SlideShare a Scribd company logo
1 of 8
Download to read offline
Judgment and Decision Making, Vol. 7, No. 1, January 2012, pp. 69–76
The default pull: An experimental demonstration of subtle default
effects on preferences
Nikhil Dhingra∗
Zach Gorn∗
Andrew Kener∗
Jason Dana†
Abstract
The impact of default options on choice is a reliable, well-established behavioral finding. However, several different
effects may lend to choosing defaults in an often indistinguishable manner, including loss aversion, inattention, infor-
mation leakage, and transaction costs associated with switching. We introduce the notion of the “default pull” as the
effect that even subtle default options have on decision makers’ uncertainty about their own preferences. The default
pull shapes what a decision maker prefers by causing her to consider whether she prefers the default. We demonstrate
default pull effects using a simple decision making task that strips away many of the usual reasons that defaults could
affect choices, and we show that defaults can have substantial effects on choice, even when the default itself was not
chosen.
Keywords: default, loss aversion, uncertainty.
1 Introduction
Perhaps one of the most well-established behavioral de-
cision making effects is the effect of default options on
choice. People choose options presented as defaults more
often than they otherwise would, even for important de-
cisions that would seem to require careful thought, such
as choosing health care or retirement plans (for several
examples, see Thaler & Sunstein, 2008). But under the
umbrella that is “default bias” are several different ef-
fects that all point in the direction of choosing the default.
Mere inattention could lead some decision makers to re-
tain a default if action is required only when opting out
of the default. Loss-averse decision makers may not want
to give up the default because it feels like a loss that is
more painful than gaining a different option is pleasurable
(Kahneman, Knetsch, & Thaler, 1991; Camerer, 2004).
The fact that someone has set an option as a default can
create an “information leakage” (McKenzie, Liersch, &
Finkelstein, 2006; Sher & McKenzie, 2006) from which
people might infer normative reasons for choosing the de-
fault. Finally, people may choose defaults when there are
sufficient transaction costs of money or time in choosing
an alternative.
We examine an effect of default options on choices that
we call the default pull. The default pull is the effect
∗University of Pennsylvania
†Corresponding author: University of Pennsylvania, Dept. of
Psychology, 3720 Walnut St., Philadelphia PA 19104. Email:
danajd@psych.upenn.edu.
that default options have on decision makers’ uncertainty
about their own preferences. When deciding what one
likes, we argue that even subtle defaults can help to shape
what a decision maker prefers by causing her to consider
whether she prefers the default. This process provides a
link between how defaults influence choices and how an-
chors influence judgments (Strack & Mussweiler, 1997).
In this way, the default pull effect is a kind of constructed
preference (Slovic, 1995), wherein the manner in which
preference is elicited influences what one’s preferences
are. Unlike many findings that people stick with the de-
fault, we show that the default pull sometimes involves
choosing the default and sometimes involves choosing
something different from what one otherwise would in
the presence of a default, but not the default itself.
To study the default pull, we use a motivated experi-
mental choice that strips away many of the common rea-
sons why defaults might work: a modified presentation of
a dictator game (Forsythe et al., 1994) in which whatever
option is on the top of a list of allocations is left selected
on a computer interface, ostensibly unintentionally (see
Figure 1). This subtle default option substantially affects
players’ choices; different defaults can change the aver-
age amount given by 17% of the total endowment. The
design and results of our experiment allow us to rule out
inattention, loss aversion, information leakage, and trans-
action costs as explanations for the effect of the default.
Before we describe the specifics of the task, we briefly
review the literature on default biases, and then formally
define the default pull.
69
Judgment and Decision Making, Vol. 7, No. 1, January 2012 Default pull 70
1.1 Default biases
Making an option a default that will be retained unless
the decision maker actively chooses something else leads
to more people choosing the default across a variety of
contexts. Johnson et al. (1993) analyzed auto insur-
ance choices in two bordering states (New Jersey and
Pennsylvania) that switched to a no-fault regime that al-
lowed consumers to limit their right to sue for tort dam-
ages. New Jersey made limited tort the default option,
while Pennsylvanians were presumed to select full tort,
for which they would pay higher rates unless they speci-
fied that they wanted limited tort. In this natural experi-
ment, 75% of Pennsylvania consumers paid to retain full
tort, while only 20% of New Jersey consumers did. Penn-
sylvanians spent millions of dollars more on auto insur-
ance, apparently as a result of this default setting. Stick-
ing with the default in this manner has been argued to
reflect loss aversion (e.g., Kahneman, Knetsch, & Thaler,
1991; Camerer, 2004), with the default choice represent-
ing the reference point. If full tort is a default, then the
prospect of losing it makes it seem more valuable than
the prospect of gaining it, due to the steeper slope of the
Prospect Theory value function in losses.
Similarly, Korobkin (1998) demonstrates default ef-
fects in an experiment with legal contract default rules
that are consistent with loss aversion. Law student sub-
jects provided advice to clients in hypothetical contract
negotiation scenarios, with the content of the legal default
terms (e.g., limited or full liability) manipulated between
experimental groups. The results show that the choice of
default terms subsequently affected the students’ prefer-
ences for the terms of their contract. While the standard
law and economics view is that defaults promote efficient
bargaining, these results suggest that the choice of legal
default terms can be problematic because it can also di-
rectly affect what terms the contracting parties prefer.
Another explanation for choosing defaults is that for
unfamiliar decisions, consumers see defaults as carrying
normative information that serves as guidance for their
decision making. In the example above, if the state saw
fit to make full tort rights the default, then some might
reason that it is unwise to relinquish this right unless they
feel sure of the consequences. Thaler and Sunstein (2008)
discuss the ramifications of default options in the con-
text of the Medicare Part D prescription drug program,
which can be difficult for some consumers to navigate.
Subjects who failed to sign up for a plan, perhaps be-
cause they were overwhelmed with the choice, were as-
signed to default plans and once assigned to such default
plans, may never switch. This bias toward the status quo
(Samuelson & Zeckhauser, 1988) has been demonstrated
for similar decisions, e.g., sticking with one’s retirement
plan provider when new options become available, even
though most people making the choice for the first time
prefer the new options.
Defaults have been to shown to have effects on a wide
variety of health decisions. For example, employees are
more likely to get flu vaccinations when given a default
appointment time than when asked to set an appointment
(Chapman et al., 2010) and cadaveric organ donation
rates increase when people are presumed to be donors
(Johnson & Goldstein, 2003). Abadie and Gay (2006)
examine default options within the opt-in/opt-out struc-
ture of cadaveric organ donation. In opt-in systems of in-
formed consent, one must demonstrate explicit consent to
being a donor, e.g., checking a box that says one wants to
donate her organs in the event of death, while with opt-out
systems of presumed consent, one is classified as a poten-
tial donor unless one actively opposes donation. Across
22 nations, opt-out structures were found to increase the
number of people choosing to be organ donors. It is un-
clear how much the default conveyed normative informa-
tion about what one should choose or how much transac-
tion costs influenced the decision to stick with the default.
1.2 Default pull effect
In this section, we present a formal representation of
the default pull effect that borrows from Kreps’ (1979)
preference for flexibility model. Default effects have
been formally modeled using (A, f) representations (see
Salant & Rubinstein, 2008), where preference is a func-
tion of both the choice options available and the frame,
taken to include problems in which one option is a de-
fault. Axiomatic models of choice where defaults af-
fect preferences (Masatlioglu & Ok, 2005; Sagi, 2006)
have also been developed, but all of these representa-
tions do not necessarily distinguish among reasons why
the default affects preferences. We chose a representation
that describes the default as helping to resolve a decision
maker’s own uncertainty about preferences.
Unlike the many findings of people sticking with a de-
fault option, which may be due to loss aversion, infor-
mation leakage, inattention, or transaction costs, the de-
fault pull effect does not imply that one will stick with
the default. Rather, decision makers sometimes retain the
default and sometimes move substantially away from it,
while still being affected by it. This happens because the
default affects the manner in which the decision maker
constructs his or her preferences. Decision makers, we
argue, recruit information to decide whether the default
is plausibly what they prefer, so that, even if the default
isn’t chosen, it affects their preferences.
To formalize our idea of the default pull, it is help-
ful to conceive of variability in choice behavior. For ex-
ample, one can imagine that if a subject were asked to
make the dictator choice many times with memory be-
Judgment and Decision Making, Vol. 7, No. 1, January 2012 Default pull 71
ing wiped out between each choice, he or she might not
always choose the same thing. Similarly, the idea of con-
structed preference (Payne, Bettman, & Johnson, 1992;
Slovic, 1995) is that across a number of different prefer-
ence elicitations with the same choice options, a person
does not always choose the same thing. The influence
of a default option is one such example. If basic pref-
erences are indeed shaped by the presence of a default,
we need a conception of how decision makers are uncer-
tain about what it is that they want. We focus on mixture
models (also called random preference models, Loomes
& Sugden, 1995; see Heyer & Niederée, 1992; Regen-
wetter, Dana, & Davis-Stober, 2010, 2011) as a way to
characterize choice variability. Mixture models assume
that the decision maker has a probability distribution over
the different possible preference orderings of the choice
objects. That is, mixture models assume choices vary be-
cause the decision has varying preferences across time.
As opposed to a true plus error conception of choice
variability, wherein a decision maker has one true pref-
erence that is expressed with error when making choices,
or multi-attribute models that rely on thresholds of no-
ticeable differences between attributes to create uncer-
tainty in choice (Tversky, 1969; Ariely, Loewenstein, &
Prelec, 2003), mixture models seem more naturally re-
lated to constructed preference, wherein what one prefers
changes as a function of how preferences are elicited.
Mixture models hold that when decision makers with
variable preferences make a choice, it is as if they make
a draw from this probability distribution. For the prefer-
ence that they draw, they choose the most preferred op-
tion. Applying a mixture model to the case of our dictator
game task, we assume that experimental subjects have a
probability distribution over all possible preference rank-
ings of the allocations. Some rankings might have little
or no support in this distribution, e.g., those rankings that
place 0–10 as the most preferred option, while empiri-
cally, rankings that place 10–0 or 5–5 as the most pre-
ferred option should tend to have the most support. The
probability that a decision maker selects an allocation
is, then, the probability that the allocation is preferred,
which in turn is the sum of the probabilities of all pref-
erence states which rank that allocation most preferred.
Formally stated,
Pxy =
s∈S
x y
Ps (1)
where Pxy is the probability of choosing allocation x over
y, s ∈ S is a preference state (i.e., a ranking of the alloca-
tions) from among the set of all possible states, and Ps is
the probability that one is in a state that ranks x over y.
We can use the mixture model framework to put into
expected utility terms a decision maker’s utility for a
given menu of choice options. The decision maker has
utility us(x) for an allocation x when in a preference state
s. Given a menu of options A, like the options available
in our dictator game, the decision maker’s utility for the
menu, v(A), is the sum of the utilities for the most pre-
ferred allocations within each mental state:
v(A) =
s∈S
p(s) max
x∈A
u(x, s) (2)
At this point, our formulation simply represents a pref-
erence for flexibility, wherein a decision maker prefers
a larger menu because she is uncertain what she will
want in the future (Kreps, 1979; see also Ergin & Sarver,
2010). The notion of the default pull is that the presen-
tation of options itself, or more precisely which option is
presented as the default, somehow influences the decision
maker’s preference distribution. For example, because
prior literature on dictator games suggests that 0–10 is
rarely chosen (see review in Camerer, 2003), one might
conclude that it would not even matter if 0–10 was an op-
tion presented to the dictator. Yet, our study will show
that having the option of 0–10 affects choices, particu-
larly when 0–10 is the default, even if the decision maker
does not choose 0–10.
The default pull suggests that an option defined as a
default directly influences the decision maker’s probabil-
ity distribution over preferences states. Put differently,
the default influences the decision maker’s beliefs about
her own preferences. Thus, the particular presentation of
a menu becomes important. We can define the decision
maker’s utility over pairs (A,a) where A is the menu of
all options and a ∈ A is the default option. The decision
maker’s utility for a pair (A,a) where the probability dis-
tribution over states is referenced by the default is then:
v(A, a) =
s∈S
p(s : (A, a)) max
x∈A
u(x, s) (3)
One way to describe the process is that the decision
maker is unsure whether she will ultimately be happy
with a particular choice. The presence of a default alloca-
tion primes her to consider first whether that allocation is
the one she prefers. A literature on anchoring processes
in judgment suggests that a selective accessibility takes
place (Strack & Musweiler, 1997) in which decision mak-
ers test a proposition in a confirmatory manner by first re-
cruiting reasons why it might be true. In anchoring pro-
cesses, selective accessibility leads to judgments that are
closer to an anchor’s value because people have consid-
ered reasons why the anchor might be accurate. Here, we
suggest a similar process in which the default leads de-
cision makers to conclude that their own mixtures place
greater weight on some preference states because con-
sidering whether they prefer the default triggers “salient
considerations” for making the choice (Salant & Rubin-
stein, 2008).
Judgment and Decision Making, Vol. 7, No. 1, January 2012 Default pull 72
For example, a decision maker faced with a default
choice of (0–10) in a dictator game may consider whether
she will be happy with being very generous. In doing so,
she may recruit reasons why she likes generosity, and as
a result conclude that her mixture places more weight on
generous outcomes than it otherwise would. Note that
this process does not imply that the decision maker will
choose the default, in this case (0–10). If the decision
maker normally has zero weight on preference states that
rank (0–10) highest, she may come away from the process
still with zero weight on (0–10), but in recruiting reasons
why she likes generosity, support could shift toward plau-
sibly favorite but generous allocations like (5–5) so that
they are more likely to be chosen.
We hypothesize that once the default pull has triggered
these salient considerations, they can influence choices
beyond the one in which preference construction takes
place. That is, the presence of a default choice af-
fects the probability distribution over preference states,
but that distribution may remain as such for successive
choices. In this way, the default pull is similar to work by
Ariely, Loewenstein, and Prelec on “coherent arbitrari-
ness” (2003) in that there is uncertainty when formulat-
ing preferences, but then decision makers behave as if
those preferences are stable. The default pull differs from
the coherent arbitrariness work in that we suggest a dif-
ferent process by which preferences are formulated and
conceive of preference uncertainty in a different manner.
2 Experiment
We chose our particular formulation of a dictator game to
demonstrate the default pull because it strips away several
reasons why a default might influence choices. First, the
game is incentivized and not particularly complicated, so
that there is little reason to believe that the default would
be chosen because the task was overwhelming or because
subjects were indifferent among the options. Second, it is
difficult to apply the loss aversion explanation in a con-
sistent manner across our results. Suppose, for example,
that a decision maker who normally chooses (10,0) with-
out a default chooses (5,5) when it is the default option.
We could view own and other’s payoff as separate dimen-
sions and thus, choosing (10,0) could seem like a gain of
5 in the “self” dimension, but a loss of 5 in the “other”
dimension relative to the default. Standard loss aversion
could then be applied if losing 5 in the “other” dimension
is more painful than gaining 5 for one’s self is pleasur-
able. However, we will show that (5,5) is a modal choice
when (0,10) is offered as a default, implying that gaining
5 is better than losing 5 in the “other” dimension. Third,
our particular default treatment involves leaving the top
option in an apparently random payoff array preselected,
subtly encouraging subjects to consider using that option
without calling it a default as such. In this way, it is un-
likely that the default involves information leakage about
what one ought to do. Indeed, several subjects reported
either not noticing the default or not realizing that the ex-
perimenters left it selected intentionally. Finally, our task
uses multiple rounds of the same decision. If inattentive-
ness or transaction costs were the reason that subjects left
the default selected, then they should leave the default
selected in every round. We show that if a default allo-
cation is selected in the first round, subjects are likely to
seek it out and choose it again in subsequent rounds, even
though it is no longer a default and the order of the allo-
cations changes in every round.
Previous work has noted that dictator games are notori-
ously sensitive to context (see, e.g., Bardsley, 2008; List,
2007; Levitt & List, 2007; Dana, Weber, & Kuang, 2007),
thus it is not surprising that a manipulation could strongly
affect levels of giving. While this prior work draws into
question how we should interpret giving and points out
how strong demand effects can be in the dictator game,
neither concern bears on the question of whether a sub-
tle default affects choices. Indeed, our subjects explicitly
deny the possibility of a demand affect, overwhelmingly
reporting that the default did not affect their choices.
3 Methods
3.1 Subjects
Subjects (n = 82) were students at the University of Penn-
sylvania, all of whom participated voluntarily in response
to an online advertisement for paid decision experiments.
All subjects gave informed consent prior to the experi-
ment. Seven sessions were run, ranging in size from 6 to
18 subjects.
3.2 Procedures
Stimuli were presented via computer interface and in-
structions were additionally read aloud. Subjects were
instructed that they would play a simple economic game
with another person with whom they would be randomly
matched and that all identities would be kept anony-
mous. Each subject was instructed to complete a series
of four consecutive dictator games in which they would
choose an allocation of points between themselves and
the anonymous person with whom they were matched.
Each game consisted of a list of possible divisions of 10
points between the subject and the anonymous other party
in whole number amounts. The points were converted to
cash at a rate of 25 cents each at the end of the experi-
ment, making the total endowment being allocated over
the four rounds $10.
Judgment and Decision Making, Vol. 7, No. 1, January 2012 Default pull 73
Figure 1: Interface.
Figure1.png (PNG Image, 947 × 721 pixels) file:///home/baron/jdm/10/10831a/Figure1.png
1 of 1 01/24/2012 06:08 AM
The strategy method was used to elicit choices; all sub-
jects were instructed to make choices in the role of dic-
tator (described in neutral language as “Player X”) and
informed that after all decisions were made, half would
be randomly assigned to be Player X, and thus have their
choices executed, while the other half (“Player Y”) would
not have their choices executed and instead be assigned to
be the recipients of the choices made by Player X. No
subject could be assigned to be the recipient of his or
her own choices. There is some concern that the strat-
egy method could affect levels of giving because dictator
choices are made while knowing that one could end up
being a recipient instead. Our results will show, however,
that our subjects gave at somewhat lower levels than av-
erage (typically a little under 30%, see Camerer, 2003)
when they were not assigned a default. More importantly,
we are less concerned in this study with the levels of giv-
ing than with differences in giving across default treat-
ments.
In each round of the game, thirteen possible wealth
allocations were presented in a checklist format on the
computer interface (see Figure 1 below). These alloca-
tions included all 11 of the possible whole divisions of 10
plus 2 distracter allocations that were Pareto-dominated
(i.e., summed to less than 10). The distractors changed in
each round and were included to promote attentiveness.
The order in which the options were presented changed
in each round of the game, such that the subject had to
search through a randomized list of options to select their
choice. Subjects were instructed to select one option in
each round and verify their choice before continuing to
the next round.
“Defaults” were created by leaving the allocation at the
top of the list pre-selected on the screen at the beginning
of each round (e.g., 10–0 in Figure 1). This situation is
common, for example, on web forms where one of the
objects on the display must have focus. At no time dur-
ing the experiment was mention made of the pre-selected
choices. One of four default conditions was assigned in
each round, with allocations of (10–0), (5–5), and (0–10)
used as defaults in 3 of the rounds, and no default selected
in the 4th
. The order of default presentation was fully bal-
anced; each subject was serially assigned to see one of
the 4! = 24 possible orders until all were exhausted and
the process was repeated.
After subjects completed all four rounds, roles were
randomly assigned and subjects were informed of their
monetary compensation for the experiment. Subjects
then filled out a brief survey including three questions
about the experiment. In one version (n = 37), we asked
(1) whether they noticed the presence of a pre-selected
option; (2) whether the presence of a default affected
their choices; and (3) whether their choice in the first
round of the experiment affected their choice in subse-
quent rounds. For a second group of subjects (n = 32),
we replaced question (2) by a free-response question ask-
ing why they thought an option was left selected on the
screen. For this group of subjects, we only asked the free-
response question if they had responded affirmatively to
question (1) about noticing that an option had been se-
lected. Due to an error in one session and one subject
leaving the items blank, 13 subjects did not answer any
survey questions.
4 Results
4.1 Dictator choices
Within-subject choices stayed largely consistent across
the 4 rounds of the experiment. Figure 2 plots the mean
amount of points given in each round by which default
was presented in round 1. The between-subject effect
of having either a fair or hyperfair default in round 1
(5–5 or 0–10) vs. a selfish default (10–0) or no default
drowns out the within-subject effect of having different
defaults across rounds; mean giving starts relatively high
for the fair and hyperfair defaults and remains so through-
out the 4 rounds, while giving stays relatively low across
all rounds for the selfish default and no default. Choices
in the first round were highly correlated with choices in
the second, third, and fourth rounds (rs = .71, .52, and
.65 respectively). Thus, the default affects choices in
round 1, but then recognizing that the subsequent rounds
essentially represent iterations of the same decision, sub-
jects stay consistent with their earlier choices even though
the default changes—a “coherent arbitrariness” of sorts
(Ariely, Loewenstein, & Prelec, 2003). In light of the
distracter allocations and randomized choice set, the ob-
Judgment and Decision Making, Vol. 7, No. 1, January 2012 Default pull 74
Figure 2: Mean amount of points given as a function of
the default in round 1.
1 2 3 4
01234
Round
Meanpointsgiven
(10,0)
(5,5)
(0,10)
no default
served behavior strongly supports the idea that subjects
did not make their choices through indifference or inat-
tentiveness, but rather actively remained consistent by
having to search through the list in each round for the
desired allocation. We will focus the remainder of our
analyses on the between-subject effects of the round 1
default on the total amount a dictator gave.
Figure 3 displays the mean amount of money players
gave for each of the default conditions. Choices were
strongly affected by the presence of first-round defaults.
Overall, giving was higher in the 5–5 (n = 21) and 0–10
(n = 20) default conditions (ms = $2.71 and $3.14, re-
spectively) than in the 10–0 (n = 22) and no default (n =
19) conditions (ms = $1.47 and $2.09, respectively), so
that the default that a subject received in the first round
could influence the amount they gave overall by about
17% of the total endowment. The omnibus null hypothe-
sis of equal giving across all default conditions can be re-
jected (F(3,78) = 3.17, p = .029), while a planned contrast
confirms that giving in the 5–5 and 0–10 default groups
combined is significantly higher than in the 10–0 and no
default groups combined (t(78) = -2.74, p = .008). Fur-
ther planned contrasts reveal that giving is significantly
less in the 10–0 default condition than in both the 5–5
default condition (t(78) = -2.07, p = .04) and the 0–10 de-
fault condition (t(78) = 2.91, p = .005). No significant
differences emerged between giving in the 10–0 and no
default groups, suggesting that keeping the endowment
was a sort of default position of our subjects. Further,
we failed to reject the null hypothesis of equal giving be-
tween the 5–5 and 0–10 default groups, consistent with
the idea that our subjects, while affected by the default,
did not just stick with the default.
Figure 3: Mean total dollar amounts given out by dic-
tators and standard errors by which default they saw in
round 1.
(10,0) (5,5) (0,10) No default
Default
Meandollaramountsgiven
0.00.51.01.52.02.53.03.5
The effect of the first-round default clearly did not de-
pend on choices of the default itself. We eliminated all
cases in which 10 or 0 contribution was chosen, then ex-
amined contributions (mean contribution over the four
rounds) as a function of the first-round default, looking
only at those subjects who received 10 or 0 as the first-
round default. The mean contributions were 3.61 when
the first-round default was 0 and 4.66 when it was 10,
and these differed significantly (t(13) = 2.87, p = .013).
Figure 4 displays the frequencies of giving decisions
across all rounds when facing each first round default
condition. We note that the distribution of choices when
facing the (5,5) and (0,10) defaults is nearly identical.
While the large number of even split choices in the (5–
5) default condition could be attributed to subjects retain-
ing the default, we note that a similar number of subjects
chose the even split when the default was (0–10). Further,
gifts of the entire 10 points were uncommon, even when
the default was 0–10. This behavior is consistent with
our idea of the default pull: Subjects are not necessarily
sticking with the default, though the default affects be-
havior. The default is sometimes used if it is a plausibly
favorite allocation, as in the case of (5–5), but only affects
choices without being chosen itself when not a plausi-
bly preferred allocation, as in the case of (0–10). This
behavioral result is thus consistent with subjects having
uncertainty over what they want and using the default to
construct their preferences.
Judgment and Decision Making, Vol. 7, No. 1, January 2012 Default pull 75
Figure 4: Frequency of amounts given in any round as a
function of the default.
0103050
Default 10−0
051525
Default 5−5
051020
Default 0−10
0 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10
0102030
No default
4.2 Survey responses
Survey responses confirmed the subtlety of the default
manipulation. Approximately 29% (20/69) of subjects
reported that they had not even noticed the presence of a
pre-selected option on the screen. Although the presence
of this option had an effect on choices, of 37 respondents
who were asked explicitly whether their choices were in-
fluenced by the default, only 3 (8%) replied that it had. Of
the 32 subjects assigned to be probed about why an option
was pre-selected, 26 noticed the default. Interestingly, 18
of these 26 responses suggested in some way the possi-
bility that the experimenter was trying to influence their
choice with the pre-selected option. Apparently, subjects
considered that a default might be an attempt to influence
them, but did not believe that it worked to affect their
own choices. Further, only 29 out of 69 (42%) felt that
their choice in the first round influenced the choices in
subsequent rounds, despite the fact that choices in later
rounds were strongly correlated with first round choices.
Taken together, these responses are consistent with Nis-
bett and Wilson’s (1977) classic findings on “telling more
than we can know”. While the effects of the default in the
first round and status quo in subsequent rounds are quite
evident when viewed between-subject, the subjects them-
selves do not appear to experience the default as affecting
their choices. These results speak against an information
leakage explanation of why defaults worked in this set-
ting, as subjects are explicitly denying that they are using
the default to make choices.
5 Discussion
We have shown evidence of a default pull effect wherein
people appear to be affected by subtly presented default
options while constructing their preferences. Unlike bi-
ases toward sticking with the default, the default pull
affects choices even though decision makers may not
choose the default itself. Additionally, we have shown
evidence that the default pull happens outside of the de-
cision maker’s awareness; almost all of our subjects de-
nied that they were affected by the presence of a default
despite statistical evidence to the contrary, and a size-
able portion of our subjects reported not even noticing the
presence of defaults. Finally, we show that even though
preferences are largely determined by an arbitrary de-
fault, decision makers try to remain consistent with those
preferences in future decisions, a sort of “coherent arbi-
trariness” (Ariely, Loewenstein, & Prelec, 2003).
One concern is that the default pull effects we find are
the result of poor incentives. Although our payment was
standard for this type of task, it represented compensation
for 4 such choices combined. This payment structure,
however, was transparent to subjects, who also tended to
choose the same thing across all 4 rounds, so the total in-
centives they faced were standard. Further, a lack of mo-
tivation would predict the opposite of what we observed:
If people were not making careful choices, we wouldn’t
find systematic differences based on defaults. These dif-
ferences did not arise from laziness: a (0–10) default was
rarely chosen, for example, but it did lead subjects to seek
out (5–5). Further, defaults that were retained in round 1
often led subjects to seek out that same allocation in sub-
sequent rounds, even though it was not a default.
The present findings can enrich our understanding of
how defaults affect behavior. While defaults can be cho-
sen for many reasons including loss aversion, inatten-
tiveness, information leakage, and transaction costs, we
show that default options can subtly affect preferences in
a more fundamental way by serving as a cue by which
people decide what they like. That people do not have
access into this mental process points to a reason why
the effects of arbitrary defaults are so persistent. Because
people do not consciously realize when defaults affect
their choices, they cannot effectively learn not to be af-
fected by them. For decisions such as what prescription
plan to choose, whether to waive one’s right to full tort,
or, as in our case, how generous to be, it remains unclear
how a market would punish the default pull and promote
resistance to the effects of arbitrary defaults, thus allow-
ing default effects to persist in the face of incentives to be
unbiased.
Judgment and Decision Making, Vol. 7, No. 1, January 2012 Default pull 76
References
Abadie, A., Gay, S. (2006). The Impact of Presumed
Consent Legislation on Cadaveric Organ Donation: A
Cross Country Study. Journal of Health Economics,
25, 599–620.
Ariely, D., Loewenstein, G., & Prelec, D. (2003). Coher-
ent Arbitrariness: Stable Demand Curves without Sta-
ble Preferences. The Quarterly Journal of Economics,
1, 73–105.
Bardsley, N. (2008). Dictator Game Giving: Altruism
or Artifact? Journal of Experimental Economics, 11,
122–133.
Camerer, C. (2003). Behavioral Game Theory: Experi-
ments on Strategic Interaction. Princeton, NJ: Prince-
ton University Press.
Camerer, C. (2004). Prospect theory in the wild: Ev-
idence from the field. In Camerer, C., Loewenstein,
G., and Rabin, M. (Eds): Advances in behavioral eco-
nomics. New York: Princeton University Press.
Chapman, G.B., Li, M., Colby, H., & Yoon, H. (2010).
Opting in versus opting out of influenza vaccination.
JAMA, 304, 43–44.
Dana, J., Weber, R., & Kuang, J. (2007). Exploiting
Moral Wriggle Room: Behavior Inconsistent with a
Preference for Fair Outcomes. Journal of Economic
Theory, 1, 67–80.
Ergin, H., & Sarver, T. (2010). A unique costly contem-
plation representation. Econometrica, 78, 1285–1339.
Forsythe, R., Horowitz, J., Savin, N.E., & Sefton, M.
(1994). Fairness in Simple Bargaining Experiments.
Games and Economic Behavior, 6, 347–69.
Heyer, D., & Niederée, R. (1992). Generalizing the con-
cept of binary choice systems induced by rankings:
One way of probabilizing deterministic measurement
structures. Mathematical Social Sciences, 23, 31–44.
Johnson, E. & Goldstein, D. (2003). Do defaults save
lives? Science, 302, 1338–1339.
Johnson, E., Hershey, J., Meszaros, J., & Kunreuther, H.
(1993). Framing, Probability Distortions, and Insur-
ance Decisions. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 1,
35–51.
Kahneman, D., Knetsch, J., & Thaler, R. (1991). Anoma-
lies: The Endowment Effect, Loss Aversion, and Status
Quo Bias. Journal of Economic Perspectives, 5, 193–
206.
Korobkin, R. (1998). The Status Quo Bias and Contract
Default Rules. Cornell Law Review, 83, 609–687.
Kreps, D. (1988). A representation theorem for “prefer-
ence for flexibility.” Econometrica, 47, 565–577.
Levitt, S., & List, J. (2007). What do Laboratory Exper-
iments Measuring Social Preferences tell us about the
Real World? Journal of Economic Perspectives, 21,
153–174.
List, J. (2007). On the Interpretation of Giving in Dictator
Games. Journal of Political Economy, 3, 482–493.
Loomes, G., & Sugden, R. (1995). Incorporating a
stochastic element into decision theories. European
Economic Review, 39, 641–648.
Masatlioglu, Y., & Ok, E. (2005) Rational choice with
status quo bias. Journal of Economic Theory, 121, 1–
29.
McKenzie, C. R. M., Liersch, M. J., & Finkelstein, S. R.
(2006). Recommendations implicit in policy defaults.
Psychological Science, 17, 414–420.
Nisbett, R., & Wilson, T. (1977). Telling more than we
can know: Verbal reports on mental processes. Psy-
chological Review, 84, 231–259.
Payne, J., Bettman, J. & Johnson, E. (1992). Behavioral
decision research: A constructive process perspective.
Annual Review of Psychology, 43, 87–131.
Regenwetter, M., Dana, J., & Davis-Stober, C. (2010).
Testing transitivity of preferences on two-alternative
forced choice data. Frontiers of Quantitative Psychol-
ogy and Measurement, 1, 1–15.
Regenwetter, M., Dana, J., & Davis-Stober, C. (2011).
Transitivity of preferences. Psychological Review,
118, 42–56.
Sagi, J. (2006). Anchored preference relations. Journal
of Economic Theory, 130, 283–295.
Salant, Y. & Rubinstein, A. (2008). (A, f): Choice with
frames. Review of Economic Studies, 75, 1287–1296.
Samuelson, W., & Zeckhauser, R. (1988). Status quo bias
in decision making. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty,
1, 7–59.
Sher, S., & McKenzie, C. R. M. (2006). Information
leakage from logically equivalent frames. Cognition,
101, 467–494.
Slovic, P. (1995). The construction of preference. Amer-
ican Psychologist, 50, 364–371.
Strack, F., & Mussweiler, T. (1997). Explaining the enig-
matic anchoring effect: Mechanisms of selective ac-
cessibility. Journal of Personality and Social Psychol-
ogy, 73, 437–446.
Thaler, R., & Sunstein, C. (2008). Nudge: improving
decisions about health, wealth, and happiness. New
Haven: Yale University Press.
Tversky, A. (1969). Intransitivity of preferences. Psycho-
logical Review, 76, 31–48.

More Related Content

Viewers also liked

Photography planning
Photography planningPhotography planning
Photography planningjoelbmedia
 
Farookh Sekh_ Resume
Farookh Sekh_ ResumeFarookh Sekh_ Resume
Farookh Sekh_ ResumeFarookh Sekh
 
Store design layout_visual_merchandising
Store design layout_visual_merchandisingStore design layout_visual_merchandising
Store design layout_visual_merchandisingsurbhis123
 
Metabolism of nucleotides
Metabolism of nucleotidesMetabolism of nucleotides
Metabolism of nucleotidesRoshan Mahat
 
EduNxt V2 for GNU - Email using Office 365
EduNxt V2 for GNU - Email using Office 365EduNxt V2 for GNU - Email using Office 365
EduNxt V2 for GNU - Email using Office 365Siddharth Goyal
 
Celular y tablet inicio red de comunicación
Celular y tablet  inicio red de comunicaciónCelular y tablet  inicio red de comunicación
Celular y tablet inicio red de comunicaciónMauricio Eberle Morales
 

Viewers also liked (10)

EduNxt for GNU
EduNxt for GNUEduNxt for GNU
EduNxt for GNU
 
Profile - Suresh Kumar
Profile - Suresh KumarProfile - Suresh Kumar
Profile - Suresh Kumar
 
Photography planning
Photography planningPhotography planning
Photography planning
 
Farookh Sekh_ Resume
Farookh Sekh_ ResumeFarookh Sekh_ Resume
Farookh Sekh_ Resume
 
Store design layout_visual_merchandising
Store design layout_visual_merchandisingStore design layout_visual_merchandising
Store design layout_visual_merchandising
 
Các loại ic
Các loại icCác loại ic
Các loại ic
 
User Manual - EduNxt v3
User Manual - EduNxt v3User Manual - EduNxt v3
User Manual - EduNxt v3
 
Metabolism of nucleotides
Metabolism of nucleotidesMetabolism of nucleotides
Metabolism of nucleotides
 
EduNxt V2 for GNU - Email using Office 365
EduNxt V2 for GNU - Email using Office 365EduNxt V2 for GNU - Email using Office 365
EduNxt V2 for GNU - Email using Office 365
 
Celular y tablet inicio red de comunicación
Celular y tablet  inicio red de comunicaciónCelular y tablet  inicio red de comunicación
Celular y tablet inicio red de comunicación
 

Similar to The default pull: An experimental demonstration of subtle default effects on preferences

Discussion 1Decision-Making ProcessWith the paternalistic de
Discussion 1Decision-Making ProcessWith the paternalistic deDiscussion 1Decision-Making ProcessWith the paternalistic de
Discussion 1Decision-Making ProcessWith the paternalistic deVinaOconner450
 
RATIO ANALYSIS RATIO ANALYSIS Note Please change the column names.docx
RATIO ANALYSIS RATIO ANALYSIS Note Please change the column names.docxRATIO ANALYSIS RATIO ANALYSIS Note Please change the column names.docx
RATIO ANALYSIS RATIO ANALYSIS Note Please change the column names.docxaudeleypearl
 
Behavioral Economics and Psychology of Incentives
Behavioral Economics and Psychology of IncentivesBehavioral Economics and Psychology of Incentives
Behavioral Economics and Psychology of IncentivesHarsha MV
 
Behavioral Public Choice The Behavioral Paradox of Gove.docx
Behavioral Public Choice The Behavioral Paradox of Gove.docxBehavioral Public Choice The Behavioral Paradox of Gove.docx
Behavioral Public Choice The Behavioral Paradox of Gove.docxtaitcandie
 
THE IMPACT OF PSYCHOLOGICAL BARRIERS IN INFLUENCING CUSTOMERS’ DECISIONS IN T...
THE IMPACT OF PSYCHOLOGICAL BARRIERS IN INFLUENCING CUSTOMERS’ DECISIONS IN T...THE IMPACT OF PSYCHOLOGICAL BARRIERS IN INFLUENCING CUSTOMERS’ DECISIONS IN T...
THE IMPACT OF PSYCHOLOGICAL BARRIERS IN INFLUENCING CUSTOMERS’ DECISIONS IN T...ijmpict
 
Introduction to Business Decision Making - 76%
Introduction to Business Decision Making - 76%Introduction to Business Decision Making - 76%
Introduction to Business Decision Making - 76%Kennedy Emma Round
 
Decision making
Decision makingDecision making
Decision makingwolfygrey
 
Is Decision-Based Evidence Making Necessarily BadS U .docx
Is Decision-Based Evidence Making Necessarily BadS U .docxIs Decision-Based Evidence Making Necessarily BadS U .docx
Is Decision-Based Evidence Making Necessarily BadS U .docxLaticiaGrissomzz
 
Using Information Aggregation Markets for Decision Support
Using Information Aggregation Markets for Decision SupportUsing Information Aggregation Markets for Decision Support
Using Information Aggregation Markets for Decision SupportWaqas Tariq
 
Lunenburg, fred c, escalation of commitment ijmba v13 n1 2010
Lunenburg, fred c, escalation of commitment ijmba v13 n1 2010Lunenburg, fred c, escalation of commitment ijmba v13 n1 2010
Lunenburg, fred c, escalation of commitment ijmba v13 n1 2010William Kritsonis
 
Dr. Fred C. Lunenburg, Escalation of Commitment - Published in the INTERNAT...
Dr. Fred C. Lunenburg,   Escalation of Commitment - Published in the INTERNAT...Dr. Fred C. Lunenburg,   Escalation of Commitment - Published in the INTERNAT...
Dr. Fred C. Lunenburg, Escalation of Commitment - Published in the INTERNAT...William Kritsonis
 

Similar to The default pull: An experimental demonstration of subtle default effects on preferences (20)

Discussion 1Decision-Making ProcessWith the paternalistic de
Discussion 1Decision-Making ProcessWith the paternalistic deDiscussion 1Decision-Making ProcessWith the paternalistic de
Discussion 1Decision-Making ProcessWith the paternalistic de
 
Parental Decision-Making Essay Example
Parental Decision-Making Essay ExampleParental Decision-Making Essay Example
Parental Decision-Making Essay Example
 
RATIO ANALYSIS RATIO ANALYSIS Note Please change the column names.docx
RATIO ANALYSIS RATIO ANALYSIS Note Please change the column names.docxRATIO ANALYSIS RATIO ANALYSIS Note Please change the column names.docx
RATIO ANALYSIS RATIO ANALYSIS Note Please change the column names.docx
 
Behavioral Economics and Psychology of Incentives
Behavioral Economics and Psychology of IncentivesBehavioral Economics and Psychology of Incentives
Behavioral Economics and Psychology of Incentives
 
Behavioral Public Choice The Behavioral Paradox of Gove.docx
Behavioral Public Choice The Behavioral Paradox of Gove.docxBehavioral Public Choice The Behavioral Paradox of Gove.docx
Behavioral Public Choice The Behavioral Paradox of Gove.docx
 
Behavioural Economics Overview
Behavioural Economics OverviewBehavioural Economics Overview
Behavioural Economics Overview
 
Review
ReviewReview
Review
 
behavioural_term_paper
behavioural_term_paperbehavioural_term_paper
behavioural_term_paper
 
Decision making
Decision makingDecision making
Decision making
 
THE IMPACT OF PSYCHOLOGICAL BARRIERS IN INFLUENCING CUSTOMERS’ DECISIONS IN T...
THE IMPACT OF PSYCHOLOGICAL BARRIERS IN INFLUENCING CUSTOMERS’ DECISIONS IN T...THE IMPACT OF PSYCHOLOGICAL BARRIERS IN INFLUENCING CUSTOMERS’ DECISIONS IN T...
THE IMPACT OF PSYCHOLOGICAL BARRIERS IN INFLUENCING CUSTOMERS’ DECISIONS IN T...
 
Decisions & Results
Decisions & ResultsDecisions & Results
Decisions & Results
 
Introduction to Business Decision Making - 76%
Introduction to Business Decision Making - 76%Introduction to Business Decision Making - 76%
Introduction to Business Decision Making - 76%
 
Making Decisions Essay
Making Decisions EssayMaking Decisions Essay
Making Decisions Essay
 
Decision making
Decision makingDecision making
Decision making
 
Is Decision-Based Evidence Making Necessarily BadS U .docx
Is Decision-Based Evidence Making Necessarily BadS U .docxIs Decision-Based Evidence Making Necessarily BadS U .docx
Is Decision-Based Evidence Making Necessarily BadS U .docx
 
Dissertation
DissertationDissertation
Dissertation
 
Decisions Essay
Decisions EssayDecisions Essay
Decisions Essay
 
Using Information Aggregation Markets for Decision Support
Using Information Aggregation Markets for Decision SupportUsing Information Aggregation Markets for Decision Support
Using Information Aggregation Markets for Decision Support
 
Lunenburg, fred c, escalation of commitment ijmba v13 n1 2010
Lunenburg, fred c, escalation of commitment ijmba v13 n1 2010Lunenburg, fred c, escalation of commitment ijmba v13 n1 2010
Lunenburg, fred c, escalation of commitment ijmba v13 n1 2010
 
Dr. Fred C. Lunenburg, Escalation of Commitment - Published in the INTERNAT...
Dr. Fred C. Lunenburg,   Escalation of Commitment - Published in the INTERNAT...Dr. Fred C. Lunenburg,   Escalation of Commitment - Published in the INTERNAT...
Dr. Fred C. Lunenburg, Escalation of Commitment - Published in the INTERNAT...
 

Recently uploaded

POINT- BIOCHEMISTRY SEM 2 ENZYMES UNIT 5.pptx
POINT- BIOCHEMISTRY SEM 2 ENZYMES UNIT 5.pptxPOINT- BIOCHEMISTRY SEM 2 ENZYMES UNIT 5.pptx
POINT- BIOCHEMISTRY SEM 2 ENZYMES UNIT 5.pptxSayali Powar
 
Framing an Appropriate Research Question 6b9b26d93da94caf993c038d9efcdedb.pdf
Framing an Appropriate Research Question 6b9b26d93da94caf993c038d9efcdedb.pdfFraming an Appropriate Research Question 6b9b26d93da94caf993c038d9efcdedb.pdf
Framing an Appropriate Research Question 6b9b26d93da94caf993c038d9efcdedb.pdfUjwalaBharambe
 
ECONOMIC CONTEXT - PAPER 1 Q3: NEWSPAPERS.pptx
ECONOMIC CONTEXT - PAPER 1 Q3: NEWSPAPERS.pptxECONOMIC CONTEXT - PAPER 1 Q3: NEWSPAPERS.pptx
ECONOMIC CONTEXT - PAPER 1 Q3: NEWSPAPERS.pptxiammrhaywood
 
Employee wellbeing at the workplace.pptx
Employee wellbeing at the workplace.pptxEmployee wellbeing at the workplace.pptx
Employee wellbeing at the workplace.pptxNirmalaLoungPoorunde1
 
Introduction to AI in Higher Education_draft.pptx
Introduction to AI in Higher Education_draft.pptxIntroduction to AI in Higher Education_draft.pptx
Introduction to AI in Higher Education_draft.pptxpboyjonauth
 
MARGINALIZATION (Different learners in Marginalized Group
MARGINALIZATION (Different learners in Marginalized GroupMARGINALIZATION (Different learners in Marginalized Group
MARGINALIZATION (Different learners in Marginalized GroupJonathanParaisoCruz
 
18-04-UA_REPORT_MEDIALITERAСY_INDEX-DM_23-1-final-eng.pdf
18-04-UA_REPORT_MEDIALITERAСY_INDEX-DM_23-1-final-eng.pdf18-04-UA_REPORT_MEDIALITERAСY_INDEX-DM_23-1-final-eng.pdf
18-04-UA_REPORT_MEDIALITERAСY_INDEX-DM_23-1-final-eng.pdfssuser54595a
 
Crayon Activity Handout For the Crayon A
Crayon Activity Handout For the Crayon ACrayon Activity Handout For the Crayon A
Crayon Activity Handout For the Crayon AUnboundStockton
 
History Class XII Ch. 3 Kinship, Caste and Class (1).pptx
History Class XII Ch. 3 Kinship, Caste and Class (1).pptxHistory Class XII Ch. 3 Kinship, Caste and Class (1).pptx
History Class XII Ch. 3 Kinship, Caste and Class (1).pptxsocialsciencegdgrohi
 
Roles & Responsibilities in Pharmacovigilance
Roles & Responsibilities in PharmacovigilanceRoles & Responsibilities in Pharmacovigilance
Roles & Responsibilities in PharmacovigilanceSamikshaHamane
 
Meghan Sutherland In Media Res Media Component
Meghan Sutherland In Media Res Media ComponentMeghan Sutherland In Media Res Media Component
Meghan Sutherland In Media Res Media ComponentInMediaRes1
 
Organic Name Reactions for the students and aspirants of Chemistry12th.pptx
Organic Name Reactions  for the students and aspirants of Chemistry12th.pptxOrganic Name Reactions  for the students and aspirants of Chemistry12th.pptx
Organic Name Reactions for the students and aspirants of Chemistry12th.pptxVS Mahajan Coaching Centre
 
call girls in Kamla Market (DELHI) 🔝 >༒9953330565🔝 genuine Escort Service 🔝✔️✔️
call girls in Kamla Market (DELHI) 🔝 >༒9953330565🔝 genuine Escort Service 🔝✔️✔️call girls in Kamla Market (DELHI) 🔝 >༒9953330565🔝 genuine Escort Service 🔝✔️✔️
call girls in Kamla Market (DELHI) 🔝 >༒9953330565🔝 genuine Escort Service 🔝✔️✔️9953056974 Low Rate Call Girls In Saket, Delhi NCR
 
Interactive Powerpoint_How to Master effective communication
Interactive Powerpoint_How to Master effective communicationInteractive Powerpoint_How to Master effective communication
Interactive Powerpoint_How to Master effective communicationnomboosow
 
Biting mechanism of poisonous snakes.pdf
Biting mechanism of poisonous snakes.pdfBiting mechanism of poisonous snakes.pdf
Biting mechanism of poisonous snakes.pdfadityarao40181
 
CARE OF CHILD IN INCUBATOR..........pptx
CARE OF CHILD IN INCUBATOR..........pptxCARE OF CHILD IN INCUBATOR..........pptx
CARE OF CHILD IN INCUBATOR..........pptxGaneshChakor2
 
Historical philosophical, theoretical, and legal foundations of special and i...
Historical philosophical, theoretical, and legal foundations of special and i...Historical philosophical, theoretical, and legal foundations of special and i...
Historical philosophical, theoretical, and legal foundations of special and i...jaredbarbolino94
 
Types of Journalistic Writing Grade 8.pptx
Types of Journalistic Writing Grade 8.pptxTypes of Journalistic Writing Grade 8.pptx
Types of Journalistic Writing Grade 8.pptxEyham Joco
 

Recently uploaded (20)

POINT- BIOCHEMISTRY SEM 2 ENZYMES UNIT 5.pptx
POINT- BIOCHEMISTRY SEM 2 ENZYMES UNIT 5.pptxPOINT- BIOCHEMISTRY SEM 2 ENZYMES UNIT 5.pptx
POINT- BIOCHEMISTRY SEM 2 ENZYMES UNIT 5.pptx
 
Framing an Appropriate Research Question 6b9b26d93da94caf993c038d9efcdedb.pdf
Framing an Appropriate Research Question 6b9b26d93da94caf993c038d9efcdedb.pdfFraming an Appropriate Research Question 6b9b26d93da94caf993c038d9efcdedb.pdf
Framing an Appropriate Research Question 6b9b26d93da94caf993c038d9efcdedb.pdf
 
ECONOMIC CONTEXT - PAPER 1 Q3: NEWSPAPERS.pptx
ECONOMIC CONTEXT - PAPER 1 Q3: NEWSPAPERS.pptxECONOMIC CONTEXT - PAPER 1 Q3: NEWSPAPERS.pptx
ECONOMIC CONTEXT - PAPER 1 Q3: NEWSPAPERS.pptx
 
Employee wellbeing at the workplace.pptx
Employee wellbeing at the workplace.pptxEmployee wellbeing at the workplace.pptx
Employee wellbeing at the workplace.pptx
 
Introduction to AI in Higher Education_draft.pptx
Introduction to AI in Higher Education_draft.pptxIntroduction to AI in Higher Education_draft.pptx
Introduction to AI in Higher Education_draft.pptx
 
MARGINALIZATION (Different learners in Marginalized Group
MARGINALIZATION (Different learners in Marginalized GroupMARGINALIZATION (Different learners in Marginalized Group
MARGINALIZATION (Different learners in Marginalized Group
 
18-04-UA_REPORT_MEDIALITERAСY_INDEX-DM_23-1-final-eng.pdf
18-04-UA_REPORT_MEDIALITERAСY_INDEX-DM_23-1-final-eng.pdf18-04-UA_REPORT_MEDIALITERAСY_INDEX-DM_23-1-final-eng.pdf
18-04-UA_REPORT_MEDIALITERAСY_INDEX-DM_23-1-final-eng.pdf
 
ESSENTIAL of (CS/IT/IS) class 06 (database)
ESSENTIAL of (CS/IT/IS) class 06 (database)ESSENTIAL of (CS/IT/IS) class 06 (database)
ESSENTIAL of (CS/IT/IS) class 06 (database)
 
Crayon Activity Handout For the Crayon A
Crayon Activity Handout For the Crayon ACrayon Activity Handout For the Crayon A
Crayon Activity Handout For the Crayon A
 
History Class XII Ch. 3 Kinship, Caste and Class (1).pptx
History Class XII Ch. 3 Kinship, Caste and Class (1).pptxHistory Class XII Ch. 3 Kinship, Caste and Class (1).pptx
History Class XII Ch. 3 Kinship, Caste and Class (1).pptx
 
Roles & Responsibilities in Pharmacovigilance
Roles & Responsibilities in PharmacovigilanceRoles & Responsibilities in Pharmacovigilance
Roles & Responsibilities in Pharmacovigilance
 
Meghan Sutherland In Media Res Media Component
Meghan Sutherland In Media Res Media ComponentMeghan Sutherland In Media Res Media Component
Meghan Sutherland In Media Res Media Component
 
Organic Name Reactions for the students and aspirants of Chemistry12th.pptx
Organic Name Reactions  for the students and aspirants of Chemistry12th.pptxOrganic Name Reactions  for the students and aspirants of Chemistry12th.pptx
Organic Name Reactions for the students and aspirants of Chemistry12th.pptx
 
call girls in Kamla Market (DELHI) 🔝 >༒9953330565🔝 genuine Escort Service 🔝✔️✔️
call girls in Kamla Market (DELHI) 🔝 >༒9953330565🔝 genuine Escort Service 🔝✔️✔️call girls in Kamla Market (DELHI) 🔝 >༒9953330565🔝 genuine Escort Service 🔝✔️✔️
call girls in Kamla Market (DELHI) 🔝 >༒9953330565🔝 genuine Escort Service 🔝✔️✔️
 
Interactive Powerpoint_How to Master effective communication
Interactive Powerpoint_How to Master effective communicationInteractive Powerpoint_How to Master effective communication
Interactive Powerpoint_How to Master effective communication
 
Biting mechanism of poisonous snakes.pdf
Biting mechanism of poisonous snakes.pdfBiting mechanism of poisonous snakes.pdf
Biting mechanism of poisonous snakes.pdf
 
CARE OF CHILD IN INCUBATOR..........pptx
CARE OF CHILD IN INCUBATOR..........pptxCARE OF CHILD IN INCUBATOR..........pptx
CARE OF CHILD IN INCUBATOR..........pptx
 
9953330565 Low Rate Call Girls In Rohini Delhi NCR
9953330565 Low Rate Call Girls In Rohini  Delhi NCR9953330565 Low Rate Call Girls In Rohini  Delhi NCR
9953330565 Low Rate Call Girls In Rohini Delhi NCR
 
Historical philosophical, theoretical, and legal foundations of special and i...
Historical philosophical, theoretical, and legal foundations of special and i...Historical philosophical, theoretical, and legal foundations of special and i...
Historical philosophical, theoretical, and legal foundations of special and i...
 
Types of Journalistic Writing Grade 8.pptx
Types of Journalistic Writing Grade 8.pptxTypes of Journalistic Writing Grade 8.pptx
Types of Journalistic Writing Grade 8.pptx
 

The default pull: An experimental demonstration of subtle default effects on preferences

  • 1. Judgment and Decision Making, Vol. 7, No. 1, January 2012, pp. 69–76 The default pull: An experimental demonstration of subtle default effects on preferences Nikhil Dhingra∗ Zach Gorn∗ Andrew Kener∗ Jason Dana† Abstract The impact of default options on choice is a reliable, well-established behavioral finding. However, several different effects may lend to choosing defaults in an often indistinguishable manner, including loss aversion, inattention, infor- mation leakage, and transaction costs associated with switching. We introduce the notion of the “default pull” as the effect that even subtle default options have on decision makers’ uncertainty about their own preferences. The default pull shapes what a decision maker prefers by causing her to consider whether she prefers the default. We demonstrate default pull effects using a simple decision making task that strips away many of the usual reasons that defaults could affect choices, and we show that defaults can have substantial effects on choice, even when the default itself was not chosen. Keywords: default, loss aversion, uncertainty. 1 Introduction Perhaps one of the most well-established behavioral de- cision making effects is the effect of default options on choice. People choose options presented as defaults more often than they otherwise would, even for important de- cisions that would seem to require careful thought, such as choosing health care or retirement plans (for several examples, see Thaler & Sunstein, 2008). But under the umbrella that is “default bias” are several different ef- fects that all point in the direction of choosing the default. Mere inattention could lead some decision makers to re- tain a default if action is required only when opting out of the default. Loss-averse decision makers may not want to give up the default because it feels like a loss that is more painful than gaining a different option is pleasurable (Kahneman, Knetsch, & Thaler, 1991; Camerer, 2004). The fact that someone has set an option as a default can create an “information leakage” (McKenzie, Liersch, & Finkelstein, 2006; Sher & McKenzie, 2006) from which people might infer normative reasons for choosing the de- fault. Finally, people may choose defaults when there are sufficient transaction costs of money or time in choosing an alternative. We examine an effect of default options on choices that we call the default pull. The default pull is the effect ∗University of Pennsylvania †Corresponding author: University of Pennsylvania, Dept. of Psychology, 3720 Walnut St., Philadelphia PA 19104. Email: danajd@psych.upenn.edu. that default options have on decision makers’ uncertainty about their own preferences. When deciding what one likes, we argue that even subtle defaults can help to shape what a decision maker prefers by causing her to consider whether she prefers the default. This process provides a link between how defaults influence choices and how an- chors influence judgments (Strack & Mussweiler, 1997). In this way, the default pull effect is a kind of constructed preference (Slovic, 1995), wherein the manner in which preference is elicited influences what one’s preferences are. Unlike many findings that people stick with the de- fault, we show that the default pull sometimes involves choosing the default and sometimes involves choosing something different from what one otherwise would in the presence of a default, but not the default itself. To study the default pull, we use a motivated experi- mental choice that strips away many of the common rea- sons why defaults might work: a modified presentation of a dictator game (Forsythe et al., 1994) in which whatever option is on the top of a list of allocations is left selected on a computer interface, ostensibly unintentionally (see Figure 1). This subtle default option substantially affects players’ choices; different defaults can change the aver- age amount given by 17% of the total endowment. The design and results of our experiment allow us to rule out inattention, loss aversion, information leakage, and trans- action costs as explanations for the effect of the default. Before we describe the specifics of the task, we briefly review the literature on default biases, and then formally define the default pull. 69
  • 2. Judgment and Decision Making, Vol. 7, No. 1, January 2012 Default pull 70 1.1 Default biases Making an option a default that will be retained unless the decision maker actively chooses something else leads to more people choosing the default across a variety of contexts. Johnson et al. (1993) analyzed auto insur- ance choices in two bordering states (New Jersey and Pennsylvania) that switched to a no-fault regime that al- lowed consumers to limit their right to sue for tort dam- ages. New Jersey made limited tort the default option, while Pennsylvanians were presumed to select full tort, for which they would pay higher rates unless they speci- fied that they wanted limited tort. In this natural experi- ment, 75% of Pennsylvania consumers paid to retain full tort, while only 20% of New Jersey consumers did. Penn- sylvanians spent millions of dollars more on auto insur- ance, apparently as a result of this default setting. Stick- ing with the default in this manner has been argued to reflect loss aversion (e.g., Kahneman, Knetsch, & Thaler, 1991; Camerer, 2004), with the default choice represent- ing the reference point. If full tort is a default, then the prospect of losing it makes it seem more valuable than the prospect of gaining it, due to the steeper slope of the Prospect Theory value function in losses. Similarly, Korobkin (1998) demonstrates default ef- fects in an experiment with legal contract default rules that are consistent with loss aversion. Law student sub- jects provided advice to clients in hypothetical contract negotiation scenarios, with the content of the legal default terms (e.g., limited or full liability) manipulated between experimental groups. The results show that the choice of default terms subsequently affected the students’ prefer- ences for the terms of their contract. While the standard law and economics view is that defaults promote efficient bargaining, these results suggest that the choice of legal default terms can be problematic because it can also di- rectly affect what terms the contracting parties prefer. Another explanation for choosing defaults is that for unfamiliar decisions, consumers see defaults as carrying normative information that serves as guidance for their decision making. In the example above, if the state saw fit to make full tort rights the default, then some might reason that it is unwise to relinquish this right unless they feel sure of the consequences. Thaler and Sunstein (2008) discuss the ramifications of default options in the con- text of the Medicare Part D prescription drug program, which can be difficult for some consumers to navigate. Subjects who failed to sign up for a plan, perhaps be- cause they were overwhelmed with the choice, were as- signed to default plans and once assigned to such default plans, may never switch. This bias toward the status quo (Samuelson & Zeckhauser, 1988) has been demonstrated for similar decisions, e.g., sticking with one’s retirement plan provider when new options become available, even though most people making the choice for the first time prefer the new options. Defaults have been to shown to have effects on a wide variety of health decisions. For example, employees are more likely to get flu vaccinations when given a default appointment time than when asked to set an appointment (Chapman et al., 2010) and cadaveric organ donation rates increase when people are presumed to be donors (Johnson & Goldstein, 2003). Abadie and Gay (2006) examine default options within the opt-in/opt-out struc- ture of cadaveric organ donation. In opt-in systems of in- formed consent, one must demonstrate explicit consent to being a donor, e.g., checking a box that says one wants to donate her organs in the event of death, while with opt-out systems of presumed consent, one is classified as a poten- tial donor unless one actively opposes donation. Across 22 nations, opt-out structures were found to increase the number of people choosing to be organ donors. It is un- clear how much the default conveyed normative informa- tion about what one should choose or how much transac- tion costs influenced the decision to stick with the default. 1.2 Default pull effect In this section, we present a formal representation of the default pull effect that borrows from Kreps’ (1979) preference for flexibility model. Default effects have been formally modeled using (A, f) representations (see Salant & Rubinstein, 2008), where preference is a func- tion of both the choice options available and the frame, taken to include problems in which one option is a de- fault. Axiomatic models of choice where defaults af- fect preferences (Masatlioglu & Ok, 2005; Sagi, 2006) have also been developed, but all of these representa- tions do not necessarily distinguish among reasons why the default affects preferences. We chose a representation that describes the default as helping to resolve a decision maker’s own uncertainty about preferences. Unlike the many findings of people sticking with a de- fault option, which may be due to loss aversion, infor- mation leakage, inattention, or transaction costs, the de- fault pull effect does not imply that one will stick with the default. Rather, decision makers sometimes retain the default and sometimes move substantially away from it, while still being affected by it. This happens because the default affects the manner in which the decision maker constructs his or her preferences. Decision makers, we argue, recruit information to decide whether the default is plausibly what they prefer, so that, even if the default isn’t chosen, it affects their preferences. To formalize our idea of the default pull, it is help- ful to conceive of variability in choice behavior. For ex- ample, one can imagine that if a subject were asked to make the dictator choice many times with memory be-
  • 3. Judgment and Decision Making, Vol. 7, No. 1, January 2012 Default pull 71 ing wiped out between each choice, he or she might not always choose the same thing. Similarly, the idea of con- structed preference (Payne, Bettman, & Johnson, 1992; Slovic, 1995) is that across a number of different prefer- ence elicitations with the same choice options, a person does not always choose the same thing. The influence of a default option is one such example. If basic pref- erences are indeed shaped by the presence of a default, we need a conception of how decision makers are uncer- tain about what it is that they want. We focus on mixture models (also called random preference models, Loomes & Sugden, 1995; see Heyer & Niederée, 1992; Regen- wetter, Dana, & Davis-Stober, 2010, 2011) as a way to characterize choice variability. Mixture models assume that the decision maker has a probability distribution over the different possible preference orderings of the choice objects. That is, mixture models assume choices vary be- cause the decision has varying preferences across time. As opposed to a true plus error conception of choice variability, wherein a decision maker has one true pref- erence that is expressed with error when making choices, or multi-attribute models that rely on thresholds of no- ticeable differences between attributes to create uncer- tainty in choice (Tversky, 1969; Ariely, Loewenstein, & Prelec, 2003), mixture models seem more naturally re- lated to constructed preference, wherein what one prefers changes as a function of how preferences are elicited. Mixture models hold that when decision makers with variable preferences make a choice, it is as if they make a draw from this probability distribution. For the prefer- ence that they draw, they choose the most preferred op- tion. Applying a mixture model to the case of our dictator game task, we assume that experimental subjects have a probability distribution over all possible preference rank- ings of the allocations. Some rankings might have little or no support in this distribution, e.g., those rankings that place 0–10 as the most preferred option, while empiri- cally, rankings that place 10–0 or 5–5 as the most pre- ferred option should tend to have the most support. The probability that a decision maker selects an allocation is, then, the probability that the allocation is preferred, which in turn is the sum of the probabilities of all pref- erence states which rank that allocation most preferred. Formally stated, Pxy = s∈S x y Ps (1) where Pxy is the probability of choosing allocation x over y, s ∈ S is a preference state (i.e., a ranking of the alloca- tions) from among the set of all possible states, and Ps is the probability that one is in a state that ranks x over y. We can use the mixture model framework to put into expected utility terms a decision maker’s utility for a given menu of choice options. The decision maker has utility us(x) for an allocation x when in a preference state s. Given a menu of options A, like the options available in our dictator game, the decision maker’s utility for the menu, v(A), is the sum of the utilities for the most pre- ferred allocations within each mental state: v(A) = s∈S p(s) max x∈A u(x, s) (2) At this point, our formulation simply represents a pref- erence for flexibility, wherein a decision maker prefers a larger menu because she is uncertain what she will want in the future (Kreps, 1979; see also Ergin & Sarver, 2010). The notion of the default pull is that the presen- tation of options itself, or more precisely which option is presented as the default, somehow influences the decision maker’s preference distribution. For example, because prior literature on dictator games suggests that 0–10 is rarely chosen (see review in Camerer, 2003), one might conclude that it would not even matter if 0–10 was an op- tion presented to the dictator. Yet, our study will show that having the option of 0–10 affects choices, particu- larly when 0–10 is the default, even if the decision maker does not choose 0–10. The default pull suggests that an option defined as a default directly influences the decision maker’s probabil- ity distribution over preferences states. Put differently, the default influences the decision maker’s beliefs about her own preferences. Thus, the particular presentation of a menu becomes important. We can define the decision maker’s utility over pairs (A,a) where A is the menu of all options and a ∈ A is the default option. The decision maker’s utility for a pair (A,a) where the probability dis- tribution over states is referenced by the default is then: v(A, a) = s∈S p(s : (A, a)) max x∈A u(x, s) (3) One way to describe the process is that the decision maker is unsure whether she will ultimately be happy with a particular choice. The presence of a default alloca- tion primes her to consider first whether that allocation is the one she prefers. A literature on anchoring processes in judgment suggests that a selective accessibility takes place (Strack & Musweiler, 1997) in which decision mak- ers test a proposition in a confirmatory manner by first re- cruiting reasons why it might be true. In anchoring pro- cesses, selective accessibility leads to judgments that are closer to an anchor’s value because people have consid- ered reasons why the anchor might be accurate. Here, we suggest a similar process in which the default leads de- cision makers to conclude that their own mixtures place greater weight on some preference states because con- sidering whether they prefer the default triggers “salient considerations” for making the choice (Salant & Rubin- stein, 2008).
  • 4. Judgment and Decision Making, Vol. 7, No. 1, January 2012 Default pull 72 For example, a decision maker faced with a default choice of (0–10) in a dictator game may consider whether she will be happy with being very generous. In doing so, she may recruit reasons why she likes generosity, and as a result conclude that her mixture places more weight on generous outcomes than it otherwise would. Note that this process does not imply that the decision maker will choose the default, in this case (0–10). If the decision maker normally has zero weight on preference states that rank (0–10) highest, she may come away from the process still with zero weight on (0–10), but in recruiting reasons why she likes generosity, support could shift toward plau- sibly favorite but generous allocations like (5–5) so that they are more likely to be chosen. We hypothesize that once the default pull has triggered these salient considerations, they can influence choices beyond the one in which preference construction takes place. That is, the presence of a default choice af- fects the probability distribution over preference states, but that distribution may remain as such for successive choices. In this way, the default pull is similar to work by Ariely, Loewenstein, and Prelec on “coherent arbitrari- ness” (2003) in that there is uncertainty when formulat- ing preferences, but then decision makers behave as if those preferences are stable. The default pull differs from the coherent arbitrariness work in that we suggest a dif- ferent process by which preferences are formulated and conceive of preference uncertainty in a different manner. 2 Experiment We chose our particular formulation of a dictator game to demonstrate the default pull because it strips away several reasons why a default might influence choices. First, the game is incentivized and not particularly complicated, so that there is little reason to believe that the default would be chosen because the task was overwhelming or because subjects were indifferent among the options. Second, it is difficult to apply the loss aversion explanation in a con- sistent manner across our results. Suppose, for example, that a decision maker who normally chooses (10,0) with- out a default chooses (5,5) when it is the default option. We could view own and other’s payoff as separate dimen- sions and thus, choosing (10,0) could seem like a gain of 5 in the “self” dimension, but a loss of 5 in the “other” dimension relative to the default. Standard loss aversion could then be applied if losing 5 in the “other” dimension is more painful than gaining 5 for one’s self is pleasur- able. However, we will show that (5,5) is a modal choice when (0,10) is offered as a default, implying that gaining 5 is better than losing 5 in the “other” dimension. Third, our particular default treatment involves leaving the top option in an apparently random payoff array preselected, subtly encouraging subjects to consider using that option without calling it a default as such. In this way, it is un- likely that the default involves information leakage about what one ought to do. Indeed, several subjects reported either not noticing the default or not realizing that the ex- perimenters left it selected intentionally. Finally, our task uses multiple rounds of the same decision. If inattentive- ness or transaction costs were the reason that subjects left the default selected, then they should leave the default selected in every round. We show that if a default allo- cation is selected in the first round, subjects are likely to seek it out and choose it again in subsequent rounds, even though it is no longer a default and the order of the allo- cations changes in every round. Previous work has noted that dictator games are notori- ously sensitive to context (see, e.g., Bardsley, 2008; List, 2007; Levitt & List, 2007; Dana, Weber, & Kuang, 2007), thus it is not surprising that a manipulation could strongly affect levels of giving. While this prior work draws into question how we should interpret giving and points out how strong demand effects can be in the dictator game, neither concern bears on the question of whether a sub- tle default affects choices. Indeed, our subjects explicitly deny the possibility of a demand affect, overwhelmingly reporting that the default did not affect their choices. 3 Methods 3.1 Subjects Subjects (n = 82) were students at the University of Penn- sylvania, all of whom participated voluntarily in response to an online advertisement for paid decision experiments. All subjects gave informed consent prior to the experi- ment. Seven sessions were run, ranging in size from 6 to 18 subjects. 3.2 Procedures Stimuli were presented via computer interface and in- structions were additionally read aloud. Subjects were instructed that they would play a simple economic game with another person with whom they would be randomly matched and that all identities would be kept anony- mous. Each subject was instructed to complete a series of four consecutive dictator games in which they would choose an allocation of points between themselves and the anonymous person with whom they were matched. Each game consisted of a list of possible divisions of 10 points between the subject and the anonymous other party in whole number amounts. The points were converted to cash at a rate of 25 cents each at the end of the experi- ment, making the total endowment being allocated over the four rounds $10.
  • 5. Judgment and Decision Making, Vol. 7, No. 1, January 2012 Default pull 73 Figure 1: Interface. Figure1.png (PNG Image, 947 × 721 pixels) file:///home/baron/jdm/10/10831a/Figure1.png 1 of 1 01/24/2012 06:08 AM The strategy method was used to elicit choices; all sub- jects were instructed to make choices in the role of dic- tator (described in neutral language as “Player X”) and informed that after all decisions were made, half would be randomly assigned to be Player X, and thus have their choices executed, while the other half (“Player Y”) would not have their choices executed and instead be assigned to be the recipients of the choices made by Player X. No subject could be assigned to be the recipient of his or her own choices. There is some concern that the strat- egy method could affect levels of giving because dictator choices are made while knowing that one could end up being a recipient instead. Our results will show, however, that our subjects gave at somewhat lower levels than av- erage (typically a little under 30%, see Camerer, 2003) when they were not assigned a default. More importantly, we are less concerned in this study with the levels of giv- ing than with differences in giving across default treat- ments. In each round of the game, thirteen possible wealth allocations were presented in a checklist format on the computer interface (see Figure 1 below). These alloca- tions included all 11 of the possible whole divisions of 10 plus 2 distracter allocations that were Pareto-dominated (i.e., summed to less than 10). The distractors changed in each round and were included to promote attentiveness. The order in which the options were presented changed in each round of the game, such that the subject had to search through a randomized list of options to select their choice. Subjects were instructed to select one option in each round and verify their choice before continuing to the next round. “Defaults” were created by leaving the allocation at the top of the list pre-selected on the screen at the beginning of each round (e.g., 10–0 in Figure 1). This situation is common, for example, on web forms where one of the objects on the display must have focus. At no time dur- ing the experiment was mention made of the pre-selected choices. One of four default conditions was assigned in each round, with allocations of (10–0), (5–5), and (0–10) used as defaults in 3 of the rounds, and no default selected in the 4th . The order of default presentation was fully bal- anced; each subject was serially assigned to see one of the 4! = 24 possible orders until all were exhausted and the process was repeated. After subjects completed all four rounds, roles were randomly assigned and subjects were informed of their monetary compensation for the experiment. Subjects then filled out a brief survey including three questions about the experiment. In one version (n = 37), we asked (1) whether they noticed the presence of a pre-selected option; (2) whether the presence of a default affected their choices; and (3) whether their choice in the first round of the experiment affected their choice in subse- quent rounds. For a second group of subjects (n = 32), we replaced question (2) by a free-response question ask- ing why they thought an option was left selected on the screen. For this group of subjects, we only asked the free- response question if they had responded affirmatively to question (1) about noticing that an option had been se- lected. Due to an error in one session and one subject leaving the items blank, 13 subjects did not answer any survey questions. 4 Results 4.1 Dictator choices Within-subject choices stayed largely consistent across the 4 rounds of the experiment. Figure 2 plots the mean amount of points given in each round by which default was presented in round 1. The between-subject effect of having either a fair or hyperfair default in round 1 (5–5 or 0–10) vs. a selfish default (10–0) or no default drowns out the within-subject effect of having different defaults across rounds; mean giving starts relatively high for the fair and hyperfair defaults and remains so through- out the 4 rounds, while giving stays relatively low across all rounds for the selfish default and no default. Choices in the first round were highly correlated with choices in the second, third, and fourth rounds (rs = .71, .52, and .65 respectively). Thus, the default affects choices in round 1, but then recognizing that the subsequent rounds essentially represent iterations of the same decision, sub- jects stay consistent with their earlier choices even though the default changes—a “coherent arbitrariness” of sorts (Ariely, Loewenstein, & Prelec, 2003). In light of the distracter allocations and randomized choice set, the ob-
  • 6. Judgment and Decision Making, Vol. 7, No. 1, January 2012 Default pull 74 Figure 2: Mean amount of points given as a function of the default in round 1. 1 2 3 4 01234 Round Meanpointsgiven (10,0) (5,5) (0,10) no default served behavior strongly supports the idea that subjects did not make their choices through indifference or inat- tentiveness, but rather actively remained consistent by having to search through the list in each round for the desired allocation. We will focus the remainder of our analyses on the between-subject effects of the round 1 default on the total amount a dictator gave. Figure 3 displays the mean amount of money players gave for each of the default conditions. Choices were strongly affected by the presence of first-round defaults. Overall, giving was higher in the 5–5 (n = 21) and 0–10 (n = 20) default conditions (ms = $2.71 and $3.14, re- spectively) than in the 10–0 (n = 22) and no default (n = 19) conditions (ms = $1.47 and $2.09, respectively), so that the default that a subject received in the first round could influence the amount they gave overall by about 17% of the total endowment. The omnibus null hypothe- sis of equal giving across all default conditions can be re- jected (F(3,78) = 3.17, p = .029), while a planned contrast confirms that giving in the 5–5 and 0–10 default groups combined is significantly higher than in the 10–0 and no default groups combined (t(78) = -2.74, p = .008). Fur- ther planned contrasts reveal that giving is significantly less in the 10–0 default condition than in both the 5–5 default condition (t(78) = -2.07, p = .04) and the 0–10 de- fault condition (t(78) = 2.91, p = .005). No significant differences emerged between giving in the 10–0 and no default groups, suggesting that keeping the endowment was a sort of default position of our subjects. Further, we failed to reject the null hypothesis of equal giving be- tween the 5–5 and 0–10 default groups, consistent with the idea that our subjects, while affected by the default, did not just stick with the default. Figure 3: Mean total dollar amounts given out by dic- tators and standard errors by which default they saw in round 1. (10,0) (5,5) (0,10) No default Default Meandollaramountsgiven 0.00.51.01.52.02.53.03.5 The effect of the first-round default clearly did not de- pend on choices of the default itself. We eliminated all cases in which 10 or 0 contribution was chosen, then ex- amined contributions (mean contribution over the four rounds) as a function of the first-round default, looking only at those subjects who received 10 or 0 as the first- round default. The mean contributions were 3.61 when the first-round default was 0 and 4.66 when it was 10, and these differed significantly (t(13) = 2.87, p = .013). Figure 4 displays the frequencies of giving decisions across all rounds when facing each first round default condition. We note that the distribution of choices when facing the (5,5) and (0,10) defaults is nearly identical. While the large number of even split choices in the (5– 5) default condition could be attributed to subjects retain- ing the default, we note that a similar number of subjects chose the even split when the default was (0–10). Further, gifts of the entire 10 points were uncommon, even when the default was 0–10. This behavior is consistent with our idea of the default pull: Subjects are not necessarily sticking with the default, though the default affects be- havior. The default is sometimes used if it is a plausibly favorite allocation, as in the case of (5–5), but only affects choices without being chosen itself when not a plausi- bly preferred allocation, as in the case of (0–10). This behavioral result is thus consistent with subjects having uncertainty over what they want and using the default to construct their preferences.
  • 7. Judgment and Decision Making, Vol. 7, No. 1, January 2012 Default pull 75 Figure 4: Frequency of amounts given in any round as a function of the default. 0103050 Default 10−0 051525 Default 5−5 051020 Default 0−10 0 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 0102030 No default 4.2 Survey responses Survey responses confirmed the subtlety of the default manipulation. Approximately 29% (20/69) of subjects reported that they had not even noticed the presence of a pre-selected option on the screen. Although the presence of this option had an effect on choices, of 37 respondents who were asked explicitly whether their choices were in- fluenced by the default, only 3 (8%) replied that it had. Of the 32 subjects assigned to be probed about why an option was pre-selected, 26 noticed the default. Interestingly, 18 of these 26 responses suggested in some way the possi- bility that the experimenter was trying to influence their choice with the pre-selected option. Apparently, subjects considered that a default might be an attempt to influence them, but did not believe that it worked to affect their own choices. Further, only 29 out of 69 (42%) felt that their choice in the first round influenced the choices in subsequent rounds, despite the fact that choices in later rounds were strongly correlated with first round choices. Taken together, these responses are consistent with Nis- bett and Wilson’s (1977) classic findings on “telling more than we can know”. While the effects of the default in the first round and status quo in subsequent rounds are quite evident when viewed between-subject, the subjects them- selves do not appear to experience the default as affecting their choices. These results speak against an information leakage explanation of why defaults worked in this set- ting, as subjects are explicitly denying that they are using the default to make choices. 5 Discussion We have shown evidence of a default pull effect wherein people appear to be affected by subtly presented default options while constructing their preferences. Unlike bi- ases toward sticking with the default, the default pull affects choices even though decision makers may not choose the default itself. Additionally, we have shown evidence that the default pull happens outside of the de- cision maker’s awareness; almost all of our subjects de- nied that they were affected by the presence of a default despite statistical evidence to the contrary, and a size- able portion of our subjects reported not even noticing the presence of defaults. Finally, we show that even though preferences are largely determined by an arbitrary de- fault, decision makers try to remain consistent with those preferences in future decisions, a sort of “coherent arbi- trariness” (Ariely, Loewenstein, & Prelec, 2003). One concern is that the default pull effects we find are the result of poor incentives. Although our payment was standard for this type of task, it represented compensation for 4 such choices combined. This payment structure, however, was transparent to subjects, who also tended to choose the same thing across all 4 rounds, so the total in- centives they faced were standard. Further, a lack of mo- tivation would predict the opposite of what we observed: If people were not making careful choices, we wouldn’t find systematic differences based on defaults. These dif- ferences did not arise from laziness: a (0–10) default was rarely chosen, for example, but it did lead subjects to seek out (5–5). Further, defaults that were retained in round 1 often led subjects to seek out that same allocation in sub- sequent rounds, even though it was not a default. The present findings can enrich our understanding of how defaults affect behavior. While defaults can be cho- sen for many reasons including loss aversion, inatten- tiveness, information leakage, and transaction costs, we show that default options can subtly affect preferences in a more fundamental way by serving as a cue by which people decide what they like. That people do not have access into this mental process points to a reason why the effects of arbitrary defaults are so persistent. Because people do not consciously realize when defaults affect their choices, they cannot effectively learn not to be af- fected by them. For decisions such as what prescription plan to choose, whether to waive one’s right to full tort, or, as in our case, how generous to be, it remains unclear how a market would punish the default pull and promote resistance to the effects of arbitrary defaults, thus allow- ing default effects to persist in the face of incentives to be unbiased.
  • 8. Judgment and Decision Making, Vol. 7, No. 1, January 2012 Default pull 76 References Abadie, A., Gay, S. (2006). The Impact of Presumed Consent Legislation on Cadaveric Organ Donation: A Cross Country Study. Journal of Health Economics, 25, 599–620. Ariely, D., Loewenstein, G., & Prelec, D. (2003). Coher- ent Arbitrariness: Stable Demand Curves without Sta- ble Preferences. The Quarterly Journal of Economics, 1, 73–105. Bardsley, N. (2008). Dictator Game Giving: Altruism or Artifact? Journal of Experimental Economics, 11, 122–133. Camerer, C. (2003). Behavioral Game Theory: Experi- ments on Strategic Interaction. Princeton, NJ: Prince- ton University Press. Camerer, C. (2004). Prospect theory in the wild: Ev- idence from the field. In Camerer, C., Loewenstein, G., and Rabin, M. (Eds): Advances in behavioral eco- nomics. New York: Princeton University Press. Chapman, G.B., Li, M., Colby, H., & Yoon, H. (2010). Opting in versus opting out of influenza vaccination. JAMA, 304, 43–44. Dana, J., Weber, R., & Kuang, J. (2007). Exploiting Moral Wriggle Room: Behavior Inconsistent with a Preference for Fair Outcomes. Journal of Economic Theory, 1, 67–80. Ergin, H., & Sarver, T. (2010). A unique costly contem- plation representation. Econometrica, 78, 1285–1339. Forsythe, R., Horowitz, J., Savin, N.E., & Sefton, M. (1994). Fairness in Simple Bargaining Experiments. Games and Economic Behavior, 6, 347–69. Heyer, D., & Niederée, R. (1992). Generalizing the con- cept of binary choice systems induced by rankings: One way of probabilizing deterministic measurement structures. Mathematical Social Sciences, 23, 31–44. Johnson, E. & Goldstein, D. (2003). Do defaults save lives? Science, 302, 1338–1339. Johnson, E., Hershey, J., Meszaros, J., & Kunreuther, H. (1993). Framing, Probability Distortions, and Insur- ance Decisions. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 1, 35–51. Kahneman, D., Knetsch, J., & Thaler, R. (1991). Anoma- lies: The Endowment Effect, Loss Aversion, and Status Quo Bias. Journal of Economic Perspectives, 5, 193– 206. Korobkin, R. (1998). The Status Quo Bias and Contract Default Rules. Cornell Law Review, 83, 609–687. Kreps, D. (1988). A representation theorem for “prefer- ence for flexibility.” Econometrica, 47, 565–577. Levitt, S., & List, J. (2007). What do Laboratory Exper- iments Measuring Social Preferences tell us about the Real World? Journal of Economic Perspectives, 21, 153–174. List, J. (2007). On the Interpretation of Giving in Dictator Games. Journal of Political Economy, 3, 482–493. Loomes, G., & Sugden, R. (1995). Incorporating a stochastic element into decision theories. European Economic Review, 39, 641–648. Masatlioglu, Y., & Ok, E. (2005) Rational choice with status quo bias. Journal of Economic Theory, 121, 1– 29. McKenzie, C. R. M., Liersch, M. J., & Finkelstein, S. R. (2006). Recommendations implicit in policy defaults. Psychological Science, 17, 414–420. Nisbett, R., & Wilson, T. (1977). Telling more than we can know: Verbal reports on mental processes. Psy- chological Review, 84, 231–259. Payne, J., Bettman, J. & Johnson, E. (1992). Behavioral decision research: A constructive process perspective. Annual Review of Psychology, 43, 87–131. Regenwetter, M., Dana, J., & Davis-Stober, C. (2010). Testing transitivity of preferences on two-alternative forced choice data. Frontiers of Quantitative Psychol- ogy and Measurement, 1, 1–15. Regenwetter, M., Dana, J., & Davis-Stober, C. (2011). Transitivity of preferences. Psychological Review, 118, 42–56. Sagi, J. (2006). Anchored preference relations. Journal of Economic Theory, 130, 283–295. Salant, Y. & Rubinstein, A. (2008). (A, f): Choice with frames. Review of Economic Studies, 75, 1287–1296. Samuelson, W., & Zeckhauser, R. (1988). Status quo bias in decision making. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 1, 7–59. Sher, S., & McKenzie, C. R. M. (2006). Information leakage from logically equivalent frames. Cognition, 101, 467–494. Slovic, P. (1995). The construction of preference. Amer- ican Psychologist, 50, 364–371. Strack, F., & Mussweiler, T. (1997). Explaining the enig- matic anchoring effect: Mechanisms of selective ac- cessibility. Journal of Personality and Social Psychol- ogy, 73, 437–446. Thaler, R., & Sunstein, C. (2008). Nudge: improving decisions about health, wealth, and happiness. New Haven: Yale University Press. Tversky, A. (1969). Intransitivity of preferences. Psycho- logical Review, 76, 31–48.