SlideShare a Scribd company logo
1 of 423
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601
Dr. Danielle Zanzalari
Problem Set 2
2018
Please follow the instructions listed on your syllabus regarding
problem sets. I do not accept
late work. Email me with any questions you have.
1. Using the VNM utility function of U(Y ) = Y
1−λ
1−λ where you could win $10,000 with
probability 0.20 and lose $400 with probability 0.80 calculate
the following if λ = 0.3 and
Y = $2000:
a) The expected return of this lottery.
b) The relative risk aversion of this person.
c) The absolute risk aversion of this person.
d) The certainty equivalent. (Note: Follow the same set-up as
the notes. Essentially you
replace (E(Z)) with CE(Z), CE(Z) being the certainty
equivalent.)
2. Crosby is considering investing in the following tech
startups: African Water Nonprofit and
Boston GoodWill to Go. Crosby has the following VNM utility
function: U(Y ) = 30+Y − Y
2
200
where Y is in thousands. Crosby’s total income in $200,000 and
would have to invest $50,000
in African Water Nonprofit with a probability of success of 50%
and $75,000 in Boston
GoodWill to Go with a 65% chance of success. If these start-ups
are not successful he loses
all of his money, whereas if they are successful he will retain
his initial investment plus 10%
and 15% return of each respective company. So,
a) Will Crosby invest in either company?
b) Would a risk neutral person make this investment?
3. What is the risk preference of investors with the following
VNM utility functions?
a) U(Y ) =
√
Y
b) U(Y ) = Y 2
c) U(Y ) = ln(Y )
d) U(Y ) = 10Y + 18
e) U(Y ) = Y
1−λ
1−λ
1
4. Alex has a wealth of $175,000, no health insurance and
worker’s compensation does not
apply. Alex has a 10% chance of losing $52,000, which is the
probability he breaks his leg
sliding into second base in a baseball game and the amount of
money it would cost for hos-
pital bills, rehabilitation and loss of work for a week. His utility
function is: U(Y ) = Y
0.8
0.8
.
Blue Cross Blue Shield of NYC offers the following policies
and deductibles:
Insurance Premium Deductible
$4382 $1000
$4782 $500
$5502 $0
$3682 $1350
then which insurance policy (if any) will Alex choose and why?
5. Use the Condo Price excel spreadsheet, sourced from Zillow,
on the mean condo prices of
the top 10 cities in the U.S. to help you answer the following
questions. Please use Stata,
R, Matlab or Excel and submit your code along with your
answers written down.
a) Using the 10 cities in the Excel spreadsheet and the
assumption that house prices rise
on average 7% a year and mortgage costs are 6%. Our debt to
equity ratio is 4. Based
on what you calculate the expected return on our levered
investment to be and what
you view the house price of the following year, does it make
sense to buy a condo in
each of these cities and in each of these years? Do not calculate
this by each month.
Please just use year-06 numbers (i.e. Use numbers from June
each year for all
problems. So, use 2010-06 to estimate the expected return on
your levered investment
if you sold in 2011-06. Evaluate your expected return with the
actual return. Please
do this for each city and for 2010-2018.)
b) Now, let’s assume that we put down 5% in our condo in
Boston, Massachusetts and
borrow the rest. Our borrowing costs go up 8% since we must
pay PMI (an extra cost
for not putting down 20% equity). If we want to ensure we make
a return of 5% on our
levered investment, what must our expected return on our
unlevered investment be in
Boston, Massachusetts for each year? Does it make sense to do
a levered investment
then?
c) Look at Dallas-Fort-Worth, Texas, let’s assume that we put
10% down on our condo
and our borrowing costs are 5%. For what states of the world
(i.e. for what unlevered
return) does a levered investment not make sense?
d) Using the numbers you calculate above in part c., calculate
the risk of each Dallas-Fort
Worth investment assuming that the standard deviation of the
unlevered investment
is 2%.
e) (EXTRA CREDIT: 10 pts)Lastly, the expected return on our
levered investment does
not take into account the tax benefits of owning a condo (or
home). How would you
propose we consider the tax benefits in the home purchase
leverage equation we have
been discussing?
2
Chaucer's Pardoner on the Couch: Psyche and Clio in Medieval
Literary Studies
Author(s): Lee Patterson
Source: Speculum, Vol. 76, No. 3 (Jul., 2001), pp. 638-680
Published by: The University of Chicago Press on behalf of the
Medieval Academy of
America
Stable URL: https://www.jstor.org/stable/2903882
Accessed: 15-05-2019 02:22 UTC
REFERENCES
Linked references are available on JSTOR for this article:
https://www.jstor.org/stable/2903882?seq=1&cid=pdf-
reference#references_tab_contents
You may need to log in to JSTOR to access the linked
references.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars,
researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information
technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about
JSTOR, please contact [email protected]
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the
Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms
Medieval Academy of America, The University of Chicago
Press are collaborating with
JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Speculum
This content downloaded from 128.228.0.65 on Wed, 15 May
2019 02:22:27 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Chaucer's Pardoner on the Couch:
Psyche and Clio in Medieval Literary Studies
By Lee Patterson
I, too, was greatly impressed when I first read Freud. He's
extraordinary.
Of course he is full of fishy thinking & his charm & the charm
of the subject
is so great that you may easily be fooled.
-Ludwig Wittgenstein1
Thus one virtuoso of twentieth-century thought responded to
the spell cast over
his culture by a virtuoso of the previous generation-his
response recording a
now familiar progress from the spellbound to the disenchanted.
Wittgenstein's
shrewdness, however, remains as yet part of only a minority
tradition of skepticism
about the value of Freudianism, and psychoanalysis in general,
to contemporary
literary critics. This essay is a contribution to that skepticism
as it applies to lit-
erary interpretation, a philosophically much narrower terrain
than Wittgenstein's
genial critique envisaged, but one in which fishy thinking is no
less to be avoided.
The essay falls into six sections. The first describes the
enthusiastic adoption of
psychoanalytic concepts into medieval studies at the very
moment when they are
suffering a collapse of credibility in the real world. Part 2
summarizes the fatal
flaws now widely perceived in psychoanalytic and specifically
Freudian methods
of inquiry, especially in its cavalier unconcern with questions
of evidence and
validity. In part 3 I use an apposite test case that almost
irresistibly attracts psy-
choanalytic readings-Chaucer's Pardoner and his tale-to assess
the usefulness
or otherwise of psychoanalytic assumptions in literary
interpretation. Parts 4 and
5 offer an alternative reading of the Pardoner and his tale that
interprets the
symbolic structure by reference to discourses that are not
simply medieval but
specifically contemporary to Chaucer. The essay concludes
with some reflections
on the place of theory-whether psychoanalytic or of some other
variety-in
medieval literary studies.
The goal of this essay is not to foreclose discussion but exactly
the opposite.
For an interpretive program to be taken seriously it must both
examine the foun-
This essay was first written for a symposium organized at the
University of Oklahoma by George
Economou in March 1996, and versions have subsequently been
given at various institutions, much
to its benefit. It has been read by six readers for Speculum, all
of whom-and especially those who
found it unworthy of publication-have helped me to clarify the
argument. I would like especially to
thank Richard Emmerson for his detailed and perceptive
comments, Michael Wenthe for his scrupulous
inspection of the last but one version, and Annabel Patterson
for her editorial brutality.
1 Cited by Norman Malcolm, Ludwig Wittgenstein: A Memoir,
2nd ed. (Oxford, 1984), p. 100.
Wittgenstein explained Freud's power in terms of the modern
commitment to the idea that the inner
self has uncharted depths: the "peculiar charm" of
psychoanalytic explanations, he said, derives from
"the idea of an underworld, a secret cellar" (Lectures and
Conversations on Aesthetics, Psychology
and Religious Belief, ed. Cyril Barrett [Berkeley, Calif., 1966],
p. 25).
Speculum 76 (2001) 638
This content downloaded from 128.228.0.65 on Wed, 15 May
2019 02:22:27 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Chaucer's Pardoner on the Couch
dations on which it rests and meet, with as full and receptive an
attitude as pos-
sible, the objections to which it is susceptible. I have tried
neither to travesty the
assumptions I question nor to score rhetorical points. I have
read as widely as I
could in the relevant material and seek here to present the
results in a straight-
forward manner, without misrepresentation. If this essay is to
serve as a way of
opening a discussion on the interpretive appropriateness of
psychoanalysis-a
conversation that is clearly long overdue-then one hopes that
those who disagree
with its conclusions will do the same.
1. THE FREUDIAN CHARM
We start our intellectual lives under the spell. Our vernacular
culture is saturated
with terms and concepts derived from psychoanalytic theory:
repression, resis-
tance, the unconscious, the anal personality, threatened
masculinity and castration
fear, a belief that our every activity is invested with libido, and
above all a suspicion
that everything means something other, and usually something
darker, than it
seems-these terms and concepts, and the way of thinking they
enable and en-
courage, are a central part of the shared habits of thought by
which we learn, for
good or ill, to make sense of our lives. More tangibly, our
society devotes sub-
stantial resources to mental health workers who deploy
technologies of the self
that derive ultimately if not directly from the Freudian system.
Quite apart from
the vast number of more or less professional therapists who
service what has been
called "the identity market,"2 there are school counselors,
penologists, expert wit-
nesses, social workers, and even (if they are not careful)
university professors who
dispense more or less expert advice that bears a real, if usually
ill-defined, relation
to Freudian theory. If the twentieth century has witnessed what
Philip Rieff has
called "the emergence of psychological man," we must
remember that we are not
merely observers of that momentous event but its effect.3 We
are psychological
men and women, shaped by structures of thought and feeling
that derive directly
from the work of Freud and his disciples.
But even while agreeing with the statement that the invention
and spread of
Freudian theory represent "the attainment of a new degree of
consciousness in
Western civilization," one may still ask if it is a higher form of
consciousness and,
in particular applications, whether it is a help or hindrance to
thought.4 There are,
to be sure, very good reasons for the modern triumph of
psychoanalytic modes of
thought and interpretation. For one thing, Freudianism
functioned for the first
half of the twentieth century as a liberatory alternative to far
less humane modes
of explaining human actions, especially geneticism (and its
deadly offspring, eu-
genics) and behaviorism. Particularly important in this regard
is the psychoana-
2 Peter L. Berger, "Towards a Sociological Understanding of
Psychoanalysis," Social Research 32
(1965), 26-41, at p. 37.
3 Philip Rieff, Freud: The Mind of the Moralist (Garden City,
N.Y., 1961), pp. 361-92.
4 Steven Marcus, Freud and the Culture of Psychoanalysis:
Studies in the Transition from Victorian
Humanism to Modernity (Boston, 1984), p. 7. For a similar,
highly influential account of Freudianism
as modernity, see Lionel Trilling, "Freud: Within and beyond
Culture," a lecture delivered to the New
York Psychoanalytic Institute in 1955 and printed in Beyond
Culture (New York, 1965), pp. 89-118.
639
This content downloaded from 128.228.0.65 on Wed, 15 May
2019 02:22:27 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Chaucer's Pardoner on the Couch
lytic refusal to pass moral judgment on almost all forms of
behavior, especially
sexual. As Freud said more than once, psychoanalysis has no
"concern whatsoever
with judgments of value."5 To be against psychoanalysis was,
from the period of
1920 to 1960 or so, to be against reforms in child rearing,
education, the treatment
of sexual minorities, and many other clearly progressive
causes.6 Another benign
aspect of Freudian psychologism has been its ability to address
(if not necessarily
to remedy) aspects of modern life-especially familial and other
interpersonal
relationships-that the dominant individualism and privatism of
modern urban
life, in which the self is experienced as threatened and fragile,
have made central
to a sense of well-being. Thus it is that "twentieth-century
societies have produced
'psychology' as a specialized form of knowledge and set of
techniques."7 And as
many have said, psychoanalysis has produced a humanistic
substitute for religion
in an increasingly secular culture. As Wittgenstein recognized,
Freud restored to
modernity some of the mystery that the disenchantments of
rationality were
threatening to strip away forever. In a world in which
everything is potentially
knowable to instrumental reason, psychoanalysis can satisfy a
Romantic desire
for a realm of deep meaning that is unknown and perhaps even
unknowable.
Whether it can now be seen to have achieved this without
imposing a new creed,
immune to empirical critique, is part of my concern.
If psychoanalysis can thus rightly be seen, in retrospect, as part
of the Enlight-
enment project of modernity, we are now in a position to assess
its claim to sci-
entific rationality and the ratification of that claim by its
inclusion within the
professional citadel of medicine.8 Freud always thought of
himself as a scientist
and of psychoanalysis as an empirical science. "I take no pride
in having avoided
speculation," he said, because "the material for my hypotheses
was collected by
the most extensive and laborious series of observations."9 He
speaks often of the
5 Cited by Philip Rieff, who rightly says that "psychoanalysis
is the first great system of therapy to
divorce itself from some moral aim or doctrine; that suggests
its historic importance" (Freud: The
Mind of the Moralist, p. 368). As Freud himself said, "Psycho-
analysis finds no occasion for conceal-
ments and hints, it does not think it necessary to be ashamed of
dealing with this important material,
it believes it is right and proper to call everything by its correct
name" (Introductory Lectures on
Psycho-Analysis [1915-16], in Standard Edition of the
Complete Psychological Works of Sigmund
Freud, 24 vols., trans. James Strachey et al. [London, 1953-74],
15:154). All subsequent references
are to this edition, abbreviated SE.
6 See Nathan G. Hale, Jr., The Rise and Crisis of
Psychoanalysis in America, 2: Freud and the
Americans, 1917-1985 (New York, 1995). Despite its
inflammatory and misleading title, Edwin Fuller
Torrey, Freudian Fraud: The Malignant Effect of Freud's
Theory on American Thought and Culture
(New York, 1992), provides a useful history of the
progressiveness of Freudian thought with a wealth
of specific examples, especially Margaret Mead and Benjamin
Spock.
7 Barry Richards, Images of Freud: Cultural Responses to
Psychoanalysis (London, 1989), p. 23.
8 For the combination of Romantic and Enlightenment features
in Freud's thought, see Harry Tros-
man, "Freud's Cultural Background," in John E. Gedo and
George H. Pollock, eds., Freud: The Fusion
of Science and Humanism (New York, 1976), pp. 46-70.
Psychoanalysis is both deterministic and
liberating: deterministic (in its Romantic mode) in that it
insists that all behaviors are caused by hidden,
powerful forces, liberating (in its Enlightenment mode) in
arguing that we can come to understand
and control those determining forces: see Richard Stevens,
Freud and Psychoanalysis: An Exposition
and Appraisal (New York, 1983), pp. 135-37.
9 "Fragment of an Analysis of a Case of Hysteria" (1905), SE
7:113. See also, for example, Intro-
ductory Lectures on Psycho-Analysis (1916-17), SE 16:244-45.
640
This content downloaded from 128.228.0.65 on Wed, 15 May
2019 02:22:27 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Chaucer's Pardoner on the Couch
"data" and "factual evidence" upon which he has based his
explanations and
asserts throughout his work that "the intellect and the mind are
objects for sci-
entific research in exactly the same way as any non-human
things."10
But in recent decades psychoanalysis as a scientifically reliable
system of thought
has lost much of its intellectual status, and in the second part
of this essay I will
lay out the main arguments for its demise. This doubt has
spread even to the
popular press. The cover story of the November 29, 1993, issue
of Time magazine
was entitled "Is Freud Dead?" and the June 15, 1998, issue of
Der Spiegel-its
cover story entitled "Die Psycho Falle"-features a visual lineup
of similar mag-
azine covers from the United States, France, and Germany.11
The most persistent
attempt to counter this widespread disillusionment is to argue
that Freud's claims
to the scientific status of his theories stemmed from what Paul
Ricoeur has called
his "scientistic self-misunderstanding," and that psychoanalysis
should therefore
be understood not as an empirical science but simply as a
hermeneutic, a method
of interpretation.12 But such a tactic has to accept (as does
Ricoeur) the fact that
because "psychoanalysis is itself a work of speech with the
patient," then the most
it needs to produce is a narrative that the patient finds
acceptable, whether it is
accurate or not.13 The hermeneutic rescue of psychoanalysis,
in other words, de-
nies Freud his claim to have discovered the causes of human
behavior and settles
for meanings "discovered" by the analyst: in the attempt to
rescue psychoanalysis
as a therapy, it destroys it as a general theory of human
behavior. The fact is, if
psychoanalysis is to provide a reliable paradigm for
understanding human behav-
ior-especially premodern behavior, and all the more the
behavior of characters
created by premodern writers-then it must not be denied its
claim to scientific
truth. As Freud himself said, "I have always felt it as a gross
injustice that people
have refused to treat psycho-analysis like any other science."14
10 New Introductory Lectures on Psycho-Analysis (1933), SE
22:159. Freud continues with an ar-
gument that practitioners of psychoanalytic criticism might
find unpalatable: "It is not permissible to
declare that science is one field of human mental activity and
that religion and philosophy are others,
at least equal in value, and that science has no business to
interfere with the other two. ... A view of
this kind is regarded as particularly superior, tolerant, broad-
minded and free from illiberal prejudices.
Unfortunately it is not tenable.... It is simply a fact that the
truth cannot be tolerant" (p. 160).
1 Der Spiegel 25 (1998), 199.
12 Paul Ricoeur, Freud and Philosophy: An Essay on
Interpretation, trans. Denis Savage (New Haven,
Conn., 1970).
13 The citation from Ricoeur is from Freud and Philosophy, p.
369. The hermeneutic interpretations
of Ricoeur and Jiirgen Habermas are subjected to a withering
analysis by Adolf Griinbaum, The
Foundations of Psychoanalysis: A Philosophical Critique
(Berkeley, Calif., 1984), pp. 1-94. See also
the comments by the psychoanalyst Robert R. Holt, Freud
Reappraised: A Fresh Look at Psychoan-
alytic Theory (New York, 1989), p. 337, and by the textual
critic Sebastiano Timpanaro, The Freudian
Slip: Psychoanalysis and Textual Criticism, trans. Kate Soper
(London, 1976). For Timpanaro, the
hermeneutic rescue of Freud manages only to transform
"psychoanalysis into a pastiche of Husserl or
Heidegger, orienting it towards a mysticism that evokes Jung
much more than Freud" (p. 17). Tim-
panaro later characterizes Ricoeur's version of Freud as "a
strange brew of Freudianism and religion,
in which the more imbued with mystery an interpretation, the
better it pleases" (p. 181)-a version
of Wittgenstein's point (n. 1, above).
14 An Autobiographical Study (1925), SE 20:58. The other way
of protecting Freudianism from its
own claims is to declare that the practices and results of
empirical science are no longer operative in
the brave new world of postmodernism: see Paul Robinson,
Freud and His Critics (Berkeley, Calif.,
641
This content downloaded from 128.228.0.65 on Wed, 15 May
2019 02:22:27 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Chaucer's Pardoner on the Couch
Moreover, even the hermeneutic model-which is now
therapeutically domi-
nant-requires a dialogue between analyst and patient in which
the patient's con-
tribution is acknowledged as essential. As the object-relations
analyst Heinz Kohut
has said, "If there is one lesson that I have learned during my
life as an analyst,
it is the lesson that what my patients tell me is likely to be
true-that many times
when I believed that I was right and my patients were wrong, it
turned out, though
often only after a prolonged search, that my rightness was
superficial whereas
their rightness was profound."15 But while this may be true for
real people in
contemporary therapy, such a dialogue is impossible with
persons, either real or
fictional, who can only give evidence of their psyches in fixed
texts. George Pig-
man, who is both a literary critic and a practicing analyst, has
pointed out that
"patients can object to interpretations and thereby further
understanding; texts
and documents cannot. [As used by literary critics], applied
psychoanalysis is
therefore barred from the feature of the psychoanalytic process
which gives the
greatest confidence in the validity of interpretations and
reconstructions."16
Yet despite the adjustments within the therapeutic community,
the now large
literature criticizing the truth claims of Freud and his
followers, and the reasonably
well informed discussions in the popular press, the news of the
demise of psycho-
analysis as a reliable mode of inquiry seems not to have
reached the small circle
of academic literary and cultural criticism. Here psychoanalysis
in its various
guises-whether as orthodox Freudianism or in Lacanian or post-
Lacanian revi-
sionary forms-remains not just a powerful influence but a
paradigm for inter-
pretation and a largely unquestioned source of authority.
According to a survey
done in 1977-78 of the most heavily cited twentieth-century
authors in the arts
and humanities, Freud was by far the most common name to
appear.17 Over
twenty years later the situation has not changed: in the decade
of the 1990s, at
least 921 books, and who knows how many articles, have been
published that
deal explicitly and centrally with psychoanalysis and literature,
to say nothing of
1993), and Marcus R. Bowman, "On the Idea of Natural
Science as a Resistance to Psychoanalysis,"
Psychoanalysis and Contemporary Thought 19 (1996), 371-402.
Both these authors use the familiar
psychoanalytic strategy of psychoanalyzing their opponents,
while the topic at issue is defended not
by appeals to evidence but by the assumption that it is true. As
Karl Kraus said as long ago as 1913
in exasperation with his psychoanalytically besotted friends,
"If I tell them they can kiss my ass, I must
have an anal predilection.... They have caught me!" (cited and
translated by Jacques Bouveresse,
Wittgenstein Reads Freud: The Myth of the Unconscious, trans.
Carol Cosman [Princeton, N.J., 1995],
p. 16).
15 Heinz Kohut, How Does Analysis Cure? (Chicago, 1984),
pp. 93-94; cited by G. W. Pigman III,
"Applied Psychoanalysis Today," Criticism 34 (1992), 299-315,
at p. 308.
16 Ibid., p. 309. For similar demurrals, see Gail S. Reed,
"Psychoanalysis, Psychoanalysis Appropri-
ated, Psychoanalysis Applied," Psychoanalytic Quarterly 54
(1985), 234-69, and Peter Lamarque,
"On the Irrelevance of Psychoanalysis to Literary Criticism," in
Peter Clark and Crispin Wright, eds.,
Mind, Psychoanalysis and Science (Oxford, 1988), pp. 257-73.
17 Allan Megill, "The Reception of Foucault by Historians,"
Journal of the History of Ideas 48
(1987), 117-41, at pp. 139-40. Freud was cited 966 times, with
the next name being that of Roland
Barthes, cited 678 times. It should be pointed out that Lenin
led the list with 1,737 citations; but if
Soviet journals were excluded, his name virtually disappeared.
Jung's name appeared 338 times, and
Lacan's 210.
642
This content downloaded from 128.228.0.65 on Wed, 15 May
2019 02:22:27 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Chaucer's Pardoner on the Couch
all the critical writing in which psychoanalytic categories
remain implicit and
therefore invisible to search engines.18
It might be thought that medieval studies, with its traditional
commitment to
empiricist methodologies and its mistrust of explicitly
nonhistoricist interpretive
paradigms, would be resistant to this trend. But medieval
literary critics have long
been anxious not to be perceived as intellectually backward,
and the most obvious
way to avoid that stigma is to display familiarity with some
form of what the
literary academy currently designates as theory. In a recent
review article Louise
Fradenburg announces that "psychoanalysis is simply in
medieval studies now"
and provides a bibliography that includes some 45 items that
explicitly depend
upon psychoanalytic theories.19 One could easily add to the
list.20 There are few
critics, especially those dealing explicitly with questions of
gender and sexuality,
who do not at least implicitly accept the Freudian account of
sexual formation.
I have now turned, obviously, to a field-specific interrogation
of Freudianism-
very field-specific, since I do not address the use of Freudian
theory in literary
studies in general but rather as a fairly recent development
within medieval studies.
In literary studies generally, or in literary theory, there has
been more interest,
perhaps, in psychoanalysis as a kind of hermeneutics, as a
model for doing inter-
pretation rather than as a model of behavior. But in medieval
studies there has
been a rush backwards, as it were, to Freud's beliefs about
human sexuality and
its dominance as a force in character formation and pathology.
An example from
Chaucer studies, taken almost at random, is the discussion of
the Miller's Tale by
Elaine Tuttle Hansen, who argues that the tale commodifies
women, expresses a
"horror" of their sexuality, and bespeaks a profound if
unrecognized homoso-
ciality/homosexuality.21 The presuppositions that enable this
condemnatory read-
ing derive ultimately, if unwittingly, from Freud. According to
Hansen, grabbing
18 This figure was arrived at through a keyword search of the
database of the WorldCat (http://
newfirstsearch.oclc.org).
19 "Analytical Survey 2: We Are Not Alone: Psychoanalytic
Medievalism," New Medieval Litera-
tures 2 (1998), 249-76.
20 In addition to the titles provided by Fradenburg, a sample of
recent books that apply psychoan-
alytic categories of interpretation to cultural materials includes
Jane Chance, ed., Gender and Text in
the Later Middle Ages (Gainesville, Fla., 1996); E. Jane Burns,
Bodytalk: When Women Speak in Old
French Literature (Philadelphia, 1993); Gregory B. Stone, The
Death of the Troubadour: The Late
Medieval Resistance to the Renaissance (Philadelphia, 1994);
Karma Lochrie, Peggy McCracken, and
James A. Schultz, eds., Constructing Medieval Sexuality,
Medieval Cultures 11 (Minneapolis, 1997);
Catherine S. Cox, Gender and Language in Chaucer
(Gainesville, Fla., 1997); Karma Lochrie, Covert
Operations: The Medieval Uses of Secrecy (Philadelphia,
1999); Clare A. Lees, ed., Medieval Mascu-
linities: Regarding Men in the Middle Ages, Medieval Cultures
7 (Minneapolis, 1994); Jeffrey Jerome
Cohen and Bonnie Wheeler, eds., Becoming Male in the Middle
Ages, Garland Reference Library of
the Humanities 2066, New Middle Ages 4 (New York, 1997);
John Carmi Parsons and Bonnie Wheeler,
eds., Medieval Mothering, Garland Reference Library of the
Humanities 1979, New Middle Ages 3
(New York, 1996), pp. 63-75, 183-99; Kathleen Biddick, The
Shock of Medievalism (Durham, N.C.,
1998); Carolyn Dinshaw, Getting Medieval: Sexualities and
Communities, Pre- and Postmodern (Dur-
ham, N.C., 1999); Jeffrey Jerome Cohen, Of Giants: Sex,
Monsters, and the Middle Ages, Medieval
Cultures 17 (Minneapolis, 1999); Dyan Elliott, Fallen Bodies:
Pollution, Sexuality, and Demonology
in the Middle Ages (Philadelphia, 1999); and Paul Strohm,
England's Empty Throne: Usurpation and
the Language of Legitimation, 1399-1422 (New Haven, Conn.,
1998).
21 Elaine Tuttle Hansen, Chaucer and the Fictions of Gender
(Berkeley, Calif., 1992), pp. 223-36.
643
This content downloaded from 128.228.0.65 on Wed, 15 May
2019 02:22:27 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
644 Chaucer's Pardoner on the Couch
the red-hot iron from the forge is Absolon's attempt to reassert
his masculinity,
and his desire to hurt Alison implies a connection among
homosexuality, homo-
phobia, and misogyny. But this reasonable explanation of a
fabliau's typically
coarse revenge is expressed as follows: "the boy-child
[Absolon] has in this case
felt, although not seen, the lack that seems to mark the place of
women's sexual
organs, and his response indicates both guilt and fear for his
own as yet unproven
difference and dominance, his phallus."22 This reading
depends, then, upon
Freud's theory that oedipalized men are by definition appalled
by female sexuality.
Thus for Hansen the Miller's Tale "effects the conventional
association or confla-
tion of (female) genital and anal functions, of women's sex (or
sex with a woman)
and dirt, decay, and dissolution."23
My point here is to suggest that this and similar readings of
medieval texts,
while they may be invigoratingly consistent with the political
temper of the times,
may also be intellectually misleading-for at least three reasons.
First, they ignore
the now ubiquitous skepticism about the truth claims of the
very theories they
take as presuppositions. Second, they extend what is now
accepted as a dialogic
method of therapy to a one-way analysis of fictional characters
who must stand
mute before their analyst. And third, they rise to the defense of
their method by
attacking another method of understanding literary texts from
the past-histor-
icism.24 What they actually attack, however, is a parodic
version of historicism, a
22 Ibid., p. 230.
23 Ibid., p. 227; italics added. A similar reading of the Miller's
Tale is offered by Karma Lochrie,
"Women's 'Pryvetees' and Fabliau Politics in the Miller's Tale,"
Exemplaria 6 (1994), 287-304. This
argument depends in the first instance upon Gayle Rubin's
classic essay, "The Traffic in Women: Notes
on the 'Political Economy' of Sex," in Rayna R. Reiter, ed.,
Toward an Anthropology of Women (New
York, 1975), pp. 157-210. Rubin reinterprets Levi-Strauss's
analysis of kinship in terms of the Freud-
ian account of "the Oedipal complex [as] a machine which
fashions the appropriate forms of sexual
individuals" (Rubin, p. 189). Both Lochrie and Hansen thus
rely on two assumptions: that Freud's
account of the creation of sexual identity by means of the
Oedipus complex is true; and that, in Rubin's
words, "the paleolithic relations of sexuality are still with us"
(p. 191)-i.e., that the political economy
of the sex/gender system that Rubin derives from Freud is a
universal constituent of human societies,
be it late-medieval England or the contemporary United States.
24 Many people have offered workable definitions of historicist
methodology; my own attempt may
be found in Negotiating the Past: The Historical Understanding
of Medieval Literature (Madison,
Wis., 1987), pp. 3-74. An excellent summary of recent work,
with examples, may be found in Kiernan
Ryan, ed., New Historicism and Cultural Materialism: A
Reader (London, 1996); see especially pp.
43-44. A classic defense of psychoanalytic literary criticism
can be found in Peter Brooks, "The Idea
of a Psychoanalytic Literary Criticism," in Shlomith Rimmon-
Kenan, ed., Discourse in Psychoanalysis
and Literature, University Paperbacks 960 (London, 1987), pp.
1-18, and Psychoanalysis and Sto-
rytelling, Bucknell Lectures in Literary Theory 10 (Oxford,
1994). Brooks acknowledges that any
psychoanalytic criticism worthy of the name must take the
Freudian account of the mind as a privileged
model that reveals the central truth of human behavior. This
means, in Brooks's words, accepting "the
psychoanalytic view of humans as radically determined by
sexuality.... Human desire emerges subject
to the 'laws' dictated by the castration complex and the Oedipal
triangle-emerges, that is, as desire
inhabited by loss and prohibition" (Psychoanalysis and
Storytelling, p. 25). In "'Be Not Far from Me':
Psychoanalysis, Medieval Studies and the Subject of Religion,"
Exemplaria 7 (1995), 41-54, Louise
O. Fradenburg defends the relevance of psychoanalysis to
medieval studies by asserting that "psycho-
analysis takes us to the heart of our histories of loss and desire,
to the heart of the history of culture,
or 'civilization,' as a history of the production and regulation of
pleasure and loss" (p. 44)-a statement
that is another version of Brooks's account. But neither
Fradenburg nor Brooks confronts the critiques
This content downloaded from 128.228.0.65 on Wed, 15 May
2019 02:22:27 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Chaucer's Pardoner on the Couch 645
naive positivism that believes in the absolute "alterity" of the
past. Such a histor-
icism has not been thought possible since at least Nietzsche,
Dilthey, and Weber,
let alone Foucault, Jameson, and E. P. Thompson.25 Constantly
to invoke D. W.
Robertson and a few of his students as proof of the
benightedness of medieval
historicism is misleading in a double sense: it is blind to the
very different kinds
of historicism that medieval literary scholars now practice, and
it dismisses the
very real contribution to our understanding of the Middle Ages
that Robertson
made, since he taught us much about the ubiquity of the
medieval tradition of
exegetical reading.
Another line of defense-as-attack is to psychoanalyze
historicists as reverent if
mournful seekers after a hopelessly lost past, a strategy that
reduces the many
different motives that inspire historical scholarship to
compensation for a psycho-
analytically posited "lack."26 This move endows the analyst
with the assurance
that she understands others better than they can understand
themselves. The
charge, however, not only begs the question but depends on an
assumed identity
of memory and history. As a psychic phenomenon, memory is a
mental function
confined to personal experience; as a disciplinary practice,
history is an episte-
mological effort directed toward the experience of others, all of
whom are (for
the medievalist) dead. We cannot now remember the medieval
past but only learn
about it. And even as a collective phenomenon, memory both
extends back only
a short way into the past and has to do, as is well illustrated by
the monumental
of psychoanalytic theory that have appeared over the last
twenty-five years. A defense of psychoanalysis
as an aid to historical understanding is provided by Peter Gay,
Freud for Historians (New York, 1985),
but Gay does little to counter the arguments of David E.
Stannard, Shrinking History: On Freud and
the Failure of Psychohistory (New York, 1980). For a thorough
critique of Gay's version of Freud that
is itself sympathetic to psychoanalysis, see John E. Toews,
"Historicizing Psychoanalysis: Freud in His
Time and for Our Time," Journal of Modern History 63 (1991),
504-45.
25 This accusation has been most persistently made by Louise
Fradenburg, from her initial creation
of the straw man of historicist backwardness in "Criticism,
Anti-Semitism, and the Prioress's Tale,"
Exemplaria 1 (1989), 69-115, through to her most recent work
in "We Are Not Alone: Psychoanalytic
Medievalism." There she posits an opposition between those
unnamed scholars who "still insist on
the radical alterity of the past, the incommunication of
epistemes, and the uselessness of generalizing
about the 'local' and the 'specific"' and the psychoanalytic
medievalists who avoid those errors and
thus possess "a better understanding of the ethical and political
commitments of medievalist practice"
(pp. 262-63, my italics).
26 See again Fradenburg, "Criticism, Anti-Semitism, and the
Prioress's Tale," and her "Be Not Far
from Me"; Gayle Margherita, The Romance of Origins:
Language and Sexual Difference in Middle
English Literature (Philadelphia, 1994), pp. 82-88, 100-107;
and Biddick's Shock of Medievalism,
which founds itself on Fradenburg's claims. Even Peter Gay
admits that "the days are gone when the
followers of Freud can discredit rational criticism by
psychoanalyzing the critic" (Freud for Historians,
p. 7). Yet on the very next page he refers to historians who
reject psychoanalytic methods as "anxious
and therefore hostile" (p. 8) and later asserts that "the
unflagging ardor of the counterattacks is
therefore a symptom rather than a necessary response" (p. 17).
The same tactic appears in Jonathan
Lear, Open Minded: Working Out the Logic of the Soul
(Cambridge, Mass., 1998), pp. 16-32. As
Freud himself said, "One of the first applications of psycho-
analysis was to teach us to understand the
opposition offered to us by our contemporaries because we
practised psycho-analysis" (New Intro-
ductory Lectures, SE 22:145).
This content downloaded from 128.228.0.65 on Wed, 15 May
2019 02:22:27 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Chaucer's Pardoner on the Couch
project led by Pierre Nora, primarily with the definition of the
modern nation.27
As for the recent argument that historicism is doomed to "the
task of replicating,
however hopelessly, medieval culture's self-understandings,"
while psychoanaly-
sis, from a superior posture, explores "the ways in which
medieval culture might
have misunderstood itself," one must ask how to recognize a
misunderstanding
without already knowing what correct understanding might
be.28 Like old-fash-
ioned Marxism, psychoanalysis wants to believe that it has a
pipeline to the truth,
the only difference being that the Marxist's long-abandoned
"false consciousness"
is here replaced by the psychoanalyst's gentler
"misunderstanding" or (Zizek's use
of Lacan's term) "misrecognition."29
To mention Slavoj Zizek will alert my readers to the fact that
what follows-a
summary of the arguments against psychoanalysis both as
method and as expla-
nation-is focused almost exclusively on Freud. It could be
objected that I am
aiming at the wrong target because the current psychoanalytic
theory of choice is
that propounded by Jacques Lacan or what is termed "post-
Lacanian psycho-
analysis," particularly as proposed by Ziiek. But Lacan rightly
insisted that his
entire project was a "return to Freud," and as Malcolm Bowie
has said, in what
is probably the best guide to this obscurantist writer, Lacan's
"loyalty to Freud is
intense, and the originality he seeks is that of an inspired and
devoted reader, one
who can think fruitfully only from inside someone else's
text."30 This is not to say
that Lacan's relation to Freud is not complex and shifting, nor
that he does not
finally differ from Freud in ways important to psychoanalytic
theory, perhaps most
significantly in locating within the ego itself a powerful
irrationality-he refers to
it at one point as an "organization of the passions"31-and in his
promotion of
language as an impersonal force that constructs subjectivity.
But the entire Lacan-
ian project is located within the context of the Freudian model
of the formation
of the personality. Lacan's four fundamental concepts of
psychoanalysis are the
unconscious, repetition, transference, and the drive;
subjectivity is formed through
infantile experience; and the lack that constitutes desire is a
function of the fear
of castration created by the Name of the Father. Like Freud,
Lacan presented his
work as at once scientific (despite his disdain for evidence) and
universalist. Ad-
mittedly, given his replacement of Freud's id, ego, and
superego with his ontolog-
27 Pierre Nora, ed., Les lieux de memoire, 3 vols. in 7 (Paris,
1984-92). There are clear if unremarked
affinities between Fradenburg's claims and Nora's project, with
its emphasis on the sadness of the
postmodern that has lost a living connection to the past and its
promotion of the postmodern historian
who both "meditate[s]" on his "personal liaison" with the past
and makes it "not the obstacle, but
the means of his understanding" (cited by Jeremy D. Popkin,
"Historians on the Autobiographical
Frontier," American Historical Review 104 [1999], 725-48, at
p. 731). But both Fradenburg and
Nora are stating positions that are hardly postmodern: they
have been familiar since at least the
Romantic historiography of Michelet and the historical
hermeneutics of Dilthey.
28 "Be Not Far from Me," pp. 45, 47.
29 Slavoj Ziiek, The Sublime Object of Ideology (London,
1989), pp. 55-84.
30 Malcolm Bowie, Lacan (Cambridge, Mass., 1991), p. 7. For
other accounts of Lacan's theories
within their Freudian framework, see Jean Laplanche and Jean-
Bertrand Pontalis, The Language of
Psycho-analysis, trans. Donald Nicholson-Smith (New York,
1973), and Samuel Weber, Return to
Freud: Jacques Lacan's Dislocation of Psychoanalysis, trans.
Michael Levine, Literature, Culture, The-
ory 1 (Cambridge, Eng., 1991).
31 Jacques Lacan, Ecrits: A Selection, trans. Alan Sheridan
(New York, 1977), p. 19.
646
This content downloaded from 128.228.0.65 on Wed, 15 May
2019 02:22:27 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Chaucer's Pardoner on the Couch
ical triad of the Imaginary, Symbolic, and Real, Lacan is more
truly a metaphy-
sician (or theologian) than a psychologist. But if the Freudian
foundations on
which his work rests are unreliable, then his own enterprise
(however we define
it) can hardly stand as an accurate account of human
behavior.32 As for Zizek, his
neo-Lacanian psychoanalysis of culture has a political and
sociological interest
that is lacking in Lacan himself. But his unqualified
commitment to Lacanian
categories renders his work equally dependent-at one remove-
on Freud.33 It is
with Freud that psychoanalysis begins and ends (as Freud
himself rightly predicted
it always would), and it is thus with Freud that the literary
critic must come to
terms. In any case, as the psychoanalyst Robert Holt has said,
"When the foun-
dations of our house are tottering, it makes no sense to argue
about rival designs
for new wallpaper."34
2. THE CASE AGAINST PSYCHOANALYSIS
For the last quarter of a century much of Freud's work, and
hence psychoan-
alytic theory as a whole (as opposed to the many varieties of
psychotherapy now
on offer), has been subject to a devastating critique. According
to Frederick Crews,
the one anti-Freudian known at least by reputation to literary
scholars, "there is
literally nothing to be said, scientifically or therapeutically, to
the advantage of
the entire Freudian system or any of its component dogmas."35
Those are strong
words, but they are supported by a substantial and growing
body of work that
has demolished, both systematically and in detail, the
theoretical and institutional
house that Freud built. This work can no longer be ignored or
evaded by literary
critics.36
32 Criticisms of Lacan as severe as those leveled against Freud
are not far to seek: see, for instance,
FranSois Roustang, The Lacanian Delusion, trans. Greg Sims
(New York, 1990); Luc Ferry and Alain
Renaut, French Philosophy of the Sixties: An Essay on
Antihumanism, trans. Mary H. S. Cattani
(Amherst, Mass., 1990), pp. 185-207; and an article posted on
the Web by Norman N. Holland,
"The Trouble(s) with Lacan" (1998), at
http://web.clas.ufl.edu/users/nnh/lacan.htm.
33 Ziiek's Lacanian commitments are everywhere visible in his
work, but perhaps nowhere more
explicitly than in the essay "Fetishism and Its Vicissitudes," in
The Plague of Fantasies (London, 1997),
pp. 86-126.
34 Freud Reappraised, p. 338.
35 Frederick Crews, "The Verdict on Freud," Psychological
Science 7 (1996), 63-68, at p. 63; Crews
is reviewing Malcolm Macmillan, Freud Evaluated: The
Completed Arc (Amsterdam, 1991). Crews's
own contributions to this critique may be found in Skeptical
Engagements (New York, 1986);
Crews et al., The Memory Wars: Freud's Legacy in Dispute
(New York, 1995); and Crews, ed., Unau-
thorized Freud: Doubters Confront a Legend (New York, 1998).
36 Many of the most troubling doubts about psychoanalysis are
expressed by psychoanalysts them-
selves. For example, Donald P. Spence begins his book The
Rhetorical Voice of Psychoanalysis: Dis-
placement of Evidence by Theory (Cambridge, Mass., 1994),
with the following statement: "As psy-
choanalysis prepares to enter its second century, we are force d
to realize that it is not much closer to
being a science than it was when Freud first invented the
discipline.... Rather than representing an
earnest and possibly fallible attempt to tell a true story about
the world, psychoanalytic theory may
function much more as a shared fantasy that binds its followers
in a common belief system and protects
them from uncertainty and doubt" (pp. 1, 4-5). For other
accounts of the current state of psycho-
analysis by practicing analysts, see Marshall Edelson,
Psychoanalysis: A Theory in Crisis (Chicago,
1988); Holt, Freud Reappraised; and Paul Kline, Psychology
and Freudian Theory: An Introduction
(London, 1984).
647
This content downloaded from 128.228.0.65 on Wed, 15 May
2019 02:22:27 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Chaucer's Pardoner on the Couch
To begin with, psychoanalytic theory makes universalist and
absolutist claims
that call for a large body of evidentiary support that it has
never been able to
provide. Freud insisted that all neuroses are caused by sexual
dysfunctions that
originate in infancy, and his emphasis upon both the primacy of
early childhood
and the sexual nature of identity formation remains central to
psychoanalytic
thinking. As he said in The Interpretation of Dreams (1900),
"The theory of the
psychoneuroses asserts as an indisputable and invariable fact
that only sexual
wishful impulses from infancy . . . furnish the motive force for
the formation of
psycho-neurotic symptoms of every kind."37 Similarly, Freud
used his (admittedly
failed) analysis of Dora to claim that "sexuality . . . provides
the motive power
for every single symptom, and for every single manifestation of
a symptom. The
symptoms of the disease are nothing else than the patient's
sexual activity.... I
can only repeat over and over again-for I never find it
otherwise-that sexuality
is the key to the problem of the psychoneuroses and of the
neuroses in general."38
Again, Freud repeatedly insisted that the Oedipus complex is a
universal phenom-
enon: "Every new arrival on this planet is faced by the task of
mastering the
Oedipus complex; anyone who fails to do so falls a victim to
neurosis. With the
progress of psycho-analytic studies the importance of the
Oedipus complex has
become more and more clearly evident; its recognition has
become the shibboleth
that distinguishes the adherents of psycho-analysis from its
opponents."39 And for
Freud the Oedipus complex entailed as well the inevitability of
the castration
complex, a condition whose resolution determines gender
identity.40
Freud actually went so far as to claim that the central events of
infantile expe-
rience were already present in the little boy as an ancestral
inheritance, so he did
not need to experience them at all for them to have their effect
upon him: "These
scenes of observing parental intercourse, of being seduced in
childhood, and of
being threatened with castration are unquestionably an
inherited endowment, a
phylogenetic heritage.... A child catches hold of this
phylogenetic experience
where his own experience fails him. He fills in the gaps in
individual truth with
37 SE 5:605-6; my italics.
38 "A Case of Hysteria," SE 7:114-15; the italics in the phrase
"the patient's sexual activity" are
Freud's, while the others are mine.
39 "Three Essays on the Theory of Sexuality" (1905), SE 7:226
n (a footnote added in 1920; my
italics). Freud concluded Totem and Taboo (1913) by
"insist[ing] that ... the beginnings of religion,
morals, society and art converge in the Oedipus complex" (SE
13:156). For discussions of the way in
which post-Freudian psychoanalysis has revised and rerevised
(but never discarded) the theory of the
Oedipus complex, see Bennett Simon, "Is the Oedipus Complex
Still the Cornerstone of Psychoanal-
ysis? Three Obstacles to Answering the Question," Journal of
the American Psychoanalytic Associa-
tion 39 (1991), 641-68, and Bennett Simon, "'Incest-See under
Oedipus Complex': The History of
an Error in Psychoanalysis," Journal of the American
Psychoanalytic Association 40 (1992), 955-88.
In The Sublime Object of Ideology Zizek says: "Let us take one
of the commonplaces of the Marxist-
feminist criticism of psychoanalysis, the idea that its insistence
on the crucial role of the Oedipus
complex and the nuclear-family triangle transforms a
historically conditioned form of patriarchal
family into a feature of the universal human condition: is not
this effort to historicize the family triangle
precisely an attempt to elude the 'hard kernel' which announces
itself through the 'patriarchal family'-
the Real of the Law, the rock of castration?" (p. 50; italics in
original).
40 See SE 20:38 and Allen Esterson, Seductive Mirage: An
Exploration of the Work of Sigmund
Freud (Chicago, 1993), p. 137.
648
This content downloaded from 128.228.0.65 on Wed, 15 May
2019 02:22:27 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Chaucer's Pardoner on the Couch
prehistoric truth; he replaces occurrences in his own life by
occurrences in the life
of his ancestors .... Wherever experiences fail to fit in with the
hereditary schema,
they become remodelled in the imagination.... We are often
able to see the
schema triumphing over the experience of the individual."41
Moreover, Freud
claimed that the mind never forgot any experience, that
everything was recover-
able: "All of the essentials are preserved; even things that seem
completely for-
gotten are present somehow and somewhere.... It depends only
upon analytic
technique whether we shall succeed in bringing what is
concealed completely to
light."42 Similarly, for Freud all dreams, including those that
cause anxiety, were
"a (disguised) fulfillment of a (suppressed or repressed)
wish."43 And so on: all of
the central tenets of the psychoanalytic system were presented
by Freud as both
universal and empirically demonstrable. As his collaborator
Josef Breuer put it,
Freud was "a man given to absolute and exclusive
formulations."44
This way of proceeding has created predictable problems for
both Freud and
his disciples. Evidence supportive of Freud's theories is almost
entirely derived
from the analytic session itself, "clinical" material which-as
Adolf Griinbaum
has shown in detail-is so contaminated by the presuppositions
and suggestive-
ness of the analytic session as to be useless for purposes of
confirmation.45 What
extraclinical evidence exists argues strongly against Freudian
theory. The central
tenets of the psychoanalytic system, the Oedipus complex and
the theory of in-
fantile sexuality upon which it is based, are without evidentiary
support of any
kind. Empirical studies have shown that young children of both
sexes feel closer
to the mother than the father and that as children mature, each
sex tends to
identify with the same sex parent, not out of fear of the other
but out of affection
and a desire for emulation.46 As for the retention of all
experience within memory,
empirical studies have shown that memory is in fact a highly
malleable mental
function by means of which people construct personal pasts to
accord with present
41 "From the History of an Infantile Neurosis," SE 17:97, 119.
For a discussion of this Freudian
belief, see Frank Cioffi, "Freud and the Idea of a Pseudo-
Science," in Robert Borger and Frank Cioffi,
eds., Explanation in the Behavioural Sciences (Cambridge,
Eng., 1970), pp. 471-99, at p. 481. For
Freud's Lamarckian materialism, which led him to believe that
acquired characteristics can be inher-
ited, see Frank J. Sulloway, Freud, Biologist of the Mind:
Beyond the Psychoanalytic Legend, rev. ed.
(Cambridge, Mass., 1992).
42 "Constructions in Analysis" (1937), SE 23:260.
43 Interpretation of Dreams (1900), SE 4:160.
44 Breuer's characterization is cited by Esterson, Seductive
Mirage, p. 5.
45 Griinbaum, Foundations of Psychoanalysis, pp. 95-172;
Griinbaum, Validation in the Clinical
Theory of Psychoanalysis: A Study in the Philosophy of
Psychoanalysis (Madison, Conn., 1993).
46 See, e.g., Spence, Rhetorical Voice of Psychoanalysis, pp.
22-23; Robert N. Emde, "Individual
Meaning and Increasing Complexity: Contributions of Sigmund
Freud and Rene Spitz to Develop-
mental Psychology," Developmental Psychology 28 (1992),
347-59 (Emde stresses that extensive
research "has shown that gender identity is not an outcome of
the Oedipus complex. Core gender
identity is established earlier, usually in the second and third
years of life" [p. 352]); and especially the
important and tenaciously empirical work by Margaret S.
Mahler, in Mahler et al., The Psychological
Birth of the Human Infant: Symbiosis and Individuation (New
York, 1975). As an example of the far
harsher judgments passed by nonpsychoanalytic critics of
Freud, see H. J. Eysenck, Decline and Fall
of the Freudian Empire (Harmondsworth, Eng., 1985), p. 35.
649
This content downloaded from 128.228.0.65 on Wed, 15 May
2019 02:22:27 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Chaucer's Pardoner on the Couch
conditions.47 Finally, recent studies of the mind in sleep have
shown that dreams
have a very different cause from Freud's wish fulfillment, that
their meaning is for
the most part quite clear, and that their bizarreness is an effect,
not of various
"censoring" mechanisms protecting consciousness from a
horrifying truth, but of
the physiology of the brain during sleep.48 As Malcolm
MacMillan has said, in
concluding his exhaustive survey of the fate of Freudian
theories when subjected
to the empirical standards that Freud himself claimed to have
applied, "Psycho-
analysis as a theory of personality has little to recommend it....
Do processes
like condensation and the summation of stimuli occur? Is there
such a mechanism
as repression? Is there a transformation of the primary process
into the secondary?
Is there an Oedipus complex out of which a super-ego forms
and from which the
ego is provided with defused energy? Is the development of
adult sexuality, char-
acter traits, and object-choice as Freud described them? Is
female sexuality as
Freud pictured it? From these points of view, psycho-analysis
is not so much a
bad theory, but a theory in search of some facts."49
Perhaps even more important to literary critics than this
evidentiary absence,
however, is the characteristic mode of argument by which
psychoanalysis pro-
ceeds. Psychoanalytic theory has always been able to absorb
into its system and
to explain in its own terms whatever counterevidence may be
presented. Freud
himself famously jettisoned his theory that neurotic patients
had been seduced in
infancy and replaced it with the less visible, and infinitely
resourceful, notion of
unconscious fantasy-a revision that succeeded in removing
seduction from the
real world (where it could be tested by evidence) and in
relocating it within the
patient him or herself (where it could be discerned only
through psychoanalytic
reconstructions of otherwise forgotten mental events). Freud
had initially told
his collaborator and friend Wilhelm Fliess that the seduction
theory was "the key
that unlocks everything, the etiological formula."5 But even at
this stage it is
unclear whether Freud was actually hearing such stories or
already reconstructing
them by applying his theory to the narratives his patients were
reciting.51 When
47 See Elizabeth Loftus, Memory: Surprising New Insights into
How We Remember and Why We
Forget (Reading, Mass., 1980); Alan Baddeley, Human
Memory: Theory and Practice (Boston, 1990);
Elizabeth Loftus and Katherine Ketcham, The Myth of
Repressed Memory: False Memories and Al-
legations of Sexual Abuse (New York, 1994); and Crews et al.,
Memory Wars.
48 For recent work on dreaming, see Anthony Shafton, Dream
Reader: Contemporary Approaches
to the Understanding of Dreams (Albany, N.Y., 1995); Inge
Strauch and Barbara Meier, In Search of
Dreams: Results of Experimental Dream Research (Albany,
N.Y., 1996); Michel Jouvet, The Paradox
of Sleep: The Story of Dreaming, trans. Laurence Garey
(Cambridge, Mass., 1999); Arthur W. Epstein,
Dreaming and Other Involuntary Mentation: An Essay in
Neuropsychiatry (Madison, Conn., 1995);
and J. Allan Hobson, The Dreaming Brain (New York, 1988). A
quick overview of this work will
reveal the dubious value of applying Freud's model of dreaming
either to real dreams or-as is some-
times still done-to works of fiction.
49 Macmillan, Freud Evaluated, p. 548.
50 Jeffrey Moussaieff Masson, ed. and trans., The Complete
Letters of Sigmund Freud to Wilhelm
Fliess, 1887-1904 (Cambridge, Mass., 1985), pp. 45-46.
51 See Crews et al., Memory Wars, pp. 57-58, and works cited
there. The best discussion of this
founding moment in the creation of psychoanalysis is provided
by Esterson, Seductive Mirage, pp. 11-
31; see also Richard Webster, Why Freud Was Wrong: Sin,
Science and Psychoanalysis (New York,
1995), pp. 195-213.
650
This content downloaded from 128.228.0.65 on Wed, 15 May
2019 02:22:27 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Chaucer's Pardoner on the Couch
he then decided that his claims of wholesale sexual abuse were
implausible, he
relocated them within the unconscious where they were
available only to the psy-
chotherapist. As he said, "We must not be led astray by [the
patient's] initial
denials. If we keep firmly to what we have inferred, we shall in
the end conquer
every resistance by emphasizing the unshakeable nature of our
convictions....
Since minor deviations from a normal vita sexualis are much
too common for us
to attach any value to their discovery, we shall only allow a
serious and long
continued abnormality in the sexual life of a neurotic patient to
carry weight as
an explanation."52
Hence Freud insisted that corroborative evidence from the
patient's life was not
merely unnecessary but an actual impediment: "It may seem
tempting to take the
easy course of filling up the gaps in a patient's memory by
making inquiries from
the older members of his family; but I cannot advise too
strongly against such a
technique.... One invariably regrets having made oneself
dependent upon such
information; at the same time confidence in the analysis is
shaken and a court of
appeal is set up over it."53 Freud did not abandon his
hypothesis that children
were sexually excited and seduced by their parents and then
threatened with-or
endured-castration. On the contrary, he avoided the court of
appeal of real-life
evidence by reworking the theory to accommodate it in a form
resistant to em-
pirical testing.
This process of calibrating the theory to ignore or absorb
recalcitrant evidence
rather than rethinking its central premises-perhaps the most
characteristic qual-
ity of psychoanalytic thought-gives an impression of immense
explanatory
power while concealing empirical emptiness. Two further
examples should make
this important methodological point clear. Freud argued, as we
have seen, that
"in every case of neurosis there is a sexual aetiology" and that
"anxiety is always
libido which has been deflected from its [normal] employment.
54 But what about
war neuroses, which certainly seem to have nothing to do with
sexuality? Freud's
answer is that the desire for survival is itself libidinal because
it is a form of
"narcissism, which brings the libidinal cathexis of the ego into
line with the ca-
thexes of objects and emphasizes the libidinal character of the
instinct of self-
preservation. "5 In any case, as he says in Beyond the Pleasure
Principle, "me-
chanical agitation [i.e., the concussion caused by exploding
shells] must be
recognized as one of the sources of sexual excitation."s6 By
thus expanding the
52 "Sexuality in the Aetiology of the Neuroses" (1898), SE
3:269. And Freud continues: "Moreover,
the idea that one might, by one's insistence, cause a patient
who is psychically normal to accuse himself
falsely of sexual misdemeanours-such an idea may safely be
disregarded as an imaginary danger."
Quite apart from the astonishing blindness to the power of
suggestion that the analyst's "unshakeable"
conviction could have on a patient that this comment reveals,
one need only substitute "critic" and
"text" for "analyst" and "patient" to see how vulnerable
psychoanalytic criticism is to the danger of
finding sexuality in a text that it already knows must be there.
53 "An Infantile Neurosis," SE 17:14 n; see Cioffi, "Freud and
the Idea of a Pseudo-Science," p. 480
(italics added).
54 "Sexuality in the Aetiology of the Neuroses," SE 3:268. The
brackets are in the original.
55 "Inhibitions, Symptoms and Anxiety" (1926), SE 20:129.
56 Beyond the Pleasure Principle (1920), SE 18:33. In a
footnote Freud compares explosive concus-
sion to swinging and railway travel, a startling trivialization of
the experiences of millions of men
during the Great War.
651
This content downloaded from 128.228.0.65 on Wed, 15 May
2019 02:22:27 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Chaucer's Pardoner on the Couch
notion of libido to include virtually all feelings, Freud was able
to maintain his
hypothesis that, regardless of the occasion for the appearance
of neurosis, its eti-
ology is always a displacement of libidinal energy. Hence
Freud looks forward
confidently to the time when "the libido theory could celebrate
its triumph all
along the line from the simplest 'actual' neurosis to the most
severe alienation of
the personality."57
The second example concerns Freud's familiar assertion that all
dreams are
disguised wish fulfillments. When Freud is presented with a
dream that seems not
to meet his criterion, he simply proclaims that the patient had
the dream in order
to fulfill her wish to thwart Freud's own theory of wish
fulfillment. In a typical
masterstroke of rhetorical subtlety, he then extended this lesson
to his larger au-
dience: "Indeed, it is to be expected that the same thing will
happen to some of
the readers of the present book: they will be quite ready to have
one of their wishes
frustrated in a dream if only their wish that I may be wrong can
be fulfilled."58
Given this preemptive strike, there is no recourse, as Karl
Kraus lamented: "They
have caught me!"59
We have here reached the central issue of interpretation, the
issue that above
all connects Freudian psychoanalysis to literary criticism. It is
clear that Freud's
method of dream interpretation-like his interpretive method as
a whole-is pre-
emptive. The theory posits the meaning of dreams, feelings,
and behaviors, and
the task of the analyst is to read them so that they yield their
preordained signif-
icance. Much has been written on the familiar mix of
arbitrariness and dogmatism
that characterizes psychoanalytic interpretation. Sebastiano
Timpanaro, for ex-
ample, has devoted three long and brilliant chapters to one of
Freud's interpre-
tations in The Psychopathology of Everyday Life. The famous
misquotation of a
Virgilian line made by the young man in the train is,
Timpanaro shows, determined
not by unconscious anxieties about his mistress's late menstrual
period but by the
peculiarly difficult syntax employed by Virgil, a difficulty that
caused medieval
scribes to make the same mistake. There is, Timpanaro
modestly says, "nothing
brilliant" about his demonstration, "nor is it even particularly
intelligent . . ; but
it is the simplest and most 'economical' explanation possible."
As for Freud's
interpretation, "beneath the brilliance of the intellectual
fireworks, few procedures
can be reckoned so antiscientific," for it depends upon a
"captious and sophistical
method, resistant to any verification, quick to force
interpretations [and] to secure
pre-ordained proofs."60
57 Introductory Lectures, SE 16:430.
58 Interpretation of Dreams, SE 4:158.
59 See above, n. 14. For a subtle reading of The Interpretation
of Dreams that examines its rhetorical
power, see Alexander Welsh, Freud's Wishful Dream Book
(Princeton, N.J., 1994). Welsh sees the
subject of the book as being not the psyche but Freud's own
ambition.
60 Timpanaro, The Freudian Slip, pp. 29-61, 41,42-43, and 14
(see n. 13 above). In his two-volume
account of psychoanalytic theory, The Non-Authentic Nature of
Freud's Observations, Uppsala Studies
in Education 47-48 (Uppsala, 1993), Max Scharnberg describes
the Freudian interpretive procedure
as follows:
1. Start with a preconceived interpretation.
2. Pick up a few details here and there on the criterion that they
can be used or misused to support
652
This content downloaded from 128.228.0.65 on Wed, 15 May
2019 02:22:27 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Chaucer's Pardoner on the Couch 653
In support of its empirical pretensions, psychoanalysis
systematically confuses
meanings with causes. As the British philosopher Frank Cioffi
remarks, "We did
not interpret dreams, symptoms, errors, etc., because it was
discovered that they
were meaningful, but we insisted that they were meaningful in
order that we might
interpret them."61 It may well be that the interpretation will
tell us something
important about the interpreter, or the patient, or the method of
interpretation;
but it can tell us nothing about the cause of the dream or
symptom. This confusion
of etiology with interpretation, or of reason with cause, is at
the very heart of the
psychoanalytic procedure, and it led Wittgenstein to describe
psychoanalysis as
"speculation-something prior even to the formation of an
hypothesis." Witt-
genstein argued that the power of the Freudian system was not
the correctness of
its account of the mind but the fact that Freud provided "the
sort of interpretation
that is wanted," interpretations that have "the attraction which
mythological ex-
planations have, explanations which say that this is all a
repetition of something
that has happened before."62 One sympathizes with Dora when,
after Freud has
interpreted a jewel case that appeared in one of her dreams as
the female genitalia,
she says, "I knew you would say that."63
Freud's famous case histories have been subjected to careful
investigation by
later researchers.64 The characteristic mode of argumentation
they display has led
Cioffi to characterize psychoanalysis not as a protoscience, a
theory still awaiting
its evidentiary basis, but as a pseudoscience that "involves the
habitual and wilful
the interpretation.
3. Connect them with the interpretation by means of the
principle of similarity.
4. Ignore all data which cannot be used as pseudo-support of
any interpretation.
5. If data which contradict the interpretation have inadvertently
been obtained, suppress them and
conceal them from the reader. (2:17)
The best precedent for Freud's hermeneutic is the exegetical
method of the Middle Ages. In both cases
the exegete knows beforehand what the text means-the double
law of charity, the Oedipus complex-
and her task is to explain how the text can mean what she
knows it must mean. This analogy between
the preemptive hermeneutic of medieval exegesis and
psychoanalytic procedures has been pointed out
by Cioffi, "Freud and the Idea of a Pseudo-Science," p. 498,
and by Spence, Rhetorical Voice of
Psychoanalysis (who argues at length that "psychoanalysis is as
much a medieval as a modern science"
[p. 47]).
61 "Freud and the Idea of a Pseudo-Science," p. 498.
62 Wittgenstein, Lectures and Conversations, pp. 43-44, 47.
63 "A Case of Hysteria" (1905), SE 7:69 (my italics). In a
footnote to this comment Freud easily
trumps Dora: "A very common way of putting aside a piece of
knowledge that emerges from the
repressed."
64 See, for a sample of these investigations, Charles
Bernheimer and Claire Kahane, eds., In Dora's
Case: Freud-Hysteria-Feminism (New York, 1985); Cioffi,
"Freud and the Idea of a Pseudo-Science,"
pp. 471-99 (on Dora); Henri F. Ellenberger, "The Story of
'Anna O': A Critical Review with New
Data," Journal of the History of the Behavioral Sciences 8
(1972), 267-79; Esterson, Seductive Mirage,
chaps. 3-5; Stanley Fish, "Withholding the Missing Portion:
Power, Meaning, and Persuasion in
Freud's 'The Wolf-Man,'" Times Literary Supplement, August
29, 1986; John Kerr, A Most Dangerous
Method: The Story of ung, Freud, and Sabina Spielrein (New
York, 1993); Karin Obholzer, The Wolf-
Man: Conversations with Freud's Patient-Sixty Years Later,
trans. Michael Shaw (New York, 1982);
Frank J. Sulloway, "Reassessing Freud's Case Histories: The
Social Construction of Psychoanalysis,"
Isis 82 (1991), 245-75; and Joseph Wolpe and Stanley
Rachman, "Psychoanalytic 'Evidence': A Cri-
tique Based on Freud's Case of Little Hans," Journal of
Nervous and Mental Disease 131 (1960),
135-48.
This content downloaded from 128.228.0.65 on Wed, 15 May
2019 02:22:27 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Chaucer's Pardoner on the Couch
employment of methodologically defective procedures (in a
sense of wilful which
encompasses refined self-deception).... [Hence] there are a host
of peculiarities
of psychoanalytic theory and practice which are apparently
gratuitous and unre-
lated, but which can be understood when once they are seen as
manifestations of
the same impulse: the need to avoid refutation."65 For
example, if a child has an
overbearing superego, Freud argued at one point that this is the
direct effect of a
strict father; but at another point the same phenomenon was
explained as a re-
action against a too lenient father. As Cioffi says, Freud is able
"to render any
outcome whatever an intelligible and apparently natural result
of whatever cir-
cumstances preceded it."66
Since this point is central to the literary use of psychoanalytic
interpretive pro-
cedures, it is worth quoting in full a discussion of
psychoanalytic testing by the
research analyst Sibylle Escalona:
Suppose one wished to investigate the psycho-analytic idea
that, at about the ages of
three and four, little boys characteristically experience hostile
and aggressive feelings
towards their parents and more specifically their fathers, and
that these hostile feelings
are based on the wish to possess the mother and replace the
father in the family con-
stellation. Suppose also that you create an experimental
situation which would activate
the child's feeling towards his parents. For instance, the father
might exert his authority
by sending the child off to his own room when the child wants
to remain with the
parents. If, to substantiate the core of the oedipal hypothesis,
the child were required to
display frank anger against his father, or frank possessiveness
towards his mother, things
would be reasonably simple. However, no one would seriously
believe that oedipal con-
flicts are at work only when the child obligingly acts out both
his wish and his anger at
the obstacle of wish-fulfillment. Instead, we assume that the
child tends to defend himself
against becoming aware of-or openly reflecting-aggression
because it engenders anxi-
ety. Thus, if the child gives daddy a good-night hug and insists
that he, rather than
mummy, tuck him in, this behaviour may also confirm our
original hypothesis. His desire
to have the father put him to bed rather than the mother could
be the result of a fearful
state, i.e. as long as the father is with him the little boy can be
sure the father is not
doing anything to harm him. On the other hand, or also
simultaneously, it may be an
act of aggression towards the father in that it separates him
from the mother for the
time being. Or yet again, it may be because the little boy fears
that if the mother puts
him to bed her seductive powers will prove too much for him;
he will then express his
possessive love for the mother and try to take his father's place,
and the omniscient
father will punish him for it. The example could be spun out
indefinitely, and it is safe
to say that there is nothing our little experimental subject could
possibly do, from with-
drawal, to sudden intense interest in phantasy play, to asking
for a cake, that cannot be
regarded in the light of the assumption that he is reacting to an
oedipal conflict situation.
This being so, it is self-evident that nothing the little boy can
do will confirm the original
hypothesis, since the hypothesis would still be applicable if he
had done the opposite
65 Cioffi, "Freud and the Idea of a Pseudo-Science," pp. 472-
73.
66 Ibid., p. 485. As Cioffi shows in another essay, what makes
a theory pseudoscientific rather than
nonscientific is that its statements are subject to falsifiability
but are presented and maintained in a
context in which testing is rendered impossible. A
pseudoscience will seek to prove itself by citing
positive instances while making it impossible to distinguish
between positive and negative ("Psycho-
analysis, Pseudo-Science and Testability," in Gregory Currie
and Alan Musgrave, eds., Popper and the
Human Sciences, Nijhoff International Philosophy Series 19
[Dordrecht, 1995], pp. 13-44, at p. 17.
654
This content downloaded from 128.228.0.65 on Wed, 15 May
2019 02:22:27 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Chaucer's Pardoner on the Couch
instead.... Psycho-analytic theory is greatly in need of
validation, yet it is the kind of
theory incapable of validation.67
Finally, it must be stressed that the variants of psychoanalytic
theory that have
developed over the years, and especially that associated with
Jacques Lacan, are
not only not free from the flaws of method and conceptual
vagueness that are
fatal to Freudianism but actually invoke them as a badge of
honor. Lacan shows
little interest in empirical validation in preference to
unconstrained theorizing. His
foundational account of prelinguistic identity formation by
means of the "mirror-
stage" relies, as one of his defenders acknowledges, on a "very
limited fund of
observation data," data that genuinely empirical studies have
subsequently shown
to be false.68 Indeed, Lacanianism's popularity in academic
circles derives not from
its truth-value, which remains not just undemonstrated but
indemonstrable, but
from its fit with other modes of "anti-humanist"-indeed
irrationalist-thought
that are taken to be progressive and even liberatory.69
For a long time Freud had a reputation for what Ernest Jones
called "flawless
integrity" and Steven Marcus a "profoundly moral . . .
intellectual commitment
and adherence to the idea of science."70 These reverential
hopes must now also be
abandoned. So, too, must Freud's continual claims to have gone
where no man
dared go before: we now know that many of the central
Freudian concepts-
including the unconscious and the centrality of sexuality to the
mental life-were
common currency in late-nineteenth-century medical circles.71
Freud's suppression
of evidence in the case histories, his self-glorification
(including the tale of his
famous self-analysis, which in all likelihood never took place),
his misbehavior as
67 Sibylle Escalona, "Problems in Psycho-Analytic Research,"
International Journal of Psycho-anal-
ysis 33 (1952), 11-21; cited by Cioffi, "Psychoanalysis,
Pseudo-Science and Testability," pp. 20-21;
emphasis added. See also Morris N. Eagle, "The
Epistemological Status of Recent Developments in
Psychoanalytic Theory," in R. S. Cohen and L. Laudan, eds.,
Physics, Philosophy, and Psychoanalysis:
Essays in Honor of Adolf Griinbaum, Boston Studies in the
Philosophy of Science 76 (Boston, 1983),
pp. 31-55.
68 Bowie, Lacan, p. 22. As Bowie says, Lacan "starves his
hypothesis of the clinical data that could
test its organizing power, and produces neither map nor
message" (p. 25). For empirical evidence
about how infants actually respond to mirrors, see Margaret S.
Mahler and John B. McDevitt,
"Thoughts on the Emergence of the Sense of Self, with
Particular Emphasis on the Body Self," Journal
of the American Psychoanalytic Association 30 (1982), 827-48,
and Jeanne Brooks-Gunn and Michael
Lewis, "Mirror-Image Stimulation and Self Recognition in
Infancy," a paper available at http://
askeric.org/Eric/. I am indebted for these references to Norman
Holland, "The Trouble(s) with Lacan"
(n. 32 above). As Holland says, "There is no evidence for
Lacan's notion of a mirror stage. Indeed
what evidence we have runs rather the other way.... Perhaps
Lacan knew no better in 1936, but why
do present-day Lacanians go on quoting this mish-mash of
conjecture and false assertions?"
69 See Ferry and Renaut, French Philosophy of the Sixties, pp.
3-67, 185-227.
70 Ernest Jones, The Life and Work of Sigmund Freud, 3 vols.
(New York, 1953-57), 1:327, and
Marcus, Freud and the Culture of Psychoanalysis, p. 11. The
most recent and thorough demonstration
of Freud's self-interest in misrepresenting his "data" is
provided by Han Israels, Der Fall Freud: Die
Geburt der Psychoanalyse aus der Liige, trans. (from the
Dutch) Gerd Busse (Hamburg, 1999); an
extensive summary of Israels's indictment is provided by
Mikkel Borch-Jacobsen, "How a Fabrication
Differs from a Lie," London Review of Books 22/8 (13 April
2000), 3-7.
71 See especially Henri F. Ellenberger, The Discovery of the
Unconscious: The History and Evolution
of Dynamic Psychiatry (New York, 1970); Edward Shorter, A
History of Psychiatry: From the Era of
the Asylum to the Age of Prozac (New York, 1997); and
Sulloway, Freud, Biologist of the Mind.
655
This content downloaded from 128.228.0.65 on Wed, 15 May
2019 02:22:27 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
656 Chaucer's Pardoner on the Couch
an analyst, his insistence that his co-workers share a total
commitment to his
dogma or else face exile and obloquy, and even his
championing of cocaine and
his own addiction-all of this would seem mere ad hominem
critique were it not
for the fact that the contemporary institution of psychoanalysis
follows so closely
in its father's footsteps.72 It remains resistant to the empirical
procedures that
characterize other medical practices; it continues to idolize its
founder; it treats
criticism as disloyalty; and it refuses to examine its own
disciplinary history.73
These fundamental problems in a theory that claims to explain
human behavior,
and in a medical institution that claims scientific status, are
apparently either
unknown to, unacknowledged by, or regarded as irrelevant to
the literary critics,
perhaps especially in medieval studies, who have jumped on
what they think is a
bandwagon but is in fact an ambulance or perhaps even a
hearse. The irony is
that psychoanalysis has the reputation of being cutting edge in
literary criticism
even as it has disappeared from those fields for which it was
designed-the un-
derstanding of human behavior and the management of mental
pathologies.74
3. PSYCHOANALYZING THE PARDONER
This section reexamines a well-known medieval text, Chaucer's
Pardoner's Pro-
logue and Tale. In part it constitutes a palinode on my part, a
retraction resembling
Chaucer's own selective rejection of some of his works. I wish
to show the allure
of psychoanalytic interpretation, an allure to which I myself
once succumbed, but
also its limits, specifically the way its seeming persuasiveness
can foreclose access
to relevant medieval materials and contexts. In the General
Prologue to the Can-
72 For the dubious existence of the self-analysis, see Spence,
Rhetorical Voice, chap. 5. For Freud's
misbehavior as an analyst, two instances are cited by Sulloway,
"Reassessing Freud's Case Histories,"
from the correspondence with Fliess, one in 1888, the other in
1898: "I have at this moment a lady
in hypnosis lying in front of me and therefore can go on writing
in peace"; "I sleep during my afternoon
analyses" (cited p. 157). For Freud's enthusiasm for cocaine,
Fliess's theory of the physiological con-
nection between the nose and the genitals, and its hideous
effects upon their patient Emma Eckstein,
for which Freud refused to take responsibility, see E. M.
Thornton, Freud and Cocaine: The Freudian
Fallacy (London, 1983); Sulloway, Freud, Biologist of the
Mind, pp. 327-29; Crews, Skeptical En-
gagements, pp. 48-52; and Clark Glymour, "The Theory of
Your Dreams," in Cohen and Laudan,
eds., Physics, Philosophy and Psychoanalysis, pp. 57-71, at pp.
64-69.
73 As the psychoanalyst Robert Holt says: "American
psychoanalysis has lived for so long within a
snug cocoon of myth that it seems unable to go through the
predictable pains of metamorphosis into
a viable progressive discipline. The protective threads it has
wound around itself include warding off
all criticism as resistance, idolatry of Freud, and faithful
internalization of all his faults as a scientist
and writer" (Freud Reappraised, p. 341). To be sure,
contemporary psychoanalysts are aware of their
credibility problem: the American Psychoanalytic Association
has established a Subcommittee on Stra-
tegic Marketing, hired a public relations consultant and
Washington lobbyists, and is conducting focus
groups in order, according to the chairman of the
subcommittee, "to try and define the messages we
should be giving for public use" (New York Times, December
9, 2000, pp. B7 and B9).
74 For a psychoanalyst's account of this irony, see Alan Stone,
"Where Will Psychoanalysis Survive?"
Harvard Magazine 99/3 (1997), 35-39. Stone, a former
president of the American Psychiatric Asso-
ciation, sees the future of psychoanalysis in "the arts and
humanities" and points out that in the
Harvard course catalogue for 1997 there are forty "classes
whose descriptions mention either Freud
or psychoanalysis.... All of them are in the humanities,
particularly literature; no course is being
given in the psychology department, and next to nothing is
offered in the medical school" (p. 38).
This content downloaded from 128.228.0.65 on Wed, 15 May
2019 02:22:27 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Chaucer's Pardoner on the Couch
terbury Tales the narrator explains the Pardoner's odd
appearance with the com-
ment "I trowe he were a geldyng or a mare" (691).75 For the
modern reader, for
whom sexual identity is the crucial determinant of selfhood,
this line immediately
places sex at the center of the picture. Two other aspects of the
tale encourage
interpreters to keep it there. One is the Old Man whom the
three rioters of the
tale meet in their quest to kill death, a figure who describes
himself in eerily Oe-
dipal terms.
Ne Deeth, alias, no wol nat han my lyf.
Thus walke I, lyk a restelees kaityf,
And on the ground, which is my moodres gate,
I knokke with my staf, bothe erly and late,
And seye "Leeve mooder, leet me in!"
(727-31)
Equally tempting are the false relics that the Pardoner carries
"biforn hym in his
lappe" (1.686). After he has finished his tale, he turns to the
Host and asks him
to make an offering and kiss these relics. The Host responds
with an outburst
famous for its scatological violence:
I wolde I hadde thy coillons in myn hond
In stide of relikes or of seintuarie.
Lat kutte hem of, I wol thee helpe hem carie;
They shul be shryned in an hogges toord!
(952-55)
Thus the Oedipal dream of a return to the mother (as expressed
by the Old Man)
is here punished by the paternal threat of castration-a
psychoanalytic schema as
neat as any Freudian could want. Not surprisingly, recent
criticism has read the
Pardoner almost exclusively in such terms.
A number of years ago I developed an interpretation of this text
that was es-
sentially historical-that is, it depended upon late-medieval
religious beliefs-but
also invoked psychoanalytic terms.76 I read the Old Man as a
figure for the Par-
doner's own despair; that condition is typically represented in
medieval writing
as always dying but never dead. As for his Oedipal speech, I
explained it by way
of the literary history of the Oedipus legend, which in the
Middle Ages became
linked with the theological condition of despair via the figure
of Judas. In due
course I shall briefly rehearse the main points of that
interpretation, but I want
now to acknowledge that I did not then sufficiently control my
own use of psy-
choanalytic terminology, largely because psychoanalysis
provided a temptingly
prefabricated interpretation that showed how a medieval text
could satisfy mod-
ern (and younger) preoccupations. I now know that there is a
wealth of further
75 All citations from Chaucer are to The Riverside Chaucer,
3rd ed., gen. ed. Larry D. Benson (Bos-
ton, 1987). All further citations will be included in the text by
line number; I have on occasion altered
the punctuation.
76 Chaucer and the Subject of History (Madison, Wis., 1991),
pp. 367-421; the essentials of this
reading were first presented in "Chaucerian Confession:
Penitential Literature and the Pardoner,"
Medievalia et humanistica 7 (1976), 153-73, and, with the
added psychoanalytic twist, in a paper at
the Medieval Congress at Kalamazoo in 1985.
657
This content downloaded from 128.228.0.65 on Wed, 15 May
2019 02:22:27 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Chaucer's Pardoner on the Couch
medieval material that the familiar psychoanalytic paradigm
hid from my view,
material that can help us to understand both the Pardoner and
the Old Man with
much greater historical specificity.
The reading of the tale that has now achieved almost classic
status is the thor-
oughly psychoanalytic interpretation offered by Carolyn
Dinshaw in Chaucer's
Sexual Poetics.77 According to Dinshaw the Pardoner enacts
"the modern psycho-
analytic version of the myth of loss and wished-for
reconciliation"; his being is
"essentially defective, lacking, fragmented": "the lacking
Pardoner demonstrates
the pain that must attend the subject's development. .. when it
is seen to depend
on a necessary absence-the necessary loss of plenitude initially
associated with
the mother's body and a definition of the woman as lack." This
lack is expressed
in the Pardoner's use of relics (relics are, according to
Dinshaw, historically not
usually associated with pardoners and therefore should be read
symbolically);78
his relics are fetish objects that substitute for his missing
manhood: "As free-
floating body-parts, they are both reifications of his own
fragmentariness and
substitutes for his own masculine lack."79 But "the Pardoner's
relics cannot really
produce that desired integrity, and he knows it.... They both
represent lack and
substitute for wholeness; they signify absence even as they
suggest presence."80
Although Dinshaw sounds like Lacan, and explicitly invokes
Melanie Klein,
this reading depends ultimately on Freud's account of
fetishism. For Freud, the
fetish is a sexually arousing object that substitutes for the
mother's missing penis-
it is created, in short, by the castration anxiety that both
establishes and charac-
terizes subjectivity. The fetish is a "disavowal" of a reality that
the fetishist ac-
knowledges in another part of his ego: that penises-including
his mother's and,
by implication, his own-can be missing.81 The Lacanian turn to
Dinshaw's ar-
gument is to include in this economy of castration language
itself, arguing that
77 Chaucer's Sexual Poetics (Madison, Wis., 1989). Dinshaw's
chapter has been often reprinted and
cited as providing an authoritative account of the tale: e.g.,
Derek Pearsall, ed., Chaucer to Spenser:
Critical Reader (Malden, Mass., 1999), pp. 65-106, and Bruce
R. Smith, "Premodern Sexualities,"
PMLA 115 (2000), 318-29, at p. 324.
78 In this (mistaken) assumption, Dinshaw is relying upon
Alfred L. Kellogg and Louis A. Hasel-
mayer, "Chaucer's Satire of the Pardoner," in Alfred L.
Kellogg, Chaucer, Langland, Arthur: Essays
in Middle English Literature (New Brunswick, N.J., 1972), pp.
212-44, at p. 233 n. 51. For pardoners
and relics, see Siegfried Wenzel, "Chaucer's Pardoner and His
Relics," Studies in the Age of Chaucer
11 (1989), 37-41 and n. 152. Unfortunately, Dinshaw does not
use Kellogg's excellent "An Augus-
tinian Interpretation of Chaucer's Pardoner," Speculum 26
(1951), 465-81, reprinted in Chaucer,
Langland, Arthur, pp. 245-68, which provides a good account
of the subtle psychologizing available
to medieval Christianity.
79 Dinshaw misses a Freudian opportunity here: in The
Interpretation of Dreams Freud reads one
of his own dreams as showing that he thought that his children
wished to turn his sexual organs into
relics; see Eysenck, Decline and Fall of the Freudian Empire,
p. 146.
80 Dinshaw, Chaucer's Sexual Poetics, pp. 161-64, 167-68.
81 See "Fetishism" (1927), SE 21:152-57, and An Outline of
Psycho-Analysis (1940), SE 23:202-
3. Freud argues that the particular object chosen as a fetish
depends upon whatever the child "saw at
the moment at which he saw the female genitals, or it is
something that can suitably serve as a symbolic
substitute for the penis" (SE 23:203). Given his vantage point
from the ground up, the boy thus usually
becomes a foot or shoe fetishist, although occasionally he uses
hair, since his horror at the sight of the
mother's missing penis fixates his gaze on her pubic hair.
658
This content downloaded from 128.228.0.65 on Wed, 15 May
2019 02:22:27 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Chaucer's Pardoner on the Couch
the Pardoner's sexual absence signifies linguistic absence.82
"Defined by absence,"
"lack," and "incompleteness," the Pardoner reveals "the nature
of language it-
self," that it too is castrated and lacks full significance. Hence
Chaucer explores
through him "a hermeneutics of the partial, or, for short,
eunuch hermeneutics."83
Dinshaw thus takes as a given the Pardoner's eunuchry, reading
it as both literal
and symbolic.84 But what would a reader in fourteenth-century
England have
assumed about this figure, whom the narrator introduces as
either a gelding or a
mare? Did such terms imply literal or symbolic effeminacy?
And if symbolic, sym-
bolic within what system of signification?
Let us start with the issue of gelding. In the very early Middle
Ages castration
is prescribed as a punishment for various crimes, usually sexual
and occasionally
including sodomy, as in Justinian's law code; it reappears in the
same context in
the later Middle Ages in Italy, although the usual punishment
prescribed for sod-
omy was burning.85 But in later medieval England castration
as a punishment for
any crime is very rare, if not in fact entirely absent. Froissart
reports the castration
of Edward II's reputed lover Hugh Despenser, but this is no
more historically
verifiable than the claim that Edward was himself killed by
having a hot poker
inserted in his anus. In the cultural imagination there clearly
was a link between
sodomy and castration. In the Roman de la Rose Genius wants
all sodomites
castrated, and the eccentric English work known as the Mirror
of Justices says
that at the present time (i.e., 1285-90) the punishment for rape
was hanging, but
82 This argument was first made, in relation to Chaucer's
source for the relevant passage in the
Roman de la Rose, by R. Howard Bloch, Etymologies and
Genealogies: A Literary Anthropology of
the French Middle Ages (Chicago, 1983), pp. 128-58.
83 Dinshaw, Chaucer's Sexual Poetics, pp. 158-59.
84 In a later essay, however, she has argued that the Pardoner
must be taken, by ourselves and his
fellow travelers, as queer, a concept whose existence in the
Middle Ages remains to be demonstrated:
"Chaucer's Queer Touches/A Queer Touches Chaucer,"
Exemplaria 7 (1995), 75-92. Queer readings
of the Pardoner-prefigured by Donald R. Howard in The Idea of
the Canterbury Tales (Berkeley,
Calif., 1976), pp. 339-80, and further encouraged by Monica E.
McAlpine, "The Pardoner's Ho-
mosexuality and How It Matters," PMLA 95 (1980), 8-22-have
now become common: see Glenn
Burger, "Kissing the Pardoner," PMLA 107 (1992), 1143-56;
Steven E Kruger, "Claiming the Par-
doner: Toward a Gay Reading of Chaucer's Pardoner's Tale,"
Exemplaria 6 (1994), 115-39; Allen J.
Frantzen, "The Pardoner's Tale, the Pervert, and the Price of
Order in Chaucer's World," in Britton
J. Harwood and Gillian R. Overing, eds., Class and Gender in
Early English Literature: Intersections
(Bloomington, Ind., 1994), pp. 131-47; and Robert Stuart
Sturges, Chaucer's Pardoner and Gender
Theory: Bodies of Discourse (New York, 2000). All of these
readings assume that Chaucer's account
is designed to direct the reader's attention to the Pardoner's
homosexuality. On the other hand, the
proposal that a contemporary audience would have seen the
Pardoner's feminization as an effect of
his excessive sexual dealings with women-i.e., of his too active
heterosexuality-is presented with
strong evidentiary support by C. David Benson, "Chaucer's
Pardoner: His Sexuality and Modern
Critics," Mediaevalia 8 (1985 for 1982), 337-49, and Richard F
Green, "The Sexual Normality of
Chaucer's Pardoner," Mediaevalia 8 (1985 for 1982), 351-58.
Unfortunately, the queer readings of
the Pardoner do not confront this evidence.
85 For Justinian's Code, see John Boswell, Christianity, Social
Tolerance, and Homosexuality: Gay
People in Western Europe from the Beginning of the Christian
Era to the Fourteenth Century (Chicago,
1980), p. 172; for the Italian legislation in the later Middle
Ages, see James A. Brundage, Law, Sex,
and Christian Society in Medieval Europe (Chicago, 1987), pp.
472-74, 533-35; for castration as a
penalty for sodomy, see Michael Goodich, The Unmentionable
Vice: Homosexuality in the Later
Medieval Period (Santa Barbara, Calif., 1979), p. 83.
659
This content downloaded from 128.228.0.65 on Wed, 15 May
2019 02:22:27 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
660 Chaucer's Pardoner on the Couch
that prior to the reign of Edward I rape was punished "by
tearing out of eyes and
loss of testicles, because of the appetite which entered through
the eyes and the
heat of fornication which came into the reins of the lechers."86
In the Placita
Corone, a law book written about 1274, a convicted rapist can
be castrated and
blinded, unless his wife speaks out, for "she can claim her
husband's testicles as
her own property."87 But even this quaint ruling seems to
function more in the
realm of fiction than fact: the editor of the Placita points out
that rape was in fact
punished by fine alone, and that both castration and blinding
"had almost cer-
tainly ceased to be inflicted long before 1274-1275."88 There
may have been
private instances of castration for sexual offenses against
women in the thirteenth
century-Matthew Paris reports one, and in 1275 Parliament
passed a statute
defining rape as a capital offense, perhaps to foreclose the
possibility that castra-
tion and/or blinding would be imposed as a punishment-but
there is no evidence
that this punishment was carried out in any judicial or even
semiofficial way in
England after 1300 at the latest.89 Indeed, mutilation as a
whole seems to have
disappeared in England in the thirteenth century, and even the
gruesomely detailed
execution for treason by drawing and quartering did not include
castration.90
As a physical phenomenon, then, the castrate or eunuch woul d
seem to have
been rare in late-medieval England. It may be that Walter
Clyde Curry is right
that Chaucer drew for his portrait of the Pardoner on the
medical physiognomist
86 Guillaume de Lorris and Jean de Meun, Le roman de la
Rose, ed. Daniel Poirion (Paris, 1974),
lines 19626-86, pp. 520-21; William Joseph Whittaker, ed. and
trans., The Mirror of Justices, Pub-
lications of the Selden Society 7 (London, 1895), p. 141. I am
indebted for the information about
castration as a punishment in England in this and the following
sentences to Prof. Richard F Green.
87 J. M. Kaye, ed., Placita Corone, Selden Society,
Supplementary Series, 4 (London, 1966), p. 9.
88 Ibid., p. xvi; see also p. xxxiv.
89 For Matthew Paris, see H. R. Luard, ed., Chronica majora, 7
vols., Rolls Series 57 (London,
1872-83), 5:34. For the 1285 statute, see The Statutes of the
Realm, ed. Alexander Luders et al., 9
vols. in 10 (London, 1810-22), 1:87; see also 1:29 (1275) and
2:27 (1382). In France I have found
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza
Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza

More Related Content

Similar to Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza

Healthcare Essay Topics
Healthcare Essay TopicsHealthcare Essay Topics
Healthcare Essay Topics
Julie Songy
 
An Argumentative Essay Sample.pdf
An Argumentative Essay Sample.pdfAn Argumentative Essay Sample.pdf
An Argumentative Essay Sample.pdf
Emily Parrish
 

Similar to Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza (20)

Classification And Division Essay Sample.pdf
Classification And Division Essay Sample.pdfClassification And Division Essay Sample.pdf
Classification And Division Essay Sample.pdf
 
Extended Essay Grade Boundaries 2015
Extended Essay Grade Boundaries 2015Extended Essay Grade Boundaries 2015
Extended Essay Grade Boundaries 2015
 
Healthcare Essay Topics
Healthcare Essay TopicsHealthcare Essay Topics
Healthcare Essay Topics
 
Commentary Essay Example. 10 Easy Steps: How to Write a Commentary on an Arti...
Commentary Essay Example. 10 Easy Steps: How to Write a Commentary on an Arti...Commentary Essay Example. 10 Easy Steps: How to Write a Commentary on an Arti...
Commentary Essay Example. 10 Easy Steps: How to Write a Commentary on an Arti...
 
An Argumentative Essay Sample.pdf
An Argumentative Essay Sample.pdfAn Argumentative Essay Sample.pdf
An Argumentative Essay Sample.pdf
 
Judicial Precedent Essay A Level
Judicial Precedent Essay A LevelJudicial Precedent Essay A Level
Judicial Precedent Essay A Level
 
Thesis Career Choice Questionnaire Example - T
Thesis Career Choice Questionnaire Example - TThesis Career Choice Questionnaire Example - T
Thesis Career Choice Questionnaire Example - T
 
Cause And Effect Essay Example About Smoking
Cause And Effect Essay Example About SmokingCause And Effect Essay Example About Smoking
Cause And Effect Essay Example About Smoking
 
Persuasive Analysis Essay Example
Persuasive Analysis Essay ExamplePersuasive Analysis Essay Example
Persuasive Analysis Essay Example
 
Help In Writing A Research Paper. Online assignment writing service.
Help In Writing A Research Paper. Online assignment writing service.Help In Writing A Research Paper. Online assignment writing service.
Help In Writing A Research Paper. Online assignment writing service.
 
Steps In Writing An Essay On Vimeo
Steps In Writing An Essay On VimeoSteps In Writing An Essay On Vimeo
Steps In Writing An Essay On Vimeo
 
Example Of A Satire Essay. Excellent Satire Essay Examples Thatsnotus
Example Of A Satire Essay. Excellent Satire Essay Examples  ThatsnotusExample Of A Satire Essay. Excellent Satire Essay Examples  Thatsnotus
Example Of A Satire Essay. Excellent Satire Essay Examples Thatsnotus
 
How Long Is Reasonable For Student To Write An Essa
How Long Is Reasonable For Student To Write An EssaHow Long Is Reasonable For Student To Write An Essa
How Long Is Reasonable For Student To Write An Essa
 
Essay Outlines
Essay OutlinesEssay Outlines
Essay Outlines
 
Can You Say Your In A Formal Essay
Can You Say Your In A Formal EssayCan You Say Your In A Formal Essay
Can You Say Your In A Formal Essay
 
My Hobby Essay For 2Nd Class. Online assignment writing service.
My Hobby Essay For 2Nd Class. Online assignment writing service.My Hobby Essay For 2Nd Class. Online assignment writing service.
My Hobby Essay For 2Nd Class. Online assignment writing service.
 
Expert Essay Writers - How To. Online assignment writing service.
Expert Essay Writers - How To. Online assignment writing service.Expert Essay Writers - How To. Online assignment writing service.
Expert Essay Writers - How To. Online assignment writing service.
 
College Essay Stanford Supple
College Essay Stanford SuppleCollege Essay Stanford Supple
College Essay Stanford Supple
 
Essay Topics For Air Pollution. Online assignment writing service.
Essay Topics For Air Pollution. Online assignment writing service.Essay Topics For Air Pollution. Online assignment writing service.
Essay Topics For Air Pollution. Online assignment writing service.
 
Pin On Art Analysis
Pin On Art AnalysisPin On Art Analysis
Pin On Art Analysis
 

More from AbramMartino96

Homeland Security efforts are ably reinforced by Homeland Defense an.docx
Homeland Security efforts are ably reinforced by Homeland Defense an.docxHomeland Security efforts are ably reinforced by Homeland Defense an.docx
Homeland Security efforts are ably reinforced by Homeland Defense an.docx
AbramMartino96
 
Homework Assignment Company Research  This assignment req.docx
Homework Assignment Company Research  This assignment req.docxHomework Assignment Company Research  This assignment req.docx
Homework Assignment Company Research  This assignment req.docx
AbramMartino96
 
Homework Assignment #1Directions Please answer each of the foll.docx
Homework Assignment #1Directions Please answer each of the foll.docxHomework Assignment #1Directions Please answer each of the foll.docx
Homework Assignment #1Directions Please answer each of the foll.docx
AbramMartino96
 
Homework Assignment 4 Guidelines1. Write the paper in Microsoft Wo.docx
Homework Assignment 4 Guidelines1. Write the paper in Microsoft Wo.docxHomework Assignment 4 Guidelines1. Write the paper in Microsoft Wo.docx
Homework Assignment 4 Guidelines1. Write the paper in Microsoft Wo.docx
AbramMartino96
 
History and TheoryConsiderthe eras, life histories.docx
History and TheoryConsiderthe eras, life histories.docxHistory and TheoryConsiderthe eras, life histories.docx
History and TheoryConsiderthe eras, life histories.docx
AbramMartino96
 
Historical Background of Housing PolicyHousing is one of the requi.docx
Historical Background of Housing PolicyHousing is one of the requi.docxHistorical Background of Housing PolicyHousing is one of the requi.docx
Historical Background of Housing PolicyHousing is one of the requi.docx
AbramMartino96
 

More from AbramMartino96 (20)

Homework assignmentPlease annotate one artwork you like from this.docx
Homework assignmentPlease annotate one artwork you like from this.docxHomework assignmentPlease annotate one artwork you like from this.docx
Homework assignmentPlease annotate one artwork you like from this.docx
 
Homeland Security efforts are ably reinforced by Homeland Defense an.docx
Homeland Security efforts are ably reinforced by Homeland Defense an.docxHomeland Security efforts are ably reinforced by Homeland Defense an.docx
Homeland Security efforts are ably reinforced by Homeland Defense an.docx
 
Homecoming is an annual tradition in the United States. In this repo.docx
Homecoming is an annual tradition in the United States. In this repo.docxHomecoming is an annual tradition in the United States. In this repo.docx
Homecoming is an annual tradition in the United States. In this repo.docx
 
HomerAssignmentIIReadthreeofthebooksfromTheOdyss.docx
HomerAssignmentIIReadthreeofthebooksfromTheOdyss.docxHomerAssignmentIIReadthreeofthebooksfromTheOdyss.docx
HomerAssignmentIIReadthreeofthebooksfromTheOdyss.docx
 
Homelessness in America has been a problem since the settlement of t.docx
Homelessness in America has been a problem since the settlement of t.docxHomelessness in America has been a problem since the settlement of t.docx
Homelessness in America has been a problem since the settlement of t.docx
 
Homework Assignments One pagewhat the functional currency .docx
Homework Assignments One pagewhat the functional currency .docxHomework Assignments One pagewhat the functional currency .docx
Homework Assignments One pagewhat the functional currency .docx
 
Homework Assignment Company Research  This assignment req.docx
Homework Assignment Company Research  This assignment req.docxHomework Assignment Company Research  This assignment req.docx
Homework Assignment Company Research  This assignment req.docx
 
Homework Assignment #1Directions Please answer each of the foll.docx
Homework Assignment #1Directions Please answer each of the foll.docxHomework Assignment #1Directions Please answer each of the foll.docx
Homework Assignment #1Directions Please answer each of the foll.docx
 
Homework Assignment 9Due in week 10 and worth 30 pointsSuppose t.docx
Homework Assignment 9Due in week 10 and worth 30 pointsSuppose t.docxHomework Assignment 9Due in week 10 and worth 30 pointsSuppose t.docx
Homework Assignment 9Due in week 10 and worth 30 pointsSuppose t.docx
 
Homework Assignment 4 Guidelines1. Write the paper in Microsoft Wo.docx
Homework Assignment 4 Guidelines1. Write the paper in Microsoft Wo.docxHomework Assignment 4 Guidelines1. Write the paper in Microsoft Wo.docx
Homework Assignment 4 Guidelines1. Write the paper in Microsoft Wo.docx
 
Hi we are a group doing a research and we split up the work ev.docx
Hi we are a group doing a research and we split up the work ev.docxHi we are a group doing a research and we split up the work ev.docx
Hi we are a group doing a research and we split up the work ev.docx
 
hi I need research paper  about any topics in Manufacturing Proc.docx
hi I need research paper  about any topics in Manufacturing Proc.docxhi I need research paper  about any topics in Manufacturing Proc.docx
hi I need research paper  about any topics in Manufacturing Proc.docx
 
HMIS Standards  Please respond to the followingFrom the e-A.docx
HMIS Standards  Please respond to the followingFrom the e-A.docxHMIS Standards  Please respond to the followingFrom the e-A.docx
HMIS Standards  Please respond to the followingFrom the e-A.docx
 
Hi i need a paper about (Head On )German film ( Turkey part)3 to.docx
Hi i need a paper about (Head On )German film ( Turkey part)3 to.docxHi i need a paper about (Head On )German film ( Turkey part)3 to.docx
Hi i need a paper about (Head On )German film ( Turkey part)3 to.docx
 
Hi i have new work can you do it, its due in 6 hours Boyd, Ga.docx
Hi i have new work can you do it, its due in 6 hours Boyd, Ga.docxHi i have new work can you do it, its due in 6 hours Boyd, Ga.docx
Hi i have new work can you do it, its due in 6 hours Boyd, Ga.docx
 
HIT Management and Implementation  Please respond to the followi.docx
HIT Management and Implementation  Please respond to the followi.docxHIT Management and Implementation  Please respond to the followi.docx
HIT Management and Implementation  Please respond to the followi.docx
 
History and TheoryConsiderthe eras, life histories.docx
History and TheoryConsiderthe eras, life histories.docxHistory and TheoryConsiderthe eras, life histories.docx
History and TheoryConsiderthe eras, life histories.docx
 
History of an argument Are there too many people There h.docx
History of an argument Are there too many people There h.docxHistory of an argument Are there too many people There h.docx
History of an argument Are there too many people There h.docx
 
history essays- 1000 words each essay- mla and 2 works cited. every .docx
history essays- 1000 words each essay- mla and 2 works cited. every .docxhistory essays- 1000 words each essay- mla and 2 works cited. every .docx
history essays- 1000 words each essay- mla and 2 works cited. every .docx
 
Historical Background of Housing PolicyHousing is one of the requi.docx
Historical Background of Housing PolicyHousing is one of the requi.docxHistorical Background of Housing PolicyHousing is one of the requi.docx
Historical Background of Housing PolicyHousing is one of the requi.docx
 

Recently uploaded

1029 - Danh muc Sach Giao Khoa 10 . pdf
1029 -  Danh muc Sach Giao Khoa 10 . pdf1029 -  Danh muc Sach Giao Khoa 10 . pdf
1029 - Danh muc Sach Giao Khoa 10 . pdf
QucHHunhnh
 
Seal of Good Local Governance (SGLG) 2024Final.pptx
Seal of Good Local Governance (SGLG) 2024Final.pptxSeal of Good Local Governance (SGLG) 2024Final.pptx
Seal of Good Local Governance (SGLG) 2024Final.pptx
negromaestrong
 
1029-Danh muc Sach Giao Khoa khoi 6.pdf
1029-Danh muc Sach Giao Khoa khoi  6.pdf1029-Danh muc Sach Giao Khoa khoi  6.pdf
1029-Danh muc Sach Giao Khoa khoi 6.pdf
QucHHunhnh
 
Activity 01 - Artificial Culture (1).pdf
Activity 01 - Artificial Culture (1).pdfActivity 01 - Artificial Culture (1).pdf
Activity 01 - Artificial Culture (1).pdf
ciinovamais
 
Russian Escort Service in Delhi 11k Hotel Foreigner Russian Call Girls in Delhi
Russian Escort Service in Delhi 11k Hotel Foreigner Russian Call Girls in DelhiRussian Escort Service in Delhi 11k Hotel Foreigner Russian Call Girls in Delhi
Russian Escort Service in Delhi 11k Hotel Foreigner Russian Call Girls in Delhi
kauryashika82
 

Recently uploaded (20)

Unit-IV- Pharma. Marketing Channels.pptx
Unit-IV- Pharma. Marketing Channels.pptxUnit-IV- Pharma. Marketing Channels.pptx
Unit-IV- Pharma. Marketing Channels.pptx
 
How to Give a Domain for a Field in Odoo 17
How to Give a Domain for a Field in Odoo 17How to Give a Domain for a Field in Odoo 17
How to Give a Domain for a Field in Odoo 17
 
Role Of Transgenic Animal In Target Validation-1.pptx
Role Of Transgenic Animal In Target Validation-1.pptxRole Of Transgenic Animal In Target Validation-1.pptx
Role Of Transgenic Animal In Target Validation-1.pptx
 
1029 - Danh muc Sach Giao Khoa 10 . pdf
1029 -  Danh muc Sach Giao Khoa 10 . pdf1029 -  Danh muc Sach Giao Khoa 10 . pdf
1029 - Danh muc Sach Giao Khoa 10 . pdf
 
Mixin Classes in Odoo 17 How to Extend Models Using Mixin Classes
Mixin Classes in Odoo 17  How to Extend Models Using Mixin ClassesMixin Classes in Odoo 17  How to Extend Models Using Mixin Classes
Mixin Classes in Odoo 17 How to Extend Models Using Mixin Classes
 
Seal of Good Local Governance (SGLG) 2024Final.pptx
Seal of Good Local Governance (SGLG) 2024Final.pptxSeal of Good Local Governance (SGLG) 2024Final.pptx
Seal of Good Local Governance (SGLG) 2024Final.pptx
 
Asian American Pacific Islander Month DDSD 2024.pptx
Asian American Pacific Islander Month DDSD 2024.pptxAsian American Pacific Islander Month DDSD 2024.pptx
Asian American Pacific Islander Month DDSD 2024.pptx
 
1029-Danh muc Sach Giao Khoa khoi 6.pdf
1029-Danh muc Sach Giao Khoa khoi  6.pdf1029-Danh muc Sach Giao Khoa khoi  6.pdf
1029-Danh muc Sach Giao Khoa khoi 6.pdf
 
Python Notes for mca i year students osmania university.docx
Python Notes for mca i year students osmania university.docxPython Notes for mca i year students osmania university.docx
Python Notes for mca i year students osmania university.docx
 
Measures of Central Tendency: Mean, Median and Mode
Measures of Central Tendency: Mean, Median and ModeMeasures of Central Tendency: Mean, Median and Mode
Measures of Central Tendency: Mean, Median and Mode
 
On National Teacher Day, meet the 2024-25 Kenan Fellows
On National Teacher Day, meet the 2024-25 Kenan FellowsOn National Teacher Day, meet the 2024-25 Kenan Fellows
On National Teacher Day, meet the 2024-25 Kenan Fellows
 
microwave assisted reaction. General introduction
microwave assisted reaction. General introductionmicrowave assisted reaction. General introduction
microwave assisted reaction. General introduction
 
Advanced Views - Calendar View in Odoo 17
Advanced Views - Calendar View in Odoo 17Advanced Views - Calendar View in Odoo 17
Advanced Views - Calendar View in Odoo 17
 
General Principles of Intellectual Property: Concepts of Intellectual Proper...
General Principles of Intellectual Property: Concepts of Intellectual  Proper...General Principles of Intellectual Property: Concepts of Intellectual  Proper...
General Principles of Intellectual Property: Concepts of Intellectual Proper...
 
Activity 01 - Artificial Culture (1).pdf
Activity 01 - Artificial Culture (1).pdfActivity 01 - Artificial Culture (1).pdf
Activity 01 - Artificial Culture (1).pdf
 
ICT role in 21st century education and it's challenges.
ICT role in 21st century education and it's challenges.ICT role in 21st century education and it's challenges.
ICT role in 21st century education and it's challenges.
 
Russian Escort Service in Delhi 11k Hotel Foreigner Russian Call Girls in Delhi
Russian Escort Service in Delhi 11k Hotel Foreigner Russian Call Girls in DelhiRussian Escort Service in Delhi 11k Hotel Foreigner Russian Call Girls in Delhi
Russian Escort Service in Delhi 11k Hotel Foreigner Russian Call Girls in Delhi
 
Food Chain and Food Web (Ecosystem) EVS, B. Pharmacy 1st Year, Sem-II
Food Chain and Food Web (Ecosystem) EVS, B. Pharmacy 1st Year, Sem-IIFood Chain and Food Web (Ecosystem) EVS, B. Pharmacy 1st Year, Sem-II
Food Chain and Food Web (Ecosystem) EVS, B. Pharmacy 1st Year, Sem-II
 
Micro-Scholarship, What it is, How can it help me.pdf
Micro-Scholarship, What it is, How can it help me.pdfMicro-Scholarship, What it is, How can it help me.pdf
Micro-Scholarship, What it is, How can it help me.pdf
 
Nutritional Needs Presentation - HLTH 104
Nutritional Needs Presentation - HLTH 104Nutritional Needs Presentation - HLTH 104
Nutritional Needs Presentation - HLTH 104
 

Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601Dr. Danielle Zanza

  • 1. Masters of Financial Economics, ADEC 73601 Dr. Danielle Zanzalari Problem Set 2 2018 Please follow the instructions listed on your syllabus regarding problem sets. I do not accept late work. Email me with any questions you have. 1. Using the VNM utility function of U(Y ) = Y 1−λ 1−λ where you could win $10,000 with probability 0.20 and lose $400 with probability 0.80 calculate the following if λ = 0.3 and Y = $2000: a) The expected return of this lottery. b) The relative risk aversion of this person. c) The absolute risk aversion of this person. d) The certainty equivalent. (Note: Follow the same set-up as the notes. Essentially you replace (E(Z)) with CE(Z), CE(Z) being the certainty equivalent.) 2. Crosby is considering investing in the following tech startups: African Water Nonprofit and Boston GoodWill to Go. Crosby has the following VNM utility function: U(Y ) = 30+Y − Y
  • 2. 2 200 where Y is in thousands. Crosby’s total income in $200,000 and would have to invest $50,000 in African Water Nonprofit with a probability of success of 50% and $75,000 in Boston GoodWill to Go with a 65% chance of success. If these start-ups are not successful he loses all of his money, whereas if they are successful he will retain his initial investment plus 10% and 15% return of each respective company. So, a) Will Crosby invest in either company? b) Would a risk neutral person make this investment? 3. What is the risk preference of investors with the following VNM utility functions? a) U(Y ) = √ Y b) U(Y ) = Y 2 c) U(Y ) = ln(Y ) d) U(Y ) = 10Y + 18 e) U(Y ) = Y 1−λ 1−λ
  • 3. 1 4. Alex has a wealth of $175,000, no health insurance and worker’s compensation does not apply. Alex has a 10% chance of losing $52,000, which is the probability he breaks his leg sliding into second base in a baseball game and the amount of money it would cost for hos- pital bills, rehabilitation and loss of work for a week. His utility function is: U(Y ) = Y 0.8 0.8 . Blue Cross Blue Shield of NYC offers the following policies and deductibles: Insurance Premium Deductible $4382 $1000 $4782 $500 $5502 $0 $3682 $1350 then which insurance policy (if any) will Alex choose and why? 5. Use the Condo Price excel spreadsheet, sourced from Zillow, on the mean condo prices of the top 10 cities in the U.S. to help you answer the following questions. Please use Stata, R, Matlab or Excel and submit your code along with your
  • 4. answers written down. a) Using the 10 cities in the Excel spreadsheet and the assumption that house prices rise on average 7% a year and mortgage costs are 6%. Our debt to equity ratio is 4. Based on what you calculate the expected return on our levered investment to be and what you view the house price of the following year, does it make sense to buy a condo in each of these cities and in each of these years? Do not calculate this by each month. Please just use year-06 numbers (i.e. Use numbers from June each year for all problems. So, use 2010-06 to estimate the expected return on your levered investment if you sold in 2011-06. Evaluate your expected return with the actual return. Please do this for each city and for 2010-2018.) b) Now, let’s assume that we put down 5% in our condo in Boston, Massachusetts and borrow the rest. Our borrowing costs go up 8% since we must pay PMI (an extra cost for not putting down 20% equity). If we want to ensure we make a return of 5% on our levered investment, what must our expected return on our unlevered investment be in Boston, Massachusetts for each year? Does it make sense to do a levered investment then? c) Look at Dallas-Fort-Worth, Texas, let’s assume that we put 10% down on our condo and our borrowing costs are 5%. For what states of the world (i.e. for what unlevered
  • 5. return) does a levered investment not make sense? d) Using the numbers you calculate above in part c., calculate the risk of each Dallas-Fort Worth investment assuming that the standard deviation of the unlevered investment is 2%. e) (EXTRA CREDIT: 10 pts)Lastly, the expected return on our levered investment does not take into account the tax benefits of owning a condo (or home). How would you propose we consider the tax benefits in the home purchase leverage equation we have been discussing? 2 Chaucer's Pardoner on the Couch: Psyche and Clio in Medieval Literary Studies Author(s): Lee Patterson Source: Speculum, Vol. 76, No. 3 (Jul., 2001), pp. 638-680 Published by: The University of Chicago Press on behalf of the Medieval Academy of America Stable URL: https://www.jstor.org/stable/2903882 Accessed: 15-05-2019 02:22 UTC REFERENCES Linked references are available on JSTOR for this article:
  • 6. https://www.jstor.org/stable/2903882?seq=1&cid=pdf- reference#references_tab_contents You may need to log in to JSTOR to access the linked references. JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected] Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at https://about.jstor.org/terms Medieval Academy of America, The University of Chicago Press are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Speculum This content downloaded from 128.228.0.65 on Wed, 15 May 2019 02:22:27 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms Chaucer's Pardoner on the Couch: Psyche and Clio in Medieval Literary Studies By Lee Patterson
  • 7. I, too, was greatly impressed when I first read Freud. He's extraordinary. Of course he is full of fishy thinking & his charm & the charm of the subject is so great that you may easily be fooled. -Ludwig Wittgenstein1 Thus one virtuoso of twentieth-century thought responded to the spell cast over his culture by a virtuoso of the previous generation-his response recording a now familiar progress from the spellbound to the disenchanted. Wittgenstein's shrewdness, however, remains as yet part of only a minority tradition of skepticism about the value of Freudianism, and psychoanalysis in general, to contemporary literary critics. This essay is a contribution to that skepticism as it applies to lit- erary interpretation, a philosophically much narrower terrain than Wittgenstein's genial critique envisaged, but one in which fishy thinking is no less to be avoided. The essay falls into six sections. The first describes the enthusiastic adoption of psychoanalytic concepts into medieval studies at the very moment when they are suffering a collapse of credibility in the real world. Part 2 summarizes the fatal flaws now widely perceived in psychoanalytic and specifically Freudian methods of inquiry, especially in its cavalier unconcern with questions of evidence and validity. In part 3 I use an apposite test case that almost irresistibly attracts psy-
  • 8. choanalytic readings-Chaucer's Pardoner and his tale-to assess the usefulness or otherwise of psychoanalytic assumptions in literary interpretation. Parts 4 and 5 offer an alternative reading of the Pardoner and his tale that interprets the symbolic structure by reference to discourses that are not simply medieval but specifically contemporary to Chaucer. The essay concludes with some reflections on the place of theory-whether psychoanalytic or of some other variety-in medieval literary studies. The goal of this essay is not to foreclose discussion but exactly the opposite. For an interpretive program to be taken seriously it must both examine the foun- This essay was first written for a symposium organized at the University of Oklahoma by George Economou in March 1996, and versions have subsequently been given at various institutions, much to its benefit. It has been read by six readers for Speculum, all of whom-and especially those who found it unworthy of publication-have helped me to clarify the argument. I would like especially to thank Richard Emmerson for his detailed and perceptive comments, Michael Wenthe for his scrupulous inspection of the last but one version, and Annabel Patterson for her editorial brutality. 1 Cited by Norman Malcolm, Ludwig Wittgenstein: A Memoir, 2nd ed. (Oxford, 1984), p. 100. Wittgenstein explained Freud's power in terms of the modern commitment to the idea that the inner
  • 9. self has uncharted depths: the "peculiar charm" of psychoanalytic explanations, he said, derives from "the idea of an underworld, a secret cellar" (Lectures and Conversations on Aesthetics, Psychology and Religious Belief, ed. Cyril Barrett [Berkeley, Calif., 1966], p. 25). Speculum 76 (2001) 638 This content downloaded from 128.228.0.65 on Wed, 15 May 2019 02:22:27 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms Chaucer's Pardoner on the Couch dations on which it rests and meet, with as full and receptive an attitude as pos- sible, the objections to which it is susceptible. I have tried neither to travesty the assumptions I question nor to score rhetorical points. I have read as widely as I could in the relevant material and seek here to present the results in a straight- forward manner, without misrepresentation. If this essay is to serve as a way of opening a discussion on the interpretive appropriateness of psychoanalysis-a conversation that is clearly long overdue-then one hopes that those who disagree with its conclusions will do the same. 1. THE FREUDIAN CHARM We start our intellectual lives under the spell. Our vernacular
  • 10. culture is saturated with terms and concepts derived from psychoanalytic theory: repression, resis- tance, the unconscious, the anal personality, threatened masculinity and castration fear, a belief that our every activity is invested with libido, and above all a suspicion that everything means something other, and usually something darker, than it seems-these terms and concepts, and the way of thinking they enable and en- courage, are a central part of the shared habits of thought by which we learn, for good or ill, to make sense of our lives. More tangibly, our society devotes sub- stantial resources to mental health workers who deploy technologies of the self that derive ultimately if not directly from the Freudian system. Quite apart from the vast number of more or less professional therapists who service what has been called "the identity market,"2 there are school counselors, penologists, expert wit- nesses, social workers, and even (if they are not careful) university professors who dispense more or less expert advice that bears a real, if usually ill-defined, relation to Freudian theory. If the twentieth century has witnessed what Philip Rieff has called "the emergence of psychological man," we must remember that we are not merely observers of that momentous event but its effect.3 We are psychological men and women, shaped by structures of thought and feeling that derive directly from the work of Freud and his disciples.
  • 11. But even while agreeing with the statement that the invention and spread of Freudian theory represent "the attainment of a new degree of consciousness in Western civilization," one may still ask if it is a higher form of consciousness and, in particular applications, whether it is a help or hindrance to thought.4 There are, to be sure, very good reasons for the modern triumph of psychoanalytic modes of thought and interpretation. For one thing, Freudianism functioned for the first half of the twentieth century as a liberatory alternative to far less humane modes of explaining human actions, especially geneticism (and its deadly offspring, eu- genics) and behaviorism. Particularly important in this regard is the psychoana- 2 Peter L. Berger, "Towards a Sociological Understanding of Psychoanalysis," Social Research 32 (1965), 26-41, at p. 37. 3 Philip Rieff, Freud: The Mind of the Moralist (Garden City, N.Y., 1961), pp. 361-92. 4 Steven Marcus, Freud and the Culture of Psychoanalysis: Studies in the Transition from Victorian Humanism to Modernity (Boston, 1984), p. 7. For a similar, highly influential account of Freudianism as modernity, see Lionel Trilling, "Freud: Within and beyond Culture," a lecture delivered to the New York Psychoanalytic Institute in 1955 and printed in Beyond Culture (New York, 1965), pp. 89-118.
  • 12. 639 This content downloaded from 128.228.0.65 on Wed, 15 May 2019 02:22:27 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms Chaucer's Pardoner on the Couch lytic refusal to pass moral judgment on almost all forms of behavior, especially sexual. As Freud said more than once, psychoanalysis has no "concern whatsoever with judgments of value."5 To be against psychoanalysis was, from the period of 1920 to 1960 or so, to be against reforms in child rearing, education, the treatment of sexual minorities, and many other clearly progressive causes.6 Another benign aspect of Freudian psychologism has been its ability to address (if not necessarily to remedy) aspects of modern life-especially familial and other interpersonal relationships-that the dominant individualism and privatism of modern urban life, in which the self is experienced as threatened and fragile, have made central to a sense of well-being. Thus it is that "twentieth-century societies have produced 'psychology' as a specialized form of knowledge and set of techniques."7 And as many have said, psychoanalysis has produced a humanistic substitute for religion in an increasingly secular culture. As Wittgenstein recognized, Freud restored to
  • 13. modernity some of the mystery that the disenchantments of rationality were threatening to strip away forever. In a world in which everything is potentially knowable to instrumental reason, psychoanalysis can satisfy a Romantic desire for a realm of deep meaning that is unknown and perhaps even unknowable. Whether it can now be seen to have achieved this without imposing a new creed, immune to empirical critique, is part of my concern. If psychoanalysis can thus rightly be seen, in retrospect, as part of the Enlight- enment project of modernity, we are now in a position to assess its claim to sci- entific rationality and the ratification of that claim by its inclusion within the professional citadel of medicine.8 Freud always thought of himself as a scientist and of psychoanalysis as an empirical science. "I take no pride in having avoided speculation," he said, because "the material for my hypotheses was collected by the most extensive and laborious series of observations."9 He speaks often of the 5 Cited by Philip Rieff, who rightly says that "psychoanalysis is the first great system of therapy to divorce itself from some moral aim or doctrine; that suggests its historic importance" (Freud: The Mind of the Moralist, p. 368). As Freud himself said, "Psycho- analysis finds no occasion for conceal- ments and hints, it does not think it necessary to be ashamed of dealing with this important material, it believes it is right and proper to call everything by its correct
  • 14. name" (Introductory Lectures on Psycho-Analysis [1915-16], in Standard Edition of the Complete Psychological Works of Sigmund Freud, 24 vols., trans. James Strachey et al. [London, 1953-74], 15:154). All subsequent references are to this edition, abbreviated SE. 6 See Nathan G. Hale, Jr., The Rise and Crisis of Psychoanalysis in America, 2: Freud and the Americans, 1917-1985 (New York, 1995). Despite its inflammatory and misleading title, Edwin Fuller Torrey, Freudian Fraud: The Malignant Effect of Freud's Theory on American Thought and Culture (New York, 1992), provides a useful history of the progressiveness of Freudian thought with a wealth of specific examples, especially Margaret Mead and Benjamin Spock. 7 Barry Richards, Images of Freud: Cultural Responses to Psychoanalysis (London, 1989), p. 23. 8 For the combination of Romantic and Enlightenment features in Freud's thought, see Harry Tros- man, "Freud's Cultural Background," in John E. Gedo and George H. Pollock, eds., Freud: The Fusion of Science and Humanism (New York, 1976), pp. 46-70. Psychoanalysis is both deterministic and liberating: deterministic (in its Romantic mode) in that it insists that all behaviors are caused by hidden, powerful forces, liberating (in its Enlightenment mode) in arguing that we can come to understand and control those determining forces: see Richard Stevens, Freud and Psychoanalysis: An Exposition and Appraisal (New York, 1983), pp. 135-37. 9 "Fragment of an Analysis of a Case of Hysteria" (1905), SE
  • 15. 7:113. See also, for example, Intro- ductory Lectures on Psycho-Analysis (1916-17), SE 16:244-45. 640 This content downloaded from 128.228.0.65 on Wed, 15 May 2019 02:22:27 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms Chaucer's Pardoner on the Couch "data" and "factual evidence" upon which he has based his explanations and asserts throughout his work that "the intellect and the mind are objects for sci- entific research in exactly the same way as any non-human things."10 But in recent decades psychoanalysis as a scientifically reliable system of thought has lost much of its intellectual status, and in the second part of this essay I will lay out the main arguments for its demise. This doubt has spread even to the popular press. The cover story of the November 29, 1993, issue of Time magazine was entitled "Is Freud Dead?" and the June 15, 1998, issue of Der Spiegel-its cover story entitled "Die Psycho Falle"-features a visual lineup of similar mag- azine covers from the United States, France, and Germany.11 The most persistent attempt to counter this widespread disillusionment is to argue that Freud's claims
  • 16. to the scientific status of his theories stemmed from what Paul Ricoeur has called his "scientistic self-misunderstanding," and that psychoanalysis should therefore be understood not as an empirical science but simply as a hermeneutic, a method of interpretation.12 But such a tactic has to accept (as does Ricoeur) the fact that because "psychoanalysis is itself a work of speech with the patient," then the most it needs to produce is a narrative that the patient finds acceptable, whether it is accurate or not.13 The hermeneutic rescue of psychoanalysis, in other words, de- nies Freud his claim to have discovered the causes of human behavior and settles for meanings "discovered" by the analyst: in the attempt to rescue psychoanalysis as a therapy, it destroys it as a general theory of human behavior. The fact is, if psychoanalysis is to provide a reliable paradigm for understanding human behav- ior-especially premodern behavior, and all the more the behavior of characters created by premodern writers-then it must not be denied its claim to scientific truth. As Freud himself said, "I have always felt it as a gross injustice that people have refused to treat psycho-analysis like any other science."14 10 New Introductory Lectures on Psycho-Analysis (1933), SE 22:159. Freud continues with an ar- gument that practitioners of psychoanalytic criticism might find unpalatable: "It is not permissible to
  • 17. declare that science is one field of human mental activity and that religion and philosophy are others, at least equal in value, and that science has no business to interfere with the other two. ... A view of this kind is regarded as particularly superior, tolerant, broad- minded and free from illiberal prejudices. Unfortunately it is not tenable.... It is simply a fact that the truth cannot be tolerant" (p. 160). 1 Der Spiegel 25 (1998), 199. 12 Paul Ricoeur, Freud and Philosophy: An Essay on Interpretation, trans. Denis Savage (New Haven, Conn., 1970). 13 The citation from Ricoeur is from Freud and Philosophy, p. 369. The hermeneutic interpretations of Ricoeur and Jiirgen Habermas are subjected to a withering analysis by Adolf Griinbaum, The Foundations of Psychoanalysis: A Philosophical Critique (Berkeley, Calif., 1984), pp. 1-94. See also the comments by the psychoanalyst Robert R. Holt, Freud Reappraised: A Fresh Look at Psychoan- alytic Theory (New York, 1989), p. 337, and by the textual critic Sebastiano Timpanaro, The Freudian Slip: Psychoanalysis and Textual Criticism, trans. Kate Soper (London, 1976). For Timpanaro, the hermeneutic rescue of Freud manages only to transform "psychoanalysis into a pastiche of Husserl or Heidegger, orienting it towards a mysticism that evokes Jung much more than Freud" (p. 17). Tim- panaro later characterizes Ricoeur's version of Freud as "a strange brew of Freudianism and religion, in which the more imbued with mystery an interpretation, the better it pleases" (p. 181)-a version of Wittgenstein's point (n. 1, above).
  • 18. 14 An Autobiographical Study (1925), SE 20:58. The other way of protecting Freudianism from its own claims is to declare that the practices and results of empirical science are no longer operative in the brave new world of postmodernism: see Paul Robinson, Freud and His Critics (Berkeley, Calif., 641 This content downloaded from 128.228.0.65 on Wed, 15 May 2019 02:22:27 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms Chaucer's Pardoner on the Couch Moreover, even the hermeneutic model-which is now therapeutically domi- nant-requires a dialogue between analyst and patient in which the patient's con- tribution is acknowledged as essential. As the object-relations analyst Heinz Kohut has said, "If there is one lesson that I have learned during my life as an analyst, it is the lesson that what my patients tell me is likely to be true-that many times when I believed that I was right and my patients were wrong, it turned out, though often only after a prolonged search, that my rightness was superficial whereas their rightness was profound."15 But while this may be true for real people in contemporary therapy, such a dialogue is impossible with persons, either real or
  • 19. fictional, who can only give evidence of their psyches in fixed texts. George Pig- man, who is both a literary critic and a practicing analyst, has pointed out that "patients can object to interpretations and thereby further understanding; texts and documents cannot. [As used by literary critics], applied psychoanalysis is therefore barred from the feature of the psychoanalytic process which gives the greatest confidence in the validity of interpretations and reconstructions."16 Yet despite the adjustments within the therapeutic community, the now large literature criticizing the truth claims of Freud and his followers, and the reasonably well informed discussions in the popular press, the news of the demise of psycho- analysis as a reliable mode of inquiry seems not to have reached the small circle of academic literary and cultural criticism. Here psychoanalysis in its various guises-whether as orthodox Freudianism or in Lacanian or post- Lacanian revi- sionary forms-remains not just a powerful influence but a paradigm for inter- pretation and a largely unquestioned source of authority. According to a survey done in 1977-78 of the most heavily cited twentieth-century authors in the arts and humanities, Freud was by far the most common name to appear.17 Over twenty years later the situation has not changed: in the decade of the 1990s, at least 921 books, and who knows how many articles, have been
  • 20. published that deal explicitly and centrally with psychoanalysis and literature, to say nothing of 1993), and Marcus R. Bowman, "On the Idea of Natural Science as a Resistance to Psychoanalysis," Psychoanalysis and Contemporary Thought 19 (1996), 371-402. Both these authors use the familiar psychoanalytic strategy of psychoanalyzing their opponents, while the topic at issue is defended not by appeals to evidence but by the assumption that it is true. As Karl Kraus said as long ago as 1913 in exasperation with his psychoanalytically besotted friends, "If I tell them they can kiss my ass, I must have an anal predilection.... They have caught me!" (cited and translated by Jacques Bouveresse, Wittgenstein Reads Freud: The Myth of the Unconscious, trans. Carol Cosman [Princeton, N.J., 1995], p. 16). 15 Heinz Kohut, How Does Analysis Cure? (Chicago, 1984), pp. 93-94; cited by G. W. Pigman III, "Applied Psychoanalysis Today," Criticism 34 (1992), 299-315, at p. 308. 16 Ibid., p. 309. For similar demurrals, see Gail S. Reed, "Psychoanalysis, Psychoanalysis Appropri- ated, Psychoanalysis Applied," Psychoanalytic Quarterly 54 (1985), 234-69, and Peter Lamarque, "On the Irrelevance of Psychoanalysis to Literary Criticism," in Peter Clark and Crispin Wright, eds., Mind, Psychoanalysis and Science (Oxford, 1988), pp. 257-73. 17 Allan Megill, "The Reception of Foucault by Historians," Journal of the History of Ideas 48 (1987), 117-41, at pp. 139-40. Freud was cited 966 times, with
  • 21. the next name being that of Roland Barthes, cited 678 times. It should be pointed out that Lenin led the list with 1,737 citations; but if Soviet journals were excluded, his name virtually disappeared. Jung's name appeared 338 times, and Lacan's 210. 642 This content downloaded from 128.228.0.65 on Wed, 15 May 2019 02:22:27 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms Chaucer's Pardoner on the Couch all the critical writing in which psychoanalytic categories remain implicit and therefore invisible to search engines.18 It might be thought that medieval studies, with its traditional commitment to empiricist methodologies and its mistrust of explicitly nonhistoricist interpretive paradigms, would be resistant to this trend. But medieval literary critics have long been anxious not to be perceived as intellectually backward, and the most obvious way to avoid that stigma is to display familiarity with some form of what the literary academy currently designates as theory. In a recent review article Louise Fradenburg announces that "psychoanalysis is simply in medieval studies now" and provides a bibliography that includes some 45 items that
  • 22. explicitly depend upon psychoanalytic theories.19 One could easily add to the list.20 There are few critics, especially those dealing explicitly with questions of gender and sexuality, who do not at least implicitly accept the Freudian account of sexual formation. I have now turned, obviously, to a field-specific interrogation of Freudianism- very field-specific, since I do not address the use of Freudian theory in literary studies in general but rather as a fairly recent development within medieval studies. In literary studies generally, or in literary theory, there has been more interest, perhaps, in psychoanalysis as a kind of hermeneutics, as a model for doing inter- pretation rather than as a model of behavior. But in medieval studies there has been a rush backwards, as it were, to Freud's beliefs about human sexuality and its dominance as a force in character formation and pathology. An example from Chaucer studies, taken almost at random, is the discussion of the Miller's Tale by Elaine Tuttle Hansen, who argues that the tale commodifies women, expresses a "horror" of their sexuality, and bespeaks a profound if unrecognized homoso- ciality/homosexuality.21 The presuppositions that enable this condemnatory read- ing derive ultimately, if unwittingly, from Freud. According to Hansen, grabbing 18 This figure was arrived at through a keyword search of the
  • 23. database of the WorldCat (http:// newfirstsearch.oclc.org). 19 "Analytical Survey 2: We Are Not Alone: Psychoanalytic Medievalism," New Medieval Litera- tures 2 (1998), 249-76. 20 In addition to the titles provided by Fradenburg, a sample of recent books that apply psychoan- alytic categories of interpretation to cultural materials includes Jane Chance, ed., Gender and Text in the Later Middle Ages (Gainesville, Fla., 1996); E. Jane Burns, Bodytalk: When Women Speak in Old French Literature (Philadelphia, 1993); Gregory B. Stone, The Death of the Troubadour: The Late Medieval Resistance to the Renaissance (Philadelphia, 1994); Karma Lochrie, Peggy McCracken, and James A. Schultz, eds., Constructing Medieval Sexuality, Medieval Cultures 11 (Minneapolis, 1997); Catherine S. Cox, Gender and Language in Chaucer (Gainesville, Fla., 1997); Karma Lochrie, Covert Operations: The Medieval Uses of Secrecy (Philadelphia, 1999); Clare A. Lees, ed., Medieval Mascu- linities: Regarding Men in the Middle Ages, Medieval Cultures 7 (Minneapolis, 1994); Jeffrey Jerome Cohen and Bonnie Wheeler, eds., Becoming Male in the Middle Ages, Garland Reference Library of the Humanities 2066, New Middle Ages 4 (New York, 1997); John Carmi Parsons and Bonnie Wheeler, eds., Medieval Mothering, Garland Reference Library of the Humanities 1979, New Middle Ages 3 (New York, 1996), pp. 63-75, 183-99; Kathleen Biddick, The Shock of Medievalism (Durham, N.C., 1998); Carolyn Dinshaw, Getting Medieval: Sexualities and Communities, Pre- and Postmodern (Dur- ham, N.C., 1999); Jeffrey Jerome Cohen, Of Giants: Sex,
  • 24. Monsters, and the Middle Ages, Medieval Cultures 17 (Minneapolis, 1999); Dyan Elliott, Fallen Bodies: Pollution, Sexuality, and Demonology in the Middle Ages (Philadelphia, 1999); and Paul Strohm, England's Empty Throne: Usurpation and the Language of Legitimation, 1399-1422 (New Haven, Conn., 1998). 21 Elaine Tuttle Hansen, Chaucer and the Fictions of Gender (Berkeley, Calif., 1992), pp. 223-36. 643 This content downloaded from 128.228.0.65 on Wed, 15 May 2019 02:22:27 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 644 Chaucer's Pardoner on the Couch the red-hot iron from the forge is Absolon's attempt to reassert his masculinity, and his desire to hurt Alison implies a connection among homosexuality, homo- phobia, and misogyny. But this reasonable explanation of a fabliau's typically coarse revenge is expressed as follows: "the boy-child [Absolon] has in this case felt, although not seen, the lack that seems to mark the place of women's sexual organs, and his response indicates both guilt and fear for his own as yet unproven difference and dominance, his phallus."22 This reading depends, then, upon Freud's theory that oedipalized men are by definition appalled
  • 25. by female sexuality. Thus for Hansen the Miller's Tale "effects the conventional association or confla- tion of (female) genital and anal functions, of women's sex (or sex with a woman) and dirt, decay, and dissolution."23 My point here is to suggest that this and similar readings of medieval texts, while they may be invigoratingly consistent with the political temper of the times, may also be intellectually misleading-for at least three reasons. First, they ignore the now ubiquitous skepticism about the truth claims of the very theories they take as presuppositions. Second, they extend what is now accepted as a dialogic method of therapy to a one-way analysis of fictional characters who must stand mute before their analyst. And third, they rise to the defense of their method by attacking another method of understanding literary texts from the past-histor- icism.24 What they actually attack, however, is a parodic version of historicism, a 22 Ibid., p. 230. 23 Ibid., p. 227; italics added. A similar reading of the Miller's Tale is offered by Karma Lochrie, "Women's 'Pryvetees' and Fabliau Politics in the Miller's Tale," Exemplaria 6 (1994), 287-304. This argument depends in the first instance upon Gayle Rubin's classic essay, "The Traffic in Women: Notes on the 'Political Economy' of Sex," in Rayna R. Reiter, ed.,
  • 26. Toward an Anthropology of Women (New York, 1975), pp. 157-210. Rubin reinterprets Levi-Strauss's analysis of kinship in terms of the Freud- ian account of "the Oedipal complex [as] a machine which fashions the appropriate forms of sexual individuals" (Rubin, p. 189). Both Lochrie and Hansen thus rely on two assumptions: that Freud's account of the creation of sexual identity by means of the Oedipus complex is true; and that, in Rubin's words, "the paleolithic relations of sexuality are still with us" (p. 191)-i.e., that the political economy of the sex/gender system that Rubin derives from Freud is a universal constituent of human societies, be it late-medieval England or the contemporary United States. 24 Many people have offered workable definitions of historicist methodology; my own attempt may be found in Negotiating the Past: The Historical Understanding of Medieval Literature (Madison, Wis., 1987), pp. 3-74. An excellent summary of recent work, with examples, may be found in Kiernan Ryan, ed., New Historicism and Cultural Materialism: A Reader (London, 1996); see especially pp. 43-44. A classic defense of psychoanalytic literary criticism can be found in Peter Brooks, "The Idea of a Psychoanalytic Literary Criticism," in Shlomith Rimmon- Kenan, ed., Discourse in Psychoanalysis and Literature, University Paperbacks 960 (London, 1987), pp. 1-18, and Psychoanalysis and Sto- rytelling, Bucknell Lectures in Literary Theory 10 (Oxford, 1994). Brooks acknowledges that any psychoanalytic criticism worthy of the name must take the Freudian account of the mind as a privileged model that reveals the central truth of human behavior. This means, in Brooks's words, accepting "the psychoanalytic view of humans as radically determined by
  • 27. sexuality.... Human desire emerges subject to the 'laws' dictated by the castration complex and the Oedipal triangle-emerges, that is, as desire inhabited by loss and prohibition" (Psychoanalysis and Storytelling, p. 25). In "'Be Not Far from Me': Psychoanalysis, Medieval Studies and the Subject of Religion," Exemplaria 7 (1995), 41-54, Louise O. Fradenburg defends the relevance of psychoanalysis to medieval studies by asserting that "psycho- analysis takes us to the heart of our histories of loss and desire, to the heart of the history of culture, or 'civilization,' as a history of the production and regulation of pleasure and loss" (p. 44)-a statement that is another version of Brooks's account. But neither Fradenburg nor Brooks confronts the critiques This content downloaded from 128.228.0.65 on Wed, 15 May 2019 02:22:27 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms Chaucer's Pardoner on the Couch 645 naive positivism that believes in the absolute "alterity" of the past. Such a histor- icism has not been thought possible since at least Nietzsche, Dilthey, and Weber, let alone Foucault, Jameson, and E. P. Thompson.25 Constantly to invoke D. W. Robertson and a few of his students as proof of the benightedness of medieval historicism is misleading in a double sense: it is blind to the very different kinds of historicism that medieval literary scholars now practice, and it dismisses the
  • 28. very real contribution to our understanding of the Middle Ages that Robertson made, since he taught us much about the ubiquity of the medieval tradition of exegetical reading. Another line of defense-as-attack is to psychoanalyze historicists as reverent if mournful seekers after a hopelessly lost past, a strategy that reduces the many different motives that inspire historical scholarship to compensation for a psycho- analytically posited "lack."26 This move endows the analyst with the assurance that she understands others better than they can understand themselves. The charge, however, not only begs the question but depends on an assumed identity of memory and history. As a psychic phenomenon, memory is a mental function confined to personal experience; as a disciplinary practice, history is an episte- mological effort directed toward the experience of others, all of whom are (for the medievalist) dead. We cannot now remember the medieval past but only learn about it. And even as a collective phenomenon, memory both extends back only a short way into the past and has to do, as is well illustrated by the monumental of psychoanalytic theory that have appeared over the last twenty-five years. A defense of psychoanalysis as an aid to historical understanding is provided by Peter Gay, Freud for Historians (New York, 1985), but Gay does little to counter the arguments of David E.
  • 29. Stannard, Shrinking History: On Freud and the Failure of Psychohistory (New York, 1980). For a thorough critique of Gay's version of Freud that is itself sympathetic to psychoanalysis, see John E. Toews, "Historicizing Psychoanalysis: Freud in His Time and for Our Time," Journal of Modern History 63 (1991), 504-45. 25 This accusation has been most persistently made by Louise Fradenburg, from her initial creation of the straw man of historicist backwardness in "Criticism, Anti-Semitism, and the Prioress's Tale," Exemplaria 1 (1989), 69-115, through to her most recent work in "We Are Not Alone: Psychoanalytic Medievalism." There she posits an opposition between those unnamed scholars who "still insist on the radical alterity of the past, the incommunication of epistemes, and the uselessness of generalizing about the 'local' and the 'specific"' and the psychoanalytic medievalists who avoid those errors and thus possess "a better understanding of the ethical and political commitments of medievalist practice" (pp. 262-63, my italics). 26 See again Fradenburg, "Criticism, Anti-Semitism, and the Prioress's Tale," and her "Be Not Far from Me"; Gayle Margherita, The Romance of Origins: Language and Sexual Difference in Middle English Literature (Philadelphia, 1994), pp. 82-88, 100-107; and Biddick's Shock of Medievalism, which founds itself on Fradenburg's claims. Even Peter Gay admits that "the days are gone when the followers of Freud can discredit rational criticism by psychoanalyzing the critic" (Freud for Historians, p. 7). Yet on the very next page he refers to historians who reject psychoanalytic methods as "anxious
  • 30. and therefore hostile" (p. 8) and later asserts that "the unflagging ardor of the counterattacks is therefore a symptom rather than a necessary response" (p. 17). The same tactic appears in Jonathan Lear, Open Minded: Working Out the Logic of the Soul (Cambridge, Mass., 1998), pp. 16-32. As Freud himself said, "One of the first applications of psycho- analysis was to teach us to understand the opposition offered to us by our contemporaries because we practised psycho-analysis" (New Intro- ductory Lectures, SE 22:145). This content downloaded from 128.228.0.65 on Wed, 15 May 2019 02:22:27 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms Chaucer's Pardoner on the Couch project led by Pierre Nora, primarily with the definition of the modern nation.27 As for the recent argument that historicism is doomed to "the task of replicating, however hopelessly, medieval culture's self-understandings," while psychoanaly- sis, from a superior posture, explores "the ways in which medieval culture might have misunderstood itself," one must ask how to recognize a misunderstanding without already knowing what correct understanding might be.28 Like old-fash- ioned Marxism, psychoanalysis wants to believe that it has a pipeline to the truth, the only difference being that the Marxist's long-abandoned "false consciousness"
  • 31. is here replaced by the psychoanalyst's gentler "misunderstanding" or (Zizek's use of Lacan's term) "misrecognition."29 To mention Slavoj Zizek will alert my readers to the fact that what follows-a summary of the arguments against psychoanalysis both as method and as expla- nation-is focused almost exclusively on Freud. It could be objected that I am aiming at the wrong target because the current psychoanalytic theory of choice is that propounded by Jacques Lacan or what is termed "post- Lacanian psycho- analysis," particularly as proposed by Ziiek. But Lacan rightly insisted that his entire project was a "return to Freud," and as Malcolm Bowie has said, in what is probably the best guide to this obscurantist writer, Lacan's "loyalty to Freud is intense, and the originality he seeks is that of an inspired and devoted reader, one who can think fruitfully only from inside someone else's text."30 This is not to say that Lacan's relation to Freud is not complex and shifting, nor that he does not finally differ from Freud in ways important to psychoanalytic theory, perhaps most significantly in locating within the ego itself a powerful irrationality-he refers to it at one point as an "organization of the passions"31-and in his promotion of language as an impersonal force that constructs subjectivity. But the entire Lacan- ian project is located within the context of the Freudian model of the formation
  • 32. of the personality. Lacan's four fundamental concepts of psychoanalysis are the unconscious, repetition, transference, and the drive; subjectivity is formed through infantile experience; and the lack that constitutes desire is a function of the fear of castration created by the Name of the Father. Like Freud, Lacan presented his work as at once scientific (despite his disdain for evidence) and universalist. Ad- mittedly, given his replacement of Freud's id, ego, and superego with his ontolog- 27 Pierre Nora, ed., Les lieux de memoire, 3 vols. in 7 (Paris, 1984-92). There are clear if unremarked affinities between Fradenburg's claims and Nora's project, with its emphasis on the sadness of the postmodern that has lost a living connection to the past and its promotion of the postmodern historian who both "meditate[s]" on his "personal liaison" with the past and makes it "not the obstacle, but the means of his understanding" (cited by Jeremy D. Popkin, "Historians on the Autobiographical Frontier," American Historical Review 104 [1999], 725-48, at p. 731). But both Fradenburg and Nora are stating positions that are hardly postmodern: they have been familiar since at least the Romantic historiography of Michelet and the historical hermeneutics of Dilthey. 28 "Be Not Far from Me," pp. 45, 47. 29 Slavoj Ziiek, The Sublime Object of Ideology (London, 1989), pp. 55-84. 30 Malcolm Bowie, Lacan (Cambridge, Mass., 1991), p. 7. For other accounts of Lacan's theories
  • 33. within their Freudian framework, see Jean Laplanche and Jean- Bertrand Pontalis, The Language of Psycho-analysis, trans. Donald Nicholson-Smith (New York, 1973), and Samuel Weber, Return to Freud: Jacques Lacan's Dislocation of Psychoanalysis, trans. Michael Levine, Literature, Culture, The- ory 1 (Cambridge, Eng., 1991). 31 Jacques Lacan, Ecrits: A Selection, trans. Alan Sheridan (New York, 1977), p. 19. 646 This content downloaded from 128.228.0.65 on Wed, 15 May 2019 02:22:27 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms Chaucer's Pardoner on the Couch ical triad of the Imaginary, Symbolic, and Real, Lacan is more truly a metaphy- sician (or theologian) than a psychologist. But if the Freudian foundations on which his work rests are unreliable, then his own enterprise (however we define it) can hardly stand as an accurate account of human behavior.32 As for Zizek, his neo-Lacanian psychoanalysis of culture has a political and sociological interest that is lacking in Lacan himself. But his unqualified commitment to Lacanian categories renders his work equally dependent-at one remove- on Freud.33 It is with Freud that psychoanalysis begins and ends (as Freud
  • 34. himself rightly predicted it always would), and it is thus with Freud that the literary critic must come to terms. In any case, as the psychoanalyst Robert Holt has said, "When the foun- dations of our house are tottering, it makes no sense to argue about rival designs for new wallpaper."34 2. THE CASE AGAINST PSYCHOANALYSIS For the last quarter of a century much of Freud's work, and hence psychoan- alytic theory as a whole (as opposed to the many varieties of psychotherapy now on offer), has been subject to a devastating critique. According to Frederick Crews, the one anti-Freudian known at least by reputation to literary scholars, "there is literally nothing to be said, scientifically or therapeutically, to the advantage of the entire Freudian system or any of its component dogmas."35 Those are strong words, but they are supported by a substantial and growing body of work that has demolished, both systematically and in detail, the theoretical and institutional house that Freud built. This work can no longer be ignored or evaded by literary critics.36 32 Criticisms of Lacan as severe as those leveled against Freud are not far to seek: see, for instance, FranSois Roustang, The Lacanian Delusion, trans. Greg Sims (New York, 1990); Luc Ferry and Alain Renaut, French Philosophy of the Sixties: An Essay on
  • 35. Antihumanism, trans. Mary H. S. Cattani (Amherst, Mass., 1990), pp. 185-207; and an article posted on the Web by Norman N. Holland, "The Trouble(s) with Lacan" (1998), at http://web.clas.ufl.edu/users/nnh/lacan.htm. 33 Ziiek's Lacanian commitments are everywhere visible in his work, but perhaps nowhere more explicitly than in the essay "Fetishism and Its Vicissitudes," in The Plague of Fantasies (London, 1997), pp. 86-126. 34 Freud Reappraised, p. 338. 35 Frederick Crews, "The Verdict on Freud," Psychological Science 7 (1996), 63-68, at p. 63; Crews is reviewing Malcolm Macmillan, Freud Evaluated: The Completed Arc (Amsterdam, 1991). Crews's own contributions to this critique may be found in Skeptical Engagements (New York, 1986); Crews et al., The Memory Wars: Freud's Legacy in Dispute (New York, 1995); and Crews, ed., Unau- thorized Freud: Doubters Confront a Legend (New York, 1998). 36 Many of the most troubling doubts about psychoanalysis are expressed by psychoanalysts them- selves. For example, Donald P. Spence begins his book The Rhetorical Voice of Psychoanalysis: Dis- placement of Evidence by Theory (Cambridge, Mass., 1994), with the following statement: "As psy- choanalysis prepares to enter its second century, we are force d to realize that it is not much closer to being a science than it was when Freud first invented the discipline.... Rather than representing an earnest and possibly fallible attempt to tell a true story about the world, psychoanalytic theory may
  • 36. function much more as a shared fantasy that binds its followers in a common belief system and protects them from uncertainty and doubt" (pp. 1, 4-5). For other accounts of the current state of psycho- analysis by practicing analysts, see Marshall Edelson, Psychoanalysis: A Theory in Crisis (Chicago, 1988); Holt, Freud Reappraised; and Paul Kline, Psychology and Freudian Theory: An Introduction (London, 1984). 647 This content downloaded from 128.228.0.65 on Wed, 15 May 2019 02:22:27 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms Chaucer's Pardoner on the Couch To begin with, psychoanalytic theory makes universalist and absolutist claims that call for a large body of evidentiary support that it has never been able to provide. Freud insisted that all neuroses are caused by sexual dysfunctions that originate in infancy, and his emphasis upon both the primacy of early childhood and the sexual nature of identity formation remains central to psychoanalytic thinking. As he said in The Interpretation of Dreams (1900), "The theory of the psychoneuroses asserts as an indisputable and invariable fact that only sexual wishful impulses from infancy . . . furnish the motive force for the formation of
  • 37. psycho-neurotic symptoms of every kind."37 Similarly, Freud used his (admittedly failed) analysis of Dora to claim that "sexuality . . . provides the motive power for every single symptom, and for every single manifestation of a symptom. The symptoms of the disease are nothing else than the patient's sexual activity.... I can only repeat over and over again-for I never find it otherwise-that sexuality is the key to the problem of the psychoneuroses and of the neuroses in general."38 Again, Freud repeatedly insisted that the Oedipus complex is a universal phenom- enon: "Every new arrival on this planet is faced by the task of mastering the Oedipus complex; anyone who fails to do so falls a victim to neurosis. With the progress of psycho-analytic studies the importance of the Oedipus complex has become more and more clearly evident; its recognition has become the shibboleth that distinguishes the adherents of psycho-analysis from its opponents."39 And for Freud the Oedipus complex entailed as well the inevitability of the castration complex, a condition whose resolution determines gender identity.40 Freud actually went so far as to claim that the central events of infantile expe- rience were already present in the little boy as an ancestral inheritance, so he did not need to experience them at all for them to have their effect upon him: "These scenes of observing parental intercourse, of being seduced in
  • 38. childhood, and of being threatened with castration are unquestionably an inherited endowment, a phylogenetic heritage.... A child catches hold of this phylogenetic experience where his own experience fails him. He fills in the gaps in individual truth with 37 SE 5:605-6; my italics. 38 "A Case of Hysteria," SE 7:114-15; the italics in the phrase "the patient's sexual activity" are Freud's, while the others are mine. 39 "Three Essays on the Theory of Sexuality" (1905), SE 7:226 n (a footnote added in 1920; my italics). Freud concluded Totem and Taboo (1913) by "insist[ing] that ... the beginnings of religion, morals, society and art converge in the Oedipus complex" (SE 13:156). For discussions of the way in which post-Freudian psychoanalysis has revised and rerevised (but never discarded) the theory of the Oedipus complex, see Bennett Simon, "Is the Oedipus Complex Still the Cornerstone of Psychoanal- ysis? Three Obstacles to Answering the Question," Journal of the American Psychoanalytic Associa- tion 39 (1991), 641-68, and Bennett Simon, "'Incest-See under Oedipus Complex': The History of an Error in Psychoanalysis," Journal of the American Psychoanalytic Association 40 (1992), 955-88. In The Sublime Object of Ideology Zizek says: "Let us take one of the commonplaces of the Marxist- feminist criticism of psychoanalysis, the idea that its insistence on the crucial role of the Oedipus complex and the nuclear-family triangle transforms a historically conditioned form of patriarchal
  • 39. family into a feature of the universal human condition: is not this effort to historicize the family triangle precisely an attempt to elude the 'hard kernel' which announces itself through the 'patriarchal family'- the Real of the Law, the rock of castration?" (p. 50; italics in original). 40 See SE 20:38 and Allen Esterson, Seductive Mirage: An Exploration of the Work of Sigmund Freud (Chicago, 1993), p. 137. 648 This content downloaded from 128.228.0.65 on Wed, 15 May 2019 02:22:27 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms Chaucer's Pardoner on the Couch prehistoric truth; he replaces occurrences in his own life by occurrences in the life of his ancestors .... Wherever experiences fail to fit in with the hereditary schema, they become remodelled in the imagination.... We are often able to see the schema triumphing over the experience of the individual."41 Moreover, Freud claimed that the mind never forgot any experience, that everything was recover- able: "All of the essentials are preserved; even things that seem completely for- gotten are present somehow and somewhere.... It depends only upon analytic technique whether we shall succeed in bringing what is
  • 40. concealed completely to light."42 Similarly, for Freud all dreams, including those that cause anxiety, were "a (disguised) fulfillment of a (suppressed or repressed) wish."43 And so on: all of the central tenets of the psychoanalytic system were presented by Freud as both universal and empirically demonstrable. As his collaborator Josef Breuer put it, Freud was "a man given to absolute and exclusive formulations."44 This way of proceeding has created predictable problems for both Freud and his disciples. Evidence supportive of Freud's theories is almost entirely derived from the analytic session itself, "clinical" material which-as Adolf Griinbaum has shown in detail-is so contaminated by the presuppositions and suggestive- ness of the analytic session as to be useless for purposes of confirmation.45 What extraclinical evidence exists argues strongly against Freudian theory. The central tenets of the psychoanalytic system, the Oedipus complex and the theory of in- fantile sexuality upon which it is based, are without evidentiary support of any kind. Empirical studies have shown that young children of both sexes feel closer to the mother than the father and that as children mature, each sex tends to identify with the same sex parent, not out of fear of the other but out of affection and a desire for emulation.46 As for the retention of all experience within memory,
  • 41. empirical studies have shown that memory is in fact a highly malleable mental function by means of which people construct personal pasts to accord with present 41 "From the History of an Infantile Neurosis," SE 17:97, 119. For a discussion of this Freudian belief, see Frank Cioffi, "Freud and the Idea of a Pseudo- Science," in Robert Borger and Frank Cioffi, eds., Explanation in the Behavioural Sciences (Cambridge, Eng., 1970), pp. 471-99, at p. 481. For Freud's Lamarckian materialism, which led him to believe that acquired characteristics can be inher- ited, see Frank J. Sulloway, Freud, Biologist of the Mind: Beyond the Psychoanalytic Legend, rev. ed. (Cambridge, Mass., 1992). 42 "Constructions in Analysis" (1937), SE 23:260. 43 Interpretation of Dreams (1900), SE 4:160. 44 Breuer's characterization is cited by Esterson, Seductive Mirage, p. 5. 45 Griinbaum, Foundations of Psychoanalysis, pp. 95-172; Griinbaum, Validation in the Clinical Theory of Psychoanalysis: A Study in the Philosophy of Psychoanalysis (Madison, Conn., 1993). 46 See, e.g., Spence, Rhetorical Voice of Psychoanalysis, pp. 22-23; Robert N. Emde, "Individual Meaning and Increasing Complexity: Contributions of Sigmund Freud and Rene Spitz to Develop- mental Psychology," Developmental Psychology 28 (1992), 347-59 (Emde stresses that extensive research "has shown that gender identity is not an outcome of the Oedipus complex. Core gender identity is established earlier, usually in the second and third
  • 42. years of life" [p. 352]); and especially the important and tenaciously empirical work by Margaret S. Mahler, in Mahler et al., The Psychological Birth of the Human Infant: Symbiosis and Individuation (New York, 1975). As an example of the far harsher judgments passed by nonpsychoanalytic critics of Freud, see H. J. Eysenck, Decline and Fall of the Freudian Empire (Harmondsworth, Eng., 1985), p. 35. 649 This content downloaded from 128.228.0.65 on Wed, 15 May 2019 02:22:27 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms Chaucer's Pardoner on the Couch conditions.47 Finally, recent studies of the mind in sleep have shown that dreams have a very different cause from Freud's wish fulfillment, that their meaning is for the most part quite clear, and that their bizarreness is an effect, not of various "censoring" mechanisms protecting consciousness from a horrifying truth, but of the physiology of the brain during sleep.48 As Malcolm MacMillan has said, in concluding his exhaustive survey of the fate of Freudian theories when subjected to the empirical standards that Freud himself claimed to have applied, "Psycho- analysis as a theory of personality has little to recommend it.... Do processes like condensation and the summation of stimuli occur? Is there
  • 43. such a mechanism as repression? Is there a transformation of the primary process into the secondary? Is there an Oedipus complex out of which a super-ego forms and from which the ego is provided with defused energy? Is the development of adult sexuality, char- acter traits, and object-choice as Freud described them? Is female sexuality as Freud pictured it? From these points of view, psycho-analysis is not so much a bad theory, but a theory in search of some facts."49 Perhaps even more important to literary critics than this evidentiary absence, however, is the characteristic mode of argument by which psychoanalysis pro- ceeds. Psychoanalytic theory has always been able to absorb into its system and to explain in its own terms whatever counterevidence may be presented. Freud himself famously jettisoned his theory that neurotic patients had been seduced in infancy and replaced it with the less visible, and infinitely resourceful, notion of unconscious fantasy-a revision that succeeded in removing seduction from the real world (where it could be tested by evidence) and in relocating it within the patient him or herself (where it could be discerned only through psychoanalytic reconstructions of otherwise forgotten mental events). Freud had initially told his collaborator and friend Wilhelm Fliess that the seduction theory was "the key
  • 44. that unlocks everything, the etiological formula."5 But even at this stage it is unclear whether Freud was actually hearing such stories or already reconstructing them by applying his theory to the narratives his patients were reciting.51 When 47 See Elizabeth Loftus, Memory: Surprising New Insights into How We Remember and Why We Forget (Reading, Mass., 1980); Alan Baddeley, Human Memory: Theory and Practice (Boston, 1990); Elizabeth Loftus and Katherine Ketcham, The Myth of Repressed Memory: False Memories and Al- legations of Sexual Abuse (New York, 1994); and Crews et al., Memory Wars. 48 For recent work on dreaming, see Anthony Shafton, Dream Reader: Contemporary Approaches to the Understanding of Dreams (Albany, N.Y., 1995); Inge Strauch and Barbara Meier, In Search of Dreams: Results of Experimental Dream Research (Albany, N.Y., 1996); Michel Jouvet, The Paradox of Sleep: The Story of Dreaming, trans. Laurence Garey (Cambridge, Mass., 1999); Arthur W. Epstein, Dreaming and Other Involuntary Mentation: An Essay in Neuropsychiatry (Madison, Conn., 1995); and J. Allan Hobson, The Dreaming Brain (New York, 1988). A quick overview of this work will reveal the dubious value of applying Freud's model of dreaming either to real dreams or-as is some- times still done-to works of fiction. 49 Macmillan, Freud Evaluated, p. 548. 50 Jeffrey Moussaieff Masson, ed. and trans., The Complete Letters of Sigmund Freud to Wilhelm
  • 45. Fliess, 1887-1904 (Cambridge, Mass., 1985), pp. 45-46. 51 See Crews et al., Memory Wars, pp. 57-58, and works cited there. The best discussion of this founding moment in the creation of psychoanalysis is provided by Esterson, Seductive Mirage, pp. 11- 31; see also Richard Webster, Why Freud Was Wrong: Sin, Science and Psychoanalysis (New York, 1995), pp. 195-213. 650 This content downloaded from 128.228.0.65 on Wed, 15 May 2019 02:22:27 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms Chaucer's Pardoner on the Couch he then decided that his claims of wholesale sexual abuse were implausible, he relocated them within the unconscious where they were available only to the psy- chotherapist. As he said, "We must not be led astray by [the patient's] initial denials. If we keep firmly to what we have inferred, we shall in the end conquer every resistance by emphasizing the unshakeable nature of our convictions.... Since minor deviations from a normal vita sexualis are much too common for us to attach any value to their discovery, we shall only allow a serious and long continued abnormality in the sexual life of a neurotic patient to
  • 46. carry weight as an explanation."52 Hence Freud insisted that corroborative evidence from the patient's life was not merely unnecessary but an actual impediment: "It may seem tempting to take the easy course of filling up the gaps in a patient's memory by making inquiries from the older members of his family; but I cannot advise too strongly against such a technique.... One invariably regrets having made oneself dependent upon such information; at the same time confidence in the analysis is shaken and a court of appeal is set up over it."53 Freud did not abandon his hypothesis that children were sexually excited and seduced by their parents and then threatened with-or endured-castration. On the contrary, he avoided the court of appeal of real-life evidence by reworking the theory to accommodate it in a form resistant to em- pirical testing. This process of calibrating the theory to ignore or absorb recalcitrant evidence rather than rethinking its central premises-perhaps the most characteristic qual- ity of psychoanalytic thought-gives an impression of immense explanatory power while concealing empirical emptiness. Two further examples should make this important methodological point clear. Freud argued, as we have seen, that "in every case of neurosis there is a sexual aetiology" and that
  • 47. "anxiety is always libido which has been deflected from its [normal] employment. 54 But what about war neuroses, which certainly seem to have nothing to do with sexuality? Freud's answer is that the desire for survival is itself libidinal because it is a form of "narcissism, which brings the libidinal cathexis of the ego into line with the ca- thexes of objects and emphasizes the libidinal character of the instinct of self- preservation. "5 In any case, as he says in Beyond the Pleasure Principle, "me- chanical agitation [i.e., the concussion caused by exploding shells] must be recognized as one of the sources of sexual excitation."s6 By thus expanding the 52 "Sexuality in the Aetiology of the Neuroses" (1898), SE 3:269. And Freud continues: "Moreover, the idea that one might, by one's insistence, cause a patient who is psychically normal to accuse himself falsely of sexual misdemeanours-such an idea may safely be disregarded as an imaginary danger." Quite apart from the astonishing blindness to the power of suggestion that the analyst's "unshakeable" conviction could have on a patient that this comment reveals, one need only substitute "critic" and "text" for "analyst" and "patient" to see how vulnerable psychoanalytic criticism is to the danger of finding sexuality in a text that it already knows must be there. 53 "An Infantile Neurosis," SE 17:14 n; see Cioffi, "Freud and the Idea of a Pseudo-Science," p. 480 (italics added).
  • 48. 54 "Sexuality in the Aetiology of the Neuroses," SE 3:268. The brackets are in the original. 55 "Inhibitions, Symptoms and Anxiety" (1926), SE 20:129. 56 Beyond the Pleasure Principle (1920), SE 18:33. In a footnote Freud compares explosive concus- sion to swinging and railway travel, a startling trivialization of the experiences of millions of men during the Great War. 651 This content downloaded from 128.228.0.65 on Wed, 15 May 2019 02:22:27 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms Chaucer's Pardoner on the Couch notion of libido to include virtually all feelings, Freud was able to maintain his hypothesis that, regardless of the occasion for the appearance of neurosis, its eti- ology is always a displacement of libidinal energy. Hence Freud looks forward confidently to the time when "the libido theory could celebrate its triumph all along the line from the simplest 'actual' neurosis to the most severe alienation of the personality."57 The second example concerns Freud's familiar assertion that all dreams are disguised wish fulfillments. When Freud is presented with a
  • 49. dream that seems not to meet his criterion, he simply proclaims that the patient had the dream in order to fulfill her wish to thwart Freud's own theory of wish fulfillment. In a typical masterstroke of rhetorical subtlety, he then extended this lesson to his larger au- dience: "Indeed, it is to be expected that the same thing will happen to some of the readers of the present book: they will be quite ready to have one of their wishes frustrated in a dream if only their wish that I may be wrong can be fulfilled."58 Given this preemptive strike, there is no recourse, as Karl Kraus lamented: "They have caught me!"59 We have here reached the central issue of interpretation, the issue that above all connects Freudian psychoanalysis to literary criticism. It is clear that Freud's method of dream interpretation-like his interpretive method as a whole-is pre- emptive. The theory posits the meaning of dreams, feelings, and behaviors, and the task of the analyst is to read them so that they yield their preordained signif- icance. Much has been written on the familiar mix of arbitrariness and dogmatism that characterizes psychoanalytic interpretation. Sebastiano Timpanaro, for ex- ample, has devoted three long and brilliant chapters to one of Freud's interpre- tations in The Psychopathology of Everyday Life. The famous misquotation of a Virgilian line made by the young man in the train is,
  • 50. Timpanaro shows, determined not by unconscious anxieties about his mistress's late menstrual period but by the peculiarly difficult syntax employed by Virgil, a difficulty that caused medieval scribes to make the same mistake. There is, Timpanaro modestly says, "nothing brilliant" about his demonstration, "nor is it even particularly intelligent . . ; but it is the simplest and most 'economical' explanation possible." As for Freud's interpretation, "beneath the brilliance of the intellectual fireworks, few procedures can be reckoned so antiscientific," for it depends upon a "captious and sophistical method, resistant to any verification, quick to force interpretations [and] to secure pre-ordained proofs."60 57 Introductory Lectures, SE 16:430. 58 Interpretation of Dreams, SE 4:158. 59 See above, n. 14. For a subtle reading of The Interpretation of Dreams that examines its rhetorical power, see Alexander Welsh, Freud's Wishful Dream Book (Princeton, N.J., 1994). Welsh sees the subject of the book as being not the psyche but Freud's own ambition. 60 Timpanaro, The Freudian Slip, pp. 29-61, 41,42-43, and 14 (see n. 13 above). In his two-volume account of psychoanalytic theory, The Non-Authentic Nature of Freud's Observations, Uppsala Studies in Education 47-48 (Uppsala, 1993), Max Scharnberg describes the Freudian interpretive procedure as follows:
  • 51. 1. Start with a preconceived interpretation. 2. Pick up a few details here and there on the criterion that they can be used or misused to support 652 This content downloaded from 128.228.0.65 on Wed, 15 May 2019 02:22:27 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms Chaucer's Pardoner on the Couch 653 In support of its empirical pretensions, psychoanalysis systematically confuses meanings with causes. As the British philosopher Frank Cioffi remarks, "We did not interpret dreams, symptoms, errors, etc., because it was discovered that they were meaningful, but we insisted that they were meaningful in order that we might interpret them."61 It may well be that the interpretation will tell us something important about the interpreter, or the patient, or the method of interpretation; but it can tell us nothing about the cause of the dream or symptom. This confusion of etiology with interpretation, or of reason with cause, is at the very heart of the psychoanalytic procedure, and it led Wittgenstein to describe psychoanalysis as "speculation-something prior even to the formation of an hypothesis." Witt- genstein argued that the power of the Freudian system was not
  • 52. the correctness of its account of the mind but the fact that Freud provided "the sort of interpretation that is wanted," interpretations that have "the attraction which mythological ex- planations have, explanations which say that this is all a repetition of something that has happened before."62 One sympathizes with Dora when, after Freud has interpreted a jewel case that appeared in one of her dreams as the female genitalia, she says, "I knew you would say that."63 Freud's famous case histories have been subjected to careful investigation by later researchers.64 The characteristic mode of argumentation they display has led Cioffi to characterize psychoanalysis not as a protoscience, a theory still awaiting its evidentiary basis, but as a pseudoscience that "involves the habitual and wilful the interpretation. 3. Connect them with the interpretation by means of the principle of similarity. 4. Ignore all data which cannot be used as pseudo-support of any interpretation. 5. If data which contradict the interpretation have inadvertently been obtained, suppress them and conceal them from the reader. (2:17) The best precedent for Freud's hermeneutic is the exegetical method of the Middle Ages. In both cases the exegete knows beforehand what the text means-the double law of charity, the Oedipus complex- and her task is to explain how the text can mean what she
  • 53. knows it must mean. This analogy between the preemptive hermeneutic of medieval exegesis and psychoanalytic procedures has been pointed out by Cioffi, "Freud and the Idea of a Pseudo-Science," p. 498, and by Spence, Rhetorical Voice of Psychoanalysis (who argues at length that "psychoanalysis is as much a medieval as a modern science" [p. 47]). 61 "Freud and the Idea of a Pseudo-Science," p. 498. 62 Wittgenstein, Lectures and Conversations, pp. 43-44, 47. 63 "A Case of Hysteria" (1905), SE 7:69 (my italics). In a footnote to this comment Freud easily trumps Dora: "A very common way of putting aside a piece of knowledge that emerges from the repressed." 64 See, for a sample of these investigations, Charles Bernheimer and Claire Kahane, eds., In Dora's Case: Freud-Hysteria-Feminism (New York, 1985); Cioffi, "Freud and the Idea of a Pseudo-Science," pp. 471-99 (on Dora); Henri F. Ellenberger, "The Story of 'Anna O': A Critical Review with New Data," Journal of the History of the Behavioral Sciences 8 (1972), 267-79; Esterson, Seductive Mirage, chaps. 3-5; Stanley Fish, "Withholding the Missing Portion: Power, Meaning, and Persuasion in Freud's 'The Wolf-Man,'" Times Literary Supplement, August 29, 1986; John Kerr, A Most Dangerous Method: The Story of ung, Freud, and Sabina Spielrein (New York, 1993); Karin Obholzer, The Wolf- Man: Conversations with Freud's Patient-Sixty Years Later, trans. Michael Shaw (New York, 1982); Frank J. Sulloway, "Reassessing Freud's Case Histories: The Social Construction of Psychoanalysis,"
  • 54. Isis 82 (1991), 245-75; and Joseph Wolpe and Stanley Rachman, "Psychoanalytic 'Evidence': A Cri- tique Based on Freud's Case of Little Hans," Journal of Nervous and Mental Disease 131 (1960), 135-48. This content downloaded from 128.228.0.65 on Wed, 15 May 2019 02:22:27 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms Chaucer's Pardoner on the Couch employment of methodologically defective procedures (in a sense of wilful which encompasses refined self-deception).... [Hence] there are a host of peculiarities of psychoanalytic theory and practice which are apparently gratuitous and unre- lated, but which can be understood when once they are seen as manifestations of the same impulse: the need to avoid refutation."65 For example, if a child has an overbearing superego, Freud argued at one point that this is the direct effect of a strict father; but at another point the same phenomenon was explained as a re- action against a too lenient father. As Cioffi says, Freud is able "to render any outcome whatever an intelligible and apparently natural result of whatever cir- cumstances preceded it."66 Since this point is central to the literary use of psychoanalytic interpretive pro-
  • 55. cedures, it is worth quoting in full a discussion of psychoanalytic testing by the research analyst Sibylle Escalona: Suppose one wished to investigate the psycho-analytic idea that, at about the ages of three and four, little boys characteristically experience hostile and aggressive feelings towards their parents and more specifically their fathers, and that these hostile feelings are based on the wish to possess the mother and replace the father in the family con- stellation. Suppose also that you create an experimental situation which would activate the child's feeling towards his parents. For instance, the father might exert his authority by sending the child off to his own room when the child wants to remain with the parents. If, to substantiate the core of the oedipal hypothesis, the child were required to display frank anger against his father, or frank possessiveness towards his mother, things would be reasonably simple. However, no one would seriously believe that oedipal con- flicts are at work only when the child obligingly acts out both his wish and his anger at the obstacle of wish-fulfillment. Instead, we assume that the child tends to defend himself against becoming aware of-or openly reflecting-aggression because it engenders anxi- ety. Thus, if the child gives daddy a good-night hug and insists that he, rather than mummy, tuck him in, this behaviour may also confirm our original hypothesis. His desire to have the father put him to bed rather than the mother could be the result of a fearful
  • 56. state, i.e. as long as the father is with him the little boy can be sure the father is not doing anything to harm him. On the other hand, or also simultaneously, it may be an act of aggression towards the father in that it separates him from the mother for the time being. Or yet again, it may be because the little boy fears that if the mother puts him to bed her seductive powers will prove too much for him; he will then express his possessive love for the mother and try to take his father's place, and the omniscient father will punish him for it. The example could be spun out indefinitely, and it is safe to say that there is nothing our little experimental subject could possibly do, from with- drawal, to sudden intense interest in phantasy play, to asking for a cake, that cannot be regarded in the light of the assumption that he is reacting to an oedipal conflict situation. This being so, it is self-evident that nothing the little boy can do will confirm the original hypothesis, since the hypothesis would still be applicable if he had done the opposite 65 Cioffi, "Freud and the Idea of a Pseudo-Science," pp. 472- 73. 66 Ibid., p. 485. As Cioffi shows in another essay, what makes a theory pseudoscientific rather than nonscientific is that its statements are subject to falsifiability but are presented and maintained in a context in which testing is rendered impossible. A pseudoscience will seek to prove itself by citing positive instances while making it impossible to distinguish between positive and negative ("Psycho-
  • 57. analysis, Pseudo-Science and Testability," in Gregory Currie and Alan Musgrave, eds., Popper and the Human Sciences, Nijhoff International Philosophy Series 19 [Dordrecht, 1995], pp. 13-44, at p. 17. 654 This content downloaded from 128.228.0.65 on Wed, 15 May 2019 02:22:27 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms Chaucer's Pardoner on the Couch instead.... Psycho-analytic theory is greatly in need of validation, yet it is the kind of theory incapable of validation.67 Finally, it must be stressed that the variants of psychoanalytic theory that have developed over the years, and especially that associated with Jacques Lacan, are not only not free from the flaws of method and conceptual vagueness that are fatal to Freudianism but actually invoke them as a badge of honor. Lacan shows little interest in empirical validation in preference to unconstrained theorizing. His foundational account of prelinguistic identity formation by means of the "mirror- stage" relies, as one of his defenders acknowledges, on a "very limited fund of observation data," data that genuinely empirical studies have subsequently shown to be false.68 Indeed, Lacanianism's popularity in academic
  • 58. circles derives not from its truth-value, which remains not just undemonstrated but indemonstrable, but from its fit with other modes of "anti-humanist"-indeed irrationalist-thought that are taken to be progressive and even liberatory.69 For a long time Freud had a reputation for what Ernest Jones called "flawless integrity" and Steven Marcus a "profoundly moral . . . intellectual commitment and adherence to the idea of science."70 These reverential hopes must now also be abandoned. So, too, must Freud's continual claims to have gone where no man dared go before: we now know that many of the central Freudian concepts- including the unconscious and the centrality of sexuality to the mental life-were common currency in late-nineteenth-century medical circles.71 Freud's suppression of evidence in the case histories, his self-glorification (including the tale of his famous self-analysis, which in all likelihood never took place), his misbehavior as 67 Sibylle Escalona, "Problems in Psycho-Analytic Research," International Journal of Psycho-anal- ysis 33 (1952), 11-21; cited by Cioffi, "Psychoanalysis, Pseudo-Science and Testability," pp. 20-21; emphasis added. See also Morris N. Eagle, "The Epistemological Status of Recent Developments in Psychoanalytic Theory," in R. S. Cohen and L. Laudan, eds., Physics, Philosophy, and Psychoanalysis: Essays in Honor of Adolf Griinbaum, Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science 76 (Boston, 1983),
  • 59. pp. 31-55. 68 Bowie, Lacan, p. 22. As Bowie says, Lacan "starves his hypothesis of the clinical data that could test its organizing power, and produces neither map nor message" (p. 25). For empirical evidence about how infants actually respond to mirrors, see Margaret S. Mahler and John B. McDevitt, "Thoughts on the Emergence of the Sense of Self, with Particular Emphasis on the Body Self," Journal of the American Psychoanalytic Association 30 (1982), 827-48, and Jeanne Brooks-Gunn and Michael Lewis, "Mirror-Image Stimulation and Self Recognition in Infancy," a paper available at http:// askeric.org/Eric/. I am indebted for these references to Norman Holland, "The Trouble(s) with Lacan" (n. 32 above). As Holland says, "There is no evidence for Lacan's notion of a mirror stage. Indeed what evidence we have runs rather the other way.... Perhaps Lacan knew no better in 1936, but why do present-day Lacanians go on quoting this mish-mash of conjecture and false assertions?" 69 See Ferry and Renaut, French Philosophy of the Sixties, pp. 3-67, 185-227. 70 Ernest Jones, The Life and Work of Sigmund Freud, 3 vols. (New York, 1953-57), 1:327, and Marcus, Freud and the Culture of Psychoanalysis, p. 11. The most recent and thorough demonstration of Freud's self-interest in misrepresenting his "data" is provided by Han Israels, Der Fall Freud: Die Geburt der Psychoanalyse aus der Liige, trans. (from the Dutch) Gerd Busse (Hamburg, 1999); an extensive summary of Israels's indictment is provided by Mikkel Borch-Jacobsen, "How a Fabrication
  • 60. Differs from a Lie," London Review of Books 22/8 (13 April 2000), 3-7. 71 See especially Henri F. Ellenberger, The Discovery of the Unconscious: The History and Evolution of Dynamic Psychiatry (New York, 1970); Edward Shorter, A History of Psychiatry: From the Era of the Asylum to the Age of Prozac (New York, 1997); and Sulloway, Freud, Biologist of the Mind. 655 This content downloaded from 128.228.0.65 on Wed, 15 May 2019 02:22:27 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 656 Chaucer's Pardoner on the Couch an analyst, his insistence that his co-workers share a total commitment to his dogma or else face exile and obloquy, and even his championing of cocaine and his own addiction-all of this would seem mere ad hominem critique were it not for the fact that the contemporary institution of psychoanalysis follows so closely in its father's footsteps.72 It remains resistant to the empirical procedures that characterize other medical practices; it continues to idolize its founder; it treats criticism as disloyalty; and it refuses to examine its own disciplinary history.73 These fundamental problems in a theory that claims to explain human behavior,
  • 61. and in a medical institution that claims scientific status, are apparently either unknown to, unacknowledged by, or regarded as irrelevant to the literary critics, perhaps especially in medieval studies, who have jumped on what they think is a bandwagon but is in fact an ambulance or perhaps even a hearse. The irony is that psychoanalysis has the reputation of being cutting edge in literary criticism even as it has disappeared from those fields for which it was designed-the un- derstanding of human behavior and the management of mental pathologies.74 3. PSYCHOANALYZING THE PARDONER This section reexamines a well-known medieval text, Chaucer's Pardoner's Pro- logue and Tale. In part it constitutes a palinode on my part, a retraction resembling Chaucer's own selective rejection of some of his works. I wish to show the allure of psychoanalytic interpretation, an allure to which I myself once succumbed, but also its limits, specifically the way its seeming persuasiveness can foreclose access to relevant medieval materials and contexts. In the General Prologue to the Can- 72 For the dubious existence of the self-analysis, see Spence, Rhetorical Voice, chap. 5. For Freud's misbehavior as an analyst, two instances are cited by Sulloway, "Reassessing Freud's Case Histories," from the correspondence with Fliess, one in 1888, the other in 1898: "I have at this moment a lady
  • 62. in hypnosis lying in front of me and therefore can go on writing in peace"; "I sleep during my afternoon analyses" (cited p. 157). For Freud's enthusiasm for cocaine, Fliess's theory of the physiological con- nection between the nose and the genitals, and its hideous effects upon their patient Emma Eckstein, for which Freud refused to take responsibility, see E. M. Thornton, Freud and Cocaine: The Freudian Fallacy (London, 1983); Sulloway, Freud, Biologist of the Mind, pp. 327-29; Crews, Skeptical En- gagements, pp. 48-52; and Clark Glymour, "The Theory of Your Dreams," in Cohen and Laudan, eds., Physics, Philosophy and Psychoanalysis, pp. 57-71, at pp. 64-69. 73 As the psychoanalyst Robert Holt says: "American psychoanalysis has lived for so long within a snug cocoon of myth that it seems unable to go through the predictable pains of metamorphosis into a viable progressive discipline. The protective threads it has wound around itself include warding off all criticism as resistance, idolatry of Freud, and faithful internalization of all his faults as a scientist and writer" (Freud Reappraised, p. 341). To be sure, contemporary psychoanalysts are aware of their credibility problem: the American Psychoanalytic Association has established a Subcommittee on Stra- tegic Marketing, hired a public relations consultant and Washington lobbyists, and is conducting focus groups in order, according to the chairman of the subcommittee, "to try and define the messages we should be giving for public use" (New York Times, December 9, 2000, pp. B7 and B9). 74 For a psychoanalyst's account of this irony, see Alan Stone, "Where Will Psychoanalysis Survive?"
  • 63. Harvard Magazine 99/3 (1997), 35-39. Stone, a former president of the American Psychiatric Asso- ciation, sees the future of psychoanalysis in "the arts and humanities" and points out that in the Harvard course catalogue for 1997 there are forty "classes whose descriptions mention either Freud or psychoanalysis.... All of them are in the humanities, particularly literature; no course is being given in the psychology department, and next to nothing is offered in the medical school" (p. 38). This content downloaded from 128.228.0.65 on Wed, 15 May 2019 02:22:27 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms Chaucer's Pardoner on the Couch terbury Tales the narrator explains the Pardoner's odd appearance with the com- ment "I trowe he were a geldyng or a mare" (691).75 For the modern reader, for whom sexual identity is the crucial determinant of selfhood, this line immediately places sex at the center of the picture. Two other aspects of the tale encourage interpreters to keep it there. One is the Old Man whom the three rioters of the tale meet in their quest to kill death, a figure who describes himself in eerily Oe- dipal terms. Ne Deeth, alias, no wol nat han my lyf. Thus walke I, lyk a restelees kaityf, And on the ground, which is my moodres gate,
  • 64. I knokke with my staf, bothe erly and late, And seye "Leeve mooder, leet me in!" (727-31) Equally tempting are the false relics that the Pardoner carries "biforn hym in his lappe" (1.686). After he has finished his tale, he turns to the Host and asks him to make an offering and kiss these relics. The Host responds with an outburst famous for its scatological violence: I wolde I hadde thy coillons in myn hond In stide of relikes or of seintuarie. Lat kutte hem of, I wol thee helpe hem carie; They shul be shryned in an hogges toord! (952-55) Thus the Oedipal dream of a return to the mother (as expressed by the Old Man) is here punished by the paternal threat of castration-a psychoanalytic schema as neat as any Freudian could want. Not surprisingly, recent criticism has read the Pardoner almost exclusively in such terms. A number of years ago I developed an interpretation of this text that was es- sentially historical-that is, it depended upon late-medieval religious beliefs-but also invoked psychoanalytic terms.76 I read the Old Man as a figure for the Par- doner's own despair; that condition is typically represented in
  • 65. medieval writing as always dying but never dead. As for his Oedipal speech, I explained it by way of the literary history of the Oedipus legend, which in the Middle Ages became linked with the theological condition of despair via the figure of Judas. In due course I shall briefly rehearse the main points of that interpretation, but I want now to acknowledge that I did not then sufficiently control my own use of psy- choanalytic terminology, largely because psychoanalysis provided a temptingly prefabricated interpretation that showed how a medieval text could satisfy mod- ern (and younger) preoccupations. I now know that there is a wealth of further 75 All citations from Chaucer are to The Riverside Chaucer, 3rd ed., gen. ed. Larry D. Benson (Bos- ton, 1987). All further citations will be included in the text by line number; I have on occasion altered the punctuation. 76 Chaucer and the Subject of History (Madison, Wis., 1991), pp. 367-421; the essentials of this reading were first presented in "Chaucerian Confession: Penitential Literature and the Pardoner," Medievalia et humanistica 7 (1976), 153-73, and, with the added psychoanalytic twist, in a paper at the Medieval Congress at Kalamazoo in 1985. 657 This content downloaded from 128.228.0.65 on Wed, 15 May 2019 02:22:27 UTC
  • 66. All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms Chaucer's Pardoner on the Couch medieval material that the familiar psychoanalytic paradigm hid from my view, material that can help us to understand both the Pardoner and the Old Man with much greater historical specificity. The reading of the tale that has now achieved almost classic status is the thor- oughly psychoanalytic interpretation offered by Carolyn Dinshaw in Chaucer's Sexual Poetics.77 According to Dinshaw the Pardoner enacts "the modern psycho- analytic version of the myth of loss and wished-for reconciliation"; his being is "essentially defective, lacking, fragmented": "the lacking Pardoner demonstrates the pain that must attend the subject's development. .. when it is seen to depend on a necessary absence-the necessary loss of plenitude initially associated with the mother's body and a definition of the woman as lack." This lack is expressed in the Pardoner's use of relics (relics are, according to Dinshaw, historically not usually associated with pardoners and therefore should be read symbolically);78 his relics are fetish objects that substitute for his missing manhood: "As free- floating body-parts, they are both reifications of his own fragmentariness and
  • 67. substitutes for his own masculine lack."79 But "the Pardoner's relics cannot really produce that desired integrity, and he knows it.... They both represent lack and substitute for wholeness; they signify absence even as they suggest presence."80 Although Dinshaw sounds like Lacan, and explicitly invokes Melanie Klein, this reading depends ultimately on Freud's account of fetishism. For Freud, the fetish is a sexually arousing object that substitutes for the mother's missing penis- it is created, in short, by the castration anxiety that both establishes and charac- terizes subjectivity. The fetish is a "disavowal" of a reality that the fetishist ac- knowledges in another part of his ego: that penises-including his mother's and, by implication, his own-can be missing.81 The Lacanian turn to Dinshaw's ar- gument is to include in this economy of castration language itself, arguing that 77 Chaucer's Sexual Poetics (Madison, Wis., 1989). Dinshaw's chapter has been often reprinted and cited as providing an authoritative account of the tale: e.g., Derek Pearsall, ed., Chaucer to Spenser: Critical Reader (Malden, Mass., 1999), pp. 65-106, and Bruce R. Smith, "Premodern Sexualities," PMLA 115 (2000), 318-29, at p. 324. 78 In this (mistaken) assumption, Dinshaw is relying upon Alfred L. Kellogg and Louis A. Hasel- mayer, "Chaucer's Satire of the Pardoner," in Alfred L. Kellogg, Chaucer, Langland, Arthur: Essays
  • 68. in Middle English Literature (New Brunswick, N.J., 1972), pp. 212-44, at p. 233 n. 51. For pardoners and relics, see Siegfried Wenzel, "Chaucer's Pardoner and His Relics," Studies in the Age of Chaucer 11 (1989), 37-41 and n. 152. Unfortunately, Dinshaw does not use Kellogg's excellent "An Augus- tinian Interpretation of Chaucer's Pardoner," Speculum 26 (1951), 465-81, reprinted in Chaucer, Langland, Arthur, pp. 245-68, which provides a good account of the subtle psychologizing available to medieval Christianity. 79 Dinshaw misses a Freudian opportunity here: in The Interpretation of Dreams Freud reads one of his own dreams as showing that he thought that his children wished to turn his sexual organs into relics; see Eysenck, Decline and Fall of the Freudian Empire, p. 146. 80 Dinshaw, Chaucer's Sexual Poetics, pp. 161-64, 167-68. 81 See "Fetishism" (1927), SE 21:152-57, and An Outline of Psycho-Analysis (1940), SE 23:202- 3. Freud argues that the particular object chosen as a fetish depends upon whatever the child "saw at the moment at which he saw the female genitals, or it is something that can suitably serve as a symbolic substitute for the penis" (SE 23:203). Given his vantage point from the ground up, the boy thus usually becomes a foot or shoe fetishist, although occasionally he uses hair, since his horror at the sight of the mother's missing penis fixates his gaze on her pubic hair. 658 This content downloaded from 128.228.0.65 on Wed, 15 May
  • 69. 2019 02:22:27 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms Chaucer's Pardoner on the Couch the Pardoner's sexual absence signifies linguistic absence.82 "Defined by absence," "lack," and "incompleteness," the Pardoner reveals "the nature of language it- self," that it too is castrated and lacks full significance. Hence Chaucer explores through him "a hermeneutics of the partial, or, for short, eunuch hermeneutics."83 Dinshaw thus takes as a given the Pardoner's eunuchry, reading it as both literal and symbolic.84 But what would a reader in fourteenth-century England have assumed about this figure, whom the narrator introduces as either a gelding or a mare? Did such terms imply literal or symbolic effeminacy? And if symbolic, sym- bolic within what system of signification? Let us start with the issue of gelding. In the very early Middle Ages castration is prescribed as a punishment for various crimes, usually sexual and occasionally including sodomy, as in Justinian's law code; it reappears in the same context in the later Middle Ages in Italy, although the usual punishment prescribed for sod- omy was burning.85 But in later medieval England castration as a punishment for any crime is very rare, if not in fact entirely absent. Froissart
  • 70. reports the castration of Edward II's reputed lover Hugh Despenser, but this is no more historically verifiable than the claim that Edward was himself killed by having a hot poker inserted in his anus. In the cultural imagination there clearly was a link between sodomy and castration. In the Roman de la Rose Genius wants all sodomites castrated, and the eccentric English work known as the Mirror of Justices says that at the present time (i.e., 1285-90) the punishment for rape was hanging, but 82 This argument was first made, in relation to Chaucer's source for the relevant passage in the Roman de la Rose, by R. Howard Bloch, Etymologies and Genealogies: A Literary Anthropology of the French Middle Ages (Chicago, 1983), pp. 128-58. 83 Dinshaw, Chaucer's Sexual Poetics, pp. 158-59. 84 In a later essay, however, she has argued that the Pardoner must be taken, by ourselves and his fellow travelers, as queer, a concept whose existence in the Middle Ages remains to be demonstrated: "Chaucer's Queer Touches/A Queer Touches Chaucer," Exemplaria 7 (1995), 75-92. Queer readings of the Pardoner-prefigured by Donald R. Howard in The Idea of the Canterbury Tales (Berkeley, Calif., 1976), pp. 339-80, and further encouraged by Monica E. McAlpine, "The Pardoner's Ho- mosexuality and How It Matters," PMLA 95 (1980), 8-22-have now become common: see Glenn Burger, "Kissing the Pardoner," PMLA 107 (1992), 1143-56; Steven E Kruger, "Claiming the Par-
  • 71. doner: Toward a Gay Reading of Chaucer's Pardoner's Tale," Exemplaria 6 (1994), 115-39; Allen J. Frantzen, "The Pardoner's Tale, the Pervert, and the Price of Order in Chaucer's World," in Britton J. Harwood and Gillian R. Overing, eds., Class and Gender in Early English Literature: Intersections (Bloomington, Ind., 1994), pp. 131-47; and Robert Stuart Sturges, Chaucer's Pardoner and Gender Theory: Bodies of Discourse (New York, 2000). All of these readings assume that Chaucer's account is designed to direct the reader's attention to the Pardoner's homosexuality. On the other hand, the proposal that a contemporary audience would have seen the Pardoner's feminization as an effect of his excessive sexual dealings with women-i.e., of his too active heterosexuality-is presented with strong evidentiary support by C. David Benson, "Chaucer's Pardoner: His Sexuality and Modern Critics," Mediaevalia 8 (1985 for 1982), 337-49, and Richard F Green, "The Sexual Normality of Chaucer's Pardoner," Mediaevalia 8 (1985 for 1982), 351-58. Unfortunately, the queer readings of the Pardoner do not confront this evidence. 85 For Justinian's Code, see John Boswell, Christianity, Social Tolerance, and Homosexuality: Gay People in Western Europe from the Beginning of the Christian Era to the Fourteenth Century (Chicago, 1980), p. 172; for the Italian legislation in the later Middle Ages, see James A. Brundage, Law, Sex, and Christian Society in Medieval Europe (Chicago, 1987), pp. 472-74, 533-35; for castration as a penalty for sodomy, see Michael Goodich, The Unmentionable Vice: Homosexuality in the Later Medieval Period (Santa Barbara, Calif., 1979), p. 83.
  • 72. 659 This content downloaded from 128.228.0.65 on Wed, 15 May 2019 02:22:27 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 660 Chaucer's Pardoner on the Couch that prior to the reign of Edward I rape was punished "by tearing out of eyes and loss of testicles, because of the appetite which entered through the eyes and the heat of fornication which came into the reins of the lechers."86 In the Placita Corone, a law book written about 1274, a convicted rapist can be castrated and blinded, unless his wife speaks out, for "she can claim her husband's testicles as her own property."87 But even this quaint ruling seems to function more in the realm of fiction than fact: the editor of the Placita points out that rape was in fact punished by fine alone, and that both castration and blinding "had almost cer- tainly ceased to be inflicted long before 1274-1275."88 There may have been private instances of castration for sexual offenses against women in the thirteenth century-Matthew Paris reports one, and in 1275 Parliament passed a statute defining rape as a capital offense, perhaps to foreclose the possibility that castra- tion and/or blinding would be imposed as a punishment-but
  • 73. there is no evidence that this punishment was carried out in any judicial or even semiofficial way in England after 1300 at the latest.89 Indeed, mutilation as a whole seems to have disappeared in England in the thirteenth century, and even the gruesomely detailed execution for treason by drawing and quartering did not include castration.90 As a physical phenomenon, then, the castrate or eunuch woul d seem to have been rare in late-medieval England. It may be that Walter Clyde Curry is right that Chaucer drew for his portrait of the Pardoner on the medical physiognomist 86 Guillaume de Lorris and Jean de Meun, Le roman de la Rose, ed. Daniel Poirion (Paris, 1974), lines 19626-86, pp. 520-21; William Joseph Whittaker, ed. and trans., The Mirror of Justices, Pub- lications of the Selden Society 7 (London, 1895), p. 141. I am indebted for the information about castration as a punishment in England in this and the following sentences to Prof. Richard F Green. 87 J. M. Kaye, ed., Placita Corone, Selden Society, Supplementary Series, 4 (London, 1966), p. 9. 88 Ibid., p. xvi; see also p. xxxiv. 89 For Matthew Paris, see H. R. Luard, ed., Chronica majora, 7 vols., Rolls Series 57 (London, 1872-83), 5:34. For the 1285 statute, see The Statutes of the Realm, ed. Alexander Luders et al., 9 vols. in 10 (London, 1810-22), 1:87; see also 1:29 (1275) and 2:27 (1382). In France I have found