SlideShare a Scribd company logo
Bending the Arc of North American Psychologists’ Moral
Universe
Toward Communicative Ethics and Social Justice
Richard T. G. Walsh
Wilfrid Laurier University
Social contextual and social justice perspectives on North
American psychologists’
conceptions of ethical ideals and prescribed practices show that
interpersonal, organi-
zational-institutional, and sociopolitical systems are dimly
represented on our moral
landscape. In this critical review I first examine conceptions of
ethical decision-making
from cognitive and interpersonal angles, noting the operation of
nonrational phenomena
and conversational processes and promoting a communicative
conception of ethical
decision-making. Next, I consider how the discourse on the
concepts and practice of
ethics addresses both the social conditions of our employment
and the challenges of
maintaining professional-personal boundaries on ethical
conduct. Lastly, I assess the
ways in which psychologists discuss ethical issues that arise
from our espoused
commitments to enhancing human welfare, responsibility to
society, and social justice.
I argue that certain historical trends in psychology’s culture
reduce our moral vision of
practicing the principle of justice to social reforms that sustain
the status quo. I
conclude by questioning how we can shift the transit of our
ethical discourse and
practice toward communicative ethics and social justice.
Keywords: ethical decision-making, Habermas, communicative
ethics, organizational-institutional
influences, social justice
It seems likely that most North American
(i.e., Canadian and U.S.) colleagues believe that
we psychologists behave ethically in our re-
search, educational, professional, and commu-
nity endeavors despite the embarrassment to our
discipline of some psychologists’ ethical mal-
feasance, such as participation in torture (see
Teo, 2015a). But taking ethical responsibilities
for granted could lead to their marginalization
and invoking them chiefly when a possible so-
ciopolitical transgression, professional ethical
dilemma, or institutional review of a dubious
research project occurs. Instead of central to our
identity as scientific and professional psycholo-
gists, ethics can seem peripheral to our worka-
day worlds (Prilleltensky, Rossiter, & Walsh-
Bowers, 1996), reducible to a recitation of
standards that demand adherence. A different
view is that all aspects of our vocation are pro-
foundly moral, ethical, and social. That is, princi-
ples and practices of ethics, which are historical
constructions, are enacted in the context of in-
terpersonal, organizational-institutional, and so-
cietal systems and particular cultural traditions.
Accordingly, our principles and standards for
ethical conduct, as well as our conduct itself,
should reflect critical consciousness of the so-
cial-contextual phenomena saturating ethics.
In this spirit, and from my perspective as a
Canadian contributor to the literature in critical
psychology (Teo, 2015b) and as a local political
activist, I pose two principal questions for dis-
cussion: (a) How adequately do our codes of
ethics account for the nature of the relationship
between us and those whom we serve? (b) How
might the current interest in social justice ex-
pressed by some psychologists inform a moral
imperative that could be the basis for the ethical
principle of responsibility to society specifically
and for a reconceived ethical framework for
psychologists generally? The latter question is
relevant to psychologists’ relationship with so-
cial justice (e.g., Vasquez, 2011; Walsh & Go-
I presented an earlier version of this article at the meeting
of the Canadian Psychological Association, Vancouver, BC,
Canada (June, 2014). I am grateful to Ravi Gokani for his
helpful comments.
Correspondence concerning this article should be ad-
dressed to Richard T. G. Walsh, Department of Psychology,
Wilfrid Laurier University, Waterloo, ON, Canada N2L
3C5. E-mail: [email protected]
T
hi
s
do
cu
m
en
t
is
co
py
ri
gh
te
d
by
th
e
A
m
er
ic
an
P
sy
ch
ol
og
ic
al
A
ss
oc
ia
ti
on
or
on
e
of
it
s
al
li
ed
pu
bl
is
he
rs
.
T
hi
s
ar
ti
cl
e
is
in
te
nd
ed
so
le
ly
fo
r
th
e
pe
rs
on
al
us
e
of
th
e
in
di
vi
du
al
us
er
an
d
is
no
t
to
be
di
ss
em
in
at
ed
br
oa
dl
y.
Journal of Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology © 2015
American Psychological Association
2015, Vol. 35, No. 2, 90 –102 1068-8471/15/$12.00
http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/teo0000011
90
mailto:[email protected]
http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/teo0000011
kani, 2014). In discussing these questions I as-
sess the social contextual qualities of the
conceptions and practices described in the dis-
course on the American Psychological Associ-
ation’s Code of Ethics (American Psychological
Association, 2010) (hereinafter, the APA Code)
and the Canadian Psychological Association’s
Code of Ethics (Canadian Psychological Asso-
ciation, 2000) (hereinafter, the CPA Code).
A Social Contextual Review
of Ethics Codes
The discourse on the codes suggests that so-
cial contextual aspects of ethical thought and
practice can be significant. These aspects in-
clude cognitive and interpersonal perspectives
on ethical decision-making, the social condi-
tions of psychologists’ employment, and issues
of responsibility to society and social justice,
which roughly correspond to interpersonal, or-
ganizational-institutional, and societal levels of
social analysis, respectively.
Critical Perspectives on Ethical
Decision-Making
The literature stipulates that psychologists
should know how and when to competently
apply a model of decision-making to an ethical
dilemma confronting them. Although models of
ethical decision-making emanate from distinct
philosophical roots—principled (deontologi-
cal), utilitarian (consequentialist), and relational
(Cottone, 2011)—the APA and CPA Codes
converge in their respective prescriptions for a
problem-solving approach to ethical decision-
making that entails a psychologist discerning
the most ethically appropriate course of action
in a given situation. Thus, ethical decision-
making proceeds from “what a person of good
character (aware of the virtues, values and fun-
damental principles of the discipline), with sen-
sitivity to the probable impact on the specific
other involved persons, would choose to do”
(Pettifor, 1996, p. 5). A possible link to affirm-
ing social justice rests in “a sociocultural frame-
work for ethical decision making” (Kakkad,
2005, p. 297), but this perspective is not wide-
spread in the literature.
Although the APA Code does not specify a
model of ethical decision-making, extant mod-
els (e.g., Kitchener & Kitchener, 2011) gener-
ally complement the problem-solving model
prescribed by the CPA Code. In addition, both
Codes note the value of collegial and supervi-
sory consultation for decision-making, and
Fisher’s (2013) model prescribes dialogue with
those impacted by the decision. In some con-
trast, a social-constructivist model stresses the
interpersonal nature of ethical decision-making
itself (Cottone, 2011), while an ethic of care
(Truscott & Crook, 2013) and a approach
known as communicative ethics (Rossiter,
Walsh-Bowers, & Prilleltensky, 2002) hold that
sound ethical decision-making results from
trustworthy communication with peers, as I ex-
plain subsequently. Yet the codes appear to
assume that ethical decision-making is the re-
sponsibility of a persistently rational individual
engaging in logical problem-solving, a doubtful
assumption that flows from the individualistic
moral philosophies undergirding the codes
(Walsh, 2015).
Nonrational cognitive processes. The lit-
erature on nonrational cognitive processes sug-
gests that the recommended procedure for eth-
ical decision-making might be flawed
psychologically. For example, the APA Code
suggests that psychologists’ primary ethical ob-
ligation is to maintain our competence. How-
ever, “research in health care, education, and
multicultural and social psychology raise[s] se-
rious doubts about psychologists’ capacity for
consistently accurate self-assessments of com-
petence” (Johnson, Barnett, Elman, Forrest, &
Kaslow, 2012, p. 557). If “maintaining compe-
tence beyond initial credentialing continues to
mean that psychologists rely on self-assessment
and voluntary consultation with colleagues if
problems arise” (Johnson et al., 2012, p. 559),
this disposition is prone to self-serving bias. In
fact, confirmation biases, among other nonra-
tional phenomena, also impair reasoning. Fol-
lowing Kahneman’s (2003) notion of bounded
rationality and distinction between automatic
intuition and deliberate reason, effective deci-
sion-making incorporates intuitive-emotional
processes more than solely rational ones. Con-
sequently, ethical reasoning does not necessar-
ily lead to ethical conduct, because unrecog-
nized “nonrational processes can compromise
accurate self-reflection” (Rogerson, Gottlieb,
Handelsman, Knapp, & Younggren, 2011, p.
619). Accordingly, we might make wiser ethical
decisions if we integrated “emotional sensitiv-
91BENDING THE ARC
T
hi
s
do
cu
m
en
t
is
co
py
ri
gh
te
d
by
th
e
A
m
er
ic
an
P
sy
ch
ol
og
ic
al
A
ss
oc
ia
ti
on
or
on
e
of
it
s
al
li
ed
pu
bl
is
he
rs
.
T
hi
s
ar
ti
cl
e
is
in
te
nd
ed
so
le
ly
fo
r
th
e
pe
rs
on
al
us
e
of
th
e
in
di
vi
du
al
us
er
an
d
is
no
t
to
be
di
ss
em
in
at
ed
br
oa
dl
y.
ity, personal values, contextual forces, and in-
tuitive responses with normative rational anal-
ysis nonrational with rational factors”
(Rogerson et al., p. 622), while attempting to
prevent cognitive distortions.
One interpretation of this cognitive analysis
is that if we ethical actors monitor the opera-
tions of nonrational cognitive phenomena, then
our capacity as reasoning individuals is af-
firmed. But another interpretation is that recog-
nition of nonrational processes is insufficient
for ethical decision-making. Moreover, sources
of social influence also are activated in the
process of ethical decision-making. They in-
clude the qualities of the ethical situation itself;
the roles of significant others (e.g., supervisors,
peers, the recipients of our activities); the cul-
ture and social climate of organizations or in-
stitutions with which a psychologist is affili-
ated; and societal influences stemming from
sociopolitical, socioeconomic, and technologi-
cal structures and ideologies (Malloy & Hadji-
stravopoulos, 1998). Ethical decision-making,
therefore, entails much more than a presumed
rational judgment emanating from an advanced
level of moral consciousness. In sum, given the
potential for cognitive distortions and covert
social influences, the notion of an autonomous,
reasoning, and virtuous psychologist who re-
calls and applies the correct ethical principle or
standard in a kind of cognitive decision-tree
does not represent ethical decision-making re-
alistically. Rather, sound ethical decision-
making arguably depends upon a dialogical pro-
cess of understanding the applicability of
ethical principles and corresponding standards
to the situation, for which consultation with
trustworthy colleagues is indispensable.
Interpersonal processes. Communication
difficulties in our work as psychologists often
can have ramifications for ethical decision-
making. But attending to the discursive pro-
cesses as well as the content of ethics conceiv-
ably could enrich understanding our moral
responsibilities in our professional relation-
ships. For example, a dialogical process of ne-
gotiating conversational differences ideally oc-
curs in counseling or psychotherapy, shaped in
part by differentials of social power between the
parties, the psychologist’s expertise and ethical
responsiveness, and the client’s knowledge, in-
tentions, and preferences (Strong & Sutherland,
2007). When psychologists strive to balance
their perspective with clients’ perspectives, pro-
cessual sensitivity to a given conversation’s
quality embodies the ethical principle of re-
spect.
Although the ethics discourse tends to mar-
ginalize conversational processes in decision-
making, studies on clinicians’ experiences with
ethics indicate that ethical decision-making is
more socially contextualized than first meets the
eye (Rossiter et al., 2002). It seems wiser, there-
fore, to regard ethical decision-making as a di-
alogical process of coconstruction with influen-
tial others, including the recipients of a
psychologist’s activities, rather than the product
of a solitary ethical actor. According to Cot-
tone’s (2011) social constructivist approach, in-
stead of an individual’s wholly internal deci-
sion, ethical decision-making can entail up to
three interpersonal steps: consensualizing, ne-
gotiating, and arbitrating. In this approach, re-
solving an ethical dilemma becomes an interac-
tive process of reflection and consensus,
attained through open discussion with trustwor-
thy colleagues and supervisors concerning the
balance between ethical principles and specific
standards appropriate to a particular situation.
Yet, such dialogues only can provide contest-
able ethical knowledge, not certainties, about
ethical courses of action. [See Shotter (2005)
for another constructivist approach to dialogue
and ethics.]
Some authors, drawing from critical social
philosophy, understand this dialogical approach
as communicative ethics (Rossiter et al., 2002).
In the interests of transforming societies and
drawing from his concept of “the lifeworld” (an
idealized social context of moral values, demo-
cratic principles, ethics, and consensus), Haber-
mas (1981/1983) promotes the emancipatory
character of clear and undistorted communica-
tion, which he terms an ideal speech situation.
Such communication requires that all parties in
the relationship should experience four condi-
tions: symmetrical power, sincerity, disclosure
of truth, and an inclination to express what is
morally right. Crucially, Habermas proposes
fundamental changes to society’s socioeco-
nomic conditions to lay the foundations for
ideal speech to occur. But some scholars are
wary that if undistorted communication is prac-
ticed as an abstract dialogue, it could ignore
power relations embedded in social categories
92 WALSH
T
hi
s
do
cu
m
en
t
is
co
py
ri
gh
te
d
by
th
e
A
m
er
ic
an
P
sy
ch
ol
og
ic
al
A
ss
oc
ia
ti
on
or
on
e
of
it
s
al
li
ed
pu
bl
is
he
rs
.
T
hi
s
ar
ti
cl
e
is
in
te
nd
ed
so
le
ly
fo
r
th
e
pe
rs
on
al
us
e
of
th
e
in
di
vi
du
al
us
er
an
d
is
no
t
to
be
di
ss
em
in
at
ed
br
oa
dl
y.
(e.g., ethnocultural status, gender, class; Mee-
han, 1995).
From my perspective, then, ethical decision-
making is better understood as a social process
that partly is shaped by experience and consul-
tation with other psychologists and profession-
als as well as the recipients of our activities,
rather than the activity of an autonomous rea-
soning psychologist. Accordingly, discerning
appropriate ethical conduct might best occur, if
professionals experience a safe space such as
small-group discussions with trustworthy peers,
in which to discuss their ethical concerns with-
out fear of judgment and surveillance by their
supervisors (Rossiter et al., 2002). However,
such an opportunity would require that supervi-
sors and administrators foster an organizational
climate conducive to the secure discussion of
complex ethical situations without supervisory
prejudicial judgment. Although ethics codes per
se “cannot create safe spaces for the discussion
of ethics within organizations” (Pettifor, 1998,
p. 236), the crucial concern remains how we are
to respond to “organizational or systemic pres-
sures [that] may influence [our] capacity to im-
plement ethical decisions” (Pettifor, 1998, p.
234).
The Social Conditions of
Psychologists’ Vocation
The social conditions of our vocation as psy-
chologists also can impinge upon our ethical
conceptions and practices. Two such contextual
issues are: organizational and institutional influ-
ences in places of work, and the challenge of
maintaining professional-personal boundaries.
Organizational and institutional influences.
Although there has been much discussion on
ethical issues involving police and military psy-
chology in recent years (e.g., Kennedy, 2011;
Teo, 2015a), the contextual realities that we
face when the work required within an organi-
zation or institution impacts ethical decision-
making and conduct has received rather less
attention. The APA Code covers organizational
demands in Standard 1.03, while the CPA Code
addresses organizational influences in several of
its standards. Yet, beyond police and military
contexts, the social conditions of scientific and
professional psychologists’ employment might
adversely affect our ethical judgment and the
quality of ethical relations that we maintain with
the recipients of our scientific or professional
activities. The reality is that evidently in many
organizations, agencies, or institutions, particu-
larly since the incursion of neoliberal austerity
programs, psychologists and other professional
staff have little time in which to reflect upon and
discuss ethical issues in safe, constructive dia-
logue that facilitates understanding the applica-
tion of ethical principles and standards in par-
ticular circumstances (Rossiter et al., 2002).
Instead, in a climate of “do more with less,”
staff must serve more clients for shorter periods
of time. In such contexts discussing ambiguous
ethical matters, which often induce anxiety, has
become a luxury.
Relatedly, the nature of supervisory relation-
ships can affect ethical deliberations negatively
(Rossiter et al., 2002). We psychologists might
be anxious about supervisors judging us as pro-
fessionally inadequate, if we acknowledge eth-
ical uncertainty or misgivings about ethical con-
duct in a given situation, as if we should already
know the answers to ethical questions. Thus, a
virtual taboo against admitting that often we do
not know how to behave ethically can operate.
Supervisors’ surveillance to induce supervisees’
compliance also might militate against safe,
constructive dialogue (Rossiter et al., 2002). In
short, the potential to actualize our moral re-
sponsibilities is embedded in power relations
with supervisors. But the ethical discourse
largely suggests that we engage in ethical prob-
lem-solving as if it were an abstract process
transcending the workaday realities of social
entanglements in organizations and institutions,
such as supervisor-staff relations. But some
contend that accounting for the effect of work
contexts on ethical decision-making is essential
for ethical conduct ( Vergés, 2010).
The inadequacy of the ethical discourse con-
cerning how to deal with diverse working con-
ditions is evident in the situation of psycholo-
gists who engage in humanitarian work in
cultural settings different from their own (Aubé,
2011). Typically, they experience stressful local
cultural realities, such as political and military
pressure on their nongovernmental organiza-
tion. The ethical challenges include the domi-
nant-subordinate relationship between service
providers and recipients, exacerbated by post-
colonial issues; cultural differences in ethical
standards, for instance, in the protection of con-
fidentiality and consent; and extremely limited
93BENDING THE ARC
T
hi
s
do
cu
m
en
t
is
co
py
ri
gh
te
d
by
th
e
A
m
er
ic
an
P
sy
ch
ol
og
ic
al
A
ss
oc
ia
ti
on
or
on
e
of
it
s
al
li
ed
pu
bl
is
he
rs
.
T
hi
s
ar
ti
cl
e
is
in
te
nd
ed
so
le
ly
fo
r
th
e
pe
rs
on
al
us
e
of
th
e
in
di
vi
du
al
us
er
an
d
is
no
t
to
be
di
ss
em
in
at
ed
br
oa
dl
y.
ethical resources. Ethical ambiguities appar-
ently abound in such humanitarian work, just as
they might within the permeable boundaries
between our professional and personal lives.
Professional-personal boundary maintenance.
Psychologists’ professional and personal lives
often intersect, which can present ethical prob-
lems. By practicing moral discernment, as
Pipes, Holstein, and Aguirre (2005) claimed, we
can recognize when such boundaries are more
or less fused or are distinct. One criterion for
moral discernment is the perceived risk to both
the recipients of our activities and to the disci-
pline, while a mitigating factor is the social
context of a given ethical situation. Pipes et al.
held, as the CPA Code does, that ethical con-
duct should reflect adherence to the underlying
principles as well as to standards. The authors
recommended that the APA Code emulate the
CPA Code’s direction that we indicate whether
we are speaking publicly as a professional or a
private citizen. Pipes et al. (2005) also sug-
gested that we apply the APA Code’s aspira-
tional principles to our personal lives, given the
permeable nature of personal-professional
boundaries. But, from a critical perspective,
the process of moral discernment concerning
these boundaries likely is as influenced by
nonrational cognitive processes, interpersonal
relations, and organizational-institutional in-
fluences as ethical decision-making in general
seems to be.
Allowing a role for personal conscience, the
CPA Code accepts the potential for reciprocal
influence between the personal and the pro-
fessional. In contrast, the APA Code exempts
personal activities on our own time from its
purview. Yet the virtue ethics and feminist-
relational ethical perspectives (Walsh, 2015) as-
sume that our personal characteristics do influ-
ence our conduct (as in “the personal is the
political”) and that matters of social justice re-
quire our personal commitment. But, some psy-
chologists insist, public perceptions of our con-
duct during personal time might adversely
affect professional relationships with clientele.
For instance, involvement in contentious polit-
ical issues might lead to abusing the power of
our social position inadvertently and harming
our professional role and others’ reputations.
Thus, “Taking a public position on a controver-
sial issue might call into [our] ability to be
objective and nonjudgmental” unless our asso-
ciation has taken a stance on the issue (Haeny,
2014, p. 269). This rationale implies, as I ex-
plain below, regression to the mean, so to speak,
of social reform.
Overall, the codes and the literature contain
little discussion of ethical ambiguities inherent
in professional-personal boundaries. Instead,
the discourse seems preoccupied with prevent-
ing blemishes to the image of an autonomous
psychologist practicing scientific problem-
solving that we strive to manage in society. This
inclination, however, might contribute to the
difficulties we have had in practicing ethical
responsibility to society beyond social reform.
Ethical Relationship With Society
Since World War Two (Capshew, 1999; Her-
man, 1995), the discipline has committed itself
to advance both psychological knowledge and
human welfare. From the societal level of anal-
ysis, I assess in this section how the ethical
discourse addresses the ethical principle of re-
sponsibility to society and the similar concepts
of social responsibility and social justice. Actu-
alizing a moral imperative, grounded in socio-
political consciousness (Prilleltensky & Walsh-
Bowers, 1993), might inspire a reconceived
ethic of responsibility to society.
The codes’ orientations. Not surprisingly,
the codes share a common inclination in their
respective depictions of psychologists’ ethical
obligations to promote the well-being of indi-
viduals and society and to prevent infringement
of human rights. For instance, the APA Ethics
Code “indicate[s] that psychologists are com-
mitted to creating, communicating, and apply-
ing psychological knowledge in order to benefit
individuals and society and facilitate the reso-
lution of global challenges” (Swim et al., 2011,
p. 246). However, APA introduced this princi-
ple, then known as “Social Responsibility,” in
the previous 1992 Code, but the adjective “so-
cial” since has disappeared. In the 2002 edition,
the principle of “Justice,” connoting fairness
and equity, encompasses psychologists’ respon-
sibilities to society.
In the CPA Code social justice “refers to
fairness and equity in the allocation of, impact
of, and access to psychological services”
(Truscott & Crook, 2013, p. 170), as exempli-
fied by the Values Statement for Principle I:
Respect for the Dignity of Persons. Yet the
94 WALSH
T
hi
s
do
cu
m
en
t
is
co
py
ri
gh
te
d
by
th
e
A
m
er
ic
an
P
sy
ch
ol
og
ic
al
A
ss
oc
ia
ti
on
or
on
e
of
it
s
al
li
ed
pu
bl
is
he
rs
.
T
hi
s
ar
ti
cl
e
is
in
te
nd
ed
so
le
ly
fo
r
th
e
pe
rs
on
al
us
e
of
th
e
in
di
vi
du
al
us
er
an
d
is
no
t
to
be
di
ss
em
in
at
ed
br
oa
dl
y.
concept of social justice transcends concern
simply with “the particular ethical obligations
owed to individuals arising out of professional
relationships . . . to include obligations owed to
individuals collectively . . . [and] society in
general” (Truscott & Crook, 2013, p. 176). An-
other definition of social justice is “work[ing]
for the common good by transforming the social
organizations and processes that contribute to
power inequalities, oppression, and marginal-
ization” (Vasquez, 2011, p. 76). Social justice
can be linked with civic virtue, which is synon-
ymous with “general welfare” and “public in-
terest” and implies responsibility to one’s pro-
fessional society as well as civil society. In my
view, however, social justice is better understood
concretely as a continuum of interventions that
range in their effects from reform (i.e., adjust-
ments to a social system) to transformation (i.e.,
fundamental changes in the substance of a sys-
tem or even its demise), even revolution, non-
violent or not (Walsh & Gokani, 2014). The
concept of social responsibility refers to at-
tempts to effect social justice by improving
societal systems to benefit everyone equitably.
The codes differ from each other in how they
address our potential involvement as psycholo-
gists with issues of justice and how we may
ethically engage with society to contribute to
societal improvement. Although APA does not
incorporate social justice explicitly in its Ethics
Code, the concept is identified as a core value in
the vision statement of APA’s strategic plan and
the association has become more outspoken in
its political advocacy (Vasquez, 2011).
The CPA Code’s Values Statement for Prin-
ciple IV: Responsibility to Society (CPA, 2000)
seems at first to be concerned with ensuring that
we psychologists treat extant social structures
with respect and comport ourselves in an “even-
tempered” manner. Then the code states that if
social systems obstruct the actualization of the
code’s four principles, “psychologists involved
have a responsibility to speak out in a manner
consistent with the principles of this Code, and
advocate for appropriate change to occur as
quickly as possible” (CPA, 2000). This Values
Statement stresses that we are expected to chal-
lenge extant social systems and societal prac-
tices but in a respectful and collaborative man-
ner. However, as progressive as this statement
might seem to traditional psychologists, any
code of psychological ethics founded in indi-
vidual-centered moral philosophies (Walsh,
2015) has difficulty embracing the transforma-
tional potential of social justice, because the
duty to practice social justice emanates from
“relational [and communitarian] ethics, which
motivate us to act out of concern for others and
consideration of social contexts” (Truscott &
Crook, 2013, p. 170). Our ethical codes and
discourse would be enriched, some argue, if the
codes incorporated relational and communitar-
ian perspectives, which assume human interde-
pendence (Johnson et al., 2012).
Both codes’ foundational principles do sug-
gest that we have an ethical obligation to con-
tribute to bettering society and protecting hu-
man rights, such as advocating for progressive
social change. In fact, the CPA Code’s Principle
IV: Responsibility to Society contains standards
that encourage us, as in Standard IV. Six for
example, to “Participate in the process of criti-
cal self-evaluation of the discipline’s place in
society, and in the development and implemen-
tation of structures and procedures that help the
discipline to contribute to beneficial societal
functioning and changes” (CPA, 2000). More-
over, three of the APA Code’s principles—
fidelity and responsibility, integrity, and jus-
tice— contain within them expectations for
psychologists’ making public statements about
matters of social policy. The code’s Standards
2.01, 2.06, and 3.04 urge psychologists to be
cautious and clear in drawing inferences about
social applications from psychological findings.
However, sufficient empirical evidence fre-
quently is lacking on a particular social issue,
yet societal exigencies seem to demand an au-
thoritative response from us. The consensus is
that when taking a public stance on matters
where empirical support is insufficient, we
should distinguish between our personal opin-
ions and values and our professional, scientific
claims (Martel, 2009). Nevertheless, typical
concerns are that direct participation in the work
of social justice and political activism could
politicize the discipline, confuse our formal
roles, and harm the discipline’s scientific cred-
ibility (Kakkad, 2005).
Impediments to justice. One could argue
that psychologists “who are truly respectful and
caring of others cannot be blind to social injus-
tice” (Pettifor, 1996, p. 8). But throughout our
discipline’s history, when we have responded to
social injustices, our interventions have been
95BENDING THE ARC
T
hi
s
do
cu
m
en
t
is
co
py
ri
gh
te
d
by
th
e
A
m
er
ic
an
P
sy
ch
ol
og
ic
al
A
ss
oc
ia
ti
on
or
on
e
of
it
s
al
li
ed
pu
bl
is
he
rs
.
T
hi
s
ar
ti
cl
e
is
in
te
nd
ed
so
le
ly
fo
r
th
e
pe
rs
on
al
us
e
of
th
e
in
di
vi
du
al
us
er
an
d
is
no
t
to
be
di
ss
em
in
at
ed
br
oa
dl
y.
reformist, politically speaking (Walsh, Teo, &
Baydala, 2014), which I assert, represents a
visual and behavioral impairment in social mo-
rality. Furthermore, ethical discourse in the dis-
cipline continues to counsel us to maintain po-
litically moderate professional identities
(Haeny, 2014; Kakkad, 2005). If this is our
historical and current reality and self-image,
what could move us to respond to calls to social
justice, which often are immoderate, even rad-
ical, in their implications?
When Martin Luther King, Jr. (1968) ad-
dressed psychologists in a 1967 summer of Af-
rican American rebellions against systemic rac-
ism, he urged us not to contribute to the
psychological adjustment of citizens, because,
he said, individuals and society should never be
adjusted to oppressive conditions. Rather, he
challenged us to foster “creative maladjust-
ment,” that is, to transform society into relation-
ships of justice. Answering King’s denunciation
of promoting adaptation and adjustment and his
annunciation of overturning the societal status
quo demands that we confront the impediments
in our discipline to enacting social justice be-
yond the inadequacies of our ethics codes. But
we have not practiced his exhortation, largely
because we have little history of contributing to
social change that strengthens ecological-
environmental, economic, and social justice
(Walsh & Gokani, 2014). Instead, we have ig-
nored our discipline’s inherent sociopolitical
limitations yet have contributed to various types
of social reform, if not directly, then indirectly
(Walsh et al., 2014). Aspirations for enacting
social justice notwithstanding (e.g., Vasquez,
2011, 2012), psychology has been and remains
an administrative tool for society’s power bro-
kers, that is, our activities have and continue to
enhance the efficacy of society’s economic, ed-
ucational, and governmental institutions (Dan-
ziger, 1979).
The interrelated disciplinary, institutional,
sociopolitical, and personal aspects of our tra-
ditional educational, investigative, and profes-
sional endeavors have mitigated our attempts to
address social injustice in society systematically
and systemically. Consequently, any attempts to
effect social justice require, first and foremost,
that we strive to resolve the contradictions in
our own practices. Given that many authors
have identified psychology as an individualistic
science (e.g., Sarason, 1981), a status that hin-
ders the enactment of social responsibility and
social justice, I focus on other impediments:
psychology as a natural science, its reformist
orientation, our personal distance from oppres-
sion, and our social contract with society.
A natural science. Historically, North
American psychology has been fixed in a natu-
ral-science orbit that concentrates on predicting,
controlling, and theorizing individuals’ behav-
ior and mental processes, to the virtual exclu-
sion of a human-science conception that con-
centrates on understanding and interpreting
contextualized experience of individuals and
their cultures (Walsh et al., 2014). Our lengthy
training in the natural-science orientation in-
clines us to segregate subjective from objective
judgment, as if the facts that we construct exist
independently of our interpretations of observa-
tions. In the CPA Code’s Principle III: Integrity
of Relationships, for instance, this objectivism
is apparent in four standards pertaining to ob-
jectivity, generally unqualified.
The convention in natural-science psychol-
ogy also has been that in our formal relationship
with society we are duty bound as objective
scientists to uphold the Humean distinction be-
tween facts and values (e.g., Kendler, 2008);
that is, “empirical data are and should be value-
free” (Martel, 2009, p. 104). In my view, the
relationship between putative scientific facts
and social values is key to understanding what
the ethical considerations might be when we
address social issues. The traditional position is
that if we engage in social action as individuals,
our stances of social-advocacy risk being per-
ceived as expressions of bias, which weakens
our individual credibility and stains the disci-
pline’s reputation (Haeny, 2014; Kendler, 2008;
Truscott & Crook, 2013). An alternative view is
that ethical values and practices, as well as
scientific ones, are enacted in a cultural-
historical context of social roles and relation-
ships that are embedded in societal ideologies,
structures, and institutions. From this perspec-
tive, then, our moral task is to recognize and
address how social realities influence our val-
ues, concepts, and practices. Yet, our scientific
and professional training has socialized us to
relate to the persons we study and serve from a
reputedly value-free standpoint of neutral ob-
jectivity, even as we might avoid reflecting on
our biases, such as our longstanding neglect of
social class (Walsh & Gokani, 2014). As a
96 WALSH
T
hi
s
do
cu
m
en
t
is
co
py
ri
gh
te
d
by
th
e
A
m
er
ic
an
P
sy
ch
ol
og
ic
al
A
ss
oc
ia
ti
on
or
on
e
of
it
s
al
li
ed
pu
bl
is
he
rs
.
T
hi
s
ar
ti
cl
e
is
in
te
nd
ed
so
le
ly
fo
r
th
e
pe
rs
on
al
us
e
of
th
e
in
di
vi
du
al
us
er
an
d
is
no
t
to
be
di
ss
em
in
at
ed
br
oa
dl
y.
consequence, in our formal relationships we
convey personal interests, prejudices, and so-
ciopolitical biases that are sustained by our priv-
ileged socioeconomic status as members of the
establishment. In light of this history, actualiz-
ing overarching ethical values of respecting hu-
man dignity and protecting human rights might
be compromised at least to some extent, when
we enter the public domain of social issues
laden with such baggage.
A reformist bent. Particularly in the U.S.
A., psychology originated within a nineteenth-
century social order characterized by free-
market capitalism and global imperialism.
When massive urbanization occurred, business,
industry, and government leaders, aided by sci-
entists and the new class of professionals, in-
cluding psychologists, aimed to administer the
masses effectively by rationalizing society
(Danziger, 1979). Social engineering to ensure
that citizens adapted to their station in life be-
came psychology’s applied mission, which is
reflected in the notion of social adjustment (Na-
poli, 1981). Historically, then, we psychologists
have been much more likely to engage in social
reform and thereby to sustain the societal status
quo (Herman, 1995) than in any interventions
that could merit the term transformative. More-
over, self-servingly we have regarded the prog-
ress and advancement of our science and pro-
fession as a barometer of democracy and the
health of society at large (Capshew, 1999).
Within the discipline’s tradition of social re-
form the consensus is that we have a responsi-
bility to contribute (conventional) psychologi-
cal research on the particular social issues under
scrutiny and to educate the public about the
likely outcomes of one course of action versus
another action.
Yet, there are few precedents for psycholo-
gists who take political stances, because few of
us study political action, even fewer engage
directly in it, and we rarely consider anarchistic
and revolutionary political options (Walsh &
Gokani, 2014). Moreover, the discipline shows
little interest in fostering an ethical obligation of
social responsibility to contribute to changing
social systems so that all in a given society
benefit. Instead, overtly or not, for generations
we have pledged allegiance to the flag of evolv-
ing capitalism, as APA presidential addresses
show (Sarason, 1981). We have absorbed capi-
talist discourse so well and thereby distanced
ourselves from its destructive nature that some
of us speak of social support as “social capital”
and community interventions as “social entre-
preneurship” apparently without irony; our cri-
terion of value evidently reflects the ideology of
neoliberal capitalism (see Sugarman, 2015).
Overall, then, since the postwar era psychol-
ogists have made no essential distinction among
service to the state, employment by the govern-
ment, and social responsibility for the science
and profession (Herman, 1995). Rather, indi-
rectly or directly in our psychologized societies,
we have occupied the privileged position of
plausibly explaining individuals to themselves.
Thus, as citizens, “Our feelings, beliefs, desires,
hopes and fears are suffused with the descrip-
tions, injunctions, and evaluations of those [for
example, psychologists] who claim to know
more about what is good for us than we do
ourselves” (Rose, 1996, p. 224).
Personal distance from oppressive social
conditions. The codes have insufficiently ad-
dressed the larger social context in which ethi-
cal issues and dilemmas occur, such as the
oppressive societal conditions of poverty, rac-
ism, sexism, and heterosexism that permeate all
layers of social relations. Such distancing is
manifest, for instance, in the APA Code in
which universal moral duties are understood
ideally and abstracted from societal conditions.
Thus, autonomy refers to psychologists foster-
ing the right to self-determination of those
whom we study, teach, treat, counsel, or con-
sult; beneficence and nonmaleficence mean nur-
turing well-being and doing no harm to those
with whom we engage; fidelity refers to being
trustworthy in all our scientific and professional
relations; and justice refers to acting with fair-
ness and equity.
Furthermore, the fact that, as a group, psy-
chologists operate from positions of substantial
socioeconomic privilege can inhibit our re-
sponding effectively to the diverse social loca-
tions of the individuals, groups, organizations,
and communities with whom we work (Walsh
& Gokani, 2014). Although many of us can be
subjected to oppressive experiences due to our
locations in intersecting social categories, our
socioeconomic status as scientist-professionals
distances us from understanding and relating
with the recipients of our psychological activi-
ties in a way that appreciates how societal con-
ditions of oppression might affect them directly
97BENDING THE ARC
T
hi
s
do
cu
m
en
t
is
co
py
ri
gh
te
d
by
th
e
A
m
er
ic
an
P
sy
ch
ol
og
ic
al
A
ss
oc
ia
ti
on
or
on
e
of
it
s
al
li
ed
pu
bl
is
he
rs
.
T
hi
s
ar
ti
cl
e
is
in
te
nd
ed
so
le
ly
fo
r
th
e
pe
rs
on
al
us
e
of
th
e
in
di
vi
du
al
us
er
an
d
is
no
t
to
be
di
ss
em
in
at
ed
br
oa
dl
y.
and indirectly. The potential disparities between
our social locations and those of the recipients
of our activities can impede our capacities for
ethical decision-making (Lerman & Porter,
1990).
Social contract with society. The codes’
disposition of responsibility to society assumes,
explicitly or not, an “overriding ethic of a social
contract” between psychologists and society
(Sinclair, 1998, p. 168). The current CPA Code,
for example, expanded “its [initial] scope be-
yond a narrow individualistic world view”
through the notion of a social contract that “ob-
ligates psychologists to place the public interest
above self-interest” (Pettifor, 1998, p. 232, em-
phasis added). According to this principle, we
make a commitment to contribute to human
welfare in return for receiving professional sta-
tus and autonomy in society.
However, the likelihood that this quid pro
quo obligates us to sustain extant social institu-
tions, even if attempting to improve them to
benefit all, is evident in the following depiction
of the social contract: “In order to honor and
sustain this interdependence a professional code
of ethics ought not contain anything that is
discordant with the values of society at large”
(Truscott & Crook, 2013, p. 3). Moreover, what
is meant by the public interest and what activ-
ities might be included within the domain of
privileging societal and individual welfare
above our own interests have remained unde-
fined. In addition, the politically limited scope
of this social contract is evident in CPA Stan-
dard IV.10 in which we are encouraged to
“[c]ontribute to the general welfare of society
(e.g., improving accessibility of services, re-
gardless of ability to pay).” This example rep-
resents charity not justice. Furthermore, if “psy-
chology uses ethical codes to support the
political professionalization strategies of the
discipline” and these “strategies help to market
the discipline and to ensure public support for
science and practice” (Pettifor, 1996, p. 2), as
Dunbar’s (1998) historical analysis of the CPA
Code attested, then any suggestion that altruism
is psychologists’ primary motivation for engag-
ing in a social contract is misleading. Realisti-
cally, we value our own interests at least as
much as contributing to societal welfare, as our
history has shown (Walsh et al., 2014).
Furthermore, maintaining personal-profes-
sional boundaries that do not tarnish public per-
ception of psychologists’ credentialed status is
the disciplinary norm (Haeny, 2014), which the
codes underscore. Despite the CPA Code’s di-
rection, for instance, that we are to privilege the
welfare of society and individuals above our
own, pragmatically, the social contract enables
the discipline to flourish in society. Conse-
quently, an inherent disinclination on our part to
“bite the hand that feeds us” appears to limit the
quality and degree of our contributions to hu-
man welfare and well-being and to ensure that,
as far as mainstream psychologists are con-
cerned, extant social structures and institutions
remain intact, even if reformed to benefit some
citizens.
The Transit of Social Ethics in Psychology:
Shifting Psychologists’ Ethical Discourse
In light of tensions within APA over its com-
mitment to the public interest and its stances on
public policies and the history of unjust psycho-
logical practices, Vasquez (2012) asserted that
“To prevent abusive application of psychologi-
cal principles and knowledge, psychologists
must remain vigilant about how we, and the
discipline of psychology, are encapsulated in
the social contexts and cultural positions in
which we live” (p. 338). In responding to
Vasquez’s call for vigilance yet mindful of the
limitations of the discourse on ethics, I ask: Of
what does social morality for psychologists
consist, given that we conform to society’s
laws, social structures, and mores, as well as
those of our discipline, even while some have
challenged the establishment in society and the
discipline by striving to overcome dysfunc-
tional and oppressive laws, social structures,
and mores? Is there moral space in psychology,
as King (1968) urged, in conscience and soli-
darity with other citizens, for denouncing an
ecologically, economically, politically, and cul-
turally imperiled and unjust society and promot-
ing economic, sociopolitical, and cultural trans-
formation, even to the point of rebellion and
revolution?
Discussion of such questions among psychol-
ogists is sparse, not simply perhaps because we
do not wish to jeopardize our social contract
with the societal establishment, but also because
we are both shaped by and committed to the
Enlightenment ideal of the reasoning moral sub-
ject who makes competent ethical decisions and
98 WALSH
T
hi
s
do
cu
m
en
t
is
co
py
ri
gh
te
d
by
th
e
A
m
er
ic
an
P
sy
ch
ol
og
ic
al
A
ss
oc
ia
ti
on
or
on
e
of
it
s
al
li
ed
pu
bl
is
he
rs
.
T
hi
s
ar
ti
cl
e
is
in
te
nd
ed
so
le
ly
fo
r
th
e
pe
rs
on
al
us
e
of
th
e
in
di
vi
du
al
us
er
an
d
is
no
t
to
be
di
ss
em
in
at
ed
br
oa
dl
y.
to a reformist psychological, if not also socio-
political, worldview. Besides, few of us psy-
chologists are either philosophers or political
activists. Altogether, then, our notions of re-
sponsibility to society are rather limited. In ef-
fect, we lack a moral compass for addressing
the interrelated existential challenges that con-
tinue to confront humankind: (a) escalating cli-
mate change and ecological destruction on land
and sea render life on Earth extremely precari-
ous; (b) unsustainable neoliberal economic and
financial practices (e.g., regimes of austerity)
ensure obscene largesse for the tiny minority,
continued comfort for the scientific-profes-
sional class, and relative or absolute poverty for
the masses; and (c) militarized governments
wage perpetual war in the name of fighting
terrorism, while the omnipresent danger of a
nuclear holocaust looms on the horizon with the
Doomsday Clock now registering three minutes
to midnight, meaning imminent global catastro-
phe. I conclude, therefore, that our regnant dis-
position of moderation concerning our respon-
sibility to society shows a lack of courage,
hence is unacceptable morally. Moreover, our
responses to global, national, and local precarity
will remain superficial until we develop an un-
derstanding of the concrete ecological-environ-
mental, economic, political, and cultural condi-
tions of mundane life (Walsh & Gokani, 2014),
which would require reconstructing psychology
(Walsh et al., 2014).
Nevertheless, one giant leap for our ethical
discourse might be to revise the codes to enable
the principles and standards to suit our existen-
tial realities. The APA Code could ensure that
the Principle of Justice is understood in terms of
social justice and social responsibility, while the
CPA Code could rank Principle IV: Responsi-
bility to Society equivalent to Principle I: Re-
spect for the Dignity of the Person in its hier-
archy. Both codes could incorporate dialogical
ethics within them, as the modus operandi for
ethical psychologists. Second, we could devote
our scientific and professional attention to ad-
dressing humankind’s existential challenges.
For instance, psychologists from different sub-
disciplines could investigate and interpret the
human perceptions, causes, and consequences
of climate change as well as adaptive and mit-
igating responses by individuals and communi-
ties to climate change (Swim et al., 2011).
However, some cautionary notes are neces-
sary on the prospects of psychologists becom-
ing mindful advocates and practitioners of so-
cial justice. One moral flaw in the codes is that
they address the rights of the recipients of our
scientific, educational, and professional activi-
ties only indirectly in their focus on our per-
spectives and privileges (Prilleltensky et al.,
1996). As a result, the balance of social power
implicit within the codes’ texts strongly favors
protecting our interests. The CPA Code, for
instance, does not specifically prescribe consul-
tation with recipients concerning “ethical deci-
sions that affect them” (Pettifor, 1998, p. 233).
If equal emphasis were placed on the ethical
rights of the recipients of our activities, which
would strengthen the centrality of dialogical
communication in the prescribed procedures of
ethical decision-making, it could balance our
social-cultural power and aid in preventing ma-
leficence and fostering beneficence. However,
such a development, although welcome and vi-
tal, would affect the interpersonal level of social
systems primarily, not the organizational-
institutional and societal levels. Furthermore, a
transition toward social-ethical conceptions and
practices of ethics is unlikely to occur, if we
remain committed in theory and practice to an
exclusively natural-science individualistic con-
ception of psychology. Rather, a transition to-
ward social ethics requires, and could enrich,
basic changes in our conceptions and practices
of psychological science, applications and ser-
vice to society, education of students, and our
functions in organizational and institutional sys-
tems (Walsh et al., 2014).
In addition, not only does our heritage consist
of shoring up the status quo through social
reform, but also the history of progressive
movements in psychology shows that the disci-
pline constrains impulses for progressive
change just as the larger socioeconomic system
coopts such impulses in its economic, political,
and social institutions (Walsh & Gokani, 2014).
Various calls for incorporating “social justice
and activism into [psychology’s] larger iden-
tity” (Kakkad, 2005, p. 307) neglect how soci-
ety and psychologists struggle with regression
toward the societal mean. Societal regression
serves as a sociopolitical undertow that drags us
back to the comforts of the abundant intellectual
and material privileges that we members of the
scientific-professional class enjoy, relative to
99BENDING THE ARC
T
hi
s
do
cu
m
en
t
is
co
py
ri
gh
te
d
by
th
e
A
m
er
ic
an
P
sy
ch
ol
og
ic
al
A
ss
oc
ia
ti
on
or
on
e
of
it
s
al
li
ed
pu
bl
is
he
rs
.
T
hi
s
ar
ti
cl
e
is
in
te
nd
ed
so
le
ly
fo
r
th
e
pe
rs
on
al
us
e
of
th
e
in
di
vi
du
al
us
er
an
d
is
no
t
to
be
di
ss
em
in
at
ed
br
oa
dl
y.
most North Americans. But this very status con-
strains our moral engagement as participants in
solidarity and in dialogue with other citizens,
rather than objectivistic spectators, in the strug-
gle to collectively confront the existential issues
of our time.
To conclude, I have argued for a critique both
of the taken-for-granted assumption of the psy-
chologist as an autonomous ethical actor who
competently applies logical problem-solving to
ethical situations and of the sociopolitical ide-
ology implicit in ethical discourse, which con-
flates social reform with social transformation
in the name of social justice. I am arguing that
as psychologists we lack moral preparation for
progressive engagement in society. This defi-
ciency seems attributable largely to a basic his-
torical contradiction for which there is no easy
resolution and many moral ambiguities. On the
one hand, we barely consider the dubious con-
viction that we can practice moral discernment
as autonomous ethical actors, even while non-
rational and communicative processes affect
our ethical conduct and social-historical forces
shape our vocation. This conviction obscures
psychological and sociocultural limits to our
capacity for exercising reason in ethical deci-
sion-making. On the other hand, we seek to
apply our science for the betterment of society,
according to the tradition of social reform and
adjustment to society.
An alternative to these standard practices is
one of animating the fundamentally moral na-
ture of our vocation by shifting our conceptions
and practices of ethics from an individualistic
orientation toward communicative and emanci-
patory orientations (see also Teo, 2015b). In
advancing this case I invoke the hope that we
will bend the arc of our moral universe toward
ecological-environmental, economic, political,
cultural, and social justice (Walsh & Gokani,
2014). However, if our ethical conceptions and
practices, including the APA and CPA Codes,
are merely reformed, thus remain unchanged in
substance, they will serve more as emblems of
professional pride than as worthy instruments in
the urgent struggle toward justice locally, na-
tionally, and globally.
References
American Psychological Association. (2010). Ethical
principles of psychologists and code of conduct
(2002, Amended June 1, 2010). Retrieved from
http://www.apa.org/ethics/code/index.aspx
Aubé, N. (2011). Ethical challenges for psychologists
conducting humanitarian work. Canadian Psy-
chology/Psychologie canadienne, 52, 225–229.
http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/a0024342
Canadian Psychological Association. (2000). Cana-
dian Code of Ethics for psychologists (3rd ed.).
Ottawa, Canada: Author.
Capshew, J. H. (1999). Psychologists on the march:
Science, practice, and professional identity in
America, 1929 –1969. New York, NY: Cambridge
University Press. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/
CBO9780511572944
Cottone, R. R. (2011). Ethical decision making in
mental health contexts: Representative models and
an organizational framework. In S. J. Knapp, M. C.
Gottlieb, M. M. Handelsman, & L. D. VandeCreek
(Eds.), APA handbook of ethics in psychology:
Vol. 1. Moral foundations and common themes
(pp. 99 –121). Washington, DC: American Psycho-
logical Association.
Danziger, K. (1979). The social origins of modern
psychology. In A. R. Buss (Ed.), Psychology in
social context (pp. 27– 45). New York, NY: Irving-
ton.
Dunbar, J. (1998). A critical history of CPA’s various
codes of ethics for psychologists (1939 –1986).
Canadian Psychology/Psychologie canadienne,
39, 177–186. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/h0086806
Fisher, C. B. (2013). Decoding the ethics code; A
practical guide for psychologists (3rd ed.). Thou-
sand Oaks, CA: Sage.
Habermas, J. (1983). The theory of communicative
action: Vol. 2. Lifeworld and system: A critique of
functionalist reason (T. McCarthy, Trans.). Bos-
ton, MA: Beacon. (Original work published in
German 1981)
Haeny, A. M. (2014). Ethical considerations for psy-
chologists taking a public stance on controversial
issues: The balance between personal and profes-
sional life. Ethics & Behavior, 24, 265–278. http://
dx.doi.org/10.1080/10508422.2013.860030
Herman, E. (1995). The romance of American psy-
chology: Political culture in the age of experts.
Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.
Johnson, W. B., Barnett, J. E., Elman, N. S., Forrest,
L., & Kaslow, N. J. (2012). The competent com-
munity: Toward a vital reformulation of profes-
sional ethics. American Psychologist, 67, 557–569.
http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/a0027206
Kahneman, D. (2003). A perspective on judgment
and choice: Mapping bounded rationality. Ameri-
can Psychologist, 58, 697–720. http://dx.doi.org/
10.1037/0003-066X.58.9.697
Kakkad, D. (2005). A new ethical praxis: Psycholo-
gists’ emerging responsibilities in issues of social
100 WALSH
T
hi
s
do
cu
m
en
t
is
co
py
ri
gh
te
d
by
th
e
A
m
er
ic
an
P
sy
ch
ol
og
ic
al
A
ss
oc
ia
ti
on
or
on
e
of
it
s
al
li
ed
pu
bl
is
he
rs
.
T
hi
s
ar
ti
cl
e
is
in
te
nd
ed
so
le
ly
fo
r
th
e
pe
rs
on
al
us
e
of
th
e
in
di
vi
du
al
us
er
an
d
is
no
t
to
be
di
ss
em
in
at
ed
br
oa
dl
y.
http://www.apa.org/ethics/code/index.aspx
http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/a0024342
http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511572944
http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511572944
http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/h0086806
http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/10508422.2013.860030
http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/10508422.2013.860030
http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/a0027206
http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/0003-066X.58.9.697
http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/0003-066X.58.9.697
justice. Ethics & Behavior, 15, 293–308. http://dx
.doi.org/10.1207/s15327019eb1504_2
Kendler, H. H. (2008). Amoral thoughts about mo-
rality: The intersection of science, psychology, and
ethics (2nd ed.). Springfield, IL: Thomas.
Kennedy, C. H. (2011). Institutional ethical conflicts
with illustrations from police and military psychol-
ogy. In S. J. Knapp, M. C. Gottlieb, M. M. Han-
delsman, & L. D. VandeCreek (Eds.), APA hand-
book of ethics in psychology: Vol. 1. Moral
foundations and common themes (pp. 123–144).
Washington, DC: American Psychological Associ-
ation.
King, M. L., Jr. (1968). The role of the behavioral
scientist in the civil rights movement. American
Psychologist, 23, 180 –186. http://dx.doi.org/
10.1037/h0025715
Kitchener, R. F., & Kitchener, K. S. (2011). Ethical
foundations of psychology. In S. J. Knapp, M. C.
Gottlieb, M. M. Handelsman, & L. D. VandeCreek
(Eds.), APA handbook of ethics in psychology:
Vol. 1. Moral foundations and common themes
(pp. 3– 42). Washington, DC: American Psycho-
logical Association. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/
13271-001
Lerman, H., & Porter, N. (1990). Feminist ethics in
psychotherapy. New York, NY: Springer.
Malloy, D. C., & Hadjistavropoulos, T. (1998). A
philosophical value analysis of the Canadian Code
of Ethics for psychologists. Canadian Psychology/
Psychologie canadienne, 39, 187–193. http://dx
.doi.org/10.1037/h0086807
Martel, M. M. (2009). The ethics of psychology’s
role in politics and the development and institution
of social policy. Ethics & Behavior, 19, 103–111.
http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/10508420902772694
Meehan, J. (1995). (Ed.). Feminists read Habermas:
Gendering the subject of discourse. New York,
NY: Routledge.
Napoli, D. S. (1981). Architects of adjustment. Port
Washington, NY: Kennikat.
Pettifor, J. L. (1996). Ethics: Virtue and politics in
the science and practice of psychology. Canadian
Psychology/Psychologie canadienne, 37, 1–12.
http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/0708-5591.37.1.1
Pettifor, J. L. (1998). The Canadian Code of Ethics
for Psychologists: A moral context for ethical de-
cision-making in emerging areas of practice. Ca-
nadian Psychology/Psychologie canadienne, 39,
231–238. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/h0086812
Pipes, R. B., Holstein, J. E., & Aguirre, M. G. (2005).
Examining the personal-professional distinction:
Ethics codes and the difficulty of drawing a bound-
ary. American Psychologist, 60, 325–334. http://
dx.doi.org/10.1037/0003-066X.60.4.325
Prilleltensky, I., Rossiter, A., & Walsh-Bowers, R.
(1996). Preventing harm and promoting ethical
discourse in the helping professions: Conceptual,
research, analytical, and action frameworks. Ethics
& Behavior, 6, 287–306. http://dx.doi.org/
10.1207/s15327019eb0604_1
Prilleltensky, I., & Walsh-Bowers, R. (1993). Psy-
chology and the moral imperative. Journal of The-
oretical and Philosophical Psychology, 13, 90 –
102. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/h0091122
Rogerson, M. D., Gottlieb, M. C., Handelsman,
M. M., Knapp, S., & Younggren, J. (2011). Non-
rational processes in ethical decision making.
American Psychologist, 66, 614 – 623. http://dx.doi
.org/10.1037/a0025215
Rose, N. (1996). Assembling the modern self. In R.
Porter (Ed.), The history of the self (pp. 224 –248).
London, UK: Routledge.
Rossiter, A., Walsh-Bowers, R., & Prilleltensky, I.
(2002). Ethics as a located story: A comparison of
North American and Cuban clinical ethics. Theory
& Psychology, 12, 533–556. http://dx.doi.org/10
.1177/0959354302012004298
Sarason, S. B. (1981). Psychology misdirected. New
York, NY: Free Press.
Shotter, J. (2005). Acknowledging unique others:
Ethics, “expressive realism,” and social con-
structionism. Journal of Constructivist Psychol-
ogy, 18, 103–130. http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/
10720530590914761
Sinclair, C. (1998). Nine unique features of the Ca-
nadian Code of Ethics for Psychologists. Cana-
dian Psychology/Psychologie canadienne, 39,
167–176. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/h0086805
Strong, T., & Sutherland, O. (2007). Conversational
ethics in psychological dialogues: Discursive and
collaborative considerations. Canadian Psycholo-
gy/Psychologie canadienne, 48, 94 –105. http://dx
.doi.org/10.1037/cp2007011
Sugarman, J. (2015). Neoliberalism and psychologi-
cal ethics. Journal of Theoretical and Philosophi-
cal Psychology, 35, 103–116. http://dx.doi.org/
10.1037/a0038960
Swim, J. K., Stern, P. C., Doherty, T. J., Clayton, S.,
Reser, J. P., Weber, E. U., . . . Howard, G. S.
(2011). Psychology’s contributions to understand-
ing and addressing global climate change. Ameri-
can Psychologist, 66, 241–250. http://dx.doi.org/
10.1037/a0023220
Teo, T. (2015a). Are psychological “ethics codes”
morally oblique? Journal of Theoretical and Phil-
osophical Psychology, 35, 78 – 89. http://dx.doi
.org/10.1037/a0038944
Teo, T. (2015b). Critical psychology: A geography of
intellectual engagement and resistance. American
Psychologist, 70, 1–12.
Truscott, D., & Crook, K. H. (2013). Ethics for the
practice of psychology in Canada (Rev. ed.). Ed-
monton, Canada: University of Alberta Press.
Vasquez, M. J. T. (2011). Social justice and civic
101BENDING THE ARC
T
hi
s
do
cu
m
en
t
is
co
py
ri
gh
te
d
by
th
e
A
m
er
ic
an
P
sy
ch
ol
og
ic
al
A
ss
oc
ia
ti
on
or
on
e
of
it
s
al
li
ed
pu
bl
is
he
rs
.
T
hi
s
ar
ti
cl
e
is
in
te
nd
ed
so
le
ly
fo
r
th
e
pe
rs
on
al
us
e
of
th
e
in
di
vi
du
al
us
er
an
d
is
no
t
to
be
di
ss
em
in
at
ed
br
oa
dl
y.
http://dx.doi.org/10.1207/s15327019eb1504_2
http://dx.doi.org/10.1207/s15327019eb1504_2
http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/ h0025715
http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/h0025715
http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/13271-001
http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/13271-001
http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/h0086807
http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/h0086807
http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/10508420902772694
http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/0708-5591.37.1.1
http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/h0086812
http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/0003-066X.60.4.325
http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/0003-066X.60.4.325
http://dx.doi.org/10.1207/s15327019eb0604_1
http://dx.doi.org/10.1207/s15327019eb0604_1
http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/ h0091122
http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/a0025215
http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/a0025215
http://dx.doi.org/10.1177/0959354302012004298
http://dx.doi.org/10.1177/0959354302012004298
http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/10720530590914761
http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/10720530590914761
http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/h0086805
http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/cp2007011
http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/cp2007011
http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/a0038960
http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/a0038960
http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/a0023220
http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/a0023220
http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/a0038944
http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/a0038944
virtue. In S. J. Knapp, M. C. Gottlieb, M. M.
Handelsman, & L. D. VandeCreek (Eds.), APA
handbook of ethics in psychology: Vol. 1. Moral
foundations and common themes (pp. 75–98).
Washington, DC: American Psychological Associ-
ation.
Vasquez, M. J. T. (2012). Psychology and social
justice: Why we do what we do. American Psy-
chologist, 67, 337–346. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/
a0029232
Verges, A. (2010). Integrating contextual issues in
ethical decision making. Ethics & Behavior, 20,
497–507. http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/10508422
.2010.521451
Walsh, R. T. G. (2015). Introduction to the special
section on ethics in psychology: Historical and
philosophical grounding. Journal of Theoretical
and Philosophical Psychology, 35, 69 –77. http://
dx.doi.org/10.1037/teo0000011
Walsh, R. T. G., & Gokani, R. (2014). The personal
and political economy of psychologists’ desires for
social justice. Journal of Theoretical and Philo-
sophical Psychology, 34, 41–55. http://dx.doi.org/
10.1037/a0033081
Walsh, R. T. G., Teo, T., & Baydala, A. (2014). A
critical history and philosophy of psychology: Di-
versity of context, thought, and practice. New
York, NY: New York: Cambridge University
Press.
Received February 13, 2015
Accepted March 3, 2015 �
Members of Underrepresented Groups:
Reviewers for Journal Manuscripts Wanted
If you are interested in reviewing manuscripts for APA journals,
the APA Publications
and Communications Board would like to invite your
participation. Manuscript reviewers
are vital to the publications process. As a reviewer, you would
gain valuable experience
in publishing. The P&C Board is particularly interested in
encouraging members of
underrepresented groups to participate more in this process.
If you are interested in reviewing manuscripts, please write
APA Journals at
[email protected] Please note the following important points:
• To be selected as a reviewer, you must have published articles
in peer-reviewed
journals. The experience of publishing provides a reviewer with
the basis for preparing
a thorough, objective review.
• To be selected, it is critical to be a regular reader of the five
to six empirical journals
that are most central to the area or journal for which you would
like to review. Current
knowledge of recently published research provides a reviewer
with the knowledge base
to evaluate a new submission within the context of existing
research.
• To select the appropriate reviewers for each manuscript, the
editor needs detailed
information. Please include with your letter your vita. In the
letter, please identify
which APA journal(s) you are interested in, and describe your
area of expertise. Be as
specific as possible. For example, “social psychology” is not
sufficient—you would
need to specify “social cognition” or “attitude change” as well.
• Reviewing a manuscript takes time (1– 4 hours per manuscript
reviewed). If you are
selected to review a manuscript, be prepared to invest the
necessary time to evaluate
the manuscript thoroughly.
APA now has an online video course that provides guidance in
reviewing manuscripts. To
learn more about the course and to access the video, visit
http://www.apa.org/pubs/
authors/review-manuscript-ce-video.aspx.
102 WALSH
T
hi
s
do
cu
m
en
t
is
co
py
ri
gh
te
d
by
th
e
A
m
er
ic
an
P
sy
ch
ol
og
ic
al
A
ss
oc
ia
ti
on
or
on
e
of
it
s
al
li
ed
pu
bl
is
he
rs
.
T
hi
s
ar
ti
cl
e
is
in
te
nd
ed
so
le
ly
fo
r
th
e
pe
rs
on
al
us
e
of
th
e
in
di
vi
du
al
us
er
an
d
is
no
t
to
be
di
ss
em
in
at
ed
br
oa
dl
y.
http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/a0029232
http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/a0029232
http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/10508422.2010.521451
http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/10508422.2010.521451
http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/teo0000011
http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/teo0000011
http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/a0033081
http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/a0033081Bending the Arc of North
American Psychologists’ Moral Universe Toward
Communicative Ethi ...A Social Contextual Review of Ethics
CodesCritical Perspectives on Ethical Decision-
MakingNonrational cognitive processesInterpersonal
processesThe Social Conditions of Psychologists’
VocationOrganizational and institutional
influencesProfessional-personal boundary maintenanceEthical
Relationship With SocietyThe codes’ orientationsImpediments
to justiceA natural scienceA reformist bentPersonal distance
from oppressive social conditionsSocial contract with
societyThe Transit of Social Ethics in Psychology: Shifting
Psychologists’ Ethical DiscourseReferences

More Related Content

Similar to Bending the Arc of North American Psychologists’ Moral Univers

Journal of HumaNisTic cOuNsELiNG ◆ July 2016 ◆ Volume 55 99
Journal of HumaNisTic cOuNsELiNG ◆ July 2016 ◆ Volume 55 99Journal of HumaNisTic cOuNsELiNG ◆ July 2016 ◆ Volume 55 99
Journal of HumaNisTic cOuNsELiNG ◆ July 2016 ◆ Volume 55 99
TatianaMajor22
 
ETHICS & BEHAVIOR, 24(6), 510–522Copyright © 2014 Taylor &
ETHICS & BEHAVIOR, 24(6), 510–522Copyright © 2014 Taylor &ETHICS & BEHAVIOR, 24(6), 510–522Copyright © 2014 Taylor &
ETHICS & BEHAVIOR, 24(6), 510–522Copyright © 2014 Taylor &
BetseyCalderon89
 
FINAL-RESEARCH-ETICS.docx How Character development affects reasoning and im...
FINAL-RESEARCH-ETICS.docx  How Character development affects reasoning and im...FINAL-RESEARCH-ETICS.docx  How Character development affects reasoning and im...
FINAL-RESEARCH-ETICS.docx How Character development affects reasoning and im...
ChristianMariano16
 
2020 - Smillie - Personality and moral judgement.pdf
2020 - Smillie - Personality and moral judgement.pdf2020 - Smillie - Personality and moral judgement.pdf
2020 - Smillie - Personality and moral judgement.pdf
srinivasschandru
 
Attitudes, Values and Organizational Culture: Disentangling the Concepts
Attitudes, Values and Organizational Culture: Disentangling the ConceptsAttitudes, Values and Organizational Culture: Disentangling the Concepts
Attitudes, Values and Organizational Culture: Disentangling the Concepts
ValerieBez1
 
Factors Influencing The Way In Which Decisions Are Made Looking a.docx
Factors Influencing The Way In Which Decisions Are Made Looking a.docxFactors Influencing The Way In Which Decisions Are Made Looking a.docx
Factors Influencing The Way In Which Decisions Are Made Looking a.docx
POLY33
 
Descriptive Ethics Encyclopedia Of Business Ethics
Descriptive Ethics   Encyclopedia Of Business EthicsDescriptive Ethics   Encyclopedia Of Business Ethics
Descriptive Ethics Encyclopedia Of Business Ethicssimply_coool
 
نقد وتحليل لثلاثة أساليب علاجية
نقد وتحليل لثلاثة أساليب علاجيةنقد وتحليل لثلاثة أساليب علاجية
نقد وتحليل لثلاثة أساليب علاجية
Mohammed Alali
 
WHO’S WITH ME FALSE CONSENSUS, BROKERAGE, ANDETHICAL DECISI.docx
WHO’S WITH ME FALSE CONSENSUS, BROKERAGE, ANDETHICAL DECISI.docxWHO’S WITH ME FALSE CONSENSUS, BROKERAGE, ANDETHICAL DECISI.docx
WHO’S WITH ME FALSE CONSENSUS, BROKERAGE, ANDETHICAL DECISI.docx
harold7fisher61282
 
ASSESSMENT-2 OVERVIEWWrite a 3–4-page assessment in which yo.docx
ASSESSMENT-2 OVERVIEWWrite a 3–4-page assessment in which yo.docxASSESSMENT-2 OVERVIEWWrite a 3–4-page assessment in which yo.docx
ASSESSMENT-2 OVERVIEWWrite a 3–4-page assessment in which yo.docx
petuniahita
 
Healthcare Ethics© marekullaszShutterstockEthics is nothi
Healthcare Ethics© marekullaszShutterstockEthics is nothiHealthcare Ethics© marekullaszShutterstockEthics is nothi
Healthcare Ethics© marekullaszShutterstockEthics is nothi
SusanaFurman449
 
Discussion AutismNo unread replies.No replies.Discussion- Cha
Discussion AutismNo unread replies.No replies.Discussion- ChaDiscussion AutismNo unread replies.No replies.Discussion- Cha
Discussion AutismNo unread replies.No replies.Discussion- Cha
LyndonPelletier761
 
3 c organizational behavior, development, culture paper final
3 c organizational behavior, development, culture paper final3 c organizational behavior, development, culture paper final
3 c organizational behavior, development, culture paper final
asfawm
 
Ethical Issues Essay.pdf
Ethical Issues Essay.pdfEthical Issues Essay.pdf
Ethical Issues Essay.pdf
Jennifer Smith
 
Ethics and Ethical Reasoningermissible, etc.)” One answe
Ethics and Ethical Reasoningermissible, etc.)” One answeEthics and Ethical Reasoningermissible, etc.)” One answe
Ethics and Ethical Reasoningermissible, etc.)” One answe
BetseyCalderon89
 
Ethic Essay
Ethic EssayEthic Essay
REINTERPRETING ETHICS AS PEDAGOGICAL REFERENCE: A META-SYNTHESIS
REINTERPRETING ETHICS AS PEDAGOGICAL REFERENCE: A META-SYNTHESISREINTERPRETING ETHICS AS PEDAGOGICAL REFERENCE: A META-SYNTHESIS
REINTERPRETING ETHICS AS PEDAGOGICAL REFERENCE: A META-SYNTHESIS
Wilson Temporal
 
Article Summary • Introduction (1 – 2 Sentences) •.docx
Article Summary • Introduction (1 – 2 Sentences) •.docxArticle Summary • Introduction (1 – 2 Sentences) •.docx
Article Summary • Introduction (1 – 2 Sentences) •.docx
festockton
 
3 c organizational behavior, development, culture paper final
3 c organizational behavior, development, culture paper final3 c organizational behavior, development, culture paper final
3 c organizational behavior, development, culture paper final
asfawm
 

Similar to Bending the Arc of North American Psychologists’ Moral Univers (20)

Psychoanalysis and Management
Psychoanalysis and ManagementPsychoanalysis and Management
Psychoanalysis and Management
 
Journal of HumaNisTic cOuNsELiNG ◆ July 2016 ◆ Volume 55 99
Journal of HumaNisTic cOuNsELiNG ◆ July 2016 ◆ Volume 55 99Journal of HumaNisTic cOuNsELiNG ◆ July 2016 ◆ Volume 55 99
Journal of HumaNisTic cOuNsELiNG ◆ July 2016 ◆ Volume 55 99
 
ETHICS & BEHAVIOR, 24(6), 510–522Copyright © 2014 Taylor &
ETHICS & BEHAVIOR, 24(6), 510–522Copyright © 2014 Taylor &ETHICS & BEHAVIOR, 24(6), 510–522Copyright © 2014 Taylor &
ETHICS & BEHAVIOR, 24(6), 510–522Copyright © 2014 Taylor &
 
FINAL-RESEARCH-ETICS.docx How Character development affects reasoning and im...
FINAL-RESEARCH-ETICS.docx  How Character development affects reasoning and im...FINAL-RESEARCH-ETICS.docx  How Character development affects reasoning and im...
FINAL-RESEARCH-ETICS.docx How Character development affects reasoning and im...
 
2020 - Smillie - Personality and moral judgement.pdf
2020 - Smillie - Personality and moral judgement.pdf2020 - Smillie - Personality and moral judgement.pdf
2020 - Smillie - Personality and moral judgement.pdf
 
Attitudes, Values and Organizational Culture: Disentangling the Concepts
Attitudes, Values and Organizational Culture: Disentangling the ConceptsAttitudes, Values and Organizational Culture: Disentangling the Concepts
Attitudes, Values and Organizational Culture: Disentangling the Concepts
 
Factors Influencing The Way In Which Decisions Are Made Looking a.docx
Factors Influencing The Way In Which Decisions Are Made Looking a.docxFactors Influencing The Way In Which Decisions Are Made Looking a.docx
Factors Influencing The Way In Which Decisions Are Made Looking a.docx
 
Descriptive Ethics Encyclopedia Of Business Ethics
Descriptive Ethics   Encyclopedia Of Business EthicsDescriptive Ethics   Encyclopedia Of Business Ethics
Descriptive Ethics Encyclopedia Of Business Ethics
 
نقد وتحليل لثلاثة أساليب علاجية
نقد وتحليل لثلاثة أساليب علاجيةنقد وتحليل لثلاثة أساليب علاجية
نقد وتحليل لثلاثة أساليب علاجية
 
WHO’S WITH ME FALSE CONSENSUS, BROKERAGE, ANDETHICAL DECISI.docx
WHO’S WITH ME FALSE CONSENSUS, BROKERAGE, ANDETHICAL DECISI.docxWHO’S WITH ME FALSE CONSENSUS, BROKERAGE, ANDETHICAL DECISI.docx
WHO’S WITH ME FALSE CONSENSUS, BROKERAGE, ANDETHICAL DECISI.docx
 
ASSESSMENT-2 OVERVIEWWrite a 3–4-page assessment in which yo.docx
ASSESSMENT-2 OVERVIEWWrite a 3–4-page assessment in which yo.docxASSESSMENT-2 OVERVIEWWrite a 3–4-page assessment in which yo.docx
ASSESSMENT-2 OVERVIEWWrite a 3–4-page assessment in which yo.docx
 
Healthcare Ethics© marekullaszShutterstockEthics is nothi
Healthcare Ethics© marekullaszShutterstockEthics is nothiHealthcare Ethics© marekullaszShutterstockEthics is nothi
Healthcare Ethics© marekullaszShutterstockEthics is nothi
 
Discussion AutismNo unread replies.No replies.Discussion- Cha
Discussion AutismNo unread replies.No replies.Discussion- ChaDiscussion AutismNo unread replies.No replies.Discussion- Cha
Discussion AutismNo unread replies.No replies.Discussion- Cha
 
3 c organizational behavior, development, culture paper final
3 c organizational behavior, development, culture paper final3 c organizational behavior, development, culture paper final
3 c organizational behavior, development, culture paper final
 
Ethical Issues Essay.pdf
Ethical Issues Essay.pdfEthical Issues Essay.pdf
Ethical Issues Essay.pdf
 
Ethics and Ethical Reasoningermissible, etc.)” One answe
Ethics and Ethical Reasoningermissible, etc.)” One answeEthics and Ethical Reasoningermissible, etc.)” One answe
Ethics and Ethical Reasoningermissible, etc.)” One answe
 
Ethic Essay
Ethic EssayEthic Essay
Ethic Essay
 
REINTERPRETING ETHICS AS PEDAGOGICAL REFERENCE: A META-SYNTHESIS
REINTERPRETING ETHICS AS PEDAGOGICAL REFERENCE: A META-SYNTHESISREINTERPRETING ETHICS AS PEDAGOGICAL REFERENCE: A META-SYNTHESIS
REINTERPRETING ETHICS AS PEDAGOGICAL REFERENCE: A META-SYNTHESIS
 
Article Summary • Introduction (1 – 2 Sentences) •.docx
Article Summary • Introduction (1 – 2 Sentences) •.docxArticle Summary • Introduction (1 – 2 Sentences) •.docx
Article Summary • Introduction (1 – 2 Sentences) •.docx
 
3 c organizational behavior, development, culture paper final
3 c organizational behavior, development, culture paper final3 c organizational behavior, development, culture paper final
3 c organizational behavior, development, culture paper final
 

More from ChantellPantoja184

Problem 1Problem 2.docx
Problem 1Problem 2.docxProblem 1Problem 2.docx
Problem 1Problem 2.docx
ChantellPantoja184
 
Problem 20-1A Production cost flow and measurement; journal entrie.docx
Problem 20-1A Production cost flow and measurement; journal entrie.docxProblem 20-1A Production cost flow and measurement; journal entrie.docx
Problem 20-1A Production cost flow and measurement; journal entrie.docx
ChantellPantoja184
 
Problem 2 Obtain Io.Let x be the current through j2, ..docx
Problem 2 Obtain Io.Let x be the current through j2, ..docxProblem 2 Obtain Io.Let x be the current through j2, ..docx
Problem 2 Obtain Io.Let x be the current through j2, ..docx
ChantellPantoja184
 
Problem 1On April 1, 20X4, Rojas purchased land by giving $100,000.docx
Problem 1On April 1, 20X4, Rojas purchased land by giving $100,000.docxProblem 1On April 1, 20X4, Rojas purchased land by giving $100,000.docx
Problem 1On April 1, 20X4, Rojas purchased land by giving $100,000.docx
ChantellPantoja184
 
Problem 17-1 Dividends and Taxes [LO2]Dark Day, Inc., has declar.docx
Problem 17-1 Dividends and Taxes [LO2]Dark Day, Inc., has declar.docxProblem 17-1 Dividends and Taxes [LO2]Dark Day, Inc., has declar.docx
Problem 17-1 Dividends and Taxes [LO2]Dark Day, Inc., has declar.docx
ChantellPantoja184
 
Problem 1Problem 1 - Constant-Growth Common StockWhat is the value.docx
Problem 1Problem 1 - Constant-Growth Common StockWhat is the value.docxProblem 1Problem 1 - Constant-Growth Common StockWhat is the value.docx
Problem 1Problem 1 - Constant-Growth Common StockWhat is the value.docx
ChantellPantoja184
 
Problem 1Prescott, Inc., manufactures bookcases and uses an activi.docx
Problem 1Prescott, Inc., manufactures bookcases and uses an activi.docxProblem 1Prescott, Inc., manufactures bookcases and uses an activi.docx
Problem 1Prescott, Inc., manufactures bookcases and uses an activi.docx
ChantellPantoja184
 
Problem 1Preston Recliners manufactures leather recliners and uses.docx
Problem 1Preston Recliners manufactures leather recliners and uses.docxProblem 1Preston Recliners manufactures leather recliners and uses.docx
Problem 1Preston Recliners manufactures leather recliners and uses.docx
ChantellPantoja184
 
Problem 1Pro Forma Income Statement and Balance SheetBelow is the .docx
Problem 1Pro Forma Income Statement and Balance SheetBelow is the .docxProblem 1Pro Forma Income Statement and Balance SheetBelow is the .docx
Problem 1Pro Forma Income Statement and Balance SheetBelow is the .docx
ChantellPantoja184
 
Problem 2-1PROBLEM 2-1Solution Legend= Value given in problemGiven.docx
Problem 2-1PROBLEM 2-1Solution Legend= Value given in problemGiven.docxProblem 2-1PROBLEM 2-1Solution Legend= Value given in problemGiven.docx
Problem 2-1PROBLEM 2-1Solution Legend= Value given in problemGiven.docx
ChantellPantoja184
 
PROBLEM 14-6AProblem 14-6A Norwoods Borrowings1. Total amount of .docx
PROBLEM 14-6AProblem 14-6A Norwoods Borrowings1. Total amount of .docxPROBLEM 14-6AProblem 14-6A Norwoods Borrowings1. Total amount of .docx
PROBLEM 14-6AProblem 14-6A Norwoods Borrowings1. Total amount of .docx
ChantellPantoja184
 
Problem 13-3AThe stockholders’ equity accounts of Ashley Corpo.docx
Problem 13-3AThe stockholders’ equity accounts of Ashley Corpo.docxProblem 13-3AThe stockholders’ equity accounts of Ashley Corpo.docx
Problem 13-3AThe stockholders’ equity accounts of Ashley Corpo.docx
ChantellPantoja184
 
Problem 12-9AYour answer is partially correct.  Try again..docx
Problem 12-9AYour answer is partially correct.  Try again..docxProblem 12-9AYour answer is partially correct.  Try again..docx
Problem 12-9AYour answer is partially correct.  Try again..docx
ChantellPantoja184
 
Problem 1123456Xf122437455763715813910106Name DateTopic.docx
Problem 1123456Xf122437455763715813910106Name DateTopic.docxProblem 1123456Xf122437455763715813910106Name DateTopic.docx
Problem 1123456Xf122437455763715813910106Name DateTopic.docx
ChantellPantoja184
 
Problem 1. For the truss and loading shown below, calculate th.docx
Problem 1. For the truss and loading shown below, calculate th.docxProblem 1. For the truss and loading shown below, calculate th.docx
Problem 1. For the truss and loading shown below, calculate th.docx
ChantellPantoja184
 
Problem 1 (30 marks)Review enough information about .docx
Problem 1 (30 marks)Review enough information about .docxProblem 1 (30 marks)Review enough information about .docx
Problem 1 (30 marks)Review enough information about .docx
ChantellPantoja184
 
Problem 1 (10 points) Note that an eigenvector cannot be zero.docx
Problem 1 (10 points) Note that an eigenvector cannot be zero.docxProblem 1 (10 points) Note that an eigenvector cannot be zero.docx
Problem 1 (10 points) Note that an eigenvector cannot be zero.docx
ChantellPantoja184
 
Probation and Parole 3Running head Probation and Parole.docx
Probation and Parole 3Running head Probation and Parole.docxProbation and Parole 3Running head Probation and Parole.docx
Probation and Parole 3Running head Probation and Parole.docx
ChantellPantoja184
 
Problem 1(a) Complete the following ANOVA table based on 20 obs.docx
Problem 1(a) Complete the following ANOVA table based on 20 obs.docxProblem 1(a) Complete the following ANOVA table based on 20 obs.docx
Problem 1(a) Complete the following ANOVA table based on 20 obs.docx
ChantellPantoja184
 
Probe 140 SPrecipitation in inchesTemperature in F.docx
Probe 140 SPrecipitation in inchesTemperature in F.docxProbe 140 SPrecipitation in inchesTemperature in F.docx
Probe 140 SPrecipitation in inchesTemperature in F.docx
ChantellPantoja184
 

More from ChantellPantoja184 (20)

Problem 1Problem 2.docx
Problem 1Problem 2.docxProblem 1Problem 2.docx
Problem 1Problem 2.docx
 
Problem 20-1A Production cost flow and measurement; journal entrie.docx
Problem 20-1A Production cost flow and measurement; journal entrie.docxProblem 20-1A Production cost flow and measurement; journal entrie.docx
Problem 20-1A Production cost flow and measurement; journal entrie.docx
 
Problem 2 Obtain Io.Let x be the current through j2, ..docx
Problem 2 Obtain Io.Let x be the current through j2, ..docxProblem 2 Obtain Io.Let x be the current through j2, ..docx
Problem 2 Obtain Io.Let x be the current through j2, ..docx
 
Problem 1On April 1, 20X4, Rojas purchased land by giving $100,000.docx
Problem 1On April 1, 20X4, Rojas purchased land by giving $100,000.docxProblem 1On April 1, 20X4, Rojas purchased land by giving $100,000.docx
Problem 1On April 1, 20X4, Rojas purchased land by giving $100,000.docx
 
Problem 17-1 Dividends and Taxes [LO2]Dark Day, Inc., has declar.docx
Problem 17-1 Dividends and Taxes [LO2]Dark Day, Inc., has declar.docxProblem 17-1 Dividends and Taxes [LO2]Dark Day, Inc., has declar.docx
Problem 17-1 Dividends and Taxes [LO2]Dark Day, Inc., has declar.docx
 
Problem 1Problem 1 - Constant-Growth Common StockWhat is the value.docx
Problem 1Problem 1 - Constant-Growth Common StockWhat is the value.docxProblem 1Problem 1 - Constant-Growth Common StockWhat is the value.docx
Problem 1Problem 1 - Constant-Growth Common StockWhat is the value.docx
 
Problem 1Prescott, Inc., manufactures bookcases and uses an activi.docx
Problem 1Prescott, Inc., manufactures bookcases and uses an activi.docxProblem 1Prescott, Inc., manufactures bookcases and uses an activi.docx
Problem 1Prescott, Inc., manufactures bookcases and uses an activi.docx
 
Problem 1Preston Recliners manufactures leather recliners and uses.docx
Problem 1Preston Recliners manufactures leather recliners and uses.docxProblem 1Preston Recliners manufactures leather recliners and uses.docx
Problem 1Preston Recliners manufactures leather recliners and uses.docx
 
Problem 1Pro Forma Income Statement and Balance SheetBelow is the .docx
Problem 1Pro Forma Income Statement and Balance SheetBelow is the .docxProblem 1Pro Forma Income Statement and Balance SheetBelow is the .docx
Problem 1Pro Forma Income Statement and Balance SheetBelow is the .docx
 
Problem 2-1PROBLEM 2-1Solution Legend= Value given in problemGiven.docx
Problem 2-1PROBLEM 2-1Solution Legend= Value given in problemGiven.docxProblem 2-1PROBLEM 2-1Solution Legend= Value given in problemGiven.docx
Problem 2-1PROBLEM 2-1Solution Legend= Value given in problemGiven.docx
 
PROBLEM 14-6AProblem 14-6A Norwoods Borrowings1. Total amount of .docx
PROBLEM 14-6AProblem 14-6A Norwoods Borrowings1. Total amount of .docxPROBLEM 14-6AProblem 14-6A Norwoods Borrowings1. Total amount of .docx
PROBLEM 14-6AProblem 14-6A Norwoods Borrowings1. Total amount of .docx
 
Problem 13-3AThe stockholders’ equity accounts of Ashley Corpo.docx
Problem 13-3AThe stockholders’ equity accounts of Ashley Corpo.docxProblem 13-3AThe stockholders’ equity accounts of Ashley Corpo.docx
Problem 13-3AThe stockholders’ equity accounts of Ashley Corpo.docx
 
Problem 12-9AYour answer is partially correct.  Try again..docx
Problem 12-9AYour answer is partially correct.  Try again..docxProblem 12-9AYour answer is partially correct.  Try again..docx
Problem 12-9AYour answer is partially correct.  Try again..docx
 
Problem 1123456Xf122437455763715813910106Name DateTopic.docx
Problem 1123456Xf122437455763715813910106Name DateTopic.docxProblem 1123456Xf122437455763715813910106Name DateTopic.docx
Problem 1123456Xf122437455763715813910106Name DateTopic.docx
 
Problem 1. For the truss and loading shown below, calculate th.docx
Problem 1. For the truss and loading shown below, calculate th.docxProblem 1. For the truss and loading shown below, calculate th.docx
Problem 1. For the truss and loading shown below, calculate th.docx
 
Problem 1 (30 marks)Review enough information about .docx
Problem 1 (30 marks)Review enough information about .docxProblem 1 (30 marks)Review enough information about .docx
Problem 1 (30 marks)Review enough information about .docx
 
Problem 1 (10 points) Note that an eigenvector cannot be zero.docx
Problem 1 (10 points) Note that an eigenvector cannot be zero.docxProblem 1 (10 points) Note that an eigenvector cannot be zero.docx
Problem 1 (10 points) Note that an eigenvector cannot be zero.docx
 
Probation and Parole 3Running head Probation and Parole.docx
Probation and Parole 3Running head Probation and Parole.docxProbation and Parole 3Running head Probation and Parole.docx
Probation and Parole 3Running head Probation and Parole.docx
 
Problem 1(a) Complete the following ANOVA table based on 20 obs.docx
Problem 1(a) Complete the following ANOVA table based on 20 obs.docxProblem 1(a) Complete the following ANOVA table based on 20 obs.docx
Problem 1(a) Complete the following ANOVA table based on 20 obs.docx
 
Probe 140 SPrecipitation in inchesTemperature in F.docx
Probe 140 SPrecipitation in inchesTemperature in F.docxProbe 140 SPrecipitation in inchesTemperature in F.docx
Probe 140 SPrecipitation in inchesTemperature in F.docx
 

Recently uploaded

"Protectable subject matters, Protection in biotechnology, Protection of othe...
"Protectable subject matters, Protection in biotechnology, Protection of othe..."Protectable subject matters, Protection in biotechnology, Protection of othe...
"Protectable subject matters, Protection in biotechnology, Protection of othe...
SACHIN R KONDAGURI
 
Additional Benefits for Employee Website.pdf
Additional Benefits for Employee Website.pdfAdditional Benefits for Employee Website.pdf
Additional Benefits for Employee Website.pdf
joachimlavalley1
 
Overview on Edible Vaccine: Pros & Cons with Mechanism
Overview on Edible Vaccine: Pros & Cons with MechanismOverview on Edible Vaccine: Pros & Cons with Mechanism
Overview on Edible Vaccine: Pros & Cons with Mechanism
DeeptiGupta154
 
aaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaa
aaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaa
aaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaa
siemaillard
 
Unit 8 - Information and Communication Technology (Paper I).pdf
Unit 8 - Information and Communication Technology (Paper I).pdfUnit 8 - Information and Communication Technology (Paper I).pdf
Unit 8 - Information and Communication Technology (Paper I).pdf
Thiyagu K
 
Unit 2- Research Aptitude (UGC NET Paper I).pdf
Unit 2- Research Aptitude (UGC NET Paper I).pdfUnit 2- Research Aptitude (UGC NET Paper I).pdf
Unit 2- Research Aptitude (UGC NET Paper I).pdf
Thiyagu K
 
BÀI TẬP BỔ TRỢ TIẾNG ANH GLOBAL SUCCESS LỚP 3 - CẢ NĂM (CÓ FILE NGHE VÀ ĐÁP Á...
BÀI TẬP BỔ TRỢ TIẾNG ANH GLOBAL SUCCESS LỚP 3 - CẢ NĂM (CÓ FILE NGHE VÀ ĐÁP Á...BÀI TẬP BỔ TRỢ TIẾNG ANH GLOBAL SUCCESS LỚP 3 - CẢ NĂM (CÓ FILE NGHE VÀ ĐÁP Á...
BÀI TẬP BỔ TRỢ TIẾNG ANH GLOBAL SUCCESS LỚP 3 - CẢ NĂM (CÓ FILE NGHE VÀ ĐÁP Á...
Nguyen Thanh Tu Collection
 
The French Revolution Class 9 Study Material pdf free download
The French Revolution Class 9 Study Material pdf free downloadThe French Revolution Class 9 Study Material pdf free download
The French Revolution Class 9 Study Material pdf free download
Vivekanand Anglo Vedic Academy
 
Phrasal Verbs.XXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXX
Phrasal Verbs.XXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXPhrasal Verbs.XXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXX
Phrasal Verbs.XXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXX
MIRIAMSALINAS13
 
Welcome to TechSoup New Member Orientation and Q&A (May 2024).pdf
Welcome to TechSoup   New Member Orientation and Q&A (May 2024).pdfWelcome to TechSoup   New Member Orientation and Q&A (May 2024).pdf
Welcome to TechSoup New Member Orientation and Q&A (May 2024).pdf
TechSoup
 
Mule 4.6 & Java 17 Upgrade | MuleSoft Mysore Meetup #46
Mule 4.6 & Java 17 Upgrade | MuleSoft Mysore Meetup #46Mule 4.6 & Java 17 Upgrade | MuleSoft Mysore Meetup #46
Mule 4.6 & Java 17 Upgrade | MuleSoft Mysore Meetup #46
MysoreMuleSoftMeetup
 
The Challenger.pdf DNHS Official Publication
The Challenger.pdf DNHS Official PublicationThe Challenger.pdf DNHS Official Publication
The Challenger.pdf DNHS Official Publication
Delapenabediema
 
CLASS 11 CBSE B.St Project AIDS TO TRADE - INSURANCE
CLASS 11 CBSE B.St Project AIDS TO TRADE - INSURANCECLASS 11 CBSE B.St Project AIDS TO TRADE - INSURANCE
CLASS 11 CBSE B.St Project AIDS TO TRADE - INSURANCE
BhavyaRajput3
 
The geography of Taylor Swift - some ideas
The geography of Taylor Swift - some ideasThe geography of Taylor Swift - some ideas
The geography of Taylor Swift - some ideas
GeoBlogs
 
Language Across the Curriculm LAC B.Ed.
Language Across the  Curriculm LAC B.Ed.Language Across the  Curriculm LAC B.Ed.
Language Across the Curriculm LAC B.Ed.
Atul Kumar Singh
 
A Strategic Approach: GenAI in Education
A Strategic Approach: GenAI in EducationA Strategic Approach: GenAI in Education
A Strategic Approach: GenAI in Education
Peter Windle
 
Digital Tools and AI for Teaching Learning and Research
Digital Tools and AI for Teaching Learning and ResearchDigital Tools and AI for Teaching Learning and Research
Digital Tools and AI for Teaching Learning and Research
Vikramjit Singh
 
special B.ed 2nd year old paper_20240531.pdf
special B.ed 2nd year old paper_20240531.pdfspecial B.ed 2nd year old paper_20240531.pdf
special B.ed 2nd year old paper_20240531.pdf
Special education needs
 
Supporting (UKRI) OA monographs at Salford.pptx
Supporting (UKRI) OA monographs at Salford.pptxSupporting (UKRI) OA monographs at Salford.pptx
Supporting (UKRI) OA monographs at Salford.pptx
Jisc
 
Sha'Carri Richardson Presentation 202345
Sha'Carri Richardson Presentation 202345Sha'Carri Richardson Presentation 202345
Sha'Carri Richardson Presentation 202345
beazzy04
 

Recently uploaded (20)

"Protectable subject matters, Protection in biotechnology, Protection of othe...
"Protectable subject matters, Protection in biotechnology, Protection of othe..."Protectable subject matters, Protection in biotechnology, Protection of othe...
"Protectable subject matters, Protection in biotechnology, Protection of othe...
 
Additional Benefits for Employee Website.pdf
Additional Benefits for Employee Website.pdfAdditional Benefits for Employee Website.pdf
Additional Benefits for Employee Website.pdf
 
Overview on Edible Vaccine: Pros & Cons with Mechanism
Overview on Edible Vaccine: Pros & Cons with MechanismOverview on Edible Vaccine: Pros & Cons with Mechanism
Overview on Edible Vaccine: Pros & Cons with Mechanism
 
aaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaa
aaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaa
aaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaaa
 
Unit 8 - Information and Communication Technology (Paper I).pdf
Unit 8 - Information and Communication Technology (Paper I).pdfUnit 8 - Information and Communication Technology (Paper I).pdf
Unit 8 - Information and Communication Technology (Paper I).pdf
 
Unit 2- Research Aptitude (UGC NET Paper I).pdf
Unit 2- Research Aptitude (UGC NET Paper I).pdfUnit 2- Research Aptitude (UGC NET Paper I).pdf
Unit 2- Research Aptitude (UGC NET Paper I).pdf
 
BÀI TẬP BỔ TRỢ TIẾNG ANH GLOBAL SUCCESS LỚP 3 - CẢ NĂM (CÓ FILE NGHE VÀ ĐÁP Á...
BÀI TẬP BỔ TRỢ TIẾNG ANH GLOBAL SUCCESS LỚP 3 - CẢ NĂM (CÓ FILE NGHE VÀ ĐÁP Á...BÀI TẬP BỔ TRỢ TIẾNG ANH GLOBAL SUCCESS LỚP 3 - CẢ NĂM (CÓ FILE NGHE VÀ ĐÁP Á...
BÀI TẬP BỔ TRỢ TIẾNG ANH GLOBAL SUCCESS LỚP 3 - CẢ NĂM (CÓ FILE NGHE VÀ ĐÁP Á...
 
The French Revolution Class 9 Study Material pdf free download
The French Revolution Class 9 Study Material pdf free downloadThe French Revolution Class 9 Study Material pdf free download
The French Revolution Class 9 Study Material pdf free download
 
Phrasal Verbs.XXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXX
Phrasal Verbs.XXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXPhrasal Verbs.XXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXX
Phrasal Verbs.XXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXX
 
Welcome to TechSoup New Member Orientation and Q&A (May 2024).pdf
Welcome to TechSoup   New Member Orientation and Q&A (May 2024).pdfWelcome to TechSoup   New Member Orientation and Q&A (May 2024).pdf
Welcome to TechSoup New Member Orientation and Q&A (May 2024).pdf
 
Mule 4.6 & Java 17 Upgrade | MuleSoft Mysore Meetup #46
Mule 4.6 & Java 17 Upgrade | MuleSoft Mysore Meetup #46Mule 4.6 & Java 17 Upgrade | MuleSoft Mysore Meetup #46
Mule 4.6 & Java 17 Upgrade | MuleSoft Mysore Meetup #46
 
The Challenger.pdf DNHS Official Publication
The Challenger.pdf DNHS Official PublicationThe Challenger.pdf DNHS Official Publication
The Challenger.pdf DNHS Official Publication
 
CLASS 11 CBSE B.St Project AIDS TO TRADE - INSURANCE
CLASS 11 CBSE B.St Project AIDS TO TRADE - INSURANCECLASS 11 CBSE B.St Project AIDS TO TRADE - INSURANCE
CLASS 11 CBSE B.St Project AIDS TO TRADE - INSURANCE
 
The geography of Taylor Swift - some ideas
The geography of Taylor Swift - some ideasThe geography of Taylor Swift - some ideas
The geography of Taylor Swift - some ideas
 
Language Across the Curriculm LAC B.Ed.
Language Across the  Curriculm LAC B.Ed.Language Across the  Curriculm LAC B.Ed.
Language Across the Curriculm LAC B.Ed.
 
A Strategic Approach: GenAI in Education
A Strategic Approach: GenAI in EducationA Strategic Approach: GenAI in Education
A Strategic Approach: GenAI in Education
 
Digital Tools and AI for Teaching Learning and Research
Digital Tools and AI for Teaching Learning and ResearchDigital Tools and AI for Teaching Learning and Research
Digital Tools and AI for Teaching Learning and Research
 
special B.ed 2nd year old paper_20240531.pdf
special B.ed 2nd year old paper_20240531.pdfspecial B.ed 2nd year old paper_20240531.pdf
special B.ed 2nd year old paper_20240531.pdf
 
Supporting (UKRI) OA monographs at Salford.pptx
Supporting (UKRI) OA monographs at Salford.pptxSupporting (UKRI) OA monographs at Salford.pptx
Supporting (UKRI) OA monographs at Salford.pptx
 
Sha'Carri Richardson Presentation 202345
Sha'Carri Richardson Presentation 202345Sha'Carri Richardson Presentation 202345
Sha'Carri Richardson Presentation 202345
 

Bending the Arc of North American Psychologists’ Moral Univers

  • 1. Bending the Arc of North American Psychologists’ Moral Universe Toward Communicative Ethics and Social Justice Richard T. G. Walsh Wilfrid Laurier University Social contextual and social justice perspectives on North American psychologists’ conceptions of ethical ideals and prescribed practices show that interpersonal, organi- zational-institutional, and sociopolitical systems are dimly represented on our moral landscape. In this critical review I first examine conceptions of ethical decision-making from cognitive and interpersonal angles, noting the operation of nonrational phenomena and conversational processes and promoting a communicative conception of ethical decision-making. Next, I consider how the discourse on the concepts and practice of ethics addresses both the social conditions of our employment and the challenges of maintaining professional-personal boundaries on ethical conduct. Lastly, I assess the ways in which psychologists discuss ethical issues that arise from our espoused commitments to enhancing human welfare, responsibility to society, and social justice. I argue that certain historical trends in psychology’s culture reduce our moral vision of practicing the principle of justice to social reforms that sustain
  • 2. the status quo. I conclude by questioning how we can shift the transit of our ethical discourse and practice toward communicative ethics and social justice. Keywords: ethical decision-making, Habermas, communicative ethics, organizational-institutional influences, social justice It seems likely that most North American (i.e., Canadian and U.S.) colleagues believe that we psychologists behave ethically in our re- search, educational, professional, and commu- nity endeavors despite the embarrassment to our discipline of some psychologists’ ethical mal- feasance, such as participation in torture (see Teo, 2015a). But taking ethical responsibilities for granted could lead to their marginalization and invoking them chiefly when a possible so- ciopolitical transgression, professional ethical dilemma, or institutional review of a dubious research project occurs. Instead of central to our identity as scientific and professional psycholo- gists, ethics can seem peripheral to our worka- day worlds (Prilleltensky, Rossiter, & Walsh- Bowers, 1996), reducible to a recitation of standards that demand adherence. A different view is that all aspects of our vocation are pro- foundly moral, ethical, and social. That is, princi- ples and practices of ethics, which are historical constructions, are enacted in the context of in- terpersonal, organizational-institutional, and so- cietal systems and particular cultural traditions. Accordingly, our principles and standards for ethical conduct, as well as our conduct itself,
  • 3. should reflect critical consciousness of the so- cial-contextual phenomena saturating ethics. In this spirit, and from my perspective as a Canadian contributor to the literature in critical psychology (Teo, 2015b) and as a local political activist, I pose two principal questions for dis- cussion: (a) How adequately do our codes of ethics account for the nature of the relationship between us and those whom we serve? (b) How might the current interest in social justice ex- pressed by some psychologists inform a moral imperative that could be the basis for the ethical principle of responsibility to society specifically and for a reconceived ethical framework for psychologists generally? The latter question is relevant to psychologists’ relationship with so- cial justice (e.g., Vasquez, 2011; Walsh & Go- I presented an earlier version of this article at the meeting of the Canadian Psychological Association, Vancouver, BC, Canada (June, 2014). I am grateful to Ravi Gokani for his helpful comments. Correspondence concerning this article should be ad- dressed to Richard T. G. Walsh, Department of Psychology, Wilfrid Laurier University, Waterloo, ON, Canada N2L 3C5. E-mail: [email protected] T hi s do cu m
  • 8. y. Journal of Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology © 2015 American Psychological Association 2015, Vol. 35, No. 2, 90 –102 1068-8471/15/$12.00 http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/teo0000011 90 mailto:[email protected] http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/teo0000011 kani, 2014). In discussing these questions I as- sess the social contextual qualities of the conceptions and practices described in the dis- course on the American Psychological Associ- ation’s Code of Ethics (American Psychological Association, 2010) (hereinafter, the APA Code) and the Canadian Psychological Association’s Code of Ethics (Canadian Psychological Asso- ciation, 2000) (hereinafter, the CPA Code). A Social Contextual Review of Ethics Codes The discourse on the codes suggests that so- cial contextual aspects of ethical thought and practice can be significant. These aspects in- clude cognitive and interpersonal perspectives on ethical decision-making, the social condi- tions of psychologists’ employment, and issues of responsibility to society and social justice, which roughly correspond to interpersonal, or- ganizational-institutional, and societal levels of
  • 9. social analysis, respectively. Critical Perspectives on Ethical Decision-Making The literature stipulates that psychologists should know how and when to competently apply a model of decision-making to an ethical dilemma confronting them. Although models of ethical decision-making emanate from distinct philosophical roots—principled (deontologi- cal), utilitarian (consequentialist), and relational (Cottone, 2011)—the APA and CPA Codes converge in their respective prescriptions for a problem-solving approach to ethical decision- making that entails a psychologist discerning the most ethically appropriate course of action in a given situation. Thus, ethical decision- making proceeds from “what a person of good character (aware of the virtues, values and fun- damental principles of the discipline), with sen- sitivity to the probable impact on the specific other involved persons, would choose to do” (Pettifor, 1996, p. 5). A possible link to affirm- ing social justice rests in “a sociocultural frame- work for ethical decision making” (Kakkad, 2005, p. 297), but this perspective is not wide- spread in the literature. Although the APA Code does not specify a model of ethical decision-making, extant mod- els (e.g., Kitchener & Kitchener, 2011) gener- ally complement the problem-solving model prescribed by the CPA Code. In addition, both Codes note the value of collegial and supervi-
  • 10. sory consultation for decision-making, and Fisher’s (2013) model prescribes dialogue with those impacted by the decision. In some con- trast, a social-constructivist model stresses the interpersonal nature of ethical decision-making itself (Cottone, 2011), while an ethic of care (Truscott & Crook, 2013) and a approach known as communicative ethics (Rossiter, Walsh-Bowers, & Prilleltensky, 2002) hold that sound ethical decision-making results from trustworthy communication with peers, as I ex- plain subsequently. Yet the codes appear to assume that ethical decision-making is the re- sponsibility of a persistently rational individual engaging in logical problem-solving, a doubtful assumption that flows from the individualistic moral philosophies undergirding the codes (Walsh, 2015). Nonrational cognitive processes. The lit- erature on nonrational cognitive processes sug- gests that the recommended procedure for eth- ical decision-making might be flawed psychologically. For example, the APA Code suggests that psychologists’ primary ethical ob- ligation is to maintain our competence. How- ever, “research in health care, education, and multicultural and social psychology raise[s] se- rious doubts about psychologists’ capacity for consistently accurate self-assessments of com- petence” (Johnson, Barnett, Elman, Forrest, & Kaslow, 2012, p. 557). If “maintaining compe- tence beyond initial credentialing continues to mean that psychologists rely on self-assessment and voluntary consultation with colleagues if problems arise” (Johnson et al., 2012, p. 559),
  • 11. this disposition is prone to self-serving bias. In fact, confirmation biases, among other nonra- tional phenomena, also impair reasoning. Fol- lowing Kahneman’s (2003) notion of bounded rationality and distinction between automatic intuition and deliberate reason, effective deci- sion-making incorporates intuitive-emotional processes more than solely rational ones. Con- sequently, ethical reasoning does not necessar- ily lead to ethical conduct, because unrecog- nized “nonrational processes can compromise accurate self-reflection” (Rogerson, Gottlieb, Handelsman, Knapp, & Younggren, 2011, p. 619). Accordingly, we might make wiser ethical decisions if we integrated “emotional sensitiv- 91BENDING THE ARC T hi s do cu m en t is co py ri
  • 15. us er an d is no t to be di ss em in at ed br oa dl y. ity, personal values, contextual forces, and in- tuitive responses with normative rational anal- ysis nonrational with rational factors” (Rogerson et al., p. 622), while attempting to prevent cognitive distortions.
  • 16. One interpretation of this cognitive analysis is that if we ethical actors monitor the opera- tions of nonrational cognitive phenomena, then our capacity as reasoning individuals is af- firmed. But another interpretation is that recog- nition of nonrational processes is insufficient for ethical decision-making. Moreover, sources of social influence also are activated in the process of ethical decision-making. They in- clude the qualities of the ethical situation itself; the roles of significant others (e.g., supervisors, peers, the recipients of our activities); the cul- ture and social climate of organizations or in- stitutions with which a psychologist is affili- ated; and societal influences stemming from sociopolitical, socioeconomic, and technologi- cal structures and ideologies (Malloy & Hadji- stravopoulos, 1998). Ethical decision-making, therefore, entails much more than a presumed rational judgment emanating from an advanced level of moral consciousness. In sum, given the potential for cognitive distortions and covert social influences, the notion of an autonomous, reasoning, and virtuous psychologist who re- calls and applies the correct ethical principle or standard in a kind of cognitive decision-tree does not represent ethical decision-making re- alistically. Rather, sound ethical decision- making arguably depends upon a dialogical pro- cess of understanding the applicability of ethical principles and corresponding standards to the situation, for which consultation with trustworthy colleagues is indispensable. Interpersonal processes. Communication
  • 17. difficulties in our work as psychologists often can have ramifications for ethical decision- making. But attending to the discursive pro- cesses as well as the content of ethics conceiv- ably could enrich understanding our moral responsibilities in our professional relation- ships. For example, a dialogical process of ne- gotiating conversational differences ideally oc- curs in counseling or psychotherapy, shaped in part by differentials of social power between the parties, the psychologist’s expertise and ethical responsiveness, and the client’s knowledge, in- tentions, and preferences (Strong & Sutherland, 2007). When psychologists strive to balance their perspective with clients’ perspectives, pro- cessual sensitivity to a given conversation’s quality embodies the ethical principle of re- spect. Although the ethics discourse tends to mar- ginalize conversational processes in decision- making, studies on clinicians’ experiences with ethics indicate that ethical decision-making is more socially contextualized than first meets the eye (Rossiter et al., 2002). It seems wiser, there- fore, to regard ethical decision-making as a di- alogical process of coconstruction with influen- tial others, including the recipients of a psychologist’s activities, rather than the product of a solitary ethical actor. According to Cot- tone’s (2011) social constructivist approach, in- stead of an individual’s wholly internal deci- sion, ethical decision-making can entail up to three interpersonal steps: consensualizing, ne- gotiating, and arbitrating. In this approach, re-
  • 18. solving an ethical dilemma becomes an interac- tive process of reflection and consensus, attained through open discussion with trustwor- thy colleagues and supervisors concerning the balance between ethical principles and specific standards appropriate to a particular situation. Yet, such dialogues only can provide contest- able ethical knowledge, not certainties, about ethical courses of action. [See Shotter (2005) for another constructivist approach to dialogue and ethics.] Some authors, drawing from critical social philosophy, understand this dialogical approach as communicative ethics (Rossiter et al., 2002). In the interests of transforming societies and drawing from his concept of “the lifeworld” (an idealized social context of moral values, demo- cratic principles, ethics, and consensus), Haber- mas (1981/1983) promotes the emancipatory character of clear and undistorted communica- tion, which he terms an ideal speech situation. Such communication requires that all parties in the relationship should experience four condi- tions: symmetrical power, sincerity, disclosure of truth, and an inclination to express what is morally right. Crucially, Habermas proposes fundamental changes to society’s socioeco- nomic conditions to lay the foundations for ideal speech to occur. But some scholars are wary that if undistorted communication is prac- ticed as an abstract dialogue, it could ignore power relations embedded in social categories 92 WALSH
  • 23. in at ed br oa dl y. (e.g., ethnocultural status, gender, class; Mee- han, 1995). From my perspective, then, ethical decision- making is better understood as a social process that partly is shaped by experience and consul- tation with other psychologists and profession- als as well as the recipients of our activities, rather than the activity of an autonomous rea- soning psychologist. Accordingly, discerning appropriate ethical conduct might best occur, if professionals experience a safe space such as small-group discussions with trustworthy peers, in which to discuss their ethical concerns with- out fear of judgment and surveillance by their supervisors (Rossiter et al., 2002). However, such an opportunity would require that supervi- sors and administrators foster an organizational climate conducive to the secure discussion of complex ethical situations without supervisory prejudicial judgment. Although ethics codes per se “cannot create safe spaces for the discussion of ethics within organizations” (Pettifor, 1998,
  • 24. p. 236), the crucial concern remains how we are to respond to “organizational or systemic pres- sures [that] may influence [our] capacity to im- plement ethical decisions” (Pettifor, 1998, p. 234). The Social Conditions of Psychologists’ Vocation The social conditions of our vocation as psy- chologists also can impinge upon our ethical conceptions and practices. Two such contextual issues are: organizational and institutional influ- ences in places of work, and the challenge of maintaining professional-personal boundaries. Organizational and institutional influences. Although there has been much discussion on ethical issues involving police and military psy- chology in recent years (e.g., Kennedy, 2011; Teo, 2015a), the contextual realities that we face when the work required within an organi- zation or institution impacts ethical decision- making and conduct has received rather less attention. The APA Code covers organizational demands in Standard 1.03, while the CPA Code addresses organizational influences in several of its standards. Yet, beyond police and military contexts, the social conditions of scientific and professional psychologists’ employment might adversely affect our ethical judgment and the quality of ethical relations that we maintain with the recipients of our scientific or professional activities. The reality is that evidently in many organizations, agencies, or institutions, particu-
  • 25. larly since the incursion of neoliberal austerity programs, psychologists and other professional staff have little time in which to reflect upon and discuss ethical issues in safe, constructive dia- logue that facilitates understanding the applica- tion of ethical principles and standards in par- ticular circumstances (Rossiter et al., 2002). Instead, in a climate of “do more with less,” staff must serve more clients for shorter periods of time. In such contexts discussing ambiguous ethical matters, which often induce anxiety, has become a luxury. Relatedly, the nature of supervisory relation- ships can affect ethical deliberations negatively (Rossiter et al., 2002). We psychologists might be anxious about supervisors judging us as pro- fessionally inadequate, if we acknowledge eth- ical uncertainty or misgivings about ethical con- duct in a given situation, as if we should already know the answers to ethical questions. Thus, a virtual taboo against admitting that often we do not know how to behave ethically can operate. Supervisors’ surveillance to induce supervisees’ compliance also might militate against safe, constructive dialogue (Rossiter et al., 2002). In short, the potential to actualize our moral re- sponsibilities is embedded in power relations with supervisors. But the ethical discourse largely suggests that we engage in ethical prob- lem-solving as if it were an abstract process transcending the workaday realities of social entanglements in organizations and institutions, such as supervisor-staff relations. But some contend that accounting for the effect of work contexts on ethical decision-making is essential
  • 26. for ethical conduct ( Vergés, 2010). The inadequacy of the ethical discourse con- cerning how to deal with diverse working con- ditions is evident in the situation of psycholo- gists who engage in humanitarian work in cultural settings different from their own (Aubé, 2011). Typically, they experience stressful local cultural realities, such as political and military pressure on their nongovernmental organiza- tion. The ethical challenges include the domi- nant-subordinate relationship between service providers and recipients, exacerbated by post- colonial issues; cultural differences in ethical standards, for instance, in the protection of con- fidentiality and consent; and extremely limited 93BENDING THE ARC T hi s do cu m en t is co py ri
  • 30. us er an d is no t to be di ss em in at ed br oa dl y. ethical resources. Ethical ambiguities appar- ently abound in such humanitarian work, just as they might within the permeable boundaries between our professional and personal lives.
  • 31. Professional-personal boundary maintenance. Psychologists’ professional and personal lives often intersect, which can present ethical prob- lems. By practicing moral discernment, as Pipes, Holstein, and Aguirre (2005) claimed, we can recognize when such boundaries are more or less fused or are distinct. One criterion for moral discernment is the perceived risk to both the recipients of our activities and to the disci- pline, while a mitigating factor is the social context of a given ethical situation. Pipes et al. held, as the CPA Code does, that ethical con- duct should reflect adherence to the underlying principles as well as to standards. The authors recommended that the APA Code emulate the CPA Code’s direction that we indicate whether we are speaking publicly as a professional or a private citizen. Pipes et al. (2005) also sug- gested that we apply the APA Code’s aspira- tional principles to our personal lives, given the permeable nature of personal-professional boundaries. But, from a critical perspective, the process of moral discernment concerning these boundaries likely is as influenced by nonrational cognitive processes, interpersonal relations, and organizational-institutional in- fluences as ethical decision-making in general seems to be. Allowing a role for personal conscience, the CPA Code accepts the potential for reciprocal influence between the personal and the pro- fessional. In contrast, the APA Code exempts personal activities on our own time from its purview. Yet the virtue ethics and feminist-
  • 32. relational ethical perspectives (Walsh, 2015) as- sume that our personal characteristics do influ- ence our conduct (as in “the personal is the political”) and that matters of social justice re- quire our personal commitment. But, some psy- chologists insist, public perceptions of our con- duct during personal time might adversely affect professional relationships with clientele. For instance, involvement in contentious polit- ical issues might lead to abusing the power of our social position inadvertently and harming our professional role and others’ reputations. Thus, “Taking a public position on a controver- sial issue might call into [our] ability to be objective and nonjudgmental” unless our asso- ciation has taken a stance on the issue (Haeny, 2014, p. 269). This rationale implies, as I ex- plain below, regression to the mean, so to speak, of social reform. Overall, the codes and the literature contain little discussion of ethical ambiguities inherent in professional-personal boundaries. Instead, the discourse seems preoccupied with prevent- ing blemishes to the image of an autonomous psychologist practicing scientific problem- solving that we strive to manage in society. This inclination, however, might contribute to the difficulties we have had in practicing ethical responsibility to society beyond social reform. Ethical Relationship With Society Since World War Two (Capshew, 1999; Her- man, 1995), the discipline has committed itself
  • 33. to advance both psychological knowledge and human welfare. From the societal level of anal- ysis, I assess in this section how the ethical discourse addresses the ethical principle of re- sponsibility to society and the similar concepts of social responsibility and social justice. Actu- alizing a moral imperative, grounded in socio- political consciousness (Prilleltensky & Walsh- Bowers, 1993), might inspire a reconceived ethic of responsibility to society. The codes’ orientations. Not surprisingly, the codes share a common inclination in their respective depictions of psychologists’ ethical obligations to promote the well-being of indi- viduals and society and to prevent infringement of human rights. For instance, the APA Ethics Code “indicate[s] that psychologists are com- mitted to creating, communicating, and apply- ing psychological knowledge in order to benefit individuals and society and facilitate the reso- lution of global challenges” (Swim et al., 2011, p. 246). However, APA introduced this princi- ple, then known as “Social Responsibility,” in the previous 1992 Code, but the adjective “so- cial” since has disappeared. In the 2002 edition, the principle of “Justice,” connoting fairness and equity, encompasses psychologists’ respon- sibilities to society. In the CPA Code social justice “refers to fairness and equity in the allocation of, impact of, and access to psychological services” (Truscott & Crook, 2013, p. 170), as exempli- fied by the Values Statement for Principle I: Respect for the Dignity of Persons. Yet the
  • 38. ss em in at ed br oa dl y. concept of social justice transcends concern simply with “the particular ethical obligations owed to individuals arising out of professional relationships . . . to include obligations owed to individuals collectively . . . [and] society in general” (Truscott & Crook, 2013, p. 176). An- other definition of social justice is “work[ing] for the common good by transforming the social organizations and processes that contribute to power inequalities, oppression, and marginal- ization” (Vasquez, 2011, p. 76). Social justice can be linked with civic virtue, which is synon- ymous with “general welfare” and “public in- terest” and implies responsibility to one’s pro- fessional society as well as civil society. In my view, however, social justice is better understood concretely as a continuum of interventions that range in their effects from reform (i.e., adjust- ments to a social system) to transformation (i.e., fundamental changes in the substance of a sys-
  • 39. tem or even its demise), even revolution, non- violent or not (Walsh & Gokani, 2014). The concept of social responsibility refers to at- tempts to effect social justice by improving societal systems to benefit everyone equitably. The codes differ from each other in how they address our potential involvement as psycholo- gists with issues of justice and how we may ethically engage with society to contribute to societal improvement. Although APA does not incorporate social justice explicitly in its Ethics Code, the concept is identified as a core value in the vision statement of APA’s strategic plan and the association has become more outspoken in its political advocacy (Vasquez, 2011). The CPA Code’s Values Statement for Prin- ciple IV: Responsibility to Society (CPA, 2000) seems at first to be concerned with ensuring that we psychologists treat extant social structures with respect and comport ourselves in an “even- tempered” manner. Then the code states that if social systems obstruct the actualization of the code’s four principles, “psychologists involved have a responsibility to speak out in a manner consistent with the principles of this Code, and advocate for appropriate change to occur as quickly as possible” (CPA, 2000). This Values Statement stresses that we are expected to chal- lenge extant social systems and societal prac- tices but in a respectful and collaborative man- ner. However, as progressive as this statement might seem to traditional psychologists, any code of psychological ethics founded in indi-
  • 40. vidual-centered moral philosophies (Walsh, 2015) has difficulty embracing the transforma- tional potential of social justice, because the duty to practice social justice emanates from “relational [and communitarian] ethics, which motivate us to act out of concern for others and consideration of social contexts” (Truscott & Crook, 2013, p. 170). Our ethical codes and discourse would be enriched, some argue, if the codes incorporated relational and communitar- ian perspectives, which assume human interde- pendence (Johnson et al., 2012). Both codes’ foundational principles do sug- gest that we have an ethical obligation to con- tribute to bettering society and protecting hu- man rights, such as advocating for progressive social change. In fact, the CPA Code’s Principle IV: Responsibility to Society contains standards that encourage us, as in Standard IV. Six for example, to “Participate in the process of criti- cal self-evaluation of the discipline’s place in society, and in the development and implemen- tation of structures and procedures that help the discipline to contribute to beneficial societal functioning and changes” (CPA, 2000). More- over, three of the APA Code’s principles— fidelity and responsibility, integrity, and jus- tice— contain within them expectations for psychologists’ making public statements about matters of social policy. The code’s Standards 2.01, 2.06, and 3.04 urge psychologists to be cautious and clear in drawing inferences about social applications from psychological findings. However, sufficient empirical evidence fre- quently is lacking on a particular social issue,
  • 41. yet societal exigencies seem to demand an au- thoritative response from us. The consensus is that when taking a public stance on matters where empirical support is insufficient, we should distinguish between our personal opin- ions and values and our professional, scientific claims (Martel, 2009). Nevertheless, typical concerns are that direct participation in the work of social justice and political activism could politicize the discipline, confuse our formal roles, and harm the discipline’s scientific cred- ibility (Kakkad, 2005). Impediments to justice. One could argue that psychologists “who are truly respectful and caring of others cannot be blind to social injus- tice” (Pettifor, 1996, p. 8). But throughout our discipline’s history, when we have responded to social injustices, our interventions have been 95BENDING THE ARC T hi s do cu m en t is co
  • 46. Baydala, 2014), which I assert, represents a visual and behavioral impairment in social mo- rality. Furthermore, ethical discourse in the dis- cipline continues to counsel us to maintain po- litically moderate professional identities (Haeny, 2014; Kakkad, 2005). If this is our historical and current reality and self-image, what could move us to respond to calls to social justice, which often are immoderate, even rad- ical, in their implications? When Martin Luther King, Jr. (1968) ad- dressed psychologists in a 1967 summer of Af- rican American rebellions against systemic rac- ism, he urged us not to contribute to the psychological adjustment of citizens, because, he said, individuals and society should never be adjusted to oppressive conditions. Rather, he challenged us to foster “creative maladjust- ment,” that is, to transform society into relation- ships of justice. Answering King’s denunciation of promoting adaptation and adjustment and his annunciation of overturning the societal status quo demands that we confront the impediments in our discipline to enacting social justice be- yond the inadequacies of our ethics codes. But we have not practiced his exhortation, largely because we have little history of contributing to social change that strengthens ecological- environmental, economic, and social justice (Walsh & Gokani, 2014). Instead, we have ig- nored our discipline’s inherent sociopolitical limitations yet have contributed to various types of social reform, if not directly, then indirectly (Walsh et al., 2014). Aspirations for enacting social justice notwithstanding (e.g., Vasquez,
  • 47. 2011, 2012), psychology has been and remains an administrative tool for society’s power bro- kers, that is, our activities have and continue to enhance the efficacy of society’s economic, ed- ucational, and governmental institutions (Dan- ziger, 1979). The interrelated disciplinary, institutional, sociopolitical, and personal aspects of our tra- ditional educational, investigative, and profes- sional endeavors have mitigated our attempts to address social injustice in society systematically and systemically. Consequently, any attempts to effect social justice require, first and foremost, that we strive to resolve the contradictions in our own practices. Given that many authors have identified psychology as an individualistic science (e.g., Sarason, 1981), a status that hin- ders the enactment of social responsibility and social justice, I focus on other impediments: psychology as a natural science, its reformist orientation, our personal distance from oppres- sion, and our social contract with society. A natural science. Historically, North American psychology has been fixed in a natu- ral-science orbit that concentrates on predicting, controlling, and theorizing individuals’ behav- ior and mental processes, to the virtual exclu- sion of a human-science conception that con- centrates on understanding and interpreting contextualized experience of individuals and their cultures (Walsh et al., 2014). Our lengthy training in the natural-science orientation in- clines us to segregate subjective from objective
  • 48. judgment, as if the facts that we construct exist independently of our interpretations of observa- tions. In the CPA Code’s Principle III: Integrity of Relationships, for instance, this objectivism is apparent in four standards pertaining to ob- jectivity, generally unqualified. The convention in natural-science psychol- ogy also has been that in our formal relationship with society we are duty bound as objective scientists to uphold the Humean distinction be- tween facts and values (e.g., Kendler, 2008); that is, “empirical data are and should be value- free” (Martel, 2009, p. 104). In my view, the relationship between putative scientific facts and social values is key to understanding what the ethical considerations might be when we address social issues. The traditional position is that if we engage in social action as individuals, our stances of social-advocacy risk being per- ceived as expressions of bias, which weakens our individual credibility and stains the disci- pline’s reputation (Haeny, 2014; Kendler, 2008; Truscott & Crook, 2013). An alternative view is that ethical values and practices, as well as scientific ones, are enacted in a cultural- historical context of social roles and relation- ships that are embedded in societal ideologies, structures, and institutions. From this perspec- tive, then, our moral task is to recognize and address how social realities influence our val- ues, concepts, and practices. Yet, our scientific and professional training has socialized us to relate to the persons we study and serve from a reputedly value-free standpoint of neutral ob- jectivity, even as we might avoid reflecting on
  • 49. our biases, such as our longstanding neglect of social class (Walsh & Gokani, 2014). As a 96 WALSH T hi s do cu m en t is co py ri gh te d by th e A m er
  • 53. di ss em in at ed br oa dl y. consequence, in our formal relationships we convey personal interests, prejudices, and so- ciopolitical biases that are sustained by our priv- ileged socioeconomic status as members of the establishment. In light of this history, actualiz- ing overarching ethical values of respecting hu- man dignity and protecting human rights might be compromised at least to some extent, when we enter the public domain of social issues laden with such baggage. A reformist bent. Particularly in the U.S. A., psychology originated within a nineteenth- century social order characterized by free- market capitalism and global imperialism. When massive urbanization occurred, business, industry, and government leaders, aided by sci- entists and the new class of professionals, in-
  • 54. cluding psychologists, aimed to administer the masses effectively by rationalizing society (Danziger, 1979). Social engineering to ensure that citizens adapted to their station in life be- came psychology’s applied mission, which is reflected in the notion of social adjustment (Na- poli, 1981). Historically, then, we psychologists have been much more likely to engage in social reform and thereby to sustain the societal status quo (Herman, 1995) than in any interventions that could merit the term transformative. More- over, self-servingly we have regarded the prog- ress and advancement of our science and pro- fession as a barometer of democracy and the health of society at large (Capshew, 1999). Within the discipline’s tradition of social re- form the consensus is that we have a responsi- bility to contribute (conventional) psychologi- cal research on the particular social issues under scrutiny and to educate the public about the likely outcomes of one course of action versus another action. Yet, there are few precedents for psycholo- gists who take political stances, because few of us study political action, even fewer engage directly in it, and we rarely consider anarchistic and revolutionary political options (Walsh & Gokani, 2014). Moreover, the discipline shows little interest in fostering an ethical obligation of social responsibility to contribute to changing social systems so that all in a given society benefit. Instead, overtly or not, for generations we have pledged allegiance to the flag of evolv- ing capitalism, as APA presidential addresses show (Sarason, 1981). We have absorbed capi-
  • 55. talist discourse so well and thereby distanced ourselves from its destructive nature that some of us speak of social support as “social capital” and community interventions as “social entre- preneurship” apparently without irony; our cri- terion of value evidently reflects the ideology of neoliberal capitalism (see Sugarman, 2015). Overall, then, since the postwar era psychol- ogists have made no essential distinction among service to the state, employment by the govern- ment, and social responsibility for the science and profession (Herman, 1995). Rather, indi- rectly or directly in our psychologized societies, we have occupied the privileged position of plausibly explaining individuals to themselves. Thus, as citizens, “Our feelings, beliefs, desires, hopes and fears are suffused with the descrip- tions, injunctions, and evaluations of those [for example, psychologists] who claim to know more about what is good for us than we do ourselves” (Rose, 1996, p. 224). Personal distance from oppressive social conditions. The codes have insufficiently ad- dressed the larger social context in which ethi- cal issues and dilemmas occur, such as the oppressive societal conditions of poverty, rac- ism, sexism, and heterosexism that permeate all layers of social relations. Such distancing is manifest, for instance, in the APA Code in which universal moral duties are understood ideally and abstracted from societal conditions. Thus, autonomy refers to psychologists foster- ing the right to self-determination of those
  • 56. whom we study, teach, treat, counsel, or con- sult; beneficence and nonmaleficence mean nur- turing well-being and doing no harm to those with whom we engage; fidelity refers to being trustworthy in all our scientific and professional relations; and justice refers to acting with fair- ness and equity. Furthermore, the fact that, as a group, psy- chologists operate from positions of substantial socioeconomic privilege can inhibit our re- sponding effectively to the diverse social loca- tions of the individuals, groups, organizations, and communities with whom we work (Walsh & Gokani, 2014). Although many of us can be subjected to oppressive experiences due to our locations in intersecting social categories, our socioeconomic status as scientist-professionals distances us from understanding and relating with the recipients of our psychological activi- ties in a way that appreciates how societal con- ditions of oppression might affect them directly 97BENDING THE ARC T hi s do cu m en t
  • 61. and indirectly. The potential disparities between our social locations and those of the recipients of our activities can impede our capacities for ethical decision-making (Lerman & Porter, 1990). Social contract with society. The codes’ disposition of responsibility to society assumes, explicitly or not, an “overriding ethic of a social contract” between psychologists and society (Sinclair, 1998, p. 168). The current CPA Code, for example, expanded “its [initial] scope be- yond a narrow individualistic world view” through the notion of a social contract that “ob- ligates psychologists to place the public interest above self-interest” (Pettifor, 1998, p. 232, em- phasis added). According to this principle, we make a commitment to contribute to human welfare in return for receiving professional sta- tus and autonomy in society. However, the likelihood that this quid pro quo obligates us to sustain extant social institu- tions, even if attempting to improve them to benefit all, is evident in the following depiction of the social contract: “In order to honor and sustain this interdependence a professional code of ethics ought not contain anything that is discordant with the values of society at large” (Truscott & Crook, 2013, p. 3). Moreover, what is meant by the public interest and what activ- ities might be included within the domain of privileging societal and individual welfare above our own interests have remained unde-
  • 62. fined. In addition, the politically limited scope of this social contract is evident in CPA Stan- dard IV.10 in which we are encouraged to “[c]ontribute to the general welfare of society (e.g., improving accessibility of services, re- gardless of ability to pay).” This example rep- resents charity not justice. Furthermore, if “psy- chology uses ethical codes to support the political professionalization strategies of the discipline” and these “strategies help to market the discipline and to ensure public support for science and practice” (Pettifor, 1996, p. 2), as Dunbar’s (1998) historical analysis of the CPA Code attested, then any suggestion that altruism is psychologists’ primary motivation for engag- ing in a social contract is misleading. Realisti- cally, we value our own interests at least as much as contributing to societal welfare, as our history has shown (Walsh et al., 2014). Furthermore, maintaining personal-profes- sional boundaries that do not tarnish public per- ception of psychologists’ credentialed status is the disciplinary norm (Haeny, 2014), which the codes underscore. Despite the CPA Code’s di- rection, for instance, that we are to privilege the welfare of society and individuals above our own, pragmatically, the social contract enables the discipline to flourish in society. Conse- quently, an inherent disinclination on our part to “bite the hand that feeds us” appears to limit the quality and degree of our contributions to hu- man welfare and well-being and to ensure that, as far as mainstream psychologists are con- cerned, extant social structures and institutions
  • 63. remain intact, even if reformed to benefit some citizens. The Transit of Social Ethics in Psychology: Shifting Psychologists’ Ethical Discourse In light of tensions within APA over its com- mitment to the public interest and its stances on public policies and the history of unjust psycho- logical practices, Vasquez (2012) asserted that “To prevent abusive application of psychologi- cal principles and knowledge, psychologists must remain vigilant about how we, and the discipline of psychology, are encapsulated in the social contexts and cultural positions in which we live” (p. 338). In responding to Vasquez’s call for vigilance yet mindful of the limitations of the discourse on ethics, I ask: Of what does social morality for psychologists consist, given that we conform to society’s laws, social structures, and mores, as well as those of our discipline, even while some have challenged the establishment in society and the discipline by striving to overcome dysfunc- tional and oppressive laws, social structures, and mores? Is there moral space in psychology, as King (1968) urged, in conscience and soli- darity with other citizens, for denouncing an ecologically, economically, politically, and cul- turally imperiled and unjust society and promot- ing economic, sociopolitical, and cultural trans- formation, even to the point of rebellion and revolution? Discussion of such questions among psychol- ogists is sparse, not simply perhaps because we
  • 64. do not wish to jeopardize our social contract with the societal establishment, but also because we are both shaped by and committed to the Enlightenment ideal of the reasoning moral sub- ject who makes competent ethical decisions and 98 WALSH T hi s do cu m en t is co py ri gh te d by th e A
  • 68. to be di ss em in at ed br oa dl y. to a reformist psychological, if not also socio- political, worldview. Besides, few of us psy- chologists are either philosophers or political activists. Altogether, then, our notions of re- sponsibility to society are rather limited. In ef- fect, we lack a moral compass for addressing the interrelated existential challenges that con- tinue to confront humankind: (a) escalating cli- mate change and ecological destruction on land and sea render life on Earth extremely precari- ous; (b) unsustainable neoliberal economic and financial practices (e.g., regimes of austerity) ensure obscene largesse for the tiny minority, continued comfort for the scientific-profes- sional class, and relative or absolute poverty for
  • 69. the masses; and (c) militarized governments wage perpetual war in the name of fighting terrorism, while the omnipresent danger of a nuclear holocaust looms on the horizon with the Doomsday Clock now registering three minutes to midnight, meaning imminent global catastro- phe. I conclude, therefore, that our regnant dis- position of moderation concerning our respon- sibility to society shows a lack of courage, hence is unacceptable morally. Moreover, our responses to global, national, and local precarity will remain superficial until we develop an un- derstanding of the concrete ecological-environ- mental, economic, political, and cultural condi- tions of mundane life (Walsh & Gokani, 2014), which would require reconstructing psychology (Walsh et al., 2014). Nevertheless, one giant leap for our ethical discourse might be to revise the codes to enable the principles and standards to suit our existen- tial realities. The APA Code could ensure that the Principle of Justice is understood in terms of social justice and social responsibility, while the CPA Code could rank Principle IV: Responsi- bility to Society equivalent to Principle I: Re- spect for the Dignity of the Person in its hier- archy. Both codes could incorporate dialogical ethics within them, as the modus operandi for ethical psychologists. Second, we could devote our scientific and professional attention to ad- dressing humankind’s existential challenges. For instance, psychologists from different sub- disciplines could investigate and interpret the human perceptions, causes, and consequences of climate change as well as adaptive and mit-
  • 70. igating responses by individuals and communi- ties to climate change (Swim et al., 2011). However, some cautionary notes are neces- sary on the prospects of psychologists becom- ing mindful advocates and practitioners of so- cial justice. One moral flaw in the codes is that they address the rights of the recipients of our scientific, educational, and professional activi- ties only indirectly in their focus on our per- spectives and privileges (Prilleltensky et al., 1996). As a result, the balance of social power implicit within the codes’ texts strongly favors protecting our interests. The CPA Code, for instance, does not specifically prescribe consul- tation with recipients concerning “ethical deci- sions that affect them” (Pettifor, 1998, p. 233). If equal emphasis were placed on the ethical rights of the recipients of our activities, which would strengthen the centrality of dialogical communication in the prescribed procedures of ethical decision-making, it could balance our social-cultural power and aid in preventing ma- leficence and fostering beneficence. However, such a development, although welcome and vi- tal, would affect the interpersonal level of social systems primarily, not the organizational- institutional and societal levels. Furthermore, a transition toward social-ethical conceptions and practices of ethics is unlikely to occur, if we remain committed in theory and practice to an exclusively natural-science individualistic con- ception of psychology. Rather, a transition to- ward social ethics requires, and could enrich, basic changes in our conceptions and practices of psychological science, applications and ser-
  • 71. vice to society, education of students, and our functions in organizational and institutional sys- tems (Walsh et al., 2014). In addition, not only does our heritage consist of shoring up the status quo through social reform, but also the history of progressive movements in psychology shows that the disci- pline constrains impulses for progressive change just as the larger socioeconomic system coopts such impulses in its economic, political, and social institutions (Walsh & Gokani, 2014). Various calls for incorporating “social justice and activism into [psychology’s] larger iden- tity” (Kakkad, 2005, p. 307) neglect how soci- ety and psychologists struggle with regression toward the societal mean. Societal regression serves as a sociopolitical undertow that drags us back to the comforts of the abundant intellectual and material privileges that we members of the scientific-professional class enjoy, relative to 99BENDING THE ARC T hi s do cu m en t
  • 76. most North Americans. But this very status con- strains our moral engagement as participants in solidarity and in dialogue with other citizens, rather than objectivistic spectators, in the strug- gle to collectively confront the existential issues of our time. To conclude, I have argued for a critique both of the taken-for-granted assumption of the psy- chologist as an autonomous ethical actor who competently applies logical problem-solving to ethical situations and of the sociopolitical ide- ology implicit in ethical discourse, which con- flates social reform with social transformation in the name of social justice. I am arguing that as psychologists we lack moral preparation for progressive engagement in society. This defi- ciency seems attributable largely to a basic his- torical contradiction for which there is no easy resolution and many moral ambiguities. On the one hand, we barely consider the dubious con- viction that we can practice moral discernment as autonomous ethical actors, even while non- rational and communicative processes affect our ethical conduct and social-historical forces shape our vocation. This conviction obscures psychological and sociocultural limits to our capacity for exercising reason in ethical deci- sion-making. On the other hand, we seek to apply our science for the betterment of society, according to the tradition of social reform and adjustment to society. An alternative to these standard practices is one of animating the fundamentally moral na-
  • 77. ture of our vocation by shifting our conceptions and practices of ethics from an individualistic orientation toward communicative and emanci- patory orientations (see also Teo, 2015b). In advancing this case I invoke the hope that we will bend the arc of our moral universe toward ecological-environmental, economic, political, cultural, and social justice (Walsh & Gokani, 2014). However, if our ethical conceptions and practices, including the APA and CPA Codes, are merely reformed, thus remain unchanged in substance, they will serve more as emblems of professional pride than as worthy instruments in the urgent struggle toward justice locally, na- tionally, and globally. References American Psychological Association. (2010). Ethical principles of psychologists and code of conduct (2002, Amended June 1, 2010). Retrieved from http://www.apa.org/ethics/code/index.aspx Aubé, N. (2011). Ethical challenges for psychologists conducting humanitarian work. Canadian Psy- chology/Psychologie canadienne, 52, 225–229. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/a0024342 Canadian Psychological Association. (2000). Cana- dian Code of Ethics for psychologists (3rd ed.). Ottawa, Canada: Author. Capshew, J. H. (1999). Psychologists on the march: Science, practice, and professional identity in America, 1929 –1969. New York, NY: Cambridge
  • 78. University Press. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/ CBO9780511572944 Cottone, R. R. (2011). Ethical decision making in mental health contexts: Representative models and an organizational framework. In S. J. Knapp, M. C. Gottlieb, M. M. Handelsman, & L. D. VandeCreek (Eds.), APA handbook of ethics in psychology: Vol. 1. Moral foundations and common themes (pp. 99 –121). Washington, DC: American Psycho- logical Association. Danziger, K. (1979). The social origins of modern psychology. In A. R. Buss (Ed.), Psychology in social context (pp. 27– 45). New York, NY: Irving- ton. Dunbar, J. (1998). A critical history of CPA’s various codes of ethics for psychologists (1939 –1986). Canadian Psychology/Psychologie canadienne, 39, 177–186. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/h0086806 Fisher, C. B. (2013). Decoding the ethics code; A practical guide for psychologists (3rd ed.). Thou- sand Oaks, CA: Sage. Habermas, J. (1983). The theory of communicative action: Vol. 2. Lifeworld and system: A critique of functionalist reason (T. McCarthy, Trans.). Bos- ton, MA: Beacon. (Original work published in German 1981) Haeny, A. M. (2014). Ethical considerations for psy- chologists taking a public stance on controversial issues: The balance between personal and profes- sional life. Ethics & Behavior, 24, 265–278. http://
  • 79. dx.doi.org/10.1080/10508422.2013.860030 Herman, E. (1995). The romance of American psy- chology: Political culture in the age of experts. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press. Johnson, W. B., Barnett, J. E., Elman, N. S., Forrest, L., & Kaslow, N. J. (2012). The competent com- munity: Toward a vital reformulation of profes- sional ethics. American Psychologist, 67, 557–569. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/a0027206 Kahneman, D. (2003). A perspective on judgment and choice: Mapping bounded rationality. Ameri- can Psychologist, 58, 697–720. http://dx.doi.org/ 10.1037/0003-066X.58.9.697 Kakkad, D. (2005). A new ethical praxis: Psycholo- gists’ emerging responsibilities in issues of social 100 WALSH T hi s do cu m en t is co
  • 84. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511572944 http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/h0086806 http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/10508422.2013.860030 http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/10508422.2013.860030 http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/a0027206 http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/0003-066X.58.9.697 http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/0003-066X.58.9.697 justice. Ethics & Behavior, 15, 293–308. http://dx .doi.org/10.1207/s15327019eb1504_2 Kendler, H. H. (2008). Amoral thoughts about mo- rality: The intersection of science, psychology, and ethics (2nd ed.). Springfield, IL: Thomas. Kennedy, C. H. (2011). Institutional ethical conflicts with illustrations from police and military psychol- ogy. In S. J. Knapp, M. C. Gottlieb, M. M. Han- delsman, & L. D. VandeCreek (Eds.), APA hand- book of ethics in psychology: Vol. 1. Moral foundations and common themes (pp. 123–144). Washington, DC: American Psychological Associ- ation. King, M. L., Jr. (1968). The role of the behavioral scientist in the civil rights movement. American Psychologist, 23, 180 –186. http://dx.doi.org/ 10.1037/h0025715 Kitchener, R. F., & Kitchener, K. S. (2011). Ethical foundations of psychology. In S. J. Knapp, M. C. Gottlieb, M. M. Handelsman, & L. D. VandeCreek (Eds.), APA handbook of ethics in psychology: Vol. 1. Moral foundations and common themes (pp. 3– 42). Washington, DC: American Psycho-
  • 85. logical Association. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/ 13271-001 Lerman, H., & Porter, N. (1990). Feminist ethics in psychotherapy. New York, NY: Springer. Malloy, D. C., & Hadjistavropoulos, T. (1998). A philosophical value analysis of the Canadian Code of Ethics for psychologists. Canadian Psychology/ Psychologie canadienne, 39, 187–193. http://dx .doi.org/10.1037/h0086807 Martel, M. M. (2009). The ethics of psychology’s role in politics and the development and institution of social policy. Ethics & Behavior, 19, 103–111. http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/10508420902772694 Meehan, J. (1995). (Ed.). Feminists read Habermas: Gendering the subject of discourse. New York, NY: Routledge. Napoli, D. S. (1981). Architects of adjustment. Port Washington, NY: Kennikat. Pettifor, J. L. (1996). Ethics: Virtue and politics in the science and practice of psychology. Canadian Psychology/Psychologie canadienne, 37, 1–12. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/0708-5591.37.1.1 Pettifor, J. L. (1998). The Canadian Code of Ethics for Psychologists: A moral context for ethical de- cision-making in emerging areas of practice. Ca- nadian Psychology/Psychologie canadienne, 39, 231–238. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/h0086812 Pipes, R. B., Holstein, J. E., & Aguirre, M. G. (2005).
  • 86. Examining the personal-professional distinction: Ethics codes and the difficulty of drawing a bound- ary. American Psychologist, 60, 325–334. http:// dx.doi.org/10.1037/0003-066X.60.4.325 Prilleltensky, I., Rossiter, A., & Walsh-Bowers, R. (1996). Preventing harm and promoting ethical discourse in the helping professions: Conceptual, research, analytical, and action frameworks. Ethics & Behavior, 6, 287–306. http://dx.doi.org/ 10.1207/s15327019eb0604_1 Prilleltensky, I., & Walsh-Bowers, R. (1993). Psy- chology and the moral imperative. Journal of The- oretical and Philosophical Psychology, 13, 90 – 102. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/h0091122 Rogerson, M. D., Gottlieb, M. C., Handelsman, M. M., Knapp, S., & Younggren, J. (2011). Non- rational processes in ethical decision making. American Psychologist, 66, 614 – 623. http://dx.doi .org/10.1037/a0025215 Rose, N. (1996). Assembling the modern self. In R. Porter (Ed.), The history of the self (pp. 224 –248). London, UK: Routledge. Rossiter, A., Walsh-Bowers, R., & Prilleltensky, I. (2002). Ethics as a located story: A comparison of North American and Cuban clinical ethics. Theory & Psychology, 12, 533–556. http://dx.doi.org/10 .1177/0959354302012004298 Sarason, S. B. (1981). Psychology misdirected. New York, NY: Free Press.
  • 87. Shotter, J. (2005). Acknowledging unique others: Ethics, “expressive realism,” and social con- structionism. Journal of Constructivist Psychol- ogy, 18, 103–130. http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/ 10720530590914761 Sinclair, C. (1998). Nine unique features of the Ca- nadian Code of Ethics for Psychologists. Cana- dian Psychology/Psychologie canadienne, 39, 167–176. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/h0086805 Strong, T., & Sutherland, O. (2007). Conversational ethics in psychological dialogues: Discursive and collaborative considerations. Canadian Psycholo- gy/Psychologie canadienne, 48, 94 –105. http://dx .doi.org/10.1037/cp2007011 Sugarman, J. (2015). Neoliberalism and psychologi- cal ethics. Journal of Theoretical and Philosophi- cal Psychology, 35, 103–116. http://dx.doi.org/ 10.1037/a0038960 Swim, J. K., Stern, P. C., Doherty, T. J., Clayton, S., Reser, J. P., Weber, E. U., . . . Howard, G. S. (2011). Psychology’s contributions to understand- ing and addressing global climate change. Ameri- can Psychologist, 66, 241–250. http://dx.doi.org/ 10.1037/a0023220 Teo, T. (2015a). Are psychological “ethics codes” morally oblique? Journal of Theoretical and Phil- osophical Psychology, 35, 78 – 89. http://dx.doi .org/10.1037/a0038944 Teo, T. (2015b). Critical psychology: A geography of
  • 88. intellectual engagement and resistance. American Psychologist, 70, 1–12. Truscott, D., & Crook, K. H. (2013). Ethics for the practice of psychology in Canada (Rev. ed.). Ed- monton, Canada: University of Alberta Press. Vasquez, M. J. T. (2011). Social justice and civic 101BENDING THE ARC T hi s do cu m en t is co py ri gh te d by th
  • 93. http://dx.doi.org/10.1207/s15327019eb0604_1 http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/ h0091122 http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/a0025215 http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/a0025215 http://dx.doi.org/10.1177/0959354302012004298 http://dx.doi.org/10.1177/0959354302012004298 http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/10720530590914761 http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/10720530590914761 http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/h0086805 http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/cp2007011 http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/cp2007011 http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/a0038960 http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/a0038960 http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/a0023220 http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/a0023220 http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/a0038944 http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/a0038944 virtue. In S. J. Knapp, M. C. Gottlieb, M. M. Handelsman, & L. D. VandeCreek (Eds.), APA handbook of ethics in psychology: Vol. 1. Moral foundations and common themes (pp. 75–98). Washington, DC: American Psychological Associ- ation. Vasquez, M. J. T. (2012). Psychology and social justice: Why we do what we do. American Psy- chologist, 67, 337–346. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/ a0029232 Verges, A. (2010). Integrating contextual issues in ethical decision making. Ethics & Behavior, 20, 497–507. http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/10508422 .2010.521451
  • 94. Walsh, R. T. G. (2015). Introduction to the special section on ethics in psychology: Historical and philosophical grounding. Journal of Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology, 35, 69 –77. http:// dx.doi.org/10.1037/teo0000011 Walsh, R. T. G., & Gokani, R. (2014). The personal and political economy of psychologists’ desires for social justice. Journal of Theoretical and Philo- sophical Psychology, 34, 41–55. http://dx.doi.org/ 10.1037/a0033081 Walsh, R. T. G., Teo, T., & Baydala, A. (2014). A critical history and philosophy of psychology: Di- versity of context, thought, and practice. New York, NY: New York: Cambridge University Press. Received February 13, 2015 Accepted March 3, 2015 � Members of Underrepresented Groups: Reviewers for Journal Manuscripts Wanted If you are interested in reviewing manuscripts for APA journals, the APA Publications and Communications Board would like to invite your participation. Manuscript reviewers are vital to the publications process. As a reviewer, you would gain valuable experience in publishing. The P&C Board is particularly interested in encouraging members of underrepresented groups to participate more in this process. If you are interested in reviewing manuscripts, please write
  • 95. APA Journals at [email protected] Please note the following important points: • To be selected as a reviewer, you must have published articles in peer-reviewed journals. The experience of publishing provides a reviewer with the basis for preparing a thorough, objective review. • To be selected, it is critical to be a regular reader of the five to six empirical journals that are most central to the area or journal for which you would like to review. Current knowledge of recently published research provides a reviewer with the knowledge base to evaluate a new submission within the context of existing research. • To select the appropriate reviewers for each manuscript, the editor needs detailed information. Please include with your letter your vita. In the letter, please identify which APA journal(s) you are interested in, and describe your area of expertise. Be as specific as possible. For example, “social psychology” is not sufficient—you would need to specify “social cognition” or “attitude change” as well. • Reviewing a manuscript takes time (1– 4 hours per manuscript reviewed). If you are selected to review a manuscript, be prepared to invest the necessary time to evaluate the manuscript thoroughly. APA now has an online video course that provides guidance in reviewing manuscripts. To
  • 96. learn more about the course and to access the video, visit http://www.apa.org/pubs/ authors/review-manuscript-ce-video.aspx. 102 WALSH T hi s do cu m en t is co py ri gh te d by th e A m
  • 100. be di ss em in at ed br oa dl y. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/a0029232 http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/a0029232 http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/10508422.2010.521451 http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/10508422.2010.521451 http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/teo0000011 http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/teo0000011 http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/a0033081 http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/a0033081Bending the Arc of North American Psychologists’ Moral Universe Toward Communicative Ethi ...A Social Contextual Review of Ethics CodesCritical Perspectives on Ethical Decision- MakingNonrational cognitive processesInterpersonal processesThe Social Conditions of Psychologists’ VocationOrganizational and institutional influencesProfessional-personal boundary maintenanceEthical Relationship With SocietyThe codes’ orientationsImpediments to justiceA natural scienceA reformist bentPersonal distance from oppressive social conditionsSocial contract with
  • 101. societyThe Transit of Social Ethics in Psychology: Shifting Psychologists’ Ethical DiscourseReferences