SlideShare a Scribd company logo
1 of 26
Download to read offline
1 23
Argumentation
An International Journal on Reasoning
ISSN 0920-427X
Argumentation
DOI 10.1007/s10503-012-9280-9
On Some Aristotelian Sources of Modern
Argumentation Theory
Christof Rapp & Tim Wagner
1 23
Your article is protected by copyright and
all rights are held exclusively by Springer
Science+Business Media B.V.. This e-offprint
is for personal use only and shall not be self-
archived in electronic repositories. If you
wish to self-archive your work, please use the
accepted author’s version for posting to your
own website or your institution’s repository.
You may further deposit the accepted author’s
version on a funder’s repository at a funder’s
request, provided it is not made publicly
available until 12 months after publication.
On Some Aristotelian Sources of Modern
Argumentation Theory
Christof Rapp • Tim Wagner
Ó Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2012
Abstract Although he does not provide a general analysis of argumentation,
Aristotle is a highly influential source of modern argumentation theory. In his
treatises the Topics, the Sophistical Refutations and the Rhetoric, Aristotle presents
complementary aspects of a theory of sound arguments that are seen as the most
effective means of persuasion. Aristotle’s central notion of a deductive argument
(sullogismos) does not include references to an addressee, the situative context or
non-verbal aspects of communication, and thus differs from some modern views on
argumentation. A deductive argument in the Aristotelian sense is a sequence of
intellectual steps where the conclusion follows of necessity from the premises.
Aristotle does not relativize or relax this notion but takes other factors into account
by providing supplementary theoretical elements. For example, he reflects on
acceptable premises (endoxa), the adjustment of rhetorical arguments to the horizon
of the audience, methods of finding premises on the basis of argumentative schemes
(topoi), the use of non-argumentative means of persuasion, and a framework of
implicit discourse rules. Many of these themes are, albeit under a different name,
still discussed in modern argumentation theory.
Keywords Aristotle  Dialectic  Rhetoric  Deductive Argument  Topoi 
Persuasion  Fallacy
Ch. Rapp
Lehrstuhl für Philosophie III, Ludwig-Maximilians-Universität, Geschwister-Scholl-Platz 1,
80539 Munich, Germany
e-mail: Office.Ch.Rapp@lrz.uni-muenchen.de
T. Wagner ()
Institut für Philosophie, Humboldt-Universität zu Berlin, Unter den Linden 6,
10099 Berlin, Germany
e-mail: tim.wagner@hu-berlin.de
123
Argumentation
DOI 10.1007/s10503-012-9280-9
Author's personal copy
Aristotle’s writings provide a fundamental point of reference not only for historical
approaches to argumentation theory, but also for some important modern theories of
argumentation. This does not mean, of course, that all contemporary argumentation
theorists are necessarily Aristotelians in one way or another; it only implies that
down to the present day argument theorists have been profoundly inspired by
Aristotle’s theory of argumentation.
It is a remarkable coincidence that the founding fathers, as it were, of modern
argumentation theory (MAT), Chaı̈m Perleman and Stephen Toulmin, define their
projects by almost identical references to Aristotle: Both of them stress that logic in
the sense that Aristotle calls ‘‘analytical’’ must be complemented by a project that
corresponds to what Aristotle has delineated as ‘‘dialectic’’.1
They also converge in
emphasizing that this dialectical dimension has been unduly neglected by the recent
development of philosophical logic. Against the alleged one-sidedness of formal
logic they both appeal to ancient dialectic in general and Aristotelian dialectic in
particular for the study of real argumentation between concrete interlocutors in
concrete situations. What they actually understand by Aristotelian ‘‘dialectic’’ can
best be seen when one examines their own theories—theories which set the agenda
for major parts of an emerging, modern argumentation theory; the program that is
carried out in The Use of Arguments2
and in The New Rhetoric elaborates on
something like a blend of Aristotle’s Topics and Rhetoric, where Toulmin’s
argumentation scheme seems to be closer to the Topics, while the systematics of
Chaı̈m Perleman’s and Lucie Olbrechts-Tyteca’s work is closer to the Rhetoric.
Some subsequent developments of MAT put more stress on the notion of fallacy,
thus also taking Aristotle’s treatise Sophistical refutations into account.3
In all these
cases the recourse to Aristotle is significantly more than a revival of a historical
position. The adaptation of selected Aristotelian theorems by MAT presupposes
specific theoretical interests in the theory of argumentation and requires a
theoretical framework like the one that has emerged from certain developments
in twentieth-century philosophy. If we therefore speak of ‘‘Aristotelian sources’’ of
MAT, we do not imply that these theorists have just picked up ready-made
Aristotelian theorems that were waiting in textbooks and manuals to be rediscov-
ered; we express, on the contrary, our awareness of the fact that these theories
together with their Aristotelian ingredients are the result of the ongoing debate on
how one can make the best sense of the rich, but sometimes ambiguous and
inconsistent, Aristotelian material that has come down to us and of how this material
fits best with the theoretical interests we happen to have.
In this contribution we comment on just this sort of discussion; we try to lay bare
some of the presuppositions made by some of the main representatives of MAT
about the directions of the Aristotelian texts, and we attempt to point out theoretical
options that, to our mind, are present in the Aristotelian texts. Thus, we will touch
not only on Aristotelian theorems that were actually taken up by modern
1
Cf. Perelman and Olbrechts-Tyteca (1969, 5), and Toulmin (1986, 62).
2
Toulmin (1958).
3
Cf. e.g. Walton and Krabbe (1995), Woods and Walton (1989). On the state of the art in the study of
fallacies see van Eemeren and Grootendorst (2004, chapter 7).
Ch. Rapp, T. Wagner
123
Author's personal copy
argumentation theorists, but also on Aristotelian ideas that are congenial with
certain strands of MAT, but have not yet been explicitly used, finally on points
where the direction of the Aristotelian texts seems to diverge from the modern ideas
they inspired. Of course, we cannot do justice here to the complex state of
discussion in MAT, therefore, we let our agenda be informed by what strike us as
some of the core convictions of the aforementioned founding fathers of MAT, as
well as by a more or less random selection of recent developments in MAT that we
have lately encountered.
1 The Topics and the Rhetoric as Building Blocks of a Unified Theory
of Argumentation?
Let us start with an assumption that seems so obvious that it is seldom really
discussed, but almost always tacitly presupposed, namely the assumption that there
is something like a more or less coherent theory of argumentation in Aristotle. In
fact, there is no single work of Aristotle’s that systematically unfolds his
argumentation theory. The work that comes closest is Aristotle’s Topics—either
alone or together with its sister treatise the Sophistical Refutations. Still, if we look
into the Topics, we find instructions for a quite peculiar sort of discourse, namely the
dialectical examination of philosophical theses on the basis of accepted or
acceptable premises. The exercise that is pictured in the Topics is constrained by a
set of artificial rules that distinguishes the dialectical exercise sharply from more
natural, more conversational and more persuasion-oriented types of argumentation.4
If we look, however, into the Rhetoric—the other place in Aristotle that might be
associated with his argumentation theory—we do find ample material for an account
of persuasiveness; but, again, the types of arguments that are analysed or
recommended in the Rhetoric are inseparably connected with public speaking and
the narrowly defined occasions when these speeches have to be delivered: judicial
speeches in court, political speeches at people’s assemblies, and epideictic speeches
held at certain ceremonial events, most notably funerals.5
Given that neither the Topics nor the Rhetoric provide a general systematic
theory of argumentation, what do we mean, after all, by an ‘‘Aristotelian theory of
argumentation’’? Either we use this idea to refer selectively to particular
Aristotelian theorems or techniques (e.g. the use of topoi) or we use it assuming
that there is something like a more coherent underlying theory that can, in principle,
be pieced together from Aristotle’s works, even if this underlying theory is not
explicitly presented in any particular work. In following the second line of thought
we have to explore whether the scattered ingredients of an Aristotelian theory of
argumentation are interrelated in such a way that, taken together, they make up
something like a coherent whole. For such an enterprise it will probably help to
observe that the Topics and the Rhetoric can, up to a point, be seen as providing
complementary aspects of such a theory of argumentation. For this reason, the
4
Cf. Aristotle, Topics VIII.
5
Cf. Aristotle, Rhetoric I.3.
On Some Aristotelian Sources
123
Author's personal copy
question whether there is something like a coherent theory of argumentation in
Aristotle partly boils down to the issue of whether and how the two treatises or the
two projects that are carried out in the respective treatises are interrelated, and this
latter purpose, again, depends on some far from trivial assumptions concerning the
nature of Aristotle’s Rhetoric.
In what follows, we try to answer the questions of whether there is such a
common on-going project underlying both the Topics and the Rhetoric, and, if so,
how it might contribute to a unified or coherent theory of argumentation. To this
end, we would like to start off with a preliminary characterisation of both sub-
projects.
It is the declared purpose of the Topics to outline a method by which we can find
arguments for and against any given thesis, so that we will be able to attack or
defend it at will.6
Although this method might, in principle, have manifold
applications, the Topics applies it only to a specific kind of competition, in the
course of which one of two disputants has to defend one of a contradictory pair of
assertions, while his opponent tries to deduce the contradiction of the defendant’s
original claim from assertions to which the defendant has committed himself during
the debate. The aggressor, as it were, plays the role of the questioner, as he is the
one who asks the answerer to assent to certain statements that, once admitted, can be
used as premises for a final conclusion that contradicts the defendant’s original
claim.
Given this general setting, dialecticians as pictured in the Topics, are primarily
interested in conclusive arguments, as it is the very goal of such conversations to
compel the opponent to arrive at and assent to the intended conclusion. If the
dialectical arguments were of a less binding type and were only meant to propose or
suggest the step from the acceptance of certain premises to the acceptance of the
insinuated conclusion, there would be no means by which to make the opponent
accept a certain conclusion or give up his original claim. Some, mostly
inexperienced, disputants may be vulnerable to accepting arguments that appear
to be conclusive without really being so. It may happen that a disputant succeeds in
driving his thesis home with the help of such fallacious arguments; but when the
quality of the disputants’ arguments is assessed—and Aristotle mentions criteria for
this kind of assessment in the eighth book of the Topics7
—the disputant will be
criticized for using fallacious inferences.
Furthermore, the dialectician has to be interested in endoxa, in accepted,
acceptable or reputable assertions, as the answerer, in general, is committed to
accept assertions that are of the acceptable type, and as the answerer would be
foolish to accept assertions which are contrary to them (i.e. paradoxa in contrast to
endoxa).
The themes that are discussed in the dialectical disputations are taken from the
philosophical debates of Aristotle’s time. This is why the examples given for
dialectical theses are mostly general, not particular, in form; only the topoi from the
third book of the Topics are suitable for forming arguments about particular claims.
6
Cf. Aristotle, Topics I.1, 100a
18–21.
7
Cf. Aristotle, Topics VIII.11.
Ch. Rapp, T. Wagner
123
Author's personal copy
But this is not a major surprise since this third book is most likely an appendix or
even a later addition to the agenda of the second book of the Topics.
Just as the Topics is, thus, interested in conclusiveness and validity, the Rhetoric
deals with persuasiveness. And just as the Topics distinguishes between the valid and
the only seemingly valid, the Rhetoric distinguishes between what is persuasive and
what is only seemingly persuasive.8
Finally, just as the Topics promises to develop a
method by which we can argue for and against any given thesis, the Rhetoric attempts
to determine what can be considered persuasive on any given topic.9
Hence, both
disciplines, dialectic and rhetoric, are, in principle, thematically unrestricted and
attempt to determine the conclusive and the persuasive, respectively—regardless of
whether the case in question is rather true than false or rather good than bad. Still,
although the Rhetoric provides considerations that might be significant for persuasion
in all possible fields of discourse, the three-book treatise that has come down to us
under the title of rhêtorikê technê, turns out to be interested—as already indicated—
only in persuasion in the realm of public speaking. Due to this limited field of
application, the Rhetoric is mostly concerned with particular, non-general topics, such
as whether, say, Alcibiades is guilty or not, but not with what it means to be guilty in
general, or whether, for example, it is useful for the Athenians to build a wall here and
now, but not with whether walls in general contribute to the flourishing of a city,
let alone the question of what the flourishing of a city consists in.
It seems, then, that for Aristotle dialectic and rhetoric are, at least in some
respects, complementary: Dialectic applies to dialogical, face-to-face disputations
about general topics, while rhetoric applies to speeches delivered to mass
audiences on non-general, particular topics. Such a division of labour between the
two projects might be taken as an indication that there is something like an on-
going project involving the two disciplines of dialectic and rhetoric and the
corresponding treatises the Topics and the Rhetoric. However, we must not forget
that even if we take both treatises together, thus obtaining complementary aspects
of a general theory of argumentation, the Topics and the Rhetoric as such do not
provide a general, let alone exhaustive, analysis of argumentation; what we get
are, for example, analyses of particular, contingent issues presented to a public
audience and analyses of general philosophical questions discussed in the
characteristic question–answer format that distinguishes Aristotelian dialectics;
what we do not get, however, is an analysis of, say, arguments about particular
and contingent issues presented in a dialogical face-to-face-situation. Nor do we
get, if our description of the two sub-projects is right, the complementary analysis
of the persuasiveness of arguments in the non-public sphere (given that it is not
the purpose of dialectic to actually persuade or convince an opponent, but to bring
him take positions from which his original position can be defeated). We can
state, then, as an interim result that MAT is perfectly justified in assuming that, to
a certain extent, Aristotle’s Topics and Rhetoric present something like an on-
going project that covers different aspects of a general theory of argumentation.
At the same time it is important to note that none of these writings aims at
8
Cf. Aristotle, Rhetoric I.1, 1355b
15 et seq.
9
Cf. Aristotle, Rhetoric I.2, 1355b
26 et seq.
On Some Aristotelian Sources
123
Author's personal copy
explicitly developing such a general theory, but that all pertinent writings, the
Topics, the Rhetoric and the Sophistical Refutations confine themselves to certain
narrow fields of argumentative discourse; taken together they fill some important
spots on the map of different fields and types of argumentation, but they are far
from providing a complete picture.
2 Delineating Dialectic and Rhetoric
In the previous section we discussed the relation between the Topics and the
Rhetoric and the corresponding fields of dialectic and rhetoric with a view to the
possibility of a coherent Aristotelian theory of argumentation based on a division
of labour. The relation between dialectic and rhetoric, however, is significant in
at least one further respect: different strands of MAT associate themselves with
either dialectic or rhetoric. Up to a point this might be a question of different
terminologies and different traditions, but sometimes the association with one or
the other of these fields indicates actual differences in the theoretical approaches.
Quite tentatively, some of the self-declared dialecticians are more interested in
the difference between sound and fallacious arguments, and some of the
rhetoricians are more interested in all perlocutionary aspects of our speech acts.
The former display an interest in refraining from ‘‘merely’’ psychological
questions, while the latter warn against a too narrow notion of argumentation.
Hence, the delineation between dialectic and rhetoric is definitely an issue in
MAT.10
Against that background, it is natural that authors attempt to position their own
approaches by way of reference to Aristotle, who gave the first elaborate account of
the interrelation of both fields. Unfortunately, the reference to Aristotle and his
model for correlating dialectic and rhetoric does not lead to an unambiguous result,
because his statements to the effect that rhetoric is a counterpart to dialectic or an
offshoot of it11
have been deemed highly obscure. Notwithstanding the notorious
difficulties in understanding these formulas, it is beyond all doubt that for Aristotle
dialectic and rhetoric are similar, since neither discipline is conceived as an
epistêmê of a well-defined subject matter; both are rather concerned with arguments
for and against any given position; just as dialecticians command a technê by which
they can attack and defend any given (philosophical) thesis, the rhetorician is
supposed to command a technê in virtue of which he will be able, for example, to
accuse or defend any given defendant in court. Furthermore, both of them deal with
arguments derived solely from accepted or acceptable opinions, and not from
scientific principles. It is possible to delineate the common ground between dialectic
and rhetoric by such similarities. The most basic philosophical rationale, however,
10
Cf. the papers that are collected in van Eemeren and Houtlosser (2002) as well as van Eemeren’s
contribution to this issue.
11
Rhetoric is a counterpart to dialectic: Rhetoric I.1, 1354a
1; it is an offshoot of dialectic and the study of
character: I.2, 1356a
25–27, it is a part of dialectic: I.2, 1356a
30 et seq., it is similar to it: I.2, 1356a
31.
Ch. Rapp, T. Wagner
123
Author's personal copy
for Aristotle’s attempt to align rhetoric with dialectic becomes obvious from the
following train of thought:
The activity of persuasion is, as Aristotle points out at the beginning of the
Rhetoric, a kind of proof or proving.12
Why so? People are most convinced, or so
Aristotle says,13
when they take something to have been proven. It is therefore
legitimate to model the persuasive endeavour of the rhetorician as a kind of proof
(apodeixis). Given that all proofs are kinds of sullogismoi—which we take to be
deductive arguments—persuasion can essentially be described in terms of
sullogismoi, i.e. deductive arguments. What Aristotle seems to presuppose is that
persuasion essentially follows the structure of a deductive premise-conclusion
argument: In order to convince the audience of a suggested thesis or suggestion, the
orator has to infer this thesis from what the audience already believes. In a similar
vein, Aristotle claims in the De Anima that each doxa, each opinion in the proper
sense, derives from an inference (sullogismos)—and this is, in Aristotle’s view, the
reason why animals cannot have opinions in the proper sense.
Within whose purview does the deductive argument fall? We would probably say
within the purview of the logician. Aristotle, by contrast, says that it falls within the
purview of the dialectician14
—regardless of whether he simply had no word for
logic in our sense or whether he really meant that it is the dialectician, if anyone,
who is the real expert for all kinds or applications of the sullogismos.
However this may be, if it is true that all sullogismoi fall within the purview of
the dialectician and if the syllogistic, i.e. deductive, premise-conclusion structure is
essential for all persuasive endeavours, then it follows that rhetoric, if it is
concerned with persuasion, essentially relies on the part of dialectic that is
responsible for the sullogismos. Indeed, Aristotle says in the Rhetoric that it is the
dialectician who is in fact responsible for all kinds of sullogismos and that the
dialectician will also become the master of the rhetorical argument if he only
acknowledges the differences between the dialectical and the rhetorical sullogismos.
On this account, there is no fundamental conflict between dialectic and rhetoric.
Furthermore, if sound arguments guarantee the reasonableness of argumentation and
if arguments are thought to be an efficient means of persuasion, neither is there a
fundamental conflict between reasonableness and effectiveness. This, we think, is
the essential rationale behind the dialectical turn of rhetoric initiated by Aristotle;
against rhetorical predecessors who, from Aristotle’s point of view, were too much
concerned with effectiveness, he aspires to show that arguments are central to
persuasion and not less effective than certain techniques by which the rhetorician is
instructed to speak outside the subject. Of course, no argument is thought to be
persuasive as it stands; it is one of the most crucial ingredients of Aristotle’s
rhetorical theory of argumentation that the general dialectical account of arguments
must be adjusted to the hearers and the subject matters of a public speech. And it is
of course true that Aristotle’s theory of persuasion includes moments beside mere
argumentation: Among the three technical means of persuasion (pisteis) there are
12
Cf. Aristotle, Rhetoric I.1, 1355a
4 et sq.
13
Cf. Aristotle, Rhetoric I.1, 1355a
5 et sq.
14
Cf. Aristotle, Rhetoric I.1, 1355a
8–10.
On Some Aristotelian Sources
123
Author's personal copy
also the emotional state of the audience (pathos) and the character or credibility of
the speaker (êthos); to this list we might add the linguistic form (lexis) and the order
of the parts of speech (taxis). There have been many scholarly debates about how
these non-argumentative means of persuasion (or should they also be called
‘‘argumentative’’ in some way? See Sect. 6, below) are related to logos, argument15
;
however, there are many indications that the introduction of these non-argumen-
tative means of persuasion are not meant to relativize the central role of
argumentation; after all, almost three-fourths of the text of Rhetoric I and II are
dedicated to argumentation in the narrow sense, and when Aristotle turns to the
discussion of lexis in Rhetoric III, he stresses that this is only a secondary concern.16
Also, when Aristotle says that it is necessary not only to look at the argument, but
also to present oneself as a certain kind of person and to prepare the emotional state
of the audience, as rhetoric always aims at the judgment of the audience,17
it seems
as if the non-argumentative means are required just to stabilize the audience’s
judgment formation and thus to enhance the effect of the given arguments.18
However one construes these aspects of the Aristotelian theory in detail, it seems
clear that the model he offers for reconciling dialectic and rhetoric is one in which
rhetoric is firmly based on dialectic, and rhetorical effectiveness is thought to flow
from reasonable arguments—assuming they are suitably chosen—and to not ask too
much of the audience of a public speech.19
3 Aristotelian Arguments and MAT Argumentation: A Mismatch?
Every argumentation theory should include an elucidation of what it is to be an
argument and what is meant by ‘‘argumentation’’. It is not entirely trivial, however,
to map Aristotle’s contributions to the definition of arguments onto the consensus of
MAT. As for MAT, there are, of course, many different approaches to defining
arguments and argumentation. There are, however, some recurring characterisations
that we would like to take as a starting point. Toulmin, to begin with, emphasizes
that while formal logic is concerned with propositions, argumentation theory deals
with concrete utterances.20
In a similar vein, Perelman loves to contrast
demonstration with argumentation: While demonstration proceeds in an impersonal
and abstract way, argumentation is always addressed at somebody; it ‘‘aims at
gaining the adherence of minds’’.21
Finally, in van Eemeren and Grootendorst
15
For a brief and useful overview see Kienpointner (2011, 10–12).
16
Cf. Aristotle, Rhetoric III.1, 1403b
18–20.
17
Cf. Aristotle, Rhetoric II.1, 1377b
21–24.
18
For an elaboration of this view, see Rapp (2012).
19
Put in such general terms, this goal seems to be congenial with more recent developments in MAT:
‘‘The Aristotelian rhetorical norm of successful persuasion is not necessarily in contradiction with the
ideal of reasonableness that lies at the heart of the pragma-dialectical approach’’ (van Eemeren and
Houtlosser 1999, 165). We owe this reference to Kientpointner (2011).
20
Cf. Toulmin (1996).
21
Cf. e.g. Perelman and Olbrechts-Tyteca (1969, 14), Perelman (1994, 85).
Ch. Rapp, T. Wagner
123
Author's personal copy
argumentation is defined as ‘‘a verbal, social, and rational activity aimed at
convincing a reasonable critic of the acceptability of a standpoint by putting forward
a constellation of propositions justifying or refuting the propositions expressed in
the standpoint.’’22
Let us leave it at that for the moment and go back to Aristotle.
First, it seems that there is no single word or terminus in Aristotle equivalent to
‘‘argument’’. In Topics I.12 he writes that there are two kinds of dialectical logos,
and then he hastens to distinguish between sullogismos and epagôgê—which is best
rendered as deductive and inductive argument. What most nearly approximates the
notion of an argument in this context is logos—but this word’s lack of specificity is
almost proverbial. The most neutral meaning in this context is that a logos is a
sequence of words, but this reading renders the division into exactly two kinds
inappropriate. Of course, logos can also be translated as ‘‘reason’’—the faculty of
reasoning as well as the reasons we can give. That arguments have to do with
reasoning is clear, as is the fact that providing reasons for what we maintain is close
to the notion of arguing. It seems, then, that due to these several ingredients,
Aristotle finds it natural to use the word logos as a generic term for what the two
irreducible forms of argument, sullogismos and epagôgê, have in common. In the
same chapter of the Topics Aristotle also states that an epagôgê is given when we
proceed from the particular to the general.23
This is why epagôgê came to be
translated as ‘‘induction’’ or ‘‘inductive argument’’. In the Rhetoric Aristotle briefly
revisits the issue of induction and tells us that the rhetorical form of induction is an
example of an argument which proceeds not from the particular to the general, but
from one particular to another.24
The sad truth about the theory of induction in
Aristotle is that this is almost all he has to say about it. In both treatises, the Topics
and the Rhetoric, he hastens to get back to the sullogismos, and in both fields,
dialectic and rhetoric, he seems to be almost oblivious to the inductive form of
argumentation and models both dialectical disputation and rhetorical persuasion
almost entirely in terms of ‘‘syllogistic’’, i.e. sullogismos-based, reasoning. Possibly,
this privileging of the sullogimos can be partly relativized, as Eggs (1992, 918)
suggests, if we assume that in some passages the word sullogismos takes over the
role of the missing generic concept for both forms of arguments, but it remains true
and indisputable that major parts of Aristotle’s argumentation theory are centred
around the notion of sullogismos, while the corresponding inductive form of
argumentation is widely neglected.
What is meant in Aristotle by sullogismos? Aristotle defines the sullogismos as an
argument in which, certain things being supposed, something different from the
suppositions results of necessity from them.25
According to this definition, the
sullogismos is roughly what we would call a deductive argument; it is remarkable
that this definition does not refer to the syllogistic theory that is developed in the
Prior Analytics. This means that when Aristotle speaks of the sullogismos in the
Topics and the Rhetoric (which, by the way, uses the same definition of sullogismos)
22
Cf. van Eemeren and Grootendorst (2004, 1).
23
Cf. Aristotle, Topics I.12, 105a
13 et seq.
24
Cf. Aristotle, Rhetoric I.2, 1357b
25–36.
25
Cf. Aristotle, Topics I.1, 100a
25–27.
On Some Aristotelian Sources
123
Author's personal copy
we should not expect the formally restricted canonical sullogismos that we know
from the syllogistic theory, with exactly two premises and three terms, one of which
is the middle term, etc. The Topics seems to be entirely untouched by this theory
and hence it is no surprise that the arguments we do find in the Topics and in the
Rhetoric do not obey to any formal restriction of this kind. That they are formally
less rigid than the arguments from Aristotle’s syllogistic theory does not mean,
however, that they are meant to be logically more relaxed. On the contrary, the
definition quoted makes clear that the conclusion of a sullogismos is something that
follows of necessity from the premises.
According to Aristotle’s definition, it is certainly true of the sullogismos that it
includes a constellation of propositions put forward in order to justify the
proposition that is expressed as the conclusion. On the basis of the same definition it
seems, however, that the justification is only seen as successful if the conclusion
follows of necessity from the premises. In comparison to modern accounts, which
only expect that in argumentation we try to make our standpoint more acceptable or
reasonable or that we justify it one way or another, this would be a much more
severe constraint. It is also clear that the notion of the sullogismos is neutral with
respect to the difference between demonstration and (dialectical) argumentation.
The definition of the sullogismos that is used either with scientific principles in order
to provide a scientific demonstration or with (only) accepted opinions in order to
serve as a dialectical argument is the same in both cases. This corresponds to the
fact that, as opposed to the MAT definitions we mentioned, the audience and the
expected effect on the audience is not mentioned in Aristotle’s definition of the
sullogismos.
On the basis of this brief and preliminary comparison we can state the following
possibly substantial discrepancies (disregarding the fact that, as we said, the notion
of sullogismos covers only one of the two species that fall under the generic notion
of argument): (1) In comparison to a rich notion of argumentation that includes a
reference to the addressee the notion of the sullogismos seems to be rather
underdetermined. Looking from this perspective, it seems promising not to take the
‘‘bare’’, as it were, notion of sullogismos as possibly equivalent to the MAT notion
of argumentation, but to look at the class of arguments with ‘‘endoxic’’ premises, i.e.
premises that are accepted by certain addressees.26
(2) According to some—not
all—MAT-accounts of argumentation, the addressee’s readiness to find a standpoint
acceptable can be increased by many means, both verbal and non-verbal, and not
only by putting forward premise-like constellations of propositions. From this point
of view, the Aristotelian premise-conclusion model of argumentation may seem too
narrow. One possible response would be to include means of persuasion that do not
belong to logos, as Aristotle puts it, in the notion of argumentation (see Sect. 6,
below); there is the risk, however, that we might broaden the notion of
argumentation to the point where everything that is possibly persuasive is rated
as argument, which is most probably not Aristotle’s intention. Another, more
conservative response would be to look for places where Aristotle himself
cautiously broadens the concept of argument. One such passage, e.g., would be the
26
See Sect. 4, below; there will be, however, different uses of the accepted premises.
Ch. Rapp, T. Wagner
123
Author's personal copy
discussion of maxims in Rhetoric II.21, where Aristotle acknowledges that
arguments can be given without the explicit use of the premise-conclusion scheme:
In the maxims ‘‘Being a mortal, do not cherish immortal anger’’ or ‘‘A mortal
should think mortal, not immortal, thoughts’’ the reason is, as Aristotle says,
implicitly given by the mention of ‘‘mortal’’.27
(3) The conviction that deductive
arguments are nearly omnipresent (Aristotle defines the sullogismos as deductive
argument and finds sullogismoi in everything from logic and dialectic to scientific
demonstration and rhetoric) seems to be absent from most MAT schools. Even those
who are concerned about the reasonableness of argumentation need not require all
acceptable arguments to be deductive; quite often it seems to be sufficient that the
transition from a premise to a conclusion seems to be reasonable—but not
necessary—under the given circumstances. This would be a substantial discrepancy.
For this reason it seems that Aristotle’s notion of an argument can be adapted to
MAT and fully modernized only if we can find hints of more ‘‘relaxed’’ notions of
argument in Aristotle. It is widely held that one can find such a notion in Aristotle’s
Rhetoric. Let us briefly examine this possibility:
Taking up a terminus from traditional rhetoric, Aristotle calls the rhetorical form
of proof an ‘‘enthymeme’’. Again and again he stresses that the enthymeme28
is a
kind of sullogismos or that it is the rhetorical form of the sullogismos, i.e. of the
deductive argument, while the example is the rhetorical version of the inductive
argument. As we have already said, Aristotle even invokes the dialectician’s
expertise in all kinds of sullogismos for the construction of enthymemes. Even the
advocates of ‘‘relaxed’’ arguments must admit that so far this entire setting does not
indicate any relaxation for rhetorical arguments. They therefore take recourse to the
definition of the enthymeme in Aristotle’s Rhetoric, where they try to detect
indications of a more relaxed way of arguing. In fact, the definition of the
enthymeme slightly modifies the standard definition of the sullogismos that we
discussed above; in rhetoric we speak of an enthymeme, Aristotle says, when,
‘‘certain things being the case, something different beside them results because of
their being either universally or for the most part the case.’’29
The most
controversial modification of the standard definition obviously lies in the
qualification ‘‘for the most part’’. On the one hand, if this qualification was meant
to qualify the inference itself—indicating that the conclusion does not follow of
necessity, but only for the most part—then, indeed, the idea of a deductive argument
would have to be abandoned. On the other hand, it is also possible to understand this
definition as saying that the premises maintain something to be the case either
universally or (only) for the most part. This latter reading would qualify the status of
the premise(s), not the inference itself. One could argue now, from a modern point
of view, that a premise that holds only for the most part or is only probable does not
allow for any necessary, but only for probable inferences. Again, this would result in
a remarkable deviation from, and a relaxation of, the deductive model. However, it
27
Cf. Aristotle, Rhetoric, II.21, 1394b
20–25.
28
There is a long-standing tradition that takes the enthymeme to be an incomplete syllogism. This is not
Aristotle’s view: see below, Sect. 4.
29
Cf. Aristotle, Rhetoric. I.2 1356b
15–17. For a different interpretation cf. Burnyeat (1994).
On Some Aristotelian Sources
123
Author's personal copy
seems that this is not Aristotle’s view, for he seems to be happy with saying that
what follows from a for-the-most-part premise is a for-the-most-part conclusion, but
that this modally qualified conclusion still follows of logical necessity (‘‘If such-
and-such is for the most part true, then it follows of necessity that something else is
for the most part true’’). On this account, Aristotle is being generous in granting that
due to the contingent subject matter of a public speech the premises and the
conclusions of rhetorical arguments very rarely express necessities, but he is still
insistent on his view that the deductive scheme can be used for relating for-the-
most-part premises to for-the-most-part conclusions.30
In recent scholarship the deductivist reading of Aristotle’s enthymemes has come
under scrutiny by interpreters who are obviously interested in bringing Aristotle
closer to the insights of MAT. Here, it seems quite clear that it is not Aristotle who
inspired MAT, but MAT that encouraged certain readings of Aristotle. Whichever
reading will prevail in the long run, it seems fair to say that Aristotle heavily relied
on his deductive scheme, that he stressed the less stringent character of rhetorical
premises rather than the possibility of less rigid inferences and that, if he was really
willing to deviate from the deductive scheme, he was not quite explicit in doing so.
4 Paying Attention to the Addressee’s Convictions and Capacities
As we said at the outset of this paper, MAT sets itself off from the analytic part of
logic or from the fixation on formal aspects of arguments by emphasizing that all
arguments are directed to concrete addressees with individual convictions. If
argumentation in general, as for example Perelman stresses,31
aims at increasing the
addressee’s readiness to approve a suggested point of view, a substantial account of
argumentation has to take into account what different groups of hearers are
convinced of and how arguments can be adjusted to the convictions of the people
they address.
If we look for an equivalent interest in Aristotle, we will first be faced with his
highly developed account of the role of endoxa—accepted, acceptable or reputable
opinions that play a major role in both his Topics and his Rhetoric. The dialectical
argument is defined by Aristotle as an argument, sullogismos, from accepted or
acceptable (endoxa) premises. This is what distinguishes dialectical from scientific
arguments,32
as the latter have to apply premises that are true (i.e. established as
true) and, as Aristotle puts it, ‘‘first’’. For the dialectical disputation, it does not
matter whether the deployed premises are true or not; it suffices that they are
acceptable and that they have actually been accepted or granted by the dialectical
interlocutor. Neither does it matter whether the defendant who grants a certain
premise is personally convinced of the truth of this premise or not. Due to the rules
30
At this point the supporter of relaxed rhetorical arguments could refer to one type of the sign-
enthymeme, which, as Aristotle says, does not yield a sullogismos, but is nevertheless rated as
‘‘enthymeme’’. The status of such arguments, however, is precarious, since in some passages Aristotle
treats them straightforwardly as fallacies (see below, Sect. 7).
31
Cf. Perleman and Olbrechts-Tyteca (1969, § 3 et seqq).
32
Cf. Aristotle, Topics I.1, 100a
29–100b
23.
Ch. Rapp, T. Wagner
123
Author's personal copy
of a dialectical disputation, he has no choice but to accept it if it is accepted by all,
by most or by the experts—provided he cannot come up with a counterexample. For
the rhetorician, on the contrary, everything depends on whether he is able to provide
premises that coincide with the convictions of the audience. It is the fundamental
idea of Aristotle’s technique of persuasion that it is possible to bring an audience to
an intended conclusion by appealing to the audience’s extant convictions and by
inferentially connecting these pre-existing convictions with the insinuated conclu-
sion. For this reason, the endoxa, the acceptable assertions that are used by the
rhetorician, are only a subset of the assertions that can be considered by the
dialectician; in a word, the rhetorician is not interested in the variety of accepted
opinions, but only in what a given audience might possibly be convinced of. In
dialectic, it is not the aim of the dialectical competitor to change the opponent’s
conviction or attitude; he can be content if he succeeds in compelling the competitor
to accept the insinuated conclusion; in rhetoric, by contrast, the rhetorician is
expected to steer the audience’s judgment formation up to the point that people give
their vote or cast their ballot in accordance with what the rhetorician suggests. To
achieve this, the rhetorician cannot rely on the audience’s willingness to obey
certain procedural rules (as the dialectical competitors are bound to do). Either the
rhetorician succeeds in tracing the intended conclusion back to the audience’s pre-
existing convictions or he has no influence whatsoever on what they decide.
We can then say that although both dialectic and rhetoric make use of accepted
opinions, endoxa, they do not use the same set of endoxa, they do not use them for the
same purpose and they do not use them in the same way. Although all dealings with
endoxa fall within the purview of the dialectician, it is the field of rhetoric that
applies the use of endoxa in a way that comes close to the interests of MAT to
systematically include the addressee’s individual conviction or mental horizon in the
study of arguments. In a similar vein, Aristotle says in the Rhetoric that whatever is
persuasive is persuasive to somebody.33
However, he admits that not even the
rhetorician can pick out individual convictions, but must confine himself to what is
persuasive to people of a certain general type.34
In practice, when the orator is
confronted with a mass audience he often has to start from quite general or
widespread convictions (koina),35
without being able to do justice to individual
preference or to preferences of certain groups (e.g. the young, the elderly, the rich,
the poor, etc.36
)—however that might be, this is one example where we could say that
although the scope of Aristotle’s is quite limited (here: limited to the expectations of
a mass audience of a public speech), the theoretical instrument for generally
incorporating the convictions and expectations of the addressees is actually present.
Beside the system of the endoxa, there is another important aspect of how
Aristotelian rhetoric tries to adjust arguments to the addressee’s intellectual horizon:
when Aristotle describes the peculiarities of rhetorical arguments, to which he
33
Cf. Aristotle, Rhetoric I.2, 1356b
26 et seq.
34
Cf. Aristotle, Rhetoric I.2, 1356b
28–34.
35
Cf. Aristotle, Rhetoric I.1, 1355a
27.
36
Cf. Aristotle, Rhetoric II.12–17. Perelman and Olbrechts-Tyteca (1969, 20), refer to these chapters as
contributions to the rhetorician’s knowledge of the audience.
On Some Aristotelian Sources
123
Author's personal copy
assigns the traditional rhetorical term ‘‘enthymeme’’, he stresses that the rhetorical
proofs must not be taken from ‘‘too far away’’, because the typical hearer of a public
speech is supposed to be a simple person who is not able to follow long chains of
argument.37
Due to a long-standing interpretative tradition which understands
Aristotelian enthymemes to be abbreviated arguments in which one of the required
premises is suppressed, commentators have often taken this remark as a comment
on the suppression of premises. In fact, what Aristotle says is that enthymemes must
not be as precise as a scientific demonstration and that they should be shorter than
ordinary dialectical arguments. This, however, is not to say that the enthymeme is
defined by incompleteness and brevity. The orator can avoid lengthy chains of
arguments by selecting the right premises, i.e. premises that are not too far from the
intended conclusions. On this reading, it seems that it is essential for the rhetorical
argument that it be adjusted to the capacity, expectation and intellectual horizon of
the given audience. The drawback, however, is that Aristotle’s effort to adjust
arguments to public audiences remains rather one-dimensional, as all these
arrangements are made with a view to the intellectual insufficiency of a public
mass audience.
5 The Uses of Topoi
We have already said that in the Rhetoric the sullogismos falls within the purview of
the dialectician. Part of this purview certainly consists in a sullogismos in the way
we discussed above in Sect. 3. It is likely, however, that the dialectician’s
competence also includes the ability to discern valid and invalid arguments or to
overlook, in general, the manifold ways in which such sullogismoi can be construed.
In the Topics the long catalogues of topoi seem to present different ways of
construing such deductive arguments. If we regard the topoi as something like
argumentative schemes, acquainting ourselves with these schemes will help us to
identify valid arguments, just as acquainting ourselves with a list of possible
fallacies will help us to detect deceptive arguments. At the same time, the catalogue
of topoi can be seen as a manual for the construction of arguments. How exactly the
topoi guide us in finding and constructing arguments is a controversial issue.38
The
minimal scholarly consensus is that the topoi are meant to be useful for the
construction of premises for a given conclusion. This means that we already have to
know the conclusion we intend to draw (within the dialectical game this is the
contradiction of what the opponent says), and that the topos helps us to construe a
premise from which we can deduce the intended conclusion—provided the
opponent assents to this premise. In the literature this is often called the ‘‘inventive’’
function of a topos. According to this inventive function the topos contributes to the
task of premise selection (although it is not the topos itself that determines whether
the required premise is an endoxon or not). We, at least, think that the topos has not
37
Cf. Aristotle, Rhetoric I.2, 1357a
17–22.
38
Cf. De Pater (1965) and the introduction to Brunschwig (1967); for a brief summary of the scholarly
discussion see also Wagner and Rapp (2004, 29–35).
Ch. Rapp, T. Wagner
123
Author's personal copy
only this inventive but also a probative function in that it also guarantees the
transition from the premises to the conclusion (if the topos, e.g., says that whatever
holds of the genus, must also hold of each species, then the same topos is a warrant,
as it were, for the transition from a premise concerning a particular genus to a
conclusion about its species).
What we should add about the use of topoi is this: the use of topoi is essential for
both projects, the Topics and the Rhetoric. In the Topics the topoi deployed are not
dependent on specific subjects or themes. Therefore, the topoi here are mostly taken
from semantic, logical or otherwise general rules. In the Rhetoric Aristotle
distinguishes between general and specific topoi, where the general correspond to
the topoi of the Topics39
and the specific are such in the sense that they can only be
used to construe arguments with a specific predicate, for example arguments about
what is good, just or noble. If Aristotle says that the latter type of topoi, the specific,
are more appropriate for rhetorical use, this certainly reflects the difference we
already alluded to, i.e. that dialectic is mostly about general topics, while rhetoric
aims at judgments about particular states of affairs.
The Aristotelian technique of topoi has generally met with sympathy and
approval by the proponents of MAT. Quite generally, the Aristotelian topoi are
often invoked as ‘‘role models’’ when the notion of an argumentation scheme is
introduced. In particular, Toulmin’s general analysis of the structure of argumen-
tation introduces the important notion of an ‘‘inference warrant’’,40
and it has often
been observed that the role of these warrants resembles that of the topoi in
Aristotle41
—at least in its probative function. In legal theory Viehweg appealed to
Gian Battista Vico’s contraposition of the old rhetorical/topical and the new critical/
geometrical method42
; Viehweg attempts to show that within the realm of
jurisprudence, the topical method (for which he explicitly refers to Aristotle and
Cicero) is far superior to the axiomatic-systematic approach. Perelman, too, often
highlights that in jurisdiction there are remnants of the old rhetorical art of
argumentation. He regards Aristotelian topoi as the most general premises, but
wishes to distinguish his own use of loci from the Aristotelian one; first, he attempts
to get rid of what he takes to be a metaphysical contamination of Aristotelian
39
Even if most of the general topoi in the Rhetoric are not really general in the same sense as the topoi of
the Topics are; most are general only in the sense that they can be used in all three genres of speech, while
the specific ones are always peculiar to one such genre or to one of the key notions of a genre, ‘‘just’’ in
the judicial speech, ‘‘good’’ in the forensic speech, and ‘‘noble’’ in the epideictic speech. Still, the notion
of a general topos in the Rhetoric clearly refers back to the project of the Topics, though only five out of
28 general topoi in Rhetoric II.23 clearly resemble the topoi of the Topics (1397a
7–19, 1397a
20–23,
1397b
12–174
, 1397b
174
–27, 1399a
6–9). Insofar as the topoi in the Topics rest on, as we have said,
semantic, logical or otherwise general rules it makes little sense to stress, as Warnick (2000, 111 et seq.)
does, the cultural dependency of these topoi. As an example Warnick introduces the topos from the
opposites—that if a and b are opposites and a has the quality q, the opposite of quality q can be predicated
of b. To our mind, this is just one application of Aristotle’s complex logical system of opposites and does
not indicate specific cultural preferences. Revealingly, Warnick uses the example that Aristotle gives
afterwards to make her point, not the general scheme.
40
Cf. Toulmin (1958, Chapter 3).
41
Cf. Bird (1961).
42
Cf. Viehweg (1963, §§ 1–2).
On Some Aristotelian Sources
123
Author's personal copy
topoi,43
and second, he tries to preserve the term for premises about what is valuable
and preferable.44
Others have tried to show that the argument schemes that
Perelman and Olbrechts-Tyteca unfold in The New Rhetoric45
broadly correspond to
the common topoi in Aristotle’s Rhetoric II.23. Indeed, several accounts of
argumentation schemes have been development in MAT quite independently from
Aristotle, but with an awareness of the historical origins of such schemes, e.g.
Kientpointner and Walton, to mention only two, have worked extensively on such
an argumentation theory.46
Kienpointner and Rigotti have also stressed the
inventive/generative aspect of Aristotelian topoi; Rigotti has even labeled them as
‘‘argument generators’’.47
Tetens observes that formal logic is of limited use for
argumentation training. He refers to the ancient tradition in general and the
Aristotelian tradition in particular, which abstracted paradigmatic arguments to
more general argumentation schemes which are limited to certain fields and themes,
and are not universally applicable. The formulation of such argumentation patterns
and the use of such patterns in making students sensible of differences between
good and bad argumentation belong, as Tetens puts it, to the realm of topics, as
originally formulated by Aristotle.48
In the light of these few examples it seems that the success of Aristotle’s
technique of topoi in MAT is undisputed. We would nevertheless like to point out
some differences between Aristotle’s use of topoi and the various uses that MAT
has made of them:
43
What Perelman means by ‘‘metaphysical’’ is Aristotle’s system of the four predicables (definition,
accidental predicate, genus, proprium), by which the topoi of the Topics are structured and from which
many of the general rules that make up the topoi are taken. It is certainly true that, e.g., the difference
between essential and accidental predicates rest on a certain metaphysics; it is still disputable whether this
topical system is therefore ‘‘metaphysically loaded’’. After all, the way in which the predicables are
introduced in the Topics gives clear criteria for the distinction of four sorts of predicates and does not
appeal to specific theorems of Aristotle’s metaphysics.
44
This is obviously the reason for Perelman’s somewhat surprising interest in the topoi of Aristotle,
Topics III (Cf. Perelman and Olbrechts-Tyteca 1969, § 21, and Perelman 1994, Chapter II.4). This narrow
focus is surprising, since, as we already said, the topoi of book III of the Topics are in several respects
exceptional within the Topics, most notably because they (also) apply to practical-particular and to
philosophical-general questions.
45
Cf. Warnick (2000, 109): I. The quasi logical ones: contradiction, incompatibility (1), identity,
definition, analyticity, tautology (2), reciprocity, rule of justice (3), transitivity, inclusion, division (4),
weights, measures, probabilities (5), II. The ones based on the structure of reality: (liaisons of succession
(6), liaisons of coexistence (7), symbolic liaisons, double hierarchies, differences of degree and order (8),
III. The ones establishing the structure of reality: example (9), illustration (10), model and anti-model
(11), analogy and metaphor (12), IV. Dissociation.—To be honest, we find not only Warnick’s general
account of the general topoi questionable (see footnote 39 above), but also regard many of the similarities
between Aristotle and The New Rhetoric she wishes to discover quite superficial. The problem is that
many of the common or general topoi of the Rhetoric are—due to Aristotle’s use of historical speeches—
too narrowly formulated and not really abstracted from the examples used.
46
Cf. Kienpointner (1997). Among the many titles by Walton we just want to mention one of his most
recent works on argumentation schemes: Walton et al. (2008). This latter book generously includes a
historical survey of argumentation schemes (chapter 8). Unfortunately, the section on Aristotelian topoi
turns out to be quite distorting, so that no informative conclusion about Walton’s view of Aristotle can be
drawn. For Kienpointner on Aristotle see Kienpointner (2005, 2011).
47
Cf. Rigotti (2007).
48
Cf. Tetens (2011), in particular, 491 et seqq., see also Tetens (2004, 54).
Ch. Rapp, T. Wagner
123
Author's personal copy
Quite often when Aristotle’s technique of topoi is invoked by MAT-authors the
topical approach is used to construe a contrast between the topical method and all
sorts of deductive reasoning. The assumption of such a contrast is certainly correct
in one important way, but it is also misleading in several other ways. It is right, to
begin with, also from an Aristotelian point of view to say that the topical method is
different from an axiomatic-deductive method; when using Aristotelian topoi for
construing arguments we choose a particular topos out of a plurality of topoi and we
take the reliability of the topos for granted, without investigating its credentials. We
are not interested, unlike those taking an axiomatic-deductivist approach, in
reducing the multitude of topoi to a few axioms or in deriving the topoi or the
conclusions we drew with their help from first, improvable axioms. This is, we
think, the basic sense, in which the topical and the axiomatic methods are opposed.
This does not exclude, however, the possibility of inquiring into some more general
rules or principles that govern several sets of topoi. For example, in the Topics many
topoi are derived from the rules inherent in the four kinds of predication (the
predicables), while others derive from the rules implied by the several forms of
oppositions, from the genius-species-relation, etc. Even in ancient times, commen-
tators were therefore seeking to identify such general ‘‘maxims’’.49
It would also be misleading to separate the use of topoi from deductions by making
topoi a mere matter of invention (of premises), while the construction of the
corresponding arguments is left to the logician. Such a characterization of Aristotelian
topoi derives from a traditional picture of the division of labour between Aristotle’s
Topics and his Analytica. According to this tradition, the Topics is exclusively
concerned with the finding of premises, while the business of logic is left to another
discipline. This tradition obviously derives from an over-systematization of the
Aristotelian Organon. It is more plausible to assume, as we have already said, that for
Aristotle the topoi also represented different modes of how a sullogismos can be
conclusive, and thus he meant to ascribe an additional probative function to the topoi.
Most notably, it is misleading to use Aristotle’s topical approach to construe a contrast
between topical and deductively valid arguments. A widespread assumption is that as
soon as topoi enter the stage, people are no longer really interested in deductive
arguments, but in mere plausibility, in inferences that seem likely, understandable and
in accordance with common opinion, but that do not necessarily form a valid deductive
argument. It is quite obvious where this picture comes from, if we take into account
that topoi regularly occur together with endoxa, accepted premises, in Aristotle’s
dialectics. However, within an Aristotelian frame this picture appears misleading on
closer examination, as in Aristotle’s dialectic topoi are supposed to construe
sullogismoi (deductive arguments) that are formally equivalent to scientific demon-
strations. Dialectical arguments differ from demonstrations not in their form or logical
rigour, but only in the quality of the premises.50
For Aristotle, then, there is no tension
between the use of topoi and the adherence to deductive arguments.
49
Cf. Alexander of Aphrodisias, In Arist. Top. II, 135, 2 et seq. (Wallies); for the idea of grouping
several topoi under more general headings, see also Rapp (2000).
50
The same is also true of rhetorical arguments or enthymemes, which are defined as sorts of sullogismoi
(see above, Sect. 3).
On Some Aristotelian Sources
123
Author's personal copy
Finally, it is misleading if the Aristotelian use of topoi is captured by the contrast
of formal and material reasoning or argumentation.51
As we have said, many of the
general topoi of the Topics are taken from rules that derive from the several types of
predication. If, e.g., a thesis expresses a definitional predication, then it is clear that
whatever holds for the subject must also hold for the (defining) predicate and vice
versa. If a topos is derived from such rules, it is the form of predication and not the
content that matters and, hence, such a topos is far from being ‘‘material’’. This is
also the reason why the restricted applicability of topoi is sometimes overempha-
sized.52
In the Topics the system of topoi is supposed to provide arguments for and
against any thesis, regardless of content, and for that purpose a ‘‘material’’ character
and the resulting limited applicability are not useful. What these MAT authors seem
to have in mind are rather specific topoi, as we find them in the first book of the
Rhetoric. These topoi, however, are often understood as merely providing
acceptable opinions on different subjects, while a topos in the proper sense is
expected to do more, i.e. to ‘‘find’’ or to ‘‘construe’’ a premise or to formulate a
complete argument. Whether and how the specific topoi match up to this
expectation has seldom been examined.53
At any rate, it would be mistaken to
take the less interesting lists of specific topoi as paradigmatic for all Aristotelian
topoi.
6 Character and Emotions: Towards a Broader Notion of Argumentation?
Aristotle’s theory of argumentation as it is laid out in the Topics does not seem to be
interested in factors related to interpersonal communication situations. Arguments
are primarily seen as sequences of intellectual steps. Their linguistic realization, the
form in which they are presented and their effect on the hearers are only touched
upon at random. Aristotle’s treatise on the art of rhetoric, by contrast, even though it
rather focuses on monologic speeches and not on dialogical situations, is less
restricted; the person of the speaker, the disposition and horizon of the hearer, the
general situation and context are all taken into consideration. This leads to the
question whether the rather narrow notion of argumentation that can be found in the
Topics (and likewise in the Analytics) is altered to fit into the framework of the
Rhetoric. If so, Aristotle could be seen as an early source of broader, more
pluralistic notions of argumentation, as they are discussed in MAT.
From a technical point of view the addressee can be persuaded through proof and
argument (logos), by displaying the speaker’s character (êthos) and by arousing the
emotions of the audience (pathos). These so-called ‘‘technical’’ means of persuasion
51
This contrast is emphasized by Toulmin (1986), passim. According to an often quoted example from
Toulmin (1958) the premise that a Swede can generally be taken not to be a Roman Catholic can be used
as warrant for the inference that, if Peter is a Swede, he is almost certainly not a Roman Catholic. If such
empirical facts belong to what Toulmin takes to be ‘‘material’’ in contrast to ‘‘formal’’, then none of
Aristotle’s general or common topoi and only a few of his specific topoi would qualify as material.
52
Cf. Toulmin (1996, 303) and Tetens (2011, 491).
53
Some attempts at construing specific topoi not as ready-premises, but as tools that are supposed to
generate arguments, are made in Rapp (2002, vol. II, 290–298).
Ch. Rapp, T. Wagner
123
Author's personal copy
can be coordinated to the three vertices of the triangle of speaker, hearer and subject
matter. The theory of persuasion as it is laid out in the Rhetoric thus broadens the
scope of the analysis. Whereas the theory of the Topics neglected or idealized the
vertices of speaker and hearer (by imposing artificial procedural rules on them), the
Rhetoric seems to raise them to the same level as the subject matter and the
corresponding means of persuasion, i.e. proof or argument.
The aspects of persuasion which we may call ‘‘non-argumentative’’—just for the
purpose of contrasting them with proofs or arguments in the narrow sense—may
interfere with or impede theintended persuasion process. Ifthe audience does not think
that the speaker is trustworthy, the best argument will fail to achieve the desired effect.
And if the hearers happen to be in an emotional state that prevents their minds from
forming clear thoughts, they will presumably not even be able to follow the speaker’s
train of thought. Conversely, the rhetorician may use the strong personal impact he
makes or the emotional disposition he arouses for emphasizing or highlighting those
aspects of the subject matter that are capable of influencing the audience’s judgment.
Aristotle does not give a very detailed account of the non-argumentative means
of persuasion. And the little he actually says about them is stated rather negatively,
in that it tells us what should be avoided, rather than positively instructing us on
how to support the argumentative strategy; persuasion may be accomplished by
showing character virtues the lack of which would prevent the audience from
believing that the speaker is trustworthy. If the speaker does not display practical
intelligence, the audience will not be inclined to believe that he has anything true to
say about the case at hand. But it may also be the case that a person is competent
and intelligent but seems to lack moral integrity. If the hearers have doubts about the
virtuous character of the speaker, they may concede that he is clever but refrain
from accepting what he says because he may pursue aims which are not acceptable
to them. And if the speaker is perceived as competent and virtuous, the possibility
still remains that he has, for whatever reason, an aversion to the audience. If the
speaker appears to lack goodwill for the audience and seems to display subtle
hostility or arrogance, the readiness to adopt his views will completely disappear.
If the rhetorician succeeds in presenting himself as a trustworthy person, the
audience forms a second-order judgment that what is put forward by a credible
person should be accepted. This second-order judgment has nothing to do with the
subject matter of the speech. And even though Aristotle does not give detailed
instructions on exactly how character should be displayed, he clearly seems to
prefer using rather indirect forms to express personal virtues. A speaker who opens
his speech by explicitly praising his intelligence, his virtuous character or his
benevolence before the audience, will come across as a suspect individual who
aspires to distract from some other hidden motif.
Some short remarks in the Poetics show how practical instructions on how to
display a person’s character might look. In a tragedy the character of a person can be
seen when it comes to a choice (prohairesis) between different possible actions—
‘‘hence there is no room for character in a speech in which the speaker does not
show what he chooses or avoids’’.54
Conversely, character can be displayed in a
54
Cf. Aristotle, Poetics 6, 1450b8 et seq.
On Some Aristotelian Sources
123
Author's personal copy
speech in which the speaker shows how he would choose. If the speaker uses this
means of persuasion there are two possibilities: either an element of the speech can
be stated only to serve the goal of producing a certain appearance without its being
related to the subject matter of the speech, or a statement about the subject matter of
the speech serves at the same time as a means to show the speaker’s character. But
even if the latter is the case it should not be confused with an argument that is
merely about the case at hand. The moment the hearer accepts what the speaker says
not only because of the content but also because of the speaker’s credibility, the
argument is no longer independent of the person who presented it.
The means of persuasion that is related more directly to the hearer, the arousal of
emotions (pathos), allows for a greater range of variation. Aristotle introduces this
subject as the analysis of emotions.55
The rhetorician has to know the complete
definition of an emotion in order to be able to arouse it. Aristotle therefore offers
accounts of different emotions in some detail. If the rhetorician knows, e.g., that
anger is ‘‘a desire accompanied by pain, for a conspicuous revenge for a
conspicuous slight at the hands of men who have no right to slight oneself or one’s
friends’’,56
he will be able to arouse anger by presenting a case that instantiates this
definition. Definitional knowledge allows one to model a given case correctly. For
example, anger cannot be directed against universal entities like man in general, but
must be directed against individuals, because only individuals can commit slights.
That anger is a kind of desire implies that it is followed by a certain pleasure which
arises from the expectation of revenge. It is pleasant to think that one will attain
what one aims at. Therefore, the rhetorician should rather highlight the possibility of
taking revenge than neglecting it. The rhetorician who wants to arouse a certain
emotion can do so by emphasizing aspects of the subject matter of his speech in
such a way that the persons involved and the courses of action seem to be in
accordance with the definition of the emotion. Thus, the rhetorician can steer the
hearers’ emotional state by making them believe that, for example, a slight has been
committed by someone who was not entitled to do so; and the emotional state
resulting from such a belief is likely to have an impact on the judgment the hearers
finally make.
As we have seen, both the display of the speaker’s character (êthos) and the
arousal of the hearer’s emotions (pathos) work on the basis of inferences or
judgments made by the hearer, even though they cannot be reduced to these
inferential aspects. How can the dividing line between proper argumentation and
non-argumentative means of persuasion be drawn? Obviously, it is not sufficient to
check whether or not inferences and judgments come into play. What matters is the
relationship between the premises and the target conclusion. If the speaker wants to
make the addressee accept a certain claim (for example the claim that a city wall
should be built), an argument in the proper sense should be directly relevant to this
claim. The second-order judgment that the speaker is a trustworthy person has no
direct bearing on such a claim. The emotional state of fear or anger that influences
the hearer’s judgment formation does not necessarily depend on pertinent premises.
55
Cf. Aristotle, Rhetoric II.1, 1378a20 et sqq.
56
Cf. Aristotle, Rhetoric II.2, 1378a31 et sqq.
Ch. Rapp, T. Wagner
123
Author's personal copy
Whereas within the realm of rational argumentation a premise that turns out to be
false can no longer be used in building a sound argument, emotional states may
maintain their efficacy independently of the truth value of the premises they are
based on.
The fact that inferences and judgments are involved when the speaker presents
himself as trustworthy or arouses the emotions of the audience should not blind us to
the differences between non-argumentative means of persuasion and pertinent
argumentation. It is no coincidence that Aristotle distinguishes êthos and pathos
from logos and seems not to see these means as instances of a wider notion of
argumentation. His definition of a deductive argument (sullogismos) stresses the
‘‘causal’’ role of the premises for the conclusion. The conclusion comes about
‘‘through’’ the premises or ‘‘because of’’ them. If the addressee accepts a claim
because of the presumed character of the speaker or under the influence of an
emotional state, these factors may not be pertinent in the same sense as the premises
of a proper argument. Aristotle takes the non-argumentative factors into account,
gives a neutral explanation and sketches methods for exploiting their potential; he
does not incorporate them into his notion of an argument. The concept of pertinence
or relevance that is central here, nevertheless, still awaits detailed reconstruction.57
7 Fallacies and Other Violations of Discourse Rules
The study of fallacies is one of the central topics of MAT. It is generally accepted
that Aristotle is among the founding fathers of this discipline. Especially the treatise
on Sophistical Refutations is regarded as an important contribution to the systematic
analysis of arguments that are incorrect or deceptive. As often happens in the history
of philosophy, Aristotle’s doctrine has not only served as a point of reference for
affirmative reconstruction but also as a model that has been extended, modified,
criticized and contrasted with different approaches. In recent decades, the ‘‘Standard
Treatment’’—as Hamblin (1970) called the Aristotelian heritage in the study of
fallacies—has been criticized as incomplete, insufficient, or unclear because on the
one hand it seems to be restricted to the dialectical context it stems from and on the
other hand it uses unclear, ‘‘metaphysical’’ notions and distinctions such as essential
versus accidental properties.58
Indeed, Aristotle’s system of fallacies is quite
inflexible. For him, a fallacy is an inference that seems to be a sullogismos, without
actually being conclusive. Each type of fallacy is connected with a specific reason
why people are deluded into thinking that the conclusion follows from the premises.
Appealing to these various sources of delusion, Aristotle even attempts to prove that
the list of fallacies he gives is systematically complete.59
Within Aristotle’s
conceptual frame it seems that all inferences that are non-conclusive (apart from
57
Although, of course, MAT has already incorporated the concept of relevance into its agenda; cf. e.g.
van Eemeren and Grootendorst (2004, chapter 4).
58
This second criticism resembles a motif that we already encountered in Perelman: cf. footnote 43.
59
Cf. the contribution by Pieter Sjoerd Hasper to this issue.
On Some Aristotelian Sources
123
Author's personal copy
inductions, of course) are fallacious. At least there is no single concept by which to
classify such inferences.60
The Amsterdam School has taken an entirely different approach. The concept of
pragma-dialectical fallacies which was introduced in the 1990s exemplifies a
position which seems to have little in common with Aristotle’s views about
fallacies. According to this approach fallacies are violations of discussion rules
intended to ensure that differences of opinion can be resolved. The pragma-
dialectical rules are recapitulated in ten principles—the ‘Ten Commandments’ of
critical discussion. Among these principles there are rules about logical validity61
or
the avoidance of unclear formulations62
which are not too far from Aristotle’s
account. Other rules concern the general setting of the discourse, e.g. the freedom to
advance or cast doubt on a standpoint or to define which moves are allowed and
which are not.63
If, for example, a premise represents an accepted starting point, the
other party is not allowed to deny it; otherwise this will be counted as a fallacy.
The pragma-dialectical concept of fallacies is not restricted to logical incorrect-
ness or misleading use of linguistic expressions. It also covers moves which within
the framework of Aristotelian dialectics are sometimes necessary and seem to be
part of the game. If, for example, a premise within a dialectical disputation might be
used to deduce the target conclusion of the opponent, the defendant is advised by
Aristotle not to grant it.64
Thus, we seem to be confronted with a straightforward
opposition between Aristotle’s views and MAT approaches.
On closer examination, however, the supposed opposition turns out to be less
pronounced. Aristotle does not speak about the rules of discourse in terms of fallacies
or fallacious moves. Nevertheless, the Topics rests on the ideal of an ‘‘impeccable’’
dialectical argument, which comes close to some modern normative rules of discourse.
In Topics VIII.11, Aristotle enumerates six criteria for retrospective evaluation of an
argument. Implicitly, the possible points of criticism form a set of rules which define
ideal dialectical arguments. In an ideal dialectical dispute the desired conclusion
which is opposed to the answerer’s original thesis is established only through premises
which are necessary, relevant and more acceptable than the conclusion.65
This ideal
result is only accessible for interlocutors who aim at jointly achieving deeper
knowledge about the subject-matter.
The preconditions that have to be fulfilled to realize this co-operative form of
dialectical argumentation are demanding: the dialecticians have to know which
60
Some commentators think that in Rhetoric I.2 Aristotle regards sign-enthymemes as acceptable
arguments, even if they are non-conclusive. However, he does not express his appreciation for sign-
enthymemes in so many words. In Rhetoric II.24 he straightforwardly classifies sign-enthymemes as
fallacies. The example given in this latter chapter clearly involves a dilution; possibly, Aristotle thinks
that people could accept the sign-examples in Rhetoric I.2—without being deluded. For the ancient and,
in particular, Aristotelian treatment of fallacies see also Pieter Sjoerd Hasper and Christof Rapp (eds.),
Ancient Fallacies. In Logical Analysis and History of Philosophy 15, forthcoming.
61
Cf. van Eemeren et al. (1996, 284: Rule (8) with fn. 23).
62
Cf. loc. cit.: Rule (10).
63
Cf. loc. cit.: Rules (1) and (6).
64
Cf. Aristotle, Topics VIII.6, 160a
3–6.
65
Cf. Aristotle, Topics VIII.11, 161b
19–33.
Ch. Rapp, T. Wagner
123
Author's personal copy
views are generally accepted and what the experts think; they have to be capable of
foreseeing the consequences of a statement; they should neither block the partner’s
strategy nor go down without a fight; and they should be able to establish valid
deductions. If they fail to do the latter, they commit what Aristotle would call a
fallacy. If a dialectician fails to comply with one of the other implicit rules, this is
noted in subsequent evaluations of his argumentative capacities, but is not called a
‘‘fallacy’’. All in all, the set of possible violations of discursive rules Aristotle’s
dialectic is aware of clearly extends beyond his own notion of fallacies; the spirit of
some of these rules is not too far from certain pragmatic fallacies in MAT.
8 Conclusions
Modern argumentation theorists frequently focus on oppositions such as dialectic
versus rhetoric, analytical versus topical, reasonable versus effective, formal versus
informal, or normative versus descriptive. Many of these pairs are related to the
ancient tradition of public speech and argumentative discourse, in particular to
Aristotle’s treatises the Topics and the Rhetoric. The conceptual field that they
survey and map with the help of these distinctions is broad and not always clearly
delimited. Even though Aristotle did not treat the multifaceted aspects of
argumentation under one common heading, one may see the different theoretical
elements that center around his notion of a sound argument as parts of a coherent
project. This project might anachronistically be called Aristotle’s argumentation
theory. Aristotle himself did not see argumentation as a single field of research. He
studied logical and semantical relations that could be used to find or establish
premises, he analysed the relations between the terms of standardized deductive
arguments, he systematized and evaluated accepted opinions, and he accounted for
the factors of persuasion processes. In doing so, he raised many of the questions that
are still discussed in contemporary argumentation theory. His answers to these
questions are sometimes formulated in a language that sounds unfamiliar and seems
to be far away from the modern world. But under the surface of texts that may be
difficult or sketchy, we find a coherent and self-contained approach that combines a
realistic view of what people actually do when the dispute, argue, or try to persuade
others with the normative emphasis of how people should construct and present
sound arguments. This approach has set the agenda ever since and has provoked
criticism ever since. In one way or another the elements of Aristotle’s theory still
remain important sources for modern argumentation theory.
References
Bird, Otto. 1961. The re-discovery of the Topics. Professor Toulmins inference warrants. Mind 70:
534–539.
Burnyeat, Myles F. 1994. Aristotle on the logic of persuasion. In Aristotle’s Rhetoric: Philosophical
essays, ed. David J. Furley and Alexander Nehamas, 3–55. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Brunschwig, Jacques. 1967. Aristote, Topiques, tome I, livres I-IV. Paris: Les Belles Lettres.
On Some Aristotelian Sources
123
Author's personal copy
De Pater, Wim A. 1965. Les Topiques d’Aristote e la dialectique platonicienne. Fribourg: Éditions de St.
Paul.
Eggs, Ekkehard. 1992. Argumentation. In Historisches Wörterbuch der Rhetorik, vol. I, ed. Gert Ueding,
914–991. Tübingen: Niemeyer.
Hamblin, Charles. 1970. Fallacies. London: Methuen.
Kienpointner, Manfred. 1997. On the art of finding arguments: What ancient and modern masters of
invention have to tell us about the ‘ars inveniendi’. Argumentation 11(2): 225–236.
Kienpointner, Manfred. 2005. Aristotelische Rhetoriktradition im 20. Jahrhundert. In Aristotelische
Rhetoriktradition, ed. Joachim Knape and Thomas Schirren, 363–387. Stuttgart: Steiner.
Kienpointner, Manfred. 2011. Rhetorik. In Aristoteles-Handbuch, ed. Christof Rapp and Klaus Corcilius,
510–515. Stuttgart: Metzler.
Perelman, Chaı̈m, and Lucie Olbrechts-Tyteca. 1969. The new rhetoric: A treatise on argumentation.
Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press. (Traité de l’argumentation: La nouvelle rhétorique.
Paris: Presses Universitaires de France. 1959.).
Perelman, Chaı̈m. 1994. Logik und Argumentation, 2nd ed. Weinheim: Beltz. (Logique et argumentation.
Brussels: Presses univ. de Bruxelles. 1971.).
Rapp, Christof. 2000. Topos und Syllogismus in Aristoteles’ Topik. In Topik und Rhetorik: Ein
interdisziplinäres Symposium, ed. Thomas Schirren and Gert Ueding, 15–35. Tübingen: Niemeyer.
Rapp, Christof. 2002. Aristoteles, Rhetorik (translated and explained by Christof Rapp). Two volumes.
Berlin: Akademie-Verlag.
Rapp, Christof. 2012. Aristotle on the moral psychology of persuasion. In The Oxford handbook of
Aristotle, ed. Christopher Shields, 589–611. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Rigotti, Eddo. 2007. Can classical topics be revived within the contemporary theory of argumentation. In
Proceedings of the sixth conference of the International Society of the Study of Argumentation, ed.
Frans H. van Eemeren, J. Rob Grootendorst, Anthony Blair, and Charles A. Willard, 1155–1163.
Amsterdam: Sic Sat.
Tetens, Holm. 2004. Philosophisches Argumentieren. München: Beck.
Tetens, Holm. 2011. Beweiskraft und Rhetorik – das Beispiel der Metaphern und Analogien. In
Lebenswelt und Wissenschaft, ed. Carl F. Gethmann, 489–504. Hamburg: Meiner.
Toulmin, Stephen E. 1958. The uses of argument. Updated edition. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Toulmin, Stephen E. 1986. Die Verleumdung der Rhetorik. Neue Hefte für Philosophie 26: 55–68.
Toulmin, Stephen E. 1996. Rationality and reasonableness: From propositions to utterances. Revue
Internationale de Philosophie 2: 297–305.
van Eemeren, Frans H., Rob Grootendorst, and Francisca Snoeck Henkemans. 1996. Fundamentals of
argumentation theory: A handbook of historical backgrounds and contemporary developments. New
York: Routledge.
van Eemeren, Frans H., and Peter Houtlosser. 1999. Delivering the goods in critical discussion. In
Proceedings of the fourth international conference of the International Society of the Study of
Argumentation, ed. Frans H. van Eemeren, J. Rob Grootendorst, Anthony Blair, and Charles A.
Willard, 163–167. Amsterdam: Sic Sat.
van Eemeren, Frans H., and Peter Houtlosser (eds.). 2002. Dialectic and rhetoric: The warp and woof of
argumentation analysis. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic.
van Eemeren, Frans H., and Rob Grootendorst. 2004. A systematic theory of argumentation: The pragma-
dialectical approach. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Viehweg, Theodor. 1963. Topik und Jurisprudenz, 2nd ed. München: C.H. Beck. (First edition 1953).
Wagner, Tim and Christof Rapp. 2004. Aristoteles, Topik (translated and annotated by Tim Wagner and
Christof Rapp). Stuttgart: Reclam.
Walton, Douglas N., and Erik C.W. Krabbe. 1995. Commitment in dialogue: Basic concepts of
interpersonal reasoning. Albany: SUNY Press.
Walton, Douglas N., Christopher Reed, and Fabrizio Macagno. 2008. Argumentation schemes.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Warnick, Barbara. 2000. Two systems of invention: The topics in the Rhetoric and The New Rhetoric. In
Rereading Aristotle’s Rhetoric, ed. Alan G. Gross and Arthur E. Walzer, 107–129. Carbondale:
Southern Illinois University Press.
Woods, John, and Douglas N. Walton. 1989. Fallacies: Selected papers 1972–1982. Berlin: De Gruyter.
Ch. Rapp, T. Wagner
123
Author's personal copy

More Related Content

Similar to Aristotle and Modern Argumentation Theory.pdf

ENGL570_B01_202020 - 202020 SPRING 2020 ENGL 570-B01 LUOTe.docx
ENGL570_B01_202020 - 202020 SPRING 2020 ENGL 570-B01 LUOTe.docxENGL570_B01_202020 - 202020 SPRING 2020 ENGL 570-B01 LUOTe.docx
ENGL570_B01_202020 - 202020 SPRING 2020 ENGL 570-B01 LUOTe.docxkhanpaulita
 
Aristotle Epistemology Download
Aristotle Epistemology DownloadAristotle Epistemology Download
Aristotle Epistemology DownloadCarrie Cox
 
Bunge - critica a dialectica
Bunge - critica a dialecticaBunge - critica a dialectica
Bunge - critica a dialecticaEmerson Salinas
 
Argument Schemes Typologies In Practice The Case Of Comparative Arguments
Argument Schemes Typologies In Practice  The Case Of Comparative ArgumentsArgument Schemes Typologies In Practice  The Case Of Comparative Arguments
Argument Schemes Typologies In Practice The Case Of Comparative ArgumentsKimberly Pulley
 
The laboratoryandthemarketinee bookchapter10pdf_merged
The laboratoryandthemarketinee bookchapter10pdf_mergedThe laboratoryandthemarketinee bookchapter10pdf_merged
The laboratoryandthemarketinee bookchapter10pdf_mergedJeenaDC
 
Big questions come in bundles
Big questions come in bundlesBig questions come in bundles
Big questions come in bundlesRaysa Karina
 
Final ReflectionsPossible Topics for Final Research Essay.html
Final ReflectionsPossible Topics for Final Research Essay.htmlFinal ReflectionsPossible Topics for Final Research Essay.html
Final ReflectionsPossible Topics for Final Research Essay.htmlChereCheek752
 
Argument structure The Aristotelian argument The Ar
 Argument structure The Aristotelian argument  The Ar Argument structure The Aristotelian argument  The Ar
Argument structure The Aristotelian argument The Artroutmanboris
 
Argumentative text as rhetorical structure An application of rhetorical stru...
Argumentative text as rhetorical structure  An application of rhetorical stru...Argumentative text as rhetorical structure  An application of rhetorical stru...
Argumentative text as rhetorical structure An application of rhetorical stru...Cynthia Velynne
 
Module 3 -Critical and Conspiracy Theories (Contemporary Philosophies).pdf
Module 3 -Critical and Conspiracy Theories (Contemporary Philosophies).pdfModule 3 -Critical and Conspiracy Theories (Contemporary Philosophies).pdf
Module 3 -Critical and Conspiracy Theories (Contemporary Philosophies).pdfDrDaryDacanay
 
The logic of informal proofs
The logic of informal proofsThe logic of informal proofs
The logic of informal proofsBrendan Larvor
 
Order #492895 revised
Order #492895 revisedOrder #492895 revised
Order #492895 reviseddilligan
 
The principle of constructive mathematizability of any theory: A sketch of fo...
The principle of constructive mathematizability of any theory: A sketch of fo...The principle of constructive mathematizability of any theory: A sketch of fo...
The principle of constructive mathematizability of any theory: A sketch of fo...Vasil Penchev
 
Is there a universal purpose in human Is there a.docx
Is there a universal purpose in human Is there a.docxIs there a universal purpose in human Is there a.docx
Is there a universal purpose in human Is there a.docxwrite4
 
Foundations camb july 2012
Foundations camb july 2012Foundations camb july 2012
Foundations camb july 2012Brendan Larvor
 
Manipulation and cognitive pragmatics. Preliminary hypotheses
Manipulation and cognitive pragmatics. Preliminary hypothesesManipulation and cognitive pragmatics. Preliminary hypotheses
Manipulation and cognitive pragmatics. Preliminary hypothesesLouis de Saussure
 
Techniques of persuasive essay writing
Techniques of persuasive essay writingTechniques of persuasive essay writing
Techniques of persuasive essay writingalice094
 
A Convincing Argument Corpus Analysis And Academic Persuasion
A Convincing Argument  Corpus Analysis And Academic PersuasionA Convincing Argument  Corpus Analysis And Academic Persuasion
A Convincing Argument Corpus Analysis And Academic PersuasionHeather Strinden
 
Aristotle S Metaphysics
Aristotle S MetaphysicsAristotle S Metaphysics
Aristotle S MetaphysicsFinni Rice
 

Similar to Aristotle and Modern Argumentation Theory.pdf (20)

ENGL570_B01_202020 - 202020 SPRING 2020 ENGL 570-B01 LUOTe.docx
ENGL570_B01_202020 - 202020 SPRING 2020 ENGL 570-B01 LUOTe.docxENGL570_B01_202020 - 202020 SPRING 2020 ENGL 570-B01 LUOTe.docx
ENGL570_B01_202020 - 202020 SPRING 2020 ENGL 570-B01 LUOTe.docx
 
Aristotle Epistemology Download
Aristotle Epistemology DownloadAristotle Epistemology Download
Aristotle Epistemology Download
 
Bunge - critica a dialectica
Bunge - critica a dialecticaBunge - critica a dialectica
Bunge - critica a dialectica
 
Argument Schemes Typologies In Practice The Case Of Comparative Arguments
Argument Schemes Typologies In Practice  The Case Of Comparative ArgumentsArgument Schemes Typologies In Practice  The Case Of Comparative Arguments
Argument Schemes Typologies In Practice The Case Of Comparative Arguments
 
The laboratoryandthemarketinee bookchapter10pdf_merged
The laboratoryandthemarketinee bookchapter10pdf_mergedThe laboratoryandthemarketinee bookchapter10pdf_merged
The laboratoryandthemarketinee bookchapter10pdf_merged
 
Big questions come in bundles
Big questions come in bundlesBig questions come in bundles
Big questions come in bundles
 
Final ReflectionsPossible Topics for Final Research Essay.html
Final ReflectionsPossible Topics for Final Research Essay.htmlFinal ReflectionsPossible Topics for Final Research Essay.html
Final ReflectionsPossible Topics for Final Research Essay.html
 
Argument structure The Aristotelian argument The Ar
 Argument structure The Aristotelian argument  The Ar Argument structure The Aristotelian argument  The Ar
Argument structure The Aristotelian argument The Ar
 
Argumentative text as rhetorical structure An application of rhetorical stru...
Argumentative text as rhetorical structure  An application of rhetorical stru...Argumentative text as rhetorical structure  An application of rhetorical stru...
Argumentative text as rhetorical structure An application of rhetorical stru...
 
Module 3 -Critical and Conspiracy Theories (Contemporary Philosophies).pdf
Module 3 -Critical and Conspiracy Theories (Contemporary Philosophies).pdfModule 3 -Critical and Conspiracy Theories (Contemporary Philosophies).pdf
Module 3 -Critical and Conspiracy Theories (Contemporary Philosophies).pdf
 
The logic of informal proofs
The logic of informal proofsThe logic of informal proofs
The logic of informal proofs
 
Philosophy
Philosophy Philosophy
Philosophy
 
Order #492895 revised
Order #492895 revisedOrder #492895 revised
Order #492895 revised
 
The principle of constructive mathematizability of any theory: A sketch of fo...
The principle of constructive mathematizability of any theory: A sketch of fo...The principle of constructive mathematizability of any theory: A sketch of fo...
The principle of constructive mathematizability of any theory: A sketch of fo...
 
Is there a universal purpose in human Is there a.docx
Is there a universal purpose in human Is there a.docxIs there a universal purpose in human Is there a.docx
Is there a universal purpose in human Is there a.docx
 
Foundations camb july 2012
Foundations camb july 2012Foundations camb july 2012
Foundations camb july 2012
 
Manipulation and cognitive pragmatics. Preliminary hypotheses
Manipulation and cognitive pragmatics. Preliminary hypothesesManipulation and cognitive pragmatics. Preliminary hypotheses
Manipulation and cognitive pragmatics. Preliminary hypotheses
 
Techniques of persuasive essay writing
Techniques of persuasive essay writingTechniques of persuasive essay writing
Techniques of persuasive essay writing
 
A Convincing Argument Corpus Analysis And Academic Persuasion
A Convincing Argument  Corpus Analysis And Academic PersuasionA Convincing Argument  Corpus Analysis And Academic Persuasion
A Convincing Argument Corpus Analysis And Academic Persuasion
 
Aristotle S Metaphysics
Aristotle S MetaphysicsAristotle S Metaphysics
Aristotle S Metaphysics
 

More from Nancy Ideker

Sell Essays Online
Sell Essays OnlineSell Essays Online
Sell Essays OnlineNancy Ideker
 
Printable Paper, Graph Paper With One Line Per Inch And
Printable Paper, Graph Paper With One Line Per Inch AndPrintable Paper, Graph Paper With One Line Per Inch And
Printable Paper, Graph Paper With One Line Per Inch AndNancy Ideker
 
Essay Money Cannot Buy H
Essay Money Cannot Buy HEssay Money Cannot Buy H
Essay Money Cannot Buy HNancy Ideker
 
100 Self-Introduction
100 Self-Introduction100 Self-Introduction
100 Self-IntroductionNancy Ideker
 
Who Can I Pay To Write A Paper For Me - Write My Custom Paper.
Who Can I Pay To Write A Paper For Me - Write My Custom Paper.Who Can I Pay To Write A Paper For Me - Write My Custom Paper.
Who Can I Pay To Write A Paper For Me - Write My Custom Paper.Nancy Ideker
 
Mrs. BoydS Site Research Paper
Mrs. BoydS Site Research PaperMrs. BoydS Site Research Paper
Mrs. BoydS Site Research PaperNancy Ideker
 
How To Write Impressive College Entrance Essays
How To Write Impressive College Entrance EssaysHow To Write Impressive College Entrance Essays
How To Write Impressive College Entrance EssaysNancy Ideker
 
16 Best Images Of Persuasive Writing Worksh
16 Best Images Of Persuasive Writing Worksh16 Best Images Of Persuasive Writing Worksh
16 Best Images Of Persuasive Writing WorkshNancy Ideker
 
Essay Writing Service In Australia - Essay Writing Service By Top
Essay Writing Service In Australia - Essay Writing Service By TopEssay Writing Service In Australia - Essay Writing Service By Top
Essay Writing Service In Australia - Essay Writing Service By TopNancy Ideker
 
How To Write A Law Essay Like A Pro CustomEssay
How To Write A Law Essay Like A Pro CustomEssayHow To Write A Law Essay Like A Pro CustomEssay
How To Write A Law Essay Like A Pro CustomEssayNancy Ideker
 
How To Write An Explanatory Essay Topics, Outline, Ex
How To Write An Explanatory Essay Topics, Outline, ExHow To Write An Explanatory Essay Topics, Outline, Ex
How To Write An Explanatory Essay Topics, Outline, ExNancy Ideker
 
How To Write An Introduction Paragraph Of A Research
How To Write An Introduction Paragraph Of A ResearchHow To Write An Introduction Paragraph Of A Research
How To Write An Introduction Paragraph Of A ResearchNancy Ideker
 
013 Essay Example What Is Diversity Essays On In Coll
013 Essay Example What Is Diversity Essays On In Coll013 Essay Example What Is Diversity Essays On In Coll
013 Essay Example What Is Diversity Essays On In CollNancy Ideker
 
Paragraph Writing (Simple, Five Sentence F
Paragraph Writing (Simple, Five Sentence FParagraph Writing (Simple, Five Sentence F
Paragraph Writing (Simple, Five Sentence FNancy Ideker
 
Printable Kindergarten Writing Paper Template
Printable Kindergarten Writing Paper TemplatePrintable Kindergarten Writing Paper Template
Printable Kindergarten Writing Paper TemplateNancy Ideker
 
Reddit.Com Us Papers Writing Service - Malta Blu
Reddit.Com Us Papers Writing Service - Malta BluReddit.Com Us Papers Writing Service - Malta Blu
Reddit.Com Us Papers Writing Service - Malta BluNancy Ideker
 
How To Write An Expository Thesis. Expository Essay
How To Write An Expository Thesis. Expository EssayHow To Write An Expository Thesis. Expository Essay
How To Write An Expository Thesis. Expository EssayNancy Ideker
 

More from Nancy Ideker (20)

Sell Essays Online
Sell Essays OnlineSell Essays Online
Sell Essays Online
 
Beliefs Essay
Beliefs EssayBeliefs Essay
Beliefs Essay
 
Van Gogh Essay
Van Gogh EssayVan Gogh Essay
Van Gogh Essay
 
Welfare Essays
Welfare EssaysWelfare Essays
Welfare Essays
 
Printable Paper, Graph Paper With One Line Per Inch And
Printable Paper, Graph Paper With One Line Per Inch AndPrintable Paper, Graph Paper With One Line Per Inch And
Printable Paper, Graph Paper With One Line Per Inch And
 
Essay Money Cannot Buy H
Essay Money Cannot Buy HEssay Money Cannot Buy H
Essay Money Cannot Buy H
 
100 Self-Introduction
100 Self-Introduction100 Self-Introduction
100 Self-Introduction
 
Who Can I Pay To Write A Paper For Me - Write My Custom Paper.
Who Can I Pay To Write A Paper For Me - Write My Custom Paper.Who Can I Pay To Write A Paper For Me - Write My Custom Paper.
Who Can I Pay To Write A Paper For Me - Write My Custom Paper.
 
Mrs. BoydS Site Research Paper
Mrs. BoydS Site Research PaperMrs. BoydS Site Research Paper
Mrs. BoydS Site Research Paper
 
How To Write Impressive College Entrance Essays
How To Write Impressive College Entrance EssaysHow To Write Impressive College Entrance Essays
How To Write Impressive College Entrance Essays
 
16 Best Images Of Persuasive Writing Worksh
16 Best Images Of Persuasive Writing Worksh16 Best Images Of Persuasive Writing Worksh
16 Best Images Of Persuasive Writing Worksh
 
Essay Writing Service In Australia - Essay Writing Service By Top
Essay Writing Service In Australia - Essay Writing Service By TopEssay Writing Service In Australia - Essay Writing Service By Top
Essay Writing Service In Australia - Essay Writing Service By Top
 
How To Write A Law Essay Like A Pro CustomEssay
How To Write A Law Essay Like A Pro CustomEssayHow To Write A Law Essay Like A Pro CustomEssay
How To Write A Law Essay Like A Pro CustomEssay
 
How To Write An Explanatory Essay Topics, Outline, Ex
How To Write An Explanatory Essay Topics, Outline, ExHow To Write An Explanatory Essay Topics, Outline, Ex
How To Write An Explanatory Essay Topics, Outline, Ex
 
How To Write An Introduction Paragraph Of A Research
How To Write An Introduction Paragraph Of A ResearchHow To Write An Introduction Paragraph Of A Research
How To Write An Introduction Paragraph Of A Research
 
013 Essay Example What Is Diversity Essays On In Coll
013 Essay Example What Is Diversity Essays On In Coll013 Essay Example What Is Diversity Essays On In Coll
013 Essay Example What Is Diversity Essays On In Coll
 
Paragraph Writing (Simple, Five Sentence F
Paragraph Writing (Simple, Five Sentence FParagraph Writing (Simple, Five Sentence F
Paragraph Writing (Simple, Five Sentence F
 
Printable Kindergarten Writing Paper Template
Printable Kindergarten Writing Paper TemplatePrintable Kindergarten Writing Paper Template
Printable Kindergarten Writing Paper Template
 
Reddit.Com Us Papers Writing Service - Malta Blu
Reddit.Com Us Papers Writing Service - Malta BluReddit.Com Us Papers Writing Service - Malta Blu
Reddit.Com Us Papers Writing Service - Malta Blu
 
How To Write An Expository Thesis. Expository Essay
How To Write An Expository Thesis. Expository EssayHow To Write An Expository Thesis. Expository Essay
How To Write An Expository Thesis. Expository Essay
 

Recently uploaded

A Critique of the Proposed National Education Policy Reform
A Critique of the Proposed National Education Policy ReformA Critique of the Proposed National Education Policy Reform
A Critique of the Proposed National Education Policy ReformChameera Dedduwage
 
Russian Call Girls in Andheri Airport Mumbai WhatsApp 9167673311 💞 Full Nigh...
Russian Call Girls in Andheri Airport Mumbai WhatsApp  9167673311 💞 Full Nigh...Russian Call Girls in Andheri Airport Mumbai WhatsApp  9167673311 💞 Full Nigh...
Russian Call Girls in Andheri Airport Mumbai WhatsApp 9167673311 💞 Full Nigh...Pooja Nehwal
 
Arihant handbook biology for class 11 .pdf
Arihant handbook biology for class 11 .pdfArihant handbook biology for class 11 .pdf
Arihant handbook biology for class 11 .pdfchloefrazer622
 
Introduction to Nonprofit Accounting: The Basics
Introduction to Nonprofit Accounting: The BasicsIntroduction to Nonprofit Accounting: The Basics
Introduction to Nonprofit Accounting: The BasicsTechSoup
 
Call Girls in Dwarka Mor Delhi Contact Us 9654467111
Call Girls in Dwarka Mor Delhi Contact Us 9654467111Call Girls in Dwarka Mor Delhi Contact Us 9654467111
Call Girls in Dwarka Mor Delhi Contact Us 9654467111Sapana Sha
 
Measures of Central Tendency: Mean, Median and Mode
Measures of Central Tendency: Mean, Median and ModeMeasures of Central Tendency: Mean, Median and Mode
Measures of Central Tendency: Mean, Median and ModeThiyagu K
 
APM Welcome, APM North West Network Conference, Synergies Across Sectors
APM Welcome, APM North West Network Conference, Synergies Across SectorsAPM Welcome, APM North West Network Conference, Synergies Across Sectors
APM Welcome, APM North West Network Conference, Synergies Across SectorsAssociation for Project Management
 
Nutritional Needs Presentation - HLTH 104
Nutritional Needs Presentation - HLTH 104Nutritional Needs Presentation - HLTH 104
Nutritional Needs Presentation - HLTH 104misteraugie
 
Beyond the EU: DORA and NIS 2 Directive's Global Impact
Beyond the EU: DORA and NIS 2 Directive's Global ImpactBeyond the EU: DORA and NIS 2 Directive's Global Impact
Beyond the EU: DORA and NIS 2 Directive's Global ImpactPECB
 
microwave assisted reaction. General introduction
microwave assisted reaction. General introductionmicrowave assisted reaction. General introduction
microwave assisted reaction. General introductionMaksud Ahmed
 
Separation of Lanthanides/ Lanthanides and Actinides
Separation of Lanthanides/ Lanthanides and ActinidesSeparation of Lanthanides/ Lanthanides and Actinides
Separation of Lanthanides/ Lanthanides and ActinidesFatimaKhan178732
 
mini mental status format.docx
mini    mental       status     format.docxmini    mental       status     format.docx
mini mental status format.docxPoojaSen20
 
Paris 2024 Olympic Geographies - an activity
Paris 2024 Olympic Geographies - an activityParis 2024 Olympic Geographies - an activity
Paris 2024 Olympic Geographies - an activityGeoBlogs
 
BASLIQ CURRENT LOOKBOOK LOOKBOOK(1) (1).pdf
BASLIQ CURRENT LOOKBOOK  LOOKBOOK(1) (1).pdfBASLIQ CURRENT LOOKBOOK  LOOKBOOK(1) (1).pdf
BASLIQ CURRENT LOOKBOOK LOOKBOOK(1) (1).pdfSoniaTolstoy
 
BAG TECHNIQUE Bag technique-a tool making use of public health bag through wh...
BAG TECHNIQUE Bag technique-a tool making use of public health bag through wh...BAG TECHNIQUE Bag technique-a tool making use of public health bag through wh...
BAG TECHNIQUE Bag technique-a tool making use of public health bag through wh...Sapna Thakur
 
Sports & Fitness Value Added Course FY..
Sports & Fitness Value Added Course FY..Sports & Fitness Value Added Course FY..
Sports & Fitness Value Added Course FY..Disha Kariya
 
The Most Excellent Way | 1 Corinthians 13
The Most Excellent Way | 1 Corinthians 13The Most Excellent Way | 1 Corinthians 13
The Most Excellent Way | 1 Corinthians 13Steve Thomason
 

Recently uploaded (20)

A Critique of the Proposed National Education Policy Reform
A Critique of the Proposed National Education Policy ReformA Critique of the Proposed National Education Policy Reform
A Critique of the Proposed National Education Policy Reform
 
Russian Call Girls in Andheri Airport Mumbai WhatsApp 9167673311 💞 Full Nigh...
Russian Call Girls in Andheri Airport Mumbai WhatsApp  9167673311 💞 Full Nigh...Russian Call Girls in Andheri Airport Mumbai WhatsApp  9167673311 💞 Full Nigh...
Russian Call Girls in Andheri Airport Mumbai WhatsApp 9167673311 💞 Full Nigh...
 
Arihant handbook biology for class 11 .pdf
Arihant handbook biology for class 11 .pdfArihant handbook biology for class 11 .pdf
Arihant handbook biology for class 11 .pdf
 
Introduction to Nonprofit Accounting: The Basics
Introduction to Nonprofit Accounting: The BasicsIntroduction to Nonprofit Accounting: The Basics
Introduction to Nonprofit Accounting: The Basics
 
Call Girls in Dwarka Mor Delhi Contact Us 9654467111
Call Girls in Dwarka Mor Delhi Contact Us 9654467111Call Girls in Dwarka Mor Delhi Contact Us 9654467111
Call Girls in Dwarka Mor Delhi Contact Us 9654467111
 
Measures of Central Tendency: Mean, Median and Mode
Measures of Central Tendency: Mean, Median and ModeMeasures of Central Tendency: Mean, Median and Mode
Measures of Central Tendency: Mean, Median and Mode
 
INDIA QUIZ 2024 RLAC DELHI UNIVERSITY.pptx
INDIA QUIZ 2024 RLAC DELHI UNIVERSITY.pptxINDIA QUIZ 2024 RLAC DELHI UNIVERSITY.pptx
INDIA QUIZ 2024 RLAC DELHI UNIVERSITY.pptx
 
APM Welcome, APM North West Network Conference, Synergies Across Sectors
APM Welcome, APM North West Network Conference, Synergies Across SectorsAPM Welcome, APM North West Network Conference, Synergies Across Sectors
APM Welcome, APM North West Network Conference, Synergies Across Sectors
 
Nutritional Needs Presentation - HLTH 104
Nutritional Needs Presentation - HLTH 104Nutritional Needs Presentation - HLTH 104
Nutritional Needs Presentation - HLTH 104
 
Beyond the EU: DORA and NIS 2 Directive's Global Impact
Beyond the EU: DORA and NIS 2 Directive's Global ImpactBeyond the EU: DORA and NIS 2 Directive's Global Impact
Beyond the EU: DORA and NIS 2 Directive's Global Impact
 
microwave assisted reaction. General introduction
microwave assisted reaction. General introductionmicrowave assisted reaction. General introduction
microwave assisted reaction. General introduction
 
Separation of Lanthanides/ Lanthanides and Actinides
Separation of Lanthanides/ Lanthanides and ActinidesSeparation of Lanthanides/ Lanthanides and Actinides
Separation of Lanthanides/ Lanthanides and Actinides
 
mini mental status format.docx
mini    mental       status     format.docxmini    mental       status     format.docx
mini mental status format.docx
 
Paris 2024 Olympic Geographies - an activity
Paris 2024 Olympic Geographies - an activityParis 2024 Olympic Geographies - an activity
Paris 2024 Olympic Geographies - an activity
 
BASLIQ CURRENT LOOKBOOK LOOKBOOK(1) (1).pdf
BASLIQ CURRENT LOOKBOOK  LOOKBOOK(1) (1).pdfBASLIQ CURRENT LOOKBOOK  LOOKBOOK(1) (1).pdf
BASLIQ CURRENT LOOKBOOK LOOKBOOK(1) (1).pdf
 
Código Creativo y Arte de Software | Unidad 1
Código Creativo y Arte de Software | Unidad 1Código Creativo y Arte de Software | Unidad 1
Código Creativo y Arte de Software | Unidad 1
 
Mattingly "AI & Prompt Design: The Basics of Prompt Design"
Mattingly "AI & Prompt Design: The Basics of Prompt Design"Mattingly "AI & Prompt Design: The Basics of Prompt Design"
Mattingly "AI & Prompt Design: The Basics of Prompt Design"
 
BAG TECHNIQUE Bag technique-a tool making use of public health bag through wh...
BAG TECHNIQUE Bag technique-a tool making use of public health bag through wh...BAG TECHNIQUE Bag technique-a tool making use of public health bag through wh...
BAG TECHNIQUE Bag technique-a tool making use of public health bag through wh...
 
Sports & Fitness Value Added Course FY..
Sports & Fitness Value Added Course FY..Sports & Fitness Value Added Course FY..
Sports & Fitness Value Added Course FY..
 
The Most Excellent Way | 1 Corinthians 13
The Most Excellent Way | 1 Corinthians 13The Most Excellent Way | 1 Corinthians 13
The Most Excellent Way | 1 Corinthians 13
 

Aristotle and Modern Argumentation Theory.pdf

  • 1. 1 23 Argumentation An International Journal on Reasoning ISSN 0920-427X Argumentation DOI 10.1007/s10503-012-9280-9 On Some Aristotelian Sources of Modern Argumentation Theory Christof Rapp & Tim Wagner
  • 2. 1 23 Your article is protected by copyright and all rights are held exclusively by Springer Science+Business Media B.V.. This e-offprint is for personal use only and shall not be self- archived in electronic repositories. If you wish to self-archive your work, please use the accepted author’s version for posting to your own website or your institution’s repository. You may further deposit the accepted author’s version on a funder’s repository at a funder’s request, provided it is not made publicly available until 12 months after publication.
  • 3. On Some Aristotelian Sources of Modern Argumentation Theory Christof Rapp • Tim Wagner Ó Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2012 Abstract Although he does not provide a general analysis of argumentation, Aristotle is a highly influential source of modern argumentation theory. In his treatises the Topics, the Sophistical Refutations and the Rhetoric, Aristotle presents complementary aspects of a theory of sound arguments that are seen as the most effective means of persuasion. Aristotle’s central notion of a deductive argument (sullogismos) does not include references to an addressee, the situative context or non-verbal aspects of communication, and thus differs from some modern views on argumentation. A deductive argument in the Aristotelian sense is a sequence of intellectual steps where the conclusion follows of necessity from the premises. Aristotle does not relativize or relax this notion but takes other factors into account by providing supplementary theoretical elements. For example, he reflects on acceptable premises (endoxa), the adjustment of rhetorical arguments to the horizon of the audience, methods of finding premises on the basis of argumentative schemes (topoi), the use of non-argumentative means of persuasion, and a framework of implicit discourse rules. Many of these themes are, albeit under a different name, still discussed in modern argumentation theory. Keywords Aristotle Dialectic Rhetoric Deductive Argument Topoi Persuasion Fallacy Ch. Rapp Lehrstuhl für Philosophie III, Ludwig-Maximilians-Universität, Geschwister-Scholl-Platz 1, 80539 Munich, Germany e-mail: Office.Ch.Rapp@lrz.uni-muenchen.de T. Wagner () Institut für Philosophie, Humboldt-Universität zu Berlin, Unter den Linden 6, 10099 Berlin, Germany e-mail: tim.wagner@hu-berlin.de 123 Argumentation DOI 10.1007/s10503-012-9280-9 Author's personal copy
  • 4. Aristotle’s writings provide a fundamental point of reference not only for historical approaches to argumentation theory, but also for some important modern theories of argumentation. This does not mean, of course, that all contemporary argumentation theorists are necessarily Aristotelians in one way or another; it only implies that down to the present day argument theorists have been profoundly inspired by Aristotle’s theory of argumentation. It is a remarkable coincidence that the founding fathers, as it were, of modern argumentation theory (MAT), Chaı̈m Perleman and Stephen Toulmin, define their projects by almost identical references to Aristotle: Both of them stress that logic in the sense that Aristotle calls ‘‘analytical’’ must be complemented by a project that corresponds to what Aristotle has delineated as ‘‘dialectic’’.1 They also converge in emphasizing that this dialectical dimension has been unduly neglected by the recent development of philosophical logic. Against the alleged one-sidedness of formal logic they both appeal to ancient dialectic in general and Aristotelian dialectic in particular for the study of real argumentation between concrete interlocutors in concrete situations. What they actually understand by Aristotelian ‘‘dialectic’’ can best be seen when one examines their own theories—theories which set the agenda for major parts of an emerging, modern argumentation theory; the program that is carried out in The Use of Arguments2 and in The New Rhetoric elaborates on something like a blend of Aristotle’s Topics and Rhetoric, where Toulmin’s argumentation scheme seems to be closer to the Topics, while the systematics of Chaı̈m Perleman’s and Lucie Olbrechts-Tyteca’s work is closer to the Rhetoric. Some subsequent developments of MAT put more stress on the notion of fallacy, thus also taking Aristotle’s treatise Sophistical refutations into account.3 In all these cases the recourse to Aristotle is significantly more than a revival of a historical position. The adaptation of selected Aristotelian theorems by MAT presupposes specific theoretical interests in the theory of argumentation and requires a theoretical framework like the one that has emerged from certain developments in twentieth-century philosophy. If we therefore speak of ‘‘Aristotelian sources’’ of MAT, we do not imply that these theorists have just picked up ready-made Aristotelian theorems that were waiting in textbooks and manuals to be rediscov- ered; we express, on the contrary, our awareness of the fact that these theories together with their Aristotelian ingredients are the result of the ongoing debate on how one can make the best sense of the rich, but sometimes ambiguous and inconsistent, Aristotelian material that has come down to us and of how this material fits best with the theoretical interests we happen to have. In this contribution we comment on just this sort of discussion; we try to lay bare some of the presuppositions made by some of the main representatives of MAT about the directions of the Aristotelian texts, and we attempt to point out theoretical options that, to our mind, are present in the Aristotelian texts. Thus, we will touch not only on Aristotelian theorems that were actually taken up by modern 1 Cf. Perelman and Olbrechts-Tyteca (1969, 5), and Toulmin (1986, 62). 2 Toulmin (1958). 3 Cf. e.g. Walton and Krabbe (1995), Woods and Walton (1989). On the state of the art in the study of fallacies see van Eemeren and Grootendorst (2004, chapter 7). Ch. Rapp, T. Wagner 123 Author's personal copy
  • 5. argumentation theorists, but also on Aristotelian ideas that are congenial with certain strands of MAT, but have not yet been explicitly used, finally on points where the direction of the Aristotelian texts seems to diverge from the modern ideas they inspired. Of course, we cannot do justice here to the complex state of discussion in MAT, therefore, we let our agenda be informed by what strike us as some of the core convictions of the aforementioned founding fathers of MAT, as well as by a more or less random selection of recent developments in MAT that we have lately encountered. 1 The Topics and the Rhetoric as Building Blocks of a Unified Theory of Argumentation? Let us start with an assumption that seems so obvious that it is seldom really discussed, but almost always tacitly presupposed, namely the assumption that there is something like a more or less coherent theory of argumentation in Aristotle. In fact, there is no single work of Aristotle’s that systematically unfolds his argumentation theory. The work that comes closest is Aristotle’s Topics—either alone or together with its sister treatise the Sophistical Refutations. Still, if we look into the Topics, we find instructions for a quite peculiar sort of discourse, namely the dialectical examination of philosophical theses on the basis of accepted or acceptable premises. The exercise that is pictured in the Topics is constrained by a set of artificial rules that distinguishes the dialectical exercise sharply from more natural, more conversational and more persuasion-oriented types of argumentation.4 If we look, however, into the Rhetoric—the other place in Aristotle that might be associated with his argumentation theory—we do find ample material for an account of persuasiveness; but, again, the types of arguments that are analysed or recommended in the Rhetoric are inseparably connected with public speaking and the narrowly defined occasions when these speeches have to be delivered: judicial speeches in court, political speeches at people’s assemblies, and epideictic speeches held at certain ceremonial events, most notably funerals.5 Given that neither the Topics nor the Rhetoric provide a general systematic theory of argumentation, what do we mean, after all, by an ‘‘Aristotelian theory of argumentation’’? Either we use this idea to refer selectively to particular Aristotelian theorems or techniques (e.g. the use of topoi) or we use it assuming that there is something like a more coherent underlying theory that can, in principle, be pieced together from Aristotle’s works, even if this underlying theory is not explicitly presented in any particular work. In following the second line of thought we have to explore whether the scattered ingredients of an Aristotelian theory of argumentation are interrelated in such a way that, taken together, they make up something like a coherent whole. For such an enterprise it will probably help to observe that the Topics and the Rhetoric can, up to a point, be seen as providing complementary aspects of such a theory of argumentation. For this reason, the 4 Cf. Aristotle, Topics VIII. 5 Cf. Aristotle, Rhetoric I.3. On Some Aristotelian Sources 123 Author's personal copy
  • 6. question whether there is something like a coherent theory of argumentation in Aristotle partly boils down to the issue of whether and how the two treatises or the two projects that are carried out in the respective treatises are interrelated, and this latter purpose, again, depends on some far from trivial assumptions concerning the nature of Aristotle’s Rhetoric. In what follows, we try to answer the questions of whether there is such a common on-going project underlying both the Topics and the Rhetoric, and, if so, how it might contribute to a unified or coherent theory of argumentation. To this end, we would like to start off with a preliminary characterisation of both sub- projects. It is the declared purpose of the Topics to outline a method by which we can find arguments for and against any given thesis, so that we will be able to attack or defend it at will.6 Although this method might, in principle, have manifold applications, the Topics applies it only to a specific kind of competition, in the course of which one of two disputants has to defend one of a contradictory pair of assertions, while his opponent tries to deduce the contradiction of the defendant’s original claim from assertions to which the defendant has committed himself during the debate. The aggressor, as it were, plays the role of the questioner, as he is the one who asks the answerer to assent to certain statements that, once admitted, can be used as premises for a final conclusion that contradicts the defendant’s original claim. Given this general setting, dialecticians as pictured in the Topics, are primarily interested in conclusive arguments, as it is the very goal of such conversations to compel the opponent to arrive at and assent to the intended conclusion. If the dialectical arguments were of a less binding type and were only meant to propose or suggest the step from the acceptance of certain premises to the acceptance of the insinuated conclusion, there would be no means by which to make the opponent accept a certain conclusion or give up his original claim. Some, mostly inexperienced, disputants may be vulnerable to accepting arguments that appear to be conclusive without really being so. It may happen that a disputant succeeds in driving his thesis home with the help of such fallacious arguments; but when the quality of the disputants’ arguments is assessed—and Aristotle mentions criteria for this kind of assessment in the eighth book of the Topics7 —the disputant will be criticized for using fallacious inferences. Furthermore, the dialectician has to be interested in endoxa, in accepted, acceptable or reputable assertions, as the answerer, in general, is committed to accept assertions that are of the acceptable type, and as the answerer would be foolish to accept assertions which are contrary to them (i.e. paradoxa in contrast to endoxa). The themes that are discussed in the dialectical disputations are taken from the philosophical debates of Aristotle’s time. This is why the examples given for dialectical theses are mostly general, not particular, in form; only the topoi from the third book of the Topics are suitable for forming arguments about particular claims. 6 Cf. Aristotle, Topics I.1, 100a 18–21. 7 Cf. Aristotle, Topics VIII.11. Ch. Rapp, T. Wagner 123 Author's personal copy
  • 7. But this is not a major surprise since this third book is most likely an appendix or even a later addition to the agenda of the second book of the Topics. Just as the Topics is, thus, interested in conclusiveness and validity, the Rhetoric deals with persuasiveness. And just as the Topics distinguishes between the valid and the only seemingly valid, the Rhetoric distinguishes between what is persuasive and what is only seemingly persuasive.8 Finally, just as the Topics promises to develop a method by which we can argue for and against any given thesis, the Rhetoric attempts to determine what can be considered persuasive on any given topic.9 Hence, both disciplines, dialectic and rhetoric, are, in principle, thematically unrestricted and attempt to determine the conclusive and the persuasive, respectively—regardless of whether the case in question is rather true than false or rather good than bad. Still, although the Rhetoric provides considerations that might be significant for persuasion in all possible fields of discourse, the three-book treatise that has come down to us under the title of rhêtorikê technê, turns out to be interested—as already indicated— only in persuasion in the realm of public speaking. Due to this limited field of application, the Rhetoric is mostly concerned with particular, non-general topics, such as whether, say, Alcibiades is guilty or not, but not with what it means to be guilty in general, or whether, for example, it is useful for the Athenians to build a wall here and now, but not with whether walls in general contribute to the flourishing of a city, let alone the question of what the flourishing of a city consists in. It seems, then, that for Aristotle dialectic and rhetoric are, at least in some respects, complementary: Dialectic applies to dialogical, face-to-face disputations about general topics, while rhetoric applies to speeches delivered to mass audiences on non-general, particular topics. Such a division of labour between the two projects might be taken as an indication that there is something like an on- going project involving the two disciplines of dialectic and rhetoric and the corresponding treatises the Topics and the Rhetoric. However, we must not forget that even if we take both treatises together, thus obtaining complementary aspects of a general theory of argumentation, the Topics and the Rhetoric as such do not provide a general, let alone exhaustive, analysis of argumentation; what we get are, for example, analyses of particular, contingent issues presented to a public audience and analyses of general philosophical questions discussed in the characteristic question–answer format that distinguishes Aristotelian dialectics; what we do not get, however, is an analysis of, say, arguments about particular and contingent issues presented in a dialogical face-to-face-situation. Nor do we get, if our description of the two sub-projects is right, the complementary analysis of the persuasiveness of arguments in the non-public sphere (given that it is not the purpose of dialectic to actually persuade or convince an opponent, but to bring him take positions from which his original position can be defeated). We can state, then, as an interim result that MAT is perfectly justified in assuming that, to a certain extent, Aristotle’s Topics and Rhetoric present something like an on- going project that covers different aspects of a general theory of argumentation. At the same time it is important to note that none of these writings aims at 8 Cf. Aristotle, Rhetoric I.1, 1355b 15 et seq. 9 Cf. Aristotle, Rhetoric I.2, 1355b 26 et seq. On Some Aristotelian Sources 123 Author's personal copy
  • 8. explicitly developing such a general theory, but that all pertinent writings, the Topics, the Rhetoric and the Sophistical Refutations confine themselves to certain narrow fields of argumentative discourse; taken together they fill some important spots on the map of different fields and types of argumentation, but they are far from providing a complete picture. 2 Delineating Dialectic and Rhetoric In the previous section we discussed the relation between the Topics and the Rhetoric and the corresponding fields of dialectic and rhetoric with a view to the possibility of a coherent Aristotelian theory of argumentation based on a division of labour. The relation between dialectic and rhetoric, however, is significant in at least one further respect: different strands of MAT associate themselves with either dialectic or rhetoric. Up to a point this might be a question of different terminologies and different traditions, but sometimes the association with one or the other of these fields indicates actual differences in the theoretical approaches. Quite tentatively, some of the self-declared dialecticians are more interested in the difference between sound and fallacious arguments, and some of the rhetoricians are more interested in all perlocutionary aspects of our speech acts. The former display an interest in refraining from ‘‘merely’’ psychological questions, while the latter warn against a too narrow notion of argumentation. Hence, the delineation between dialectic and rhetoric is definitely an issue in MAT.10 Against that background, it is natural that authors attempt to position their own approaches by way of reference to Aristotle, who gave the first elaborate account of the interrelation of both fields. Unfortunately, the reference to Aristotle and his model for correlating dialectic and rhetoric does not lead to an unambiguous result, because his statements to the effect that rhetoric is a counterpart to dialectic or an offshoot of it11 have been deemed highly obscure. Notwithstanding the notorious difficulties in understanding these formulas, it is beyond all doubt that for Aristotle dialectic and rhetoric are similar, since neither discipline is conceived as an epistêmê of a well-defined subject matter; both are rather concerned with arguments for and against any given position; just as dialecticians command a technê by which they can attack and defend any given (philosophical) thesis, the rhetorician is supposed to command a technê in virtue of which he will be able, for example, to accuse or defend any given defendant in court. Furthermore, both of them deal with arguments derived solely from accepted or acceptable opinions, and not from scientific principles. It is possible to delineate the common ground between dialectic and rhetoric by such similarities. The most basic philosophical rationale, however, 10 Cf. the papers that are collected in van Eemeren and Houtlosser (2002) as well as van Eemeren’s contribution to this issue. 11 Rhetoric is a counterpart to dialectic: Rhetoric I.1, 1354a 1; it is an offshoot of dialectic and the study of character: I.2, 1356a 25–27, it is a part of dialectic: I.2, 1356a 30 et seq., it is similar to it: I.2, 1356a 31. Ch. Rapp, T. Wagner 123 Author's personal copy
  • 9. for Aristotle’s attempt to align rhetoric with dialectic becomes obvious from the following train of thought: The activity of persuasion is, as Aristotle points out at the beginning of the Rhetoric, a kind of proof or proving.12 Why so? People are most convinced, or so Aristotle says,13 when they take something to have been proven. It is therefore legitimate to model the persuasive endeavour of the rhetorician as a kind of proof (apodeixis). Given that all proofs are kinds of sullogismoi—which we take to be deductive arguments—persuasion can essentially be described in terms of sullogismoi, i.e. deductive arguments. What Aristotle seems to presuppose is that persuasion essentially follows the structure of a deductive premise-conclusion argument: In order to convince the audience of a suggested thesis or suggestion, the orator has to infer this thesis from what the audience already believes. In a similar vein, Aristotle claims in the De Anima that each doxa, each opinion in the proper sense, derives from an inference (sullogismos)—and this is, in Aristotle’s view, the reason why animals cannot have opinions in the proper sense. Within whose purview does the deductive argument fall? We would probably say within the purview of the logician. Aristotle, by contrast, says that it falls within the purview of the dialectician14 —regardless of whether he simply had no word for logic in our sense or whether he really meant that it is the dialectician, if anyone, who is the real expert for all kinds or applications of the sullogismos. However this may be, if it is true that all sullogismoi fall within the purview of the dialectician and if the syllogistic, i.e. deductive, premise-conclusion structure is essential for all persuasive endeavours, then it follows that rhetoric, if it is concerned with persuasion, essentially relies on the part of dialectic that is responsible for the sullogismos. Indeed, Aristotle says in the Rhetoric that it is the dialectician who is in fact responsible for all kinds of sullogismos and that the dialectician will also become the master of the rhetorical argument if he only acknowledges the differences between the dialectical and the rhetorical sullogismos. On this account, there is no fundamental conflict between dialectic and rhetoric. Furthermore, if sound arguments guarantee the reasonableness of argumentation and if arguments are thought to be an efficient means of persuasion, neither is there a fundamental conflict between reasonableness and effectiveness. This, we think, is the essential rationale behind the dialectical turn of rhetoric initiated by Aristotle; against rhetorical predecessors who, from Aristotle’s point of view, were too much concerned with effectiveness, he aspires to show that arguments are central to persuasion and not less effective than certain techniques by which the rhetorician is instructed to speak outside the subject. Of course, no argument is thought to be persuasive as it stands; it is one of the most crucial ingredients of Aristotle’s rhetorical theory of argumentation that the general dialectical account of arguments must be adjusted to the hearers and the subject matters of a public speech. And it is of course true that Aristotle’s theory of persuasion includes moments beside mere argumentation: Among the three technical means of persuasion (pisteis) there are 12 Cf. Aristotle, Rhetoric I.1, 1355a 4 et sq. 13 Cf. Aristotle, Rhetoric I.1, 1355a 5 et sq. 14 Cf. Aristotle, Rhetoric I.1, 1355a 8–10. On Some Aristotelian Sources 123 Author's personal copy
  • 10. also the emotional state of the audience (pathos) and the character or credibility of the speaker (êthos); to this list we might add the linguistic form (lexis) and the order of the parts of speech (taxis). There have been many scholarly debates about how these non-argumentative means of persuasion (or should they also be called ‘‘argumentative’’ in some way? See Sect. 6, below) are related to logos, argument15 ; however, there are many indications that the introduction of these non-argumen- tative means of persuasion are not meant to relativize the central role of argumentation; after all, almost three-fourths of the text of Rhetoric I and II are dedicated to argumentation in the narrow sense, and when Aristotle turns to the discussion of lexis in Rhetoric III, he stresses that this is only a secondary concern.16 Also, when Aristotle says that it is necessary not only to look at the argument, but also to present oneself as a certain kind of person and to prepare the emotional state of the audience, as rhetoric always aims at the judgment of the audience,17 it seems as if the non-argumentative means are required just to stabilize the audience’s judgment formation and thus to enhance the effect of the given arguments.18 However one construes these aspects of the Aristotelian theory in detail, it seems clear that the model he offers for reconciling dialectic and rhetoric is one in which rhetoric is firmly based on dialectic, and rhetorical effectiveness is thought to flow from reasonable arguments—assuming they are suitably chosen—and to not ask too much of the audience of a public speech.19 3 Aristotelian Arguments and MAT Argumentation: A Mismatch? Every argumentation theory should include an elucidation of what it is to be an argument and what is meant by ‘‘argumentation’’. It is not entirely trivial, however, to map Aristotle’s contributions to the definition of arguments onto the consensus of MAT. As for MAT, there are, of course, many different approaches to defining arguments and argumentation. There are, however, some recurring characterisations that we would like to take as a starting point. Toulmin, to begin with, emphasizes that while formal logic is concerned with propositions, argumentation theory deals with concrete utterances.20 In a similar vein, Perelman loves to contrast demonstration with argumentation: While demonstration proceeds in an impersonal and abstract way, argumentation is always addressed at somebody; it ‘‘aims at gaining the adherence of minds’’.21 Finally, in van Eemeren and Grootendorst 15 For a brief and useful overview see Kienpointner (2011, 10–12). 16 Cf. Aristotle, Rhetoric III.1, 1403b 18–20. 17 Cf. Aristotle, Rhetoric II.1, 1377b 21–24. 18 For an elaboration of this view, see Rapp (2012). 19 Put in such general terms, this goal seems to be congenial with more recent developments in MAT: ‘‘The Aristotelian rhetorical norm of successful persuasion is not necessarily in contradiction with the ideal of reasonableness that lies at the heart of the pragma-dialectical approach’’ (van Eemeren and Houtlosser 1999, 165). We owe this reference to Kientpointner (2011). 20 Cf. Toulmin (1996). 21 Cf. e.g. Perelman and Olbrechts-Tyteca (1969, 14), Perelman (1994, 85). Ch. Rapp, T. Wagner 123 Author's personal copy
  • 11. argumentation is defined as ‘‘a verbal, social, and rational activity aimed at convincing a reasonable critic of the acceptability of a standpoint by putting forward a constellation of propositions justifying or refuting the propositions expressed in the standpoint.’’22 Let us leave it at that for the moment and go back to Aristotle. First, it seems that there is no single word or terminus in Aristotle equivalent to ‘‘argument’’. In Topics I.12 he writes that there are two kinds of dialectical logos, and then he hastens to distinguish between sullogismos and epagôgê—which is best rendered as deductive and inductive argument. What most nearly approximates the notion of an argument in this context is logos—but this word’s lack of specificity is almost proverbial. The most neutral meaning in this context is that a logos is a sequence of words, but this reading renders the division into exactly two kinds inappropriate. Of course, logos can also be translated as ‘‘reason’’—the faculty of reasoning as well as the reasons we can give. That arguments have to do with reasoning is clear, as is the fact that providing reasons for what we maintain is close to the notion of arguing. It seems, then, that due to these several ingredients, Aristotle finds it natural to use the word logos as a generic term for what the two irreducible forms of argument, sullogismos and epagôgê, have in common. In the same chapter of the Topics Aristotle also states that an epagôgê is given when we proceed from the particular to the general.23 This is why epagôgê came to be translated as ‘‘induction’’ or ‘‘inductive argument’’. In the Rhetoric Aristotle briefly revisits the issue of induction and tells us that the rhetorical form of induction is an example of an argument which proceeds not from the particular to the general, but from one particular to another.24 The sad truth about the theory of induction in Aristotle is that this is almost all he has to say about it. In both treatises, the Topics and the Rhetoric, he hastens to get back to the sullogismos, and in both fields, dialectic and rhetoric, he seems to be almost oblivious to the inductive form of argumentation and models both dialectical disputation and rhetorical persuasion almost entirely in terms of ‘‘syllogistic’’, i.e. sullogismos-based, reasoning. Possibly, this privileging of the sullogimos can be partly relativized, as Eggs (1992, 918) suggests, if we assume that in some passages the word sullogismos takes over the role of the missing generic concept for both forms of arguments, but it remains true and indisputable that major parts of Aristotle’s argumentation theory are centred around the notion of sullogismos, while the corresponding inductive form of argumentation is widely neglected. What is meant in Aristotle by sullogismos? Aristotle defines the sullogismos as an argument in which, certain things being supposed, something different from the suppositions results of necessity from them.25 According to this definition, the sullogismos is roughly what we would call a deductive argument; it is remarkable that this definition does not refer to the syllogistic theory that is developed in the Prior Analytics. This means that when Aristotle speaks of the sullogismos in the Topics and the Rhetoric (which, by the way, uses the same definition of sullogismos) 22 Cf. van Eemeren and Grootendorst (2004, 1). 23 Cf. Aristotle, Topics I.12, 105a 13 et seq. 24 Cf. Aristotle, Rhetoric I.2, 1357b 25–36. 25 Cf. Aristotle, Topics I.1, 100a 25–27. On Some Aristotelian Sources 123 Author's personal copy
  • 12. we should not expect the formally restricted canonical sullogismos that we know from the syllogistic theory, with exactly two premises and three terms, one of which is the middle term, etc. The Topics seems to be entirely untouched by this theory and hence it is no surprise that the arguments we do find in the Topics and in the Rhetoric do not obey to any formal restriction of this kind. That they are formally less rigid than the arguments from Aristotle’s syllogistic theory does not mean, however, that they are meant to be logically more relaxed. On the contrary, the definition quoted makes clear that the conclusion of a sullogismos is something that follows of necessity from the premises. According to Aristotle’s definition, it is certainly true of the sullogismos that it includes a constellation of propositions put forward in order to justify the proposition that is expressed as the conclusion. On the basis of the same definition it seems, however, that the justification is only seen as successful if the conclusion follows of necessity from the premises. In comparison to modern accounts, which only expect that in argumentation we try to make our standpoint more acceptable or reasonable or that we justify it one way or another, this would be a much more severe constraint. It is also clear that the notion of the sullogismos is neutral with respect to the difference between demonstration and (dialectical) argumentation. The definition of the sullogismos that is used either with scientific principles in order to provide a scientific demonstration or with (only) accepted opinions in order to serve as a dialectical argument is the same in both cases. This corresponds to the fact that, as opposed to the MAT definitions we mentioned, the audience and the expected effect on the audience is not mentioned in Aristotle’s definition of the sullogismos. On the basis of this brief and preliminary comparison we can state the following possibly substantial discrepancies (disregarding the fact that, as we said, the notion of sullogismos covers only one of the two species that fall under the generic notion of argument): (1) In comparison to a rich notion of argumentation that includes a reference to the addressee the notion of the sullogismos seems to be rather underdetermined. Looking from this perspective, it seems promising not to take the ‘‘bare’’, as it were, notion of sullogismos as possibly equivalent to the MAT notion of argumentation, but to look at the class of arguments with ‘‘endoxic’’ premises, i.e. premises that are accepted by certain addressees.26 (2) According to some—not all—MAT-accounts of argumentation, the addressee’s readiness to find a standpoint acceptable can be increased by many means, both verbal and non-verbal, and not only by putting forward premise-like constellations of propositions. From this point of view, the Aristotelian premise-conclusion model of argumentation may seem too narrow. One possible response would be to include means of persuasion that do not belong to logos, as Aristotle puts it, in the notion of argumentation (see Sect. 6, below); there is the risk, however, that we might broaden the notion of argumentation to the point where everything that is possibly persuasive is rated as argument, which is most probably not Aristotle’s intention. Another, more conservative response would be to look for places where Aristotle himself cautiously broadens the concept of argument. One such passage, e.g., would be the 26 See Sect. 4, below; there will be, however, different uses of the accepted premises. Ch. Rapp, T. Wagner 123 Author's personal copy
  • 13. discussion of maxims in Rhetoric II.21, where Aristotle acknowledges that arguments can be given without the explicit use of the premise-conclusion scheme: In the maxims ‘‘Being a mortal, do not cherish immortal anger’’ or ‘‘A mortal should think mortal, not immortal, thoughts’’ the reason is, as Aristotle says, implicitly given by the mention of ‘‘mortal’’.27 (3) The conviction that deductive arguments are nearly omnipresent (Aristotle defines the sullogismos as deductive argument and finds sullogismoi in everything from logic and dialectic to scientific demonstration and rhetoric) seems to be absent from most MAT schools. Even those who are concerned about the reasonableness of argumentation need not require all acceptable arguments to be deductive; quite often it seems to be sufficient that the transition from a premise to a conclusion seems to be reasonable—but not necessary—under the given circumstances. This would be a substantial discrepancy. For this reason it seems that Aristotle’s notion of an argument can be adapted to MAT and fully modernized only if we can find hints of more ‘‘relaxed’’ notions of argument in Aristotle. It is widely held that one can find such a notion in Aristotle’s Rhetoric. Let us briefly examine this possibility: Taking up a terminus from traditional rhetoric, Aristotle calls the rhetorical form of proof an ‘‘enthymeme’’. Again and again he stresses that the enthymeme28 is a kind of sullogismos or that it is the rhetorical form of the sullogismos, i.e. of the deductive argument, while the example is the rhetorical version of the inductive argument. As we have already said, Aristotle even invokes the dialectician’s expertise in all kinds of sullogismos for the construction of enthymemes. Even the advocates of ‘‘relaxed’’ arguments must admit that so far this entire setting does not indicate any relaxation for rhetorical arguments. They therefore take recourse to the definition of the enthymeme in Aristotle’s Rhetoric, where they try to detect indications of a more relaxed way of arguing. In fact, the definition of the enthymeme slightly modifies the standard definition of the sullogismos that we discussed above; in rhetoric we speak of an enthymeme, Aristotle says, when, ‘‘certain things being the case, something different beside them results because of their being either universally or for the most part the case.’’29 The most controversial modification of the standard definition obviously lies in the qualification ‘‘for the most part’’. On the one hand, if this qualification was meant to qualify the inference itself—indicating that the conclusion does not follow of necessity, but only for the most part—then, indeed, the idea of a deductive argument would have to be abandoned. On the other hand, it is also possible to understand this definition as saying that the premises maintain something to be the case either universally or (only) for the most part. This latter reading would qualify the status of the premise(s), not the inference itself. One could argue now, from a modern point of view, that a premise that holds only for the most part or is only probable does not allow for any necessary, but only for probable inferences. Again, this would result in a remarkable deviation from, and a relaxation of, the deductive model. However, it 27 Cf. Aristotle, Rhetoric, II.21, 1394b 20–25. 28 There is a long-standing tradition that takes the enthymeme to be an incomplete syllogism. This is not Aristotle’s view: see below, Sect. 4. 29 Cf. Aristotle, Rhetoric. I.2 1356b 15–17. For a different interpretation cf. Burnyeat (1994). On Some Aristotelian Sources 123 Author's personal copy
  • 14. seems that this is not Aristotle’s view, for he seems to be happy with saying that what follows from a for-the-most-part premise is a for-the-most-part conclusion, but that this modally qualified conclusion still follows of logical necessity (‘‘If such- and-such is for the most part true, then it follows of necessity that something else is for the most part true’’). On this account, Aristotle is being generous in granting that due to the contingent subject matter of a public speech the premises and the conclusions of rhetorical arguments very rarely express necessities, but he is still insistent on his view that the deductive scheme can be used for relating for-the- most-part premises to for-the-most-part conclusions.30 In recent scholarship the deductivist reading of Aristotle’s enthymemes has come under scrutiny by interpreters who are obviously interested in bringing Aristotle closer to the insights of MAT. Here, it seems quite clear that it is not Aristotle who inspired MAT, but MAT that encouraged certain readings of Aristotle. Whichever reading will prevail in the long run, it seems fair to say that Aristotle heavily relied on his deductive scheme, that he stressed the less stringent character of rhetorical premises rather than the possibility of less rigid inferences and that, if he was really willing to deviate from the deductive scheme, he was not quite explicit in doing so. 4 Paying Attention to the Addressee’s Convictions and Capacities As we said at the outset of this paper, MAT sets itself off from the analytic part of logic or from the fixation on formal aspects of arguments by emphasizing that all arguments are directed to concrete addressees with individual convictions. If argumentation in general, as for example Perelman stresses,31 aims at increasing the addressee’s readiness to approve a suggested point of view, a substantial account of argumentation has to take into account what different groups of hearers are convinced of and how arguments can be adjusted to the convictions of the people they address. If we look for an equivalent interest in Aristotle, we will first be faced with his highly developed account of the role of endoxa—accepted, acceptable or reputable opinions that play a major role in both his Topics and his Rhetoric. The dialectical argument is defined by Aristotle as an argument, sullogismos, from accepted or acceptable (endoxa) premises. This is what distinguishes dialectical from scientific arguments,32 as the latter have to apply premises that are true (i.e. established as true) and, as Aristotle puts it, ‘‘first’’. For the dialectical disputation, it does not matter whether the deployed premises are true or not; it suffices that they are acceptable and that they have actually been accepted or granted by the dialectical interlocutor. Neither does it matter whether the defendant who grants a certain premise is personally convinced of the truth of this premise or not. Due to the rules 30 At this point the supporter of relaxed rhetorical arguments could refer to one type of the sign- enthymeme, which, as Aristotle says, does not yield a sullogismos, but is nevertheless rated as ‘‘enthymeme’’. The status of such arguments, however, is precarious, since in some passages Aristotle treats them straightforwardly as fallacies (see below, Sect. 7). 31 Cf. Perleman and Olbrechts-Tyteca (1969, § 3 et seqq). 32 Cf. Aristotle, Topics I.1, 100a 29–100b 23. Ch. Rapp, T. Wagner 123 Author's personal copy
  • 15. of a dialectical disputation, he has no choice but to accept it if it is accepted by all, by most or by the experts—provided he cannot come up with a counterexample. For the rhetorician, on the contrary, everything depends on whether he is able to provide premises that coincide with the convictions of the audience. It is the fundamental idea of Aristotle’s technique of persuasion that it is possible to bring an audience to an intended conclusion by appealing to the audience’s extant convictions and by inferentially connecting these pre-existing convictions with the insinuated conclu- sion. For this reason, the endoxa, the acceptable assertions that are used by the rhetorician, are only a subset of the assertions that can be considered by the dialectician; in a word, the rhetorician is not interested in the variety of accepted opinions, but only in what a given audience might possibly be convinced of. In dialectic, it is not the aim of the dialectical competitor to change the opponent’s conviction or attitude; he can be content if he succeeds in compelling the competitor to accept the insinuated conclusion; in rhetoric, by contrast, the rhetorician is expected to steer the audience’s judgment formation up to the point that people give their vote or cast their ballot in accordance with what the rhetorician suggests. To achieve this, the rhetorician cannot rely on the audience’s willingness to obey certain procedural rules (as the dialectical competitors are bound to do). Either the rhetorician succeeds in tracing the intended conclusion back to the audience’s pre- existing convictions or he has no influence whatsoever on what they decide. We can then say that although both dialectic and rhetoric make use of accepted opinions, endoxa, they do not use the same set of endoxa, they do not use them for the same purpose and they do not use them in the same way. Although all dealings with endoxa fall within the purview of the dialectician, it is the field of rhetoric that applies the use of endoxa in a way that comes close to the interests of MAT to systematically include the addressee’s individual conviction or mental horizon in the study of arguments. In a similar vein, Aristotle says in the Rhetoric that whatever is persuasive is persuasive to somebody.33 However, he admits that not even the rhetorician can pick out individual convictions, but must confine himself to what is persuasive to people of a certain general type.34 In practice, when the orator is confronted with a mass audience he often has to start from quite general or widespread convictions (koina),35 without being able to do justice to individual preference or to preferences of certain groups (e.g. the young, the elderly, the rich, the poor, etc.36 )—however that might be, this is one example where we could say that although the scope of Aristotle’s is quite limited (here: limited to the expectations of a mass audience of a public speech), the theoretical instrument for generally incorporating the convictions and expectations of the addressees is actually present. Beside the system of the endoxa, there is another important aspect of how Aristotelian rhetoric tries to adjust arguments to the addressee’s intellectual horizon: when Aristotle describes the peculiarities of rhetorical arguments, to which he 33 Cf. Aristotle, Rhetoric I.2, 1356b 26 et seq. 34 Cf. Aristotle, Rhetoric I.2, 1356b 28–34. 35 Cf. Aristotle, Rhetoric I.1, 1355a 27. 36 Cf. Aristotle, Rhetoric II.12–17. Perelman and Olbrechts-Tyteca (1969, 20), refer to these chapters as contributions to the rhetorician’s knowledge of the audience. On Some Aristotelian Sources 123 Author's personal copy
  • 16. assigns the traditional rhetorical term ‘‘enthymeme’’, he stresses that the rhetorical proofs must not be taken from ‘‘too far away’’, because the typical hearer of a public speech is supposed to be a simple person who is not able to follow long chains of argument.37 Due to a long-standing interpretative tradition which understands Aristotelian enthymemes to be abbreviated arguments in which one of the required premises is suppressed, commentators have often taken this remark as a comment on the suppression of premises. In fact, what Aristotle says is that enthymemes must not be as precise as a scientific demonstration and that they should be shorter than ordinary dialectical arguments. This, however, is not to say that the enthymeme is defined by incompleteness and brevity. The orator can avoid lengthy chains of arguments by selecting the right premises, i.e. premises that are not too far from the intended conclusions. On this reading, it seems that it is essential for the rhetorical argument that it be adjusted to the capacity, expectation and intellectual horizon of the given audience. The drawback, however, is that Aristotle’s effort to adjust arguments to public audiences remains rather one-dimensional, as all these arrangements are made with a view to the intellectual insufficiency of a public mass audience. 5 The Uses of Topoi We have already said that in the Rhetoric the sullogismos falls within the purview of the dialectician. Part of this purview certainly consists in a sullogismos in the way we discussed above in Sect. 3. It is likely, however, that the dialectician’s competence also includes the ability to discern valid and invalid arguments or to overlook, in general, the manifold ways in which such sullogismoi can be construed. In the Topics the long catalogues of topoi seem to present different ways of construing such deductive arguments. If we regard the topoi as something like argumentative schemes, acquainting ourselves with these schemes will help us to identify valid arguments, just as acquainting ourselves with a list of possible fallacies will help us to detect deceptive arguments. At the same time, the catalogue of topoi can be seen as a manual for the construction of arguments. How exactly the topoi guide us in finding and constructing arguments is a controversial issue.38 The minimal scholarly consensus is that the topoi are meant to be useful for the construction of premises for a given conclusion. This means that we already have to know the conclusion we intend to draw (within the dialectical game this is the contradiction of what the opponent says), and that the topos helps us to construe a premise from which we can deduce the intended conclusion—provided the opponent assents to this premise. In the literature this is often called the ‘‘inventive’’ function of a topos. According to this inventive function the topos contributes to the task of premise selection (although it is not the topos itself that determines whether the required premise is an endoxon or not). We, at least, think that the topos has not 37 Cf. Aristotle, Rhetoric I.2, 1357a 17–22. 38 Cf. De Pater (1965) and the introduction to Brunschwig (1967); for a brief summary of the scholarly discussion see also Wagner and Rapp (2004, 29–35). Ch. Rapp, T. Wagner 123 Author's personal copy
  • 17. only this inventive but also a probative function in that it also guarantees the transition from the premises to the conclusion (if the topos, e.g., says that whatever holds of the genus, must also hold of each species, then the same topos is a warrant, as it were, for the transition from a premise concerning a particular genus to a conclusion about its species). What we should add about the use of topoi is this: the use of topoi is essential for both projects, the Topics and the Rhetoric. In the Topics the topoi deployed are not dependent on specific subjects or themes. Therefore, the topoi here are mostly taken from semantic, logical or otherwise general rules. In the Rhetoric Aristotle distinguishes between general and specific topoi, where the general correspond to the topoi of the Topics39 and the specific are such in the sense that they can only be used to construe arguments with a specific predicate, for example arguments about what is good, just or noble. If Aristotle says that the latter type of topoi, the specific, are more appropriate for rhetorical use, this certainly reflects the difference we already alluded to, i.e. that dialectic is mostly about general topics, while rhetoric aims at judgments about particular states of affairs. The Aristotelian technique of topoi has generally met with sympathy and approval by the proponents of MAT. Quite generally, the Aristotelian topoi are often invoked as ‘‘role models’’ when the notion of an argumentation scheme is introduced. In particular, Toulmin’s general analysis of the structure of argumen- tation introduces the important notion of an ‘‘inference warrant’’,40 and it has often been observed that the role of these warrants resembles that of the topoi in Aristotle41 —at least in its probative function. In legal theory Viehweg appealed to Gian Battista Vico’s contraposition of the old rhetorical/topical and the new critical/ geometrical method42 ; Viehweg attempts to show that within the realm of jurisprudence, the topical method (for which he explicitly refers to Aristotle and Cicero) is far superior to the axiomatic-systematic approach. Perelman, too, often highlights that in jurisdiction there are remnants of the old rhetorical art of argumentation. He regards Aristotelian topoi as the most general premises, but wishes to distinguish his own use of loci from the Aristotelian one; first, he attempts to get rid of what he takes to be a metaphysical contamination of Aristotelian 39 Even if most of the general topoi in the Rhetoric are not really general in the same sense as the topoi of the Topics are; most are general only in the sense that they can be used in all three genres of speech, while the specific ones are always peculiar to one such genre or to one of the key notions of a genre, ‘‘just’’ in the judicial speech, ‘‘good’’ in the forensic speech, and ‘‘noble’’ in the epideictic speech. Still, the notion of a general topos in the Rhetoric clearly refers back to the project of the Topics, though only five out of 28 general topoi in Rhetoric II.23 clearly resemble the topoi of the Topics (1397a 7–19, 1397a 20–23, 1397b 12–174 , 1397b 174 –27, 1399a 6–9). Insofar as the topoi in the Topics rest on, as we have said, semantic, logical or otherwise general rules it makes little sense to stress, as Warnick (2000, 111 et seq.) does, the cultural dependency of these topoi. As an example Warnick introduces the topos from the opposites—that if a and b are opposites and a has the quality q, the opposite of quality q can be predicated of b. To our mind, this is just one application of Aristotle’s complex logical system of opposites and does not indicate specific cultural preferences. Revealingly, Warnick uses the example that Aristotle gives afterwards to make her point, not the general scheme. 40 Cf. Toulmin (1958, Chapter 3). 41 Cf. Bird (1961). 42 Cf. Viehweg (1963, §§ 1–2). On Some Aristotelian Sources 123 Author's personal copy
  • 18. topoi,43 and second, he tries to preserve the term for premises about what is valuable and preferable.44 Others have tried to show that the argument schemes that Perelman and Olbrechts-Tyteca unfold in The New Rhetoric45 broadly correspond to the common topoi in Aristotle’s Rhetoric II.23. Indeed, several accounts of argumentation schemes have been development in MAT quite independently from Aristotle, but with an awareness of the historical origins of such schemes, e.g. Kientpointner and Walton, to mention only two, have worked extensively on such an argumentation theory.46 Kienpointner and Rigotti have also stressed the inventive/generative aspect of Aristotelian topoi; Rigotti has even labeled them as ‘‘argument generators’’.47 Tetens observes that formal logic is of limited use for argumentation training. He refers to the ancient tradition in general and the Aristotelian tradition in particular, which abstracted paradigmatic arguments to more general argumentation schemes which are limited to certain fields and themes, and are not universally applicable. The formulation of such argumentation patterns and the use of such patterns in making students sensible of differences between good and bad argumentation belong, as Tetens puts it, to the realm of topics, as originally formulated by Aristotle.48 In the light of these few examples it seems that the success of Aristotle’s technique of topoi in MAT is undisputed. We would nevertheless like to point out some differences between Aristotle’s use of topoi and the various uses that MAT has made of them: 43 What Perelman means by ‘‘metaphysical’’ is Aristotle’s system of the four predicables (definition, accidental predicate, genus, proprium), by which the topoi of the Topics are structured and from which many of the general rules that make up the topoi are taken. It is certainly true that, e.g., the difference between essential and accidental predicates rest on a certain metaphysics; it is still disputable whether this topical system is therefore ‘‘metaphysically loaded’’. After all, the way in which the predicables are introduced in the Topics gives clear criteria for the distinction of four sorts of predicates and does not appeal to specific theorems of Aristotle’s metaphysics. 44 This is obviously the reason for Perelman’s somewhat surprising interest in the topoi of Aristotle, Topics III (Cf. Perelman and Olbrechts-Tyteca 1969, § 21, and Perelman 1994, Chapter II.4). This narrow focus is surprising, since, as we already said, the topoi of book III of the Topics are in several respects exceptional within the Topics, most notably because they (also) apply to practical-particular and to philosophical-general questions. 45 Cf. Warnick (2000, 109): I. The quasi logical ones: contradiction, incompatibility (1), identity, definition, analyticity, tautology (2), reciprocity, rule of justice (3), transitivity, inclusion, division (4), weights, measures, probabilities (5), II. The ones based on the structure of reality: (liaisons of succession (6), liaisons of coexistence (7), symbolic liaisons, double hierarchies, differences of degree and order (8), III. The ones establishing the structure of reality: example (9), illustration (10), model and anti-model (11), analogy and metaphor (12), IV. Dissociation.—To be honest, we find not only Warnick’s general account of the general topoi questionable (see footnote 39 above), but also regard many of the similarities between Aristotle and The New Rhetoric she wishes to discover quite superficial. The problem is that many of the common or general topoi of the Rhetoric are—due to Aristotle’s use of historical speeches— too narrowly formulated and not really abstracted from the examples used. 46 Cf. Kienpointner (1997). Among the many titles by Walton we just want to mention one of his most recent works on argumentation schemes: Walton et al. (2008). This latter book generously includes a historical survey of argumentation schemes (chapter 8). Unfortunately, the section on Aristotelian topoi turns out to be quite distorting, so that no informative conclusion about Walton’s view of Aristotle can be drawn. For Kienpointner on Aristotle see Kienpointner (2005, 2011). 47 Cf. Rigotti (2007). 48 Cf. Tetens (2011), in particular, 491 et seqq., see also Tetens (2004, 54). Ch. Rapp, T. Wagner 123 Author's personal copy
  • 19. Quite often when Aristotle’s technique of topoi is invoked by MAT-authors the topical approach is used to construe a contrast between the topical method and all sorts of deductive reasoning. The assumption of such a contrast is certainly correct in one important way, but it is also misleading in several other ways. It is right, to begin with, also from an Aristotelian point of view to say that the topical method is different from an axiomatic-deductive method; when using Aristotelian topoi for construing arguments we choose a particular topos out of a plurality of topoi and we take the reliability of the topos for granted, without investigating its credentials. We are not interested, unlike those taking an axiomatic-deductivist approach, in reducing the multitude of topoi to a few axioms or in deriving the topoi or the conclusions we drew with their help from first, improvable axioms. This is, we think, the basic sense, in which the topical and the axiomatic methods are opposed. This does not exclude, however, the possibility of inquiring into some more general rules or principles that govern several sets of topoi. For example, in the Topics many topoi are derived from the rules inherent in the four kinds of predication (the predicables), while others derive from the rules implied by the several forms of oppositions, from the genius-species-relation, etc. Even in ancient times, commen- tators were therefore seeking to identify such general ‘‘maxims’’.49 It would also be misleading to separate the use of topoi from deductions by making topoi a mere matter of invention (of premises), while the construction of the corresponding arguments is left to the logician. Such a characterization of Aristotelian topoi derives from a traditional picture of the division of labour between Aristotle’s Topics and his Analytica. According to this tradition, the Topics is exclusively concerned with the finding of premises, while the business of logic is left to another discipline. This tradition obviously derives from an over-systematization of the Aristotelian Organon. It is more plausible to assume, as we have already said, that for Aristotle the topoi also represented different modes of how a sullogismos can be conclusive, and thus he meant to ascribe an additional probative function to the topoi. Most notably, it is misleading to use Aristotle’s topical approach to construe a contrast between topical and deductively valid arguments. A widespread assumption is that as soon as topoi enter the stage, people are no longer really interested in deductive arguments, but in mere plausibility, in inferences that seem likely, understandable and in accordance with common opinion, but that do not necessarily form a valid deductive argument. It is quite obvious where this picture comes from, if we take into account that topoi regularly occur together with endoxa, accepted premises, in Aristotle’s dialectics. However, within an Aristotelian frame this picture appears misleading on closer examination, as in Aristotle’s dialectic topoi are supposed to construe sullogismoi (deductive arguments) that are formally equivalent to scientific demon- strations. Dialectical arguments differ from demonstrations not in their form or logical rigour, but only in the quality of the premises.50 For Aristotle, then, there is no tension between the use of topoi and the adherence to deductive arguments. 49 Cf. Alexander of Aphrodisias, In Arist. Top. II, 135, 2 et seq. (Wallies); for the idea of grouping several topoi under more general headings, see also Rapp (2000). 50 The same is also true of rhetorical arguments or enthymemes, which are defined as sorts of sullogismoi (see above, Sect. 3). On Some Aristotelian Sources 123 Author's personal copy
  • 20. Finally, it is misleading if the Aristotelian use of topoi is captured by the contrast of formal and material reasoning or argumentation.51 As we have said, many of the general topoi of the Topics are taken from rules that derive from the several types of predication. If, e.g., a thesis expresses a definitional predication, then it is clear that whatever holds for the subject must also hold for the (defining) predicate and vice versa. If a topos is derived from such rules, it is the form of predication and not the content that matters and, hence, such a topos is far from being ‘‘material’’. This is also the reason why the restricted applicability of topoi is sometimes overempha- sized.52 In the Topics the system of topoi is supposed to provide arguments for and against any thesis, regardless of content, and for that purpose a ‘‘material’’ character and the resulting limited applicability are not useful. What these MAT authors seem to have in mind are rather specific topoi, as we find them in the first book of the Rhetoric. These topoi, however, are often understood as merely providing acceptable opinions on different subjects, while a topos in the proper sense is expected to do more, i.e. to ‘‘find’’ or to ‘‘construe’’ a premise or to formulate a complete argument. Whether and how the specific topoi match up to this expectation has seldom been examined.53 At any rate, it would be mistaken to take the less interesting lists of specific topoi as paradigmatic for all Aristotelian topoi. 6 Character and Emotions: Towards a Broader Notion of Argumentation? Aristotle’s theory of argumentation as it is laid out in the Topics does not seem to be interested in factors related to interpersonal communication situations. Arguments are primarily seen as sequences of intellectual steps. Their linguistic realization, the form in which they are presented and their effect on the hearers are only touched upon at random. Aristotle’s treatise on the art of rhetoric, by contrast, even though it rather focuses on monologic speeches and not on dialogical situations, is less restricted; the person of the speaker, the disposition and horizon of the hearer, the general situation and context are all taken into consideration. This leads to the question whether the rather narrow notion of argumentation that can be found in the Topics (and likewise in the Analytics) is altered to fit into the framework of the Rhetoric. If so, Aristotle could be seen as an early source of broader, more pluralistic notions of argumentation, as they are discussed in MAT. From a technical point of view the addressee can be persuaded through proof and argument (logos), by displaying the speaker’s character (êthos) and by arousing the emotions of the audience (pathos). These so-called ‘‘technical’’ means of persuasion 51 This contrast is emphasized by Toulmin (1986), passim. According to an often quoted example from Toulmin (1958) the premise that a Swede can generally be taken not to be a Roman Catholic can be used as warrant for the inference that, if Peter is a Swede, he is almost certainly not a Roman Catholic. If such empirical facts belong to what Toulmin takes to be ‘‘material’’ in contrast to ‘‘formal’’, then none of Aristotle’s general or common topoi and only a few of his specific topoi would qualify as material. 52 Cf. Toulmin (1996, 303) and Tetens (2011, 491). 53 Some attempts at construing specific topoi not as ready-premises, but as tools that are supposed to generate arguments, are made in Rapp (2002, vol. II, 290–298). Ch. Rapp, T. Wagner 123 Author's personal copy
  • 21. can be coordinated to the three vertices of the triangle of speaker, hearer and subject matter. The theory of persuasion as it is laid out in the Rhetoric thus broadens the scope of the analysis. Whereas the theory of the Topics neglected or idealized the vertices of speaker and hearer (by imposing artificial procedural rules on them), the Rhetoric seems to raise them to the same level as the subject matter and the corresponding means of persuasion, i.e. proof or argument. The aspects of persuasion which we may call ‘‘non-argumentative’’—just for the purpose of contrasting them with proofs or arguments in the narrow sense—may interfere with or impede theintended persuasion process. Ifthe audience does not think that the speaker is trustworthy, the best argument will fail to achieve the desired effect. And if the hearers happen to be in an emotional state that prevents their minds from forming clear thoughts, they will presumably not even be able to follow the speaker’s train of thought. Conversely, the rhetorician may use the strong personal impact he makes or the emotional disposition he arouses for emphasizing or highlighting those aspects of the subject matter that are capable of influencing the audience’s judgment. Aristotle does not give a very detailed account of the non-argumentative means of persuasion. And the little he actually says about them is stated rather negatively, in that it tells us what should be avoided, rather than positively instructing us on how to support the argumentative strategy; persuasion may be accomplished by showing character virtues the lack of which would prevent the audience from believing that the speaker is trustworthy. If the speaker does not display practical intelligence, the audience will not be inclined to believe that he has anything true to say about the case at hand. But it may also be the case that a person is competent and intelligent but seems to lack moral integrity. If the hearers have doubts about the virtuous character of the speaker, they may concede that he is clever but refrain from accepting what he says because he may pursue aims which are not acceptable to them. And if the speaker is perceived as competent and virtuous, the possibility still remains that he has, for whatever reason, an aversion to the audience. If the speaker appears to lack goodwill for the audience and seems to display subtle hostility or arrogance, the readiness to adopt his views will completely disappear. If the rhetorician succeeds in presenting himself as a trustworthy person, the audience forms a second-order judgment that what is put forward by a credible person should be accepted. This second-order judgment has nothing to do with the subject matter of the speech. And even though Aristotle does not give detailed instructions on exactly how character should be displayed, he clearly seems to prefer using rather indirect forms to express personal virtues. A speaker who opens his speech by explicitly praising his intelligence, his virtuous character or his benevolence before the audience, will come across as a suspect individual who aspires to distract from some other hidden motif. Some short remarks in the Poetics show how practical instructions on how to display a person’s character might look. In a tragedy the character of a person can be seen when it comes to a choice (prohairesis) between different possible actions— ‘‘hence there is no room for character in a speech in which the speaker does not show what he chooses or avoids’’.54 Conversely, character can be displayed in a 54 Cf. Aristotle, Poetics 6, 1450b8 et seq. On Some Aristotelian Sources 123 Author's personal copy
  • 22. speech in which the speaker shows how he would choose. If the speaker uses this means of persuasion there are two possibilities: either an element of the speech can be stated only to serve the goal of producing a certain appearance without its being related to the subject matter of the speech, or a statement about the subject matter of the speech serves at the same time as a means to show the speaker’s character. But even if the latter is the case it should not be confused with an argument that is merely about the case at hand. The moment the hearer accepts what the speaker says not only because of the content but also because of the speaker’s credibility, the argument is no longer independent of the person who presented it. The means of persuasion that is related more directly to the hearer, the arousal of emotions (pathos), allows for a greater range of variation. Aristotle introduces this subject as the analysis of emotions.55 The rhetorician has to know the complete definition of an emotion in order to be able to arouse it. Aristotle therefore offers accounts of different emotions in some detail. If the rhetorician knows, e.g., that anger is ‘‘a desire accompanied by pain, for a conspicuous revenge for a conspicuous slight at the hands of men who have no right to slight oneself or one’s friends’’,56 he will be able to arouse anger by presenting a case that instantiates this definition. Definitional knowledge allows one to model a given case correctly. For example, anger cannot be directed against universal entities like man in general, but must be directed against individuals, because only individuals can commit slights. That anger is a kind of desire implies that it is followed by a certain pleasure which arises from the expectation of revenge. It is pleasant to think that one will attain what one aims at. Therefore, the rhetorician should rather highlight the possibility of taking revenge than neglecting it. The rhetorician who wants to arouse a certain emotion can do so by emphasizing aspects of the subject matter of his speech in such a way that the persons involved and the courses of action seem to be in accordance with the definition of the emotion. Thus, the rhetorician can steer the hearers’ emotional state by making them believe that, for example, a slight has been committed by someone who was not entitled to do so; and the emotional state resulting from such a belief is likely to have an impact on the judgment the hearers finally make. As we have seen, both the display of the speaker’s character (êthos) and the arousal of the hearer’s emotions (pathos) work on the basis of inferences or judgments made by the hearer, even though they cannot be reduced to these inferential aspects. How can the dividing line between proper argumentation and non-argumentative means of persuasion be drawn? Obviously, it is not sufficient to check whether or not inferences and judgments come into play. What matters is the relationship between the premises and the target conclusion. If the speaker wants to make the addressee accept a certain claim (for example the claim that a city wall should be built), an argument in the proper sense should be directly relevant to this claim. The second-order judgment that the speaker is a trustworthy person has no direct bearing on such a claim. The emotional state of fear or anger that influences the hearer’s judgment formation does not necessarily depend on pertinent premises. 55 Cf. Aristotle, Rhetoric II.1, 1378a20 et sqq. 56 Cf. Aristotle, Rhetoric II.2, 1378a31 et sqq. Ch. Rapp, T. Wagner 123 Author's personal copy
  • 23. Whereas within the realm of rational argumentation a premise that turns out to be false can no longer be used in building a sound argument, emotional states may maintain their efficacy independently of the truth value of the premises they are based on. The fact that inferences and judgments are involved when the speaker presents himself as trustworthy or arouses the emotions of the audience should not blind us to the differences between non-argumentative means of persuasion and pertinent argumentation. It is no coincidence that Aristotle distinguishes êthos and pathos from logos and seems not to see these means as instances of a wider notion of argumentation. His definition of a deductive argument (sullogismos) stresses the ‘‘causal’’ role of the premises for the conclusion. The conclusion comes about ‘‘through’’ the premises or ‘‘because of’’ them. If the addressee accepts a claim because of the presumed character of the speaker or under the influence of an emotional state, these factors may not be pertinent in the same sense as the premises of a proper argument. Aristotle takes the non-argumentative factors into account, gives a neutral explanation and sketches methods for exploiting their potential; he does not incorporate them into his notion of an argument. The concept of pertinence or relevance that is central here, nevertheless, still awaits detailed reconstruction.57 7 Fallacies and Other Violations of Discourse Rules The study of fallacies is one of the central topics of MAT. It is generally accepted that Aristotle is among the founding fathers of this discipline. Especially the treatise on Sophistical Refutations is regarded as an important contribution to the systematic analysis of arguments that are incorrect or deceptive. As often happens in the history of philosophy, Aristotle’s doctrine has not only served as a point of reference for affirmative reconstruction but also as a model that has been extended, modified, criticized and contrasted with different approaches. In recent decades, the ‘‘Standard Treatment’’—as Hamblin (1970) called the Aristotelian heritage in the study of fallacies—has been criticized as incomplete, insufficient, or unclear because on the one hand it seems to be restricted to the dialectical context it stems from and on the other hand it uses unclear, ‘‘metaphysical’’ notions and distinctions such as essential versus accidental properties.58 Indeed, Aristotle’s system of fallacies is quite inflexible. For him, a fallacy is an inference that seems to be a sullogismos, without actually being conclusive. Each type of fallacy is connected with a specific reason why people are deluded into thinking that the conclusion follows from the premises. Appealing to these various sources of delusion, Aristotle even attempts to prove that the list of fallacies he gives is systematically complete.59 Within Aristotle’s conceptual frame it seems that all inferences that are non-conclusive (apart from 57 Although, of course, MAT has already incorporated the concept of relevance into its agenda; cf. e.g. van Eemeren and Grootendorst (2004, chapter 4). 58 This second criticism resembles a motif that we already encountered in Perelman: cf. footnote 43. 59 Cf. the contribution by Pieter Sjoerd Hasper to this issue. On Some Aristotelian Sources 123 Author's personal copy
  • 24. inductions, of course) are fallacious. At least there is no single concept by which to classify such inferences.60 The Amsterdam School has taken an entirely different approach. The concept of pragma-dialectical fallacies which was introduced in the 1990s exemplifies a position which seems to have little in common with Aristotle’s views about fallacies. According to this approach fallacies are violations of discussion rules intended to ensure that differences of opinion can be resolved. The pragma- dialectical rules are recapitulated in ten principles—the ‘Ten Commandments’ of critical discussion. Among these principles there are rules about logical validity61 or the avoidance of unclear formulations62 which are not too far from Aristotle’s account. Other rules concern the general setting of the discourse, e.g. the freedom to advance or cast doubt on a standpoint or to define which moves are allowed and which are not.63 If, for example, a premise represents an accepted starting point, the other party is not allowed to deny it; otherwise this will be counted as a fallacy. The pragma-dialectical concept of fallacies is not restricted to logical incorrect- ness or misleading use of linguistic expressions. It also covers moves which within the framework of Aristotelian dialectics are sometimes necessary and seem to be part of the game. If, for example, a premise within a dialectical disputation might be used to deduce the target conclusion of the opponent, the defendant is advised by Aristotle not to grant it.64 Thus, we seem to be confronted with a straightforward opposition between Aristotle’s views and MAT approaches. On closer examination, however, the supposed opposition turns out to be less pronounced. Aristotle does not speak about the rules of discourse in terms of fallacies or fallacious moves. Nevertheless, the Topics rests on the ideal of an ‘‘impeccable’’ dialectical argument, which comes close to some modern normative rules of discourse. In Topics VIII.11, Aristotle enumerates six criteria for retrospective evaluation of an argument. Implicitly, the possible points of criticism form a set of rules which define ideal dialectical arguments. In an ideal dialectical dispute the desired conclusion which is opposed to the answerer’s original thesis is established only through premises which are necessary, relevant and more acceptable than the conclusion.65 This ideal result is only accessible for interlocutors who aim at jointly achieving deeper knowledge about the subject-matter. The preconditions that have to be fulfilled to realize this co-operative form of dialectical argumentation are demanding: the dialecticians have to know which 60 Some commentators think that in Rhetoric I.2 Aristotle regards sign-enthymemes as acceptable arguments, even if they are non-conclusive. However, he does not express his appreciation for sign- enthymemes in so many words. In Rhetoric II.24 he straightforwardly classifies sign-enthymemes as fallacies. The example given in this latter chapter clearly involves a dilution; possibly, Aristotle thinks that people could accept the sign-examples in Rhetoric I.2—without being deluded. For the ancient and, in particular, Aristotelian treatment of fallacies see also Pieter Sjoerd Hasper and Christof Rapp (eds.), Ancient Fallacies. In Logical Analysis and History of Philosophy 15, forthcoming. 61 Cf. van Eemeren et al. (1996, 284: Rule (8) with fn. 23). 62 Cf. loc. cit.: Rule (10). 63 Cf. loc. cit.: Rules (1) and (6). 64 Cf. Aristotle, Topics VIII.6, 160a 3–6. 65 Cf. Aristotle, Topics VIII.11, 161b 19–33. Ch. Rapp, T. Wagner 123 Author's personal copy
  • 25. views are generally accepted and what the experts think; they have to be capable of foreseeing the consequences of a statement; they should neither block the partner’s strategy nor go down without a fight; and they should be able to establish valid deductions. If they fail to do the latter, they commit what Aristotle would call a fallacy. If a dialectician fails to comply with one of the other implicit rules, this is noted in subsequent evaluations of his argumentative capacities, but is not called a ‘‘fallacy’’. All in all, the set of possible violations of discursive rules Aristotle’s dialectic is aware of clearly extends beyond his own notion of fallacies; the spirit of some of these rules is not too far from certain pragmatic fallacies in MAT. 8 Conclusions Modern argumentation theorists frequently focus on oppositions such as dialectic versus rhetoric, analytical versus topical, reasonable versus effective, formal versus informal, or normative versus descriptive. Many of these pairs are related to the ancient tradition of public speech and argumentative discourse, in particular to Aristotle’s treatises the Topics and the Rhetoric. The conceptual field that they survey and map with the help of these distinctions is broad and not always clearly delimited. Even though Aristotle did not treat the multifaceted aspects of argumentation under one common heading, one may see the different theoretical elements that center around his notion of a sound argument as parts of a coherent project. This project might anachronistically be called Aristotle’s argumentation theory. Aristotle himself did not see argumentation as a single field of research. He studied logical and semantical relations that could be used to find or establish premises, he analysed the relations between the terms of standardized deductive arguments, he systematized and evaluated accepted opinions, and he accounted for the factors of persuasion processes. In doing so, he raised many of the questions that are still discussed in contemporary argumentation theory. His answers to these questions are sometimes formulated in a language that sounds unfamiliar and seems to be far away from the modern world. But under the surface of texts that may be difficult or sketchy, we find a coherent and self-contained approach that combines a realistic view of what people actually do when the dispute, argue, or try to persuade others with the normative emphasis of how people should construct and present sound arguments. This approach has set the agenda ever since and has provoked criticism ever since. In one way or another the elements of Aristotle’s theory still remain important sources for modern argumentation theory. References Bird, Otto. 1961. The re-discovery of the Topics. Professor Toulmins inference warrants. Mind 70: 534–539. Burnyeat, Myles F. 1994. Aristotle on the logic of persuasion. In Aristotle’s Rhetoric: Philosophical essays, ed. David J. Furley and Alexander Nehamas, 3–55. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Brunschwig, Jacques. 1967. Aristote, Topiques, tome I, livres I-IV. Paris: Les Belles Lettres. On Some Aristotelian Sources 123 Author's personal copy
  • 26. De Pater, Wim A. 1965. Les Topiques d’Aristote e la dialectique platonicienne. Fribourg: Éditions de St. Paul. Eggs, Ekkehard. 1992. Argumentation. In Historisches Wörterbuch der Rhetorik, vol. I, ed. Gert Ueding, 914–991. Tübingen: Niemeyer. Hamblin, Charles. 1970. Fallacies. London: Methuen. Kienpointner, Manfred. 1997. On the art of finding arguments: What ancient and modern masters of invention have to tell us about the ‘ars inveniendi’. Argumentation 11(2): 225–236. Kienpointner, Manfred. 2005. Aristotelische Rhetoriktradition im 20. Jahrhundert. In Aristotelische Rhetoriktradition, ed. Joachim Knape and Thomas Schirren, 363–387. Stuttgart: Steiner. Kienpointner, Manfred. 2011. Rhetorik. In Aristoteles-Handbuch, ed. Christof Rapp and Klaus Corcilius, 510–515. Stuttgart: Metzler. Perelman, Chaı̈m, and Lucie Olbrechts-Tyteca. 1969. The new rhetoric: A treatise on argumentation. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press. (Traité de l’argumentation: La nouvelle rhétorique. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France. 1959.). Perelman, Chaı̈m. 1994. Logik und Argumentation, 2nd ed. Weinheim: Beltz. (Logique et argumentation. Brussels: Presses univ. de Bruxelles. 1971.). Rapp, Christof. 2000. Topos und Syllogismus in Aristoteles’ Topik. In Topik und Rhetorik: Ein interdisziplinäres Symposium, ed. Thomas Schirren and Gert Ueding, 15–35. Tübingen: Niemeyer. Rapp, Christof. 2002. Aristoteles, Rhetorik (translated and explained by Christof Rapp). Two volumes. Berlin: Akademie-Verlag. Rapp, Christof. 2012. Aristotle on the moral psychology of persuasion. In The Oxford handbook of Aristotle, ed. Christopher Shields, 589–611. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Rigotti, Eddo. 2007. Can classical topics be revived within the contemporary theory of argumentation. In Proceedings of the sixth conference of the International Society of the Study of Argumentation, ed. Frans H. van Eemeren, J. Rob Grootendorst, Anthony Blair, and Charles A. Willard, 1155–1163. Amsterdam: Sic Sat. Tetens, Holm. 2004. Philosophisches Argumentieren. München: Beck. Tetens, Holm. 2011. Beweiskraft und Rhetorik – das Beispiel der Metaphern und Analogien. In Lebenswelt und Wissenschaft, ed. Carl F. Gethmann, 489–504. Hamburg: Meiner. Toulmin, Stephen E. 1958. The uses of argument. Updated edition. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Toulmin, Stephen E. 1986. Die Verleumdung der Rhetorik. Neue Hefte für Philosophie 26: 55–68. Toulmin, Stephen E. 1996. Rationality and reasonableness: From propositions to utterances. Revue Internationale de Philosophie 2: 297–305. van Eemeren, Frans H., Rob Grootendorst, and Francisca Snoeck Henkemans. 1996. Fundamentals of argumentation theory: A handbook of historical backgrounds and contemporary developments. New York: Routledge. van Eemeren, Frans H., and Peter Houtlosser. 1999. Delivering the goods in critical discussion. In Proceedings of the fourth international conference of the International Society of the Study of Argumentation, ed. Frans H. van Eemeren, J. Rob Grootendorst, Anthony Blair, and Charles A. Willard, 163–167. Amsterdam: Sic Sat. van Eemeren, Frans H., and Peter Houtlosser (eds.). 2002. Dialectic and rhetoric: The warp and woof of argumentation analysis. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic. van Eemeren, Frans H., and Rob Grootendorst. 2004. A systematic theory of argumentation: The pragma- dialectical approach. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Viehweg, Theodor. 1963. Topik und Jurisprudenz, 2nd ed. München: C.H. Beck. (First edition 1953). Wagner, Tim and Christof Rapp. 2004. Aristoteles, Topik (translated and annotated by Tim Wagner and Christof Rapp). Stuttgart: Reclam. Walton, Douglas N., and Erik C.W. Krabbe. 1995. Commitment in dialogue: Basic concepts of interpersonal reasoning. Albany: SUNY Press. Walton, Douglas N., Christopher Reed, and Fabrizio Macagno. 2008. Argumentation schemes. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Warnick, Barbara. 2000. Two systems of invention: The topics in the Rhetoric and The New Rhetoric. In Rereading Aristotle’s Rhetoric, ed. Alan G. Gross and Arthur E. Walzer, 107–129. Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press. Woods, John, and Douglas N. Walton. 1989. Fallacies: Selected papers 1972–1982. Berlin: De Gruyter. Ch. Rapp, T. Wagner 123 Author's personal copy