SlideShare a Scribd company logo
Commitment in Alternating O¤ers Bargaining
Topi Miettinen
Stockholm School of Economics
Andrés Perea
Maastricht University
This version: September 2010
Abstract
We extend the Ståhl-Rubinstein alternating-o¤er bargaining procedure to allow players,
prior to each bargaining round, to simultaneously and visibly commit to some share of the
pie. If commitment costs are small but increasing in the committed share, then the unique
outcome consistent with common belief in future rationality (Perea, 2010), or more restric-
tively subgame perfect Nash equilibrium, exhibits a second mover advantage. In particular,
as the smallest share of the pie approaches zero, the horizon approaches in…nity, and com-
mitment costs approach zero, the unique bargaining outcome corresponds to the reversed
Rubinstein outcome ( =(1 + ); 1=(1 + )), where is the common discount factor.
KEYWORDS: alternating o¤er bargaining, bargaining power, commitment, epistemic
game theory, patience
JEL CODES: C73, C78, D84
Topi Miettinen: Stockholm School of Economics
P.O. Box 6501, Sveavägen 65, SE-113 83 Stockholm, Sweden.
topi.miettinen@hhs.se
Web: http://www2.hhs.se/SITE/homepages/topi.html
Andrés Perea: Maastricht University, Department of Quantitative Economics
P.O. Box 616, 6200 MD Maastricht, The Netherlands.
a.perea@maastrichtuniversity.nl
Web: http://www.personeel.unimaas.nl/a.perea/
We would like to thank Tore Ellingsen and Jörgen Weibull for insightful comments.
1. Introduction
"...it has not been uncommon for union o¢ cials to stir up excitement and determination on the
part of the membership during or prior to a wage negotiation. If the union is going to insist
on $2 and expects the management to counter with $1.60, an e¤ort is made to persuade the
membership not only that the management could pay $2 but even perhaps that the negotiators
themselves are incompetent if they fail to obtain close to $2. The purpose ... is to make clear to
the management that the negotiators could not accept less than $2 even if they wished to because
they no longer control the members or because they would lose their own positions if they tried."
In this quotation from his classic book, Schelling (1960) vividly illustrates that strategic
commitment is often an essential feature of bargaining tactics and that parties of negotiations
often have access to actions that commit them to some strategically chosen bargaining position.
During the 50 years that have followed, however, there has been fairly little progress in game
theoretic analysis of such commitments. Notable exceptions are Crawford (1982), Muthoo (1992,
1996), and more recently Ellingsen and Miettinen (2008, 2010) and Li (2010).
In this paper, we follow Muthoo (1992), Li (2010) and Ellingsen and Miettinen (2010) and
consider the e¤ect of commitment strategies in a dynamic complete information bargaining
framework. We limit attention to the …nite horizon alternating o¤er game (Ståhl, 1972; Ru-
binstein, 1982) although we do study the in…nite horizon limit. We model parties who can,
simultaneously and prior to each alternating o¤er, commit not to agree on any share smaller
than speci…ed in the commitment. Strategic commitment is assumed to incur small costs. These
costs are increasing in the share to which the party commits re‡ecting the idea that more re-
sources must be invested to build a credible commitment when the opportunity cost of turning
down a deal is larger. After each round of bargaining, any prior commitments are relaxed and
players may again choose a commitment to any share they wish.
Our work builds heavily upon the work of Rubinstein (1982) and Ellingsen and Miettinen
(2008). The main insight of Rubinstein’s pioneering work on bargaining is that, under complete
information, equilibrium strategies are determined by the relative impatience of the bargaining
parties. In equilibrium, the proposer makes an o¤er so that the responder is indi¤erent between
accepting the o¤er and rejecting it, given the cost of waiting; and the responder accepts the
o¤er. Thus there is an e¢ cient immediate agreement with a …rst-mover advantage. Ellingsen
and Miettinen (2008) recently illustrated how mutual attempts of aggressive incompatible com-
mitment may be unavoidable in bilateral bargaining, if commitments can only be attempted
prior to the negotiations and they are not certain to succeed. With certain commitments, it
is better to remain ‡exible and sign on the other’s o¤er than to commit oneself, especially if
commitment incurs a small cost. Yet, a very aggressive commitment is the best-response to not
committing at all. The opponent’s aggressive commitment leaves little room of manoeuvre and
thus even small loopholes in the opponent’s commitment invite betting on being the only one
to succeed in an aggressive commitment attempt despite the risk of an impasse.
2
In the present context we show that, in line with Rubinstein (1982) and contrary to Ellingsen
and Miettinen (2008), the deal is always stroke immediately. However, contrary to Rubinstein’s
outcome, there is a second-mover advantage rather than a …rst-mover advantage! This is sur-
prising, as both parties commit simultaneously at the beginning of every round and there are no
exogenous asymmetries in the commitment technology. The intuition for the result is the fol-
lowing: commitments are short-lasting and there is no uncertainty about who has the initiative
(pre-determined alternating o¤ers structure). Thus, the …rst one to propose does not have to
worry about committing before her proposal; whatever share the second-mover commits to, it
is best for the …rst-mover to avoid any costs by refraining from committing. In equilibrium she
proposes the second-mover the share he commits to and takes the residual share herself, provided
that the residual makes her better o¤ than waiting for the follow-up round. Knowing this, the
second-mover will commit up to the share that makes the …rst-mover indi¤erent between having
the residual share and waiting. Thus, the presence of symmetric commitment strategies entirely
reverses the bargaining power of the parties! In the limit, where the cost of commitment and the
smallest indivisible share of the pie approach zero, and where the number of rounds approaches
in…nity, the outcome approaches the reversed Rubinstein (1982) outcome, ( =(1 + ); 1=(1 + )),
where is the common discount factor.
We analyze the game using the concept of common belief in future rationality (Perea, 2010),
meaning that both players always believe that the opponent will choose rationally now and in
the future, that both players always believe that both players always believe that the opponent
will choose rationally now and in the future, and so on. This concept is a typical backward
induction concept as it assumes that players, throughout the game, only reason about the
future, and not about the past. In fact, in generic games with perfect information, common
belief in future rationality leads to the unique backward induction strategy for every player.
The concept is weaker, but at the same time more basic, than subgame perfect equilibrium as
no equilibrium condition is being imposed1. As Perea (2010) has shown, the strategies that
may be chosen under common belief in future rationality can be computed by the algorithm
of backward dominance. Since every subgame perfect equilibrium of the game survives the
backward dominance procedure, it follows that the outcome of the bargaining game described
above is also the unique subgame perfect equilibrium outcome of the game.
Our analysis contributes to the agenda, initiated by Schelling (1956), of carefully analyzing
and understanding commitment institutions and mechanisms and their implications on the bar-
gaining outcomes. Among the related works, Crawford (1982) and Muthoo (1992, 1996) have
studied the e¤ects of revocable commitments; in our model in contrast, commitments auto-
1
Another non-equilibrium concept which has been developed for dynamic games is extensive form rationalizabil-
ity (Pearce (1984), Battigalli (1997), Battigalli and Siniscalchi (2002)). However, extensive form rationalizability
is a typical forward induction concept, which requires players also to critically reason about the opponents’past
choices, and not only about the opponents’ present and future choices, as common belief in future rationality
does. In many dynamic games, extensive form rationalizability and common belief in future rationality lead to
di¤erent strategy choices for the players .
3
matically vanish but parties can make a costly recommitment to any share they like after each
round. Ellingsen and Miettinen (2008, 2010) analyze costly and long-lasting precommitment to
o¤ers and thus they cannot be freely adjusted after each round. Also, unlike in Ellingsen and
Miettinen (2008, 2010), players do not commit directly to proposals in our model, but rather
to veto any deal where their share is smaller than their commitment. In this respect the model
resembles those of Muthoo (1992, 1996) and the endogenous commitment models analyzed in
Fershtman and Seidmann (1993), Li (2007), and Miettinen (2010), in which yet, the smallest
acceptable shares are determined by the bargaining history in some exogenously determined way
rather than freely chosen by players.
Schelling also mentions reputation as an important means of pre-commitment. Myerson
(1991) and Abreu and Gul (2000) analyze such reputation contexts where one party has in-
complete information about the opponent’s stubbornness not to accept anything less than an
exogenously given share of the pie. The opponent can then use commitment tactics that exploit
this incomplete information and strategically mimic stubbornness in order to force concessions
from the other party. This induces delay and in‡uences the …nal sharing.
Outside options bear a close relation to the current complete information alternating o¤er
bargaining model. Compte and Jehiel (2002) show that exogenous outside options may alto-
gether eliminate the strategic e¤ects of reputation for stubbornness. It has also been shown that,
when a party, by opting out, gets a payo¤ that is inferior to the equilibrium payo¤ he would
obtain in the game without outside options, then these latter have no e¤ect on the equilibrium
outcomes (Binmore et al. 1989). In our setting deliberately chosen commitment strategies in-
‡uence bargaining outcomes exactly because they are chosen so as to force concessions superior
to those in the Rubinstein outcome.
The results closest in spirit to ours are perhaps Dixit’s (1980) extension of the Spence-Dixit
excess capacity model and Ellingsen’s (1995) analysis of timing in oligopoly. Dixit shows that
an incumbent …rm, who nevertheless is presumed to play the role of the follower, can use the
commitment, provided by an excess capacity investment, in seizing limited initiative back from
the entrant. Ellingsen shows in a Cournot duopoly setting that, if one of the …rms alone can
choose to pile up investment later, that …rm will endogenously end up in the Stackelberg follower
position, whereas the …rm who can only invest at present will become the leader.2
The paper is organized as follows. In Section 2, we set up the model and the bargaining
procedure. In Section 3 we present the concept of common belief in future rationality, and the
associated algorithm of backward dominance. In Section 4 we analyze the model with one round
of bargaining. We will use it as a benchmark for our analysis of more than one round in Section
5. We also investigate the limit behavior of this outcome, when the commitment costs go to
zero and the number of rounds goes to in…nity. We conclude in Section 6.
2
These are the only strategies surviving iterated elimination of weakly dominated strategies.
4
2. The Bargaining Procedure
There are two players, 1 and 2, who must reach an agreement about the division of one unit
of some good. We assume that the smallest amount is 1=K for some integer number K: Let
X := f0; 1=K; 2=K; :::; 1g: Hence, the set of possible divisions is given by
D := f(x1; x2) : x1; x2 2 X and x1 + x2 1g:
Players 1 and 2 use the following bargaining procedure, which can last for at most N rounds.
Round 1: At the beginning, both players simultaneously choose commitment levels c1; c2 2
X: The commitment levels become known to both players, and player 1 proposes a division
(x1; x2) 2 D with x1 c1: Subsequently, player 2 decides whether to accept or reject the
proposal under the condition that he can only accept o¤ers with x2 c2: If he accepts, (x1; x2)
is the …nal outcome. If he rejects, the game moves to round 2.
Round 2: At the beginning, both players simultaneously choose new commitment levels c1; c2 2
X: Afterwards, player 2 proposes a division (x1; x2) 2 D with x2 c2: Subsequently, player 1
decides whether to accept or reject (x1; x2); under the condition that he can only accept o¤ers
with x1 c1: If he accepts, (x1; x2) is the …nal outcome. If he rejects, the game moves to round
3.
Round 3: This is a repetition of round 1. And so on.
This bargaining procedure goes on until an agreement is reached, or the process enters round
N + 1: In round N + 1; a given division (y1; y2) 2 D is realized.
We assume that both players incur a cost for commitment, and that this cost is increasing
in the amount to which the player commits. The reason for the latter is that the higher the
amount to which the player commits, the more di¢ cult it will be to stick to this commitment.
More precisely, if player i commits to an amount ci; this will cost him ci; where is some small
positive number. For convenience, we assume that is the same for both players. We …nally
assume that both players discount future payo¤s by a common discount factor :
So, in view of all the above, the players’ utilities are as follows: If the players reach an
agreement on division (x1; x2) in round n; then the utility for player i is
n 1
xi c1
i + c2
i + ::: + n 1
cn
i ;
where ck
i is the commitment level chosen at round k: If the game reaches round N +1; his utility
would be
N
yi c1
i + c2
i + ::: + N 1
cN
i :
In order to avoid uninteresting indi¤erences, we assume that is such that a player is never
indi¤erent between two outcomes that are realized at two di¤erent rounds. Note that for every
open interval (a; b) in [0; 1]; we can always …nd such a that lies in (a; b); since there are only
5
…nitely many rounds, and …nitely many divisions and commitment levels at every round. By
choosing is this way, we guarantee that a player will never be indi¤erent between accepting
and rejecting an o¤er. This, eventually, will lead to a unique outcome in the bargaining game,
which makes our analysis more transparent.
Within our bargaining procedure above, the interpretation of the commitment levels is thus
that the proposer commits to never o¤er less than his commitment level for himself, whereas the
responder commits to reject any o¤er that would give him less than his commitment level. With
this interpretation in mind, it makes intuitive sense that the cost of commitment is assumed
to be increasing in the commitment level. A higher commitment level, namely, more heavily
restricts the subsequent choice set of the player, and for higher commitment levels, makes it
more tempting for this player to break his commitment. The higher cost of commitment for
larger shares should in this way re‡ect the larger opportunity cost.
3. Common Belief in Future Rationality
The concept we use to analyze the game is common belief in future rationality (Perea, 2010). In
this concept, we assume that a player always believes that his opponent will choose rationally
now and in the future, that a player always believes that his opponent always believes that he
will choose rationally now and in the future, and so on. It is thus a typical backward induction
concept, as a player is only required to reason about the opponents’choices in the future of
the game, and not about the opponents’ past choices. In that sense, is di¤ers considerably
from the notion of extensive form rationalizability (Pearce, 1984; Battigalli, 1997; Battigalli
and Siniscalchi, 2002), which is a typical forward induction concept, requiring players also to
think critically about opponents’past choices, and where possible try to draw conclusions from
these about possible future moves by this opponent. In many dynamic games, common belief
in future rationality and extensive form rationalizability select di¤erent strategy choices for the
players. In fact, in terms of strategy choices there is no general logical relationship between the
two concepts –in some games the former can be more restrictive, in other games the latter can
be more restrictive, and in yet some other games they may select completely opposed strategies
for a given player.
For a formal de…nition of common belief in future rationality within an epistemic model
the reader is referred to Perea (2010). In that paper, it is also shown that the strategies
that can rationally be chosen under common belief in future rationality are characterized by
an elimination procedure called backward dominance. For dynamic games with observed past
choices3, such as the game we consider in this paper, the backward dominance procedure works
as follows: We start at the ultimate subgames, that is, those subgames after which the game
is over. At each of those subgames, we restrict to strategies that reach this subgame, and
3
That is, games that may include simultaneous moves, but where the players always observe which choices
have been made by the opponents in the past.
6
apply iterated strict dominance (or, iterated elimination of strictly dominated strategies) to this
restricted game.
We then move to penultimate subgames, that is, subgames after which either the game is
over or an ultimate subgame starts. At each of those subgames, we restrict to strategies that
reach this subgame and that have not been eliminated yet by the procedure. We then apply
iterated strict dominance to these restricted games.
And so on, until we reach the beginning of the game. There, we restrict to strategies that
have not been eliminated yet, and apply iterated strict dominance to this restricted game. The
strategies that survive the …nal round of iterated strict dominance at the beginning of the game
are said to survive the backward dominance procedure.
For dynamic games with observed past choices, subgame perfect equilibrium is a strict re…ne-
ment of common belief in future rationality. That is, every strategy that is optimal in a subgame
perfect equilibrium can also be chosen rationally under common belief in future rationality, but
not vice versa (Perea, 2010). So, common belief in future rationality is weaker than subgame
perfect equilibrium. At the same time, we believe it is a more basic concept than subgame
perfect equilibrium, as no equilibrium condition is being imposed –we only require a player to
believe that his opponent chooses rationally now and in the future, that he believes that his
opponent reasons in this way as well, and so on. No other conditions are being imposed. If we
apply common belief in future rationality to generic games with perfect information, we obtain
the usual backward induction procedure, and hence the unique backward induction strategy for
every player. This con…rms the intuition that it is indeed a backward induction concept.
4. The Case of One Round
We start with the easiest case, namely when there is only one round of bargaining. For this
case, we already encounter a surprising result: Under common belief in future rationality (and
hence also under subgame perfect equilibrium) the proposer faces a …rst-mover disadvantage,
rather than a …rst-mover advantage. Actually, we can say a little more, namely the proposer
gets exactly what he would obtain as a responder in the procedure without commitment. So,
introducing the possibility to commit reverses the outcome completely! All this is obtained
under the assumption that the commitment costs are su¢ ciently small. More precisely, we
require < 1 :
Theorem 4.1. (Case of one round) Consider the procedure with only one round of bargaining,
and suppose that < 1 . Then, under common belief in future rationality, player 1 chooses
commitment level 0, player 2 chooses commitment level 1 y1; player 1 proposes ( y1; 1 y1)
and player 2 accepts.
Here, x denotes the smallest number in X larger than, or equal to, x: Remember that (y1; y2)
is the outcome if the proposal is rejected. So, player 1, the proposer, gets the minimal amount
7
he would still accept, whereas player 2, the responder, gets all the surplus! Notice that in the
classical bargaining procedure without commitment, this would be exactly the outcome when
player 2 would be the proposer and player 1 the responder.
Proof. For every pair (c1; c2) of commitment levels, the subgame that starts after (c1; c2) is
a game with perfect information. Hence, applying backward dominance to this subgame is the
same as using backward induction. After every (c1; c2); the backward induction outcome is as
follows:
1. If c1 + c2 > 1; or c1 > 1 y2; then player 2 will reject any proposal by player 1. Hence,
the outcome will be (y1; y2); with utility y1 c1 for player 1, and utility y2 c2 for
player 2.
2. If c2 > 1 y1; then player 1 does not want to make any o¤er that player 2 would accept.
Hence, the outcome will be (y1; y2); with utility y1 c1 for player 1, and utility y2 c2
for player 2.
3. Suppose that c1 + c2 1 and y2 < c2 < 1 y1: Then, the best that player 1 can do
is to o¤er player 2 precisely c2; which player 2 would accept. So, the outcome would be
(1 c2; c2); with utility 1 c2 c1 for player 1, and utility c2 c2 for player 2.
4. Suppose that c1 < 1 y2 and c2 < y2: Then, the best that player 1 can do is to o¤er
player 2 exactly y2; which player 2 would accept. So, the outcome would be (1 y2;
y2); with utility 1 y2 c1 for player 1, and utility y2 c2 for player 2.
It can easily be seen that this covers all possible cases. In Figure 1 we have depicted the
backwards induction utilities for both players after every possible pair (c1; c2): So, Figure 1
represents exactly the restricted game that the backward dominance procedure would consider
at the beginning of the game. In order to …nish the backward dominance procedure, we must
apply iterated strict dominance to the game in Figure 1.
From player 1’s utilities in Figure 1 it is easily veri…ed that, for every c2; player 1’s utility
is decreasing in his commitment level c1: This means, however, that c1 = 0 strictly dominates
every other c1 for player 1. So, we eliminate all c1 > 0 for player 1, which leaves only c1 = 0:
But then, in the reduced game that remains, player 2’s best choice is c2 = 1 y1: Here, we use
the assumption that < 1 : As we have seen above, the best that player 1 can do in this
case is to propose ( y1; 1 y1); which player 2 would accept. So, by applying the backward
dominance procedure, we obtain that player 1 chooses commitment level c1 = 0; player 2 chooses
c2 = 1 y1; player 1 proposes ( y1; 1 y1) and player 2 accepts. This completes the proof.
Theorem 4.1 illustrates two points. First, by setting y1 = y2 = 0, one can see that in a
single round ultimatum bargaining game, the second mover will reap the entire pie. Second,
by setting y1 = =(1 + ) and y2 = 1=(1 + ); we would e¤ectively add a simultaneous move
8
@
@
@
@
@
@
@@
y1 c1; y2 c2
1 c2 c1; c2 c2
1 y2 c1; y2 c2
1 y2
y2
1 y1
c1
c2
Figure 1: The case of one round: Backward induction utilities after every pair (c1; c1)
9
commitment stage to the alternating-o¤er protocol such that precommitments are valid only in
the …rst round of bargaining. Our result shows that this would in fact put the recipient of the
…rst o¤er in an even more advantageous position than where the proposer in the game without
commitments is: the recipient of the …rst proposal commits to 1 2
=(1+ ) = 1+ 2
1+ and leaves
only 2
=(1 + ) to the …rst mover.
5. The Case of More Rounds
We now turn to the case of more than one round. Also in this case, common belief in future
rationality leads to a unique outcome, where the proposer at round 1 faces a …rst-mover dis-
advantage, rather than a …rst-mover advantage. Actually, when the commitment cost tends
to zero, then the …rst proposer gets exactly what he would obtain as the …rst responder in the
procedure without commitment, and vice versa. So, again, introducing the possibility to com-
mit completely reverses the outcome as tends to zero! As every subgame perfect equilibrium
satis…es common belief in future rationality (Perea, 2010), it follows that this outcome is also
the unique subgame perfect equilibrium outcome in the game.
Theorem 5.1. (Case of more than one round) Suppose that the bargaining procedure consists
of N potential rounds, and that < 1 . Let p denote the proposer at round 1, and r the
responder at round 1. Then, common belief in future rationality leads to a unique outcome,
namely at round 1 proposer p commits to cp = 0, responder r commits to cr = xN
r ; proposer p
proposes the division (xN
p ; xN
r ) and responder r accepts, where xN
p ; xN
r are recursively given by
x1
p = yp; x1
r = 1 yp;
xN
p = (1 )xN 1
r ; and xN
r = 1 (1 )xN 1
r ;
for every N 2:
If we let tend to zero, then the recursive equations above would exactly yield the outcomes
for the players in the procedure without commitment, but with the roles of the proposer and
responder reversed! If the size of the smallest slice 1=K is small, then the amounts xN
p and xN
r
are approximately equal to
xN
p
(1 ) + ( 1)n n
(1 )n
1 + (1 )
+ ( 1)n 1 n
(1 )n 1
yp
and
xN
r
1 ( 1)n n
(1 )n
1 + (1 )
( 1)n 1 n
(1 )n 1
yp:
10
Recall that yp is the amount that player p would get at the end of the game, when all proposals
have been rejected. These approximations are obtained by setting x = x in the recursive
equations above, and solving them. If the number of rounds N becomes very large, then
xN
p
(1 )
1 + (1 )
and xN
r
1
1 + (1 )
which shows that there is a clear …rst-mover disadvantage. If in addition the commitment cost
would tend to zero, then in the limit we would obtain the reversed Rubinstein outcome
xN
p
1 +
and xN
r
1
1 +
:
Proof of Theorem 5.1. We prove the statement by induction on the number of rounds. If
N = 1; then the statement follows immediately from Theorem 4.1.
Now, assume that N 2; and that the statement holds for the procedure with N 1 rounds.
Let p be the proposer at round 1, and r the responder at round 1. Suppose that the proposal
at round 1 would be rejected. Then, the subgame that starts at round 2 is a procedure with
N 1 rounds, where r is the …rst proposer and p is the …rst responder. The commitment costs
incurred at round 1 are sunk costs, and therefore do not a¤ect the analysis in this subgame. By
our induction assumption we know that in this subgame, common belief in future rationality (or,
equivalently, the backward dominance procedure) leads to a unique outcome: player r chooses
commitment level cr = 0; player p chooses commitment level cp = xN 1
r ; player r proposes xN 1
p
for himself and xN 1
r for player p; and player p accepts. The corresponding utilities would be
xN 1
r xN 1
r = (1 )xN 1
r for player p and xN 1
p for player r:
Let us now move to round 1, the beginning of the game. If we apply the backward dominance
procedure, then we restrict to strategies that have not been eliminated yet, and perform iterated
strict dominance within this restricted game. By our induction assumption, the strategies that
have not been eliminated yet are such that, whenever the proposal at round 1 is rejected, then
the discounted utility for p is (1 )xN 1
r ; and the discounted utility for r is xN 1
p : By a
similar argument as in the proof of Theorem 4.1, we can then conclude that the restricted game
at round 1 is given by Figure 2. The only change compared to the proof in Theorem 4.1 is that
we substitute (1 )xN 1
r for y1; and substitute xN 1
p for y2: In Figure 2, the …rst utility always
corresponds to player p; and the second utility to player r:
From Figure 2, it can easily be concluded that proposer p’s utility is strictly decreasing in
his commitment level cp: Hence, all choices but cp = 0 are strictly dominated for player p: So, we
obtain a reduced game in which player p only chooses cp = 0: But then, using the assumption that
< 1 ; we see that player r’s best choice is cr = 1 (1 )xN 1
r : So, the backward dominance
procedure (and hence also common belief in future rationality) leads to a unique outcome, in
which at round 1 player p commits to cp = 0; player r commits to cr = 1 (1 )xN 1
r ; player
11
@
@
@
@
@
@
@
@
@@
(1 )xN 1
r cp; xN 1
p cr
1 cr cp; cr cr
1 xN 1
p cp; xN 1
p cr
1 xN 1
p
xN 1
p
1 (1 )xN 1
r
cp
cr
Figure 2: The restricted game at round 1
12
p proposes (1 )xN 1
r for himself, player p proposes 1 (1 )xN 1
r for player r; and player
r accepts. Since xN
p = (1 )xN 1
r and xN
r = 1 (1 )xN 1
r ; the statement of the theorem
follows for N rounds. By induction on N; the statement holds for every N; and hence the proof
is complete.
6. Concluding Remarks
6.1. Commitment Costs
In our model we have assumed that the commitment costs for both players are given by c;
where c is the amount committed to, and is some …xed number less than 1 : In fact, we
do not really need this speci…c functional form for the commitment costs. Instead, we could
assume that the commitment costs are given by a more general function (c); where (0) = 0;
the function is strictly increasing in the commitment level c; and (1) 1 : The reader
may verify that under these assumptions, common belief in future rationality would again lead
to a unique outcome, in which the proposer at round 1 faces a …rst-mover disadvantage. The
outcome can be computed by a recursive formula similar to the one used in Theorem 5.1. Also
under these assumptions we would obtain the reversed Rubinstein outcome ( =(1+ ); 1=(1+ ))
if we let the number of rounds go to in…nity, let the size of the smallest slice go to zero, and let
the commitment costs go to zero. However, in the paper we have chosen the speci…c functional
form c for the commitment costs as to keep the presentation and the analysis as simple as
possible.
6.2. Common Belief in Future Rationality
The reader may wonder why we have not chosen the more traditional concept of subgame perfect
equilibrium, instead of common belief in future rationality, to analyze the game. There are two
reasons.
First, common belief in future rationality is a more basic concept than subgame perfect
equilibrium, as it does not impose any equilibrium condition. It only requires that a player
always believes that his opponent will choose rationally now and in the future, that he always
believes that his opponent always believes that he will choose rationally now and in the future,
and so on. The concept of subgame perfect equilibrium also imposes these conditions, but
in addition requires some equilibrium conditions that are harder to justify, and which are not
assumed by common belief in future rationality.
Second, using common belief in future rationality as a concept makes our Theorem 5.1
stronger. Namely, common belief in future rationality is a weaker concept than subgame perfect
equilibrium. In fact, every subgame perfect equilibrium satis…es common belief in future ratio-
nality, but not vice versa. Therefore, our Theorem 5.1 implies that the outcome described there
is also the unique subgame perfect equilibrium outcome. However, the statement is stronger
13
than this: We do not need the equilibrium condition to arrive at this outcome. Imposing only
common belief in future rationality is already enough.
References
[1] Abreu, D., F. Gul (2000): "Bargaining and Reputation", Econometrica, 68, 85-118.
[2] Battigalli, P. (1997): "On rationalizability in extensive games", Journal of Economic
Theory, 74, 40-61.
[3] Battigalli, P. and M. Siniscalchi (2002): "Strong belief and forward induction reasoning",
Journal of Economic Theory, 106, 356-391.
[4] Binmore, K., Shaked, A., Sutton, J. (1989): "An Outside Option Experiment" Quarterly
Journal of Economics, 104, 753-770.
[5] Compte, O., P. Jehiel (2002): "On the Role of Outside Options in Bargaining with Obstinate
Parties", Econometrica 70, 1477–1517.
[6] Crawford, V.P. (1982): "A Theory of Disagreement in Bargaining" Econometrica, 50, 607-
637.
[7] Dixit, A. (1980): "The Role of Investment in Entry-Deterrence", Economic Journal, 90,
95-106.
[8] Ellingsen (1995): "On Flexibility in Oligopoly", Economics Letters, 48, 83-89.
[9] Ellingsen, T., T. Miettinen (2008): "Commitment and Con‡ict in Bilateral Bargaining",
American Economic Review 98, 1629-1635.
[10] Ellingsen, T., T. Miettinen (2010): "Temporary Commitment in Dynamic Bargaining"
Stockholm School of Economics, mimeo.
[11] Fershtman, C., D. Seidmann (1993): "Deadline E¤ects and Ine¢ cient Delay in Bargaining
with Endogenous Commitment." Journal of Economic Theory 60, 306–321.
[12] Li, D. (2007): "Bargaining with History-Dependent Preferences", Journal of Economic
Theory 136, 695-708.
[13] Li, D. (2010): "Commitment and Compromise in Dynamic Bargaining", Chinese University
of Hong Kong, mimeo.
[14] Miettinen, T. (2010): "History-dependent Reciprocity in Alternating O¤er Bargaining",
Finnish Economic Papers, 23, 1-15.
14
[15] Muthoo, A. (1992): "Revocable Commitment and Sequential Bargaining", Eonomic Jour-
nal, 102, 378-387.
[16] Muthoo, A. (1996): "A Bargaining Model Based on the Commitment Tactic", Journal of
Economic Theory, 69, 134-152.
[17] Myerson, R. (1991). Game Theory: Analysis of Con‡ict, Harvard University Press, Cam-
bridge, MA/USA.
[18] Pearce, D.G. (1984): "Rationalizable strategic behavior and the problem of perfection",
Econometrica ,52, 1029-1050.
[19] Perea, A. (2010): "Belief in the Opponents’Future Rationality" Working paper, Available
at: http://www.personeel.unimaas.nl/a.perea/
[20] Rubinstein, A. (1982): "Perfect Equilibrium in a Bargaining Model" Econometrica 50, 97-
110.
[21] Schelling, T. (1956): "An Essay on Bargaining." American Economic Review 46, 281-306.
[22] Schelling, T. (1960): The Strategy of Con‡ict. Harvard University Press, Cambridge,
MA/USA.
[23] Ståhl, I. (1972). Bargaining Theory. Stockholm School of Economics, Stockholm, Sweden.
15

More Related Content

What's hot

Disentangling the effect of private and public cash flows on firm value
Disentangling the effect of private and public cash flows on firm valueDisentangling the effect of private and public cash flows on firm value
Disentangling the effect of private and public cash flows on firm value
FGV Brazil
 
The Relationship Between Firm Investment and Financial Status
The Relationship Between Firm Investment and Financial StatusThe Relationship Between Firm Investment and Financial Status
The Relationship Between Firm Investment and Financial StatusSudarshan Kadariya
 
Role of commitment and emotions for long-term relations
Role of commitment and emotions for long-term relationsRole of commitment and emotions for long-term relations
Role of commitment and emotions for long-term relations
Tom Lenaerts
 
The Cost of Capital, Corporation Finance, and the Theory of Investment: Comments
The Cost of Capital, Corporation Finance, and the Theory of Investment: CommentsThe Cost of Capital, Corporation Finance, and the Theory of Investment: Comments
The Cost of Capital, Corporation Finance, and the Theory of Investment: CommentsSudarshan Kadariya
 
Moral Hazard Summary Microeconomics 2016
Moral Hazard Summary Microeconomics 2016Moral Hazard Summary Microeconomics 2016
Moral Hazard Summary Microeconomics 2016
Lisa Raffi
 
9. most favoured nation clauses revisited
9.  most favoured nation clauses revisited9.  most favoured nation clauses revisited
9. most favoured nation clauses revisitedMatias González Muñoz
 
The Determınants of Capıtal Structure: an Empırıcal Study of The Lısted Fırms...
The Determınants of Capıtal Structure: an Empırıcal Study of The Lısted Fırms...The Determınants of Capıtal Structure: an Empırıcal Study of The Lısted Fırms...
The Determınants of Capıtal Structure: an Empırıcal Study of The Lısted Fırms...
The International Journal of Business Management and Technology
 
Applying The Lessons From Conan O’Brien To Talent Contracts
Applying The Lessons From Conan O’Brien To Talent ContractsApplying The Lessons From Conan O’Brien To Talent Contracts
Applying The Lessons From Conan O’Brien To Talent Contracts
Wendi S. Lazar, Outten & Golden LLP
 
Case real estate
Case real estateCase real estate
Case real estate
Edoardo Falchetti
 
1594798413701 application of game theory in real world decision making enviro...
1594798413701 application of game theory in real world decision making enviro...1594798413701 application of game theory in real world decision making enviro...
1594798413701 application of game theory in real world decision making enviro...
VICTORODOYO16
 
Ssrn commercial real estate leasing litigation
Ssrn commercial real estate leasing litigationSsrn commercial real estate leasing litigation
Ssrn commercial real estate leasing litigation
Bob Lowery
 
STRESS TESTING IN BANKING SECTOR FRAMEWORK
STRESS TESTING IN BANKING SECTOR FRAMEWORKSTRESS TESTING IN BANKING SECTOR FRAMEWORK
STRESS TESTING IN BANKING SECTOR FRAMEWORK
Dinabandhu Bag
 
Manishin stafford slides (pp show)
Manishin stafford slides (pp show)Manishin stafford slides (pp show)
Manishin stafford slides (pp show)Glenn Manishin
 
Negotiation
NegotiationNegotiation
Busn 420 entire course business law devry
Busn 420 entire course business law   devryBusn 420 entire course business law   devry
Busn 420 entire course business law devryProfessorLance
 
Busn 420 entire course business law devry
Busn 420 entire course business law   devryBusn 420 entire course business law   devry
Busn 420 entire course business law devryProfessorLance
 
What do Trade Creditors need to know about Antitrust Laws
What do Trade Creditors need to know about Antitrust LawsWhat do Trade Creditors need to know about Antitrust Laws
What do Trade Creditors need to know about Antitrust Laws
Credit Management Association
 
Financial Management Slides Ch 22
Financial Management Slides Ch 22Financial Management Slides Ch 22
Financial Management Slides Ch 22
Sayyed Naveed Ali
 
59 lambsdorff%20and%20 nell
59 lambsdorff%20and%20 nell59 lambsdorff%20and%20 nell
59 lambsdorff%20and%20 nellguillenleon
 

What's hot (20)

Disentangling the effect of private and public cash flows on firm value
Disentangling the effect of private and public cash flows on firm valueDisentangling the effect of private and public cash flows on firm value
Disentangling the effect of private and public cash flows on firm value
 
The Relationship Between Firm Investment and Financial Status
The Relationship Between Firm Investment and Financial StatusThe Relationship Between Firm Investment and Financial Status
The Relationship Between Firm Investment and Financial Status
 
Role of commitment and emotions for long-term relations
Role of commitment and emotions for long-term relationsRole of commitment and emotions for long-term relations
Role of commitment and emotions for long-term relations
 
The Cost of Capital, Corporation Finance, and the Theory of Investment: Comments
The Cost of Capital, Corporation Finance, and the Theory of Investment: CommentsThe Cost of Capital, Corporation Finance, and the Theory of Investment: Comments
The Cost of Capital, Corporation Finance, and the Theory of Investment: Comments
 
Ep elo
Ep eloEp elo
Ep elo
 
Moral Hazard Summary Microeconomics 2016
Moral Hazard Summary Microeconomics 2016Moral Hazard Summary Microeconomics 2016
Moral Hazard Summary Microeconomics 2016
 
9. most favoured nation clauses revisited
9.  most favoured nation clauses revisited9.  most favoured nation clauses revisited
9. most favoured nation clauses revisited
 
The Determınants of Capıtal Structure: an Empırıcal Study of The Lısted Fırms...
The Determınants of Capıtal Structure: an Empırıcal Study of The Lısted Fırms...The Determınants of Capıtal Structure: an Empırıcal Study of The Lısted Fırms...
The Determınants of Capıtal Structure: an Empırıcal Study of The Lısted Fırms...
 
Applying The Lessons From Conan O’Brien To Talent Contracts
Applying The Lessons From Conan O’Brien To Talent ContractsApplying The Lessons From Conan O’Brien To Talent Contracts
Applying The Lessons From Conan O’Brien To Talent Contracts
 
Case real estate
Case real estateCase real estate
Case real estate
 
1594798413701 application of game theory in real world decision making enviro...
1594798413701 application of game theory in real world decision making enviro...1594798413701 application of game theory in real world decision making enviro...
1594798413701 application of game theory in real world decision making enviro...
 
Ssrn commercial real estate leasing litigation
Ssrn commercial real estate leasing litigationSsrn commercial real estate leasing litigation
Ssrn commercial real estate leasing litigation
 
STRESS TESTING IN BANKING SECTOR FRAMEWORK
STRESS TESTING IN BANKING SECTOR FRAMEWORKSTRESS TESTING IN BANKING SECTOR FRAMEWORK
STRESS TESTING IN BANKING SECTOR FRAMEWORK
 
Manishin stafford slides (pp show)
Manishin stafford slides (pp show)Manishin stafford slides (pp show)
Manishin stafford slides (pp show)
 
Negotiation
NegotiationNegotiation
Negotiation
 
Busn 420 entire course business law devry
Busn 420 entire course business law   devryBusn 420 entire course business law   devry
Busn 420 entire course business law devry
 
Busn 420 entire course business law devry
Busn 420 entire course business law   devryBusn 420 entire course business law   devry
Busn 420 entire course business law devry
 
What do Trade Creditors need to know about Antitrust Laws
What do Trade Creditors need to know about Antitrust LawsWhat do Trade Creditors need to know about Antitrust Laws
What do Trade Creditors need to know about Antitrust Laws
 
Financial Management Slides Ch 22
Financial Management Slides Ch 22Financial Management Slides Ch 22
Financial Management Slides Ch 22
 
59 lambsdorff%20and%20 nell
59 lambsdorff%20and%20 nell59 lambsdorff%20and%20 nell
59 lambsdorff%20and%20 nell
 

Viewers also liked

Futbolforkids donating football for kids
Futbolforkids donating football for kidsFutbolforkids donating football for kids
Futbolforkids donating football for kids
Futbol for Kids
 
Kênh truyền thông pr
Kênh truyền thông prKênh truyền thông pr
Kênh truyền thông pr
Trà Lê
 
Why and How to do a Software Startup
Why and How to do a Software StartupWhy and How to do a Software Startup
Why and How to do a Software Startup
kyptin
 
Front-End Developer's work process
Front-End Developer's work processFront-End Developer's work process
Front-End Developer's work process
sonsanghun
 
Cv yogesh
Cv yogeshCv yogesh
Cv yogesh
Yogesh Bhave
 
Peran Cultural Intelligence (CQ) dalam Kepemimpinan Lintas Budaya
Peran Cultural Intelligence (CQ) dalam Kepemimpinan Lintas BudayaPeran Cultural Intelligence (CQ) dalam Kepemimpinan Lintas Budaya
Peran Cultural Intelligence (CQ) dalam Kepemimpinan Lintas BudayaNaning Broto
 
Herding in Aid Allocation
Herding in Aid AllocationHerding in Aid Allocation
Austin's Visual Resume
Austin's Visual ResumeAustin's Visual Resume
Austin's Visual ResumeAustin Green
 
Vita - Ashton comprehensive
Vita - Ashton comprehensiveVita - Ashton comprehensive
Vita - Ashton comprehensivePatrick Ashton
 
Common Trends and Shocks to Top Incomes: A Structural Breaks Approach
Common Trends and Shocks to Top Incomes: A Structural Breaks ApproachCommon Trends and Shocks to Top Incomes: A Structural Breaks Approach
Common Trends and Shocks to Top Incomes: A Structural Breaks Approach
Stockholm Institute of Transition Economics
 
The Substitution of ICT Capital for Routine Labor: Transitional Dynamics and ...
The Substitution of ICT Capital for Routine Labor: Transitional Dynamics and ...The Substitution of ICT Capital for Routine Labor: Transitional Dynamics and ...
The Substitution of ICT Capital for Routine Labor: Transitional Dynamics and ...
Stockholm Institute of Transition Economics
 
The Costs of Political In‡fluence: Firm-Level Evidence from Developing Countries
The Costs of Political In‡fluence: Firm-Level Evidence from Developing CountriesThe Costs of Political In‡fluence: Firm-Level Evidence from Developing Countries
The Costs of Political In‡fluence: Firm-Level Evidence from Developing Countries
Stockholm Institute of Transition Economics
 
Intergenerational mobility, intergenerational effects, the role of family bac...
Intergenerational mobility, intergenerational effects, the role of family bac...Intergenerational mobility, intergenerational effects, the role of family bac...
Intergenerational mobility, intergenerational effects, the role of family bac...
Stockholm Institute of Transition Economics
 
الإستثناء
الإستثناءالإستثناء
الإستثناء
muhammad sholeh
 
Teenage Kicks: New (Old) Evidence on the Pill and Teenage Childbearing
Teenage Kicks: New (Old) Evidence on the Pill and Teenage ChildbearingTeenage Kicks: New (Old) Evidence on the Pill and Teenage Childbearing
Teenage Kicks: New (Old) Evidence on the Pill and Teenage Childbearing
Stockholm Institute of Transition Economics
 

Viewers also liked (17)

Futbolforkids donating football for kids
Futbolforkids donating football for kidsFutbolforkids donating football for kids
Futbolforkids donating football for kids
 
Kênh truyền thông pr
Kênh truyền thông prKênh truyền thông pr
Kênh truyền thông pr
 
Why and How to do a Software Startup
Why and How to do a Software StartupWhy and How to do a Software Startup
Why and How to do a Software Startup
 
Front-End Developer's work process
Front-End Developer's work processFront-End Developer's work process
Front-End Developer's work process
 
Cv yogesh
Cv yogeshCv yogesh
Cv yogesh
 
Peran Cultural Intelligence (CQ) dalam Kepemimpinan Lintas Budaya
Peran Cultural Intelligence (CQ) dalam Kepemimpinan Lintas BudayaPeran Cultural Intelligence (CQ) dalam Kepemimpinan Lintas Budaya
Peran Cultural Intelligence (CQ) dalam Kepemimpinan Lintas Budaya
 
Herding in Aid Allocation
Herding in Aid AllocationHerding in Aid Allocation
Herding in Aid Allocation
 
Austin's Visual Resume
Austin's Visual ResumeAustin's Visual Resume
Austin's Visual Resume
 
CV_yogesh
CV_yogeshCV_yogesh
CV_yogesh
 
Vita - Ashton comprehensive
Vita - Ashton comprehensiveVita - Ashton comprehensive
Vita - Ashton comprehensive
 
Common Trends and Shocks to Top Incomes: A Structural Breaks Approach
Common Trends and Shocks to Top Incomes: A Structural Breaks ApproachCommon Trends and Shocks to Top Incomes: A Structural Breaks Approach
Common Trends and Shocks to Top Incomes: A Structural Breaks Approach
 
The Substitution of ICT Capital for Routine Labor: Transitional Dynamics and ...
The Substitution of ICT Capital for Routine Labor: Transitional Dynamics and ...The Substitution of ICT Capital for Routine Labor: Transitional Dynamics and ...
The Substitution of ICT Capital for Routine Labor: Transitional Dynamics and ...
 
The Costs of Political In‡fluence: Firm-Level Evidence from Developing Countries
The Costs of Political In‡fluence: Firm-Level Evidence from Developing CountriesThe Costs of Political In‡fluence: Firm-Level Evidence from Developing Countries
The Costs of Political In‡fluence: Firm-Level Evidence from Developing Countries
 
CV_yogesh
CV_yogeshCV_yogesh
CV_yogesh
 
Intergenerational mobility, intergenerational effects, the role of family bac...
Intergenerational mobility, intergenerational effects, the role of family bac...Intergenerational mobility, intergenerational effects, the role of family bac...
Intergenerational mobility, intergenerational effects, the role of family bac...
 
الإستثناء
الإستثناءالإستثناء
الإستثناء
 
Teenage Kicks: New (Old) Evidence on the Pill and Teenage Childbearing
Teenage Kicks: New (Old) Evidence on the Pill and Teenage ChildbearingTeenage Kicks: New (Old) Evidence on the Pill and Teenage Childbearing
Teenage Kicks: New (Old) Evidence on the Pill and Teenage Childbearing
 

Similar to Commitment in Alternating Offers Bargaining

Game Theory Introduction
Game Theory IntroductionGame Theory Introduction
Game Theory Introduction
Robin Anderson
 
Nash Equilibrium
Nash EquilibriumNash Equilibrium
Nash Equilibrium
iosrjce
 
Legal contract presentation
Legal contract presentationLegal contract presentation
Legal contract presentationguestfae7fe
 
Game Theory and Competitive Strategy / abshor.marantika / Devandra Nabila Aul...
Game Theory and Competitive Strategy / abshor.marantika / Devandra Nabila Aul...Game Theory and Competitive Strategy / abshor.marantika / Devandra Nabila Aul...
Game Theory and Competitive Strategy / abshor.marantika / Devandra Nabila Aul...
bbyjello
 
Contract theory
Contract theoryContract theory
Contract theory
av190286
 
A brief introduction to the basics of game theory
A brief introduction to the basics of game theoryA brief introduction to the basics of game theory
A brief introduction to the basics of game theory
Ying wei (Joe) Chou
 
A brief introduction to the basics of game theory
A brief introduction to the basics of game theoryA brief introduction to the basics of game theory
A brief introduction to the basics of game theory
Wladimir Augusto
 
Cdam 2001-09
Cdam 2001-09Cdam 2001-09
Cdam 2001-09Naa Adom
 
Ssrn a brief inrtoduction to the basic of game theory
Ssrn a brief inrtoduction to the basic of game theorySsrn a brief inrtoduction to the basic of game theory
Ssrn a brief inrtoduction to the basic of game theory
Ying wei (Joe) Chou
 
A Brief Introduction to the Basics of Game Theory
A Brief Introduction to the Basics of Game TheoryA Brief Introduction to the Basics of Game Theory
A Brief Introduction to the Basics of Game Theory
Trading Game Pty Ltd
 
Delegation versus Communication in the Organization of Government
Delegation versus Communication in the Organization of GovernmentDelegation versus Communication in the Organization of Government
Delegation versus Communication in the Organization of Government
Stockholm Institute of Transition Economics
 
FQH Experimental Economics Final Paper
FQH Experimental Economics Final PaperFQH Experimental Economics Final Paper
FQH Experimental Economics Final PaperFaisal Haider
 
Msc Project - Hedging vs Speculating with derivative instruments
Msc Project - Hedging vs Speculating with derivative instrumentsMsc Project - Hedging vs Speculating with derivative instruments
Msc Project - Hedging vs Speculating with derivative instruments
Panos Charalampopoulos
 
Prisoner’s Dilemma in the Software Industry
Prisoner’s Dilemma in the Software IndustryPrisoner’s Dilemma in the Software Industry
Prisoner’s Dilemma in the Software Industry
Peter Louis
 
Dividend policy and share price volatility in kenya
Dividend policy and share price volatility in kenyaDividend policy and share price volatility in kenya
Dividend policy and share price volatility in kenya
Alexander Decker
 
A Nash equilibrium is a pair of strategies, one for each player, i.docx
A Nash equilibrium is a pair of strategies, one for each player, i.docxA Nash equilibrium is a pair of strategies, one for each player, i.docx
A Nash equilibrium is a pair of strategies, one for each player, i.docx
evonnehoggarth79783
 

Similar to Commitment in Alternating Offers Bargaining (20)

Game Theory Introduction
Game Theory IntroductionGame Theory Introduction
Game Theory Introduction
 
Nash Equilibrium
Nash EquilibriumNash Equilibrium
Nash Equilibrium
 
Mid term
Mid termMid term
Mid term
 
Legal contract presentation
Legal contract presentationLegal contract presentation
Legal contract presentation
 
Game Theory and Competitive Strategy / abshor.marantika / Devandra Nabila Aul...
Game Theory and Competitive Strategy / abshor.marantika / Devandra Nabila Aul...Game Theory and Competitive Strategy / abshor.marantika / Devandra Nabila Aul...
Game Theory and Competitive Strategy / abshor.marantika / Devandra Nabila Aul...
 
Contract theory
Contract theoryContract theory
Contract theory
 
A brief introduction to the basics of game theory
A brief introduction to the basics of game theoryA brief introduction to the basics of game theory
A brief introduction to the basics of game theory
 
A brief introduction to the basics of game theory
A brief introduction to the basics of game theoryA brief introduction to the basics of game theory
A brief introduction to the basics of game theory
 
Cdam 2001-09
Cdam 2001-09Cdam 2001-09
Cdam 2001-09
 
Game theory
Game theoryGame theory
Game theory
 
Ssrn a brief inrtoduction to the basic of game theory
Ssrn a brief inrtoduction to the basic of game theorySsrn a brief inrtoduction to the basic of game theory
Ssrn a brief inrtoduction to the basic of game theory
 
A Brief Introduction to the Basics of Game Theory
A Brief Introduction to the Basics of Game TheoryA Brief Introduction to the Basics of Game Theory
A Brief Introduction to the Basics of Game Theory
 
Delegation versus Communication in the Organization of Government
Delegation versus Communication in the Organization of GovernmentDelegation versus Communication in the Organization of Government
Delegation versus Communication in the Organization of Government
 
FQH Experimental Economics Final Paper
FQH Experimental Economics Final PaperFQH Experimental Economics Final Paper
FQH Experimental Economics Final Paper
 
Msc Project - Hedging vs Speculating with derivative instruments
Msc Project - Hedging vs Speculating with derivative instrumentsMsc Project - Hedging vs Speculating with derivative instruments
Msc Project - Hedging vs Speculating with derivative instruments
 
Sub1536
Sub1536Sub1536
Sub1536
 
Essay _ Anatoly
Essay _ AnatolyEssay _ Anatoly
Essay _ Anatoly
 
Prisoner’s Dilemma in the Software Industry
Prisoner’s Dilemma in the Software IndustryPrisoner’s Dilemma in the Software Industry
Prisoner’s Dilemma in the Software Industry
 
Dividend policy and share price volatility in kenya
Dividend policy and share price volatility in kenyaDividend policy and share price volatility in kenya
Dividend policy and share price volatility in kenya
 
A Nash equilibrium is a pair of strategies, one for each player, i.docx
A Nash equilibrium is a pair of strategies, one for each player, i.docxA Nash equilibrium is a pair of strategies, one for each player, i.docx
A Nash equilibrium is a pair of strategies, one for each player, i.docx
 

More from Stockholm Institute of Transition Economics

IT sector development fading | Belarus Conference in Stockholm
IT sector development fading | Belarus Conference in StockholmIT sector development fading | Belarus Conference in Stockholm
IT sector development fading | Belarus Conference in Stockholm
Stockholm Institute of Transition Economics
 
Corisk Sanctions of Russia | Belarus Conference in Stockholm
Corisk Sanctions of Russia | Belarus Conference in StockholmCorisk Sanctions of Russia | Belarus Conference in Stockholm
Corisk Sanctions of Russia | Belarus Conference in Stockholm
Stockholm Institute of Transition Economics
 
Selected Economic Effects of Sanctions | Belarus Conference in Stockholm
Selected Economic Effects of Sanctions | Belarus Conference in StockholmSelected Economic Effects of Sanctions | Belarus Conference in Stockholm
Selected Economic Effects of Sanctions | Belarus Conference in Stockholm
Stockholm Institute of Transition Economics
 
Belarusian Economy 2024 | Conference in Stockholm
Belarusian Economy 2024 | Conference in StockholmBelarusian Economy 2024 | Conference in Stockholm
Belarusian Economy 2024 | Conference in Stockholm
Stockholm Institute of Transition Economics
 
Tracking sanctions compliance | SITE 2023 Development Day conference
Tracking sanctions compliance | SITE 2023 Development Day conferenceTracking sanctions compliance | SITE 2023 Development Day conference
Tracking sanctions compliance | SITE 2023 Development Day conference
Stockholm Institute of Transition Economics
 
War and Trade in Eurasia | SITE 2023 Development Day conference
War and Trade in Eurasia | SITE 2023 Development Day conferenceWar and Trade in Eurasia | SITE 2023 Development Day conference
War and Trade in Eurasia | SITE 2023 Development Day conference
Stockholm Institute of Transition Economics
 
Reducing the Russian Economic Capacity and support Ukraine
Reducing the Russian Economic Capacity and support UkraineReducing the Russian Economic Capacity and support Ukraine
Reducing the Russian Economic Capacity and support Ukraine
Stockholm Institute of Transition Economics
 
Energy sanctions - What else can be done?
Energy sanctions - What else can be done?Energy sanctions - What else can be done?
Energy sanctions - What else can be done?
Stockholm Institute of Transition Economics
 
How should policy be designed during energy-economic warfare?
How should policy be designed during energy-economic warfare?How should policy be designed during energy-economic warfare?
How should policy be designed during energy-economic warfare?
Stockholm Institute of Transition Economics
 
The impact of the war on Russia’s fossil fuel earnings
The impact of the war on Russia’s fossil fuel earningsThe impact of the war on Russia’s fossil fuel earnings
The impact of the war on Russia’s fossil fuel earnings
Stockholm Institute of Transition Economics
 
The Russia sanctions as a human rights instrument: Violations of export contr...
The Russia sanctions as a human rights instrument: Violations of export contr...The Russia sanctions as a human rights instrument: Violations of export contr...
The Russia sanctions as a human rights instrument: Violations of export contr...
Stockholm Institute of Transition Economics
 
SITE 2022 Development Day conference program
SITE 2022 Development Day conference programSITE 2022 Development Day conference program
SITE 2022 Development Day conference program
Stockholm Institute of Transition Economics
 
SITE 2022 Development Day conference | Program
SITE 2022 Development Day conference | ProgramSITE 2022 Development Day conference | Program
SITE 2022 Development Day conference | Program
Stockholm Institute of Transition Economics
 
Program | SITE 2022 Development Day conference
Program | SITE 2022 Development Day conferenceProgram | SITE 2022 Development Day conference
Program | SITE 2022 Development Day conference
Stockholm Institute of Transition Economics
 
Ce^2 Conference 2022 Programme
Ce^2 Conference 2022 ProgrammeCe^2 Conference 2022 Programme
Ce^2 Conference 2022 Programme
Stockholm Institute of Transition Economics
 
Ce2 Worksop & Conference 2022 Program
Ce2 Worksop & Conference 2022 ProgramCe2 Worksop & Conference 2022 Program
Ce2 Worksop & Conference 2022 Program
Stockholm Institute of Transition Economics
 
Ce^2 Conference 2022 Program
Ce^2 Conference 2022 ProgramCe^2 Conference 2022 Program
Ce^2 Conference 2022 Program
Stockholm Institute of Transition Economics
 
(Ce)2 Workshop program (preliminary)
(Ce)2 Workshop program (preliminary)(Ce)2 Workshop program (preliminary)
(Ce)2 Workshop program (preliminary)
Stockholm Institute of Transition Economics
 
Unemployment and Intra-Household Dynamics: the Effect of Male Job Loss on Int...
Unemployment and Intra-Household Dynamics: the Effect of Male Job Loss on Int...Unemployment and Intra-Household Dynamics: the Effect of Male Job Loss on Int...
Unemployment and Intra-Household Dynamics: the Effect of Male Job Loss on Int...
Stockholm Institute of Transition Economics
 
Football, Alcohol and Domestic Abuse
Football, Alcohol and Domestic AbuseFootball, Alcohol and Domestic Abuse
Football, Alcohol and Domestic Abuse
Stockholm Institute of Transition Economics
 

More from Stockholm Institute of Transition Economics (20)

IT sector development fading | Belarus Conference in Stockholm
IT sector development fading | Belarus Conference in StockholmIT sector development fading | Belarus Conference in Stockholm
IT sector development fading | Belarus Conference in Stockholm
 
Corisk Sanctions of Russia | Belarus Conference in Stockholm
Corisk Sanctions of Russia | Belarus Conference in StockholmCorisk Sanctions of Russia | Belarus Conference in Stockholm
Corisk Sanctions of Russia | Belarus Conference in Stockholm
 
Selected Economic Effects of Sanctions | Belarus Conference in Stockholm
Selected Economic Effects of Sanctions | Belarus Conference in StockholmSelected Economic Effects of Sanctions | Belarus Conference in Stockholm
Selected Economic Effects of Sanctions | Belarus Conference in Stockholm
 
Belarusian Economy 2024 | Conference in Stockholm
Belarusian Economy 2024 | Conference in StockholmBelarusian Economy 2024 | Conference in Stockholm
Belarusian Economy 2024 | Conference in Stockholm
 
Tracking sanctions compliance | SITE 2023 Development Day conference
Tracking sanctions compliance | SITE 2023 Development Day conferenceTracking sanctions compliance | SITE 2023 Development Day conference
Tracking sanctions compliance | SITE 2023 Development Day conference
 
War and Trade in Eurasia | SITE 2023 Development Day conference
War and Trade in Eurasia | SITE 2023 Development Day conferenceWar and Trade in Eurasia | SITE 2023 Development Day conference
War and Trade in Eurasia | SITE 2023 Development Day conference
 
Reducing the Russian Economic Capacity and support Ukraine
Reducing the Russian Economic Capacity and support UkraineReducing the Russian Economic Capacity and support Ukraine
Reducing the Russian Economic Capacity and support Ukraine
 
Energy sanctions - What else can be done?
Energy sanctions - What else can be done?Energy sanctions - What else can be done?
Energy sanctions - What else can be done?
 
How should policy be designed during energy-economic warfare?
How should policy be designed during energy-economic warfare?How should policy be designed during energy-economic warfare?
How should policy be designed during energy-economic warfare?
 
The impact of the war on Russia’s fossil fuel earnings
The impact of the war on Russia’s fossil fuel earningsThe impact of the war on Russia’s fossil fuel earnings
The impact of the war on Russia’s fossil fuel earnings
 
The Russia sanctions as a human rights instrument: Violations of export contr...
The Russia sanctions as a human rights instrument: Violations of export contr...The Russia sanctions as a human rights instrument: Violations of export contr...
The Russia sanctions as a human rights instrument: Violations of export contr...
 
SITE 2022 Development Day conference program
SITE 2022 Development Day conference programSITE 2022 Development Day conference program
SITE 2022 Development Day conference program
 
SITE 2022 Development Day conference | Program
SITE 2022 Development Day conference | ProgramSITE 2022 Development Day conference | Program
SITE 2022 Development Day conference | Program
 
Program | SITE 2022 Development Day conference
Program | SITE 2022 Development Day conferenceProgram | SITE 2022 Development Day conference
Program | SITE 2022 Development Day conference
 
Ce^2 Conference 2022 Programme
Ce^2 Conference 2022 ProgrammeCe^2 Conference 2022 Programme
Ce^2 Conference 2022 Programme
 
Ce2 Worksop & Conference 2022 Program
Ce2 Worksop & Conference 2022 ProgramCe2 Worksop & Conference 2022 Program
Ce2 Worksop & Conference 2022 Program
 
Ce^2 Conference 2022 Program
Ce^2 Conference 2022 ProgramCe^2 Conference 2022 Program
Ce^2 Conference 2022 Program
 
(Ce)2 Workshop program (preliminary)
(Ce)2 Workshop program (preliminary)(Ce)2 Workshop program (preliminary)
(Ce)2 Workshop program (preliminary)
 
Unemployment and Intra-Household Dynamics: the Effect of Male Job Loss on Int...
Unemployment and Intra-Household Dynamics: the Effect of Male Job Loss on Int...Unemployment and Intra-Household Dynamics: the Effect of Male Job Loss on Int...
Unemployment and Intra-Household Dynamics: the Effect of Male Job Loss on Int...
 
Football, Alcohol and Domestic Abuse
Football, Alcohol and Domestic AbuseFootball, Alcohol and Domestic Abuse
Football, Alcohol and Domestic Abuse
 

Recently uploaded

This assessment plan proposal is to outline a structured approach to evaluati...
This assessment plan proposal is to outline a structured approach to evaluati...This assessment plan proposal is to outline a structured approach to evaluati...
This assessment plan proposal is to outline a structured approach to evaluati...
lamluanvan.net Viết thuê luận văn
 
What price will pi network be listed on exchanges
What price will pi network be listed on exchangesWhat price will pi network be listed on exchanges
What price will pi network be listed on exchanges
DOT TECH
 
Poonawalla Fincorp and IndusInd Bank Introduce New Co-Branded Credit Card
Poonawalla Fincorp and IndusInd Bank Introduce New Co-Branded Credit CardPoonawalla Fincorp and IndusInd Bank Introduce New Co-Branded Credit Card
Poonawalla Fincorp and IndusInd Bank Introduce New Co-Branded Credit Card
nickysharmasucks
 
The WhatsPump Pseudonym Problem and the Hilarious Downfall of Artificial Enga...
The WhatsPump Pseudonym Problem and the Hilarious Downfall of Artificial Enga...The WhatsPump Pseudonym Problem and the Hilarious Downfall of Artificial Enga...
The WhatsPump Pseudonym Problem and the Hilarious Downfall of Artificial Enga...
muslimdavidovich670
 
655264371-checkpoint-science-past-papers-april-2023.pdf
655264371-checkpoint-science-past-papers-april-2023.pdf655264371-checkpoint-science-past-papers-april-2023.pdf
655264371-checkpoint-science-past-papers-april-2023.pdf
morearsh02
 
Exploring Abhay Bhutada’s Views After Poonawalla Fincorp’s Collaboration With...
Exploring Abhay Bhutada’s Views After Poonawalla Fincorp’s Collaboration With...Exploring Abhay Bhutada’s Views After Poonawalla Fincorp’s Collaboration With...
Exploring Abhay Bhutada’s Views After Poonawalla Fincorp’s Collaboration With...
beulahfernandes8
 
US Economic Outlook - Being Decided - M Capital Group August 2021.pdf
US Economic Outlook - Being Decided - M Capital Group August 2021.pdfUS Economic Outlook - Being Decided - M Capital Group August 2021.pdf
US Economic Outlook - Being Decided - M Capital Group August 2021.pdf
pchutichetpong
 
when will pi network coin be available on crypto exchange.
when will pi network coin be available on crypto exchange.when will pi network coin be available on crypto exchange.
when will pi network coin be available on crypto exchange.
DOT TECH
 
Intro_Economics_ GPresentation Week 4.pptx
Intro_Economics_ GPresentation Week 4.pptxIntro_Economics_ GPresentation Week 4.pptx
Intro_Economics_ GPresentation Week 4.pptx
shetivia
 
Empowering the Unbanked: The Vital Role of NBFCs in Promoting Financial Inclu...
Empowering the Unbanked: The Vital Role of NBFCs in Promoting Financial Inclu...Empowering the Unbanked: The Vital Role of NBFCs in Promoting Financial Inclu...
Empowering the Unbanked: The Vital Role of NBFCs in Promoting Financial Inclu...
Vighnesh Shashtri
 
innovative-invoice-discounting-platforms-in-india-empowering-retail-investors...
innovative-invoice-discounting-platforms-in-india-empowering-retail-investors...innovative-invoice-discounting-platforms-in-india-empowering-retail-investors...
innovative-invoice-discounting-platforms-in-india-empowering-retail-investors...
Falcon Invoice Discounting
 
where can I find a legit pi merchant online
where can I find a legit pi merchant onlinewhere can I find a legit pi merchant online
where can I find a legit pi merchant online
DOT TECH
 
what is a pi whale and how to access one.
what is a pi whale and how to access one.what is a pi whale and how to access one.
what is a pi whale and how to access one.
DOT TECH
 
managementaccountingunitiv-230422140105-dd17d80b.ppt
managementaccountingunitiv-230422140105-dd17d80b.pptmanagementaccountingunitiv-230422140105-dd17d80b.ppt
managementaccountingunitiv-230422140105-dd17d80b.ppt
SuseelaPalanimuthu
 
Summary of financial results for 1Q2024
Summary of financial  results for 1Q2024Summary of financial  results for 1Q2024
Summary of financial results for 1Q2024
InterCars
 
一比一原版BCU毕业证伯明翰城市大学毕业证成绩单如何办理
一比一原版BCU毕业证伯明翰城市大学毕业证成绩单如何办理一比一原版BCU毕业证伯明翰城市大学毕业证成绩单如何办理
一比一原版BCU毕业证伯明翰城市大学毕业证成绩单如何办理
ydubwyt
 
How to get verified on Coinbase Account?_.docx
How to get verified on Coinbase Account?_.docxHow to get verified on Coinbase Account?_.docx
How to get verified on Coinbase Account?_.docx
Buy bitget
 
how can I sell/buy bulk pi coins securely
how can I sell/buy bulk pi coins securelyhow can I sell/buy bulk pi coins securely
how can I sell/buy bulk pi coins securely
DOT TECH
 
Introduction to Value Added Tax System.ppt
Introduction to Value Added Tax System.pptIntroduction to Value Added Tax System.ppt
Introduction to Value Added Tax System.ppt
VishnuVenugopal84
 
The secret way to sell pi coins effortlessly.
The secret way to sell pi coins effortlessly.The secret way to sell pi coins effortlessly.
The secret way to sell pi coins effortlessly.
DOT TECH
 

Recently uploaded (20)

This assessment plan proposal is to outline a structured approach to evaluati...
This assessment plan proposal is to outline a structured approach to evaluati...This assessment plan proposal is to outline a structured approach to evaluati...
This assessment plan proposal is to outline a structured approach to evaluati...
 
What price will pi network be listed on exchanges
What price will pi network be listed on exchangesWhat price will pi network be listed on exchanges
What price will pi network be listed on exchanges
 
Poonawalla Fincorp and IndusInd Bank Introduce New Co-Branded Credit Card
Poonawalla Fincorp and IndusInd Bank Introduce New Co-Branded Credit CardPoonawalla Fincorp and IndusInd Bank Introduce New Co-Branded Credit Card
Poonawalla Fincorp and IndusInd Bank Introduce New Co-Branded Credit Card
 
The WhatsPump Pseudonym Problem and the Hilarious Downfall of Artificial Enga...
The WhatsPump Pseudonym Problem and the Hilarious Downfall of Artificial Enga...The WhatsPump Pseudonym Problem and the Hilarious Downfall of Artificial Enga...
The WhatsPump Pseudonym Problem and the Hilarious Downfall of Artificial Enga...
 
655264371-checkpoint-science-past-papers-april-2023.pdf
655264371-checkpoint-science-past-papers-april-2023.pdf655264371-checkpoint-science-past-papers-april-2023.pdf
655264371-checkpoint-science-past-papers-april-2023.pdf
 
Exploring Abhay Bhutada’s Views After Poonawalla Fincorp’s Collaboration With...
Exploring Abhay Bhutada’s Views After Poonawalla Fincorp’s Collaboration With...Exploring Abhay Bhutada’s Views After Poonawalla Fincorp’s Collaboration With...
Exploring Abhay Bhutada’s Views After Poonawalla Fincorp’s Collaboration With...
 
US Economic Outlook - Being Decided - M Capital Group August 2021.pdf
US Economic Outlook - Being Decided - M Capital Group August 2021.pdfUS Economic Outlook - Being Decided - M Capital Group August 2021.pdf
US Economic Outlook - Being Decided - M Capital Group August 2021.pdf
 
when will pi network coin be available on crypto exchange.
when will pi network coin be available on crypto exchange.when will pi network coin be available on crypto exchange.
when will pi network coin be available on crypto exchange.
 
Intro_Economics_ GPresentation Week 4.pptx
Intro_Economics_ GPresentation Week 4.pptxIntro_Economics_ GPresentation Week 4.pptx
Intro_Economics_ GPresentation Week 4.pptx
 
Empowering the Unbanked: The Vital Role of NBFCs in Promoting Financial Inclu...
Empowering the Unbanked: The Vital Role of NBFCs in Promoting Financial Inclu...Empowering the Unbanked: The Vital Role of NBFCs in Promoting Financial Inclu...
Empowering the Unbanked: The Vital Role of NBFCs in Promoting Financial Inclu...
 
innovative-invoice-discounting-platforms-in-india-empowering-retail-investors...
innovative-invoice-discounting-platforms-in-india-empowering-retail-investors...innovative-invoice-discounting-platforms-in-india-empowering-retail-investors...
innovative-invoice-discounting-platforms-in-india-empowering-retail-investors...
 
where can I find a legit pi merchant online
where can I find a legit pi merchant onlinewhere can I find a legit pi merchant online
where can I find a legit pi merchant online
 
what is a pi whale and how to access one.
what is a pi whale and how to access one.what is a pi whale and how to access one.
what is a pi whale and how to access one.
 
managementaccountingunitiv-230422140105-dd17d80b.ppt
managementaccountingunitiv-230422140105-dd17d80b.pptmanagementaccountingunitiv-230422140105-dd17d80b.ppt
managementaccountingunitiv-230422140105-dd17d80b.ppt
 
Summary of financial results for 1Q2024
Summary of financial  results for 1Q2024Summary of financial  results for 1Q2024
Summary of financial results for 1Q2024
 
一比一原版BCU毕业证伯明翰城市大学毕业证成绩单如何办理
一比一原版BCU毕业证伯明翰城市大学毕业证成绩单如何办理一比一原版BCU毕业证伯明翰城市大学毕业证成绩单如何办理
一比一原版BCU毕业证伯明翰城市大学毕业证成绩单如何办理
 
How to get verified on Coinbase Account?_.docx
How to get verified on Coinbase Account?_.docxHow to get verified on Coinbase Account?_.docx
How to get verified on Coinbase Account?_.docx
 
how can I sell/buy bulk pi coins securely
how can I sell/buy bulk pi coins securelyhow can I sell/buy bulk pi coins securely
how can I sell/buy bulk pi coins securely
 
Introduction to Value Added Tax System.ppt
Introduction to Value Added Tax System.pptIntroduction to Value Added Tax System.ppt
Introduction to Value Added Tax System.ppt
 
The secret way to sell pi coins effortlessly.
The secret way to sell pi coins effortlessly.The secret way to sell pi coins effortlessly.
The secret way to sell pi coins effortlessly.
 

Commitment in Alternating Offers Bargaining

  • 1. Commitment in Alternating O¤ers Bargaining Topi Miettinen Stockholm School of Economics Andrés Perea Maastricht University This version: September 2010 Abstract We extend the Ståhl-Rubinstein alternating-o¤er bargaining procedure to allow players, prior to each bargaining round, to simultaneously and visibly commit to some share of the pie. If commitment costs are small but increasing in the committed share, then the unique outcome consistent with common belief in future rationality (Perea, 2010), or more restric- tively subgame perfect Nash equilibrium, exhibits a second mover advantage. In particular, as the smallest share of the pie approaches zero, the horizon approaches in…nity, and com- mitment costs approach zero, the unique bargaining outcome corresponds to the reversed Rubinstein outcome ( =(1 + ); 1=(1 + )), where is the common discount factor. KEYWORDS: alternating o¤er bargaining, bargaining power, commitment, epistemic game theory, patience JEL CODES: C73, C78, D84 Topi Miettinen: Stockholm School of Economics P.O. Box 6501, Sveavägen 65, SE-113 83 Stockholm, Sweden. topi.miettinen@hhs.se Web: http://www2.hhs.se/SITE/homepages/topi.html Andrés Perea: Maastricht University, Department of Quantitative Economics P.O. Box 616, 6200 MD Maastricht, The Netherlands. a.perea@maastrichtuniversity.nl Web: http://www.personeel.unimaas.nl/a.perea/ We would like to thank Tore Ellingsen and Jörgen Weibull for insightful comments.
  • 2. 1. Introduction "...it has not been uncommon for union o¢ cials to stir up excitement and determination on the part of the membership during or prior to a wage negotiation. If the union is going to insist on $2 and expects the management to counter with $1.60, an e¤ort is made to persuade the membership not only that the management could pay $2 but even perhaps that the negotiators themselves are incompetent if they fail to obtain close to $2. The purpose ... is to make clear to the management that the negotiators could not accept less than $2 even if they wished to because they no longer control the members or because they would lose their own positions if they tried." In this quotation from his classic book, Schelling (1960) vividly illustrates that strategic commitment is often an essential feature of bargaining tactics and that parties of negotiations often have access to actions that commit them to some strategically chosen bargaining position. During the 50 years that have followed, however, there has been fairly little progress in game theoretic analysis of such commitments. Notable exceptions are Crawford (1982), Muthoo (1992, 1996), and more recently Ellingsen and Miettinen (2008, 2010) and Li (2010). In this paper, we follow Muthoo (1992), Li (2010) and Ellingsen and Miettinen (2010) and consider the e¤ect of commitment strategies in a dynamic complete information bargaining framework. We limit attention to the …nite horizon alternating o¤er game (Ståhl, 1972; Ru- binstein, 1982) although we do study the in…nite horizon limit. We model parties who can, simultaneously and prior to each alternating o¤er, commit not to agree on any share smaller than speci…ed in the commitment. Strategic commitment is assumed to incur small costs. These costs are increasing in the share to which the party commits re‡ecting the idea that more re- sources must be invested to build a credible commitment when the opportunity cost of turning down a deal is larger. After each round of bargaining, any prior commitments are relaxed and players may again choose a commitment to any share they wish. Our work builds heavily upon the work of Rubinstein (1982) and Ellingsen and Miettinen (2008). The main insight of Rubinstein’s pioneering work on bargaining is that, under complete information, equilibrium strategies are determined by the relative impatience of the bargaining parties. In equilibrium, the proposer makes an o¤er so that the responder is indi¤erent between accepting the o¤er and rejecting it, given the cost of waiting; and the responder accepts the o¤er. Thus there is an e¢ cient immediate agreement with a …rst-mover advantage. Ellingsen and Miettinen (2008) recently illustrated how mutual attempts of aggressive incompatible com- mitment may be unavoidable in bilateral bargaining, if commitments can only be attempted prior to the negotiations and they are not certain to succeed. With certain commitments, it is better to remain ‡exible and sign on the other’s o¤er than to commit oneself, especially if commitment incurs a small cost. Yet, a very aggressive commitment is the best-response to not committing at all. The opponent’s aggressive commitment leaves little room of manoeuvre and thus even small loopholes in the opponent’s commitment invite betting on being the only one to succeed in an aggressive commitment attempt despite the risk of an impasse. 2
  • 3. In the present context we show that, in line with Rubinstein (1982) and contrary to Ellingsen and Miettinen (2008), the deal is always stroke immediately. However, contrary to Rubinstein’s outcome, there is a second-mover advantage rather than a …rst-mover advantage! This is sur- prising, as both parties commit simultaneously at the beginning of every round and there are no exogenous asymmetries in the commitment technology. The intuition for the result is the fol- lowing: commitments are short-lasting and there is no uncertainty about who has the initiative (pre-determined alternating o¤ers structure). Thus, the …rst one to propose does not have to worry about committing before her proposal; whatever share the second-mover commits to, it is best for the …rst-mover to avoid any costs by refraining from committing. In equilibrium she proposes the second-mover the share he commits to and takes the residual share herself, provided that the residual makes her better o¤ than waiting for the follow-up round. Knowing this, the second-mover will commit up to the share that makes the …rst-mover indi¤erent between having the residual share and waiting. Thus, the presence of symmetric commitment strategies entirely reverses the bargaining power of the parties! In the limit, where the cost of commitment and the smallest indivisible share of the pie approach zero, and where the number of rounds approaches in…nity, the outcome approaches the reversed Rubinstein (1982) outcome, ( =(1 + ); 1=(1 + )), where is the common discount factor. We analyze the game using the concept of common belief in future rationality (Perea, 2010), meaning that both players always believe that the opponent will choose rationally now and in the future, that both players always believe that both players always believe that the opponent will choose rationally now and in the future, and so on. This concept is a typical backward induction concept as it assumes that players, throughout the game, only reason about the future, and not about the past. In fact, in generic games with perfect information, common belief in future rationality leads to the unique backward induction strategy for every player. The concept is weaker, but at the same time more basic, than subgame perfect equilibrium as no equilibrium condition is being imposed1. As Perea (2010) has shown, the strategies that may be chosen under common belief in future rationality can be computed by the algorithm of backward dominance. Since every subgame perfect equilibrium of the game survives the backward dominance procedure, it follows that the outcome of the bargaining game described above is also the unique subgame perfect equilibrium outcome of the game. Our analysis contributes to the agenda, initiated by Schelling (1956), of carefully analyzing and understanding commitment institutions and mechanisms and their implications on the bar- gaining outcomes. Among the related works, Crawford (1982) and Muthoo (1992, 1996) have studied the e¤ects of revocable commitments; in our model in contrast, commitments auto- 1 Another non-equilibrium concept which has been developed for dynamic games is extensive form rationalizabil- ity (Pearce (1984), Battigalli (1997), Battigalli and Siniscalchi (2002)). However, extensive form rationalizability is a typical forward induction concept, which requires players also to critically reason about the opponents’past choices, and not only about the opponents’ present and future choices, as common belief in future rationality does. In many dynamic games, extensive form rationalizability and common belief in future rationality lead to di¤erent strategy choices for the players . 3
  • 4. matically vanish but parties can make a costly recommitment to any share they like after each round. Ellingsen and Miettinen (2008, 2010) analyze costly and long-lasting precommitment to o¤ers and thus they cannot be freely adjusted after each round. Also, unlike in Ellingsen and Miettinen (2008, 2010), players do not commit directly to proposals in our model, but rather to veto any deal where their share is smaller than their commitment. In this respect the model resembles those of Muthoo (1992, 1996) and the endogenous commitment models analyzed in Fershtman and Seidmann (1993), Li (2007), and Miettinen (2010), in which yet, the smallest acceptable shares are determined by the bargaining history in some exogenously determined way rather than freely chosen by players. Schelling also mentions reputation as an important means of pre-commitment. Myerson (1991) and Abreu and Gul (2000) analyze such reputation contexts where one party has in- complete information about the opponent’s stubbornness not to accept anything less than an exogenously given share of the pie. The opponent can then use commitment tactics that exploit this incomplete information and strategically mimic stubbornness in order to force concessions from the other party. This induces delay and in‡uences the …nal sharing. Outside options bear a close relation to the current complete information alternating o¤er bargaining model. Compte and Jehiel (2002) show that exogenous outside options may alto- gether eliminate the strategic e¤ects of reputation for stubbornness. It has also been shown that, when a party, by opting out, gets a payo¤ that is inferior to the equilibrium payo¤ he would obtain in the game without outside options, then these latter have no e¤ect on the equilibrium outcomes (Binmore et al. 1989). In our setting deliberately chosen commitment strategies in- ‡uence bargaining outcomes exactly because they are chosen so as to force concessions superior to those in the Rubinstein outcome. The results closest in spirit to ours are perhaps Dixit’s (1980) extension of the Spence-Dixit excess capacity model and Ellingsen’s (1995) analysis of timing in oligopoly. Dixit shows that an incumbent …rm, who nevertheless is presumed to play the role of the follower, can use the commitment, provided by an excess capacity investment, in seizing limited initiative back from the entrant. Ellingsen shows in a Cournot duopoly setting that, if one of the …rms alone can choose to pile up investment later, that …rm will endogenously end up in the Stackelberg follower position, whereas the …rm who can only invest at present will become the leader.2 The paper is organized as follows. In Section 2, we set up the model and the bargaining procedure. In Section 3 we present the concept of common belief in future rationality, and the associated algorithm of backward dominance. In Section 4 we analyze the model with one round of bargaining. We will use it as a benchmark for our analysis of more than one round in Section 5. We also investigate the limit behavior of this outcome, when the commitment costs go to zero and the number of rounds goes to in…nity. We conclude in Section 6. 2 These are the only strategies surviving iterated elimination of weakly dominated strategies. 4
  • 5. 2. The Bargaining Procedure There are two players, 1 and 2, who must reach an agreement about the division of one unit of some good. We assume that the smallest amount is 1=K for some integer number K: Let X := f0; 1=K; 2=K; :::; 1g: Hence, the set of possible divisions is given by D := f(x1; x2) : x1; x2 2 X and x1 + x2 1g: Players 1 and 2 use the following bargaining procedure, which can last for at most N rounds. Round 1: At the beginning, both players simultaneously choose commitment levels c1; c2 2 X: The commitment levels become known to both players, and player 1 proposes a division (x1; x2) 2 D with x1 c1: Subsequently, player 2 decides whether to accept or reject the proposal under the condition that he can only accept o¤ers with x2 c2: If he accepts, (x1; x2) is the …nal outcome. If he rejects, the game moves to round 2. Round 2: At the beginning, both players simultaneously choose new commitment levels c1; c2 2 X: Afterwards, player 2 proposes a division (x1; x2) 2 D with x2 c2: Subsequently, player 1 decides whether to accept or reject (x1; x2); under the condition that he can only accept o¤ers with x1 c1: If he accepts, (x1; x2) is the …nal outcome. If he rejects, the game moves to round 3. Round 3: This is a repetition of round 1. And so on. This bargaining procedure goes on until an agreement is reached, or the process enters round N + 1: In round N + 1; a given division (y1; y2) 2 D is realized. We assume that both players incur a cost for commitment, and that this cost is increasing in the amount to which the player commits. The reason for the latter is that the higher the amount to which the player commits, the more di¢ cult it will be to stick to this commitment. More precisely, if player i commits to an amount ci; this will cost him ci; where is some small positive number. For convenience, we assume that is the same for both players. We …nally assume that both players discount future payo¤s by a common discount factor : So, in view of all the above, the players’ utilities are as follows: If the players reach an agreement on division (x1; x2) in round n; then the utility for player i is n 1 xi c1 i + c2 i + ::: + n 1 cn i ; where ck i is the commitment level chosen at round k: If the game reaches round N +1; his utility would be N yi c1 i + c2 i + ::: + N 1 cN i : In order to avoid uninteresting indi¤erences, we assume that is such that a player is never indi¤erent between two outcomes that are realized at two di¤erent rounds. Note that for every open interval (a; b) in [0; 1]; we can always …nd such a that lies in (a; b); since there are only 5
  • 6. …nitely many rounds, and …nitely many divisions and commitment levels at every round. By choosing is this way, we guarantee that a player will never be indi¤erent between accepting and rejecting an o¤er. This, eventually, will lead to a unique outcome in the bargaining game, which makes our analysis more transparent. Within our bargaining procedure above, the interpretation of the commitment levels is thus that the proposer commits to never o¤er less than his commitment level for himself, whereas the responder commits to reject any o¤er that would give him less than his commitment level. With this interpretation in mind, it makes intuitive sense that the cost of commitment is assumed to be increasing in the commitment level. A higher commitment level, namely, more heavily restricts the subsequent choice set of the player, and for higher commitment levels, makes it more tempting for this player to break his commitment. The higher cost of commitment for larger shares should in this way re‡ect the larger opportunity cost. 3. Common Belief in Future Rationality The concept we use to analyze the game is common belief in future rationality (Perea, 2010). In this concept, we assume that a player always believes that his opponent will choose rationally now and in the future, that a player always believes that his opponent always believes that he will choose rationally now and in the future, and so on. It is thus a typical backward induction concept, as a player is only required to reason about the opponents’choices in the future of the game, and not about the opponents’ past choices. In that sense, is di¤ers considerably from the notion of extensive form rationalizability (Pearce, 1984; Battigalli, 1997; Battigalli and Siniscalchi, 2002), which is a typical forward induction concept, requiring players also to think critically about opponents’past choices, and where possible try to draw conclusions from these about possible future moves by this opponent. In many dynamic games, common belief in future rationality and extensive form rationalizability select di¤erent strategy choices for the players. In fact, in terms of strategy choices there is no general logical relationship between the two concepts –in some games the former can be more restrictive, in other games the latter can be more restrictive, and in yet some other games they may select completely opposed strategies for a given player. For a formal de…nition of common belief in future rationality within an epistemic model the reader is referred to Perea (2010). In that paper, it is also shown that the strategies that can rationally be chosen under common belief in future rationality are characterized by an elimination procedure called backward dominance. For dynamic games with observed past choices3, such as the game we consider in this paper, the backward dominance procedure works as follows: We start at the ultimate subgames, that is, those subgames after which the game is over. At each of those subgames, we restrict to strategies that reach this subgame, and 3 That is, games that may include simultaneous moves, but where the players always observe which choices have been made by the opponents in the past. 6
  • 7. apply iterated strict dominance (or, iterated elimination of strictly dominated strategies) to this restricted game. We then move to penultimate subgames, that is, subgames after which either the game is over or an ultimate subgame starts. At each of those subgames, we restrict to strategies that reach this subgame and that have not been eliminated yet by the procedure. We then apply iterated strict dominance to these restricted games. And so on, until we reach the beginning of the game. There, we restrict to strategies that have not been eliminated yet, and apply iterated strict dominance to this restricted game. The strategies that survive the …nal round of iterated strict dominance at the beginning of the game are said to survive the backward dominance procedure. For dynamic games with observed past choices, subgame perfect equilibrium is a strict re…ne- ment of common belief in future rationality. That is, every strategy that is optimal in a subgame perfect equilibrium can also be chosen rationally under common belief in future rationality, but not vice versa (Perea, 2010). So, common belief in future rationality is weaker than subgame perfect equilibrium. At the same time, we believe it is a more basic concept than subgame perfect equilibrium, as no equilibrium condition is being imposed –we only require a player to believe that his opponent chooses rationally now and in the future, that he believes that his opponent reasons in this way as well, and so on. No other conditions are being imposed. If we apply common belief in future rationality to generic games with perfect information, we obtain the usual backward induction procedure, and hence the unique backward induction strategy for every player. This con…rms the intuition that it is indeed a backward induction concept. 4. The Case of One Round We start with the easiest case, namely when there is only one round of bargaining. For this case, we already encounter a surprising result: Under common belief in future rationality (and hence also under subgame perfect equilibrium) the proposer faces a …rst-mover disadvantage, rather than a …rst-mover advantage. Actually, we can say a little more, namely the proposer gets exactly what he would obtain as a responder in the procedure without commitment. So, introducing the possibility to commit reverses the outcome completely! All this is obtained under the assumption that the commitment costs are su¢ ciently small. More precisely, we require < 1 : Theorem 4.1. (Case of one round) Consider the procedure with only one round of bargaining, and suppose that < 1 . Then, under common belief in future rationality, player 1 chooses commitment level 0, player 2 chooses commitment level 1 y1; player 1 proposes ( y1; 1 y1) and player 2 accepts. Here, x denotes the smallest number in X larger than, or equal to, x: Remember that (y1; y2) is the outcome if the proposal is rejected. So, player 1, the proposer, gets the minimal amount 7
  • 8. he would still accept, whereas player 2, the responder, gets all the surplus! Notice that in the classical bargaining procedure without commitment, this would be exactly the outcome when player 2 would be the proposer and player 1 the responder. Proof. For every pair (c1; c2) of commitment levels, the subgame that starts after (c1; c2) is a game with perfect information. Hence, applying backward dominance to this subgame is the same as using backward induction. After every (c1; c2); the backward induction outcome is as follows: 1. If c1 + c2 > 1; or c1 > 1 y2; then player 2 will reject any proposal by player 1. Hence, the outcome will be (y1; y2); with utility y1 c1 for player 1, and utility y2 c2 for player 2. 2. If c2 > 1 y1; then player 1 does not want to make any o¤er that player 2 would accept. Hence, the outcome will be (y1; y2); with utility y1 c1 for player 1, and utility y2 c2 for player 2. 3. Suppose that c1 + c2 1 and y2 < c2 < 1 y1: Then, the best that player 1 can do is to o¤er player 2 precisely c2; which player 2 would accept. So, the outcome would be (1 c2; c2); with utility 1 c2 c1 for player 1, and utility c2 c2 for player 2. 4. Suppose that c1 < 1 y2 and c2 < y2: Then, the best that player 1 can do is to o¤er player 2 exactly y2; which player 2 would accept. So, the outcome would be (1 y2; y2); with utility 1 y2 c1 for player 1, and utility y2 c2 for player 2. It can easily be seen that this covers all possible cases. In Figure 1 we have depicted the backwards induction utilities for both players after every possible pair (c1; c2): So, Figure 1 represents exactly the restricted game that the backward dominance procedure would consider at the beginning of the game. In order to …nish the backward dominance procedure, we must apply iterated strict dominance to the game in Figure 1. From player 1’s utilities in Figure 1 it is easily veri…ed that, for every c2; player 1’s utility is decreasing in his commitment level c1: This means, however, that c1 = 0 strictly dominates every other c1 for player 1. So, we eliminate all c1 > 0 for player 1, which leaves only c1 = 0: But then, in the reduced game that remains, player 2’s best choice is c2 = 1 y1: Here, we use the assumption that < 1 : As we have seen above, the best that player 1 can do in this case is to propose ( y1; 1 y1); which player 2 would accept. So, by applying the backward dominance procedure, we obtain that player 1 chooses commitment level c1 = 0; player 2 chooses c2 = 1 y1; player 1 proposes ( y1; 1 y1) and player 2 accepts. This completes the proof. Theorem 4.1 illustrates two points. First, by setting y1 = y2 = 0, one can see that in a single round ultimatum bargaining game, the second mover will reap the entire pie. Second, by setting y1 = =(1 + ) and y2 = 1=(1 + ); we would e¤ectively add a simultaneous move 8
  • 9. @ @ @ @ @ @ @@ y1 c1; y2 c2 1 c2 c1; c2 c2 1 y2 c1; y2 c2 1 y2 y2 1 y1 c1 c2 Figure 1: The case of one round: Backward induction utilities after every pair (c1; c1) 9
  • 10. commitment stage to the alternating-o¤er protocol such that precommitments are valid only in the …rst round of bargaining. Our result shows that this would in fact put the recipient of the …rst o¤er in an even more advantageous position than where the proposer in the game without commitments is: the recipient of the …rst proposal commits to 1 2 =(1+ ) = 1+ 2 1+ and leaves only 2 =(1 + ) to the …rst mover. 5. The Case of More Rounds We now turn to the case of more than one round. Also in this case, common belief in future rationality leads to a unique outcome, where the proposer at round 1 faces a …rst-mover dis- advantage, rather than a …rst-mover advantage. Actually, when the commitment cost tends to zero, then the …rst proposer gets exactly what he would obtain as the …rst responder in the procedure without commitment, and vice versa. So, again, introducing the possibility to com- mit completely reverses the outcome as tends to zero! As every subgame perfect equilibrium satis…es common belief in future rationality (Perea, 2010), it follows that this outcome is also the unique subgame perfect equilibrium outcome in the game. Theorem 5.1. (Case of more than one round) Suppose that the bargaining procedure consists of N potential rounds, and that < 1 . Let p denote the proposer at round 1, and r the responder at round 1. Then, common belief in future rationality leads to a unique outcome, namely at round 1 proposer p commits to cp = 0, responder r commits to cr = xN r ; proposer p proposes the division (xN p ; xN r ) and responder r accepts, where xN p ; xN r are recursively given by x1 p = yp; x1 r = 1 yp; xN p = (1 )xN 1 r ; and xN r = 1 (1 )xN 1 r ; for every N 2: If we let tend to zero, then the recursive equations above would exactly yield the outcomes for the players in the procedure without commitment, but with the roles of the proposer and responder reversed! If the size of the smallest slice 1=K is small, then the amounts xN p and xN r are approximately equal to xN p (1 ) + ( 1)n n (1 )n 1 + (1 ) + ( 1)n 1 n (1 )n 1 yp and xN r 1 ( 1)n n (1 )n 1 + (1 ) ( 1)n 1 n (1 )n 1 yp: 10
  • 11. Recall that yp is the amount that player p would get at the end of the game, when all proposals have been rejected. These approximations are obtained by setting x = x in the recursive equations above, and solving them. If the number of rounds N becomes very large, then xN p (1 ) 1 + (1 ) and xN r 1 1 + (1 ) which shows that there is a clear …rst-mover disadvantage. If in addition the commitment cost would tend to zero, then in the limit we would obtain the reversed Rubinstein outcome xN p 1 + and xN r 1 1 + : Proof of Theorem 5.1. We prove the statement by induction on the number of rounds. If N = 1; then the statement follows immediately from Theorem 4.1. Now, assume that N 2; and that the statement holds for the procedure with N 1 rounds. Let p be the proposer at round 1, and r the responder at round 1. Suppose that the proposal at round 1 would be rejected. Then, the subgame that starts at round 2 is a procedure with N 1 rounds, where r is the …rst proposer and p is the …rst responder. The commitment costs incurred at round 1 are sunk costs, and therefore do not a¤ect the analysis in this subgame. By our induction assumption we know that in this subgame, common belief in future rationality (or, equivalently, the backward dominance procedure) leads to a unique outcome: player r chooses commitment level cr = 0; player p chooses commitment level cp = xN 1 r ; player r proposes xN 1 p for himself and xN 1 r for player p; and player p accepts. The corresponding utilities would be xN 1 r xN 1 r = (1 )xN 1 r for player p and xN 1 p for player r: Let us now move to round 1, the beginning of the game. If we apply the backward dominance procedure, then we restrict to strategies that have not been eliminated yet, and perform iterated strict dominance within this restricted game. By our induction assumption, the strategies that have not been eliminated yet are such that, whenever the proposal at round 1 is rejected, then the discounted utility for p is (1 )xN 1 r ; and the discounted utility for r is xN 1 p : By a similar argument as in the proof of Theorem 4.1, we can then conclude that the restricted game at round 1 is given by Figure 2. The only change compared to the proof in Theorem 4.1 is that we substitute (1 )xN 1 r for y1; and substitute xN 1 p for y2: In Figure 2, the …rst utility always corresponds to player p; and the second utility to player r: From Figure 2, it can easily be concluded that proposer p’s utility is strictly decreasing in his commitment level cp: Hence, all choices but cp = 0 are strictly dominated for player p: So, we obtain a reduced game in which player p only chooses cp = 0: But then, using the assumption that < 1 ; we see that player r’s best choice is cr = 1 (1 )xN 1 r : So, the backward dominance procedure (and hence also common belief in future rationality) leads to a unique outcome, in which at round 1 player p commits to cp = 0; player r commits to cr = 1 (1 )xN 1 r ; player 11
  • 12. @ @ @ @ @ @ @ @ @@ (1 )xN 1 r cp; xN 1 p cr 1 cr cp; cr cr 1 xN 1 p cp; xN 1 p cr 1 xN 1 p xN 1 p 1 (1 )xN 1 r cp cr Figure 2: The restricted game at round 1 12
  • 13. p proposes (1 )xN 1 r for himself, player p proposes 1 (1 )xN 1 r for player r; and player r accepts. Since xN p = (1 )xN 1 r and xN r = 1 (1 )xN 1 r ; the statement of the theorem follows for N rounds. By induction on N; the statement holds for every N; and hence the proof is complete. 6. Concluding Remarks 6.1. Commitment Costs In our model we have assumed that the commitment costs for both players are given by c; where c is the amount committed to, and is some …xed number less than 1 : In fact, we do not really need this speci…c functional form for the commitment costs. Instead, we could assume that the commitment costs are given by a more general function (c); where (0) = 0; the function is strictly increasing in the commitment level c; and (1) 1 : The reader may verify that under these assumptions, common belief in future rationality would again lead to a unique outcome, in which the proposer at round 1 faces a …rst-mover disadvantage. The outcome can be computed by a recursive formula similar to the one used in Theorem 5.1. Also under these assumptions we would obtain the reversed Rubinstein outcome ( =(1+ ); 1=(1+ )) if we let the number of rounds go to in…nity, let the size of the smallest slice go to zero, and let the commitment costs go to zero. However, in the paper we have chosen the speci…c functional form c for the commitment costs as to keep the presentation and the analysis as simple as possible. 6.2. Common Belief in Future Rationality The reader may wonder why we have not chosen the more traditional concept of subgame perfect equilibrium, instead of common belief in future rationality, to analyze the game. There are two reasons. First, common belief in future rationality is a more basic concept than subgame perfect equilibrium, as it does not impose any equilibrium condition. It only requires that a player always believes that his opponent will choose rationally now and in the future, that he always believes that his opponent always believes that he will choose rationally now and in the future, and so on. The concept of subgame perfect equilibrium also imposes these conditions, but in addition requires some equilibrium conditions that are harder to justify, and which are not assumed by common belief in future rationality. Second, using common belief in future rationality as a concept makes our Theorem 5.1 stronger. Namely, common belief in future rationality is a weaker concept than subgame perfect equilibrium. In fact, every subgame perfect equilibrium satis…es common belief in future ratio- nality, but not vice versa. Therefore, our Theorem 5.1 implies that the outcome described there is also the unique subgame perfect equilibrium outcome. However, the statement is stronger 13
  • 14. than this: We do not need the equilibrium condition to arrive at this outcome. Imposing only common belief in future rationality is already enough. References [1] Abreu, D., F. Gul (2000): "Bargaining and Reputation", Econometrica, 68, 85-118. [2] Battigalli, P. (1997): "On rationalizability in extensive games", Journal of Economic Theory, 74, 40-61. [3] Battigalli, P. and M. Siniscalchi (2002): "Strong belief and forward induction reasoning", Journal of Economic Theory, 106, 356-391. [4] Binmore, K., Shaked, A., Sutton, J. (1989): "An Outside Option Experiment" Quarterly Journal of Economics, 104, 753-770. [5] Compte, O., P. Jehiel (2002): "On the Role of Outside Options in Bargaining with Obstinate Parties", Econometrica 70, 1477–1517. [6] Crawford, V.P. (1982): "A Theory of Disagreement in Bargaining" Econometrica, 50, 607- 637. [7] Dixit, A. (1980): "The Role of Investment in Entry-Deterrence", Economic Journal, 90, 95-106. [8] Ellingsen (1995): "On Flexibility in Oligopoly", Economics Letters, 48, 83-89. [9] Ellingsen, T., T. Miettinen (2008): "Commitment and Con‡ict in Bilateral Bargaining", American Economic Review 98, 1629-1635. [10] Ellingsen, T., T. Miettinen (2010): "Temporary Commitment in Dynamic Bargaining" Stockholm School of Economics, mimeo. [11] Fershtman, C., D. Seidmann (1993): "Deadline E¤ects and Ine¢ cient Delay in Bargaining with Endogenous Commitment." Journal of Economic Theory 60, 306–321. [12] Li, D. (2007): "Bargaining with History-Dependent Preferences", Journal of Economic Theory 136, 695-708. [13] Li, D. (2010): "Commitment and Compromise in Dynamic Bargaining", Chinese University of Hong Kong, mimeo. [14] Miettinen, T. (2010): "History-dependent Reciprocity in Alternating O¤er Bargaining", Finnish Economic Papers, 23, 1-15. 14
  • 15. [15] Muthoo, A. (1992): "Revocable Commitment and Sequential Bargaining", Eonomic Jour- nal, 102, 378-387. [16] Muthoo, A. (1996): "A Bargaining Model Based on the Commitment Tactic", Journal of Economic Theory, 69, 134-152. [17] Myerson, R. (1991). Game Theory: Analysis of Con‡ict, Harvard University Press, Cam- bridge, MA/USA. [18] Pearce, D.G. (1984): "Rationalizable strategic behavior and the problem of perfection", Econometrica ,52, 1029-1050. [19] Perea, A. (2010): "Belief in the Opponents’Future Rationality" Working paper, Available at: http://www.personeel.unimaas.nl/a.perea/ [20] Rubinstein, A. (1982): "Perfect Equilibrium in a Bargaining Model" Econometrica 50, 97- 110. [21] Schelling, T. (1956): "An Essay on Bargaining." American Economic Review 46, 281-306. [22] Schelling, T. (1960): The Strategy of Con‡ict. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA/USA. [23] Ståhl, I. (1972). Bargaining Theory. Stockholm School of Economics, Stockholm, Sweden. 15