourmet meal, you do, as
it were, start again from the beginning.
The second kind of enjoyment that Peters considers includes
games and sports.
People take great satisfaction in these. The advantage they have
over the pleasures of
the senses above is that they offer extraordinary possibilities for
the development of
ability or skill. If you play chess or tennis and you practise
regularly, you may be able
to press your achievement to higher and higher levels.
Activities of this kind do not
depend on cyclical appetites, and indeed, they may strengthen
your capacity the more
you do them. When you resume such activities, you do not have
to start from
the beginning, as it were, but build on the skill level that you
have reached. They offer
the possibility for extending human capacities in remarkable
ways. But these activities
also have limitations. Sports and games tend to be limited parts
of our lives. Taking
part in such activities does not, in general, cast light on the
world as a whole or help
you in other aspects of your life.
The third type of activity that Peters considers is what he calls
‘theoretical activi-
ties’. He has in mind such academic pursuits as the study of
history or mathematics or
literature. Unlike the pleasures of eating and drinking, these do
not depend on cycli-
cal appetites but, on the contrary, are intensified the more you
do them. Of course, you
have to take a break for a rest sometimes! But the chances are
that the more you know
about, say, history, the more satisfying further study will be.
They do not depend upon
competition over resources that are scarce, because in
intellectual activities the
42 PAUL STANDISH
possibilities extend the more they are pursued, nor do they
depend upon competition,
where, as in sports and games, the winner takes the prize,
because these activities
depend upon and are enhanced by the shared pursuit of their
goals. Moreover, they are
not confined in terms of their influence on our lives. The way
we live in the world is
transformed and improved if we know something about how it
has developed (in terms
of social and political history, geography, geology and so on)
and something about the
science and technology upon which it depends. More strongly,
this knowledge, and
perhaps the understanding of human nature that we can gain
from such disciplines as
history and literature, makes us better able to address the
practical problems that we
will face, in all their ethical diversity. Furthermore, in view of
the fact that reason is
the most obvious feature that distinguishes us from other forms
of life and that these
activities are supreme developments of human reason, it is this
that we should
develop. In sum, theoretical activities offer unparalleled
opportunities for satisfaction.
Cultural initiation and the development of mind
If we think a little about reason and the nature of mind, we
should come to realize that
the development of the mind is quite unlike the development of,
say, a muscle in the
body. Of course, there are physical parts of the body upon
which the mind depends,
but the mind is not an organ of the body; the brain is not the
mind. To recognize this
is to realize the immense importance that initiation into a
culture has for the mind’s
development. To speak of initiation into a culture here is not to
refer to something
highbrow but rather to think of the range of complex practices
that make up any soci-
ety and into which children are gradually introduced. Coming to
participate in these
practices is the development of mind. This may seem a
surprising statement, but it can
be supported by reference to the well-known case of the so-
called wild child of
Aveyron.
In France in the 18th Century, a child was discovered in the
forest. The child was
probably about 10 years old but was behaving like no ordinary
child. He moved about
on his hands and feet, and, obviously terrified of people, made
animal-like noises
when he was approached. Eventually, he was surrounded and
caught, and then taken
to an asylum in Paris. Asylums in Europe at that time, quite
unlike modern hospitals,
were places where mentally ill or abnormal people were
confined. The public could
pay an entrance fee to come and look (and probably laugh) at
the people inside. An
enlightened doctor heard about the child and became interested.
The evidence was that
this was a child who had been abandoned at birth and who had
been left in the woods
to die. The amazing thing was that it seemed that he had been
found by wolves and
protected by them, and so had spent several years amongst
them. The doctor was inter-
ested to see how far this child had become different from a
normal child because of
being so dramatically cut off from society, and also whether he
could be civilized. The
doctor took the child into his home and cared for him, and tried
to do just this.
What is immediately striking about this story is that, although
the child is not
radically different physiologically from other children (his brain
has developed
MORAL EDUCATION, LIBERAL EDUCATION 43
organically, just as his muscles have), his mental state is barely
recognizable as that
of a human being at all. This should draw our attention to what
it is we mean when
we speak of the mind of a human being. In short, the mind is
nothing without the
cultural practices into which the child is introduced. Most
important among those
practices is language itself, as virtually all distinctively human
activity seems to
follow in some way from this. This child has been cutoff from
language users, and
so, the limited and strange ways of thinking that he has
developed are scarcely
recognizable to us. Indeed, it relates more to a wolf’s behaviour
than to anything we
could call mind.
If this is right, it seems to follow that a child’s upbringing
cannot simply be a natural
process of growth, or of unfolding from within, or even of
unaided discovery learning.
In any culture, the child must be introduced into the practices of
that culture. Thinking
of the way we treat infants and very young children – over such
practices as sitting,
walking, eating, talking, dressing, laughing – can help to show
that this is the case.
A further comparison with animals helps to make this point. The
societies that we
live in are extremely complex, and our practices are the result
of thousands of years
of development. To see quite how far this is true, it is worth
thinking for a moment of
animals living in a natural environment – say, lions living in the
African savannah. It
is probably the case that the way that lions live today – their
patterns of hunting, eating
and mating – are no different from the way they were 5000
years ago. If we think, on
the contrary, of the way in which people live in any ordinary
city today in contrast to
the lives of people there 5000 years ago, the difference is truly
remarkable. It should
leave us with no doubt, first, of the importance of educational
practices through which
these ways of thinking and understanding are passed on and
advanced from one
generation to the next, and, second, of the dependence of what
we mean by ‘mind’
upon these practices.
It seems to follow from the above that education ought to
initiate people into the
forms of knowledge and understanding that have come down to
us. For, if education
is to be more than mere training for a job, it should free the
mind to function in as rich
a way as is possible; it is in this sense particularly that it is
liberal. Not to introduce
learners to the ways of understanding that have come down to
us would amount to
leaving them confined within limited ways of thinking – ones
that they had acquired
perhaps only from their immediate community or perhaps from
a diet of cartoon
programmes on television.
The ‘conversation of mankind’
One of the most influential articles by Paul Hirst concludes with
words from an essay
by Michael Oakeshott entitled ‘The Voice of Poetry in the
Conversation of Mankind’
(in Oakeshott, 1962):
As civilised human beings, we are the inheritors, neither of an
inquiry about ourselves and
the world, nor of an accumulating body of information, but of a
conversation, begun in the
primeval forests and extended and made more articulate in the
course of centuries. It is a
conversation which goes on both in public and within each of
ourselves. Of course there
44 PAUL STANDISH
is argument and enquiry and information, but wherever these are
profitable they are to be
recognized as passages in this conversation, and perhaps they
are not the most captivating
of the passages . . . Conversation is not an enterprise designed
to yield an extrinsic profit,
a contest where a winner gets a prize, nor is it an activity of
exegesis; it is an unrehearsed
intellectual adventure . . . Education, properly speaking, is an
initiation into the skill and
partnership of this conversation in which we learn to recognize
the voices, to distinguish
the proper occasions of utterance, and in which we acquire the
intellectual and moral
habits appropriate to conversation. And it is this conversation
which, in the end, gives
place and character to every human utterance (Hirst, 1965, pp.
52–53).
Oakeshott’s moving words here underline the connection
between the ways in which
an education of this kind is properly described as liberal. It is
liberal in the same sense
of the term as is used in the liberal arts colleges of the United
States. The initiation
into the ‘conversation of mankind’ then involves something like
an initiation into ‘the
best that has been thought and said’, in Matthew Arnold’s
famous (if contentious)
phrase. And, in this respect, these words not only value the past
but connect with val-
ues that shaped the thinking of the world of Ancient Greece.
The past is not valuable
because it is the past. It is valuable because it offers us the
developing history of
attempts to get at the truth of things and to understand what
matters in human lives.
In the Republic, Plato gives us a wonderful image of education
with the myth of
the Cave. He describes the human condition as being like that of
people living in the
darkness of a cave and watching the flickering images projected
onto the back of the
cave by the light from its mouth. What they see is not real but
the distorted images
(the shadows) of real objects at the mouth of the cave, objects
illuminated by the
bright light of the sun. (The relevance of the fact that the idea
of reality that many
people have today is given by the distorted images of the world
on television scarcely
needs spelling out.) Education involves the process of helping
these people to turn
their heads away from these images in order that they should
come to see the real
objects at the mouth of the cave and eventually look at the sun
itself, the source of
truth and goodness. But, just as we find it difficult to look at
bright lights when we
have been in the dark and are inclined to be dazzled and to turn
back to the darkness,
so too people would prefer to look at these images (and to
remain in ignorance) rather
than to face up to the truth. Crucial to Plato’s account then is
coming to see things
truly (the contemplation of truth and goodness); it is freeing the
mind from illusion.
Rational autonomy and political liberalism
A commitment to truth is close to the heart of the idea of a
liberal education that is
developed by Peters and his colleagues. But their position is
also complicated by a fur-
ther dimension of freedom, and this connects with the modern
political liberalism
associated especially with J. S. Mill. Here, the emphasis is not
so much on freedom
from illusion as on freedom to choose what to do: in the
absence of any indisputable
substantive conception of the good, the individual should decide
for herself how she
is going to live her life. Far from being a licence for
irresponsibility, however, this was
developed in terms of what came to be called ‘rational
autonomy’. Although there is
now a huge literature on autonomy, especially in relation to
education but also more
MORAL EDUCATION, LIBERAL EDUCATION 45
generally in political philosophy, perhaps the most succinct
expression of rational
autonomy is to be found in Dearden’s essay ‘Autonomy and
Education’. As Dearden
explains: ‘A man is autonomous, on Kant’s view, if in his
actions he has bound himself
by moral laws legislated by his own reason, as opposed to being
governed by his own
inclinations’ (Dearden, 1972, p. 58). What should be noticed
here is the emphasis on
reasoning through one’s principles for oneself. On this view,
you should not do some-
thing simply because the priest or the government or your
parents or the media tell
you to, or because you do not have the strength of character to
do anything different,
or because you are under the influence of drugs or obsessions or
neurotic fears, and
so on. You should reflect on your desires and reason through
what to do. Of course,
the principles you adopt, the reasons for your actions, may be
ones that are likely to
be current in your culture in one way or another, but what is
crucial is that you decide
to adopt these as your own.
In the decades since this restatement of the idea of a liberal
education was made,
there has been a tendency for the connection with political
liberalism (and hence with
autonomy) to come to the fore, to the growing neglect of the
more classical connec-
tion with the contemplation of truth. The term ‘liberal
education’ is sometimes now
used solely with such political principles in mind, in such a way
that the robust
account of the curriculum that was produced has been largely
lost. In my own view
this is very much to be regretted. Questions about what is to be
learned and why
should be recognized as unavoidable by any policy maker or
practising teacher, and
philosophy of education must find ways of addressing them.
In what follows, and to confront such questions myself, I shall
say something
about problems with the vision of a liberal education that I have
sketched and shall
point to ways in which its limitations may be overcome. I shall
also attempt to show
how what I have to say connects with the account of
contemporary individualism with
which the present discussion began.
Addressing the difficulties with the idea of a liberal education
Peters and his colleagues had great influence throughout the
English-speaking world.
But the idea of a liberal education that they advanced was not
without its critics. A
common response was that it provided nothing new: it was
simply a rationalization for
what was in fact going on at the time in grammar schools, with
children at other
schools – that is, the majority – given a watered-down version,
and thus, it shored up
the power relationships and class distinctions that were
responsible for some of the
injustice in society. Its conception of the curriculum itself was
dull and outmoded – a
matter of passing on the knowledge that happened to be
preferred by a section of soci-
ety rather than anything that was likely to be truly meaningful
to the lives of people
in general. That knowledge was highbrow and academic, the
critics said, and so, not
surprisingly, many children were alienated and did badly at
school. Not only did it
reflect the interests of particular social classes; it was also
inherently sexist, being
46 PAUL STANDISH
based on the work or the deeds of ‘dead white males’. And, far
from developing crit-
ical thinking, it encouraged the repetition of received ideas.
Moreover, because of its
emphasis on this outmoded content, it failed to appreciate the
importance of the
insights of progressivism – in particular, the need for education
to acknowledge the
differences between people and to develop from the individual
herself.
If liberal education is practised in the way described in the
preceding paragraph, it
should indeed be criticised. Many students, including some of
the most intelligent, are
not moved by ‘the best that has been thought and said’. Such an
education will, more-
over, be a limitation of the individual rather than something that
might engage her
more deeply and foster her development. And it must be
admitted that over-attention
to the subject matter can inhibit opportunities for students to
respond authentically
and to find their own voices.
To be fair to Peters and his colleagues, however, it was never
their intention that
the curriculum should be a mere passing on of received ideas:
they advocated cur-
riculum content that incorporated traditions of criticism, and
they saw the initiation of
the learner into such forms of knowledge as a means of her
engagement. The criticism
of their views considered here then depends upon a distortion of
the ideas that they
advanced. I do, nevertheless, want to draw attention to two main
concerns.
In the first place, the emphasis on rational autonomy as a
central aim of education
is based on a narrow view of human life and morality. It
encourages us to think of the
good life as one that is carefully planned out in (perhaps) most
respects. In conse-
quence, it loses sight of the value of spontaneity. This might be
found, for example, in
acts of unreflective generosity or courage and in the everyday
kindness that good peo-
ple show to others. Indeed, sometimes to reflect before you act
– say, when an acci-
dent occurs – could be a sign of moral failing. Spontaneity is
also apparent in a kind
of joie de vivre, a delight in living or even just a sense of fun,
as it is in a certain
receptiveness to others. The emphasis on rational autonomy
makes it sound also as
though being morally good is likely to coincide with being
intelligent and so hides the
goodness that can exist in simple unreflective lives. As such, it
may suppress the vari-
ety of human life and thereby have a limiting effect on the kinds
of community that
we can develop. To exaggerate (just a little unfairly!), it
sometimes seems that the
ideal rationally autonomous person would be someone like Mr
Spock on the Starship
Enterprise, someone who always meticulously plans everything
he does and for whom
a spontaneous emotion is something to be quickly mastered and
overcome.
A second criticism concerns its emphasis on intellectual
pursuits and the elitist
connotations this has. While there is a good case for saying that
everyone should be
given the chance to pursue such activities, it is likely that these
will appeal most to
more intelligent people, and perhaps, as has been noted, not to
all of them: many will
find that an academic curriculum of this kind does not speak to
them and stifles their
voices. The point of studying history or physics may be lost on
many people, espe-
cially while they are children. The fact that people who write
theoretical articles about
education almost by definition enjoy such things makes them
bad at seeing how this
may not be so for everyone!
MORAL EDUCATION, LIBERAL EDUCATION 47
Three questions arise from this. First, what response should
there be to the problem
of the demanding and potentially alienating nature of
intellectual pursuits? Second,
does this justify different curricula for those who do not
progress well with such activ-
ities? And third, is there anything in the account of the value of
theoretical activities –
anything liberal, that is – that can be extended to other less
intellectual pursuits?
Intellectual activities are demanding, and their appeal is often
difficult to under-
stand from the outside. It is usually the case that, before one
can participate in them
with any great satisfaction, one has to undergo periods of hard
work and perhaps bore-
dom: one has to acquire the ‘vocabulary’ to take part in the
conversation, as it were –
whether this is in literary criticism, physics or history, or in
more creative activities
such as music and art. Hence, the teacher must tread a careful
path that enables the
child to acquire the vocabulary appropriate to the subject – the
skills, knowledge and
understanding – while avoiding the alienating effects that the
demands of the subject
may have. It must be her aim in the course of this for the
subject to speak to the child
in such a manner that the child can come to find her voice in it:
that she sees how it
may (come to) matter to her. And this does not mean that she
finds that it may match
something that already exists in herself, but rather that it offers
a new possibility for the
development of her voice – that is, for the expansion of herself.
Without this, the sub-
ject is in danger of going dead on the child, and schooling is
likely to be an alienating
experience, even if it equips the child with high grades. Bearing
these factors in mind,
then, it does seem that a degree of coercion is justified in taking
the child through those
difficult stages of learning that lead to this more rewarding
understanding.
My own view regarding the second question is that the demands
of a liberal edu-
cation, thus conceived, are likely to be too great for some
children and so that it is
appropriate to provide different curricula, probably at some
stage during high school.
Of course, this need not be done on an all-or-nothing basis. And
there should be
opportunities for children to move from one route to another.
A further factor is important here – in terms of social justice but
also for purely
educational reasons. It is sometimes said that education is
wasted on the young.
Certainly there is evidence that mature students make much
better use of educational
opportunities. Hence, there is every reason to encourage people
to take up such study
throughout their lives, and so this is a powerful argument for
meaningful lifelong
learning. I do not necessarily suggest that full-time education
should be available to
adults at public expense because the costs of this may well be
prohibitive. But there
is a strong case for state subsidy of part-time education for
adults. Even part-time
study in evening classes can transform people’s lives, and
sometimes the combination
of study and working can be peculiarly enriching.
With regard to the third question, it should be recognized that
there are aspects of
a liberal education that cannot easily be extended or replicated.
The ideal product of
such an education is someone who has a breadth of
understanding across the different
forms of knowledge that are our inheritance, in sciences, the
humanities and the arts.
But such a person will also have a deep love for at least one of
these pursuits, such
that it is an absorbing interest that brings to her life the sense of
participating in an
48 PAUL STANDISH
‘unrehearsed intellectual adventure’, in Oakeshott’s words, an
adventure that becomes
all the more intense and absorbing the more it is pursued. And,
surprising though this
may at first seem, it is in the idea of intense absorption that a
Nietzschean inflection
is found once again. It is perhaps this more dynamic aspect that
we should look to if
we hope to extend something of this experience to those who
are not intellectually up
to the full demands of a liberal education.
I suggest that there are other less intellectual activities that can
offer such kinds of
intense absorption. For examples, we should perhaps turn
attention in the direction of
craft activities. Of course, we can think of the kinds of
satisfactions that people gain
from activities such as carpentry or pottery, but there is
obviously a danger of anachro-
nism or nostalgia here. These things play a less prominent part
in people’s lives,
whether at work or in their leisure time, than they used to. So,
we need to be prepared
to consider activities of quite different and perhaps surprising
kinds. I am struck by the
kind of enthusiasm and delight that people can take in practical
work with things – in
making them and shaping them – in more contemporary,
everyday circumstances.
I am thinking of the pride of the engineer in the smooth-running
machine, of the hair-
dresser in cutting and styling, or of the bricklayer in the clean
lines of a wall, or of the
chef in preparing fine food. Take car mechanics as an example.
Such activity does
indeed offer scope for further understanding and enquiry, and
for the refinement of
skill with the accumulation of experience. Those involved in it
often seem to take a
delight in the work that incorporates aesthetic and ethical values
– say, in the good
timing of the engine, the pleasure to be found in its efficiently
moving parts, its func-
tional capability and improvement, and so on. This is a very
ordinary example but one
worthy of attention. When people take pleasure in their work in
this way, this can spill
over into other areas of life, generating a kind of curiosity about
things and bringing
them into intense involvement with others. Such involvement is
often not confined to
the activities concerned but becomes a broader social
commitment and identification.
The idea of a liberal education has tended to reinforce certain
dichotomies in our
thinking – between theory and practice, between the academic
and the vocational,
between the mind and the body – in each case favouring the
former term. It has also,
and perhaps in consequence of these dichotomies, been
excessively preoccupied with
propositional knowledge. Of course, it would be absurd to deny
the massive impor-
tance of propositional knowledge – not as the expression of
inert facts but as the sub-
stance and vocabulary of the forms of knowledge of which
Peters and Hirst speak. The
alternative advocated here is not the skill-based curriculum that
has become fashion-
able, important though skills obviously also are. What is
missing from the picture, and
what the craft examples above may suggest, is the importance of
knowledge by direct
acquaintance. Amongst more intellectual pursuits, art
appreciation plainly involves an
acquaintance with particular works of art, where one’s
encounter with them exceeds
anything that could be rendered in propositional terms, however
rich propositional
language may be as an approach to these works. This kind of
acquaintance is also, I
suggest, to be found somewhere in the mechanic’s relation to
the engine or the hair-
stylist’s relation to hair – including their relation to the kinds of
resistance that the
MORAL EDUCATION, LIBERAL EDUCATION 49
materials they work with present. It is there too, I also want to
say, in the historian’s
familiarity with a particular period, or in the physicist’s or the
philosopher’s familiar-
ity with particular sets of problems, and the characteristic kinds
of resistance that they
present. Indeed, this familiarity is very much a part of knowing
one’s way around a
subject and the satisfactions that this offers.
Finally, it is important to draw attention to the fact that there is
a kind of moral edu-
cation that is inherent in the demands that learning can make on
us, but these are
demands that sometimes elude progressive education. These
include, first, the intellec-
tual virtues celebrated in the academic life, but the thought here
is that what is most
important extends across more practical domains. Without the
understanding devel-
oped through knowledge by acquaintance, through patient
attention to the way things
are, these intellectual virtues may cut loose from the substance
that gives them their
sense. These are moral matters also in the way that such forms
of learning draw the
learner into practices that are sustained by communities.
Although this may not be
explicit, such communities uphold standards to which the
learner must constantly
aspire to be worthy – whether this is to the standards of truth
and critical argument
found in an academic discipline or to those inherent in the
creation and maintenance of
the fabric of the world we live in. When one applies oneself to
such activities, there is
a real sense in which one’s attention is turned beyond oneself.
What is learned –
whether this is the functioning of the machine, the stresses that
metal will take, and the
explosiveness of a gas in an engine, or the substance of an
academic subject – can lead
to a kind of attention-to-the-way-things-are that has its intrinsic
virtues but that also can
disturb us from the self-preoccupied tendencies to which we can
otherwise succumb.
Far from a direct concentration on the development of the self,
it is in such endeavours
that the individual can flourish most, and through this
engagement that she may find
not only her own voice but that she has something meaningful
to say.3
References
Boyson, R. (1975) The Crisis in Education (London, The
Woburn Press).
Cox, C.B. (1992) The Great Betrayal (London, Chapmans
Publishing Ltd.).
Cox, C.B. and Boyson, R. (eds) (1975) The Fight for Education:
Black Paper 1975 (London, Dent).
Cox, C.B. and Boyson, R. (eds) (1977) Black Paper 1977
(London, Maurice Temple Smith).
Cox, C.B. and Dyson, C.B. (1969) The Crisis in Education
(London, Critical Quarterly Society).
Darling, J. and Nordenbo, S.E. (2003) “Progressivism”, In:
Blake, N. et al. (eds) The Blackwell Guide to
Philosophy of Education (Oxford, Blackwell), pp. 288–308.
Dearden, R.F. (1972) “Autonomy and Education”, In: Dearden,
R.F., Hirst, P.H. and Peters, R.S. (eds)
Education and Reason (London, RKP), pp. 390–397.
Dewey, J. (1925) Democracy and Education (New York,
MacMillan).
Hirst,P.H. (1965) “Liberal Educationand the Nature of
Knowledge”, In: Archambault, R.D. (ed.) (1965)
Philosophical Analysis and Education (London, RKP); also in
Hirst, P.H. (1974), Knowledge and the
3 An earlier version of this chapter was presented as the Ogata
Lecture at the University of Tohoku, Japan.
I am grateful to those present on that occasion, and to Morinichi
Kato and Naoko Saito especially, for their
comments and response.
50 PAUL STANDISH
Curriculum (London, RKP); also in Dearden, R.F., Hirst, P.H.,
and Peters, R.S. (eds) (1972) Education
and Reason (London, RKP).
Mill, J.S. (1978) On Liberty (Indianapolis, IN, Hackett
Publishing Company).
Oakeshott, M. (1962) Rationalism in Politics and Other Essays,
edited by Fuller, T. (London, Methuen).
Rousseau, J-J. (1911) Emile (London, J.M. Dent).
SED (1965) The Primary Memorandum (Edinburgh, Scottish
Education Department).
Taylor, C. (1991) The Ethics of Authenticity (London, Harvard
University Press).
Blindsided by the Avatar: White
Saviors and Allies Out of Hollywood
and in Education
Julio Cammarota
Any real change implies the breakup of the world as one has
always known
it, the loss of all that gave one an identity, the end of safety.
And at such
moment, unable to see and not daring to imagine what the future
will
now bring forth, one clings to what one knew, or thought one
knew, to
what one possessed or dreamed that one possessed. Yet, it is
only when
a man is able, without bitterness or self-pity, to surrender a
dream he
has long cherished or a privilege he has long possessed that he
is set
free—he has set himself free—for higher dreams, for greater
privileges.
—James Baldwin
Every week I assist a social studies teacher with the
implementation
of a social justice government course at a Tucson high school
located
in Arizona. My role is to teach students qualitative research
techni-
ques so they can ‘‘read the world’’—in the Freirian sense
(Freire
1993). The teacher provides the students with terms such as
‘‘cultural
capital,’’ ‘‘social construction,’’ and ‘‘white privilege’’ so they
can
express critically the complexity of what they are ‘‘reading.’’
As part of a lesson on white privilege, the teacher whom I will
refer to as Juan Gomez decided to show a trailer to the film,
The
Blind Side as evidence of the ‘‘white savior syndrome.’’ This
was
the first time that I had seen this trailer, and I was struck by the
affect of the actors. Sandra Bullock’s character was fierce, bold,
and eminently determined to change the world in ways that mat-
tered to her. Quinton Aaron, who plays a young African
American
The Review of Education, Pedagogy,
and Cultural Studies, 33:242–259, 2011
Copyright # Taylor & Francis Group, LLC
ISSN: 1071-4413 print=1556-3022 online
DOI: 10.1080/10714413.2011.585287
242
football player Michael Oher with many needs (i.e., housing,
financial resources, emotional support), appears subdued,
emotion-
ally withdrawn, almost developmentally handicapped—with no
real sense that he has the capacity to change the world in any
way, shape, or form. Juan showed this trailer to demonstrate
that
Hollywood tends to make films based on this theme; young
people
of color can escape their predicament of marginalization
through
the guidance and agency of a lone white actor. Juan identified
this
theme as the ‘‘white savior syndrome.’’
After the trailer, we engaged students in critical media literacy
(Alverman and Hogood 2000; Kellner and Share 2005, 2007).
Students are often unaware of unjust representations and thus
need
critical media literacy, which cultivates ‘‘skills in analyzing
media
codes and conventions, abilities to criticize stereotypes,
dominant
values, and ideologies, and competencies to interpret the
multiple
meanings and messages generated by media texts’’ (Kellner and
Share 2005, 372). Additionally, media is often how students
learn
about racial prejudices and privileges, as part of an encoded
social
logic of racist expression and exclusion.
We started our media literacy lesson by querying the students
about their general perceptions of The Blind Side. We drew
from
Freire’s (1993) approach of ‘‘problem-posing’’ by suggesting
ques-
tions to the students and facilitating a dialogue about the
problems
of the film. To our general question about their perceptions,
many
responded that they ‘‘liked the film,’’ or thought it was a ‘‘good
story about helping someone out.’’ Our facilitator roles allow us
to offer our positions and take responsibility as educators to
stimulate dialogue in critical directions. Therefore, I interjected
and mentioned how I thought the trailer represented the white
female and black male in extreme, polarized ways. I told the
stu-
dents that the white female seemed strong, capable, and
effective
while the black male appeared dilatory, dour and even, perhaps,
mentally challenged. Some students immediately defended the
film
saying that the African American character did not appear
‘‘mentally challenged’’ and that it was ‘‘good that he was being
helped.’’ One student stated that she saw the entire film and
that it
‘‘focuses more on the football player than on her (the white
female).’’
Juan reminded the students that the trailer represents the white
savior syndrome in which a white person guides people of color
from the margins to the mainstream with his or her own
initiative
and benevolence. The movement occurs through the ‘‘smarts’’
of
Blindsided by the Avatar 243
the lone savior and not by any effort of those being saved. The
white savior syndrome has the tendency to render people of
color
incapable of helping themselves—infantile or hapless=helpless
victims who survive by instinct. People of color supposedly
lack
the capacity to seek change and thus become perceived as
dispos-
sessed of historical agency. Any progress or success tends to
result
from the succor of the white individual, which suggests that
escaping poverty or ignorance happens only through the savior’s
intelligence.
This assistance amounts to what Freire calls ‘‘false generosity’’
such that a white person may provide help to people of color yet
help comes in the form of a saving action that tends to help a
single
individual or group. The focus on ‘‘saving’’ instead of
‘‘transform-
ing’’ fails to address oppressive structures and thus the
privileges
that maintain white supremacy. False generosity is an ‘‘attempt
to
soften the power of the oppressor in deference to the weakness
of
the oppressed’’ (Freire 1998, 46).
The teacher then contrasted his definition of white savior with
white ally. According to Juan, a white ally is someone who does
engage in what Freire calls ‘‘true generosity’’ by joining in
soli-
darity with people of color to struggle collaboratively against
those
institutions that maintain oppression. Solidarity involves
sublimat-
ing one’s ego and status so that people of color can provide
empow-
ered leadership in movements of liberation. A reduction of
status
requires challenging the very institutions and practices that
proffer
white privilege and power. Anything less would amount to
‘‘false
generosity’’ such that support would at best make a difference
to
a handful of people as opposed to engaging in actions of
solidarity
that may lead to the dismantling of oppressive institutions and
thus
long-term change. True generosity requires of the oppressed
‘‘hands . . . extended less and less in supplication, so that more
and more they become hands which work, and working,
transform
the world’’ (Freire 1998, 46).
Although we problem-posed several questions to the students,
they also have equal opportunity to pose their own questions.
When Juan completed his statements about the white savior
versus
the white ally, an African American male student expressed,
‘‘But
Blind Side is a true story! How could you criticize someone
helping
another human being?’’
Juan and I do not argue against the veracity and value of white
people helping people of color. Significant social change can
and
244 J. Cammarota
does happen with the assistance of white allies. However, we
are concerned, through an Althusserian symptomatic reading
(Althusser and Balibar 1979), about what might be missing or
even
implicitly assumed in films like The Blind Side. In such
cinematic
treatments of race, people of color appear to lack the agency
neces-
sary to enact positive changes in their own lives. The
underlying
assumption is that people of color, on their own, fail to enact
resili-
ence, resistance, and success—as made gratuitously evident in
the
representation of Michael’s family life. Any achievements in
these
areas seem to result from the initiatives of the white savior.
Further-
more, these Hollywood narratives often miss or ignore how
people
and communities of color do successfully resist and overcome
marginalization through their self-initiated agency.
This article discusses how the white savior syndrome renders
the
misrepresentation of the potential of people of color to resist
and
lead the transformation of oppressive conditions within their
own
social context. Indigenous resistance requires endogenous
(internal)
leadership such that all social justice actions derive from and
con-
tinue to flow through communities of color and their leaders.
White
saviors represented in popular media overshadow the fact that
people of color are part of and, most importantly, make history.
For instance, the historical legend of Abraham Lincoln ‘‘freeing
the slaves’’ eclipses the real efforts of myriad African
Americans
who resisted and fought against their bondage.
In the school context, I discuss Ruby Payne’s (2005) work to
underscore pseudo-educational approaches that avoid building
leadership in communities of color while continuing to label
them
as deficient. This negligence results from the impact of racism
shap-
ing the worldview of the savior. Acceptance of Payne’s
approach
depends upon internalized racism influencing the perspective of
the ‘‘saved.’’ In contrast, I examine the virtues of white allies
and
how they can help promote leadership among people of color by
challenging the privileges that provide them with superior
social
status and legitimacy. The article concludes with a discussion of
how racial justice can occur with the oppressed in leadership
posi-
tions and the oppressor adhering to and following this
leadership.
The existence of white saviors may help some people of color
but it
will not result in long-term systematic change. White allies can
contribute to systematic change by abdicating both privileges
and
superior status while cultivating leadership within communities
of color and relations of mutuality and respect.
Blindsided by the Avatar 245
WHITE SAVIORS IN HOLLYWOOD
The Hollywood industry is a proponent of what Giroux and
Giroux
(2004) call ‘‘corporate culture’’ that shapes active
‘‘[c]itizenship’’
into a ‘‘solitary affair whose aim is to produce competitive,
self-interested individuals vying for their own material and
ideological gains’’ (252). The needs and interests of the
individual,
particularly the white male who possesses market power (social
and cultural capital), supersedes the importance of people of
color
struggling to gain collective rights. The neoliberal logic driving
corporate culture demands that the market regulates all social
and economic practices, and the overarching principle
regulating
markets is competition (Lazzarato 2009, 117). Corporate culture
facilitates a social climate of competition by feeding and
managing
inequalities so that individuals with power and status can
dominate
and succeed over marginalized others.
In the competitive market, neoliberalism applies racial distinc-
tions in the process of managing inequalities to ensure the
dominant
racial group maintains advantages and privileges in the practice
of
individualism. Goldberg (2009) asserts that neoliberalism shifts
the
focus of the state from public welfare to private concerns and
‘‘thus also ensures a space for extending socio-racial
interventions—
demographic exclusions, belittlements, forms of control,
ongoing
humiliations . . .’’ (334). This shift involves moving racial
practices
from the public to the private realm, thereby engendering a
privati-
zation of racism by securing racial exclusions, preferences, and
privileges within the private world away from government inter-
vention (Goldberg 2009, 339). Privatized racism is what
Goldberg
would refer to as ‘‘racial neoliberalism.’’ With the continued
prevalence of racial practices promoting injustices, the
neoliberal
inclination toward individualism will proffer advantages to the
dominant racial group in market-driven structures, such as
capital-
ism, private schools, and insurance managed health care.
Hollywood films tend to gravitate toward the theme of the indi-
vidual savior whose actions of saving others from themselves as
opposed to addressing oppressive structures elide the possibility
of recognizing social injustices and the need for collective
action
to secure rights and opportunities. The neoliberal logic of
corporate
culture highlights the savior as a model that narrows human
agency to only the pursuit of individual success and gains.
‘‘Responsibility,’’ according to Susan Searls Giroux (2010),
under
246 J. Cammarota
⼆
在竞争性市场中,新⾃
由主义在管理不平等现
象的过程中采⽤了种族
差异,以确保占主导地
位的种族团体在个⼈主
义实践中保持优势和特
the neoliberal regime initiated in the Reagan era ‘‘was divested
of
its social character; indeed . . . there was ‘no such thing as
society’’’
(3). Thus, lost in neoliberalism is the recognition that
subordination
is not a failure of individual initiative but the result of a whole
host
of oppressive conditions including inadequate education,
limited
employment opportunities, unfair wages, and unjust
discriminatory
treatment.
In the Hollywood ‘‘savior’’ film Avatar, the main protagonist
and
individual savior, in this case, is a white male marine, named
Jake
Sully whom the military plants to gain access and information
from
the indigenous people, the Navi of the moon Pandora. The
narra-
tive parallels the film Dances With Wolves in which Kevin
Costner
plays an Army captain who is sent to an outpost to protect white
settlers from the Sioux Indians. Similar to Costner’s character,
Jake
Sully becomes enamored with the native people, even falling in
love with the female Navi character Neytiri. Jake then decides
to
lead a resistance that saves Pandora from the colonizers. Avatar
parallels Dances With Wolves so much so that one might
consider
the screenplay a twenty-first century version.
New York Times editorialist, David Brooks (2010) writes that
Avatar follows the
oft-repeated story about a manly young adventurer who goes
into the wil-
derness in search of thrills and profit. But once there, he meets
the native
people and finds that they are noble and spiritual and pure. And
so he
emerges as their Messiah, leading them on a righteous crusade
against
his own rotten civilization. (27)
This narrative, what Brooks calls the ‘‘White Messiah Fable’’ is
prevalent in several Hollywood productions, including A Man
Called Horse, The Last Samurai, and most notably,Dances With
Wolves.
We have seen this trope or fable many times before such that a
film-
maker ‘‘doesn’t have to waste time explaining the plot because
everybody knows roughly what’s going to happen’’ (Brooks
2010,
27). The dominant theme in these films centers on colonized
people
who ‘‘possess not the . . .physical or intellectual capacity to
compete
with their European counterparts and thus have not the ability to
adequately govern themselves, much less in times of adversity
ergo
the need for a White savior’’ (Meade 2010, 209).
The natives appear the same way to the white savior in these
films: always beautiful, spiritual, and reverent to God and earth.
These qualities render the natives appealing to both audiences
Blindsided by the Avatar 247
and white saviors. However, as Brooks (2010) correctly points
out,
‘‘they are natural creatures, not history making ones’’ (27).
Their
agency is understated to a point in which the natives resemble
elegant, graceful animals more than competent human agents.
The lack of human agency among people of color is perhaps the
most offensive aspect of the white savior productions. The
oppressed have no other choice but to follow the leadership of
oppressors who generally choose to oppress but occasionally
choose to play the role of savior. These productions undermine
the value of indigenous ideas for shaping the destiny of native
people. Moreover, most native people would have been fine and
not in need of rescuing were it not for the exploitation of the
saviors’ people in the first place.
In the social science class, Juan Gomez talked about the white
savior syndrome in Avatar and The Blind Side. He pointed out
that
the films focus on the white savior’s deeds to the exclusion of
the
real conditions of oppression that put the ‘‘saved’’ in the
predica-
ment of needing to be ‘‘saved.’’ Avatar does, however, present
a
narrative of colonization, which students in southern Arizona
understand intuitively from a similar colonial process afflicting
the U.S.–Mexico border. However, Avatar fails to address the
historical context of what Mendelsohn (2010) describes as ‘‘the
scary and often violent confrontation between human and alien
civilizations’’ (1). This failure leaves students with a lack of
under-
standing of how conflicts occur between civilizations (alien or
human) or cultures along borders.
In The Blind Side, the discussion of social and economic forces
(i.e., racism, lack of affordable housing, unemployment, inferior
education) impacting black communities is largely absent. The
history of oppression and negative social and economic forces
are
missing in these films, yet their absence nonetheless allowed
Juan
Gomez and me ‘‘teachable’’ moments by filling in the historical
silences.
RESISTANCE OUT OF HOLLYWOOD
History directly contradicts these films by exposing their
untruths.
Rather than awaiting white saviors, people of color do act in
accordance with their own interests and in the interest of a more
just society. Resistance leaders are often people of color
struggling
248 J. Cammarota
against white colonization, who end up either in prison,
murdered
or both. For instance, Puerto Ricans have struggled for
liberation
longer than the U.S. occupation, which began in 1898. Pedro
Albizu
Campos and Lolita Lebron are two of the most prominent Puerto
Rican resistance leaders in the twentieth century. Campos was
the leader of the Puerto Rican nationalist independence party
from
1930 until his death in 1956. Because of Campos’ political
actions for
independence, the U.S. government arrested and then
condemned
him to more than 10 years in prison. He eventually died from
radiation torture imposed while under arrest. Two years after
the
U.S. Congress voted to make Puerto Rico a permanent colony in
1952, Lolita Lebron entered the House of Representatives to
shoot
at her colonizers. Five representatives were injured in the
shooting.
She was also arrested, sentenced to 70 years in prison but
served a
‘‘modest’’ 25 years for her actions.
There have been other resisters like Campos and Lebron. Assata
Shakur was falsely arrested for her involvement in the Black
Panther
party. After spending time in jail she escaped and fled to Cuba.
She
has been living there ever since her escape. Another Black
Panther,
Fred Hampton was shot and killed in Chicago by FBI agents,
and the
famed Soledad Brother, writer, and activist George Jackson,
was
also shot by a prison guard during an attempted escape. A young
Angela Davis would also find herself the subject of repeated
harass-
ment by then Governor Ronald Reagan, placed on the FBI’s Ten
Most Wanted list and incarcerated, even facing the death
penalty,
on absurdly trumped up charges. Leonard Peltier was jailed for
his involvement in the American Indian Movement, and Mumia
Abu Jamal is also suffering a similar fate on death row for his
connection to the black liberation organization MOVE.
There have not been any Hollywood films made about these
resistance leaders. A film about a person of color standing up to
white colonization would anger, intimidate, alarm, and thus
ultimately fail with white audiences. Currently whites are still a
majority in the United States and perhaps the most important
racial
group among movie-going consumers. However, the white
savior
syndrome in films like Dances With Wolves or even Avatar do
more
damage than good to the historical record. These films suggest
that
social change occurs through white leadership and that people
of
color in change processes occupy primarily the role of the
victim
as opposed to the victor. Perhaps the worst misrepresentation is
Allan Parker’s Mississippi Burning, which depicts the FBI as
key
Blindsided by the Avatar 249
电影表明,社会变⾰是
通过⽩⼈领导⽽发⽣
的,在变⾰过程中,有
⾊⼈种主要扮演受害者
⽽不是胜利者的⻆⾊
activists in the civil rights movement. This, in contrast to their
actual roles as agents of repression under J. Edgar Hoover and
his covert program of ‘‘dirty tricks,’’ COINTELPRO.
Overshadowed
in this film is the critical role of people of color organizations
such
as the Student Non-Violent Coordinating Committee and
Southern
Christian Leadership Council. Young people of color who
consti-
tute an important segment of moviegoers will have little to draw
from models of leadership and positive, empowered roles to
adopt
in social change movements if movies continue to misrepresent
the
role of people of color in history.
Apathy among people of color is a real concern because they are
consistently bombarded with images of inferiority and
victimiza-
tion. Hollywood films sustain these messages via constant
repetition
and obfuscate the historical record. In the social studies class,
Juan
Gomez queried the students about their knowledge of film stars
versus real educators. They were more familiar with Michelle
Pfeiffer in Dangerous Minds than with Bob Moses of the
Algebra
project. When a picture of Jeffery Canada was shown to the
students, he was not recognized. However, students recognized
the white savior played by Hilary Swank in the film
FreedomWriters.
WHITE ALLIES IN HOLLYWOOD
Occasionally Hollywood has made films about white allies in
which
the white leader stands in solidarity with the leadership and
actions
of people of color. Perhaps the best white ally example appears
in
the film, Glory, based on the true Civil War events of an all-
black
troop of the 54th Regiment led by the white Colonel Robert
Gould
Shaw, played by Matthew Broderick. Although the film does not
accurately or fairly represent the African American perspective,
it
does shift the standard white leadership role from messiah to
martyr (Stoddard and Marcus 2006). Colonel Shaw accepted the
leadership assignment knowing that racism would prevent the
troop from ever seeing battle. However, at the end of the movie,
the Union forces needed to take a Rebel bunker to win a battle
and the only troop available to fight was the 54th. The troop
elected
to fight knowing that the straight on attack of the bunker would
lead to their deaths. The soldiers’ white ally, Colonel Shaw
stood
and fought shoulder to shoulder with them. Shaw and the
soldiers
were eventually killed but their defeat led to the enlistment of
250 J. Cammarota
150,000 African Americans, which Lincoln assessed as the
turning
point of the Civil War.
In this example, the white ally Colonel Shaw assisted the
African
American soldiers with becoming agents of history by preparing
and
then fighting alongside them in battle. Matthew Broderick’s
charac-
ter sacrificed his status and power to stand with the soldiers and
face
death together while struggling against the forces of oppression.
Although fighting alongside the African American soldiers was
a
suicide mission, a white ally does not have to give up his or her
life to
achieve solidarity. Alliance requires at minimum a symbolic
death,
more in the line with Amilcar Cabral’s ‘‘class suicide’’ in
which one
relinquishes social status to work collaboratively with the
oppressed.
Cabral asserts that allies with privilege and power who join
move-
ments of change should commit ‘‘suicide as a class in order to
be
reborn as revolutionary workers, completely identified with the
deepest aspirations of the people to which they belong’’ (quoted
in
Rudebeck 2006, 94). Hierarchical positioning becomes inactive
betweenwhite allies and people of color so that ideas
andmovements
emerge unilaterally with those united democratically on the
ground.
In order for Colonel Shaw to become an ally he had to dismount
from his high horse, abdicating his status and power as an
officer in
this final moment and place his feet on the ground next to the
foot
soldiers. When the time to act and make history comes, the
white
ally must sacrifice his power so that the agency of the oppressed
becomes central.
THE WHITE SAVIOR OF EDUCATION
Popular film culture not only undermines young people of
color’s
potential to become change agents but also reinforces and at
times
shapes the social policies that bear the greatest impact on their
lives.
For instance, Ruby Payne is perhaps the most influential
individual
with shaping teacher practices for poor students in this country.
Although she focuses primarily on class and poverty, most
exam-
ples in her writings involve the work of students of color
(Stinnent
2008). Nevertheless, many school districts that serve students of
color have adopted her ‘‘framework’’ for professional
development
and teacher training (Sato and Lensmire 2009).
Payne’s ideas are not much different than those espoused by the
white saviors in Dangerous Minds, Freedom Writers, and The
Blind
Blindsided by the Avatar 251
Side. She perceives poor students of color existing in deficit
such
that they supposedly do not possess any knowledge or
intellectual
capacity beyond what they absorb from their more educated and
economically stable teachers. The following represents how
Payne
(2005) characterizes poor students’ behavior in the classroom:
She believes that they ‘‘laugh when disciplined, argue loudly,
make
angry responses, make inappropriate or vulgar comments, have
hands on someone else, fail to follow directions, learn to be
disor-
ganized, unable to finish tasks, become disrespectful to
teachers,
harm others, cheat or steal, and talk incessantly’’ (79–80).
Missing
here is any sense of how students resist forms of teacher
authority
that relentlessly define students according to their alleged
lacks—
often as a matter of maintaining dignity.
The ‘‘important’’ knowledge that poor people may procure
reportedly derives from institutional or ‘‘official’’ instruction
and
not from any indigenous or local practices generated by their
own initiatives. What she does report as indigenous knowledge
is quite insulting. For instance, she claims, without supporting
research, that poor people relative to middle-class folks know
more
about how to ‘‘buy guns, bail someone out of jail, function in
laundromats, acquire food from grocery bins, and use duct
tape’’
(Payne 2005, 53–58).
Furthermore, Payne perceives poor students of color as lacking
middle-class cultural capital, values, and behavior. The
teacher’s
job is to ensure that poor students learn middle-class culture
and
values, ‘‘and this very need characterizes them as deficient’’
(Stinnent 2009, 65). Once they assimilate to the middle-class
value
system, they supposedly become better off. This approach
allows
the educator to adopt a savior perspective and mistakenly see
his
or her role as saving the poor student by extirpating him or her
from a culture of pathology and then remaking him or her into
the image of the educator=savior (Sato and Lensmire 2009,
368).
‘‘Saving,’’ according to Michie (2007), ‘‘is not how real
teaching
works. Teaching . . . can only happen over time as trusting and
mutually respectful relationships are built’’ (8). The savior
perspec-
tive in Payne’s method translates into a messiah complex,
elevating
educators to an artificially high level of self-importance and
value
for ‘‘feeding’’ their supposedly bereft students. This higher
status
buttressed by racism, classism, and general elitism allows white
and wealthier people to feel superior over the supposedly down-
trodden others. It would be hard for teachers to build trust with
252 J. Cammarota
students who they believe to be from a much lower social
position
and perspective than them.
Educational assimilation posits that people of low
socioeconomic
status lack the appropriate values to achieve success, and any
lack
of success or low status is the result of their personal
deficiencies.
This is an example of the way that the privatized racism of the
neo-
liberal order works. Inequalities are reduced to private character
flaws (e.g., laziness, predilection for drugs, sex, etc.) rather
than
understood as (historically and currently) institutionally shaped
and maintained. The deficiencies, according to Payne, are
dimin-
ished resources, but her definition of ‘‘resources’’ surpasses
money.
She includes ‘‘emotional, spiritual, physical, relational, and
social
resources’’ (Payne 2005, 16). However, repeated ethnographic
stu-
dies demonstrate the real resourcefulness and resilience of poor
people (Edin and Lein 1997; Gregory 1998; Cammarota 2008).
This
research demonstrates that poverty presents political and
economic
restraints that may impose effects on human development yet
sep-
arate from cognitive and cultural realms. Some, in fact, argue
that
poor people cultivate valuable ‘‘funds of knowledge’’ or
‘‘cultural
wealth’’ out of the necessity to negotiate and survive the harsh
cir-
cumstances of poverty (Velez-Ibanez and Greenberg 1992;
Yosso
2005). The incorrect assumption that poor people lack
resourceful-
ness exonerates social or economic structures from any
culpability
in reproducing poverty and oppression generation after
generation.
Approaching poverty or any form of oppression as an individual
behavioral problem evades the entire point about economic
marginal-
ity and low status. Society influences the social position one
inhabits;
the individual may have some say about his or her social status,
but
for the most part society plays a huge role with shaping status
distinc-
tions. Inmany societies, includingAmerica, social and economic
prac-
tices tend to organize individuals into gradients so that some
people
access greater power andwealth than others. This happens
systemati-
cally, and schools are part and parcel of this system of unequal
distri-
bution of wealth and power. Teaching down to poor students, as
if
they are unintelligent and culturally deficient, when coupled
with
the real material hardships they face, will only reproduce
poverty.
THE WHITE ALLY IN EDUCATION
White allies adopt a significantly different position from white
saviors. They realize they have privileges and work to
undermine
Blindsided by the Avatar 253
the very power that provides them with superiority. Beverly
Tatum
(1997) asserts that a white ally’s role should not be about
‘‘helping’’
people of color but rather about speaking ‘‘up against systems
of
oppression and to challenge other Whites to do the same’’
(109).
Allies tend to redirect resources toward addressing racism,
resources that would otherwise only be given to a chosen
few.White
allies, therefore, look to end oppression by challenging the
neolib-
eral logic of competitive individualism and privatization, then
look-
ing for fair and equal treatment for all—even at the expense of
diminishing their status to share power with the oppressed.
However, teacher educator Christine Sleeter (1993, 173) warns
that many white teachers fail to accept and thus deal with the
‘‘paradox’’ of supporting students of color by challenging the
racial
neoliberalism that grants superior market status to whiteness.
Rather, she notices patterned responses of avoidance that
includes
‘‘colorblindness’’ or presenting the model of European
immigrants
as a way to demonstrate positive shifts in race relations.
Bonilla-
Silva (2002) asserts that whites may use rhetorical strategies to
maintain color-blind racism. These strategies include the
avoidance
of racial terminology altogether, the use of semantic moves
such as
saying that they have ‘‘friends who are black’’ to deny
accusations
of racism, and the projection of racism onto the marginalized
racial
other by saying that ‘‘they are the racist ones, not me.’’
Addition-
ally, there is the ‘‘Obama effect’’ in which people falsely
assume
a black president means a postracial America.
Sleeter (1993, 174) recommends white teachers become allies
by a
process of reeducation that helps them analyze white privilege
and
the ways neoliberalism perpetuates racism through competitive
individualism and de-regulated, market-based forms of
resegrega-
tion. This education begins with an immersion into a community
of
color in which the ally focuses his or her learning on the history
of
racism and those structures such as inferior education,
depressed
wages, and inadequate housing that maintain others’ subordinate
statuses. Through this process, ‘‘teachers . . . are not just
learning
about other races but becoming committed to anti-racism as part
of their own self-hood’’ (Thompson 2003, 14). The immersion
can
be integrated into field research experience in a teacher
education
program (Sleeter 2001). The outcome, according to Sleeter,
from this
deep immersion should be willingness to work collectively with
people of color to end structural or institutional racism. This
means
that allies work in collaboration, not as leaders, not as saviors,
but
254 J. Cammarota
as engaged participants who share power in a democratic
process.
Esteva, Prakash, and Stuchul (2008) write
[in]stead of pro-motion (which operates under the assumption
that the
people are paralyzed or are moving in the wrong direction),
those taking
initiatives at the grassroots to govern them autonomously or
democrati-
cally speak of co-motion—moving with the people, rather than
moving
the people. (99)
White allies, therefore, should ‘‘follow people of color as they
provide the leadership in the struggle for racial justice’’
(Gardiner
2009, 1). Following requires accepting and validating the
oppressive
experiences of people of color and acknowledging their
critiques of
the power of whiteness (Gardiner 2009, 1). ‘‘The White
person,’’
according to Tatum (1997, 113), ‘‘who has worked through his
or
her own racial identity process has a deep understanding of
racism
and an appreciation and respect for the identity struggles of
people
of color.’’ White allies must engage leaders of communities of
color
in a dialogue based on this appreciation and respect,
particularly as
it pertains to the years of suffering caused by racism. This type
of
open and honest dialogue might be painful, and even the most
well-intentioned ally might feel the need to retreat (Dickar
2008,
130). However, allies must become compassionate listeners and
remain engaged in dialogue no matter how painful it becomes.
FREEDOM FROM PRIVILEGE
In this article’s epigraph, James Baldwin speaks of the need to
abandon privilege. He refers to not only the privileges of racial
superiority, but also that of pure ignorance. Somehow the
vague-
ness of insularity must cease so that hearts and minds open to
the realities of human suffering. Our greatest and most
nefarious
privilege in America is the blatant willingness to turn a blind
eye
to our deepest social problems. Everyday, many live without
shelter; brown and black men fill prison cells; workers lose
their
jobs; women experience violent abuse; gays and lesbians face
unbearable threats; and migrants risk their lives for their
survival.
National dialogue about these daily tragedies is delimited to
victi-
mization at best. But this discursive turn proves a double-edged
sword: victims are either to be pitied or scorned. More often
than
not, the problem supposedly lies with the victims’ choices and
Blindsided by the Avatar 255
not with neoliberal policies that generate unfair wages, subpar
education, and ineffective and rapidly disappearing social
support.
Those who benefit from the managed inequalities of racial
neoliber-
alism have the responsibility of correcting the disparities that
result
from it.
Ignoring the social and economic inequalities of ongoing
market-based residential segregation, labor exploitation, health
disparities, racial profiling, and racially tracked schooling that
influence the daily experiences of most people of color is the
most
guarded privilege in America. When we finally become ‘‘free’’
of
this privilege, we will truly begin to address the entire range of
human suffering. It is within this ‘‘freedom’’ that Baldwin
asserts
we will experience higher privileges—the rewards of ‘‘justice,’’
‘‘peace,’’ and true ‘‘compassion,’’ inclusive of those under the
weight of oppression. Removing the privilege of ignorance will
cure our blindness and allow us to truly ‘‘read the world.’’
The false generosity of the contemporary white savior binds to
the privilege of ignorance by failing to see how the maintenance
of his or her higher status in relation to the oppressed
perpetuates
inequalities. Limiting people’s access to opportunities and
resources
also provides the context in which higher status individuals
benefit
from the hierarchical system they maintain. The savior requires
exploiting his or her status to procure leadership positions and
thus
denying people of color the process of developing the agency
required for long-term systematic change. Real change within
struc-
tural racism requires the leadership of people of color, because
it
involves the sharing of power to the point in which an
affirmative
democratic character will emerge in society. Sharing power for
those
members of dominant groups necessitates the abdication of
status to
clear space for the leadership of people of color. Once there are
more
progressive people of color in leadership positions, then the
Revision of Comparison of Theories” At the doctoral level, wr.docx
Revision of Comparison of Theories” At the doctoral level, wr.docx
Revision of Comparison of Theories” At the doctoral level, wr.docx
Revision of Comparison of Theories” At the doctoral level, wr.docx
Revision of Comparison of Theories” At the doctoral level, wr.docx
Revision of Comparison of Theories” At the doctoral level, wr.docx
Revision of Comparison of Theories” At the doctoral level, wr.docx
Revision of Comparison of Theories” At the doctoral level, wr.docx
Revision of Comparison of Theories” At the doctoral level, wr.docx
Revision of Comparison of Theories” At the doctoral level, wr.docx
Revision of Comparison of Theories” At the doctoral level, wr.docx
Revision of Comparison of Theories” At the doctoral level, wr.docx
Revision of Comparison of Theories” At the doctoral level, wr.docx
Revision of Comparison of Theories” At the doctoral level, wr.docx
Revision of Comparison of Theories” At the doctoral level, wr.docx

More Related Content

Similar to Revision of Comparison of Theories” At the doctoral level, wr.docx

Nathalie English Research.docxFZXCXCXZCZXXZC
Nathalie English Research.docxFZXCXCXZCZXXZCNathalie English Research.docxFZXCXCXZCZXXZC
Nathalie English Research.docxFZXCXCXZCZXXZCLyndon32
 
What is the value of studying humanities in a business or technical .pdf
What is the value of studying humanities in a business or technical .pdfWhat is the value of studying humanities in a business or technical .pdf
What is the value of studying humanities in a business or technical .pdfinfo785431
 
Essentialism and perennialism
Essentialism and perennialismEssentialism and perennialism
Essentialism and perennialismArneyo
 
Persuasive Essay Against School Uniforms.pdf
Persuasive Essay Against School Uniforms.pdfPersuasive Essay Against School Uniforms.pdf
Persuasive Essay Against School Uniforms.pdfChristine Love
 
Interdisciplinary study disciples of disciplinesUpdated Tuesda.docx
Interdisciplinary study disciples of disciplinesUpdated Tuesda.docxInterdisciplinary study disciples of disciplinesUpdated Tuesda.docx
Interdisciplinary study disciples of disciplinesUpdated Tuesda.docxvrickens
 
Modernism In Literature Essay
Modernism In Literature EssayModernism In Literature Essay
Modernism In Literature EssayStacey Smith
 
A Reflection On The Research Method And Exemplary
A Reflection On The Research Method And ExemplaryA Reflection On The Research Method And Exemplary
A Reflection On The Research Method And ExemplaryKathryn Patel
 
How to write an abstract
How to write an abstractHow to write an abstract
How to write an abstractsaleh Rehman
 
Sujay Academic freedom versus social responsibility for researchers FINAL FIN...
Sujay Academic freedom versus social responsibility for researchers FINAL FIN...Sujay Academic freedom versus social responsibility for researchers FINAL FIN...
Sujay Academic freedom versus social responsibility for researchers FINAL FIN...Sujay Rao Mandavilli
 
Sujay Academic freedom versus social responsibility for researchers FINAL FIN...
Sujay Academic freedom versus social responsibility for researchers FINAL FIN...Sujay Academic freedom versus social responsibility for researchers FINAL FIN...
Sujay Academic freedom versus social responsibility for researchers FINAL FIN...Sujay Rao Mandavilli
 
Rhetorical Précis Method of SummaryHow to write a rhetorical pré.docx
Rhetorical Précis Method of SummaryHow to write a rhetorical pré.docxRhetorical Précis Method of SummaryHow to write a rhetorical pré.docx
Rhetorical Précis Method of SummaryHow to write a rhetorical pré.docxjoellemurphey
 
Professionalism Essays.pdf
Professionalism Essays.pdfProfessionalism Essays.pdf
Professionalism Essays.pdfAdriana Lovato
 

Similar to Revision of Comparison of Theories” At the doctoral level, wr.docx (20)

Nathalie English Research.docxFZXCXCXZCZXXZC
Nathalie English Research.docxFZXCXCXZCZXXZCNathalie English Research.docxFZXCXCXZCZXXZC
Nathalie English Research.docxFZXCXCXZCZXXZC
 
Abstract Essay Example
Abstract Essay ExampleAbstract Essay Example
Abstract Essay Example
 
Abstract Essay Example
Abstract Essay ExampleAbstract Essay Example
Abstract Essay Example
 
What is the value of studying humanities in a business or technical .pdf
What is the value of studying humanities in a business or technical .pdfWhat is the value of studying humanities in a business or technical .pdf
What is the value of studying humanities in a business or technical .pdf
 
Sociology Essay Topic
Sociology Essay TopicSociology Essay Topic
Sociology Essay Topic
 
Essentialism and perennialism
Essentialism and perennialismEssentialism and perennialism
Essentialism and perennialism
 
Persuasive Essay Against School Uniforms.pdf
Persuasive Essay Against School Uniforms.pdfPersuasive Essay Against School Uniforms.pdf
Persuasive Essay Against School Uniforms.pdf
 
Interdisciplinary study disciples of disciplinesUpdated Tuesda.docx
Interdisciplinary study disciples of disciplinesUpdated Tuesda.docxInterdisciplinary study disciples of disciplinesUpdated Tuesda.docx
Interdisciplinary study disciples of disciplinesUpdated Tuesda.docx
 
Cda by terry_locke
Cda by terry_lockeCda by terry_locke
Cda by terry_locke
 
Modernism In Literature Essay
Modernism In Literature EssayModernism In Literature Essay
Modernism In Literature Essay
 
A Reflection On The Research Method And Exemplary
A Reflection On The Research Method And ExemplaryA Reflection On The Research Method And Exemplary
A Reflection On The Research Method And Exemplary
 
How to write an abstract
How to write an abstractHow to write an abstract
How to write an abstract
 
How to write an abstract
How to write an abstractHow to write an abstract
How to write an abstract
 
Academic Research Essay
Academic Research EssayAcademic Research Essay
Academic Research Essay
 
Sujay Academic freedom versus social responsibility for researchers FINAL FIN...
Sujay Academic freedom versus social responsibility for researchers FINAL FIN...Sujay Academic freedom versus social responsibility for researchers FINAL FIN...
Sujay Academic freedom versus social responsibility for researchers FINAL FIN...
 
Sujay Academic freedom versus social responsibility for researchers FINAL FIN...
Sujay Academic freedom versus social responsibility for researchers FINAL FIN...Sujay Academic freedom versus social responsibility for researchers FINAL FIN...
Sujay Academic freedom versus social responsibility for researchers FINAL FIN...
 
Positivism Vs Interpretivism Essay
Positivism Vs Interpretivism EssayPositivism Vs Interpretivism Essay
Positivism Vs Interpretivism Essay
 
Rhetorical Précis Method of SummaryHow to write a rhetorical pré.docx
Rhetorical Précis Method of SummaryHow to write a rhetorical pré.docxRhetorical Précis Method of SummaryHow to write a rhetorical pré.docx
Rhetorical Précis Method of SummaryHow to write a rhetorical pré.docx
 
Professionalism Essays.pdf
Professionalism Essays.pdfProfessionalism Essays.pdf
Professionalism Essays.pdf
 
Translation Essay
Translation EssayTranslation Essay
Translation Essay
 

More from healdkathaleen

Mill proposes his Art of Life, but he also insists that it is not ve.docx
Mill proposes his Art of Life, but he also insists that it is not ve.docxMill proposes his Art of Life, but he also insists that it is not ve.docx
Mill proposes his Art of Life, but he also insists that it is not ve.docxhealdkathaleen
 
Milford Bank and Trust Company is revamping its credit management de.docx
Milford Bank and Trust Company is revamping its credit management de.docxMilford Bank and Trust Company is revamping its credit management de.docx
Milford Bank and Trust Company is revamping its credit management de.docxhealdkathaleen
 
milies (most with teenage children) and the Baby Boomers (teens and .docx
milies (most with teenage children) and the Baby Boomers (teens and .docxmilies (most with teenage children) and the Baby Boomers (teens and .docx
milies (most with teenage children) and the Baby Boomers (teens and .docxhealdkathaleen
 
Midterm Paper - Recombinant DNA TechnologySome scientists are conc.docx
Midterm Paper - Recombinant DNA TechnologySome scientists are conc.docxMidterm Paper - Recombinant DNA TechnologySome scientists are conc.docx
Midterm Paper - Recombinant DNA TechnologySome scientists are conc.docxhealdkathaleen
 
Midterm Study GuideAnswers need to be based on the files i will em.docx
Midterm Study GuideAnswers need to be based on the files i will em.docxMidterm Study GuideAnswers need to be based on the files i will em.docx
Midterm Study GuideAnswers need to be based on the files i will em.docxhealdkathaleen
 
Michelle Carroll is a coworker of yours and she overheard a conversa.docx
Michelle Carroll is a coworker of yours and she overheard a conversa.docxMichelle Carroll is a coworker of yours and she overheard a conversa.docx
Michelle Carroll is a coworker of yours and she overheard a conversa.docxhealdkathaleen
 
Michelle is attending college and has a part-time job. Once she fini.docx
Michelle is attending college and has a part-time job. Once she fini.docxMichelle is attending college and has a part-time job. Once she fini.docx
Michelle is attending college and has a part-time job. Once she fini.docxhealdkathaleen
 
Midterm Assignment Instructions (due 31 August)The mid-term essay .docx
Midterm Assignment Instructions (due 31 August)The mid-term essay .docxMidterm Assignment Instructions (due 31 August)The mid-term essay .docx
Midterm Assignment Instructions (due 31 August)The mid-term essay .docxhealdkathaleen
 
Milestone 2Outline of Final PaperYou will create a robust.docx
Milestone 2Outline of Final PaperYou will create a robust.docxMilestone 2Outline of Final PaperYou will create a robust.docx
Milestone 2Outline of Final PaperYou will create a robust.docxhealdkathaleen
 
MigrationThe human population has lived a rural lifestyle thro.docx
MigrationThe human population has lived a rural lifestyle thro.docxMigrationThe human population has lived a rural lifestyle thro.docx
MigrationThe human population has lived a rural lifestyle thro.docxhealdkathaleen
 
Mid-TermDismiss Mid-Term1) As you consider the challenges fa.docx
Mid-TermDismiss Mid-Term1) As you consider the challenges fa.docxMid-TermDismiss Mid-Term1) As you consider the challenges fa.docx
Mid-TermDismiss Mid-Term1) As you consider the challenges fa.docxhealdkathaleen
 
MicroeconomicsUse what you have learned about economic indicators .docx
MicroeconomicsUse what you have learned about economic indicators .docxMicroeconomicsUse what you have learned about economic indicators .docx
MicroeconomicsUse what you have learned about economic indicators .docxhealdkathaleen
 
Michael Dell began building and selling computers from his dorm room.docx
Michael Dell began building and selling computers from his dorm room.docxMichael Dell began building and selling computers from his dorm room.docx
Michael Dell began building and selling computers from his dorm room.docxhealdkathaleen
 
Michael is a three-year-old boy with severe seizure activity. He h.docx
Michael is a three-year-old boy with severe seizure activity. He h.docxMichael is a three-year-old boy with severe seizure activity. He h.docx
Michael is a three-year-old boy with severe seizure activity. He h.docxhealdkathaleen
 
Michael graduates from New York University and on February 1st of th.docx
Michael graduates from New York University and on February 1st of th.docxMichael graduates from New York University and on February 1st of th.docx
Michael graduates from New York University and on February 1st of th.docxhealdkathaleen
 
Message Using Multisim 11, please help me build a home security sys.docx
Message Using Multisim 11, please help me build a home security sys.docxMessage Using Multisim 11, please help me build a home security sys.docx
Message Using Multisim 11, please help me build a home security sys.docxhealdkathaleen
 
Methodology of H&M internationalization Research purposeRe.docx
Methodology of H&M internationalization Research purposeRe.docxMethodology of H&M internationalization Research purposeRe.docx
Methodology of H&M internationalization Research purposeRe.docxhealdkathaleen
 
Mental Disability DiscussionConsider the typification of these c.docx
Mental Disability DiscussionConsider the typification of these c.docxMental Disability DiscussionConsider the typification of these c.docx
Mental Disability DiscussionConsider the typification of these c.docxhealdkathaleen
 
Meningitis Analyze the assigned neurological disorder and prepar.docx
Meningitis Analyze the assigned neurological disorder and prepar.docxMeningitis Analyze the assigned neurological disorder and prepar.docx
Meningitis Analyze the assigned neurological disorder and prepar.docxhealdkathaleen
 
Memoir Format(chart this)Introduction (that captures the r.docx
Memoir Format(chart this)Introduction (that captures the r.docxMemoir Format(chart this)Introduction (that captures the r.docx
Memoir Format(chart this)Introduction (that captures the r.docxhealdkathaleen
 

More from healdkathaleen (20)

Mill proposes his Art of Life, but he also insists that it is not ve.docx
Mill proposes his Art of Life, but he also insists that it is not ve.docxMill proposes his Art of Life, but he also insists that it is not ve.docx
Mill proposes his Art of Life, but he also insists that it is not ve.docx
 
Milford Bank and Trust Company is revamping its credit management de.docx
Milford Bank and Trust Company is revamping its credit management de.docxMilford Bank and Trust Company is revamping its credit management de.docx
Milford Bank and Trust Company is revamping its credit management de.docx
 
milies (most with teenage children) and the Baby Boomers (teens and .docx
milies (most with teenage children) and the Baby Boomers (teens and .docxmilies (most with teenage children) and the Baby Boomers (teens and .docx
milies (most with teenage children) and the Baby Boomers (teens and .docx
 
Midterm Paper - Recombinant DNA TechnologySome scientists are conc.docx
Midterm Paper - Recombinant DNA TechnologySome scientists are conc.docxMidterm Paper - Recombinant DNA TechnologySome scientists are conc.docx
Midterm Paper - Recombinant DNA TechnologySome scientists are conc.docx
 
Midterm Study GuideAnswers need to be based on the files i will em.docx
Midterm Study GuideAnswers need to be based on the files i will em.docxMidterm Study GuideAnswers need to be based on the files i will em.docx
Midterm Study GuideAnswers need to be based on the files i will em.docx
 
Michelle Carroll is a coworker of yours and she overheard a conversa.docx
Michelle Carroll is a coworker of yours and she overheard a conversa.docxMichelle Carroll is a coworker of yours and she overheard a conversa.docx
Michelle Carroll is a coworker of yours and she overheard a conversa.docx
 
Michelle is attending college and has a part-time job. Once she fini.docx
Michelle is attending college and has a part-time job. Once she fini.docxMichelle is attending college and has a part-time job. Once she fini.docx
Michelle is attending college and has a part-time job. Once she fini.docx
 
Midterm Assignment Instructions (due 31 August)The mid-term essay .docx
Midterm Assignment Instructions (due 31 August)The mid-term essay .docxMidterm Assignment Instructions (due 31 August)The mid-term essay .docx
Midterm Assignment Instructions (due 31 August)The mid-term essay .docx
 
Milestone 2Outline of Final PaperYou will create a robust.docx
Milestone 2Outline of Final PaperYou will create a robust.docxMilestone 2Outline of Final PaperYou will create a robust.docx
Milestone 2Outline of Final PaperYou will create a robust.docx
 
MigrationThe human population has lived a rural lifestyle thro.docx
MigrationThe human population has lived a rural lifestyle thro.docxMigrationThe human population has lived a rural lifestyle thro.docx
MigrationThe human population has lived a rural lifestyle thro.docx
 
Mid-TermDismiss Mid-Term1) As you consider the challenges fa.docx
Mid-TermDismiss Mid-Term1) As you consider the challenges fa.docxMid-TermDismiss Mid-Term1) As you consider the challenges fa.docx
Mid-TermDismiss Mid-Term1) As you consider the challenges fa.docx
 
MicroeconomicsUse what you have learned about economic indicators .docx
MicroeconomicsUse what you have learned about economic indicators .docxMicroeconomicsUse what you have learned about economic indicators .docx
MicroeconomicsUse what you have learned about economic indicators .docx
 
Michael Dell began building and selling computers from his dorm room.docx
Michael Dell began building and selling computers from his dorm room.docxMichael Dell began building and selling computers from his dorm room.docx
Michael Dell began building and selling computers from his dorm room.docx
 
Michael is a three-year-old boy with severe seizure activity. He h.docx
Michael is a three-year-old boy with severe seizure activity. He h.docxMichael is a three-year-old boy with severe seizure activity. He h.docx
Michael is a three-year-old boy with severe seizure activity. He h.docx
 
Michael graduates from New York University and on February 1st of th.docx
Michael graduates from New York University and on February 1st of th.docxMichael graduates from New York University and on February 1st of th.docx
Michael graduates from New York University and on February 1st of th.docx
 
Message Using Multisim 11, please help me build a home security sys.docx
Message Using Multisim 11, please help me build a home security sys.docxMessage Using Multisim 11, please help me build a home security sys.docx
Message Using Multisim 11, please help me build a home security sys.docx
 
Methodology of H&M internationalization Research purposeRe.docx
Methodology of H&M internationalization Research purposeRe.docxMethodology of H&M internationalization Research purposeRe.docx
Methodology of H&M internationalization Research purposeRe.docx
 
Mental Disability DiscussionConsider the typification of these c.docx
Mental Disability DiscussionConsider the typification of these c.docxMental Disability DiscussionConsider the typification of these c.docx
Mental Disability DiscussionConsider the typification of these c.docx
 
Meningitis Analyze the assigned neurological disorder and prepar.docx
Meningitis Analyze the assigned neurological disorder and prepar.docxMeningitis Analyze the assigned neurological disorder and prepar.docx
Meningitis Analyze the assigned neurological disorder and prepar.docx
 
Memoir Format(chart this)Introduction (that captures the r.docx
Memoir Format(chart this)Introduction (that captures the r.docxMemoir Format(chart this)Introduction (that captures the r.docx
Memoir Format(chart this)Introduction (that captures the r.docx
 

Recently uploaded

Introduction to AI in Higher Education_draft.pptx
Introduction to AI in Higher Education_draft.pptxIntroduction to AI in Higher Education_draft.pptx
Introduction to AI in Higher Education_draft.pptxpboyjonauth
 
DATA STRUCTURE AND ALGORITHM for beginners
DATA STRUCTURE AND ALGORITHM for beginnersDATA STRUCTURE AND ALGORITHM for beginners
DATA STRUCTURE AND ALGORITHM for beginnersSabitha Banu
 
POINT- BIOCHEMISTRY SEM 2 ENZYMES UNIT 5.pptx
POINT- BIOCHEMISTRY SEM 2 ENZYMES UNIT 5.pptxPOINT- BIOCHEMISTRY SEM 2 ENZYMES UNIT 5.pptx
POINT- BIOCHEMISTRY SEM 2 ENZYMES UNIT 5.pptxSayali Powar
 
Procuring digital preservation CAN be quick and painless with our new dynamic...
Procuring digital preservation CAN be quick and painless with our new dynamic...Procuring digital preservation CAN be quick and painless with our new dynamic...
Procuring digital preservation CAN be quick and painless with our new dynamic...Jisc
 
EPANDING THE CONTENT OF AN OUTLINE using notes.pptx
EPANDING THE CONTENT OF AN OUTLINE using notes.pptxEPANDING THE CONTENT OF AN OUTLINE using notes.pptx
EPANDING THE CONTENT OF AN OUTLINE using notes.pptxRaymartEstabillo3
 
Organic Name Reactions for the students and aspirants of Chemistry12th.pptx
Organic Name Reactions  for the students and aspirants of Chemistry12th.pptxOrganic Name Reactions  for the students and aspirants of Chemistry12th.pptx
Organic Name Reactions for the students and aspirants of Chemistry12th.pptxVS Mahajan Coaching Centre
 
What is Model Inheritance in Odoo 17 ERP
What is Model Inheritance in Odoo 17 ERPWhat is Model Inheritance in Odoo 17 ERP
What is Model Inheritance in Odoo 17 ERPCeline George
 
18-04-UA_REPORT_MEDIALITERAСY_INDEX-DM_23-1-final-eng.pdf
18-04-UA_REPORT_MEDIALITERAСY_INDEX-DM_23-1-final-eng.pdf18-04-UA_REPORT_MEDIALITERAСY_INDEX-DM_23-1-final-eng.pdf
18-04-UA_REPORT_MEDIALITERAСY_INDEX-DM_23-1-final-eng.pdfssuser54595a
 
Roles & Responsibilities in Pharmacovigilance
Roles & Responsibilities in PharmacovigilanceRoles & Responsibilities in Pharmacovigilance
Roles & Responsibilities in PharmacovigilanceSamikshaHamane
 
Full Stack Web Development Course for Beginners
Full Stack Web Development Course  for BeginnersFull Stack Web Development Course  for Beginners
Full Stack Web Development Course for BeginnersSabitha Banu
 
How to Make a Pirate ship Primary Education.pptx
How to Make a Pirate ship Primary Education.pptxHow to Make a Pirate ship Primary Education.pptx
How to Make a Pirate ship Primary Education.pptxmanuelaromero2013
 
Types of Journalistic Writing Grade 8.pptx
Types of Journalistic Writing Grade 8.pptxTypes of Journalistic Writing Grade 8.pptx
Types of Journalistic Writing Grade 8.pptxEyham Joco
 
ENGLISH 7_Q4_LESSON 2_ Employing a Variety of Strategies for Effective Interp...
ENGLISH 7_Q4_LESSON 2_ Employing a Variety of Strategies for Effective Interp...ENGLISH 7_Q4_LESSON 2_ Employing a Variety of Strategies for Effective Interp...
ENGLISH 7_Q4_LESSON 2_ Employing a Variety of Strategies for Effective Interp...JhezDiaz1
 
Enzyme, Pharmaceutical Aids, Miscellaneous Last Part of Chapter no 5th.pdf
Enzyme, Pharmaceutical Aids, Miscellaneous Last Part of Chapter no 5th.pdfEnzyme, Pharmaceutical Aids, Miscellaneous Last Part of Chapter no 5th.pdf
Enzyme, Pharmaceutical Aids, Miscellaneous Last Part of Chapter no 5th.pdfSumit Tiwari
 
Alper Gobel In Media Res Media Component
Alper Gobel In Media Res Media ComponentAlper Gobel In Media Res Media Component
Alper Gobel In Media Res Media ComponentInMediaRes1
 
Pharmacognosy Flower 3. Compositae 2023.pdf
Pharmacognosy Flower 3. Compositae 2023.pdfPharmacognosy Flower 3. Compositae 2023.pdf
Pharmacognosy Flower 3. Compositae 2023.pdfMahmoud M. Sallam
 

Recently uploaded (20)

Introduction to AI in Higher Education_draft.pptx
Introduction to AI in Higher Education_draft.pptxIntroduction to AI in Higher Education_draft.pptx
Introduction to AI in Higher Education_draft.pptx
 
DATA STRUCTURE AND ALGORITHM for beginners
DATA STRUCTURE AND ALGORITHM for beginnersDATA STRUCTURE AND ALGORITHM for beginners
DATA STRUCTURE AND ALGORITHM for beginners
 
POINT- BIOCHEMISTRY SEM 2 ENZYMES UNIT 5.pptx
POINT- BIOCHEMISTRY SEM 2 ENZYMES UNIT 5.pptxPOINT- BIOCHEMISTRY SEM 2 ENZYMES UNIT 5.pptx
POINT- BIOCHEMISTRY SEM 2 ENZYMES UNIT 5.pptx
 
Procuring digital preservation CAN be quick and painless with our new dynamic...
Procuring digital preservation CAN be quick and painless with our new dynamic...Procuring digital preservation CAN be quick and painless with our new dynamic...
Procuring digital preservation CAN be quick and painless with our new dynamic...
 
EPANDING THE CONTENT OF AN OUTLINE using notes.pptx
EPANDING THE CONTENT OF AN OUTLINE using notes.pptxEPANDING THE CONTENT OF AN OUTLINE using notes.pptx
EPANDING THE CONTENT OF AN OUTLINE using notes.pptx
 
Model Call Girl in Bikash Puri Delhi reach out to us at 🔝9953056974🔝
Model Call Girl in Bikash Puri  Delhi reach out to us at 🔝9953056974🔝Model Call Girl in Bikash Puri  Delhi reach out to us at 🔝9953056974🔝
Model Call Girl in Bikash Puri Delhi reach out to us at 🔝9953056974🔝
 
ESSENTIAL of (CS/IT/IS) class 06 (database)
ESSENTIAL of (CS/IT/IS) class 06 (database)ESSENTIAL of (CS/IT/IS) class 06 (database)
ESSENTIAL of (CS/IT/IS) class 06 (database)
 
Organic Name Reactions for the students and aspirants of Chemistry12th.pptx
Organic Name Reactions  for the students and aspirants of Chemistry12th.pptxOrganic Name Reactions  for the students and aspirants of Chemistry12th.pptx
Organic Name Reactions for the students and aspirants of Chemistry12th.pptx
 
What is Model Inheritance in Odoo 17 ERP
What is Model Inheritance in Odoo 17 ERPWhat is Model Inheritance in Odoo 17 ERP
What is Model Inheritance in Odoo 17 ERP
 
18-04-UA_REPORT_MEDIALITERAСY_INDEX-DM_23-1-final-eng.pdf
18-04-UA_REPORT_MEDIALITERAСY_INDEX-DM_23-1-final-eng.pdf18-04-UA_REPORT_MEDIALITERAСY_INDEX-DM_23-1-final-eng.pdf
18-04-UA_REPORT_MEDIALITERAСY_INDEX-DM_23-1-final-eng.pdf
 
Roles & Responsibilities in Pharmacovigilance
Roles & Responsibilities in PharmacovigilanceRoles & Responsibilities in Pharmacovigilance
Roles & Responsibilities in Pharmacovigilance
 
Full Stack Web Development Course for Beginners
Full Stack Web Development Course  for BeginnersFull Stack Web Development Course  for Beginners
Full Stack Web Development Course for Beginners
 
How to Make a Pirate ship Primary Education.pptx
How to Make a Pirate ship Primary Education.pptxHow to Make a Pirate ship Primary Education.pptx
How to Make a Pirate ship Primary Education.pptx
 
Types of Journalistic Writing Grade 8.pptx
Types of Journalistic Writing Grade 8.pptxTypes of Journalistic Writing Grade 8.pptx
Types of Journalistic Writing Grade 8.pptx
 
ENGLISH 7_Q4_LESSON 2_ Employing a Variety of Strategies for Effective Interp...
ENGLISH 7_Q4_LESSON 2_ Employing a Variety of Strategies for Effective Interp...ENGLISH 7_Q4_LESSON 2_ Employing a Variety of Strategies for Effective Interp...
ENGLISH 7_Q4_LESSON 2_ Employing a Variety of Strategies for Effective Interp...
 
Enzyme, Pharmaceutical Aids, Miscellaneous Last Part of Chapter no 5th.pdf
Enzyme, Pharmaceutical Aids, Miscellaneous Last Part of Chapter no 5th.pdfEnzyme, Pharmaceutical Aids, Miscellaneous Last Part of Chapter no 5th.pdf
Enzyme, Pharmaceutical Aids, Miscellaneous Last Part of Chapter no 5th.pdf
 
Alper Gobel In Media Res Media Component
Alper Gobel In Media Res Media ComponentAlper Gobel In Media Res Media Component
Alper Gobel In Media Res Media Component
 
Model Call Girl in Tilak Nagar Delhi reach out to us at 🔝9953056974🔝
Model Call Girl in Tilak Nagar Delhi reach out to us at 🔝9953056974🔝Model Call Girl in Tilak Nagar Delhi reach out to us at 🔝9953056974🔝
Model Call Girl in Tilak Nagar Delhi reach out to us at 🔝9953056974🔝
 
TataKelola dan KamSiber Kecerdasan Buatan v022.pdf
TataKelola dan KamSiber Kecerdasan Buatan v022.pdfTataKelola dan KamSiber Kecerdasan Buatan v022.pdf
TataKelola dan KamSiber Kecerdasan Buatan v022.pdf
 
Pharmacognosy Flower 3. Compositae 2023.pdf
Pharmacognosy Flower 3. Compositae 2023.pdfPharmacognosy Flower 3. Compositae 2023.pdf
Pharmacognosy Flower 3. Compositae 2023.pdf
 

Revision of Comparison of Theories” At the doctoral level, wr.docx

  • 1. Revision of “Comparison of Theories” At the doctoral level, writing is a continual process of revision as individuals improve skills and build subject matter expertise. This notion of writing, reflecting, and revising carries forward through the dissertation process to the publication of professional materials. In this assignment, you will reflect on the written work you submitted in Topic 3 and the feedback provided by your instructor to create a revised version of the paper “Comparison of Theories.” General Requirements: Use the following information to ensure successful completion of the assignment: · This assignment uses a rubric. Please review the rubric prior to beginning the assignment to become familiar with the expectations for successful completion. · Doctoral learners are required to use APA style for their writing assignments. The APA Style Guide is located in the Student Success Center. · Refer to Chapters 2-4 of the Publication Manual of the American Psychological Association (6th ed.) for specific guidelines related to doctoral level writing. These chapters contain essential information on manuscript structure and content, clear and concise writing, and academic grammar and usage. · This assignment requires that at least two additional scholarly research sources related to this topic, and at least one in-text citation from each source be included. · You are required to submit this assignment to LopesWrite. Refer to the LopesWrite Technical Support articles for assistance. Directions: Reflect on your writing and the feedback from your instructor on the paper “Comparison of Theories” that you submitted in
  • 2. Topic 3. What could you do to improve the academic quality of the content and the writing of the submitted paper? Write a revised version (1,500-1,800 words total) of the paper “Comparison of Theories” that makes improvements in the caliber of the writing and incorporates instructor feedback regarding content and writing. Include the following in your submission: 1. A reflection (250-300 words) that provides a bulleted list of the changes you made to the paper and discusses your revision process including how you incorporated your instructor's feedback into the revised version. Similar to an abstract, this section will receive its own page following the title page and preceding the introduction to the paper. 2. The revised paper that incorporates instructor feedback; clarifies the thesis statement and solidifies supporting arguments; edits for grammar, spelling, and punctuation; adjusts word choice to display professional and scholarly language; and adjusts sentence structure for improved readability. CHAPTER 2 MORAL EDUCATION, LIBERAL EDUCATION AND THE VOICE OF THE INDIVIDUAL Paul Standish ‘I want to break free.’ – Freddie Mercury The words above, from Freddie Mercury’s hit song, Free, have, so it seems, a guaran- teed appeal to young (and older) people today. In fact, there are many songs in which one finds expressions of, or cries of, or demands for freedom.
  • 3. We live in a world that, in so many respects, offers freedom to people as never before. But the word seems to have an unstoppable emotive force. Don’t we all at times utter it or think it – whether we are thinking ‘Now at last I feel free’, or ‘If only I could be free’, or ‘Once I get away from here I shall be free’? Where does the emotive power of the idea of freedom come from and why does it seem so important to us? For all the apparent impetus towards new possibilities of life, however, there is in some of these expressions more than a suggestion of the ressentiment that Nietzsche saw as a manifestation of nihilism. Nihilism of such kinds involves a negativity towards the way things are, in a never-ending, perhaps compulsive longing for some other world. If only things could be different, these thoughts seem to say; they are the opposite of the yea-saying, the intense absorption in experience, that might otherwise be associated with freedom. But, this is an essay about neither Nietzsche nor nihilism. What I propose to do is to consider the ways in which concerns with freedom have been played out in the philosophy of the curriculum. I shall do this by tracing a story that leads from the rise of progressivism to the reactions against it. Although there is, in a sense, something timeless about questions concerning free- dom, they acquire new dimensions in circumstances of globalization. Whereas one
  • 4. might, on a standard analysis, ask questions about what it can mean for the individual to be free when he or she is at the same time conditioned by social, cultural, political and religious circumstances within the nation-state, the very terms of this question are now challenged by globalization. It is not just that the nation- state finds itself com- promised by the power of multinationals or by the invasive forms of new communi- cations or by larger political forms of organization; it is that the very space of the political, the terms of the public and the private, is reconfigured in new and sometimes frenetic, sometimes tranquilized forms. Education systems now routinely acknowl- edge questions of globalization, but these rarely go beyond gestures towards the knowledge economy or the somewhat haphazard adoption of web-based learning. From country to country, however, the picture varies. A dimension of the demise of 33 K. Roth and I. Gur-Ze’ev (eds.), Education in the Era of Globalization, 33–50 © 2007 Springer. 34 PAUL STANDISH the nation-state for many citizens in European countries, for
  • 5. example, is precisely that they now think of themselves as citizens of Europe. The ways in which individual identities are developed, and hence that the possibilities of freedom are conceived, are deeply conditioned by these changing political terms. In countries, such as the UK or Japan, however a relative isolation is maintained, with correspondingly more intro- spective conceptions of citizenship and its education. There are obvious debates to be had about how far public education should foster loyalty to the nation-state and how far cosmopolitan values, and about how far these are incompatible. In other political regimes, to be sure – say, in theocracies, in countries devastated by poverty or in newly formed democracies – the stakes of freedom are plainly very different. When one looks across this range of difference, and against the in some respects common background of global change, what is clear is that Enlightenment ideals of freedom are themselves challenged. While I do not propose to foreground the Nietzschean themes alluded to here, it is in the restoring of such an inflection at the end of the chapter that an alternative, richer conception of freedom in relation to the curriculum is sought. It is in this context that concerns about freedom and schooling have developed in various ways and in diverse circumstances. In Japan, there is concern about
  • 6. drop-out rates from education, about the rebellious behaviour of young people, about classroom disruption, and lack of respect for tradition, about hair dyed blond . . . And, in this context, some argue that what is needed is education of the heart (kokoro no kyoiku). In the UK within recent decades, debates about moral education and citizenship have gained a new prominence. What is needed, the argument has been, is to get ‘back to basics’. What we need to do is to teach children the difference between right and wrong. In these and other countries, it has become a common wisdom that it is progressive (or child- centred) ideas and methods, that have given children too much freedom and so deprived them of the standards of behaviour and the discipline that is necessary in their upbringing. John Major went so far, in the early 1990s, as to say: ‘The progressives have had their say and they have had their day’. In fact, in the UK, during the past 20 years, no leading politician (of any of the parties) has been willing to speak in favour of progressivism because in the eyes of the public it has become so much associated with the image of self-indulgent teachers, who want to be ‘friends’ with the children rather than to teach them, to let children do whatever they want, and because the one thing that the general public wants from education is for it to make sure that their children come out of school with the necessary skills to find
  • 7. decent jobs. I want shortly to give a brief account of that development in the UK and of reac- tions against it. But, first, it is appropriate to say more about the value of freedom that is so close to its heart. For brevity, I shall not say anything here about the prominence of the idea in the world of Ancient Greece but shall confine myself to some remarks about the rise of the idea of freedom, principally in Europe, over the past 300 or so years. What does a consideration of that period show? MORAL EDUCATION, LIBERAL EDUCATION 35 The development of the idea of freedom in the modern Western world When people speak in history or philosophy of ‘the modern world’, they typically have in mind a period of time extending back to René Descartes and the individual- ism of disengaged rationality and to the political individualism of John Locke. But probably the most striking changes come with the political upheavals of the late 18th century and, in the UK especially, the massive social change brought about by the Industrial Revolution. Perhaps equally important during these centuries is the rise of science, which came with a new confidence in man’s reasoning and a faith in progress.
  • 8. (It was indeed thought of as ‘man’s’ reasoning at the time!) Words such as ‘progress’ and ‘development’ have now become so commonplace in our thinking that we suppose them to be perfectly natural, almost as if progress were built into the universe, but really this is very much the result of these massive changes in thought. With this new confidence in human abilities, there was an unprecedented questioning of estab- lished religious and moral horizons, and also the growing belief that, just as science had brought about spectacular changes in technology, so too rationality could be applied to the organization of society. The gradual move from a conception of the universe as God’s creation towards a placing of man at the centre of things (that is, the rise of humanism) gave new promi- nence to the idea of freedom. Immanuel Kant advanced the key principle that, because human beings were capable of free will, they should always be treated as ends, never simply as means. (In other words, they should never be treated simply as slaves, but should be recognized as beings with interests of their own, and with the capacity ratio- nally to reflect on those interests.) This has become a guiding principle for the modern world. Perhaps the most important figure in the change we are considering, however, is Jean-Jacques Rousseau. His radical ideas pointed to the ways in which the contem- porary world caused people to lead lives that were shaped by mere convention and that
  • 9. were unnatural. One can perhaps picture the extraordinary costumes that were worn by the aristocracy of that time – the long wigs, the make-up, the brightly coloured fancy clothing for women and men! – and think of these as symbols of the falseness of people’s values and behaviour. In fact, however, the very ideas of what is natural and of falseness here are themselves familiar to us very much because of Rousseau’s own work. For, in his rejection of the values of convention, he argued that human beings had lost touch with nature and with their true selves. The way that today we cherish the natural world – our delight in a beautiful mountain range as well as our current environmentalism – would probably have made little sense in the Western world before Rousseau’s time. And, when today we read in a popular magazine such as Cosmopolitan of the need to get in touch with your ‘real self’ (Are you in touch with the real you?), this idea, which apparently comes so naturally to us, is surely partly attributable to Rousseau. The idea of what is real or true to ourselves, which connects with our notions of honesty, sincerity, integrity and being ‘together’ as a per- son, is sometimes spoken of as authenticity. In his book The Ethics of Authenticity 36 PAUL STANDISH (1991), Charles Taylor speaks of the massive inward turn that is
  • 10. brought about by Rousseau’s thinking: Rousseau gives us a sense of ourselves as beings with inner depths, for whom the morally good life must be one where we feel in tune with our own deepest commitments and feelings (as opposed to one where we simply follow what our religious or political leaders, or our parents, say). The source of morality is a voice within. What Rousseau also offers, of course, in his conception of nature is a new idea of childhood – hence his enormous influence on thinking about education. Against the Christian idea that human beings are born in a state of ‘original sin’, he enables us to think of children as innocent (and pure and good, perhaps) because they are closer to nature. In contrast to the idea that the role of education was to mould children into a shape that would fit society, Rousseau’s view was that the perverted forms that soci- ety had come to assume must themselves change in accordance with what was natural. His description of Emile’s upbringing does indeed have an important bearing on edu- cation, but the book needs to be seen as part of his larger political philosophy: his vision of the good society and of citizenship. In the light of Emile (Rousseau, 1911, originally published 1762) and his other more obviously political writings, there is a clear connection between his thought and an event that was profoundly to shape the history of modern Europe and its understanding of itself – the
  • 11. French Revolution (1789). Its slogan of ‘liberty, equality, fraternity’ underlines the point. In the 19th century, the thinker who stands out for his importance in the political thinking of the English-speaking world is, of course, John Stuart Mill. In Mill’s On Liberty, originally published in 1859, he advances what has become taken by people in general to be a fundamental principle. He writes: The object of this essay is to assert one very simple principle, as entitled to govern absolutely the dealings of society with the individual in the way of compulsion and con- trol, whether the means used be physical force in the form of legal penalties or the moral coercion of public opinion. That principle is that the sole end for which mankind are war- ranted, individually or collectively, in interfering with the liberty of action of any of their number is self-protection. That the only purpose for which power can rightfully be exer- cised over any member of a civilized community, against his will, is to prevent harm to oth- ers. His own good, either physical or moral, is not a sufficient warrant (Mill, 1978, p. 9). In other words, you should not prevent someone from doing what they want to do unless they are harming someone else. You should not interfere with them because they are harming themselves or because you think you know what is best for them. This principle encounters many problem cases, some of which
  • 12. Mill and his critics have addressed, but it remains an immensely powerful guiding principle and a natural reference point. Although the ways of thinking sketched here have become naturalized in the Western world, they have undoubtedly brought problems, problems that could not easily have been anticipated. When the individual becomes the ultimate reference point, there is a loss of horizons of meaning that in the past had given sense to much of what he did; community ties are weakened, and the individual feels rootless and purposeless; there is a kind of ‘disenchantment’ of the world. Within the democracies that have MORAL EDUCATION, LIBERAL EDUCATION 37 developed, especially where the masses are not well educated, there is some tendency for values and policies to be determined by the ‘lowest common denominator’, so that societies are flattened and narrowed. And in these circumstances morality can degen- erate into crude utilitarianism, governed by a technical rationality. Of course, the history of the 20th century is marked by two world wars. Amongst the social consequences of these in the UK were a weakening of the British class system, which had been such a pronounced feature of the period
  • 13. of the Empire, and a change in the role of women (as they too became directly involved in the war effort or took over civilian jobs normally held by men). In the 15 or so years immediately following the Second World War, the UK faced a period of austerity and at the same time saw the closing decades of its empire, as colonized countries moved towards independence. But, in the 1960s, there was a new period of economic prosperity and suddenly the feeling that things could change. New universities were built to meet the needs of the children of the post-war baby boom who were now passing through adolescence, sex scandals in the government changed people’s attitudes towards those in power and authority, the Beatles made their first records and ‘flower-power’ (the hippies) arrived! This was a new sense that one could question the way things had been done in the past, that one could, and one should, live one’s life as one chose. One must above all be authentic. It was in this context that progressivism came to be intro- duced in schools. Progressive schooling and its introduction in the UK While the advent of progressivism in state education in the UK was later than it had been in Germany and Scandinavia, for example, or for that matter in the United States, its development was perhaps more dramatic.1 The Primary Memorandum in Scotland (1965) and the Plowden Report (1967), two major government
  • 14. reports, advocated a radical change in the education of children in elementary school. The following para- graph from the Primary Memorandum is indicative: It is now generally accepted that the primary school is much more than a preparation for secondary school: it is a stage of development in its own right . . . [Schooling must] meet the child’s needs and interests . . . [The teacher must] provide the environment, experi- ences and guidance which will stimulate growth along natural lines . . . [The child is] not an adult in miniature . . . [N]atural endowment of children is not uniform . . . [G]rowth and development . . . are continuous . . . The artificial nature of school organisation [needs to be compensated for] (SED, 1965, pp. 3–4). To anyone familiar with the texts of progressive educators, these ideas will be famil- iar enough. It would be easy to match the phrases here to ideas of John Dewey, espe- cially in Democracy and Education (Dewey, 1925, originally published in 1916). It is undoubtedly the case that the ideas that were promoted in the teacher education 1 There had been a number of influential experiments in private education before this time. For a full discussion of the development of progressivism, see Darling and Nordenbo (2003). 38 PAUL STANDISH
  • 15. colleges at this time were a watered-down, if not a distorted, version of the thinking of the philosophers whom they quoted (Rousseau and Dewey above all). And even if the new approaches that they advocated did not affect all schools, there was neverthe- less a sudden wave of interest in these innovations. Visitors came from many coun- tries to see the new ‘Plowden schools’. It is worth pausing for a moment to think what one might have seen in a visit to a progressive elementary school classroom in England at that time. In contrast to the plain, rather forbidding room with high windows (so that the children would look up towards God) and straight rows of desks (so that would work silently and attend only to the teacher) that had been the experience of the previous generation, the new class- room would be a colourful and comfortable place: there would be large windows, let- ting the light in and encouraging children to look out at the garden outside; tables would be arranged in ‘family’ groups, encouraging children to work with one another; the walls would be decorated with the brightly coloured art work of the children; there would be a ‘quiet corner’ with a carpet and cushions, and picture-books for children to browse; there would be pet animals (such as guinea pigs) for the children to care for, and plants for them to tend; and there would be a variety of activity, with children writing, drawing, making things, playing, talking and laughing
  • 16. excitedly; the teacher would not generally have spoken to the class as a whole, but would move around the room, attending to one child then another as the need arose. The children would up to a point be free to pursue the activities in whatever order they chose – in other words, to follow their interests. The principles and values governing this scene can be summed up in the following set of precepts: • children learn best through doing, through experience; • learning takes place in a process of discovery; • creativity should be developed; • imagination should be developed; • children learn through play; • they learn best when they are happy; • learning should begin with the interests of the child; • children must not become bored; • children must learn things in meaningful contexts (not just isolated facts or mindless drills); • learning should be organized on the basis of themes or topics, not according to abstract academic subjects; • education is a process of growth from within; • the role of the teacher is to provide conditions that will assist that growth; • all children are different and they have their individual needs and rates of growth; • the teacher must respond to the child’s needs, not present them with what she
  • 17. wants to teach; • the emphasis should be on encouragement and praise, not punishment; • the teacher should not be an authoritarian figure but more like a friend to the children. MORAL EDUCATION, LIBERAL EDUCATION 39 These then were the values promoted by many of those training teachers at the time and to some extent they became a kind of ideology. It is not the case that all schools adopted them entirely, but the general climate in the primary school undoubtedly went through a period of major change. Economic change and conservative reactions In the 1970s, however, events outside the school came to have an important bearing on the country’s development and on how education and teachers were seen. In 1972, a world crisis was occasioned when some of the main oil- producing countries in the Middle East made the decision to act collectively to raise prices. In the UK, one effect was a doubling in the cost of petrol overnight. Inevitably, this put severe pressure on the economy. This occurred following a time of prosperity when the major trade unions had succeeded, through collective bargaining, in gaining
  • 18. wage increases for their members. Now, with higher prices in the shops, they understandably pressed for more. Through the 1970s, there was a series of strikes against a background of rising inflation (to over 20%). Social problems appeared to be on the increase, with crime rising, and there was a general air of unrest. In 1979, Margaret Thatcher came to power, with a radical agenda for reform, one that involved high levels of unemploy- ment, new kinds of poverty and a squeeze on the funding of public services, welfare and education. Inevitably, progressive education was blamed for much that was wrong in society. Her first Minister of Education, Keith Joseph, even went so far as to say that it was teacher educators who were to blame because they had introduced teach- ers to Dewey! In or around the 1970s, a number of publications had been produced under the ominous title of ‘Black Papers in Education’2 (see Boyson, 1975; Cox, 1992; Cox and Boyson, 1975, 1977; Cox and Dyson, 1969). At the time these reactionary texts struck many teachers as the ranting of conservative extremists, and they were assumed simply to be wildly out of touch. It was striking, however, that a decade later, with the reforms that Margaret Thatcher was to introduce, they had come closer to the mainstream. What Thatcher picked up on and skilfully exploited was suspi- cions amongst ordinary people that all was not well with
  • 19. education. For many peo- ple, the challenge to conventional notions of discipline and authority that had come with progressivism had seemed threatening, and the emphasis on creativity, play, and happiness in the elementary classroom appeared to involve a neglect of the knowl- edge and values that children needed. Not surprisingly, this laid the way for the idea that we needed to ‘get back to basics’ and that children must learn the difference between right and wrong. 2 The term ‘Black Paper’ borrows from the normal use of the phrase ‘White Paper’ for a government policy document. 40 PAUL STANDISH This widespread reaction to progressivism may have been justified in some ways, but it was generally based on very crude and limited ideas about education. It needs to be contrasted with the serious and careful work of a number of critics who, from the 1960s onwards, raised questions of a predominantly philosophical kind about some of the assumptions of progressivism. These criticisms were advanced in the name of liberal education, and it is to this that I now turn. The idea of a liberal education The views in Question are particularly interesting because,
  • 20. unlike those of the reactionary critics above, they also were committed to the idea that education was fundamentally con- nected with freedom. But they disagreed about what this freedom consisted in. The lead- ing figure in this in the UK was R. S. Peters, although in many respects his work related to ideas being developed around the same time by Israel Scheffler in the United States. In collaboration with his colleagues, Paul Hirst and Robert Dearden, Peters attempted to restate the idea of a liberal education. The importance of this idea and its influence on Anglophone philosophy of education can scarcely be questioned. It is a conception of education with ancient roots that presents us with cogent criticisms of progressivism. Criticism of progressivism from liberal education Like the reactionary critics mentioned above, these thinkers were concerned about vari- ous aspects of the wave of progressivism that was changing education. Within the child- centred preoccupations with play, happiness, creativity, learning by discovery (or experiential learning) and growth, they detected a somewhat sentimental view of the child. They identified also a failure to think through what these terms really implied. To take an example, progressive educators tended to think that children must above all be happy and that only the happy child would learn well, and this came to mean that a class- room in which children were smiling and laughing was a good classroom. But, as
  • 21. Dearden in particular pointed out, happiness is a much more elusive notion than this sug- gests. Sometimes we can be laughing but not be happy or only happy in a superficial way. Sometimes a greater degree of happiness comes because of struggling and then feeling that one has really achieved something. Some kinds of happiness bring satisfactions that are more profound. If smiling and laughing were the ultimate satisfaction, we should put scientists to work on a drug that would produce this state reliably and without difficulty. But surely we want more from our lives than this. At least, surely we should! This connects very much with what is perhaps the most pervasive criticism of pro- gressive education that these philosophers made. This was, in R. S. Peters’ words, that child-centred education was concerned too much with the manner and insufficiently with the matter of education. In other words, it was too concerned with questions about the methods of learning and insufficiently concerned with what was learned. From the point of view of liberal education, the question of what is to be learned is the fundamental ques- tion of education. Let us consider how they set about answering that question. MORAL EDUCATION, LIBERAL EDUCATION 41 What is worthwhile?
  • 22. There are obviously some things that we learn to do that we need more or less for our survival and some that are really a matter of training for the jobs that we take up in society. For example, in the comparatively recent past, many young women were trained in typing skills. With the development of voice- recognition, these skills will perhaps eventually become obsolete, and it is not obvious why anyone would then what to acquire them. So they are useful skills but nothing more. On the contrary, there are some things we learn that are not obsolescent in this way. It is noticeable that these are things that, unlike typing, have often been pursued by people who have not had to find jobs to support themselves (the aristocracy, for example). They seem to be things that, whether or not they are useful, are intrinsically worthwhile. The idea of what is worthwhile in itself is at the heart of this account of education. So we must ask what it is that people find worthwhile. What do they find most satisfaction in? In addressing this question in his book Ethics and Education, Peters considers the things that people enjoy in a series of ascending stages. In the first place, they enjoy physical pleasures such as eating and drinking, sex, and lying in the sun. These are genuine sources of satisfaction for human beings, and they are activities that allow scope for care, refinement and sophistication. (Think for a moment of the remarkable difference between the way in which even the higher animals
  • 23. eat and a simple meal shared amongst friends or family.) But these activities also have their limitations. They depend on cyclical appetites – for example, there is only so much that one can eat at one time. And each time you eat, even where this is a gourmet meal, you do, as it were, start again from the beginning. The second kind of enjoyment that Peters considers includes games and sports. People take great satisfaction in these. The advantage they have over the pleasures of the senses above is that they offer extraordinary possibilities for the development of ability or skill. If you play chess or tennis and you practise regularly, you may be able to press your achievement to higher and higher levels. Activities of this kind do not depend on cyclical appetites, and indeed, they may strengthen your capacity the more you do them. When you resume such activities, you do not have to start from the beginning, as it were, but build on the skill level that you have reached. They offer the possibility for extending human capacities in remarkable ways. But these activities also have limitations. Sports and games tend to be limited parts of our lives. Taking part in such activities does not, in general, cast light on the world as a whole or help you in other aspects of your life. The third type of activity that Peters considers is what he calls ‘theoretical activi- ties’. He has in mind such academic pursuits as the study of
  • 24. history or mathematics or literature. Unlike the pleasures of eating and drinking, these do not depend on cycli- cal appetites but, on the contrary, are intensified the more you do them. Of course, you have to take a break for a rest sometimes! But the chances are that the more you know about, say, history, the more satisfying further study will be. They do not depend upon competition over resources that are scarce, because in intellectual activities the 42 PAUL STANDISH possibilities extend the more they are pursued, nor do they depend upon competition, where, as in sports and games, the winner takes the prize, because these activities depend upon and are enhanced by the shared pursuit of their goals. Moreover, they are not confined in terms of their influence on our lives. The way we live in the world is transformed and improved if we know something about how it has developed (in terms of social and political history, geography, geology and so on) and something about the science and technology upon which it depends. More strongly, this knowledge, and perhaps the understanding of human nature that we can gain from such disciplines as history and literature, makes us better able to address the practical problems that we will face, in all their ethical diversity. Furthermore, in view of the fact that reason is
  • 25. the most obvious feature that distinguishes us from other forms of life and that these activities are supreme developments of human reason, it is this that we should develop. In sum, theoretical activities offer unparalleled opportunities for satisfaction. Cultural initiation and the development of mind If we think a little about reason and the nature of mind, we should come to realize that the development of the mind is quite unlike the development of, say, a muscle in the body. Of course, there are physical parts of the body upon which the mind depends, but the mind is not an organ of the body; the brain is not the mind. To recognize this is to realize the immense importance that initiation into a culture has for the mind’s development. To speak of initiation into a culture here is not to refer to something highbrow but rather to think of the range of complex practices that make up any soci- ety and into which children are gradually introduced. Coming to participate in these practices is the development of mind. This may seem a surprising statement, but it can be supported by reference to the well-known case of the so- called wild child of Aveyron. In France in the 18th Century, a child was discovered in the forest. The child was probably about 10 years old but was behaving like no ordinary child. He moved about on his hands and feet, and, obviously terrified of people, made
  • 26. animal-like noises when he was approached. Eventually, he was surrounded and caught, and then taken to an asylum in Paris. Asylums in Europe at that time, quite unlike modern hospitals, were places where mentally ill or abnormal people were confined. The public could pay an entrance fee to come and look (and probably laugh) at the people inside. An enlightened doctor heard about the child and became interested. The evidence was that this was a child who had been abandoned at birth and who had been left in the woods to die. The amazing thing was that it seemed that he had been found by wolves and protected by them, and so had spent several years amongst them. The doctor was inter- ested to see how far this child had become different from a normal child because of being so dramatically cut off from society, and also whether he could be civilized. The doctor took the child into his home and cared for him, and tried to do just this. What is immediately striking about this story is that, although the child is not radically different physiologically from other children (his brain has developed MORAL EDUCATION, LIBERAL EDUCATION 43 organically, just as his muscles have), his mental state is barely recognizable as that of a human being at all. This should draw our attention to what
  • 27. it is we mean when we speak of the mind of a human being. In short, the mind is nothing without the cultural practices into which the child is introduced. Most important among those practices is language itself, as virtually all distinctively human activity seems to follow in some way from this. This child has been cutoff from language users, and so, the limited and strange ways of thinking that he has developed are scarcely recognizable to us. Indeed, it relates more to a wolf’s behaviour than to anything we could call mind. If this is right, it seems to follow that a child’s upbringing cannot simply be a natural process of growth, or of unfolding from within, or even of unaided discovery learning. In any culture, the child must be introduced into the practices of that culture. Thinking of the way we treat infants and very young children – over such practices as sitting, walking, eating, talking, dressing, laughing – can help to show that this is the case. A further comparison with animals helps to make this point. The societies that we live in are extremely complex, and our practices are the result of thousands of years of development. To see quite how far this is true, it is worth thinking for a moment of animals living in a natural environment – say, lions living in the African savannah. It is probably the case that the way that lions live today – their patterns of hunting, eating
  • 28. and mating – are no different from the way they were 5000 years ago. If we think, on the contrary, of the way in which people live in any ordinary city today in contrast to the lives of people there 5000 years ago, the difference is truly remarkable. It should leave us with no doubt, first, of the importance of educational practices through which these ways of thinking and understanding are passed on and advanced from one generation to the next, and, second, of the dependence of what we mean by ‘mind’ upon these practices. It seems to follow from the above that education ought to initiate people into the forms of knowledge and understanding that have come down to us. For, if education is to be more than mere training for a job, it should free the mind to function in as rich a way as is possible; it is in this sense particularly that it is liberal. Not to introduce learners to the ways of understanding that have come down to us would amount to leaving them confined within limited ways of thinking – ones that they had acquired perhaps only from their immediate community or perhaps from a diet of cartoon programmes on television. The ‘conversation of mankind’ One of the most influential articles by Paul Hirst concludes with words from an essay by Michael Oakeshott entitled ‘The Voice of Poetry in the Conversation of Mankind’
  • 29. (in Oakeshott, 1962): As civilised human beings, we are the inheritors, neither of an inquiry about ourselves and the world, nor of an accumulating body of information, but of a conversation, begun in the primeval forests and extended and made more articulate in the course of centuries. It is a conversation which goes on both in public and within each of ourselves. Of course there 44 PAUL STANDISH is argument and enquiry and information, but wherever these are profitable they are to be recognized as passages in this conversation, and perhaps they are not the most captivating of the passages . . . Conversation is not an enterprise designed to yield an extrinsic profit, a contest where a winner gets a prize, nor is it an activity of exegesis; it is an unrehearsed intellectual adventure . . . Education, properly speaking, is an initiation into the skill and partnership of this conversation in which we learn to recognize the voices, to distinguish the proper occasions of utterance, and in which we acquire the intellectual and moral habits appropriate to conversation. And it is this conversation which, in the end, gives place and character to every human utterance (Hirst, 1965, pp. 52–53). Oakeshott’s moving words here underline the connection between the ways in which
  • 30. an education of this kind is properly described as liberal. It is liberal in the same sense of the term as is used in the liberal arts colleges of the United States. The initiation into the ‘conversation of mankind’ then involves something like an initiation into ‘the best that has been thought and said’, in Matthew Arnold’s famous (if contentious) phrase. And, in this respect, these words not only value the past but connect with val- ues that shaped the thinking of the world of Ancient Greece. The past is not valuable because it is the past. It is valuable because it offers us the developing history of attempts to get at the truth of things and to understand what matters in human lives. In the Republic, Plato gives us a wonderful image of education with the myth of the Cave. He describes the human condition as being like that of people living in the darkness of a cave and watching the flickering images projected onto the back of the cave by the light from its mouth. What they see is not real but the distorted images (the shadows) of real objects at the mouth of the cave, objects illuminated by the bright light of the sun. (The relevance of the fact that the idea of reality that many people have today is given by the distorted images of the world on television scarcely needs spelling out.) Education involves the process of helping these people to turn their heads away from these images in order that they should come to see the real objects at the mouth of the cave and eventually look at the sun
  • 31. itself, the source of truth and goodness. But, just as we find it difficult to look at bright lights when we have been in the dark and are inclined to be dazzled and to turn back to the darkness, so too people would prefer to look at these images (and to remain in ignorance) rather than to face up to the truth. Crucial to Plato’s account then is coming to see things truly (the contemplation of truth and goodness); it is freeing the mind from illusion. Rational autonomy and political liberalism A commitment to truth is close to the heart of the idea of a liberal education that is developed by Peters and his colleagues. But their position is also complicated by a fur- ther dimension of freedom, and this connects with the modern political liberalism associated especially with J. S. Mill. Here, the emphasis is not so much on freedom from illusion as on freedom to choose what to do: in the absence of any indisputable substantive conception of the good, the individual should decide for herself how she is going to live her life. Far from being a licence for irresponsibility, however, this was developed in terms of what came to be called ‘rational autonomy’. Although there is now a huge literature on autonomy, especially in relation to education but also more MORAL EDUCATION, LIBERAL EDUCATION 45
  • 32. generally in political philosophy, perhaps the most succinct expression of rational autonomy is to be found in Dearden’s essay ‘Autonomy and Education’. As Dearden explains: ‘A man is autonomous, on Kant’s view, if in his actions he has bound himself by moral laws legislated by his own reason, as opposed to being governed by his own inclinations’ (Dearden, 1972, p. 58). What should be noticed here is the emphasis on reasoning through one’s principles for oneself. On this view, you should not do some- thing simply because the priest or the government or your parents or the media tell you to, or because you do not have the strength of character to do anything different, or because you are under the influence of drugs or obsessions or neurotic fears, and so on. You should reflect on your desires and reason through what to do. Of course, the principles you adopt, the reasons for your actions, may be ones that are likely to be current in your culture in one way or another, but what is crucial is that you decide to adopt these as your own. In the decades since this restatement of the idea of a liberal education was made, there has been a tendency for the connection with political liberalism (and hence with autonomy) to come to the fore, to the growing neglect of the more classical connec- tion with the contemplation of truth. The term ‘liberal education’ is sometimes now used solely with such political principles in mind, in such a way
  • 33. that the robust account of the curriculum that was produced has been largely lost. In my own view this is very much to be regretted. Questions about what is to be learned and why should be recognized as unavoidable by any policy maker or practising teacher, and philosophy of education must find ways of addressing them. In what follows, and to confront such questions myself, I shall say something about problems with the vision of a liberal education that I have sketched and shall point to ways in which its limitations may be overcome. I shall also attempt to show how what I have to say connects with the account of contemporary individualism with which the present discussion began. Addressing the difficulties with the idea of a liberal education Peters and his colleagues had great influence throughout the English-speaking world. But the idea of a liberal education that they advanced was not without its critics. A common response was that it provided nothing new: it was simply a rationalization for what was in fact going on at the time in grammar schools, with children at other schools – that is, the majority – given a watered-down version, and thus, it shored up the power relationships and class distinctions that were responsible for some of the injustice in society. Its conception of the curriculum itself was dull and outmoded – a matter of passing on the knowledge that happened to be
  • 34. preferred by a section of soci- ety rather than anything that was likely to be truly meaningful to the lives of people in general. That knowledge was highbrow and academic, the critics said, and so, not surprisingly, many children were alienated and did badly at school. Not only did it reflect the interests of particular social classes; it was also inherently sexist, being 46 PAUL STANDISH based on the work or the deeds of ‘dead white males’. And, far from developing crit- ical thinking, it encouraged the repetition of received ideas. Moreover, because of its emphasis on this outmoded content, it failed to appreciate the importance of the insights of progressivism – in particular, the need for education to acknowledge the differences between people and to develop from the individual herself. If liberal education is practised in the way described in the preceding paragraph, it should indeed be criticised. Many students, including some of the most intelligent, are not moved by ‘the best that has been thought and said’. Such an education will, more- over, be a limitation of the individual rather than something that might engage her more deeply and foster her development. And it must be admitted that over-attention to the subject matter can inhibit opportunities for students to
  • 35. respond authentically and to find their own voices. To be fair to Peters and his colleagues, however, it was never their intention that the curriculum should be a mere passing on of received ideas: they advocated cur- riculum content that incorporated traditions of criticism, and they saw the initiation of the learner into such forms of knowledge as a means of her engagement. The criticism of their views considered here then depends upon a distortion of the ideas that they advanced. I do, nevertheless, want to draw attention to two main concerns. In the first place, the emphasis on rational autonomy as a central aim of education is based on a narrow view of human life and morality. It encourages us to think of the good life as one that is carefully planned out in (perhaps) most respects. In conse- quence, it loses sight of the value of spontaneity. This might be found, for example, in acts of unreflective generosity or courage and in the everyday kindness that good peo- ple show to others. Indeed, sometimes to reflect before you act – say, when an acci- dent occurs – could be a sign of moral failing. Spontaneity is also apparent in a kind of joie de vivre, a delight in living or even just a sense of fun, as it is in a certain receptiveness to others. The emphasis on rational autonomy makes it sound also as though being morally good is likely to coincide with being intelligent and so hides the
  • 36. goodness that can exist in simple unreflective lives. As such, it may suppress the vari- ety of human life and thereby have a limiting effect on the kinds of community that we can develop. To exaggerate (just a little unfairly!), it sometimes seems that the ideal rationally autonomous person would be someone like Mr Spock on the Starship Enterprise, someone who always meticulously plans everything he does and for whom a spontaneous emotion is something to be quickly mastered and overcome. A second criticism concerns its emphasis on intellectual pursuits and the elitist connotations this has. While there is a good case for saying that everyone should be given the chance to pursue such activities, it is likely that these will appeal most to more intelligent people, and perhaps, as has been noted, not to all of them: many will find that an academic curriculum of this kind does not speak to them and stifles their voices. The point of studying history or physics may be lost on many people, espe- cially while they are children. The fact that people who write theoretical articles about education almost by definition enjoy such things makes them bad at seeing how this may not be so for everyone! MORAL EDUCATION, LIBERAL EDUCATION 47 Three questions arise from this. First, what response should
  • 37. there be to the problem of the demanding and potentially alienating nature of intellectual pursuits? Second, does this justify different curricula for those who do not progress well with such activ- ities? And third, is there anything in the account of the value of theoretical activities – anything liberal, that is – that can be extended to other less intellectual pursuits? Intellectual activities are demanding, and their appeal is often difficult to under- stand from the outside. It is usually the case that, before one can participate in them with any great satisfaction, one has to undergo periods of hard work and perhaps bore- dom: one has to acquire the ‘vocabulary’ to take part in the conversation, as it were – whether this is in literary criticism, physics or history, or in more creative activities such as music and art. Hence, the teacher must tread a careful path that enables the child to acquire the vocabulary appropriate to the subject – the skills, knowledge and understanding – while avoiding the alienating effects that the demands of the subject may have. It must be her aim in the course of this for the subject to speak to the child in such a manner that the child can come to find her voice in it: that she sees how it may (come to) matter to her. And this does not mean that she finds that it may match something that already exists in herself, but rather that it offers a new possibility for the development of her voice – that is, for the expansion of herself. Without this, the sub-
  • 38. ject is in danger of going dead on the child, and schooling is likely to be an alienating experience, even if it equips the child with high grades. Bearing these factors in mind, then, it does seem that a degree of coercion is justified in taking the child through those difficult stages of learning that lead to this more rewarding understanding. My own view regarding the second question is that the demands of a liberal edu- cation, thus conceived, are likely to be too great for some children and so that it is appropriate to provide different curricula, probably at some stage during high school. Of course, this need not be done on an all-or-nothing basis. And there should be opportunities for children to move from one route to another. A further factor is important here – in terms of social justice but also for purely educational reasons. It is sometimes said that education is wasted on the young. Certainly there is evidence that mature students make much better use of educational opportunities. Hence, there is every reason to encourage people to take up such study throughout their lives, and so this is a powerful argument for meaningful lifelong learning. I do not necessarily suggest that full-time education should be available to adults at public expense because the costs of this may well be prohibitive. But there is a strong case for state subsidy of part-time education for adults. Even part-time study in evening classes can transform people’s lives, and
  • 39. sometimes the combination of study and working can be peculiarly enriching. With regard to the third question, it should be recognized that there are aspects of a liberal education that cannot easily be extended or replicated. The ideal product of such an education is someone who has a breadth of understanding across the different forms of knowledge that are our inheritance, in sciences, the humanities and the arts. But such a person will also have a deep love for at least one of these pursuits, such that it is an absorbing interest that brings to her life the sense of participating in an 48 PAUL STANDISH ‘unrehearsed intellectual adventure’, in Oakeshott’s words, an adventure that becomes all the more intense and absorbing the more it is pursued. And, surprising though this may at first seem, it is in the idea of intense absorption that a Nietzschean inflection is found once again. It is perhaps this more dynamic aspect that we should look to if we hope to extend something of this experience to those who are not intellectually up to the full demands of a liberal education. I suggest that there are other less intellectual activities that can offer such kinds of intense absorption. For examples, we should perhaps turn attention in the direction of
  • 40. craft activities. Of course, we can think of the kinds of satisfactions that people gain from activities such as carpentry or pottery, but there is obviously a danger of anachro- nism or nostalgia here. These things play a less prominent part in people’s lives, whether at work or in their leisure time, than they used to. So, we need to be prepared to consider activities of quite different and perhaps surprising kinds. I am struck by the kind of enthusiasm and delight that people can take in practical work with things – in making them and shaping them – in more contemporary, everyday circumstances. I am thinking of the pride of the engineer in the smooth-running machine, of the hair- dresser in cutting and styling, or of the bricklayer in the clean lines of a wall, or of the chef in preparing fine food. Take car mechanics as an example. Such activity does indeed offer scope for further understanding and enquiry, and for the refinement of skill with the accumulation of experience. Those involved in it often seem to take a delight in the work that incorporates aesthetic and ethical values – say, in the good timing of the engine, the pleasure to be found in its efficiently moving parts, its func- tional capability and improvement, and so on. This is a very ordinary example but one worthy of attention. When people take pleasure in their work in this way, this can spill over into other areas of life, generating a kind of curiosity about things and bringing them into intense involvement with others. Such involvement is often not confined to
  • 41. the activities concerned but becomes a broader social commitment and identification. The idea of a liberal education has tended to reinforce certain dichotomies in our thinking – between theory and practice, between the academic and the vocational, between the mind and the body – in each case favouring the former term. It has also, and perhaps in consequence of these dichotomies, been excessively preoccupied with propositional knowledge. Of course, it would be absurd to deny the massive impor- tance of propositional knowledge – not as the expression of inert facts but as the sub- stance and vocabulary of the forms of knowledge of which Peters and Hirst speak. The alternative advocated here is not the skill-based curriculum that has become fashion- able, important though skills obviously also are. What is missing from the picture, and what the craft examples above may suggest, is the importance of knowledge by direct acquaintance. Amongst more intellectual pursuits, art appreciation plainly involves an acquaintance with particular works of art, where one’s encounter with them exceeds anything that could be rendered in propositional terms, however rich propositional language may be as an approach to these works. This kind of acquaintance is also, I suggest, to be found somewhere in the mechanic’s relation to the engine or the hair- stylist’s relation to hair – including their relation to the kinds of resistance that the
  • 42. MORAL EDUCATION, LIBERAL EDUCATION 49 materials they work with present. It is there too, I also want to say, in the historian’s familiarity with a particular period, or in the physicist’s or the philosopher’s familiar- ity with particular sets of problems, and the characteristic kinds of resistance that they present. Indeed, this familiarity is very much a part of knowing one’s way around a subject and the satisfactions that this offers. Finally, it is important to draw attention to the fact that there is a kind of moral edu- cation that is inherent in the demands that learning can make on us, but these are demands that sometimes elude progressive education. These include, first, the intellec- tual virtues celebrated in the academic life, but the thought here is that what is most important extends across more practical domains. Without the understanding devel- oped through knowledge by acquaintance, through patient attention to the way things are, these intellectual virtues may cut loose from the substance that gives them their sense. These are moral matters also in the way that such forms of learning draw the learner into practices that are sustained by communities. Although this may not be explicit, such communities uphold standards to which the learner must constantly aspire to be worthy – whether this is to the standards of truth and critical argument
  • 43. found in an academic discipline or to those inherent in the creation and maintenance of the fabric of the world we live in. When one applies oneself to such activities, there is a real sense in which one’s attention is turned beyond oneself. What is learned – whether this is the functioning of the machine, the stresses that metal will take, and the explosiveness of a gas in an engine, or the substance of an academic subject – can lead to a kind of attention-to-the-way-things-are that has its intrinsic virtues but that also can disturb us from the self-preoccupied tendencies to which we can otherwise succumb. Far from a direct concentration on the development of the self, it is in such endeavours that the individual can flourish most, and through this engagement that she may find not only her own voice but that she has something meaningful to say.3 References Boyson, R. (1975) The Crisis in Education (London, The Woburn Press). Cox, C.B. (1992) The Great Betrayal (London, Chapmans Publishing Ltd.). Cox, C.B. and Boyson, R. (eds) (1975) The Fight for Education: Black Paper 1975 (London, Dent). Cox, C.B. and Boyson, R. (eds) (1977) Black Paper 1977 (London, Maurice Temple Smith). Cox, C.B. and Dyson, C.B. (1969) The Crisis in Education (London, Critical Quarterly Society). Darling, J. and Nordenbo, S.E. (2003) “Progressivism”, In: Blake, N. et al. (eds) The Blackwell Guide to
  • 44. Philosophy of Education (Oxford, Blackwell), pp. 288–308. Dearden, R.F. (1972) “Autonomy and Education”, In: Dearden, R.F., Hirst, P.H. and Peters, R.S. (eds) Education and Reason (London, RKP), pp. 390–397. Dewey, J. (1925) Democracy and Education (New York, MacMillan). Hirst,P.H. (1965) “Liberal Educationand the Nature of Knowledge”, In: Archambault, R.D. (ed.) (1965) Philosophical Analysis and Education (London, RKP); also in Hirst, P.H. (1974), Knowledge and the 3 An earlier version of this chapter was presented as the Ogata Lecture at the University of Tohoku, Japan. I am grateful to those present on that occasion, and to Morinichi Kato and Naoko Saito especially, for their comments and response. 50 PAUL STANDISH Curriculum (London, RKP); also in Dearden, R.F., Hirst, P.H., and Peters, R.S. (eds) (1972) Education and Reason (London, RKP). Mill, J.S. (1978) On Liberty (Indianapolis, IN, Hackett Publishing Company). Oakeshott, M. (1962) Rationalism in Politics and Other Essays, edited by Fuller, T. (London, Methuen). Rousseau, J-J. (1911) Emile (London, J.M. Dent). SED (1965) The Primary Memorandum (Edinburgh, Scottish Education Department). Taylor, C. (1991) The Ethics of Authenticity (London, Harvard University Press).
  • 45. Blindsided by the Avatar: White Saviors and Allies Out of Hollywood and in Education Julio Cammarota Any real change implies the breakup of the world as one has always known it, the loss of all that gave one an identity, the end of safety. And at such moment, unable to see and not daring to imagine what the future will now bring forth, one clings to what one knew, or thought one knew, to what one possessed or dreamed that one possessed. Yet, it is only when a man is able, without bitterness or self-pity, to surrender a dream he has long cherished or a privilege he has long possessed that he is set free—he has set himself free—for higher dreams, for greater privileges. —James Baldwin Every week I assist a social studies teacher with the implementation of a social justice government course at a Tucson high school located
  • 46. in Arizona. My role is to teach students qualitative research techni- ques so they can ‘‘read the world’’—in the Freirian sense (Freire 1993). The teacher provides the students with terms such as ‘‘cultural capital,’’ ‘‘social construction,’’ and ‘‘white privilege’’ so they can express critically the complexity of what they are ‘‘reading.’’ As part of a lesson on white privilege, the teacher whom I will refer to as Juan Gomez decided to show a trailer to the film, The Blind Side as evidence of the ‘‘white savior syndrome.’’ This was the first time that I had seen this trailer, and I was struck by the affect of the actors. Sandra Bullock’s character was fierce, bold, and eminently determined to change the world in ways that mat- tered to her. Quinton Aaron, who plays a young African American The Review of Education, Pedagogy, and Cultural Studies, 33:242–259, 2011 Copyright # Taylor & Francis Group, LLC ISSN: 1071-4413 print=1556-3022 online DOI: 10.1080/10714413.2011.585287 242 football player Michael Oher with many needs (i.e., housing, financial resources, emotional support), appears subdued, emotion-
  • 47. ally withdrawn, almost developmentally handicapped—with no real sense that he has the capacity to change the world in any way, shape, or form. Juan showed this trailer to demonstrate that Hollywood tends to make films based on this theme; young people of color can escape their predicament of marginalization through the guidance and agency of a lone white actor. Juan identified this theme as the ‘‘white savior syndrome.’’ After the trailer, we engaged students in critical media literacy (Alverman and Hogood 2000; Kellner and Share 2005, 2007). Students are often unaware of unjust representations and thus need critical media literacy, which cultivates ‘‘skills in analyzing media codes and conventions, abilities to criticize stereotypes, dominant values, and ideologies, and competencies to interpret the multiple meanings and messages generated by media texts’’ (Kellner and Share 2005, 372). Additionally, media is often how students learn about racial prejudices and privileges, as part of an encoded social logic of racist expression and exclusion. We started our media literacy lesson by querying the students about their general perceptions of The Blind Side. We drew from Freire’s (1993) approach of ‘‘problem-posing’’ by suggesting ques- tions to the students and facilitating a dialogue about the problems
  • 48. of the film. To our general question about their perceptions, many responded that they ‘‘liked the film,’’ or thought it was a ‘‘good story about helping someone out.’’ Our facilitator roles allow us to offer our positions and take responsibility as educators to stimulate dialogue in critical directions. Therefore, I interjected and mentioned how I thought the trailer represented the white female and black male in extreme, polarized ways. I told the stu- dents that the white female seemed strong, capable, and effective while the black male appeared dilatory, dour and even, perhaps, mentally challenged. Some students immediately defended the film saying that the African American character did not appear ‘‘mentally challenged’’ and that it was ‘‘good that he was being helped.’’ One student stated that she saw the entire film and that it ‘‘focuses more on the football player than on her (the white female).’’ Juan reminded the students that the trailer represents the white savior syndrome in which a white person guides people of color from the margins to the mainstream with his or her own initiative and benevolence. The movement occurs through the ‘‘smarts’’ of Blindsided by the Avatar 243 the lone savior and not by any effort of those being saved. The white savior syndrome has the tendency to render people of
  • 49. color incapable of helping themselves—infantile or hapless=helpless victims who survive by instinct. People of color supposedly lack the capacity to seek change and thus become perceived as dispos- sessed of historical agency. Any progress or success tends to result from the succor of the white individual, which suggests that escaping poverty or ignorance happens only through the savior’s intelligence. This assistance amounts to what Freire calls ‘‘false generosity’’ such that a white person may provide help to people of color yet help comes in the form of a saving action that tends to help a single individual or group. The focus on ‘‘saving’’ instead of ‘‘transform- ing’’ fails to address oppressive structures and thus the privileges that maintain white supremacy. False generosity is an ‘‘attempt to soften the power of the oppressor in deference to the weakness of the oppressed’’ (Freire 1998, 46). The teacher then contrasted his definition of white savior with white ally. According to Juan, a white ally is someone who does engage in what Freire calls ‘‘true generosity’’ by joining in soli- darity with people of color to struggle collaboratively against those institutions that maintain oppression. Solidarity involves sublimat- ing one’s ego and status so that people of color can provide empow-
  • 50. ered leadership in movements of liberation. A reduction of status requires challenging the very institutions and practices that proffer white privilege and power. Anything less would amount to ‘‘false generosity’’ such that support would at best make a difference to a handful of people as opposed to engaging in actions of solidarity that may lead to the dismantling of oppressive institutions and thus long-term change. True generosity requires of the oppressed ‘‘hands . . . extended less and less in supplication, so that more and more they become hands which work, and working, transform the world’’ (Freire 1998, 46). Although we problem-posed several questions to the students, they also have equal opportunity to pose their own questions. When Juan completed his statements about the white savior versus the white ally, an African American male student expressed, ‘‘But Blind Side is a true story! How could you criticize someone helping another human being?’’ Juan and I do not argue against the veracity and value of white people helping people of color. Significant social change can and 244 J. Cammarota
  • 51. does happen with the assistance of white allies. However, we are concerned, through an Althusserian symptomatic reading (Althusser and Balibar 1979), about what might be missing or even implicitly assumed in films like The Blind Side. In such cinematic treatments of race, people of color appear to lack the agency neces- sary to enact positive changes in their own lives. The underlying assumption is that people of color, on their own, fail to enact resili- ence, resistance, and success—as made gratuitously evident in the representation of Michael’s family life. Any achievements in these areas seem to result from the initiatives of the white savior. Further- more, these Hollywood narratives often miss or ignore how people and communities of color do successfully resist and overcome marginalization through their self-initiated agency. This article discusses how the white savior syndrome renders the misrepresentation of the potential of people of color to resist and lead the transformation of oppressive conditions within their own social context. Indigenous resistance requires endogenous (internal) leadership such that all social justice actions derive from and con- tinue to flow through communities of color and their leaders.
  • 52. White saviors represented in popular media overshadow the fact that people of color are part of and, most importantly, make history. For instance, the historical legend of Abraham Lincoln ‘‘freeing the slaves’’ eclipses the real efforts of myriad African Americans who resisted and fought against their bondage. In the school context, I discuss Ruby Payne’s (2005) work to underscore pseudo-educational approaches that avoid building leadership in communities of color while continuing to label them as deficient. This negligence results from the impact of racism shap- ing the worldview of the savior. Acceptance of Payne’s approach depends upon internalized racism influencing the perspective of the ‘‘saved.’’ In contrast, I examine the virtues of white allies and how they can help promote leadership among people of color by challenging the privileges that provide them with superior social status and legitimacy. The article concludes with a discussion of how racial justice can occur with the oppressed in leadership posi- tions and the oppressor adhering to and following this leadership. The existence of white saviors may help some people of color but it will not result in long-term systematic change. White allies can contribute to systematic change by abdicating both privileges and superior status while cultivating leadership within communities of color and relations of mutuality and respect. Blindsided by the Avatar 245
  • 53. WHITE SAVIORS IN HOLLYWOOD The Hollywood industry is a proponent of what Giroux and Giroux (2004) call ‘‘corporate culture’’ that shapes active ‘‘[c]itizenship’’ into a ‘‘solitary affair whose aim is to produce competitive, self-interested individuals vying for their own material and ideological gains’’ (252). The needs and interests of the individual, particularly the white male who possesses market power (social and cultural capital), supersedes the importance of people of color struggling to gain collective rights. The neoliberal logic driving corporate culture demands that the market regulates all social and economic practices, and the overarching principle regulating markets is competition (Lazzarato 2009, 117). Corporate culture facilitates a social climate of competition by feeding and managing inequalities so that individuals with power and status can dominate and succeed over marginalized others. In the competitive market, neoliberalism applies racial distinc- tions in the process of managing inequalities to ensure the dominant racial group maintains advantages and privileges in the practice of individualism. Goldberg (2009) asserts that neoliberalism shifts the
  • 54. focus of the state from public welfare to private concerns and ‘‘thus also ensures a space for extending socio-racial interventions— demographic exclusions, belittlements, forms of control, ongoing humiliations . . .’’ (334). This shift involves moving racial practices from the public to the private realm, thereby engendering a privati- zation of racism by securing racial exclusions, preferences, and privileges within the private world away from government inter- vention (Goldberg 2009, 339). Privatized racism is what Goldberg would refer to as ‘‘racial neoliberalism.’’ With the continued prevalence of racial practices promoting injustices, the neoliberal inclination toward individualism will proffer advantages to the dominant racial group in market-driven structures, such as capital- ism, private schools, and insurance managed health care. Hollywood films tend to gravitate toward the theme of the indi- vidual savior whose actions of saving others from themselves as opposed to addressing oppressive structures elide the possibility of recognizing social injustices and the need for collective action to secure rights and opportunities. The neoliberal logic of corporate culture highlights the savior as a model that narrows human agency to only the pursuit of individual success and gains. ‘‘Responsibility,’’ according to Susan Searls Giroux (2010), under 246 J. Cammarota
  • 55. ⼆ 在竞争性市场中,新⾃ 由主义在管理不平等现 象的过程中采⽤了种族 差异,以确保占主导地 位的种族团体在个⼈主 义实践中保持优势和特 the neoliberal regime initiated in the Reagan era ‘‘was divested of its social character; indeed . . . there was ‘no such thing as society’’’ (3). Thus, lost in neoliberalism is the recognition that subordination is not a failure of individual initiative but the result of a whole host of oppressive conditions including inadequate education, limited employment opportunities, unfair wages, and unjust discriminatory treatment. In the Hollywood ‘‘savior’’ film Avatar, the main protagonist and individual savior, in this case, is a white male marine, named Jake Sully whom the military plants to gain access and information from
  • 56. the indigenous people, the Navi of the moon Pandora. The narra- tive parallels the film Dances With Wolves in which Kevin Costner plays an Army captain who is sent to an outpost to protect white settlers from the Sioux Indians. Similar to Costner’s character, Jake Sully becomes enamored with the native people, even falling in love with the female Navi character Neytiri. Jake then decides to lead a resistance that saves Pandora from the colonizers. Avatar parallels Dances With Wolves so much so that one might consider the screenplay a twenty-first century version. New York Times editorialist, David Brooks (2010) writes that Avatar follows the oft-repeated story about a manly young adventurer who goes into the wil- derness in search of thrills and profit. But once there, he meets the native people and finds that they are noble and spiritual and pure. And so he emerges as their Messiah, leading them on a righteous crusade against his own rotten civilization. (27) This narrative, what Brooks calls the ‘‘White Messiah Fable’’ is prevalent in several Hollywood productions, including A Man Called Horse, The Last Samurai, and most notably,Dances With Wolves. We have seen this trope or fable many times before such that a film- maker ‘‘doesn’t have to waste time explaining the plot because everybody knows roughly what’s going to happen’’ (Brooks
  • 57. 2010, 27). The dominant theme in these films centers on colonized people who ‘‘possess not the . . .physical or intellectual capacity to compete with their European counterparts and thus have not the ability to adequately govern themselves, much less in times of adversity ergo the need for a White savior’’ (Meade 2010, 209). The natives appear the same way to the white savior in these films: always beautiful, spiritual, and reverent to God and earth. These qualities render the natives appealing to both audiences Blindsided by the Avatar 247 and white saviors. However, as Brooks (2010) correctly points out, ‘‘they are natural creatures, not history making ones’’ (27). Their agency is understated to a point in which the natives resemble elegant, graceful animals more than competent human agents. The lack of human agency among people of color is perhaps the most offensive aspect of the white savior productions. The oppressed have no other choice but to follow the leadership of oppressors who generally choose to oppress but occasionally choose to play the role of savior. These productions undermine the value of indigenous ideas for shaping the destiny of native people. Moreover, most native people would have been fine and not in need of rescuing were it not for the exploitation of the saviors’ people in the first place.
  • 58. In the social science class, Juan Gomez talked about the white savior syndrome in Avatar and The Blind Side. He pointed out that the films focus on the white savior’s deeds to the exclusion of the real conditions of oppression that put the ‘‘saved’’ in the predica- ment of needing to be ‘‘saved.’’ Avatar does, however, present a narrative of colonization, which students in southern Arizona understand intuitively from a similar colonial process afflicting the U.S.–Mexico border. However, Avatar fails to address the historical context of what Mendelsohn (2010) describes as ‘‘the scary and often violent confrontation between human and alien civilizations’’ (1). This failure leaves students with a lack of under- standing of how conflicts occur between civilizations (alien or human) or cultures along borders. In The Blind Side, the discussion of social and economic forces (i.e., racism, lack of affordable housing, unemployment, inferior education) impacting black communities is largely absent. The history of oppression and negative social and economic forces are missing in these films, yet their absence nonetheless allowed Juan Gomez and me ‘‘teachable’’ moments by filling in the historical silences. RESISTANCE OUT OF HOLLYWOOD History directly contradicts these films by exposing their untruths. Rather than awaiting white saviors, people of color do act in accordance with their own interests and in the interest of a more just society. Resistance leaders are often people of color
  • 59. struggling 248 J. Cammarota against white colonization, who end up either in prison, murdered or both. For instance, Puerto Ricans have struggled for liberation longer than the U.S. occupation, which began in 1898. Pedro Albizu Campos and Lolita Lebron are two of the most prominent Puerto Rican resistance leaders in the twentieth century. Campos was the leader of the Puerto Rican nationalist independence party from 1930 until his death in 1956. Because of Campos’ political actions for independence, the U.S. government arrested and then condemned him to more than 10 years in prison. He eventually died from radiation torture imposed while under arrest. Two years after the U.S. Congress voted to make Puerto Rico a permanent colony in 1952, Lolita Lebron entered the House of Representatives to shoot at her colonizers. Five representatives were injured in the shooting. She was also arrested, sentenced to 70 years in prison but served a ‘‘modest’’ 25 years for her actions. There have been other resisters like Campos and Lebron. Assata Shakur was falsely arrested for her involvement in the Black
  • 60. Panther party. After spending time in jail she escaped and fled to Cuba. She has been living there ever since her escape. Another Black Panther, Fred Hampton was shot and killed in Chicago by FBI agents, and the famed Soledad Brother, writer, and activist George Jackson, was also shot by a prison guard during an attempted escape. A young Angela Davis would also find herself the subject of repeated harass- ment by then Governor Ronald Reagan, placed on the FBI’s Ten Most Wanted list and incarcerated, even facing the death penalty, on absurdly trumped up charges. Leonard Peltier was jailed for his involvement in the American Indian Movement, and Mumia Abu Jamal is also suffering a similar fate on death row for his connection to the black liberation organization MOVE. There have not been any Hollywood films made about these resistance leaders. A film about a person of color standing up to white colonization would anger, intimidate, alarm, and thus ultimately fail with white audiences. Currently whites are still a majority in the United States and perhaps the most important racial group among movie-going consumers. However, the white savior syndrome in films like Dances With Wolves or even Avatar do more damage than good to the historical record. These films suggest that social change occurs through white leadership and that people of color in change processes occupy primarily the role of the victim
  • 61. as opposed to the victor. Perhaps the worst misrepresentation is Allan Parker’s Mississippi Burning, which depicts the FBI as key Blindsided by the Avatar 249 电影表明,社会变⾰是 通过⽩⼈领导⽽发⽣ 的,在变⾰过程中,有 ⾊⼈种主要扮演受害者 ⽽不是胜利者的⻆⾊ activists in the civil rights movement. This, in contrast to their actual roles as agents of repression under J. Edgar Hoover and his covert program of ‘‘dirty tricks,’’ COINTELPRO. Overshadowed in this film is the critical role of people of color organizations such as the Student Non-Violent Coordinating Committee and Southern Christian Leadership Council. Young people of color who consti- tute an important segment of moviegoers will have little to draw from models of leadership and positive, empowered roles to adopt in social change movements if movies continue to misrepresent the role of people of color in history. Apathy among people of color is a real concern because they are consistently bombarded with images of inferiority and
  • 62. victimiza- tion. Hollywood films sustain these messages via constant repetition and obfuscate the historical record. In the social studies class, Juan Gomez queried the students about their knowledge of film stars versus real educators. They were more familiar with Michelle Pfeiffer in Dangerous Minds than with Bob Moses of the Algebra project. When a picture of Jeffery Canada was shown to the students, he was not recognized. However, students recognized the white savior played by Hilary Swank in the film FreedomWriters. WHITE ALLIES IN HOLLYWOOD Occasionally Hollywood has made films about white allies in which the white leader stands in solidarity with the leadership and actions of people of color. Perhaps the best white ally example appears in the film, Glory, based on the true Civil War events of an all- black troop of the 54th Regiment led by the white Colonel Robert Gould Shaw, played by Matthew Broderick. Although the film does not accurately or fairly represent the African American perspective, it does shift the standard white leadership role from messiah to martyr (Stoddard and Marcus 2006). Colonel Shaw accepted the leadership assignment knowing that racism would prevent the troop from ever seeing battle. However, at the end of the movie, the Union forces needed to take a Rebel bunker to win a battle and the only troop available to fight was the 54th. The troop elected
  • 63. to fight knowing that the straight on attack of the bunker would lead to their deaths. The soldiers’ white ally, Colonel Shaw stood and fought shoulder to shoulder with them. Shaw and the soldiers were eventually killed but their defeat led to the enlistment of 250 J. Cammarota 150,000 African Americans, which Lincoln assessed as the turning point of the Civil War. In this example, the white ally Colonel Shaw assisted the African American soldiers with becoming agents of history by preparing and then fighting alongside them in battle. Matthew Broderick’s charac- ter sacrificed his status and power to stand with the soldiers and face death together while struggling against the forces of oppression. Although fighting alongside the African American soldiers was a suicide mission, a white ally does not have to give up his or her life to achieve solidarity. Alliance requires at minimum a symbolic death, more in the line with Amilcar Cabral’s ‘‘class suicide’’ in which one relinquishes social status to work collaboratively with the oppressed. Cabral asserts that allies with privilege and power who join
  • 64. move- ments of change should commit ‘‘suicide as a class in order to be reborn as revolutionary workers, completely identified with the deepest aspirations of the people to which they belong’’ (quoted in Rudebeck 2006, 94). Hierarchical positioning becomes inactive betweenwhite allies and people of color so that ideas andmovements emerge unilaterally with those united democratically on the ground. In order for Colonel Shaw to become an ally he had to dismount from his high horse, abdicating his status and power as an officer in this final moment and place his feet on the ground next to the foot soldiers. When the time to act and make history comes, the white ally must sacrifice his power so that the agency of the oppressed becomes central. THE WHITE SAVIOR OF EDUCATION Popular film culture not only undermines young people of color’s potential to become change agents but also reinforces and at times shapes the social policies that bear the greatest impact on their lives. For instance, Ruby Payne is perhaps the most influential individual with shaping teacher practices for poor students in this country. Although she focuses primarily on class and poverty, most exam- ples in her writings involve the work of students of color
  • 65. (Stinnent 2008). Nevertheless, many school districts that serve students of color have adopted her ‘‘framework’’ for professional development and teacher training (Sato and Lensmire 2009). Payne’s ideas are not much different than those espoused by the white saviors in Dangerous Minds, Freedom Writers, and The Blind Blindsided by the Avatar 251 Side. She perceives poor students of color existing in deficit such that they supposedly do not possess any knowledge or intellectual capacity beyond what they absorb from their more educated and economically stable teachers. The following represents how Payne (2005) characterizes poor students’ behavior in the classroom: She believes that they ‘‘laugh when disciplined, argue loudly, make angry responses, make inappropriate or vulgar comments, have hands on someone else, fail to follow directions, learn to be disor- ganized, unable to finish tasks, become disrespectful to teachers, harm others, cheat or steal, and talk incessantly’’ (79–80). Missing here is any sense of how students resist forms of teacher authority that relentlessly define students according to their alleged lacks— often as a matter of maintaining dignity.
  • 66. The ‘‘important’’ knowledge that poor people may procure reportedly derives from institutional or ‘‘official’’ instruction and not from any indigenous or local practices generated by their own initiatives. What she does report as indigenous knowledge is quite insulting. For instance, she claims, without supporting research, that poor people relative to middle-class folks know more about how to ‘‘buy guns, bail someone out of jail, function in laundromats, acquire food from grocery bins, and use duct tape’’ (Payne 2005, 53–58). Furthermore, Payne perceives poor students of color as lacking middle-class cultural capital, values, and behavior. The teacher’s job is to ensure that poor students learn middle-class culture and values, ‘‘and this very need characterizes them as deficient’’ (Stinnent 2009, 65). Once they assimilate to the middle-class value system, they supposedly become better off. This approach allows the educator to adopt a savior perspective and mistakenly see his or her role as saving the poor student by extirpating him or her from a culture of pathology and then remaking him or her into the image of the educator=savior (Sato and Lensmire 2009, 368). ‘‘Saving,’’ according to Michie (2007), ‘‘is not how real teaching works. Teaching . . . can only happen over time as trusting and mutually respectful relationships are built’’ (8). The savior perspec- tive in Payne’s method translates into a messiah complex,
  • 67. elevating educators to an artificially high level of self-importance and value for ‘‘feeding’’ their supposedly bereft students. This higher status buttressed by racism, classism, and general elitism allows white and wealthier people to feel superior over the supposedly down- trodden others. It would be hard for teachers to build trust with 252 J. Cammarota students who they believe to be from a much lower social position and perspective than them. Educational assimilation posits that people of low socioeconomic status lack the appropriate values to achieve success, and any lack of success or low status is the result of their personal deficiencies. This is an example of the way that the privatized racism of the neo- liberal order works. Inequalities are reduced to private character flaws (e.g., laziness, predilection for drugs, sex, etc.) rather than understood as (historically and currently) institutionally shaped and maintained. The deficiencies, according to Payne, are dimin- ished resources, but her definition of ‘‘resources’’ surpasses money. She includes ‘‘emotional, spiritual, physical, relational, and social resources’’ (Payne 2005, 16). However, repeated ethnographic
  • 68. stu- dies demonstrate the real resourcefulness and resilience of poor people (Edin and Lein 1997; Gregory 1998; Cammarota 2008). This research demonstrates that poverty presents political and economic restraints that may impose effects on human development yet sep- arate from cognitive and cultural realms. Some, in fact, argue that poor people cultivate valuable ‘‘funds of knowledge’’ or ‘‘cultural wealth’’ out of the necessity to negotiate and survive the harsh cir- cumstances of poverty (Velez-Ibanez and Greenberg 1992; Yosso 2005). The incorrect assumption that poor people lack resourceful- ness exonerates social or economic structures from any culpability in reproducing poverty and oppression generation after generation. Approaching poverty or any form of oppression as an individual behavioral problem evades the entire point about economic marginal- ity and low status. Society influences the social position one inhabits; the individual may have some say about his or her social status, but for the most part society plays a huge role with shaping status distinc- tions. Inmany societies, includingAmerica, social and economic prac- tices tend to organize individuals into gradients so that some people
  • 69. access greater power andwealth than others. This happens systemati- cally, and schools are part and parcel of this system of unequal distri- bution of wealth and power. Teaching down to poor students, as if they are unintelligent and culturally deficient, when coupled with the real material hardships they face, will only reproduce poverty. THE WHITE ALLY IN EDUCATION White allies adopt a significantly different position from white saviors. They realize they have privileges and work to undermine Blindsided by the Avatar 253 the very power that provides them with superiority. Beverly Tatum (1997) asserts that a white ally’s role should not be about ‘‘helping’’ people of color but rather about speaking ‘‘up against systems of oppression and to challenge other Whites to do the same’’ (109). Allies tend to redirect resources toward addressing racism, resources that would otherwise only be given to a chosen few.White allies, therefore, look to end oppression by challenging the neolib- eral logic of competitive individualism and privatization, then look-
  • 70. ing for fair and equal treatment for all—even at the expense of diminishing their status to share power with the oppressed. However, teacher educator Christine Sleeter (1993, 173) warns that many white teachers fail to accept and thus deal with the ‘‘paradox’’ of supporting students of color by challenging the racial neoliberalism that grants superior market status to whiteness. Rather, she notices patterned responses of avoidance that includes ‘‘colorblindness’’ or presenting the model of European immigrants as a way to demonstrate positive shifts in race relations. Bonilla- Silva (2002) asserts that whites may use rhetorical strategies to maintain color-blind racism. These strategies include the avoidance of racial terminology altogether, the use of semantic moves such as saying that they have ‘‘friends who are black’’ to deny accusations of racism, and the projection of racism onto the marginalized racial other by saying that ‘‘they are the racist ones, not me.’’ Addition- ally, there is the ‘‘Obama effect’’ in which people falsely assume a black president means a postracial America. Sleeter (1993, 174) recommends white teachers become allies by a process of reeducation that helps them analyze white privilege and the ways neoliberalism perpetuates racism through competitive individualism and de-regulated, market-based forms of resegrega-
  • 71. tion. This education begins with an immersion into a community of color in which the ally focuses his or her learning on the history of racism and those structures such as inferior education, depressed wages, and inadequate housing that maintain others’ subordinate statuses. Through this process, ‘‘teachers . . . are not just learning about other races but becoming committed to anti-racism as part of their own self-hood’’ (Thompson 2003, 14). The immersion can be integrated into field research experience in a teacher education program (Sleeter 2001). The outcome, according to Sleeter, from this deep immersion should be willingness to work collectively with people of color to end structural or institutional racism. This means that allies work in collaboration, not as leaders, not as saviors, but 254 J. Cammarota as engaged participants who share power in a democratic process. Esteva, Prakash, and Stuchul (2008) write [in]stead of pro-motion (which operates under the assumption that the people are paralyzed or are moving in the wrong direction), those taking initiatives at the grassroots to govern them autonomously or democrati-
  • 72. cally speak of co-motion—moving with the people, rather than moving the people. (99) White allies, therefore, should ‘‘follow people of color as they provide the leadership in the struggle for racial justice’’ (Gardiner 2009, 1). Following requires accepting and validating the oppressive experiences of people of color and acknowledging their critiques of the power of whiteness (Gardiner 2009, 1). ‘‘The White person,’’ according to Tatum (1997, 113), ‘‘who has worked through his or her own racial identity process has a deep understanding of racism and an appreciation and respect for the identity struggles of people of color.’’ White allies must engage leaders of communities of color in a dialogue based on this appreciation and respect, particularly as it pertains to the years of suffering caused by racism. This type of open and honest dialogue might be painful, and even the most well-intentioned ally might feel the need to retreat (Dickar 2008, 130). However, allies must become compassionate listeners and remain engaged in dialogue no matter how painful it becomes. FREEDOM FROM PRIVILEGE In this article’s epigraph, James Baldwin speaks of the need to abandon privilege. He refers to not only the privileges of racial superiority, but also that of pure ignorance. Somehow the
  • 73. vague- ness of insularity must cease so that hearts and minds open to the realities of human suffering. Our greatest and most nefarious privilege in America is the blatant willingness to turn a blind eye to our deepest social problems. Everyday, many live without shelter; brown and black men fill prison cells; workers lose their jobs; women experience violent abuse; gays and lesbians face unbearable threats; and migrants risk their lives for their survival. National dialogue about these daily tragedies is delimited to victi- mization at best. But this discursive turn proves a double-edged sword: victims are either to be pitied or scorned. More often than not, the problem supposedly lies with the victims’ choices and Blindsided by the Avatar 255 not with neoliberal policies that generate unfair wages, subpar education, and ineffective and rapidly disappearing social support. Those who benefit from the managed inequalities of racial neoliber- alism have the responsibility of correcting the disparities that result from it. Ignoring the social and economic inequalities of ongoing market-based residential segregation, labor exploitation, health disparities, racial profiling, and racially tracked schooling that influence the daily experiences of most people of color is the
  • 74. most guarded privilege in America. When we finally become ‘‘free’’ of this privilege, we will truly begin to address the entire range of human suffering. It is within this ‘‘freedom’’ that Baldwin asserts we will experience higher privileges—the rewards of ‘‘justice,’’ ‘‘peace,’’ and true ‘‘compassion,’’ inclusive of those under the weight of oppression. Removing the privilege of ignorance will cure our blindness and allow us to truly ‘‘read the world.’’ The false generosity of the contemporary white savior binds to the privilege of ignorance by failing to see how the maintenance of his or her higher status in relation to the oppressed perpetuates inequalities. Limiting people’s access to opportunities and resources also provides the context in which higher status individuals benefit from the hierarchical system they maintain. The savior requires exploiting his or her status to procure leadership positions and thus denying people of color the process of developing the agency required for long-term systematic change. Real change within struc- tural racism requires the leadership of people of color, because it involves the sharing of power to the point in which an affirmative democratic character will emerge in society. Sharing power for those members of dominant groups necessitates the abdication of status to clear space for the leadership of people of color. Once there are more progressive people of color in leadership positions, then the