SlideShare a Scribd company logo
1 of 40
Running head: DEATH PENALTY
1
DEATH PENALTY
6
Death Penalty
Maria Feistel
Strayer University
Professor Jenna Thrasher-Sneathen
10/19/2017
Death Penalty
Death penalty is also known as capital punishment. It is a
practice sanctioned by the government as punishment for people
who have committed a capital offense. The sentence for such a
crime is what is referred to as a death sentence; the process of
carrying out the sentence is what they refer to as execution.
Capital offenses include; murder, espionage, treason, genocide,
war crimes and crimes against humanity. Currently, only fifty-
six countries have maintained capital punishment, other have
either abolished it or maintained it for special crimes such as
war crimes (Hoffman, 2005). In the United States, only 18
states have completely abolished capital punishment.
The United States has carried out more than 1400 executions in
four decades (1977 to 2016). To begin with, there are no major
differences in crime rates in the states that allow death penalty
and those which do not. Personally, I believe capital punishment
is the worst violation of human rights, it is cruel and inhuman
and infliction of unnecessary psychological torture on the
victims. Death sentences are biased and to favor the rich who
can afford good attorneys (Hoffman, K. (2005). It is also
prejudiced against the poor and the minority races. In my
opinion on would rather get a life in prison sentence than a
death penalty.
The first premise we are going to consider is whether death
penalty helps deter crime or not. Personally, I believe it doesn't.
According to an article by Professor John J. Donohue who
teaches law at Stanford University, there is no statistical
evidence indicating that death penalty is a deterrent against
crimes such as homicide. However, Professor Cass R. Sunstein
of the University of Chicago believes that capital punishment
may be required not for retributive reasons but for preventing
loss of innocent lives. George W. Bush, the 43rd president of
the United States in a 2000 debate, said that he believes that
death penalty saves other people’s lives. However, I believe that
it is not right to justify death penalty solely due to its deterrent
effect. The policymakers ought to find more effective, less
costly ways of addressing capital offenses.
The view that capital punishment deters crime is an interesting
one since it doesn't have any credible statistical evidence that
proves its effectiveness in reducing crime yet many influential
people, including George W. Bush a former U.S president,
believe it should continue. Jimmy Carter the 39th President of
the United States in his 2012 article observed that the claim that
death penalty deters crime is ironical since homicide rates in the
US country were five times greater than in other western
countries without the death penalty. If I believed in this view, I
would have observed that death sentences can serve justice to
the victims and their families since many people feel some kind
of relief when the offender hangs. However, this view would
only be right if, there was sufficient evidence to prove that it
deters crime. Another condition is that if policymakers are
confident that it will enhance public safety and it will be
administered fairly and justly.
The second premise is whether capital punishment is ethical or
immoral. According to me, the death penalty is both unethical
and immoral, and it violates the right of man to life. Professor
Edward Feser believes that since death sentences are reserved
for the worst cases committed by the most heartless and brutal
murderers, they deserve capital punishments as it justifies the
heinousness of their crimes. However, former Oregon State
Penitentiary superintendent, Mr. Semon Frank thinks that on a
moral perspective, the death penalty is a failed policy. He also
believes that the judges who handle such cases fall into deeper
convictions emotionally leaving feelings of guilt and
contemplation (Thompson 2017).
Capital punishment is immoral, unfair and discriminatory.
Criminals need not be treated in the same brutal manner they
treated their victims since this depicts a society as uncivilized
and savage (Hoffman, 2005). Alex Kozinski, a former judge of
the court of appeals in the United States, believes that a moral
society should demand the life of any person who murders
another. Religious books such as the Qur'an however, teach that
human life is God-given and it is only He that is allowed to take
it. An article by the National Catholic reporter states that, like
Jesus Christ, Christians should learn to forgive those who hurt
them and their loved ones and love those who have been
condemned rather than judge them. This wheel help to stop the
vicious cycle of violence. The Jewish Social Policy Action
Network advocates for the abolition of the death penalty
arguing that it is immoral and constitutes a cruel and
unreasonable punishment that depict a culture of violence and
misleads the young generations.
The issue regarding whether capital punishment is moral or
ethical is an interesting topic due to the views of the proponents
and the opponents (Thompson, 2017). For example, proponents
suggest that the brutal actions of the murderers deserve equally
brutal punishments. Others feel that it is immoral on the part of
society not to punish offenders. However, the religion which is
sure most of these proponents profess is against taking God-
given lives thus making this issue very controversial. If I
believed in this opinion, I would probably face the greatest
dilemma ever since my religion wouldn't support my opinions.
Under some conditions, however, proponents might be right. In
countries where cases of jailbreaks are rampant for example, it
would be risky to keep murder convicts in such facilities since
they will most probably escape. This would put the lives of
those who put these convicts in jail at risk. Death sentences can
also be considered for crimes that contribute to gross loss of
lives.
Finally, our last premise to consider in this paper is whether life
in prison without parole is a better substitution to the death
penalty. My opinion on this matter is that life in prison is
better, less brutal and less expensive. On the other hand, death
sentences are costlier, less effective and can wrongly lead to the
prosecution of innocent people (Appleton & Grover 2006).
Proponents of death sentences, however, argue differently, they
believe life in prison exposes convicts to unnecessary
psychological torture. The prisons where they are condemned to
are designed to be most punitive where they do not have access
to rehabilitative or restorative programs. These prisoners often
succumb to psychiatric problems such as depression and active
psychosis (Hoffman, 2005). Proponents of death sentences feel
that the kind of solitude these prisoners go through makes them
lose their sanity while lowering their dignity hence this
sentence is not lenient in any way.
Proponents of capital punishment bring to light some
fascinating facts. According to Ronald Earle, an attorney, it is
quite possible for offenders to commit murder again while in
prison thus indicating just how risky life imprisonment without
parole can be. Some prisoners would rather experience the 15-
minute trauma associated with carrying out a death sentence
rather than face a lifetime of psychological and emotional
torture. Kenneth Hartman a convicted prisoner facing life in
prison without parole perceives LWOP prisoners as dead men
walking whose lives are condemned to lifetime torture and
devoid of any chance of restoration. If I were a death sentence
advocate, I would probably notice the additional torture one
faces in prison life knowing that one will die there without a
chance of ever tasting freedom again. I might also find out that
life in prison is not as lenient as I thought it was. However, in
circumstances where the prisoner is likely to develop some
mental instability and commit more crimes while in prison,
executions can be swiftly carried out. Again, in countries where
prisons are not well guarded or where cases of jailbreaks are
high, death sentences can be considered.
References
Appleton, C., & Grover, B. (2006). The Pros and Cons of Life
Without Parole. British Journal Of Criminology, 47(4), 597-
615. http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/bjc/azm001
Hoffman, K. (2005). Book Review: Life Without Parole: Living
in Prison TodayLife Without Parole: Living in Prison
TodayHassineVictor3d ed.Los Angeles, CA:Roxbury. 2004. 267
pp. $38.95. Teaching Sociology, 33(2), 229-231.
http://dx.doi.org/10.1177/0092055x0503300214
Novek, E. (2011). The Alternatives to Violence Project's Work
for Peace Behind Bars. Peace Review, 23(3), 335-341.
http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/10402659.2011.596061
Thompson, S. (2017). Opinion | What I Learned From Executing
Two Men. Nytimes.com. Retrieved 11 October 2017, from
https://www.nytimes.com/2016/09/18/opinion/sunday/what-i-
learned-from-executing-two-men.html
13
The Believing Game and How to Make Conflicting Opinions
More Fruitful
Peter Elbow
[A chapter in Nurturing the Peacemakers in Our Students: A
Guide to Teaching Peace,
Empathy, and
Understanding. Chris Weber, editor. Heinemann, 2006. The
present version contains a
few short
passages that had to be cut for space reasons in the published
version.]
Don Quixote says he admires Sancho Panza because he
doubts everything and he believes everything.
In the chapter before this, Chris Weber suggests ways to help
students speak their minds, listen well, and engage in
nonadversarial
dialogue rather than debate. His suggestions focus on outward
behavior.
In this essay, I will move inward to the mysterious dimension of
thinking
and feeling. I’ll start by asking you to imagine that you are
looking at an
inkblot (for examples, ask Google Images for “inkblots”).
Imagine that you see something in it that interests and pleases
you--
-but your colleagues or classmates don’t see what you see. In
fact they
think you are crazy or disturbed for seeing it. What would you
do if you
wanted to convince them that your interpretation makes sense?
If it were a matter of geometry, you could prove you are right
(or
wrong!). But with inkblots, you don’t have logic’s leverage.
Your only
hope is to get them to enter into your way of seeing---to have
the
experience you are having. You need to get them to say the
magic
words: “Oh now I see what you see.”
This means getting them to exercise the ability to see something
differently (i.e., seeing the same thing in multiple ways), and
also the
willingness to risk doing so (not knowing where it will lead).
In short, you
need them to be flexible both cognitively and emotionally. You
can’t
make people enter into a new way of seeing, even if they are
capable
of it. Perhaps your colleagues or classmates are bothered by
what you
see in the inkblot. Perhaps they think it’s aberrant or psychotic.
If you
want them to take the risk, your only option is to set a good
example and
show that you are willing to see it the way they see it.
From Inkblots to Arguments
14
Interpreting inkblots is highly subjective, but the process serves
to
highlight how arguments also have a subjective dimension. Few
arguments are settled by logic. Should we invade countries that
might
attack us? Should we torture prisoners who might know what we
need to
know? Should we drop a nuclear bomb on a country that did
attack us?
And by the way, what grade is fair for this paper or this
student? Should
we use grades at all?
I’m not denying the force of logic. Logic can uncover a genuine
error in someone’s argument. But logic cannot uncover an error
in
someone’s position. If we could have proven that Iraq had no
weapons
of mass destruction, that wouldn’t have proven that it was
wrong to
invade Iraq. “We should invade Iraq” is a claim that is
impossible to prove
or disprove. We can use logic to strengthen arguments for or
against the
claim, but we cannot prove or disprove it. Over and over we see
illogical
arguments for good ideas and logical arguments for bad ideas.
We can
never prove that an opinion or position is wrong---or right. No
wonder
people so seldom change their minds when someone finds bad
reasoning in their argument. (By the same token—or at least a
very
similar token—it is impossible to prove or disprove the
interpretation of a
text. For more on this, see my longer essays on the believing
game.)
This explains a lot about how most people deal with differences
of
opinion:
• Some people love to argue and disagree, and they do it for fun
in a
friendly way. They enjoy the disagreement and the give-and-
take and
they let criticisms and even attacks roll right off their backs.
It’s good
intellectual sport for them.
• Some people look like they enjoy the sport of argument. They
stay
friendly and rational---they’re “cool”---because they’ve been
trained
well. “Don’t let your feelings cloud your thinking.” But inside
they feel
hurt when others attack ideas they care about. They hunker
down into
their ideas behind hidden walls.
• Some people actually get mad, raise their voices, dig in, stop
listening,
and even call each other names. Perhaps they realize that
language
and logic have no power to make their listeners change their
minds---
so they give in to shouting or anger.
• And some people---seeing that nothing can be proven with
words---
just give up on argument. They retreat. “Let’s just not argue.
You see it
15
your way, I’ll see it my way. That’s the end of it. There’s no
use
talking.” They sidestep arguments and take a relativist position:
any
opinion is as good as any other opinion. (It’s worth pondering
why so
many students fall into this attitude.)
But sometimes people actually listen to each other, come to
really see
the merit in opinions they started off fighting. Through listening
to
someone else’s views, they do something amazing: they actually
change their thinking. Sometimes strong differences of opinion
are
resolved---even heated arguments.
When this happens people demonstrate the two inkblot skills I
just
described: the ability and the willingness to see something
differently---or
in this case to think or understand something differently. (We
often say “I
see” when we “understand” something differently). These are
precious
skills, cognitive and psychological. We won’t have much luck
encouraging them in other people unless we develop them in
ourselves.
With inkblots, the risk seems small. If we manage to see a blot
the
way a classmate or colleague sees it, we don’t have to say,
“Stupid me. I
was wrong.” It’s “live and let live” when we’re dealing with
inkblots. With
arguments, however, it feels like win or lose. We often want
people not
just to understand our position; we often want them to give up
their
(“wrong, stupid”) position.
I used inkblots earlier to look for the subjective dimension in
most
arguments (given that logic cannot prove or destroy a position).
Now
inkblots can teach us something else. They can teach us that
there’s
actually a “live-and-let-live” dimension in many arguments---
probably
most. But we often feel arguments as win/lose situations
because we so
naturally focus on how our side of an argument differs from the
other
person’s side. We assume that one person has to say, “Stupid
me. I was
wrong.”
The believing game will help us understand ideas we disagree
with,
and thereby help us see that one one needs to lose or give up
their
central idea. The believing game can help us see that both sides
in an
argument are often right; or that both are right in a sense; or
that both
positions are implicitly pointing to some larger, wiser position
that both
arguers can agree on.
16
What is the Believing Game?
In a sense I’ve already explained it with my analogy between
inkblots and arguments. I can summarize it quickly now by
contrasting it
with the doubting game.
The doubting game represents the kind of thinking most widely
honored and taught. It’s the disciplined practice of trying to be
as
skeptical and analytic as possible with every idea we encounter.
By
doubting well, we can discover hidden contradictions, bad
reasoning, or
other weaknesses in ideas that look true or attractive. We
scrutinize with
the tool of doubt. This is the tradition that Walter Lippman
invokes:
The opposition is indispensable. A good statesman, like any
other
sensible human being, always learns more from his opponents
than
from his fervent supporters. For his supporters will push him to
disaster
unless his opponents show him where the dangers are. So if he
is
wise he will often pray to be delivered from his friends, because
they will ruin him. But, though it hurts, he ought . . . to pray
never to
be left without opponents; for they keep him on the path of
reason
and good sense.
The widespread veneration of “critical thinking” illustrates how
our
intellectual culture venerates skepticism and doubting.
(“Critical
thinking” is a fuzzy, fad term , but its various meanings usually
appeal to
skepticism and analysis for the sake of uncovering bad thinking.
When
people call a movement “critical linguistics” or “critical legal
studies,”
they are saying that the old linguistics or legal studies are
flawed by
being insufficiently skeptical or critical---too hospitable to
something
that’s wrong.)
The believing game is the mirror image of the doubting game or
critical thinking. It’s the disciplined practice of trying to be as
welcoming
as possible to every idea we encounter: not just listening to
views
different from our own and holding back from arguing with
them, but
actually trying to believe them. We can use the tool of believing
to
scrutinize not for flaws but to find hidden virtues in ideas that
are
unfashionable or repellent. Often we cannot see what’s good in
someone else’s idea (or in our own!) till we work at believing
it. When an
idea goes against current assumptions and beliefs---or seems
alien,
weird, dangerous---or if it’s poorly formulated---we often
cannot see any
merit in it.
17
“Believing” is a Scary Word
Many people get nervous when I celebrate believing. They point
to
an asymmetry between our sense of what “doubting” and
“believing”
mean. Believing seems to entail commitment, where doubting
does not.
It commonly feels as though we can doubt something without
committing ourselves to rejecting it---but that we cannot believe
something without committing ourselves to accepting it and
even living
by it. Thus it feels as though we can doubt and remain
unscathed, but
believing will scathe us. Indeed believing can feel hopelessly
bound up
with religion. (“Do you BELIEVE? Yes, Lord, I BELIEVE!”)
This contrast in meanings is a fairly valid picture of natural
,individual
acts of doubting and believing. (Though I wonder if doubting
leaves us
fully unchanged.) But it’s not a picture of doubting and
believing as
methodological disciplines or unnatural games. Let me explain
the
distinction.
Natural individual acts of doubting happen when someone tells
us
something that seems dubious or hard to believe. (“You say the
earth is
spinning? I doubt it. I feel it steady under my feet.”) But our
culture has
learned to go way beyond natural individual acts of doubting.
We
humans had to struggle for a long time to learn how to doubt
unnaturally
as a methodological discipline. We now know that for good
thinking, we
must doubt everything, not just what’s dubious; indeed the
whole point
of critical thinking is to try to doubt what we find most obvious
or true or
right (as Lippman advises).
In order to develop systematic doubting, we had to overcome
believing: the natural pull to believe what's easy to believe,
what we
want to believe, or what powerful people tell us to believe. (It’s
easy to
believe that the earth is stationary.) As a culture, we learned
systematic
doubting through the growth of philosophical thinking (Greek
thinkers
developing logic, Renaissance thinkers developing science, and
Enlightenment thinkers pulling away from established religion).
And we
each had to learn to be skeptical as individuals, too---for
example
learning not to believe that if we are very very good, Santa
Claus/God
will bring us everything we want. As children, we begin to
notice that
naïve belief leads us astray. As adults we begin to notice the
dreadful
18
things that belief leads humans to do---like torturing alleged
witches/prisoners till they "confess."
Now that we’ve finally learned systematic doubting with its
tools of
logic and strict reasoning and its attitude of systematic
skepticism---
critical thinking---we are likely to end up afraid of believing
itself. We had
to learn to distrust natural believing (“My parents/country/God
will take
care of me whenever I am in need.”). So believing can seem a
scary
word because our culture has not yet learned to go beyond
natural acts
of naïve believing to develop unnatural believing as a
methodological
discipline. In short, the believing game is not much honored or
even
known (though it’s not new).
The methodology of the doubting game gives us a model for the
methodology of the believing game. When the doubting game
asks us
to doubt an idea, it doesn't ask us to throw it away forever. We
couldn’t
do that because the game teaches us to doubt all ideas, and we’ll
learn
to find weaknesses even in good ideas. We can’t throw all ideas
away.
The scrutiny of doubt is methodological, provisional,
conditional. So when
a good doubter finally decides what to believe or do, this
involves an
additional act of judgment and commitment. The doubting
game gives
good evidence, but it doesn’t do our judging and committing for
us.
Similarly, when the believing game asks us to believe all ideas--
-
especially those that seem most wrong---it cannot ask us to
marry them
or commit ourselves to them. Our believing is also
methodological,
conditional, provisional---unnatural. (It’s hard to try to believe
conflicting
ideas all at once, but we can try to enter into them one after
another.)
And so too, if we commit ourselves to accepting an idea because
the
believing game helped us see virtues in it, this involves an
additional act
of judgment and commitment. The believing game gives us good
evidence, but it doesn’t do our deciding for us.
In short, we must indeed continue to resist the pull to believe
what's
easy to believe. But believing what’s easy to believe is far
different from
using the disciplined effort to believe as an intellectual
methodological
tool in order to find hidden strengths in ideas that people want
to ignore.
A Surprising Blind Spot for the Doubting Game
19
The doubting and believing games have symmetrical
weaknesses:
the doubting game is poor at helping us find hidden virtues; the
believing
game is poor at helping us find hidden flaws. But many people
don’t
realize that the doubting game is also poor at reaching one of its
main
goals: helping us find hidden flaws in our own thinking.
The flaws in our own thinking usually come from our
assumptions---our
ways of thinking that we accept without noticing. But it’s hard
to doubt
what we can’t see because we unconsciously take it for granted.
The
believing game comes to the rescue here. Our best hope for
finding
invisible flaws in what we can’t see in our own thinking is to
enter into
different ideas or points of view---ideas that carry different
assumptions.
Only after we’ve managed to inhabit a different way of thinking
will our
currently invisible assumptions become visible to us.
This blind spot in the doubting game shows up frequently in
classrooms and other meetings. When smart people are trained
only in
critical thinking, they get better and better at doubting and
criticizing
other people’s ideas. They use this skill particularly well when
they feel a
threat to their own ideas or their unexamined assumptions. Yet
they feel
justified in fending-off what they disagree with because they
feel that this
doubting activity is “critical thinking.” They take refuge in the
feeling that
they would be “unintellectual” if they said to an opponent what
in fact
they ought to say: “Wow, your idea sounds really wrong to me.
It must
be alien to how I think. Let me try to enter into it and see if
there’s
something important that I’m missing. Let me see if I can get a
better
perspective on my own thinking.” In short, if we want to be
good at
finding flaws in our own thinking (a goal that doubters
constantly
trumpet), we need the believing game.
The Believing Game is Not Actually New
If we look closely at the behavior of genuinely smart and
productive
people, we will see that many of them have exactly this skill of
entering
into views that conflict with their own. John Stuart Mill is a
philosopher
associated with the doubting game, but he also advises good
thinkers to
engage in the central act of the believing game:
[People who] have never thrown themselves into the mental
position of those who think differently from them . . . do not, in
any
20
proper sense of the word, know the doctrine which they
themselves
profess. (129)
Yet this skill of sophisticated unnatural belief is not much
understood or
celebrated in our culture---and almost never taught.
Imagine, for example, a seminar or a meeting where lots of
ideas
come up. One person is quick to point out flaws in each idea as
it is
presented. A second person mostly listens and gets intrigued
with each
idea--and tends to make comments like these: “Oh I see” and
“That’s
interesting” and “Tell me more about such and such” and “As I
go with
your thinking, I begin to see some things I never noticed
before.” This
second person may be appreciated as a good listener, but the
first
person will tend to be considered smarter and a better thinker
because
of that quick skill at finding flaws.
I used to feel that I was unintelligent because when one person
gave an argument I would feel, “Oh that’s a good idea,” but
then when
the other person argued the other way, I found myself feeling,
“Oh that
sounds good, too.” I wondered what was the matter with my
loose,
sloppy mind to let me agree with people and ideas that are
completely
at odds with each other. The “smart people” tended to argue
cleverly
and find flaws that I didn’t notice. But now I’m finally insisting
that my
instinctive ability to play the believing game is not just
“niceness” or
sloppy thinking; it’s a crucial intellectual strength rather than a
weakness-
--a discipline that needs to be taught and developed.
Let me emphasize that I’m not arguing against the doubting
game.
We need the ability to be skeptical and find flaws. Indeed, the
doubting
game probably deserves the last word in any valid process of
trying to
work out trustworthy thinking. For even though the scrutiny of
belief may
lead us to choose a good idea that most people at first wanted to
throw
away, nevertheless, we mustn’t commit ourselves to that idea
before
applying the scrutiny of doubt to check for hidden problems.
My only argument is against the monopoly of the doubting game
as
the only kind of good thinking. We need both disciplines. Some
of our
most needed insights come from opinions that are easy to
criticize or
dismiss. But those insights are only available if people work at
entering
into such opinions in search of unnoticed virtues.
21
Concrete Ways to Learn to Play the Believing Game
As teachers and students we are in a good position to learn the
ability to see things differently from how we usually see them,
and the
willingness to risk doing it. If we want to learn those skills, it
helps to notice
the inner stances ---the cognitive and psychological
dispositions---we
need for doubting and believing:
• If we want to doubt or find flaws in ideas that we are tempted
to
accept or believe (perhaps they are ideas that “everyone knows
are
true”), we need to work at extricating or distancing ourselves
from
those ideas. There’s a kind of language that helps here: clear,
impersonal sentences that lay bare the logic or lack of logic in
them.
• If, on the other hand, we want to believe ideas that we are
tempted
to reject (“Anyone can see that’s a crazy idea”)---if we are
trying to
enter in or experience or dwell in those ideas---we benefit from
the
language of imagination, narrative, and the personal experience.
Here are some specific practices to help us experience things
from
someone else’s point of view.
1. If people are stuck in a disagreement, we can invoke Carl
Rogers’
application of “active listening.” John must not try to argue his
point till
he has restated Mary’s point to her satisfaction.
2. But what if John has trouble seeing things from Mary’s point
of view?
His lame efforts to restate her view show that “he doesn't get
it.” He
probably needs to stop talking and listen; keep his mouth shut.
Thus, in a
discussion where someone is trying to advance a view and
everyone
fights it, there is a simple rule of thumb: the doubters need to
stop talking
and simply give extended floor time to the minority view. The
following
three concrete activities give enormous help here:
• The three-minute or five-minute rule. Any participant who
feels he or
she is not being heard can make a sign and invoke the rule: no
one
else can talk for three or five minutes. This voice speaks, we
listen; we
cannot reply.
• Allies only---no objections. Others can speak---but only those
who are
having more success believing or entering into or assenting to
the
minority view. No objections allowed. (Most people are familiar
with
this “no-objections” rule from brainstorming.)
22
• “Testimony session.” Participants having a hard time being
heard or
understood are invited to tell stories of the experiences that led
them
to their point of view and to describe what it's like having or
living with
this view. Not only must the rest of us not answer or argue or
disagree
while they are speaking; we must refrain, even afterwards, from
questioning their stories or experiences or feelings. We may
speak only
to their ideas. (This process is particularly useful when issues
of race,
gender, and sexual orientation are being discussed.)
The goal here is safety. Most speakers feel unsafe if they sense
we
are just waiting to jump in with all our objections. But we
listeners need
safety, too. We are trying to enter into a view we want to
quarrel with or
feel threatened by. We’re trying to learn the difficult skill of in-
dwelling. It's
safer for us if we have permission simply not to talk about it
any more for
a while. We need time for the words we resist just to sink in for
a while with
no comment.
3. The language of story and poetry helps us experience alien
ideas.
Stories, metaphors, and images can often find a path around our
resistance. When it’s hard to enter into a new point of view, try
telling a
story of someone who believes it; imagine and describe
someone who
sees things this way; tell the story of events that might have led
people to
have this view of the world; what would it be like to be
someone who
sees things this way? Write a story or poem about the world that
this view
implies.
4. Step out of language. Language itself can sometimes get in
the way
of trying to experience or enter into a point of view different
from our
own. There are various productive ways to set language aside.
We can
draw or sketch images (rough stick figures are fine). What do
you
actually see when you take this position? It’s also powerful to
use
movement, gesture, dance, sounds, and role-playing.
5. Silence. For centuries, people have made good use of silence
for in-
dwelling. If we’re having trouble trying to believe someone’s
idea,
sometimes it’s helpful for no one to say anything for a couple of
minutes.
That’s not much time out of a meeting or conference or class
hour, but it
can be surprisingly fertile.
6. Private writing. There's a kind of silence involved when
everyone
engages in private writing. Stop talking and do 7-10 minutes of
writing for
23
no one else’s eyes. What's crucial is the invitation to language
in
conditions of privacy and safety.
7. Use the physical voice. When it’s hard to enter into a piece of
writing
that feels difficult or distant, for example something written by
someone
very different from us---or an intricate work like a Shakespeare
sonnet---it
helps to try to read it aloud as well and meaningfully as
possible. (When
I’m teaching a longer text, I choose crux passages of a few
paragraphs
or a page.) The goal is not good acting; the goal is simply to say
the
words so that we feel every meaning in them---so that we fully
mean
every meaning. Get the words to “sound right” or to carry the
meanings
across—for example, to listeners who don’t have a text. After
we have
three or four different readings of the same passage, we can
discuss
which ones manage to “sound right”---and usually these
readings help us
enter in or assent. (It’s not fair to put students on the spot by
asking them
to read with no preparation time. I ask students to prepare these
reading
at home or practice them briefly in class in pairs.)
This activity illustrates something interesting about language.
It’s
impossible simply to say words so they “sound right" without
dwelling in
them and thus feeling their meaning. So instead of asking
students to
“study carefully” this Shakespeare sonnet, I say, “Practice
reading it
aloud till you can say every word with meaning.” This involves
giving a
kind of bodily assent.
8. Nonadversarial argument. Finally, the classroom is an ideal
place to
practice nonadversarial forms of argument. Our traditional
model of
argument is a zero-sum game: “If I'm right, you must be
wrong.” Essays
and dissertations traditionally start off by trying to demolish the
views of
opponents. “Unless I criticize every other idea,” the assumption
goes, “I
won’t have a clear space for my idea.” But this approach is
usually
counterproductive--except with readers who already agree with
you
and don’t need to be persuaded. This traditional argument
structure
says to readers: “You cannot agree with my ideas---or even hear
them---
until after you admit that you’ve been wrong or stupid.”
The structure of nonadversarial argument is simple, but it takes
practice and discipline: argue only for your position, not against
other
positions. This is easy for me here since I have no criticisms at
all of the
doubting game or critical thinking in itself. It’s much harder if I
really hate
the idea I’m fighting. It’s particularly hard if my essential
argument is
negative: “Don’t invade Iraq.” So yes, there are some situations
in which
24
we cannot avoid arguing why an idea is wrong. Yet even in my
position
on Iraq, there is, in fact, some space for nonadversarial
argument. I can
talk about the advantages of not invading Iraq---and not try to
refute for
invasion. In this way, I would increase the chances of my
opponent
actually hearing my arguments.
The general principle is this: If all I have to offer are negative
reasons
why the other person’s idea is bad, I’ll probably make less
progress than if
I can give some positive reasons for my alternative idea---and
even
acknowledge why the other person might favor her idea. (For
more on
nonadversarial argument, see my “Introduction” xviii-xxiii.)
I can end by glancing back at the inkblots. Arguments that look
conflicting might both be somehow valid or right. They might
need to be
articulated better or seen from a larger view---a view the
disputants
haven't yet figured out. I may be convinced that someone else’s
idea is
dead wrong, but if I’m willing to play the believing game with
it, I will not
only set a good example, I may even be able to see how we are
both
on the right track. Nonadversarial argument and the believing
game
help us work out larger frames of reference and better ideas.
Works Cited
Elbow, Peter. “Appendix Essay. The Doubting Game and the
Believing
Game: An Analysis of the Intellectual Process.” In Writing
Without
Teachers. Oxford University Press, 1973. 147-91.
---. “Bringing the Rhetoric of Assent and The Believing Game
Together--
and into the Classroom.” College English 67.4 (March 2005):
388-99.
---. Introduction. Everyone Can Write: Essays Toward a
Hopeful Theory of
Writing and Teaching Writing. NY: Oxford University Press,
2000.
---. “Methodological Doubting and Believing: Contraries in
Inquiry.” In
Embracing Contraries: Explorations in Learning and Teaching.
Oxford University Press, 1986. 254-300.
Graff, Gerald. Clueless in Academe: How Schooling Obscures
the Life of
the Mind. New Haven: Yale UP, 2003.
Lippman, Walter. “The Indispensable Opposition.” Atlantic
Monthly
(August 1939). It’s notable that this essay is canonized in many
editions of The Norton Reader (e.g., in the 6th edition, pages
850-55).
Mill, John Stuart. On Liberty. London, Dent, 1951.
25
Rogers, Carl. "Communication: Its Blocking and Its
Facilitation." On
Becoming a Person. NY: Houghton Mifflin, 1961.
Tannen, Deborah. The Argument Culture: Moving From Debate
to
Dialogue. Random House, 1998

More Related Content

Similar to Death Penalty Debate (10)

Culture
CultureCulture
Culture
 
Death Penalty Persuasive Essay
Death Penalty Persuasive EssayDeath Penalty Persuasive Essay
Death Penalty Persuasive Essay
 
Running head Capital punishment debate Capital punishment deba.docx
Running head Capital punishment debate  Capital punishment deba.docxRunning head Capital punishment debate  Capital punishment deba.docx
Running head Capital punishment debate Capital punishment deba.docx
 
Death Penalty Debate
Death Penalty DebateDeath Penalty Debate
Death Penalty Debate
 
Death Penalty Against Essay
Death Penalty Against EssayDeath Penalty Against Essay
Death Penalty Against Essay
 
Texas And The Death Penalty Essay
Texas And The Death Penalty EssayTexas And The Death Penalty Essay
Texas And The Death Penalty Essay
 
For The Death Penalty Essay
For The Death Penalty EssayFor The Death Penalty Essay
For The Death Penalty Essay
 
Harvard Discussion post Sample on Capital punishment (Death penalty) by writi...
Harvard Discussion post Sample on Capital punishment (Death penalty) by writi...Harvard Discussion post Sample on Capital punishment (Death penalty) by writi...
Harvard Discussion post Sample on Capital punishment (Death penalty) by writi...
 
Anti Death Penalty Arguments Essay
Anti Death Penalty Arguments EssayAnti Death Penalty Arguments Essay
Anti Death Penalty Arguments Essay
 
Pro Death Penalty Essays
Pro Death Penalty EssaysPro Death Penalty Essays
Pro Death Penalty Essays
 

More from susanschei

Src TemplateStandard Recipe CardName of dishSpanish Vegie Tray Ba.docx
Src TemplateStandard Recipe CardName of dishSpanish Vegie Tray Ba.docxSrc TemplateStandard Recipe CardName of dishSpanish Vegie Tray Ba.docx
Src TemplateStandard Recipe CardName of dishSpanish Vegie Tray Ba.docxsusanschei
 
SPT 208 Final Project Guidelines and Rubric Overview .docx
SPT 208 Final Project Guidelines and Rubric  Overview .docxSPT 208 Final Project Guidelines and Rubric  Overview .docx
SPT 208 Final Project Guidelines and Rubric Overview .docxsusanschei
 
Ssalinas_ThreeMountainsRegionalHospitalCodeofEthics73119.docxR.docx
Ssalinas_ThreeMountainsRegionalHospitalCodeofEthics73119.docxR.docxSsalinas_ThreeMountainsRegionalHospitalCodeofEthics73119.docxR.docx
Ssalinas_ThreeMountainsRegionalHospitalCodeofEthics73119.docxR.docxsusanschei
 
Spring 2020Professor Tim SmithE mail [email protected]Teach.docx
Spring 2020Professor Tim SmithE mail [email protected]Teach.docxSpring 2020Professor Tim SmithE mail [email protected]Teach.docx
Spring 2020Professor Tim SmithE mail [email protected]Teach.docxsusanschei
 
Spring 2020 – Business Continuity & Disaster R.docx
Spring 2020 – Business Continuity & Disaster R.docxSpring 2020 – Business Continuity & Disaster R.docx
Spring 2020 – Business Continuity & Disaster R.docxsusanschei
 
Sports Business Landscape Graphic OrganizerContent.docx
Sports Business Landscape Graphic OrganizerContent.docxSports Business Landscape Graphic OrganizerContent.docx
Sports Business Landscape Graphic OrganizerContent.docxsusanschei
 
Spring 2020Carlow University Department of Psychology & Co.docx
Spring 2020Carlow University Department of Psychology & Co.docxSpring 2020Carlow University Department of Psychology & Co.docx
Spring 2020Carlow University Department of Psychology & Co.docxsusanschei
 
SPOTLIGHT ON STRATEGY FOR TURBULENT TIMESSpotlight ARTWORK.docx
SPOTLIGHT ON STRATEGY FOR TURBULENT TIMESSpotlight ARTWORK.docxSPOTLIGHT ON STRATEGY FOR TURBULENT TIMESSpotlight ARTWORK.docx
SPOTLIGHT ON STRATEGY FOR TURBULENT TIMESSpotlight ARTWORK.docxsusanschei
 
Sport Ticket sales staff trainingChapter 4Sales .docx
Sport Ticket sales staff trainingChapter 4Sales .docxSport Ticket sales staff trainingChapter 4Sales .docx
Sport Ticket sales staff trainingChapter 4Sales .docxsusanschei
 
SPOTLIGHT ARTWORK Do Ho Suh, Floor, 1997–2000, PVC figures, gl.docx
SPOTLIGHT ARTWORK Do Ho Suh, Floor, 1997–2000, PVC figures, gl.docxSPOTLIGHT ARTWORK Do Ho Suh, Floor, 1997–2000, PVC figures, gl.docx
SPOTLIGHT ARTWORK Do Ho Suh, Floor, 1997–2000, PVC figures, gl.docxsusanschei
 
Sponsorship Works 2018 8PROJECT DETAILSSponsorship tit.docx
Sponsorship Works 2018 8PROJECT DETAILSSponsorship tit.docxSponsorship Works 2018 8PROJECT DETAILSSponsorship tit.docx
Sponsorship Works 2018 8PROJECT DETAILSSponsorship tit.docxsusanschei
 
SPM 4723 Annotated Bibliography You second major proje.docx
SPM 4723 Annotated Bibliography You second major proje.docxSPM 4723 Annotated Bibliography You second major proje.docx
SPM 4723 Annotated Bibliography You second major proje.docxsusanschei
 
Speech Environment and Recording Requirements• You must have a.docx
Speech Environment and Recording Requirements• You must have a.docxSpeech Environment and Recording Requirements• You must have a.docx
Speech Environment and Recording Requirements• You must have a.docxsusanschei
 
Sped4 Interview 2.10.17 Audio.m4aJodee [000008] And we are .docx
Sped4 Interview 2.10.17 Audio.m4aJodee [000008] And we are .docxSped4 Interview 2.10.17 Audio.m4aJodee [000008] And we are .docx
Sped4 Interview 2.10.17 Audio.m4aJodee [000008] And we are .docxsusanschei
 
Speech Recognition in the Electronic Health Record (2013 u.docx
Speech Recognition in the Electronic Health Record (2013 u.docxSpeech Recognition in the Electronic Health Record (2013 u.docx
Speech Recognition in the Electronic Health Record (2013 u.docxsusanschei
 
Sped Focus Group.m4aJodee [000001] This is a focus group wi.docx
Sped Focus Group.m4aJodee [000001] This is a focus group wi.docxSped Focus Group.m4aJodee [000001] This is a focus group wi.docx
Sped Focus Group.m4aJodee [000001] This is a focus group wi.docxsusanschei
 
Specialized Terms 20.0 Definitions and examples of specialized.docx
Specialized Terms 20.0 Definitions and examples of specialized.docxSpecialized Terms 20.0 Definitions and examples of specialized.docx
Specialized Terms 20.0 Definitions and examples of specialized.docxsusanschei
 
Special notes Media and the media are plural and take plural verb.docx
Special notes Media and the media are plural and take plural verb.docxSpecial notes Media and the media are plural and take plural verb.docx
Special notes Media and the media are plural and take plural verb.docxsusanschei
 
SPECIAL ISSUE ON POLITICAL VIOLENCEResearch on Social Move.docx
SPECIAL ISSUE ON POLITICAL VIOLENCEResearch on Social Move.docxSPECIAL ISSUE ON POLITICAL VIOLENCEResearch on Social Move.docx
SPECIAL ISSUE ON POLITICAL VIOLENCEResearch on Social Move.docxsusanschei
 
SPECIAL ISSUE CRITICAL REALISM IN IS RESEARCHCRITICAL RE.docx
SPECIAL ISSUE  CRITICAL REALISM IN IS RESEARCHCRITICAL RE.docxSPECIAL ISSUE  CRITICAL REALISM IN IS RESEARCHCRITICAL RE.docx
SPECIAL ISSUE CRITICAL REALISM IN IS RESEARCHCRITICAL RE.docxsusanschei
 

More from susanschei (20)

Src TemplateStandard Recipe CardName of dishSpanish Vegie Tray Ba.docx
Src TemplateStandard Recipe CardName of dishSpanish Vegie Tray Ba.docxSrc TemplateStandard Recipe CardName of dishSpanish Vegie Tray Ba.docx
Src TemplateStandard Recipe CardName of dishSpanish Vegie Tray Ba.docx
 
SPT 208 Final Project Guidelines and Rubric Overview .docx
SPT 208 Final Project Guidelines and Rubric  Overview .docxSPT 208 Final Project Guidelines and Rubric  Overview .docx
SPT 208 Final Project Guidelines and Rubric Overview .docx
 
Ssalinas_ThreeMountainsRegionalHospitalCodeofEthics73119.docxR.docx
Ssalinas_ThreeMountainsRegionalHospitalCodeofEthics73119.docxR.docxSsalinas_ThreeMountainsRegionalHospitalCodeofEthics73119.docxR.docx
Ssalinas_ThreeMountainsRegionalHospitalCodeofEthics73119.docxR.docx
 
Spring 2020Professor Tim SmithE mail [email protected]Teach.docx
Spring 2020Professor Tim SmithE mail [email protected]Teach.docxSpring 2020Professor Tim SmithE mail [email protected]Teach.docx
Spring 2020Professor Tim SmithE mail [email protected]Teach.docx
 
Spring 2020 – Business Continuity & Disaster R.docx
Spring 2020 – Business Continuity & Disaster R.docxSpring 2020 – Business Continuity & Disaster R.docx
Spring 2020 – Business Continuity & Disaster R.docx
 
Sports Business Landscape Graphic OrganizerContent.docx
Sports Business Landscape Graphic OrganizerContent.docxSports Business Landscape Graphic OrganizerContent.docx
Sports Business Landscape Graphic OrganizerContent.docx
 
Spring 2020Carlow University Department of Psychology & Co.docx
Spring 2020Carlow University Department of Psychology & Co.docxSpring 2020Carlow University Department of Psychology & Co.docx
Spring 2020Carlow University Department of Psychology & Co.docx
 
SPOTLIGHT ON STRATEGY FOR TURBULENT TIMESSpotlight ARTWORK.docx
SPOTLIGHT ON STRATEGY FOR TURBULENT TIMESSpotlight ARTWORK.docxSPOTLIGHT ON STRATEGY FOR TURBULENT TIMESSpotlight ARTWORK.docx
SPOTLIGHT ON STRATEGY FOR TURBULENT TIMESSpotlight ARTWORK.docx
 
Sport Ticket sales staff trainingChapter 4Sales .docx
Sport Ticket sales staff trainingChapter 4Sales .docxSport Ticket sales staff trainingChapter 4Sales .docx
Sport Ticket sales staff trainingChapter 4Sales .docx
 
SPOTLIGHT ARTWORK Do Ho Suh, Floor, 1997–2000, PVC figures, gl.docx
SPOTLIGHT ARTWORK Do Ho Suh, Floor, 1997–2000, PVC figures, gl.docxSPOTLIGHT ARTWORK Do Ho Suh, Floor, 1997–2000, PVC figures, gl.docx
SPOTLIGHT ARTWORK Do Ho Suh, Floor, 1997–2000, PVC figures, gl.docx
 
Sponsorship Works 2018 8PROJECT DETAILSSponsorship tit.docx
Sponsorship Works 2018 8PROJECT DETAILSSponsorship tit.docxSponsorship Works 2018 8PROJECT DETAILSSponsorship tit.docx
Sponsorship Works 2018 8PROJECT DETAILSSponsorship tit.docx
 
SPM 4723 Annotated Bibliography You second major proje.docx
SPM 4723 Annotated Bibliography You second major proje.docxSPM 4723 Annotated Bibliography You second major proje.docx
SPM 4723 Annotated Bibliography You second major proje.docx
 
Speech Environment and Recording Requirements• You must have a.docx
Speech Environment and Recording Requirements• You must have a.docxSpeech Environment and Recording Requirements• You must have a.docx
Speech Environment and Recording Requirements• You must have a.docx
 
Sped4 Interview 2.10.17 Audio.m4aJodee [000008] And we are .docx
Sped4 Interview 2.10.17 Audio.m4aJodee [000008] And we are .docxSped4 Interview 2.10.17 Audio.m4aJodee [000008] And we are .docx
Sped4 Interview 2.10.17 Audio.m4aJodee [000008] And we are .docx
 
Speech Recognition in the Electronic Health Record (2013 u.docx
Speech Recognition in the Electronic Health Record (2013 u.docxSpeech Recognition in the Electronic Health Record (2013 u.docx
Speech Recognition in the Electronic Health Record (2013 u.docx
 
Sped Focus Group.m4aJodee [000001] This is a focus group wi.docx
Sped Focus Group.m4aJodee [000001] This is a focus group wi.docxSped Focus Group.m4aJodee [000001] This is a focus group wi.docx
Sped Focus Group.m4aJodee [000001] This is a focus group wi.docx
 
Specialized Terms 20.0 Definitions and examples of specialized.docx
Specialized Terms 20.0 Definitions and examples of specialized.docxSpecialized Terms 20.0 Definitions and examples of specialized.docx
Specialized Terms 20.0 Definitions and examples of specialized.docx
 
Special notes Media and the media are plural and take plural verb.docx
Special notes Media and the media are plural and take plural verb.docxSpecial notes Media and the media are plural and take plural verb.docx
Special notes Media and the media are plural and take plural verb.docx
 
SPECIAL ISSUE ON POLITICAL VIOLENCEResearch on Social Move.docx
SPECIAL ISSUE ON POLITICAL VIOLENCEResearch on Social Move.docxSPECIAL ISSUE ON POLITICAL VIOLENCEResearch on Social Move.docx
SPECIAL ISSUE ON POLITICAL VIOLENCEResearch on Social Move.docx
 
SPECIAL ISSUE CRITICAL REALISM IN IS RESEARCHCRITICAL RE.docx
SPECIAL ISSUE  CRITICAL REALISM IN IS RESEARCHCRITICAL RE.docxSPECIAL ISSUE  CRITICAL REALISM IN IS RESEARCHCRITICAL RE.docx
SPECIAL ISSUE CRITICAL REALISM IN IS RESEARCHCRITICAL RE.docx
 

Recently uploaded

Kisan Call Centre - To harness potential of ICT in Agriculture by answer farm...
Kisan Call Centre - To harness potential of ICT in Agriculture by answer farm...Kisan Call Centre - To harness potential of ICT in Agriculture by answer farm...
Kisan Call Centre - To harness potential of ICT in Agriculture by answer farm...Krashi Coaching
 
Explore beautiful and ugly buildings. Mathematics helps us create beautiful d...
Explore beautiful and ugly buildings. Mathematics helps us create beautiful d...Explore beautiful and ugly buildings. Mathematics helps us create beautiful d...
Explore beautiful and ugly buildings. Mathematics helps us create beautiful d...christianmathematics
 
social pharmacy d-pharm 1st year by Pragati K. Mahajan
social pharmacy d-pharm 1st year by Pragati K. Mahajansocial pharmacy d-pharm 1st year by Pragati K. Mahajan
social pharmacy d-pharm 1st year by Pragati K. Mahajanpragatimahajan3
 
Z Score,T Score, Percential Rank and Box Plot Graph
Z Score,T Score, Percential Rank and Box Plot GraphZ Score,T Score, Percential Rank and Box Plot Graph
Z Score,T Score, Percential Rank and Box Plot GraphThiyagu K
 
Advanced Views - Calendar View in Odoo 17
Advanced Views - Calendar View in Odoo 17Advanced Views - Calendar View in Odoo 17
Advanced Views - Calendar View in Odoo 17Celine George
 
Arihant handbook biology for class 11 .pdf
Arihant handbook biology for class 11 .pdfArihant handbook biology for class 11 .pdf
Arihant handbook biology for class 11 .pdfchloefrazer622
 
fourth grading exam for kindergarten in writing
fourth grading exam for kindergarten in writingfourth grading exam for kindergarten in writing
fourth grading exam for kindergarten in writingTeacherCyreneCayanan
 
A Critique of the Proposed National Education Policy Reform
A Critique of the Proposed National Education Policy ReformA Critique of the Proposed National Education Policy Reform
A Critique of the Proposed National Education Policy ReformChameera Dedduwage
 
Unit-IV- Pharma. Marketing Channels.pptx
Unit-IV- Pharma. Marketing Channels.pptxUnit-IV- Pharma. Marketing Channels.pptx
Unit-IV- Pharma. Marketing Channels.pptxVishalSingh1417
 
SOCIAL AND HISTORICAL CONTEXT - LFTVD.pptx
SOCIAL AND HISTORICAL CONTEXT - LFTVD.pptxSOCIAL AND HISTORICAL CONTEXT - LFTVD.pptx
SOCIAL AND HISTORICAL CONTEXT - LFTVD.pptxiammrhaywood
 
1029-Danh muc Sach Giao Khoa khoi 6.pdf
1029-Danh muc Sach Giao Khoa khoi  6.pdf1029-Danh muc Sach Giao Khoa khoi  6.pdf
1029-Danh muc Sach Giao Khoa khoi 6.pdfQucHHunhnh
 
Paris 2024 Olympic Geographies - an activity
Paris 2024 Olympic Geographies - an activityParis 2024 Olympic Geographies - an activity
Paris 2024 Olympic Geographies - an activityGeoBlogs
 
BAG TECHNIQUE Bag technique-a tool making use of public health bag through wh...
BAG TECHNIQUE Bag technique-a tool making use of public health bag through wh...BAG TECHNIQUE Bag technique-a tool making use of public health bag through wh...
BAG TECHNIQUE Bag technique-a tool making use of public health bag through wh...Sapna Thakur
 
Interactive Powerpoint_How to Master effective communication
Interactive Powerpoint_How to Master effective communicationInteractive Powerpoint_How to Master effective communication
Interactive Powerpoint_How to Master effective communicationnomboosow
 
General AI for Medical Educators April 2024
General AI for Medical Educators April 2024General AI for Medical Educators April 2024
General AI for Medical Educators April 2024Janet Corral
 
Russian Escort Service in Delhi 11k Hotel Foreigner Russian Call Girls in Delhi
Russian Escort Service in Delhi 11k Hotel Foreigner Russian Call Girls in DelhiRussian Escort Service in Delhi 11k Hotel Foreigner Russian Call Girls in Delhi
Russian Escort Service in Delhi 11k Hotel Foreigner Russian Call Girls in Delhikauryashika82
 

Recently uploaded (20)

Kisan Call Centre - To harness potential of ICT in Agriculture by answer farm...
Kisan Call Centre - To harness potential of ICT in Agriculture by answer farm...Kisan Call Centre - To harness potential of ICT in Agriculture by answer farm...
Kisan Call Centre - To harness potential of ICT in Agriculture by answer farm...
 
Explore beautiful and ugly buildings. Mathematics helps us create beautiful d...
Explore beautiful and ugly buildings. Mathematics helps us create beautiful d...Explore beautiful and ugly buildings. Mathematics helps us create beautiful d...
Explore beautiful and ugly buildings. Mathematics helps us create beautiful d...
 
social pharmacy d-pharm 1st year by Pragati K. Mahajan
social pharmacy d-pharm 1st year by Pragati K. Mahajansocial pharmacy d-pharm 1st year by Pragati K. Mahajan
social pharmacy d-pharm 1st year by Pragati K. Mahajan
 
Código Creativo y Arte de Software | Unidad 1
Código Creativo y Arte de Software | Unidad 1Código Creativo y Arte de Software | Unidad 1
Código Creativo y Arte de Software | Unidad 1
 
Mattingly "AI & Prompt Design: Structured Data, Assistants, & RAG"
Mattingly "AI & Prompt Design: Structured Data, Assistants, & RAG"Mattingly "AI & Prompt Design: Structured Data, Assistants, & RAG"
Mattingly "AI & Prompt Design: Structured Data, Assistants, & RAG"
 
Z Score,T Score, Percential Rank and Box Plot Graph
Z Score,T Score, Percential Rank and Box Plot GraphZ Score,T Score, Percential Rank and Box Plot Graph
Z Score,T Score, Percential Rank and Box Plot Graph
 
Advanced Views - Calendar View in Odoo 17
Advanced Views - Calendar View in Odoo 17Advanced Views - Calendar View in Odoo 17
Advanced Views - Calendar View in Odoo 17
 
Arihant handbook biology for class 11 .pdf
Arihant handbook biology for class 11 .pdfArihant handbook biology for class 11 .pdf
Arihant handbook biology for class 11 .pdf
 
fourth grading exam for kindergarten in writing
fourth grading exam for kindergarten in writingfourth grading exam for kindergarten in writing
fourth grading exam for kindergarten in writing
 
Advance Mobile Application Development class 07
Advance Mobile Application Development class 07Advance Mobile Application Development class 07
Advance Mobile Application Development class 07
 
A Critique of the Proposed National Education Policy Reform
A Critique of the Proposed National Education Policy ReformA Critique of the Proposed National Education Policy Reform
A Critique of the Proposed National Education Policy Reform
 
Unit-IV- Pharma. Marketing Channels.pptx
Unit-IV- Pharma. Marketing Channels.pptxUnit-IV- Pharma. Marketing Channels.pptx
Unit-IV- Pharma. Marketing Channels.pptx
 
SOCIAL AND HISTORICAL CONTEXT - LFTVD.pptx
SOCIAL AND HISTORICAL CONTEXT - LFTVD.pptxSOCIAL AND HISTORICAL CONTEXT - LFTVD.pptx
SOCIAL AND HISTORICAL CONTEXT - LFTVD.pptx
 
1029-Danh muc Sach Giao Khoa khoi 6.pdf
1029-Danh muc Sach Giao Khoa khoi  6.pdf1029-Danh muc Sach Giao Khoa khoi  6.pdf
1029-Danh muc Sach Giao Khoa khoi 6.pdf
 
Paris 2024 Olympic Geographies - an activity
Paris 2024 Olympic Geographies - an activityParis 2024 Olympic Geographies - an activity
Paris 2024 Olympic Geographies - an activity
 
BAG TECHNIQUE Bag technique-a tool making use of public health bag through wh...
BAG TECHNIQUE Bag technique-a tool making use of public health bag through wh...BAG TECHNIQUE Bag technique-a tool making use of public health bag through wh...
BAG TECHNIQUE Bag technique-a tool making use of public health bag through wh...
 
Interactive Powerpoint_How to Master effective communication
Interactive Powerpoint_How to Master effective communicationInteractive Powerpoint_How to Master effective communication
Interactive Powerpoint_How to Master effective communication
 
General AI for Medical Educators April 2024
General AI for Medical Educators April 2024General AI for Medical Educators April 2024
General AI for Medical Educators April 2024
 
Russian Escort Service in Delhi 11k Hotel Foreigner Russian Call Girls in Delhi
Russian Escort Service in Delhi 11k Hotel Foreigner Russian Call Girls in DelhiRussian Escort Service in Delhi 11k Hotel Foreigner Russian Call Girls in Delhi
Russian Escort Service in Delhi 11k Hotel Foreigner Russian Call Girls in Delhi
 
Mattingly "AI & Prompt Design: The Basics of Prompt Design"
Mattingly "AI & Prompt Design: The Basics of Prompt Design"Mattingly "AI & Prompt Design: The Basics of Prompt Design"
Mattingly "AI & Prompt Design: The Basics of Prompt Design"
 

Death Penalty Debate

  • 1. Running head: DEATH PENALTY 1 DEATH PENALTY 6 Death Penalty Maria Feistel Strayer University Professor Jenna Thrasher-Sneathen 10/19/2017 Death Penalty Death penalty is also known as capital punishment. It is a practice sanctioned by the government as punishment for people who have committed a capital offense. The sentence for such a crime is what is referred to as a death sentence; the process of carrying out the sentence is what they refer to as execution. Capital offenses include; murder, espionage, treason, genocide, war crimes and crimes against humanity. Currently, only fifty- six countries have maintained capital punishment, other have either abolished it or maintained it for special crimes such as war crimes (Hoffman, 2005). In the United States, only 18 states have completely abolished capital punishment. The United States has carried out more than 1400 executions in four decades (1977 to 2016). To begin with, there are no major differences in crime rates in the states that allow death penalty and those which do not. Personally, I believe capital punishment is the worst violation of human rights, it is cruel and inhuman and infliction of unnecessary psychological torture on the
  • 2. victims. Death sentences are biased and to favor the rich who can afford good attorneys (Hoffman, K. (2005). It is also prejudiced against the poor and the minority races. In my opinion on would rather get a life in prison sentence than a death penalty. The first premise we are going to consider is whether death penalty helps deter crime or not. Personally, I believe it doesn't. According to an article by Professor John J. Donohue who teaches law at Stanford University, there is no statistical evidence indicating that death penalty is a deterrent against crimes such as homicide. However, Professor Cass R. Sunstein of the University of Chicago believes that capital punishment may be required not for retributive reasons but for preventing loss of innocent lives. George W. Bush, the 43rd president of the United States in a 2000 debate, said that he believes that death penalty saves other people’s lives. However, I believe that it is not right to justify death penalty solely due to its deterrent effect. The policymakers ought to find more effective, less costly ways of addressing capital offenses. The view that capital punishment deters crime is an interesting one since it doesn't have any credible statistical evidence that proves its effectiveness in reducing crime yet many influential people, including George W. Bush a former U.S president, believe it should continue. Jimmy Carter the 39th President of the United States in his 2012 article observed that the claim that death penalty deters crime is ironical since homicide rates in the US country were five times greater than in other western countries without the death penalty. If I believed in this view, I would have observed that death sentences can serve justice to the victims and their families since many people feel some kind of relief when the offender hangs. However, this view would only be right if, there was sufficient evidence to prove that it deters crime. Another condition is that if policymakers are confident that it will enhance public safety and it will be
  • 3. administered fairly and justly. The second premise is whether capital punishment is ethical or immoral. According to me, the death penalty is both unethical and immoral, and it violates the right of man to life. Professor Edward Feser believes that since death sentences are reserved for the worst cases committed by the most heartless and brutal murderers, they deserve capital punishments as it justifies the heinousness of their crimes. However, former Oregon State Penitentiary superintendent, Mr. Semon Frank thinks that on a moral perspective, the death penalty is a failed policy. He also believes that the judges who handle such cases fall into deeper convictions emotionally leaving feelings of guilt and contemplation (Thompson 2017). Capital punishment is immoral, unfair and discriminatory. Criminals need not be treated in the same brutal manner they treated their victims since this depicts a society as uncivilized and savage (Hoffman, 2005). Alex Kozinski, a former judge of the court of appeals in the United States, believes that a moral society should demand the life of any person who murders another. Religious books such as the Qur'an however, teach that human life is God-given and it is only He that is allowed to take it. An article by the National Catholic reporter states that, like Jesus Christ, Christians should learn to forgive those who hurt them and their loved ones and love those who have been condemned rather than judge them. This wheel help to stop the vicious cycle of violence. The Jewish Social Policy Action Network advocates for the abolition of the death penalty arguing that it is immoral and constitutes a cruel and unreasonable punishment that depict a culture of violence and misleads the young generations. The issue regarding whether capital punishment is moral or ethical is an interesting topic due to the views of the proponents and the opponents (Thompson, 2017). For example, proponents suggest that the brutal actions of the murderers deserve equally
  • 4. brutal punishments. Others feel that it is immoral on the part of society not to punish offenders. However, the religion which is sure most of these proponents profess is against taking God- given lives thus making this issue very controversial. If I believed in this opinion, I would probably face the greatest dilemma ever since my religion wouldn't support my opinions. Under some conditions, however, proponents might be right. In countries where cases of jailbreaks are rampant for example, it would be risky to keep murder convicts in such facilities since they will most probably escape. This would put the lives of those who put these convicts in jail at risk. Death sentences can also be considered for crimes that contribute to gross loss of lives. Finally, our last premise to consider in this paper is whether life in prison without parole is a better substitution to the death penalty. My opinion on this matter is that life in prison is better, less brutal and less expensive. On the other hand, death sentences are costlier, less effective and can wrongly lead to the prosecution of innocent people (Appleton & Grover 2006). Proponents of death sentences, however, argue differently, they believe life in prison exposes convicts to unnecessary psychological torture. The prisons where they are condemned to are designed to be most punitive where they do not have access to rehabilitative or restorative programs. These prisoners often succumb to psychiatric problems such as depression and active psychosis (Hoffman, 2005). Proponents of death sentences feel that the kind of solitude these prisoners go through makes them lose their sanity while lowering their dignity hence this sentence is not lenient in any way. Proponents of capital punishment bring to light some fascinating facts. According to Ronald Earle, an attorney, it is quite possible for offenders to commit murder again while in prison thus indicating just how risky life imprisonment without parole can be. Some prisoners would rather experience the 15-
  • 5. minute trauma associated with carrying out a death sentence rather than face a lifetime of psychological and emotional torture. Kenneth Hartman a convicted prisoner facing life in prison without parole perceives LWOP prisoners as dead men walking whose lives are condemned to lifetime torture and devoid of any chance of restoration. If I were a death sentence advocate, I would probably notice the additional torture one faces in prison life knowing that one will die there without a chance of ever tasting freedom again. I might also find out that life in prison is not as lenient as I thought it was. However, in circumstances where the prisoner is likely to develop some mental instability and commit more crimes while in prison, executions can be swiftly carried out. Again, in countries where prisons are not well guarded or where cases of jailbreaks are high, death sentences can be considered. References Appleton, C., & Grover, B. (2006). The Pros and Cons of Life Without Parole. British Journal Of Criminology, 47(4), 597- 615. http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/bjc/azm001 Hoffman, K. (2005). Book Review: Life Without Parole: Living in Prison TodayLife Without Parole: Living in Prison TodayHassineVictor3d ed.Los Angeles, CA:Roxbury. 2004. 267 pp. $38.95. Teaching Sociology, 33(2), 229-231. http://dx.doi.org/10.1177/0092055x0503300214 Novek, E. (2011). The Alternatives to Violence Project's Work for Peace Behind Bars. Peace Review, 23(3), 335-341. http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/10402659.2011.596061 Thompson, S. (2017). Opinion | What I Learned From Executing Two Men. Nytimes.com. Retrieved 11 October 2017, from https://www.nytimes.com/2016/09/18/opinion/sunday/what-i- learned-from-executing-two-men.html
  • 6. 13 The Believing Game and How to Make Conflicting Opinions More Fruitful Peter Elbow [A chapter in Nurturing the Peacemakers in Our Students: A Guide to Teaching Peace, Empathy, and Understanding. Chris Weber, editor. Heinemann, 2006. The present version contains a few short passages that had to be cut for space reasons in the published version.] Don Quixote says he admires Sancho Panza because he doubts everything and he believes everything. In the chapter before this, Chris Weber suggests ways to help students speak their minds, listen well, and engage in nonadversarial dialogue rather than debate. His suggestions focus on outward behavior. In this essay, I will move inward to the mysterious dimension of thinking
  • 7. and feeling. I’ll start by asking you to imagine that you are looking at an inkblot (for examples, ask Google Images for “inkblots”). Imagine that you see something in it that interests and pleases you-- -but your colleagues or classmates don’t see what you see. In fact they think you are crazy or disturbed for seeing it. What would you do if you wanted to convince them that your interpretation makes sense? If it were a matter of geometry, you could prove you are right (or wrong!). But with inkblots, you don’t have logic’s leverage. Your only hope is to get them to enter into your way of seeing---to have the experience you are having. You need to get them to say the magic words: “Oh now I see what you see.” This means getting them to exercise the ability to see something differently (i.e., seeing the same thing in multiple ways), and also the willingness to risk doing so (not knowing where it will lead).
  • 8. In short, you need them to be flexible both cognitively and emotionally. You can’t make people enter into a new way of seeing, even if they are capable of it. Perhaps your colleagues or classmates are bothered by what you see in the inkblot. Perhaps they think it’s aberrant or psychotic. If you want them to take the risk, your only option is to set a good example and show that you are willing to see it the way they see it. From Inkblots to Arguments 14 Interpreting inkblots is highly subjective, but the process serves to highlight how arguments also have a subjective dimension. Few arguments are settled by logic. Should we invade countries that might attack us? Should we torture prisoners who might know what we
  • 9. need to know? Should we drop a nuclear bomb on a country that did attack us? And by the way, what grade is fair for this paper or this student? Should we use grades at all? I’m not denying the force of logic. Logic can uncover a genuine error in someone’s argument. But logic cannot uncover an error in someone’s position. If we could have proven that Iraq had no weapons of mass destruction, that wouldn’t have proven that it was wrong to invade Iraq. “We should invade Iraq” is a claim that is impossible to prove or disprove. We can use logic to strengthen arguments for or against the claim, but we cannot prove or disprove it. Over and over we see illogical arguments for good ideas and logical arguments for bad ideas. We can never prove that an opinion or position is wrong---or right. No wonder
  • 10. people so seldom change their minds when someone finds bad reasoning in their argument. (By the same token—or at least a very similar token—it is impossible to prove or disprove the interpretation of a text. For more on this, see my longer essays on the believing game.) This explains a lot about how most people deal with differences of opinion: • Some people love to argue and disagree, and they do it for fun in a friendly way. They enjoy the disagreement and the give-and- take and they let criticisms and even attacks roll right off their backs. It’s good intellectual sport for them. • Some people look like they enjoy the sport of argument. They stay friendly and rational---they’re “cool”---because they’ve been trained well. “Don’t let your feelings cloud your thinking.” But inside they feel hurt when others attack ideas they care about. They hunker down into
  • 11. their ideas behind hidden walls. • Some people actually get mad, raise their voices, dig in, stop listening, and even call each other names. Perhaps they realize that language and logic have no power to make their listeners change their minds--- so they give in to shouting or anger. • And some people---seeing that nothing can be proven with words--- just give up on argument. They retreat. “Let’s just not argue. You see it 15 your way, I’ll see it my way. That’s the end of it. There’s no use talking.” They sidestep arguments and take a relativist position: any opinion is as good as any other opinion. (It’s worth pondering why so many students fall into this attitude.) But sometimes people actually listen to each other, come to really see
  • 12. the merit in opinions they started off fighting. Through listening to someone else’s views, they do something amazing: they actually change their thinking. Sometimes strong differences of opinion are resolved---even heated arguments. When this happens people demonstrate the two inkblot skills I just described: the ability and the willingness to see something differently---or in this case to think or understand something differently. (We often say “I see” when we “understand” something differently). These are precious skills, cognitive and psychological. We won’t have much luck encouraging them in other people unless we develop them in ourselves. With inkblots, the risk seems small. If we manage to see a blot the way a classmate or colleague sees it, we don’t have to say, “Stupid me. I was wrong.” It’s “live and let live” when we’re dealing with inkblots. With
  • 13. arguments, however, it feels like win or lose. We often want people not just to understand our position; we often want them to give up their (“wrong, stupid”) position. I used inkblots earlier to look for the subjective dimension in most arguments (given that logic cannot prove or destroy a position). Now inkblots can teach us something else. They can teach us that there’s actually a “live-and-let-live” dimension in many arguments--- probably most. But we often feel arguments as win/lose situations because we so naturally focus on how our side of an argument differs from the other person’s side. We assume that one person has to say, “Stupid me. I was wrong.” The believing game will help us understand ideas we disagree with, and thereby help us see that one one needs to lose or give up
  • 14. their central idea. The believing game can help us see that both sides in an argument are often right; or that both are right in a sense; or that both positions are implicitly pointing to some larger, wiser position that both arguers can agree on. 16 What is the Believing Game? In a sense I’ve already explained it with my analogy between inkblots and arguments. I can summarize it quickly now by contrasting it with the doubting game. The doubting game represents the kind of thinking most widely honored and taught. It’s the disciplined practice of trying to be as skeptical and analytic as possible with every idea we encounter. By
  • 15. doubting well, we can discover hidden contradictions, bad reasoning, or other weaknesses in ideas that look true or attractive. We scrutinize with the tool of doubt. This is the tradition that Walter Lippman invokes: The opposition is indispensable. A good statesman, like any other sensible human being, always learns more from his opponents than from his fervent supporters. For his supporters will push him to disaster unless his opponents show him where the dangers are. So if he is wise he will often pray to be delivered from his friends, because they will ruin him. But, though it hurts, he ought . . . to pray never to be left without opponents; for they keep him on the path of reason and good sense. The widespread veneration of “critical thinking” illustrates how our intellectual culture venerates skepticism and doubting.
  • 16. (“Critical thinking” is a fuzzy, fad term , but its various meanings usually appeal to skepticism and analysis for the sake of uncovering bad thinking. When people call a movement “critical linguistics” or “critical legal studies,” they are saying that the old linguistics or legal studies are flawed by being insufficiently skeptical or critical---too hospitable to something that’s wrong.) The believing game is the mirror image of the doubting game or critical thinking. It’s the disciplined practice of trying to be as welcoming as possible to every idea we encounter: not just listening to views different from our own and holding back from arguing with them, but actually trying to believe them. We can use the tool of believing to scrutinize not for flaws but to find hidden virtues in ideas that are
  • 17. unfashionable or repellent. Often we cannot see what’s good in someone else’s idea (or in our own!) till we work at believing it. When an idea goes against current assumptions and beliefs---or seems alien, weird, dangerous---or if it’s poorly formulated---we often cannot see any merit in it. 17 “Believing” is a Scary Word Many people get nervous when I celebrate believing. They point to an asymmetry between our sense of what “doubting” and “believing” mean. Believing seems to entail commitment, where doubting does not. It commonly feels as though we can doubt something without committing ourselves to rejecting it---but that we cannot believe something without committing ourselves to accepting it and even living
  • 18. by it. Thus it feels as though we can doubt and remain unscathed, but believing will scathe us. Indeed believing can feel hopelessly bound up with religion. (“Do you BELIEVE? Yes, Lord, I BELIEVE!”) This contrast in meanings is a fairly valid picture of natural ,individual acts of doubting and believing. (Though I wonder if doubting leaves us fully unchanged.) But it’s not a picture of doubting and believing as methodological disciplines or unnatural games. Let me explain the distinction. Natural individual acts of doubting happen when someone tells us something that seems dubious or hard to believe. (“You say the earth is spinning? I doubt it. I feel it steady under my feet.”) But our culture has learned to go way beyond natural individual acts of doubting. We humans had to struggle for a long time to learn how to doubt
  • 19. unnaturally as a methodological discipline. We now know that for good thinking, we must doubt everything, not just what’s dubious; indeed the whole point of critical thinking is to try to doubt what we find most obvious or true or right (as Lippman advises). In order to develop systematic doubting, we had to overcome believing: the natural pull to believe what's easy to believe, what we want to believe, or what powerful people tell us to believe. (It’s easy to believe that the earth is stationary.) As a culture, we learned systematic doubting through the growth of philosophical thinking (Greek thinkers developing logic, Renaissance thinkers developing science, and Enlightenment thinkers pulling away from established religion). And we each had to learn to be skeptical as individuals, too---for example learning not to believe that if we are very very good, Santa
  • 20. Claus/God will bring us everything we want. As children, we begin to notice that naïve belief leads us astray. As adults we begin to notice the dreadful 18 things that belief leads humans to do---like torturing alleged witches/prisoners till they "confess." Now that we’ve finally learned systematic doubting with its tools of logic and strict reasoning and its attitude of systematic skepticism--- critical thinking---we are likely to end up afraid of believing itself. We had to learn to distrust natural believing (“My parents/country/God will take care of me whenever I am in need.”). So believing can seem a scary word because our culture has not yet learned to go beyond natural acts of naïve believing to develop unnatural believing as a
  • 21. methodological discipline. In short, the believing game is not much honored or even known (though it’s not new). The methodology of the doubting game gives us a model for the methodology of the believing game. When the doubting game asks us to doubt an idea, it doesn't ask us to throw it away forever. We couldn’t do that because the game teaches us to doubt all ideas, and we’ll learn to find weaknesses even in good ideas. We can’t throw all ideas away. The scrutiny of doubt is methodological, provisional, conditional. So when a good doubter finally decides what to believe or do, this involves an additional act of judgment and commitment. The doubting game gives good evidence, but it doesn’t do our judging and committing for us. Similarly, when the believing game asks us to believe all ideas-- -
  • 22. especially those that seem most wrong---it cannot ask us to marry them or commit ourselves to them. Our believing is also methodological, conditional, provisional---unnatural. (It’s hard to try to believe conflicting ideas all at once, but we can try to enter into them one after another.) And so too, if we commit ourselves to accepting an idea because the believing game helped us see virtues in it, this involves an additional act of judgment and commitment. The believing game gives us good evidence, but it doesn’t do our deciding for us. In short, we must indeed continue to resist the pull to believe what's easy to believe. But believing what’s easy to believe is far different from using the disciplined effort to believe as an intellectual methodological tool in order to find hidden strengths in ideas that people want to ignore. A Surprising Blind Spot for the Doubting Game
  • 23. 19 The doubting and believing games have symmetrical weaknesses: the doubting game is poor at helping us find hidden virtues; the believing game is poor at helping us find hidden flaws. But many people don’t realize that the doubting game is also poor at reaching one of its main goals: helping us find hidden flaws in our own thinking. The flaws in our own thinking usually come from our assumptions---our ways of thinking that we accept without noticing. But it’s hard to doubt what we can’t see because we unconsciously take it for granted. The believing game comes to the rescue here. Our best hope for finding invisible flaws in what we can’t see in our own thinking is to enter into different ideas or points of view---ideas that carry different
  • 24. assumptions. Only after we’ve managed to inhabit a different way of thinking will our currently invisible assumptions become visible to us. This blind spot in the doubting game shows up frequently in classrooms and other meetings. When smart people are trained only in critical thinking, they get better and better at doubting and criticizing other people’s ideas. They use this skill particularly well when they feel a threat to their own ideas or their unexamined assumptions. Yet they feel justified in fending-off what they disagree with because they feel that this doubting activity is “critical thinking.” They take refuge in the feeling that they would be “unintellectual” if they said to an opponent what in fact they ought to say: “Wow, your idea sounds really wrong to me. It must be alien to how I think. Let me try to enter into it and see if there’s
  • 25. something important that I’m missing. Let me see if I can get a better perspective on my own thinking.” In short, if we want to be good at finding flaws in our own thinking (a goal that doubters constantly trumpet), we need the believing game. The Believing Game is Not Actually New If we look closely at the behavior of genuinely smart and productive people, we will see that many of them have exactly this skill of entering into views that conflict with their own. John Stuart Mill is a philosopher associated with the doubting game, but he also advises good thinkers to engage in the central act of the believing game: [People who] have never thrown themselves into the mental position of those who think differently from them . . . do not, in any
  • 26. 20 proper sense of the word, know the doctrine which they themselves profess. (129) Yet this skill of sophisticated unnatural belief is not much understood or celebrated in our culture---and almost never taught. Imagine, for example, a seminar or a meeting where lots of ideas come up. One person is quick to point out flaws in each idea as it is presented. A second person mostly listens and gets intrigued with each idea--and tends to make comments like these: “Oh I see” and “That’s interesting” and “Tell me more about such and such” and “As I go with your thinking, I begin to see some things I never noticed before.” This second person may be appreciated as a good listener, but the first person will tend to be considered smarter and a better thinker because
  • 27. of that quick skill at finding flaws. I used to feel that I was unintelligent because when one person gave an argument I would feel, “Oh that’s a good idea,” but then when the other person argued the other way, I found myself feeling, “Oh that sounds good, too.” I wondered what was the matter with my loose, sloppy mind to let me agree with people and ideas that are completely at odds with each other. The “smart people” tended to argue cleverly and find flaws that I didn’t notice. But now I’m finally insisting that my instinctive ability to play the believing game is not just “niceness” or sloppy thinking; it’s a crucial intellectual strength rather than a weakness- --a discipline that needs to be taught and developed. Let me emphasize that I’m not arguing against the doubting game. We need the ability to be skeptical and find flaws. Indeed, the doubting
  • 28. game probably deserves the last word in any valid process of trying to work out trustworthy thinking. For even though the scrutiny of belief may lead us to choose a good idea that most people at first wanted to throw away, nevertheless, we mustn’t commit ourselves to that idea before applying the scrutiny of doubt to check for hidden problems. My only argument is against the monopoly of the doubting game as the only kind of good thinking. We need both disciplines. Some of our most needed insights come from opinions that are easy to criticize or dismiss. But those insights are only available if people work at entering into such opinions in search of unnoticed virtues. 21 Concrete Ways to Learn to Play the Believing Game
  • 29. As teachers and students we are in a good position to learn the ability to see things differently from how we usually see them, and the willingness to risk doing it. If we want to learn those skills, it helps to notice the inner stances ---the cognitive and psychological dispositions---we need for doubting and believing: • If we want to doubt or find flaws in ideas that we are tempted to accept or believe (perhaps they are ideas that “everyone knows are true”), we need to work at extricating or distancing ourselves from those ideas. There’s a kind of language that helps here: clear, impersonal sentences that lay bare the logic or lack of logic in them. • If, on the other hand, we want to believe ideas that we are tempted to reject (“Anyone can see that’s a crazy idea”)---if we are trying to enter in or experience or dwell in those ideas---we benefit from the language of imagination, narrative, and the personal experience.
  • 30. Here are some specific practices to help us experience things from someone else’s point of view. 1. If people are stuck in a disagreement, we can invoke Carl Rogers’ application of “active listening.” John must not try to argue his point till he has restated Mary’s point to her satisfaction. 2. But what if John has trouble seeing things from Mary’s point of view? His lame efforts to restate her view show that “he doesn't get it.” He probably needs to stop talking and listen; keep his mouth shut. Thus, in a discussion where someone is trying to advance a view and everyone fights it, there is a simple rule of thumb: the doubters need to stop talking and simply give extended floor time to the minority view. The following three concrete activities give enormous help here: • The three-minute or five-minute rule. Any participant who feels he or
  • 31. she is not being heard can make a sign and invoke the rule: no one else can talk for three or five minutes. This voice speaks, we listen; we cannot reply. • Allies only---no objections. Others can speak---but only those who are having more success believing or entering into or assenting to the minority view. No objections allowed. (Most people are familiar with this “no-objections” rule from brainstorming.) 22 • “Testimony session.” Participants having a hard time being heard or understood are invited to tell stories of the experiences that led them to their point of view and to describe what it's like having or living with this view. Not only must the rest of us not answer or argue or disagree while they are speaking; we must refrain, even afterwards, from
  • 32. questioning their stories or experiences or feelings. We may speak only to their ideas. (This process is particularly useful when issues of race, gender, and sexual orientation are being discussed.) The goal here is safety. Most speakers feel unsafe if they sense we are just waiting to jump in with all our objections. But we listeners need safety, too. We are trying to enter into a view we want to quarrel with or feel threatened by. We’re trying to learn the difficult skill of in- dwelling. It's safer for us if we have permission simply not to talk about it any more for a while. We need time for the words we resist just to sink in for a while with no comment. 3. The language of story and poetry helps us experience alien ideas. Stories, metaphors, and images can often find a path around our resistance. When it’s hard to enter into a new point of view, try telling a
  • 33. story of someone who believes it; imagine and describe someone who sees things this way; tell the story of events that might have led people to have this view of the world; what would it be like to be someone who sees things this way? Write a story or poem about the world that this view implies. 4. Step out of language. Language itself can sometimes get in the way of trying to experience or enter into a point of view different from our own. There are various productive ways to set language aside. We can draw or sketch images (rough stick figures are fine). What do you actually see when you take this position? It’s also powerful to use movement, gesture, dance, sounds, and role-playing. 5. Silence. For centuries, people have made good use of silence for in- dwelling. If we’re having trouble trying to believe someone’s idea,
  • 34. sometimes it’s helpful for no one to say anything for a couple of minutes. That’s not much time out of a meeting or conference or class hour, but it can be surprisingly fertile. 6. Private writing. There's a kind of silence involved when everyone engages in private writing. Stop talking and do 7-10 minutes of writing for 23 no one else’s eyes. What's crucial is the invitation to language in conditions of privacy and safety. 7. Use the physical voice. When it’s hard to enter into a piece of writing that feels difficult or distant, for example something written by someone very different from us---or an intricate work like a Shakespeare sonnet---it helps to try to read it aloud as well and meaningfully as possible. (When
  • 35. I’m teaching a longer text, I choose crux passages of a few paragraphs or a page.) The goal is not good acting; the goal is simply to say the words so that we feel every meaning in them---so that we fully mean every meaning. Get the words to “sound right” or to carry the meanings across—for example, to listeners who don’t have a text. After we have three or four different readings of the same passage, we can discuss which ones manage to “sound right”---and usually these readings help us enter in or assent. (It’s not fair to put students on the spot by asking them to read with no preparation time. I ask students to prepare these reading at home or practice them briefly in class in pairs.) This activity illustrates something interesting about language. It’s impossible simply to say words so they “sound right" without dwelling in
  • 36. them and thus feeling their meaning. So instead of asking students to “study carefully” this Shakespeare sonnet, I say, “Practice reading it aloud till you can say every word with meaning.” This involves giving a kind of bodily assent. 8. Nonadversarial argument. Finally, the classroom is an ideal place to practice nonadversarial forms of argument. Our traditional model of argument is a zero-sum game: “If I'm right, you must be wrong.” Essays and dissertations traditionally start off by trying to demolish the views of opponents. “Unless I criticize every other idea,” the assumption goes, “I won’t have a clear space for my idea.” But this approach is usually counterproductive--except with readers who already agree with you and don’t need to be persuaded. This traditional argument structure says to readers: “You cannot agree with my ideas---or even hear
  • 37. them--- until after you admit that you’ve been wrong or stupid.” The structure of nonadversarial argument is simple, but it takes practice and discipline: argue only for your position, not against other positions. This is easy for me here since I have no criticisms at all of the doubting game or critical thinking in itself. It’s much harder if I really hate the idea I’m fighting. It’s particularly hard if my essential argument is negative: “Don’t invade Iraq.” So yes, there are some situations in which 24 we cannot avoid arguing why an idea is wrong. Yet even in my position on Iraq, there is, in fact, some space for nonadversarial argument. I can talk about the advantages of not invading Iraq---and not try to refute for invasion. In this way, I would increase the chances of my
  • 38. opponent actually hearing my arguments. The general principle is this: If all I have to offer are negative reasons why the other person’s idea is bad, I’ll probably make less progress than if I can give some positive reasons for my alternative idea---and even acknowledge why the other person might favor her idea. (For more on nonadversarial argument, see my “Introduction” xviii-xxiii.) I can end by glancing back at the inkblots. Arguments that look conflicting might both be somehow valid or right. They might need to be articulated better or seen from a larger view---a view the disputants haven't yet figured out. I may be convinced that someone else’s idea is dead wrong, but if I’m willing to play the believing game with it, I will not only set a good example, I may even be able to see how we are both on the right track. Nonadversarial argument and the believing
  • 39. game help us work out larger frames of reference and better ideas. Works Cited Elbow, Peter. “Appendix Essay. The Doubting Game and the Believing Game: An Analysis of the Intellectual Process.” In Writing Without Teachers. Oxford University Press, 1973. 147-91. ---. “Bringing the Rhetoric of Assent and The Believing Game Together-- and into the Classroom.” College English 67.4 (March 2005): 388-99. ---. Introduction. Everyone Can Write: Essays Toward a Hopeful Theory of Writing and Teaching Writing. NY: Oxford University Press, 2000. ---. “Methodological Doubting and Believing: Contraries in Inquiry.” In Embracing Contraries: Explorations in Learning and Teaching. Oxford University Press, 1986. 254-300. Graff, Gerald. Clueless in Academe: How Schooling Obscures the Life of
  • 40. the Mind. New Haven: Yale UP, 2003. Lippman, Walter. “The Indispensable Opposition.” Atlantic Monthly (August 1939). It’s notable that this essay is canonized in many editions of The Norton Reader (e.g., in the 6th edition, pages 850-55). Mill, John Stuart. On Liberty. London, Dent, 1951. 25 Rogers, Carl. "Communication: Its Blocking and Its Facilitation." On Becoming a Person. NY: Houghton Mifflin, 1961. Tannen, Deborah. The Argument Culture: Moving From Debate to Dialogue. Random House, 1998