SlideShare a Scribd company logo
1 of 12
Download to read offline
A PRAGMATIC ANALYSIS OF PAUL TAYLOR'S BIOCENTRISM
Terzungwe Inja
Department of Philosophy
Benue State University
Abstract
Contemporary societies in Africa (like the rest of the world) are
increasingly facing drastic environmental problems which, in most
cases, are a direct consequence of man's anthropocentric attitudes
toward nature. Since the dawn of the twentieth Century,
multidisciplinary efforts to articulate a universal praxis for the
environment have become frantic. In Philosophy, arguments in
support of a paradigm shift led to the emergence of non-
anthropocentric thoughts like Paul Taylor's respect to nature. He
rejects anthropocentrism and advocates for equality and moral
significance among different life forms irrespective of different
interests. Thus his biocentrism is egalitarian, and essentially, an
extension of inherent worth from humans to other life forms. He
thinks this paradigm shift in the way man views and treats nature
can solve the crises. The main objective of this paper was to
ascertain the applicability of Taylor's theory. In this direction, a
pragmatic approach was adopted. This methodology was
preferred for its tendency of evaluating everything based on
practicability. It was found that there were links between Taylor's
thought and Kant's notion of respect for persons; and that
biocentric egalitarianism marked a major shift from traditional
ethics. Furthermore, the theory was found tenable in areas like
strategic planning for attitudinal change, policy design, law,
administration, environmental remediation, reparations and
environmental justice; which are practical ways of quelling
environmental crises. However, there were some conceptual,
exegetical, and existential weaknesses within Biocentric
Egalitarianism. The study concluded that Biocentric Egalitarianism
is, in several ways, tenable in tackling contemporary environmental
problems.
Keywords: Biocentrism, Egalitarianism, Environmental Ethics,
Paul Taylor, Pragmatism, Pollution, Non-anthropocentrism
INTRODUCTION
 Much of human civilization and its amazing improvements in living conditions
would not have been possible without reliance on the Earth's resources. Obviously,
everything has come at a great environmental cost. All along, mankind has operated on
the anthropocentric notion that nature's resources are only useful to the extent that they
satisfy his desires; and the consequences have been devastating: an alarming rate of
environmental pollution, degradation, species extinction, and depletion of non-
renewable resources. Most of these negative effects of man's environmental
58
Sapientia Journal of Philosophy
th
exploitation were evident at the turn of the 20 century; it became obvious that if nothing
was done, humankind would drive the world to a catastrophic end. This realization
marked the emergence of several and various efforts to remedy the damage; involving
experts in areas like sociology, politics, geography, ecology, ethnobotany, and
philosophy.
Particularly, philosophers found that anthropocentric attitudes and praxis toward the
natural environment were largely to blame for the teeming environmental challenges.
Thus they set out to unearth alternative ethical paradigms by which to reshape man's
attitude and behaviour toward the environment (Minster 185). This period marked the
birth of non-anthropocentrism which, generally, extends inherent worth to non-human
life forms (in the case of biocentrism) and to every component of the ecosystem (in case
of ecocentrism). It maintains that justice is not whatever man deems fit, rather it is what
nature ought to have. Through non-anthropocentrism, “philosophers were hoping to
advance a persuasive moral justification for a robust environmental policy and a general
rationalization of proenvironmental [sic] practices” (Minster 185).
In line with this movement Paul Taylor proposes his theory known as biocentric
egalitarianism, by which he argues that anthropocentric attitudes and ways of exploiting
the natural environment are responsible for the problems we have. He maintains that
humans must adopt the attitude of respect for nature by which all living things would be
valued, not in an instrumental way anymore, but to accord them respect as ends-in-
themselves.
This is where the problem for this paper finds its root; an examination of Taylor's critics
revealed that they have been mostly focused on its theoretical ramifications. Many
scholars and researchers have questioned the extent to which man can be equated with
nature; the dynamics of power that would emanate if such an egalitarian notion were
possible; the individuality of species which Taylor proposes; and the implications of
harnessing this thought for the development of an environmental praxis. Thus, scholars
have almost completely covered the theoretical implications (Inja 4).
In the light of the above, this researcher has focused on the practical tenability of Taylor's
viewpoint. More so, while Taylor himself has shied away from propounding an empirical
modus operandi, he has admitted to proposing “a philosophical worldview” (“The Ethics
of Respect for Nature” 205). And since every worldview is supposed to have a practical
impact, the researcher has decided to undertake a pragmatic analysis with emphasis on
the practicality of the theory. Thus the extent to which such an egalitarian ethos is useful
in curbing environmental problems is the thrust of this paper.
Conceptual Clarifications
 The following terms have been clarified to enhance the understanding of this
discourse:-Biocentrism
Environmental thoughts are generally categorised into two intellectual camps: those that
are anthropocentric (or 'human-centred') and those that are non-anthropocentric ('life-
centred' and/or 'eco-centred'). This typology has been described in other terminology as
'shallow' ecology and 'deep' ecology respectively. Biocentrism falls under non-
anthropocentrism; RobinAttfield defines it as “a life-centred outlook that rejects the view
that humanity alone matters in ethics and accepts the moral standing of (at least) all living
59
Sapientia Journal of Philosophy
creatures” (97). In the same vein, Lorraine Elliott defines biocentrism as a theory which
holds that nature has an intrinsic moral worth which does not depend on its usefulness to
human beings; and that this intrinsic worth should define human obligations to the
environment (“Biocentrism” n.p).
 Etymologically, the term biocentrism is traceable to two Greek words, βίος
(pronounced 'bio' meaning 'life') and κέντρον, (pronounced 'kentron' meaning 'centre').
Put together, both terms form the English 'biocentrism' which connotes a 'life-centred'
environmentalism (Mouchang and Lei 423). Biocentrism, in the light of the above
amounts to moral extensionism; that is, an extension of moral worth from humans to
non-human animals and plants.
Pragmatism
There are many ideas about the meaning of pragmatism; in a general sense, the term
refers to any “straightforward or practical way of thinking about things or dealing with
problems, [to be] concerned with results rather than with theories and principles”
(Encarta Dictionary n.p). Philosophically, the term pragmatism represents a
philosophical tradition which (is quite traceable to antiquity but) manifested most
strongly in the 1870s America through the pioneering work of Charles Sanders Pierce
(1839-1914) and his followers William James (1842-1910) and John Dewey (1859-
1952) (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy n.p).
According to James, pragmatism rejects the notion that the function of human thinking is
to describe, represent, or mirror reality (n.p). Rather, pragmatists view thought as an
instrument or tool for prediction, problem solving and action. They contend that most
philosophical topics (such as the nature of knowledge, language, concepts, meaning,
belief, and science) should be considered more in terms of their practical uses and
successes. The philosophy of pragmatism “emphasizes the practical application of
ideas by acting on them to actually test them in human experiences” (Gutek 76-100).
Also the Encarta Dictionary reports that is a philosophical method of evaluating theories
which holds, “a theory or concept should be evaluated in terms of how it works and its
consequences as the standard for action and thought” (n.p). Within this paper, the
pragmatic method of is understood and applied in this sense; thus it is the practical
applicability ofTaylor's biocentrism that has been subjected to the court of reason.
Paul Taylor's Biocentric Egalitarianism
th
 Paul Warren Taylor was born in Philadelphia on 19 November 1923. He is
specialized in normative and applied ethics, and is best known for his work in
environmental ethics. He is emeritus professor of philosophy at Brooklyn College, City
University of New York; where he studied normative and applied ethics (“Paul Taylor”
web). He has the authored several articles, essays and books. Among his most popular
books are, Normative Discourse (1961), Principles of Ethics (1975), and Respect for
Nature: A Theory of Environmental Ethics (1986). He has also edited two books of
readings:- The Moral Judgement: Readings in Contemporary Meta-Ethics (1963); and
rd
Problems of Moral Philosophy, 3 Ed. (1971). Oakley acknowledges that Taylor is a
renowned Kantian scholar (257). Taylor's biocentric egalitarianism is taught in many
university courses on environmental ethics today.
An examination of his theory shows various links to other philosophers who may have
influenced his biocentric thought; key among which is Immanuel Kant (via the principle
60
Sapientia Journal of Philosophy
of respect for persons). Also easily traced are the thoughts of Arne Naess (deep and
shallow ecology), Kenneth Goodpaster (moral considerability), Albert Schweitzer
(reverence for life), Peter Singer (sentience and equality), and Mahatma Ghandi
(ahimsa or non-violence).
Biocentric Egalitarianism
Taylor's theory of Biocentric Egalitarianism, widely known as the ethics of Respect for
Nature, is a complicated but compelling thought on the environment which was first
announced in his article titled “The Ethics of Respect for Nature” that was published in
the year 1981 (197-218). Another of his articles “Are Humans Superior to Animals and
Plants?” published in summer of 1984 also contains elements of the biocentric outlook
on life. This initial effort found expression in several of his works and culminated in his
1986 book with the title, Respect for Nature:ATheory of Environmental Ethics.
Taylor's biocentrism synthesizes Classical and Kantian virtue ethics, with elements of
Albert Schweitzer's ethics of reverence for life, Peter Singer's egalitarianism, and
Kenneth Goodpaster's account of moral considerability. He begins with the view that all
living things have inherent value, and so are deserving of moral respect, equally. For
Taylor, all that is required to have inherent value is to be alive – essentially, striving
towards staying alive. He grounds his view on the idea of Respect for Nature, which is an
extension of the Kantian principle of Respect for Persons.
Taylor clarifies his position by distinguishing it from an ecocentric view – namely, it is not
fundamentally holistic. To him the balance of nature does not lead us to any moral
principles; rather, the good or well-being of all individual living things is of primary
concern (so it is not anthropocentric either). There are many duties which require us to
protect ecological systems, but these are only indirect duties to the individual living
things that inhabit the ecological system.
He argues further that one who adopts the ultimate moral attitude of respect for nature
will become an environmentally virtuous person. He identifies environmental ethical
conduct with conduct motivated by respect for nature. Such environmentally virtuous
conduct seeks to promote the flourishing of all living organisms. In his Respect for
Nature: A Theory of Environmental Ethics, he states, “ethical action and goodness of
character naturally flow from the attitude [of respect for nature], and the attitude is made
manifest in how one acts and in what sort of person one is” (80). He maintains that a
biocentric ethic can be established (justified) if people adopt a new kind of moral attitude;
the attitude that all living things, and not only humans, have inherent worth; that is, the
attitude of respect for nature. But he acknowledges that a lot of work needs to be done to
establish that we ought to take on the new attitude. Two things need to be made clear,
first.These are:-
(a) All living things have a good of their own - that is, they can be benefited or harmed.
This is reflected in the idea that all living things have the potential to grow and develop
according to their biological natures. So, things can either go well or not with respect to
this potential. This idea is not grounded, according to Taylor, in the ideas of having
interests, or having an interest in something; and it is not conditional upon being
sentient, or having consciousness (199). Taylor thinks it is an open question whether a
machine might have a good of its own in the relevant sense.
61
Sapientia Journal of Philosophy
(b) The attitude of respect for nature requires that we accept that all living things
possess inherent worth. This would be reflected in us - were we to take on the attitude of
respect for nature - adopting certain dispositions of behaviour, namely, in general, to act
so as to show equal respect for all living things good of their own (199).
According to him this does not justify the claim that all living things do have inherent
worth, though. So, more needs to be done to show this. His strategy is to argue that living
things possess inherent worth, and that this can be justified by showing that we are
capable of adopting the attitude of respect for nature. Presumably, he thinks that a
“biocentric outlook on nature”, that is respecting nature, directly implies the regard of
living things as having some inherent worth. This is essentially an ecological outlook,
with the key idea being the interdependence of living things.
 Taylor concedes that, “we cannot see the point of taking the attitude of respect”
until we understand and accept the biocentric outlook. However, he insists, “… once we
do grasp it and shape our world outlook in accordance with it, we immediately
understand how and why a person should adopt that attitude [of respect] as the only
appropriate one to have toward nature” (Respect for Nature… 99). The biocentric
outlook, asTaylor conceives it, consists of four core beliefs:
(a) The belief that humans are members of the Earth's Community of Life in the same
sense and on the same terms in which other living things are members of that
Community.
(b) The belief that the human species, along with all other species, are integral elements
in a system of interdependence such that the survival of each living thing, as well as its
chances of faring well or poorly, is determined not only by the physical conditions of its
environment but also by its relations to other living things.
(c) The belief that all organisms are teleological centers [sic] of life in the sense that
each is a unique individual pursuing its own good in its own way.
(d)The belief that humans are not inherently superior to other living things (100).
Taylor thinks that when we accept the first three beliefs of the biocentric outlook
the denial of human superiority will make meaning to us. In turn, the acknowledgment of
the groundlessness of the claim of human superiority will enable us to justify the first
three elements of the biocentric outlook.
He argues that if we accept all four beliefs, then we have a coherent outlook on the
natural word and the place of humans in it; it is the acceptance of the fact that humans
and nonhuman life forms should relate in a certain way; such a world view is then to be
seen as the only suitable, fitting, or appropriate moral attitude to take toward the natural
world and its living inhabitants (“The Ethics of Respect for Nature” 206).Essentially, this
outlook sees living things “… as the appropriate objects of the attitude of respect and are
accordingly regarded as entities possessing inherent worth.” Taylor suggests that
adoption of the biocentric outlook leads us to adoption of the attitude of respect for
nature, with the implication that we now have a non-anthropocentric environmental ethic
(“The Ethics of Respect for Nature” 100).
62
Sapientia Journal of Philosophy
According toAdplanalp, Taylor moves from here to deny human superiority. He does this
by presenting counter arguments against four of the most common advanced
arguments for human superiority:- (i) Classical Greek Humanism (which purports that
rationality makes humans superior to other life forms); (ii) The Great Chain of Being (an
axiological paradigm which conceives of beings in a hierarchical rank that places man
above other life forms); (iii) Cartesian Dualism (which claims that non-human life forms
are mere matter without soul (mind) and as such have less worth than humans); (iv)
Louis Lombardi's argument for human superiority which goes that even though all living
things have inherent worth, animals have less inherent worth than humans –because
human's have more capacities (262).
On the question of why moral agents should accept the four beliefs that make up the
biocentric outlook, Taylor is certain that the biocentric outlook is supported by biology
and ecology, and it also meets the criteria upon which all philosophical world views have
been judged and accepted throughout the history of philosophy; these are: (a)
Comprehensiveness and completeness; (b) Systematic order, coherence, and internal
consistency; (c) Freedom from obscurity, conceptual confusion, and semantic vacuity;
(d) Consistency with all known empirical truths. He goes on to express confidence in the
validity of his arguments, “these criteria have served as tests for the overall adequacy
and satisfactoriness of a world view. When we apply them to the biocentric outlook, I
submit, we find them to be fully met” (Respect for Nature… 206).
Criticism of Taylor's Biocentric Egalitarianism
Taylor's egalitarian biocentrism has attracted a lot of criticism from diverse scholars and
philosophers. Peter Singer, in his Animal Liberation, rejects Taylor's argument that all
living things have moral significance. Instead he argues that only sentient beings should
be accorded any consideration (8 – 9). But Taylor argues that it is arbitrary to restrict the
class of morally considerable beings to sentient beings. Since all living organisms can
be harmed or benefited and what benefits them promotes their good, Taylor insists that
there is no non-arbitrary reason that prevents us from extending moral consideration to
all living organisms.
Some biocentrists take issue with Taylor's egalitarianism; that is his view that all living
things are equal and humans are on par with non-human life forms. For instance both
Kenneth Goodpaster (“On Being Morally Considerable” 308 – 325) and Gary Varner (In
Nature's Interest) agree that all living organisms deserve moral consideration, but deny
that being morally considerable entails having equal moral significance. These critics
reject Taylor's egalitarianism in favour of a hierarchical account of moral significance.
Particularly, Varner argues that some interests take priority over others and that only
recognition of this inequality will provide viable support for environmental goals. In
essence, Varner's argument is that it is impossible to derive practical principles from a
non-hierarchical system of interests likeTaylor's.
Taylor's individualism has attracted another criticism; he holds that “it is the good (well-
being, welfare) of individual organisms […] that determines our moral relations with the
Earth's wild communities of life” (“The Ethics of Respect for Nature” 198). Critics
contend that Taylor's focus on individual welfare fails to address the actual concerns of
environmentalists. Most environmentalists are concerned not with the welfare of
individual mosquitoes, dandelions, and microbes, but rather with species preservation,
ecological integrity, and pollution. These critics insist that only a holistic ethic can better
63
Sapientia Journal of Philosophy
address these environmental concerns (Williams n.p).
Taylor's rejection of human superiority has also been challenged. Critics think that the
idea of extending equal moral consideration to every living organism, is not only too
demanding, but outright absurd and impracticable (Attfield is among those who hold this
view). Taylor tries to mitigate this objection by formulating a complex set of principles
(self-defence, proportionality, minimum harm, distributive justice, and restitutive justice)
for fairly resolving the conflicts that inevitably arise between humans and other equally
considerable organisms. Even with these principles in place, Taylor's biocentric ethic
remains extremely demanding, since the principle of proportionality dictates that the
basic interests of plants trump the non-basic interests of humans (Williams n.p). Louis
Lombardi also contested Taylor's rejection of human superiority by arguing that even
though all living things have inherent worth, animals have less inherent worth than
humans (because human's have more capacities) and that in the event of a clash of
interests, human interests would trump that of other life forms (qtd inAdplanalp 264).
Taylor retorted by arguing that while humans have capacities that non-humans have, the
reverse is the case too; thus there is ground to argue (from the perspective of non-
humans) that in their own ways there are also superior. Hence the key issue whether the
capacities in question are needed to function (264). For instance, it is not proper to
expect animals to be rational since rationality is not needed to function in their world; just
like it is wrong to expect humans to possess the superior climbing ability of monkeys.
Thus Taylor believes that no particular organism should be seen as inferior on the
grounds of capacities.
Taylor's demarcation of living things and his use of terms is another source of concern to
critics. Megan Wade takes issue with the basic premise of Taylor's analysis. Particularly,
she disagrees with the way Taylor has, “drawn stark lines between humans and nature,
between moral and non-moral agents, and in so doing fails [sic] to adequately consider
those issues that would complicate this picture: non-human species with highly
developed social lives and potential species-specific codes of conduct, for instance”
(Wade n.p).
In other words, Wade finds it difficult to accept the demarcation of living things while at
the same time proposing equality. It appears the demarcation itself indicates a serious
divergence of interests which is irreconcilable ab initio. She also has a problem with
Taylor's use of the term 'nature'. In her opinion it is “slippery; really, he appears to mean
'wild', which is actually quite different in meaning from 'natural'. Much of his argument
seems unselfconsciously premised on the value of 'wild' things, without exploration of
the source of that value” (Wade n.p).
It has been argued that generally, all non-anthropocentric theories of the man-nature
relationship have failed to ascertain a true non-anthropocentric worldview because at
the end, everything boils down to the benefits of man on planet. Bryan Norton has
particularly argued that non-anthropocentric theories such as biocentrism are
redundant because sophisticated anthropocentrism supports the same policies.
However, biocentrists counter that the recognition of nonhuman interests lends stronger
support for policies of humaneness, compassion and preservation, and also shows why
it is necessary to preserve those species that are not currently the concern of humans
–for instance those that are not yet discovered (Norton qtd inAttfield 99).
64
Sapientia Journal of Philosophy
Closely related to this is another general objection to biocentrism (and other non-
anthropocentric theories) which was advanced by J. Baird Callicot who avers that all
judgements of value, however non-anthropocentric in content, are still anthropogenic
(“Rolston on Intrinsic Value: A Deconstruction” 129 – 143). With a similar view, Attfield
explains that “they are dependent on human valuation, and there can be no value in the
absence of valuers” (“Biocentrism” 100). However Attfield contends that even if such an
argument is granted, it would affect biocentrism only at the level of human judgements
and not at the normative level; since what is valuable does not mean “valued” but applies
to what there is reason to value –whether or not anyone values it.
He maintains that it is implausible to think that nothing that exists had value until humans
first appeared and began making judgements. Normative biocentrism defends an
intrinsic value which is beyond mere human judgements of morals and values. He
concludes that “biocentrists can consistently and reasonably be resolute metaethical
realists, even though their normative stance (biocentrism) does not hang upon affiliation
to realism (100).” Taylor's biocentrism, by virtue of its nonanthropocentrism, is also
affected by these general objections. However, as already pointed out by Attfield,
biocentrism at its normative level remains a strong argument. 
In the final analysis, whether these objections to Taylor's biocentric egalitarianism prove
insuperable remains to be seen. However, regardless of whether his ethic prevails in the
end or ultimately forces us to look elsewhere for an adequate environmental ethic,
Taylor's biocentric outlook helps those who tolerate it to have a greater appreciation and
respect for nature (Williams n.p).
The Pragmatics of Paul Taylor's Biocentric Egalitarianism
Taylor's biocentrism, as demonstrated above, has some objections levelled against it,
but its supporters believe it is a viable theory of environmental ethics that could be used
to change the world. When it comes to its practical relevance, even Taylor, concedes that
the biocentric outlook “is not wholly analyzable [sic] into empirically confirmable
assertions” and thus should be viewed as “a philosophical world-view” (“The Ethics of
Respect for Nature” 205). Moreover, he never attempts to derive an ought from an is;
rather, he seeks to provide us with a rational, coherent perspective on nature that will
allow us to accurately perceive (not deduce) the inherent worth of all living beings
(Williams n.p).
In any case it is the opinion of this researcher that, neither Taylor's employment of a
purely descriptive approach to explain the biocentric outlook, nor his expressed aim,
which is to provide a “world-view” rather than “wholly empirically confirmable
assertions”; should deter anyone from exploring the possibility of applying this theory in
practical situations. The first justification for this opinion is that every philosophical
worldview can have an impact on man's actions; so the issue should not be whether this
theory is applicable, rather it should be to what extent and in which particular area it can
be applied.
Secondly, Taylor's egalitarian biocentrism, as largely descriptive as it may be, is an in-
depth re-examination of anthropocentrism, the basic paradigm upon which humans
have acted out the relationship between them and non-human life forms. It must be
65
Sapientia Journal of Philosophy
recalled that Taylor has led us on a rediscovery journey that necessarily ends in a
reassessment and readjustment of the way we have been taught by tradition to
conceive, perceive, and treat nature. And such a path, to be meaningful, must also lead
to the drawing up of practical ways to deal with our ever-increasing environmental
problems. Therefore, this researcher submits that biocentrism is applicable in practical
ways.Adetailed demonstration of this possibility is contained in the following sections.
Biocentric Egalitarianism as Relevant in Formulation of Laws/Policies/Strategies
Anthropocentric ways of interacting with nature have led to such the numerous
environmental problems that we have today. Back in the early 1970s, this was what
prompted the need for a rethink of an environmental ethic in the first instance; and
evidence abounds to show that things are getting worse today because mankind has
stubbornly refused to out-rightly condemn the trend of thought behind activities that are
destructive to the environment; the idea that nature is only useful to the extent that it
satisfies man's needs and wants. It is however not very easy for man to discontinue his
exploration of the earth's resources. Man is faced with a moral dilemma; to stop and
watch the whole of civilization crumble or to go on and still drive the whole earth and its
inhabitants to extinction! Thus the middle ground is preservation and conservation
rather than wanton destruction. We have reached the point where, to survive, man must
curtail his wants and conquer his greed.
 This is the exact point where Taylor's egalitarian biocentrism comes in handy.
Now that policy makers and other stakeholders have realized the imperative for saving
the earth, one of the most viable options is to adopt Taylor's world-view, the view that
man should treat nature as an equal; with respect. This ideal will become manifest when
our laws, policies and strategies are structured to safeguard rather than destroy, to
conserve rather than consume, and to preserve rather than plunder. As Taylor himself
has stated:
There is no reason, moreover, why plants and animals, including
whole species populations and life communities, cannot be
accorded legal rights under my theory. To grant them legal
protection could be interpreted as giving them legal entitlement
to be protected, and this, in fact, would be a means by which a
society that subscribed to the ethics of respect for nature could
give public recognition to their inherent worth “The Ethics of
Respect for Nature” 218).
Thus in the areas of law, policy, and strategy formulation, this is how Taylor's biocentrism
can be made to work.
Biocentrism Egalitarianism as a Rational Basis for Environmental Remediation
Environmental remediation refers to the various scientific techniques of repairing or
restoring destroyed or badly polluted environmental media such as soil, groundwater,
sediment, or surface water. One of these methods is Bio-Remediation by which plants
and animals are used to resuscitate, detoxify, and restore ecosystems that have been
damaged through environmental degradation or pollution. Deforestation can also be
effectively checked by this means (“Bioremediation” n.p). As a rational principle, such
remediation is only possible when those who engage in practices that destroy the
environment adopt the attitude of respect for nature. Particularly applicable in this area is
Taylor's third thesis which is the realization that “…all organisms are teleological centers
[sic] of life in the sense that each is a unique individual pursuing its own good in its own
66
Sapientia Journal of Philosophy
way.” This principle provides a solid rational foundation for all activities that reflect a duty
of care rather than crass arrogance towards nature and its resources; it supports the
notion that it is possible for man to relate with nature in a manner of respect rather than
abuse.
Biocentric Egalitarianism as a Ground for Reparation
Reparation refers to “the making of amends for wrong or injury done” “Reparation” n.p).
Within the context of environmental justice, reparation usually takes the form of
pecuniary compensation which is paid to an individual, a group, or members of a host
community where environmental exploration has been carried out with harmful
consequences. Often than not, trans-national companies who explore natural resources
tend to be grossly anthropocentric, thereby destroying the habitats that have been home
to both human and non-human life forms for thousands of years. Again, some
exploration companies are ethnocentric and show disregard to the welfare of the local
community. The end result is usually a state of environmental injustice by which the host
community bears the heavier burden of the exploration (particularly the harmful effects)
while the exploration companies bear the (economic) benefits. But justice demands that
the burdens and benefits be shared equitably, so when this is not the case; a moral
paradigm is needed to conscientise the offending party.
This is where Taylor's biocentric egalitarianism again proves handy. The fourth thesis
which rejects superiority of human beings can be extended to cover two relationships:
that between man and nature; and that between a trans-national company and a host
community on whose grounds resource exploration is taking place. When this is applied
as a principle, corporate policies, strategies, and techniques will be put in place to
prevent wanton and unwarranted destruction of the host community's habitats. Also the
duty to pay adequate reparations when gross harm is caused becomes easier to
comprehend and practice.
CONCLUSION
The above discussion has been preoccupied with an analysis of Taylor's biocentric
egalitarianism using a pragmatic perspective. The philosophical tradition behind the
theory, its key arguments, its impact in the field of environmental ethics, the criticisms
levelled against it, and the various ways by which it could be applied in practice have
been exposed. We must recall that biocentrism stands in stark opposition to
anthropocentrism and that Taylor's theory has only added fuel to efforts that were made
to produce a non-anthropocentric ethic. While it is impossible to satisfactorily answer all
criticisms against this theory, one thing that can be known for certain is, Taylor's
biocentric egalitarianism has provided us with a rational, methodic, systematic, and
viable alternative to ponder over and even act on the various environmental problems
we face today. Therefore, to embrace the attitude of respect to nature is to join the army
of those warring against wanton destruction of the limited resources that Mother Nature
has so generously bestowed on us. Thus for the good of nature, humans, and that of
future generations, we must not fail to act now.
Works Cited
Adplanalp, Edward. “Review of Respect for Nature: A Theory of Environmental
Ethics”. in International Dialogue, A Multidisciplinary Journal of World Affairs. Vol 3,
2013: 262 – 264. PDF.
67
Sapientia Journal of Philosophy
Attfield, Robin. “Biocentrism”. in Encyclopedia of Environmental Ethics and
Philosophy. Vol. 1. ed. Callicott, Baird J. and Robert Frodeman. Detroit: Gale
Centage, 2009: 97 - 100. PDF.
“Biocentric Consequentialism, Pluralism and 'the Minamax Implication': A Reply to
Alan Carter.” Utilitas. Vol. 15 (1), 2003: 76 – 91. PDF.
“Biocentric Consequentialism and Value Pluralism: A Response to Alan Carter.”
Utilitas. Vol. 17 (1). 2005: 85 – 92. Print.
nd
The Ethics of Environmental Concern. 2 edit. Athens: University of Georgia Press,
1991. Print.
“The Good of Trees.” in Journal of Value Inquiry. Vol. 15, 1983: 35 – 54. Print.
“Anthropocentric vs Non-Anthropocentric Environmental Ethics”. Capilano University
Open Course Ware Website. 14 July, 2013. Web.
Minster, Ben A. “The Convergence Hypothesis”. in Encyclopedia of Environmental
Ethics and Philosophy. Vol. 1. ed. Callicott, Baird J. and Robert Frodeman.
Detroit: Gale Centage, 2009: 185 - 186. PDF.
“Bioremediation.” in Wikipedia. 10 Mar, 2013. Web.
rd
Callicott, Baird J. Environmental Ethics: I. Overview. in Encyclopedia of Bioethics 3
Edit. Stephen Post (Ed). Vol. 2, New York: Macmillan Reference USA, 1995:
676 - 686. Print.
_____ Callicott, J. Baird. 1992. ''Rolston on Intrinsic Value: A Deconstruction.''
Environmental Ethics. Vol. 14, 1992:129 - 143. Print.
Carson, Rachel. Silent Spring. Boston: Houghton Mifflin, 1962. Print.
Elliott, Lorraine. “Biocentrism”. in Encyclopaedia Britannica Online. Web.
Goodpaster, Kenneth E. “On Being Morally Considerable”. Journal of Philosophy Vol.
75(6), 1978: 308 - 325. Print.
Gutek, Gerald. Philosophical, Ideological, and Theoretical Perspectives on
Education. New Jersey: Pearson, 2014. Print.
Inja, Terzungwe. “A Critique of Paul Taylor's Biocentric Egalitarianism”. A Masters
Dissertation submitted to the Department of Philosophy, University of Nigeria,
Nsukka. July, 2016.
Leopold, Aldo. A Sand County Almanac. New York: Random House, 1949. Print.
ejoy, Arthur O. The Great Chain of Being: A Study of the History of an Idea.
Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press, 1936. qtd in Taylor,
Respect for Nature: A Theory of Environmental Ethics. p.139. Print.
Moore, George Edward. Principia Ethica. Cambridge: University Press, 1903. Print.
Mouchang, Yu  Yi Lei. “Biocentric Ethical Theories”. in Environment and
Development Journal. Vol. II, 2009: 422 – 430. Print.
Naess, Arne. “The Shallow and the Deep, Long–Range Ecology Movement: A
Summary”. in Inquiry. Vol. 16, 1973: 95 - 100. Print.
Norton, Bryan G. Why Preserve Natural Variety? Princeton, NJ: University Press,
1987. Print.
68
Sapientia Journal of Philosophy
Toward Unity among Environmentalists. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, 1991.
Print.
Oakley, Justin. “Applied Ethics', in Routledge History of Philosophy. Vol X. Canfield,
John V (Ed.). London: Routledge, 2005: 254 – 259. Print.
“Paul Taylor (philosopher)”. in Wikipedia. 22 Jun, 2015. Web.
“Paul Warren Taylor”, in Global Warming Causes: Environmental Ethics. 22 Jun,
2015. Web.
“Pragmatism”, Encarta Dictionary, Microsoft® Encarta® 2009. © 1993-2008
Microsoft Corporation. DVD-ROM.
“Reparation”. in Dictionary.Com. 20 Aug, 2015. Web.
Scherer, Donald. “Anthropocentrism, Atomism, and Environmental Ethics.” in
Environmental Ethics Vol. 4 (2), 1982: 115 – 123. Print.
Singer, Peter. Animal Liberation. London: Jonathan Cape, 1975. Print.
Sterba, James P. “Biocentrist Strikes Back.” in Environmental Ethics. Vol. 20(4),
Winter 1998: 361–376. Print.
Taylor, Paul W. “Are Humans Superior to Animals and Plants?” in Environmental
Ethics. Vol. 6, No. 2, Summer, 1984: 149 – 160. Print.
“The Ethics of Respect for Nature”. in Environmental Ethics. Vol. 3(3), 1981: 197 –
218. Print.
Respect for Nature: A Theory of Environmental Ethics (25th Anniversary Edition).
New Jersey: Princeton University Press, 2011. Print.
Varner, Gary. In Nature's Interest? Oxford: University Press, 1998. Print.
Wade, Megan. “Review of Paul Taylor's Respect for Nature: A Theory of
th
Environmental Ethics (25 Anniversary Edition)”. in Good Reads. Web.
Williams, Brian G. Paul Warren Taylor. Personal Blog. 15 Mar, 2016. Web.
About the Author
Terzungwe Inja is a Lecturer in the Department of Philosophy, Benue State
University Makurdi. He is specialized in Moral Philosophy (with a bias in
Environmental Ethics). Apart from scholarly articles and essays, he writes poetry and
short stories.
69
Sapientia Journal of Philosophy

More Related Content

Similar to A PRAGMATIC ANALYSIS OF PAUL TAYLOR S BIOCENTRISM.pdf

Environmental Science Introduction to Ecology.pptx
Environmental Science Introduction to Ecology.pptxEnvironmental Science Introduction to Ecology.pptx
Environmental Science Introduction to Ecology.pptxRicaDeCastro1
 
Beyond Theology
Beyond TheologyBeyond Theology
Beyond TheologyUmar Wyne
 
Anthropocentricism vs ecocentricism
Anthropocentricism vs ecocentricismAnthropocentricism vs ecocentricism
Anthropocentricism vs ecocentricismParmar Milan
 
The self-criticism of science
The self-criticism of scienceThe self-criticism of science
The self-criticism of scienceThink Lab
 
ENVIRONMENTAL ISSUES AND AWARENESS - Presentation
ENVIRONMENTAL ISSUES AND AWARENESS - PresentationENVIRONMENTAL ISSUES AND AWARENESS - Presentation
ENVIRONMENTAL ISSUES AND AWARENESS - PresentationTaruna Deshwal
 
notice aesthetics ways.pptx senior high school
notice aesthetics ways.pptx senior high schoolnotice aesthetics ways.pptx senior high school
notice aesthetics ways.pptx senior high schoolbryandomingo8
 
Philosophy-Lecture-1.pptx
Philosophy-Lecture-1.pptxPhilosophy-Lecture-1.pptx
Philosophy-Lecture-1.pptxJessaSiares
 
Philosophy Of Realism (Defination And Brief History)
Philosophy Of Realism (Defination And Brief History)Philosophy Of Realism (Defination And Brief History)
Philosophy Of Realism (Defination And Brief History)JOHNY NATAD
 
PS 240 Environmentalism(s) Spring 2015
PS 240 Environmentalism(s) Spring 2015PS 240 Environmentalism(s) Spring 2015
PS 240 Environmentalism(s) Spring 2015Christopher Rice
 
Lesson 4 human person in the environment.pdf
Lesson 4 human person in the environment.pdfLesson 4 human person in the environment.pdf
Lesson 4 human person in the environment.pdfMaryCrisGonzalesVill
 
Human Person in the Environment
Human Person in the EnvironmentHuman Person in the Environment
Human Person in the EnvironmentHome
 
Current epistemological theory
Current epistemological theoryCurrent epistemological theory
Current epistemological theoryFarah Ishaq
 
Geography, value paradigms and environmental justice lynn
Geography, value paradigms and environmental justice   lynnGeography, value paradigms and environmental justice   lynn
Geography, value paradigms and environmental justice lynnFábio Coltro
 
Philosophy
PhilosophyPhilosophy
Philosophynairtam
 
Professional Ethics Module 3 Notes
Professional Ethics Module 3 NotesProfessional Ethics Module 3 Notes
Professional Ethics Module 3 NotesBella Meraki
 
still contains sentences that are hard to understand, such as Evo.docx
still contains sentences that are hard to understand, such as Evo.docxstill contains sentences that are hard to understand, such as Evo.docx
still contains sentences that are hard to understand, such as Evo.docxrjoseph5
 
Anthropological Perspectives On Physical Appearance And Body Image
Anthropological Perspectives On Physical Appearance And Body ImageAnthropological Perspectives On Physical Appearance And Body Image
Anthropological Perspectives On Physical Appearance And Body ImageErin Taylor
 

Similar to A PRAGMATIC ANALYSIS OF PAUL TAYLOR S BIOCENTRISM.pdf (20)

ppt-PFE301_1.pptx
ppt-PFE301_1.pptxppt-PFE301_1.pptx
ppt-PFE301_1.pptx
 
Environmental Science Introduction to Ecology.pptx
Environmental Science Introduction to Ecology.pptxEnvironmental Science Introduction to Ecology.pptx
Environmental Science Introduction to Ecology.pptx
 
Beyond Theology
Beyond TheologyBeyond Theology
Beyond Theology
 
Anthropocentricism vs ecocentricism
Anthropocentricism vs ecocentricismAnthropocentricism vs ecocentricism
Anthropocentricism vs ecocentricism
 
The self-criticism of science
The self-criticism of scienceThe self-criticism of science
The self-criticism of science
 
Philosophy of science
Philosophy of sciencePhilosophy of science
Philosophy of science
 
ENVIRONMENTAL ISSUES AND AWARENESS - Presentation
ENVIRONMENTAL ISSUES AND AWARENESS - PresentationENVIRONMENTAL ISSUES AND AWARENESS - Presentation
ENVIRONMENTAL ISSUES AND AWARENESS - Presentation
 
notice aesthetics ways.pptx senior high school
notice aesthetics ways.pptx senior high schoolnotice aesthetics ways.pptx senior high school
notice aesthetics ways.pptx senior high school
 
Philosophy-Lecture-1.pptx
Philosophy-Lecture-1.pptxPhilosophy-Lecture-1.pptx
Philosophy-Lecture-1.pptx
 
Philosophy Of Realism (Defination And Brief History)
Philosophy Of Realism (Defination And Brief History)Philosophy Of Realism (Defination And Brief History)
Philosophy Of Realism (Defination And Brief History)
 
HM223 Lecture 3.pptx
HM223 Lecture 3.pptxHM223 Lecture 3.pptx
HM223 Lecture 3.pptx
 
PS 240 Environmentalism(s) Spring 2015
PS 240 Environmentalism(s) Spring 2015PS 240 Environmentalism(s) Spring 2015
PS 240 Environmentalism(s) Spring 2015
 
Lesson 4 human person in the environment.pdf
Lesson 4 human person in the environment.pdfLesson 4 human person in the environment.pdf
Lesson 4 human person in the environment.pdf
 
Human Person in the Environment
Human Person in the EnvironmentHuman Person in the Environment
Human Person in the Environment
 
Current epistemological theory
Current epistemological theoryCurrent epistemological theory
Current epistemological theory
 
Geography, value paradigms and environmental justice lynn
Geography, value paradigms and environmental justice   lynnGeography, value paradigms and environmental justice   lynn
Geography, value paradigms and environmental justice lynn
 
Philosophy
PhilosophyPhilosophy
Philosophy
 
Professional Ethics Module 3 Notes
Professional Ethics Module 3 NotesProfessional Ethics Module 3 Notes
Professional Ethics Module 3 Notes
 
still contains sentences that are hard to understand, such as Evo.docx
still contains sentences that are hard to understand, such as Evo.docxstill contains sentences that are hard to understand, such as Evo.docx
still contains sentences that are hard to understand, such as Evo.docx
 
Anthropological Perspectives On Physical Appearance And Body Image
Anthropological Perspectives On Physical Appearance And Body ImageAnthropological Perspectives On Physical Appearance And Body Image
Anthropological Perspectives On Physical Appearance And Body Image
 

More from Luz Martinez

Scientific Review Summary Examples How To Write
Scientific Review Summary Examples How To WriteScientific Review Summary Examples How To Write
Scientific Review Summary Examples How To WriteLuz Martinez
 
Tree Writing Paper - Made By Teachers Christmas W
Tree Writing Paper - Made By Teachers Christmas WTree Writing Paper - Made By Teachers Christmas W
Tree Writing Paper - Made By Teachers Christmas WLuz Martinez
 
Essay Cover Letter Information - Dissertationap
Essay Cover Letter Information - DissertationapEssay Cover Letter Information - Dissertationap
Essay Cover Letter Information - DissertationapLuz Martinez
 
Conclusion Of An Essay Example. Online assignment writing service.
Conclusion Of An Essay Example. Online assignment writing service.Conclusion Of An Essay Example. Online assignment writing service.
Conclusion Of An Essay Example. Online assignment writing service.Luz Martinez
 
Analytical Essay CIS1000 - Information Systems Conc
Analytical Essay CIS1000 - Information Systems ConcAnalytical Essay CIS1000 - Information Systems Conc
Analytical Essay CIS1000 - Information Systems ConcLuz Martinez
 
Elementary Teaching Philosophy Examples Tea
Elementary Teaching Philosophy Examples TeaElementary Teaching Philosophy Examples Tea
Elementary Teaching Philosophy Examples TeaLuz Martinez
 
My Favorite Childhood Memory Essay. Essay On Childhood
My Favorite Childhood Memory Essay. Essay On ChildhoodMy Favorite Childhood Memory Essay. Essay On Childhood
My Favorite Childhood Memory Essay. Essay On ChildhoodLuz Martinez
 
Example Of Methodology - Reasonable Research Met
Example Of Methodology - Reasonable Research MetExample Of Methodology - Reasonable Research Met
Example Of Methodology - Reasonable Research MetLuz Martinez
 
Research Paper Conclusion Writi. Online assignment writing service.
Research Paper Conclusion Writi. Online assignment writing service.Research Paper Conclusion Writi. Online assignment writing service.
Research Paper Conclusion Writi. Online assignment writing service.Luz Martinez
 
Old-Fashioned Correspondence Airmail Envelopes
Old-Fashioned Correspondence Airmail EnvelopesOld-Fashioned Correspondence Airmail Envelopes
Old-Fashioned Correspondence Airmail EnvelopesLuz Martinez
 
Free Printable Apple Leaf-Shaped Writing Templates
Free Printable Apple Leaf-Shaped Writing TemplatesFree Printable Apple Leaf-Shaped Writing Templates
Free Printable Apple Leaf-Shaped Writing TemplatesLuz Martinez
 
Pin On Writings Only. Online assignment writing service.
Pin On Writings Only. Online assignment writing service.Pin On Writings Only. Online assignment writing service.
Pin On Writings Only. Online assignment writing service.Luz Martinez
 
Apa Format Paragraph Structure. APA Essay Form
Apa Format Paragraph Structure. APA Essay FormApa Format Paragraph Structure. APA Essay Form
Apa Format Paragraph Structure. APA Essay FormLuz Martinez
 
Admission Essay Samples Of Descriptive Essay
Admission Essay Samples Of Descriptive EssayAdmission Essay Samples Of Descriptive Essay
Admission Essay Samples Of Descriptive EssayLuz Martinez
 
Position Paper Sample About Abortion In The Philippine
Position Paper Sample About Abortion In The PhilippinePosition Paper Sample About Abortion In The Philippine
Position Paper Sample About Abortion In The PhilippineLuz Martinez
 
Scholarship Essay Examples Graduate School - Sample
Scholarship Essay Examples Graduate School - SampleScholarship Essay Examples Graduate School - Sample
Scholarship Essay Examples Graduate School - SampleLuz Martinez
 
How To Write A Great Essay - Video Lesson Transcript
How To Write A Great Essay - Video  Lesson TranscriptHow To Write A Great Essay - Video  Lesson Transcript
How To Write A Great Essay - Video Lesson TranscriptLuz Martinez
 
Descriptive Essay Essay On A Mother. Online assignment writing service.
Descriptive Essay Essay On A Mother. Online assignment writing service.Descriptive Essay Essay On A Mother. Online assignment writing service.
Descriptive Essay Essay On A Mother. Online assignment writing service.Luz Martinez
 
How To Write A Concept Paper (With Examples) - Wi
How To Write A Concept Paper (With Examples) - WiHow To Write A Concept Paper (With Examples) - Wi
How To Write A Concept Paper (With Examples) - WiLuz Martinez
 
General Essay Outline Template Room Surf.Com
General Essay Outline Template  Room Surf.ComGeneral Essay Outline Template  Room Surf.Com
General Essay Outline Template Room Surf.ComLuz Martinez
 

More from Luz Martinez (20)

Scientific Review Summary Examples How To Write
Scientific Review Summary Examples How To WriteScientific Review Summary Examples How To Write
Scientific Review Summary Examples How To Write
 
Tree Writing Paper - Made By Teachers Christmas W
Tree Writing Paper - Made By Teachers Christmas WTree Writing Paper - Made By Teachers Christmas W
Tree Writing Paper - Made By Teachers Christmas W
 
Essay Cover Letter Information - Dissertationap
Essay Cover Letter Information - DissertationapEssay Cover Letter Information - Dissertationap
Essay Cover Letter Information - Dissertationap
 
Conclusion Of An Essay Example. Online assignment writing service.
Conclusion Of An Essay Example. Online assignment writing service.Conclusion Of An Essay Example. Online assignment writing service.
Conclusion Of An Essay Example. Online assignment writing service.
 
Analytical Essay CIS1000 - Information Systems Conc
Analytical Essay CIS1000 - Information Systems ConcAnalytical Essay CIS1000 - Information Systems Conc
Analytical Essay CIS1000 - Information Systems Conc
 
Elementary Teaching Philosophy Examples Tea
Elementary Teaching Philosophy Examples TeaElementary Teaching Philosophy Examples Tea
Elementary Teaching Philosophy Examples Tea
 
My Favorite Childhood Memory Essay. Essay On Childhood
My Favorite Childhood Memory Essay. Essay On ChildhoodMy Favorite Childhood Memory Essay. Essay On Childhood
My Favorite Childhood Memory Essay. Essay On Childhood
 
Example Of Methodology - Reasonable Research Met
Example Of Methodology - Reasonable Research MetExample Of Methodology - Reasonable Research Met
Example Of Methodology - Reasonable Research Met
 
Research Paper Conclusion Writi. Online assignment writing service.
Research Paper Conclusion Writi. Online assignment writing service.Research Paper Conclusion Writi. Online assignment writing service.
Research Paper Conclusion Writi. Online assignment writing service.
 
Old-Fashioned Correspondence Airmail Envelopes
Old-Fashioned Correspondence Airmail EnvelopesOld-Fashioned Correspondence Airmail Envelopes
Old-Fashioned Correspondence Airmail Envelopes
 
Free Printable Apple Leaf-Shaped Writing Templates
Free Printable Apple Leaf-Shaped Writing TemplatesFree Printable Apple Leaf-Shaped Writing Templates
Free Printable Apple Leaf-Shaped Writing Templates
 
Pin On Writings Only. Online assignment writing service.
Pin On Writings Only. Online assignment writing service.Pin On Writings Only. Online assignment writing service.
Pin On Writings Only. Online assignment writing service.
 
Apa Format Paragraph Structure. APA Essay Form
Apa Format Paragraph Structure. APA Essay FormApa Format Paragraph Structure. APA Essay Form
Apa Format Paragraph Structure. APA Essay Form
 
Admission Essay Samples Of Descriptive Essay
Admission Essay Samples Of Descriptive EssayAdmission Essay Samples Of Descriptive Essay
Admission Essay Samples Of Descriptive Essay
 
Position Paper Sample About Abortion In The Philippine
Position Paper Sample About Abortion In The PhilippinePosition Paper Sample About Abortion In The Philippine
Position Paper Sample About Abortion In The Philippine
 
Scholarship Essay Examples Graduate School - Sample
Scholarship Essay Examples Graduate School - SampleScholarship Essay Examples Graduate School - Sample
Scholarship Essay Examples Graduate School - Sample
 
How To Write A Great Essay - Video Lesson Transcript
How To Write A Great Essay - Video  Lesson TranscriptHow To Write A Great Essay - Video  Lesson Transcript
How To Write A Great Essay - Video Lesson Transcript
 
Descriptive Essay Essay On A Mother. Online assignment writing service.
Descriptive Essay Essay On A Mother. Online assignment writing service.Descriptive Essay Essay On A Mother. Online assignment writing service.
Descriptive Essay Essay On A Mother. Online assignment writing service.
 
How To Write A Concept Paper (With Examples) - Wi
How To Write A Concept Paper (With Examples) - WiHow To Write A Concept Paper (With Examples) - Wi
How To Write A Concept Paper (With Examples) - Wi
 
General Essay Outline Template Room Surf.Com
General Essay Outline Template  Room Surf.ComGeneral Essay Outline Template  Room Surf.Com
General Essay Outline Template Room Surf.Com
 

Recently uploaded

BASLIQ CURRENT LOOKBOOK LOOKBOOK(1) (1).pdf
BASLIQ CURRENT LOOKBOOK  LOOKBOOK(1) (1).pdfBASLIQ CURRENT LOOKBOOK  LOOKBOOK(1) (1).pdf
BASLIQ CURRENT LOOKBOOK LOOKBOOK(1) (1).pdfSoniaTolstoy
 
Separation of Lanthanides/ Lanthanides and Actinides
Separation of Lanthanides/ Lanthanides and ActinidesSeparation of Lanthanides/ Lanthanides and Actinides
Separation of Lanthanides/ Lanthanides and ActinidesFatimaKhan178732
 
Introduction to ArtificiaI Intelligence in Higher Education
Introduction to ArtificiaI Intelligence in Higher EducationIntroduction to ArtificiaI Intelligence in Higher Education
Introduction to ArtificiaI Intelligence in Higher Educationpboyjonauth
 
Presentation by Andreas Schleicher Tackling the School Absenteeism Crisis 30 ...
Presentation by Andreas Schleicher Tackling the School Absenteeism Crisis 30 ...Presentation by Andreas Schleicher Tackling the School Absenteeism Crisis 30 ...
Presentation by Andreas Schleicher Tackling the School Absenteeism Crisis 30 ...EduSkills OECD
 
How to Make a Pirate ship Primary Education.pptx
How to Make a Pirate ship Primary Education.pptxHow to Make a Pirate ship Primary Education.pptx
How to Make a Pirate ship Primary Education.pptxmanuelaromero2013
 
Solving Puzzles Benefits Everyone (English).pptx
Solving Puzzles Benefits Everyone (English).pptxSolving Puzzles Benefits Everyone (English).pptx
Solving Puzzles Benefits Everyone (English).pptxOH TEIK BIN
 
Kisan Call Centre - To harness potential of ICT in Agriculture by answer farm...
Kisan Call Centre - To harness potential of ICT in Agriculture by answer farm...Kisan Call Centre - To harness potential of ICT in Agriculture by answer farm...
Kisan Call Centre - To harness potential of ICT in Agriculture by answer farm...Krashi Coaching
 
MENTAL STATUS EXAMINATION format.docx
MENTAL     STATUS EXAMINATION format.docxMENTAL     STATUS EXAMINATION format.docx
MENTAL STATUS EXAMINATION format.docxPoojaSen20
 
APM Welcome, APM North West Network Conference, Synergies Across Sectors
APM Welcome, APM North West Network Conference, Synergies Across SectorsAPM Welcome, APM North West Network Conference, Synergies Across Sectors
APM Welcome, APM North West Network Conference, Synergies Across SectorsAssociation for Project Management
 
Hybridoma Technology ( Production , Purification , and Application )
Hybridoma Technology  ( Production , Purification , and Application  ) Hybridoma Technology  ( Production , Purification , and Application  )
Hybridoma Technology ( Production , Purification , and Application ) Sakshi Ghasle
 
Micromeritics - Fundamental and Derived Properties of Powders
Micromeritics - Fundamental and Derived Properties of PowdersMicromeritics - Fundamental and Derived Properties of Powders
Micromeritics - Fundamental and Derived Properties of PowdersChitralekhaTherkar
 
18-04-UA_REPORT_MEDIALITERAСY_INDEX-DM_23-1-final-eng.pdf
18-04-UA_REPORT_MEDIALITERAСY_INDEX-DM_23-1-final-eng.pdf18-04-UA_REPORT_MEDIALITERAСY_INDEX-DM_23-1-final-eng.pdf
18-04-UA_REPORT_MEDIALITERAСY_INDEX-DM_23-1-final-eng.pdfssuser54595a
 
CARE OF CHILD IN INCUBATOR..........pptx
CARE OF CHILD IN INCUBATOR..........pptxCARE OF CHILD IN INCUBATOR..........pptx
CARE OF CHILD IN INCUBATOR..........pptxGaneshChakor2
 
Q4-W6-Restating Informational Text Grade 3
Q4-W6-Restating Informational Text Grade 3Q4-W6-Restating Informational Text Grade 3
Q4-W6-Restating Informational Text Grade 3JemimahLaneBuaron
 
The Most Excellent Way | 1 Corinthians 13
The Most Excellent Way | 1 Corinthians 13The Most Excellent Way | 1 Corinthians 13
The Most Excellent Way | 1 Corinthians 13Steve Thomason
 
Introduction to AI in Higher Education_draft.pptx
Introduction to AI in Higher Education_draft.pptxIntroduction to AI in Higher Education_draft.pptx
Introduction to AI in Higher Education_draft.pptxpboyjonauth
 
SOCIAL AND HISTORICAL CONTEXT - LFTVD.pptx
SOCIAL AND HISTORICAL CONTEXT - LFTVD.pptxSOCIAL AND HISTORICAL CONTEXT - LFTVD.pptx
SOCIAL AND HISTORICAL CONTEXT - LFTVD.pptxiammrhaywood
 
URLs and Routing in the Odoo 17 Website App
URLs and Routing in the Odoo 17 Website AppURLs and Routing in the Odoo 17 Website App
URLs and Routing in the Odoo 17 Website AppCeline George
 

Recently uploaded (20)

BASLIQ CURRENT LOOKBOOK LOOKBOOK(1) (1).pdf
BASLIQ CURRENT LOOKBOOK  LOOKBOOK(1) (1).pdfBASLIQ CURRENT LOOKBOOK  LOOKBOOK(1) (1).pdf
BASLIQ CURRENT LOOKBOOK LOOKBOOK(1) (1).pdf
 
Separation of Lanthanides/ Lanthanides and Actinides
Separation of Lanthanides/ Lanthanides and ActinidesSeparation of Lanthanides/ Lanthanides and Actinides
Separation of Lanthanides/ Lanthanides and Actinides
 
TataKelola dan KamSiber Kecerdasan Buatan v022.pdf
TataKelola dan KamSiber Kecerdasan Buatan v022.pdfTataKelola dan KamSiber Kecerdasan Buatan v022.pdf
TataKelola dan KamSiber Kecerdasan Buatan v022.pdf
 
Introduction to ArtificiaI Intelligence in Higher Education
Introduction to ArtificiaI Intelligence in Higher EducationIntroduction to ArtificiaI Intelligence in Higher Education
Introduction to ArtificiaI Intelligence in Higher Education
 
Presentation by Andreas Schleicher Tackling the School Absenteeism Crisis 30 ...
Presentation by Andreas Schleicher Tackling the School Absenteeism Crisis 30 ...Presentation by Andreas Schleicher Tackling the School Absenteeism Crisis 30 ...
Presentation by Andreas Schleicher Tackling the School Absenteeism Crisis 30 ...
 
How to Make a Pirate ship Primary Education.pptx
How to Make a Pirate ship Primary Education.pptxHow to Make a Pirate ship Primary Education.pptx
How to Make a Pirate ship Primary Education.pptx
 
Solving Puzzles Benefits Everyone (English).pptx
Solving Puzzles Benefits Everyone (English).pptxSolving Puzzles Benefits Everyone (English).pptx
Solving Puzzles Benefits Everyone (English).pptx
 
Kisan Call Centre - To harness potential of ICT in Agriculture by answer farm...
Kisan Call Centre - To harness potential of ICT in Agriculture by answer farm...Kisan Call Centre - To harness potential of ICT in Agriculture by answer farm...
Kisan Call Centre - To harness potential of ICT in Agriculture by answer farm...
 
MENTAL STATUS EXAMINATION format.docx
MENTAL     STATUS EXAMINATION format.docxMENTAL     STATUS EXAMINATION format.docx
MENTAL STATUS EXAMINATION format.docx
 
Staff of Color (SOC) Retention Efforts DDSD
Staff of Color (SOC) Retention Efforts DDSDStaff of Color (SOC) Retention Efforts DDSD
Staff of Color (SOC) Retention Efforts DDSD
 
APM Welcome, APM North West Network Conference, Synergies Across Sectors
APM Welcome, APM North West Network Conference, Synergies Across SectorsAPM Welcome, APM North West Network Conference, Synergies Across Sectors
APM Welcome, APM North West Network Conference, Synergies Across Sectors
 
Hybridoma Technology ( Production , Purification , and Application )
Hybridoma Technology  ( Production , Purification , and Application  ) Hybridoma Technology  ( Production , Purification , and Application  )
Hybridoma Technology ( Production , Purification , and Application )
 
Micromeritics - Fundamental and Derived Properties of Powders
Micromeritics - Fundamental and Derived Properties of PowdersMicromeritics - Fundamental and Derived Properties of Powders
Micromeritics - Fundamental and Derived Properties of Powders
 
18-04-UA_REPORT_MEDIALITERAСY_INDEX-DM_23-1-final-eng.pdf
18-04-UA_REPORT_MEDIALITERAСY_INDEX-DM_23-1-final-eng.pdf18-04-UA_REPORT_MEDIALITERAСY_INDEX-DM_23-1-final-eng.pdf
18-04-UA_REPORT_MEDIALITERAСY_INDEX-DM_23-1-final-eng.pdf
 
CARE OF CHILD IN INCUBATOR..........pptx
CARE OF CHILD IN INCUBATOR..........pptxCARE OF CHILD IN INCUBATOR..........pptx
CARE OF CHILD IN INCUBATOR..........pptx
 
Q4-W6-Restating Informational Text Grade 3
Q4-W6-Restating Informational Text Grade 3Q4-W6-Restating Informational Text Grade 3
Q4-W6-Restating Informational Text Grade 3
 
The Most Excellent Way | 1 Corinthians 13
The Most Excellent Way | 1 Corinthians 13The Most Excellent Way | 1 Corinthians 13
The Most Excellent Way | 1 Corinthians 13
 
Introduction to AI in Higher Education_draft.pptx
Introduction to AI in Higher Education_draft.pptxIntroduction to AI in Higher Education_draft.pptx
Introduction to AI in Higher Education_draft.pptx
 
SOCIAL AND HISTORICAL CONTEXT - LFTVD.pptx
SOCIAL AND HISTORICAL CONTEXT - LFTVD.pptxSOCIAL AND HISTORICAL CONTEXT - LFTVD.pptx
SOCIAL AND HISTORICAL CONTEXT - LFTVD.pptx
 
URLs and Routing in the Odoo 17 Website App
URLs and Routing in the Odoo 17 Website AppURLs and Routing in the Odoo 17 Website App
URLs and Routing in the Odoo 17 Website App
 

A PRAGMATIC ANALYSIS OF PAUL TAYLOR S BIOCENTRISM.pdf

  • 1. A PRAGMATIC ANALYSIS OF PAUL TAYLOR'S BIOCENTRISM Terzungwe Inja Department of Philosophy Benue State University Abstract Contemporary societies in Africa (like the rest of the world) are increasingly facing drastic environmental problems which, in most cases, are a direct consequence of man's anthropocentric attitudes toward nature. Since the dawn of the twentieth Century, multidisciplinary efforts to articulate a universal praxis for the environment have become frantic. In Philosophy, arguments in support of a paradigm shift led to the emergence of non- anthropocentric thoughts like Paul Taylor's respect to nature. He rejects anthropocentrism and advocates for equality and moral significance among different life forms irrespective of different interests. Thus his biocentrism is egalitarian, and essentially, an extension of inherent worth from humans to other life forms. He thinks this paradigm shift in the way man views and treats nature can solve the crises. The main objective of this paper was to ascertain the applicability of Taylor's theory. In this direction, a pragmatic approach was adopted. This methodology was preferred for its tendency of evaluating everything based on practicability. It was found that there were links between Taylor's thought and Kant's notion of respect for persons; and that biocentric egalitarianism marked a major shift from traditional ethics. Furthermore, the theory was found tenable in areas like strategic planning for attitudinal change, policy design, law, administration, environmental remediation, reparations and environmental justice; which are practical ways of quelling environmental crises. However, there were some conceptual, exegetical, and existential weaknesses within Biocentric Egalitarianism. The study concluded that Biocentric Egalitarianism is, in several ways, tenable in tackling contemporary environmental problems. Keywords: Biocentrism, Egalitarianism, Environmental Ethics, Paul Taylor, Pragmatism, Pollution, Non-anthropocentrism INTRODUCTION Much of human civilization and its amazing improvements in living conditions would not have been possible without reliance on the Earth's resources. Obviously, everything has come at a great environmental cost. All along, mankind has operated on the anthropocentric notion that nature's resources are only useful to the extent that they satisfy his desires; and the consequences have been devastating: an alarming rate of environmental pollution, degradation, species extinction, and depletion of non- renewable resources. Most of these negative effects of man's environmental 58 Sapientia Journal of Philosophy
  • 2. th exploitation were evident at the turn of the 20 century; it became obvious that if nothing was done, humankind would drive the world to a catastrophic end. This realization marked the emergence of several and various efforts to remedy the damage; involving experts in areas like sociology, politics, geography, ecology, ethnobotany, and philosophy. Particularly, philosophers found that anthropocentric attitudes and praxis toward the natural environment were largely to blame for the teeming environmental challenges. Thus they set out to unearth alternative ethical paradigms by which to reshape man's attitude and behaviour toward the environment (Minster 185). This period marked the birth of non-anthropocentrism which, generally, extends inherent worth to non-human life forms (in the case of biocentrism) and to every component of the ecosystem (in case of ecocentrism). It maintains that justice is not whatever man deems fit, rather it is what nature ought to have. Through non-anthropocentrism, “philosophers were hoping to advance a persuasive moral justification for a robust environmental policy and a general rationalization of proenvironmental [sic] practices” (Minster 185). In line with this movement Paul Taylor proposes his theory known as biocentric egalitarianism, by which he argues that anthropocentric attitudes and ways of exploiting the natural environment are responsible for the problems we have. He maintains that humans must adopt the attitude of respect for nature by which all living things would be valued, not in an instrumental way anymore, but to accord them respect as ends-in- themselves. This is where the problem for this paper finds its root; an examination of Taylor's critics revealed that they have been mostly focused on its theoretical ramifications. Many scholars and researchers have questioned the extent to which man can be equated with nature; the dynamics of power that would emanate if such an egalitarian notion were possible; the individuality of species which Taylor proposes; and the implications of harnessing this thought for the development of an environmental praxis. Thus, scholars have almost completely covered the theoretical implications (Inja 4). In the light of the above, this researcher has focused on the practical tenability of Taylor's viewpoint. More so, while Taylor himself has shied away from propounding an empirical modus operandi, he has admitted to proposing “a philosophical worldview” (“The Ethics of Respect for Nature” 205). And since every worldview is supposed to have a practical impact, the researcher has decided to undertake a pragmatic analysis with emphasis on the practicality of the theory. Thus the extent to which such an egalitarian ethos is useful in curbing environmental problems is the thrust of this paper. Conceptual Clarifications The following terms have been clarified to enhance the understanding of this discourse:-Biocentrism Environmental thoughts are generally categorised into two intellectual camps: those that are anthropocentric (or 'human-centred') and those that are non-anthropocentric ('life- centred' and/or 'eco-centred'). This typology has been described in other terminology as 'shallow' ecology and 'deep' ecology respectively. Biocentrism falls under non- anthropocentrism; RobinAttfield defines it as “a life-centred outlook that rejects the view that humanity alone matters in ethics and accepts the moral standing of (at least) all living 59 Sapientia Journal of Philosophy
  • 3. creatures” (97). In the same vein, Lorraine Elliott defines biocentrism as a theory which holds that nature has an intrinsic moral worth which does not depend on its usefulness to human beings; and that this intrinsic worth should define human obligations to the environment (“Biocentrism” n.p). Etymologically, the term biocentrism is traceable to two Greek words, βίος (pronounced 'bio' meaning 'life') and κέντρον, (pronounced 'kentron' meaning 'centre'). Put together, both terms form the English 'biocentrism' which connotes a 'life-centred' environmentalism (Mouchang and Lei 423). Biocentrism, in the light of the above amounts to moral extensionism; that is, an extension of moral worth from humans to non-human animals and plants. Pragmatism There are many ideas about the meaning of pragmatism; in a general sense, the term refers to any “straightforward or practical way of thinking about things or dealing with problems, [to be] concerned with results rather than with theories and principles” (Encarta Dictionary n.p). Philosophically, the term pragmatism represents a philosophical tradition which (is quite traceable to antiquity but) manifested most strongly in the 1870s America through the pioneering work of Charles Sanders Pierce (1839-1914) and his followers William James (1842-1910) and John Dewey (1859- 1952) (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy n.p). According to James, pragmatism rejects the notion that the function of human thinking is to describe, represent, or mirror reality (n.p). Rather, pragmatists view thought as an instrument or tool for prediction, problem solving and action. They contend that most philosophical topics (such as the nature of knowledge, language, concepts, meaning, belief, and science) should be considered more in terms of their practical uses and successes. The philosophy of pragmatism “emphasizes the practical application of ideas by acting on them to actually test them in human experiences” (Gutek 76-100). Also the Encarta Dictionary reports that is a philosophical method of evaluating theories which holds, “a theory or concept should be evaluated in terms of how it works and its consequences as the standard for action and thought” (n.p). Within this paper, the pragmatic method of is understood and applied in this sense; thus it is the practical applicability ofTaylor's biocentrism that has been subjected to the court of reason. Paul Taylor's Biocentric Egalitarianism th Paul Warren Taylor was born in Philadelphia on 19 November 1923. He is specialized in normative and applied ethics, and is best known for his work in environmental ethics. He is emeritus professor of philosophy at Brooklyn College, City University of New York; where he studied normative and applied ethics (“Paul Taylor” web). He has the authored several articles, essays and books. Among his most popular books are, Normative Discourse (1961), Principles of Ethics (1975), and Respect for Nature: A Theory of Environmental Ethics (1986). He has also edited two books of readings:- The Moral Judgement: Readings in Contemporary Meta-Ethics (1963); and rd Problems of Moral Philosophy, 3 Ed. (1971). Oakley acknowledges that Taylor is a renowned Kantian scholar (257). Taylor's biocentric egalitarianism is taught in many university courses on environmental ethics today. An examination of his theory shows various links to other philosophers who may have influenced his biocentric thought; key among which is Immanuel Kant (via the principle 60 Sapientia Journal of Philosophy
  • 4. of respect for persons). Also easily traced are the thoughts of Arne Naess (deep and shallow ecology), Kenneth Goodpaster (moral considerability), Albert Schweitzer (reverence for life), Peter Singer (sentience and equality), and Mahatma Ghandi (ahimsa or non-violence). Biocentric Egalitarianism Taylor's theory of Biocentric Egalitarianism, widely known as the ethics of Respect for Nature, is a complicated but compelling thought on the environment which was first announced in his article titled “The Ethics of Respect for Nature” that was published in the year 1981 (197-218). Another of his articles “Are Humans Superior to Animals and Plants?” published in summer of 1984 also contains elements of the biocentric outlook on life. This initial effort found expression in several of his works and culminated in his 1986 book with the title, Respect for Nature:ATheory of Environmental Ethics. Taylor's biocentrism synthesizes Classical and Kantian virtue ethics, with elements of Albert Schweitzer's ethics of reverence for life, Peter Singer's egalitarianism, and Kenneth Goodpaster's account of moral considerability. He begins with the view that all living things have inherent value, and so are deserving of moral respect, equally. For Taylor, all that is required to have inherent value is to be alive – essentially, striving towards staying alive. He grounds his view on the idea of Respect for Nature, which is an extension of the Kantian principle of Respect for Persons. Taylor clarifies his position by distinguishing it from an ecocentric view – namely, it is not fundamentally holistic. To him the balance of nature does not lead us to any moral principles; rather, the good or well-being of all individual living things is of primary concern (so it is not anthropocentric either). There are many duties which require us to protect ecological systems, but these are only indirect duties to the individual living things that inhabit the ecological system. He argues further that one who adopts the ultimate moral attitude of respect for nature will become an environmentally virtuous person. He identifies environmental ethical conduct with conduct motivated by respect for nature. Such environmentally virtuous conduct seeks to promote the flourishing of all living organisms. In his Respect for Nature: A Theory of Environmental Ethics, he states, “ethical action and goodness of character naturally flow from the attitude [of respect for nature], and the attitude is made manifest in how one acts and in what sort of person one is” (80). He maintains that a biocentric ethic can be established (justified) if people adopt a new kind of moral attitude; the attitude that all living things, and not only humans, have inherent worth; that is, the attitude of respect for nature. But he acknowledges that a lot of work needs to be done to establish that we ought to take on the new attitude. Two things need to be made clear, first.These are:- (a) All living things have a good of their own - that is, they can be benefited or harmed. This is reflected in the idea that all living things have the potential to grow and develop according to their biological natures. So, things can either go well or not with respect to this potential. This idea is not grounded, according to Taylor, in the ideas of having interests, or having an interest in something; and it is not conditional upon being sentient, or having consciousness (199). Taylor thinks it is an open question whether a machine might have a good of its own in the relevant sense. 61 Sapientia Journal of Philosophy
  • 5. (b) The attitude of respect for nature requires that we accept that all living things possess inherent worth. This would be reflected in us - were we to take on the attitude of respect for nature - adopting certain dispositions of behaviour, namely, in general, to act so as to show equal respect for all living things good of their own (199). According to him this does not justify the claim that all living things do have inherent worth, though. So, more needs to be done to show this. His strategy is to argue that living things possess inherent worth, and that this can be justified by showing that we are capable of adopting the attitude of respect for nature. Presumably, he thinks that a “biocentric outlook on nature”, that is respecting nature, directly implies the regard of living things as having some inherent worth. This is essentially an ecological outlook, with the key idea being the interdependence of living things. Taylor concedes that, “we cannot see the point of taking the attitude of respect” until we understand and accept the biocentric outlook. However, he insists, “… once we do grasp it and shape our world outlook in accordance with it, we immediately understand how and why a person should adopt that attitude [of respect] as the only appropriate one to have toward nature” (Respect for Nature… 99). The biocentric outlook, asTaylor conceives it, consists of four core beliefs: (a) The belief that humans are members of the Earth's Community of Life in the same sense and on the same terms in which other living things are members of that Community. (b) The belief that the human species, along with all other species, are integral elements in a system of interdependence such that the survival of each living thing, as well as its chances of faring well or poorly, is determined not only by the physical conditions of its environment but also by its relations to other living things. (c) The belief that all organisms are teleological centers [sic] of life in the sense that each is a unique individual pursuing its own good in its own way. (d)The belief that humans are not inherently superior to other living things (100). Taylor thinks that when we accept the first three beliefs of the biocentric outlook the denial of human superiority will make meaning to us. In turn, the acknowledgment of the groundlessness of the claim of human superiority will enable us to justify the first three elements of the biocentric outlook. He argues that if we accept all four beliefs, then we have a coherent outlook on the natural word and the place of humans in it; it is the acceptance of the fact that humans and nonhuman life forms should relate in a certain way; such a world view is then to be seen as the only suitable, fitting, or appropriate moral attitude to take toward the natural world and its living inhabitants (“The Ethics of Respect for Nature” 206).Essentially, this outlook sees living things “… as the appropriate objects of the attitude of respect and are accordingly regarded as entities possessing inherent worth.” Taylor suggests that adoption of the biocentric outlook leads us to adoption of the attitude of respect for nature, with the implication that we now have a non-anthropocentric environmental ethic (“The Ethics of Respect for Nature” 100). 62 Sapientia Journal of Philosophy
  • 6. According toAdplanalp, Taylor moves from here to deny human superiority. He does this by presenting counter arguments against four of the most common advanced arguments for human superiority:- (i) Classical Greek Humanism (which purports that rationality makes humans superior to other life forms); (ii) The Great Chain of Being (an axiological paradigm which conceives of beings in a hierarchical rank that places man above other life forms); (iii) Cartesian Dualism (which claims that non-human life forms are mere matter without soul (mind) and as such have less worth than humans); (iv) Louis Lombardi's argument for human superiority which goes that even though all living things have inherent worth, animals have less inherent worth than humans –because human's have more capacities (262). On the question of why moral agents should accept the four beliefs that make up the biocentric outlook, Taylor is certain that the biocentric outlook is supported by biology and ecology, and it also meets the criteria upon which all philosophical world views have been judged and accepted throughout the history of philosophy; these are: (a) Comprehensiveness and completeness; (b) Systematic order, coherence, and internal consistency; (c) Freedom from obscurity, conceptual confusion, and semantic vacuity; (d) Consistency with all known empirical truths. He goes on to express confidence in the validity of his arguments, “these criteria have served as tests for the overall adequacy and satisfactoriness of a world view. When we apply them to the biocentric outlook, I submit, we find them to be fully met” (Respect for Nature… 206). Criticism of Taylor's Biocentric Egalitarianism Taylor's egalitarian biocentrism has attracted a lot of criticism from diverse scholars and philosophers. Peter Singer, in his Animal Liberation, rejects Taylor's argument that all living things have moral significance. Instead he argues that only sentient beings should be accorded any consideration (8 – 9). But Taylor argues that it is arbitrary to restrict the class of morally considerable beings to sentient beings. Since all living organisms can be harmed or benefited and what benefits them promotes their good, Taylor insists that there is no non-arbitrary reason that prevents us from extending moral consideration to all living organisms. Some biocentrists take issue with Taylor's egalitarianism; that is his view that all living things are equal and humans are on par with non-human life forms. For instance both Kenneth Goodpaster (“On Being Morally Considerable” 308 – 325) and Gary Varner (In Nature's Interest) agree that all living organisms deserve moral consideration, but deny that being morally considerable entails having equal moral significance. These critics reject Taylor's egalitarianism in favour of a hierarchical account of moral significance. Particularly, Varner argues that some interests take priority over others and that only recognition of this inequality will provide viable support for environmental goals. In essence, Varner's argument is that it is impossible to derive practical principles from a non-hierarchical system of interests likeTaylor's. Taylor's individualism has attracted another criticism; he holds that “it is the good (well- being, welfare) of individual organisms […] that determines our moral relations with the Earth's wild communities of life” (“The Ethics of Respect for Nature” 198). Critics contend that Taylor's focus on individual welfare fails to address the actual concerns of environmentalists. Most environmentalists are concerned not with the welfare of individual mosquitoes, dandelions, and microbes, but rather with species preservation, ecological integrity, and pollution. These critics insist that only a holistic ethic can better 63 Sapientia Journal of Philosophy
  • 7. address these environmental concerns (Williams n.p). Taylor's rejection of human superiority has also been challenged. Critics think that the idea of extending equal moral consideration to every living organism, is not only too demanding, but outright absurd and impracticable (Attfield is among those who hold this view). Taylor tries to mitigate this objection by formulating a complex set of principles (self-defence, proportionality, minimum harm, distributive justice, and restitutive justice) for fairly resolving the conflicts that inevitably arise between humans and other equally considerable organisms. Even with these principles in place, Taylor's biocentric ethic remains extremely demanding, since the principle of proportionality dictates that the basic interests of plants trump the non-basic interests of humans (Williams n.p). Louis Lombardi also contested Taylor's rejection of human superiority by arguing that even though all living things have inherent worth, animals have less inherent worth than humans (because human's have more capacities) and that in the event of a clash of interests, human interests would trump that of other life forms (qtd inAdplanalp 264). Taylor retorted by arguing that while humans have capacities that non-humans have, the reverse is the case too; thus there is ground to argue (from the perspective of non- humans) that in their own ways there are also superior. Hence the key issue whether the capacities in question are needed to function (264). For instance, it is not proper to expect animals to be rational since rationality is not needed to function in their world; just like it is wrong to expect humans to possess the superior climbing ability of monkeys. Thus Taylor believes that no particular organism should be seen as inferior on the grounds of capacities. Taylor's demarcation of living things and his use of terms is another source of concern to critics. Megan Wade takes issue with the basic premise of Taylor's analysis. Particularly, she disagrees with the way Taylor has, “drawn stark lines between humans and nature, between moral and non-moral agents, and in so doing fails [sic] to adequately consider those issues that would complicate this picture: non-human species with highly developed social lives and potential species-specific codes of conduct, for instance” (Wade n.p). In other words, Wade finds it difficult to accept the demarcation of living things while at the same time proposing equality. It appears the demarcation itself indicates a serious divergence of interests which is irreconcilable ab initio. She also has a problem with Taylor's use of the term 'nature'. In her opinion it is “slippery; really, he appears to mean 'wild', which is actually quite different in meaning from 'natural'. Much of his argument seems unselfconsciously premised on the value of 'wild' things, without exploration of the source of that value” (Wade n.p). It has been argued that generally, all non-anthropocentric theories of the man-nature relationship have failed to ascertain a true non-anthropocentric worldview because at the end, everything boils down to the benefits of man on planet. Bryan Norton has particularly argued that non-anthropocentric theories such as biocentrism are redundant because sophisticated anthropocentrism supports the same policies. However, biocentrists counter that the recognition of nonhuman interests lends stronger support for policies of humaneness, compassion and preservation, and also shows why it is necessary to preserve those species that are not currently the concern of humans –for instance those that are not yet discovered (Norton qtd inAttfield 99). 64 Sapientia Journal of Philosophy
  • 8. Closely related to this is another general objection to biocentrism (and other non- anthropocentric theories) which was advanced by J. Baird Callicot who avers that all judgements of value, however non-anthropocentric in content, are still anthropogenic (“Rolston on Intrinsic Value: A Deconstruction” 129 – 143). With a similar view, Attfield explains that “they are dependent on human valuation, and there can be no value in the absence of valuers” (“Biocentrism” 100). However Attfield contends that even if such an argument is granted, it would affect biocentrism only at the level of human judgements and not at the normative level; since what is valuable does not mean “valued” but applies to what there is reason to value –whether or not anyone values it. He maintains that it is implausible to think that nothing that exists had value until humans first appeared and began making judgements. Normative biocentrism defends an intrinsic value which is beyond mere human judgements of morals and values. He concludes that “biocentrists can consistently and reasonably be resolute metaethical realists, even though their normative stance (biocentrism) does not hang upon affiliation to realism (100).” Taylor's biocentrism, by virtue of its nonanthropocentrism, is also affected by these general objections. However, as already pointed out by Attfield, biocentrism at its normative level remains a strong argument. In the final analysis, whether these objections to Taylor's biocentric egalitarianism prove insuperable remains to be seen. However, regardless of whether his ethic prevails in the end or ultimately forces us to look elsewhere for an adequate environmental ethic, Taylor's biocentric outlook helps those who tolerate it to have a greater appreciation and respect for nature (Williams n.p). The Pragmatics of Paul Taylor's Biocentric Egalitarianism Taylor's biocentrism, as demonstrated above, has some objections levelled against it, but its supporters believe it is a viable theory of environmental ethics that could be used to change the world. When it comes to its practical relevance, even Taylor, concedes that the biocentric outlook “is not wholly analyzable [sic] into empirically confirmable assertions” and thus should be viewed as “a philosophical world-view” (“The Ethics of Respect for Nature” 205). Moreover, he never attempts to derive an ought from an is; rather, he seeks to provide us with a rational, coherent perspective on nature that will allow us to accurately perceive (not deduce) the inherent worth of all living beings (Williams n.p). In any case it is the opinion of this researcher that, neither Taylor's employment of a purely descriptive approach to explain the biocentric outlook, nor his expressed aim, which is to provide a “world-view” rather than “wholly empirically confirmable assertions”; should deter anyone from exploring the possibility of applying this theory in practical situations. The first justification for this opinion is that every philosophical worldview can have an impact on man's actions; so the issue should not be whether this theory is applicable, rather it should be to what extent and in which particular area it can be applied. Secondly, Taylor's egalitarian biocentrism, as largely descriptive as it may be, is an in- depth re-examination of anthropocentrism, the basic paradigm upon which humans have acted out the relationship between them and non-human life forms. It must be 65 Sapientia Journal of Philosophy
  • 9. recalled that Taylor has led us on a rediscovery journey that necessarily ends in a reassessment and readjustment of the way we have been taught by tradition to conceive, perceive, and treat nature. And such a path, to be meaningful, must also lead to the drawing up of practical ways to deal with our ever-increasing environmental problems. Therefore, this researcher submits that biocentrism is applicable in practical ways.Adetailed demonstration of this possibility is contained in the following sections. Biocentric Egalitarianism as Relevant in Formulation of Laws/Policies/Strategies Anthropocentric ways of interacting with nature have led to such the numerous environmental problems that we have today. Back in the early 1970s, this was what prompted the need for a rethink of an environmental ethic in the first instance; and evidence abounds to show that things are getting worse today because mankind has stubbornly refused to out-rightly condemn the trend of thought behind activities that are destructive to the environment; the idea that nature is only useful to the extent that it satisfies man's needs and wants. It is however not very easy for man to discontinue his exploration of the earth's resources. Man is faced with a moral dilemma; to stop and watch the whole of civilization crumble or to go on and still drive the whole earth and its inhabitants to extinction! Thus the middle ground is preservation and conservation rather than wanton destruction. We have reached the point where, to survive, man must curtail his wants and conquer his greed. This is the exact point where Taylor's egalitarian biocentrism comes in handy. Now that policy makers and other stakeholders have realized the imperative for saving the earth, one of the most viable options is to adopt Taylor's world-view, the view that man should treat nature as an equal; with respect. This ideal will become manifest when our laws, policies and strategies are structured to safeguard rather than destroy, to conserve rather than consume, and to preserve rather than plunder. As Taylor himself has stated: There is no reason, moreover, why plants and animals, including whole species populations and life communities, cannot be accorded legal rights under my theory. To grant them legal protection could be interpreted as giving them legal entitlement to be protected, and this, in fact, would be a means by which a society that subscribed to the ethics of respect for nature could give public recognition to their inherent worth “The Ethics of Respect for Nature” 218). Thus in the areas of law, policy, and strategy formulation, this is how Taylor's biocentrism can be made to work. Biocentrism Egalitarianism as a Rational Basis for Environmental Remediation Environmental remediation refers to the various scientific techniques of repairing or restoring destroyed or badly polluted environmental media such as soil, groundwater, sediment, or surface water. One of these methods is Bio-Remediation by which plants and animals are used to resuscitate, detoxify, and restore ecosystems that have been damaged through environmental degradation or pollution. Deforestation can also be effectively checked by this means (“Bioremediation” n.p). As a rational principle, such remediation is only possible when those who engage in practices that destroy the environment adopt the attitude of respect for nature. Particularly applicable in this area is Taylor's third thesis which is the realization that “…all organisms are teleological centers [sic] of life in the sense that each is a unique individual pursuing its own good in its own 66 Sapientia Journal of Philosophy
  • 10. way.” This principle provides a solid rational foundation for all activities that reflect a duty of care rather than crass arrogance towards nature and its resources; it supports the notion that it is possible for man to relate with nature in a manner of respect rather than abuse. Biocentric Egalitarianism as a Ground for Reparation Reparation refers to “the making of amends for wrong or injury done” “Reparation” n.p). Within the context of environmental justice, reparation usually takes the form of pecuniary compensation which is paid to an individual, a group, or members of a host community where environmental exploration has been carried out with harmful consequences. Often than not, trans-national companies who explore natural resources tend to be grossly anthropocentric, thereby destroying the habitats that have been home to both human and non-human life forms for thousands of years. Again, some exploration companies are ethnocentric and show disregard to the welfare of the local community. The end result is usually a state of environmental injustice by which the host community bears the heavier burden of the exploration (particularly the harmful effects) while the exploration companies bear the (economic) benefits. But justice demands that the burdens and benefits be shared equitably, so when this is not the case; a moral paradigm is needed to conscientise the offending party. This is where Taylor's biocentric egalitarianism again proves handy. The fourth thesis which rejects superiority of human beings can be extended to cover two relationships: that between man and nature; and that between a trans-national company and a host community on whose grounds resource exploration is taking place. When this is applied as a principle, corporate policies, strategies, and techniques will be put in place to prevent wanton and unwarranted destruction of the host community's habitats. Also the duty to pay adequate reparations when gross harm is caused becomes easier to comprehend and practice. CONCLUSION The above discussion has been preoccupied with an analysis of Taylor's biocentric egalitarianism using a pragmatic perspective. The philosophical tradition behind the theory, its key arguments, its impact in the field of environmental ethics, the criticisms levelled against it, and the various ways by which it could be applied in practice have been exposed. We must recall that biocentrism stands in stark opposition to anthropocentrism and that Taylor's theory has only added fuel to efforts that were made to produce a non-anthropocentric ethic. While it is impossible to satisfactorily answer all criticisms against this theory, one thing that can be known for certain is, Taylor's biocentric egalitarianism has provided us with a rational, methodic, systematic, and viable alternative to ponder over and even act on the various environmental problems we face today. Therefore, to embrace the attitude of respect to nature is to join the army of those warring against wanton destruction of the limited resources that Mother Nature has so generously bestowed on us. Thus for the good of nature, humans, and that of future generations, we must not fail to act now. Works Cited Adplanalp, Edward. “Review of Respect for Nature: A Theory of Environmental Ethics”. in International Dialogue, A Multidisciplinary Journal of World Affairs. Vol 3, 2013: 262 – 264. PDF. 67 Sapientia Journal of Philosophy
  • 11. Attfield, Robin. “Biocentrism”. in Encyclopedia of Environmental Ethics and Philosophy. Vol. 1. ed. Callicott, Baird J. and Robert Frodeman. Detroit: Gale Centage, 2009: 97 - 100. PDF. “Biocentric Consequentialism, Pluralism and 'the Minamax Implication': A Reply to Alan Carter.” Utilitas. Vol. 15 (1), 2003: 76 – 91. PDF. “Biocentric Consequentialism and Value Pluralism: A Response to Alan Carter.” Utilitas. Vol. 17 (1). 2005: 85 – 92. Print. nd The Ethics of Environmental Concern. 2 edit. Athens: University of Georgia Press, 1991. Print. “The Good of Trees.” in Journal of Value Inquiry. Vol. 15, 1983: 35 – 54. Print. “Anthropocentric vs Non-Anthropocentric Environmental Ethics”. Capilano University Open Course Ware Website. 14 July, 2013. Web. Minster, Ben A. “The Convergence Hypothesis”. in Encyclopedia of Environmental Ethics and Philosophy. Vol. 1. ed. Callicott, Baird J. and Robert Frodeman. Detroit: Gale Centage, 2009: 185 - 186. PDF. “Bioremediation.” in Wikipedia. 10 Mar, 2013. Web. rd Callicott, Baird J. Environmental Ethics: I. Overview. in Encyclopedia of Bioethics 3 Edit. Stephen Post (Ed). Vol. 2, New York: Macmillan Reference USA, 1995: 676 - 686. Print. _____ Callicott, J. Baird. 1992. ''Rolston on Intrinsic Value: A Deconstruction.'' Environmental Ethics. Vol. 14, 1992:129 - 143. Print. Carson, Rachel. Silent Spring. Boston: Houghton Mifflin, 1962. Print. Elliott, Lorraine. “Biocentrism”. in Encyclopaedia Britannica Online. Web. Goodpaster, Kenneth E. “On Being Morally Considerable”. Journal of Philosophy Vol. 75(6), 1978: 308 - 325. Print. Gutek, Gerald. Philosophical, Ideological, and Theoretical Perspectives on Education. New Jersey: Pearson, 2014. Print. Inja, Terzungwe. “A Critique of Paul Taylor's Biocentric Egalitarianism”. A Masters Dissertation submitted to the Department of Philosophy, University of Nigeria, Nsukka. July, 2016. Leopold, Aldo. A Sand County Almanac. New York: Random House, 1949. Print. ejoy, Arthur O. The Great Chain of Being: A Study of the History of an Idea. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press, 1936. qtd in Taylor, Respect for Nature: A Theory of Environmental Ethics. p.139. Print. Moore, George Edward. Principia Ethica. Cambridge: University Press, 1903. Print. Mouchang, Yu Yi Lei. “Biocentric Ethical Theories”. in Environment and Development Journal. Vol. II, 2009: 422 – 430. Print. Naess, Arne. “The Shallow and the Deep, Long–Range Ecology Movement: A Summary”. in Inquiry. Vol. 16, 1973: 95 - 100. Print. Norton, Bryan G. Why Preserve Natural Variety? Princeton, NJ: University Press, 1987. Print. 68 Sapientia Journal of Philosophy
  • 12. Toward Unity among Environmentalists. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, 1991. Print. Oakley, Justin. “Applied Ethics', in Routledge History of Philosophy. Vol X. Canfield, John V (Ed.). London: Routledge, 2005: 254 – 259. Print. “Paul Taylor (philosopher)”. in Wikipedia. 22 Jun, 2015. Web. “Paul Warren Taylor”, in Global Warming Causes: Environmental Ethics. 22 Jun, 2015. Web. “Pragmatism”, Encarta Dictionary, Microsoft® Encarta® 2009. © 1993-2008 Microsoft Corporation. DVD-ROM. “Reparation”. in Dictionary.Com. 20 Aug, 2015. Web. Scherer, Donald. “Anthropocentrism, Atomism, and Environmental Ethics.” in Environmental Ethics Vol. 4 (2), 1982: 115 – 123. Print. Singer, Peter. Animal Liberation. London: Jonathan Cape, 1975. Print. Sterba, James P. “Biocentrist Strikes Back.” in Environmental Ethics. Vol. 20(4), Winter 1998: 361–376. Print. Taylor, Paul W. “Are Humans Superior to Animals and Plants?” in Environmental Ethics. Vol. 6, No. 2, Summer, 1984: 149 – 160. Print. “The Ethics of Respect for Nature”. in Environmental Ethics. Vol. 3(3), 1981: 197 – 218. Print. Respect for Nature: A Theory of Environmental Ethics (25th Anniversary Edition). New Jersey: Princeton University Press, 2011. Print. Varner, Gary. In Nature's Interest? Oxford: University Press, 1998. Print. Wade, Megan. “Review of Paul Taylor's Respect for Nature: A Theory of th Environmental Ethics (25 Anniversary Edition)”. in Good Reads. Web. Williams, Brian G. Paul Warren Taylor. Personal Blog. 15 Mar, 2016. Web. About the Author Terzungwe Inja is a Lecturer in the Department of Philosophy, Benue State University Makurdi. He is specialized in Moral Philosophy (with a bias in Environmental Ethics). Apart from scholarly articles and essays, he writes poetry and short stories. 69 Sapientia Journal of Philosophy