SlideShare a Scribd company logo
1 of 237
Jean-Paul Sartre
What is Existentialism?
In his 1945 lecture on existentialism and humanism, Jean-Paul
Sartre asserts: “existentialism is nothing else but an attempt to
draw all the conclusions from a coherent atheist position.” He
begins his explication of existentialist philosophy by discussing
one of its key concepts: that existence precedes essence.
Let us, he says, consider any man-made object, a book or paper
cutter, for instance. Here is an object that began as a concept or
idea in the mind of the artisan who designed and constructed it.
The concept involves the manner by which the paper cutter is
constructed and, more importantly, the specific purpose or use
to which it is put (in this case, to cut paper). “Therefore,” Sartre
concludes,
let us say that, for the paper-cutter, essence—that is, the
ensemble of both the production routines and the properties
which enable it to be both produced and defined—precedes
existence…Therefore, we have here a technical view of the
world whereby it can be said that production precedes
existence.
In other words, in the “technical view of the world,” the
“essence” of the artifact precedes the actual physical existence
of the artifact, in the sense that the blueprint or concept of the
paper-cutter already exists in the artisan’s mind before he ever
commits to its actual production in his workshop.
When we conceive God as the Creator, Sartre continues, He is
thought of as a kind of superhuman artisan: God creates the
Earth and the human species according to a deliberate and
specific plan or idea: “Thus, the concept of man in the mind of
God is comparable to the concept of paper-cutter in the mind of
the manufacturer, and, following certain techniques and a
conception, God produces man, just as the artisan, following a
definition and a technique, makes a paper-cutter.” The concept
of mankind in the divine intelligence is what we refer to as
“human nature”: it defines mankind in terms of what we are and
how we are meant to live (as we see, for example, in the natural
law teaching of St. Thomas Aquinas).
Atheistic existentialism, Sartre claims, is a more coherent
doctrine. It states: “if God does not exist, there is at least one
being in whom existence precedes essence, a being who exists
before he can be defined by any concept, and this being is
man…” That is, man first of all exists, “turns up, appears on the
scene, and, only afterwards, defines himself.” Because there is
no God who conceives the concept “man” and then creates
mankind according to that concept, there is no such thing as
human nature. There is, in other words, no particular reason
“why” we as a species are here. We are indeterminate beings,
without any fixed essence of nature, and hence entirely free to
live our lives in whatever manner we choose. The first principle
of existentialism is that “man is nothing else but what he makes
of himself.” Sartre also refers to this principle as “subjectivity.”
Let us explore it in greater detail.
Unlike inert or non-conscious objects like stones and tables,
man has a kind of intrinsic dignity insofar as he is a being who
“is at the start a plan which is aware of itself…” “Nothing
exists prior to this plan; there is nothing in heaven; man will be
what he will have planned to be.” The human being creates his
own essence or nature through his freely chosen acts, there
being no pre-determined human nature with which he is stamped
at conception and to which he must conform his actions. Thus if
existence precedes essence, then “man is responsible for what
he is.” And to be responsible for our own individuality
necessarily entails being “responsible for all men,” for “in
creating the man that we want to be… [we] at the same time
create an image of man as we think he ought to be.” In other
words, when we make a fundamental choice in life, we do so
according to a set of personally chosen values which projects a
certain image of ourselves as we choose to be, and by extension
we are projecting an ideal image of man as we think he ought to
be. For example,
if I want to marry, to have children; even if this marriage
depends solely on my own circumstances or passion or wish, I
am involving all humanity in monogamy and not merely myself.
Therefore, I am responsible for myself and for everyone else. I
am creating a certain image of man of my own choosing. In
choosing myself, I choose man.
Anguish, Forlornness, Despair
By anguish Sartre means that “the man who involves himself
and who realizes that he is not only the person he chooses to be,
but also a law-maker who is, at the same time, choosing all
mankind as well as himself, cannot escape the feeling of his
total and deep responsibility.” Because man is free and at the
same time responsible, he cannot escape the feeling of immense,
deep, and total responsibility not only for his own actions but
also for other men, since by choosing himself he assumes the
responsibility of creating an image for all of humanity. His
actions, therefore, are those of a lawmaker to whom “everything
happens as if all mankind had its eyes fixed on him and were
guiding itself by what he does.” Of course, many people attempt
to flee from anxiety either by renouncing freedom (through
relying on the advice of others instead of deciding on our own)
or through self-deception (by believing that our actions have no
affect on anyone else). If we are truly honest with ourselves, we
recognize the disquieting and inescapable fact that we alone
must choose what to do, without relying on any external source
of guidance, however comforting that may be. Thus, in making
a decision, one “cannot help having a certain anguish.”
“When we speak of forlornness,” writes Sartre, “we mean only
that God does not exist and that we have to face all the
consequences of this.” Sartre exposes the naivety of the casual
or fashionable atheist who believes one can maintain a secular
ethics while dispensing with the need for God altogether. The
rationale of these superficial thinkers runs as follows:
God is a useless and costly hypothesis; we are discarding it, but
meanwhile, in order for there to be an ethics, a society, a
civilization, it is essential that certain values be taken seriously
and that they be considered as having an a priori existence. It
must be obligatory, a priori, to be honest, not to lie, not to beat
your wife, to have children, etc., ...In other words…nothing will
be changed if God does not exist. We shall find ourselves with
the same norms of honesty, progress, and humanism, and we
shall have made of God an outdated hypothesis which will
peacefully die off by itself.
The thoughtless atheist wants to have the best of both worlds—
that is, to jettison entirely the belief in God (with all the
irksome restraints on our personal liberty such belief
necessarily entails) while at the same time preserving the
universal moral structure that makes civilization possible (but
for which there is absolutely no place in a godless universe).
The existentialist, on the other hand, “thinks it very distressing
that God does not exist,” for once God is out of the picture,
“there can be no longer an a priori Good, since there is no
infinite and perfect consciousness to think it.” If God does not
exist, then “everything is permitted” because, to invoke St.
Thomas Aquinas, there would be no natural and eternal law to
define and punish evil and injustice. This key insight “is the
very starting point of existentialism,” and as a result man is
forlorn, consumed by a feeling of abandonment, “because
neither within him nor without does he find anything to cling
to.” We are utterly alone in the universe, without any natural (or
supernatural) basis by which we can guide and assess our lives
(This should remind you of Nietzsche’s “Mad Man and the
Death of God”). Hence Sartre’s famous dictum that “man is
condemned to be free.” Condemned, because he is not self-
created, yet, in other respects free; “because, once thrown into
the world, he is responsible for everything he does.”
In order to give us a better understanding of forlornness, Sartre
refers to one of his students, who sought his advice on whether
or not to join the French resistance, rather than stay with his
mother. Sartre points out that no world-view or ideology
(outside of existentialism) would be of any use to this boy
because universal values are too vague and broad for the
concrete and specific dilemmas each of us faces in life. For this
reason Sartre says: “the only thing left for us is to trust our
instincts,” by which he means that, “in the end, feeling is what
counts. I ought to choose whichever pushes me in one
direction.” His young student, embracing his freedom and
responsibility, ought therefore to reach a decision in the
following way:
If I feel that I love my mother enough to sacrifice everything
else for her—my desire for vengeance, for action, for
adventure—then I’ll stay with her. If, on the contrary, I feel that
my love for my mother isn’t enough, I’ll leave.
But how do we determine the value of a “feeling”? For Sartre, it
is precisely through action that we determine the value of our
“instincts.” By choosing to stay with his mother, the boy’s
feeling for her acquires value; but short of an “act which
confirms and defines it,” such “feeling” is worthless. In other
words, despite what we may think of ourselves in the safety of
our imagination, we cannot possibly know how we would act in
a given situation until we actually find ourselves in that
situation, being forced by circumstances to make a choice one
way or the other: “I may say that I like so-and-so well enough
to sacrifice a certain amount of money for him, but I may say so
only if I’ve done it.”
We arrive finally at Sartre’s analysis of despair, which results
from our awareness that there are a multitude of factors in life
that lie completely beyond our control. Thus when “we want
something, we always have to reckon with probabilities.” “The
moment,” Sartre continues, “the possibilities I am considering
are not rigorously involved by my action, I ought to disengage
myself from them, because no God, no scheme, can adapt the
world and its possibilities to my will.” Thus no matter how well
thought out your plan, no matter how determined your will,
there will be contingencies you cannot influence. You may, for
example, develop a detailed, long-term plan to become, say, an
engineer. You may study hard and get into the best schools. But
then one day, as you are driving home late one night after a
graduate seminar, someone runs a red light and hits your car on
the driver’s side, causing you severe and permanent brain
damage, and thus in one stroke destroying your chances of
fulfilling your plan to become an engineer. Or perhaps you meet
the person you think is your “soul mate,” and you invest much
effort and hope in building a life-long relationship with that
person, only to find out that after ten years of marriage, your
spouse has been cheating on you all along.
The lesson here is that it is impossible to conquer chance: hence
Descartes’ famous dictum: “Conquer yourself rather than the
world,” by which he means that you should accommodate your
will to what is probable—knowing full well that circumstances
outside of your control may hinder your plans—rather than
expect the world (through belief in, for example, Divine
Providence, or destiny) to adapt itself to your will, hopes, or
desires. “Does this mean,” Sartre asks, “that I should abandon
myself to quietism? No. First, I should involve myself; then, act
on the old saying, ‘Nothing ventured, nothing gained.’” The
existentialist says to himself: “I shall have no illusions and
shall do what I can.” This is the very opposite of quietism, since
it declares that (in a most fitting end to a chapter on atheistic
existentialism)
Man is nothing else than his plan; he exists only to the extent
that he fulfills himself; he is, therefore, nothing else than the
ensemble of his acts, nothing else than his life.
BLACK AND BROWN BODIES AND CRIMINAL JUSTICE
SYSTEMS
Criminal Justice Seminar 389 (01:202:389)
Topics in Latino and Caribbean Studies 312 (01:595:312:02)
GUIDELINES FOR SUBMITTING WEEKLY READING
SUMMARIES
(The first weekly reading summary is due via Canvas Upload by
11:59pm EST on MONDAY, SEP 9 for the Gottschalk and
Michalowski readings.)
FOR EACH READING:
Part 1:
In your own words, provide an executive summary of the
assigned reading. You might do this by succinctly covering the
main points, contributions, or overall relevance of the
reading(s). (300-500 words per reading.)
Note: Direct quotes/excerpts of the article are appropriate if
they are brief. The main priority is to summarize the article
using your own original perspective and reception.
Part 2:
2a: In 1-2 sentences, provide one substantive compliment,
reflection, or brief analysis of the assigned reading(s).
2b: In 1-2 sentences, provide one substantive critique, area of
improvement, or general assessment of the reading.
Note: Stating “it was too long” or “I just hated it in
general” does not qualify.
Part 3:
Based on your reception of the reading(s), list two substantive
questions for the instructor to consider. If there is more than
one reading assigned, provide at least one question per reading.
You may submit these questions in bullet-point format.
“Democracy and the Carceral State in America”. Gottschalk,
2014
PART ONE
Gottschalk defines the “carceral state” as the prison and jail
system as well as any punishments that are imposed for state
defined crimes. The author describes the desire to reach the
American Dream as the glue that binds society together and says
that the United States’ status as a “carceral state” inherently
inhibits a large number of individuals (~7 million people,
disproportionately affecting racial minorities) from reaching
this dream, causing complete disenfranchisement. This
disenfranchisement not only includes the individuals with
criminal histories, but their children who have had their lives
negatively impacted by this negative environment. The 2007
Great Recession caused budget cuts to the penal system that has
created an optimism about the end of this carceral state, but
Gottschalk says this optimism is largely unwarranted. The hope
was that due to these budget cuts, the same number of
individuals being incarcerated was no longer fiscally feasible,
but there has been no clear indication that an end of the carceral
state is near. The issue of a carceral state is not based on any
fiscal details, but the political implications that surround it.
Framing the issue of mass incarceration as a fiscal problem
won’t cause any change, in fact, Gottschalk says that there’s no
single factor that could dismantle the system because this isn’t a
fiscal problem isn’t great enough for it to become a focus in the
political system. Political issues such as the War on Drugs have
gotten a greater spotlight than the mass incarceration, and this
“war” has led to higher incarceration rates among commonly
underfunded/underrepresented minorities. Gottschalk goes on to
say that The United States will always view crime as a political
issue because laws are essentially determined by what’s in the
best interest of the state and of the society. To enact real
change, the author looks at Finland as a case study. Finland
focused their efforts on penal reform, especially on sentencing
reform and successfully brought down their also very high
incarceration rates. Gottschalk believes that if the goal is to end
mass incarceration, then policymakers should stop focusing so
heavily on the causes of crime and structural problems within
the penal system and start focusing on the punishments for
crimes that require jail/prison time.
PART TWO
I appreciate that Gottschalk used another country as an example
when talking about how to lower incarceration rates because it
shows what’s been effective for others. However, I think it
would have been more effective to delve deeper into how
exactly Finland enacted sentencing reform that brought down
incarceration rates, especially when the author was trying to
convince the reader that the focus of policymakers should be on
sentencing.
PART THREE
1. Should the US focus on reworking what constitutes a crime or
what the punishment for already defined crimes should be?
“What is Crime?”. Michalowski, 2016
PART ONE
Michalowski begins this reading with discussing his critiques of
orthodox criminology. The first, he explains is that there’s a
disconnect between harm and crime within the study of
criminology. He later goes on to elaborate that just because an
act is harmful does not mean that the same act is criminal
(legalist constraint). The next critique is that because of anti-
communism and the prominence of functionalism within
society, there is less of a sociological analysis of laws. Third,
he says there’s too great of a focus on the definitions of crime
and it’s keeping the victims of these crimes from getting the
necessary attention. Fourth, “anti criminology” (Cohen, 1988)
emergencies lead to issues balancing the study of crime with
other issues that emerge in society that may lead to crime. Last,
the study of analogous social injury allows criminologists to
learn that while some crimes are especially harmful, some
social injustices that aren’t against the law are still more
destructive. Michalowski presents two definitions of crime: 1.
An act that a state has determined to be wrongful and requires
punishment, and 2. An act that is not illegal but is shameful.
Crime is usually determined by which acts in human behavior
are considered devious. The powers of the state determine
which of these acts should receive punishment and what those
punishments should be. However, much of the time, these
punishments are influenced by the socioeconomic status that
most of the offenders of this crime hold. There is discussion
about the constraints that hold back the study of criminology.
The legalist constraint, as mentioned previously, corporate
constraints, and professional constraints. The corporate
constraint focuses on the social injuries resulting from corrupt
(but not illegal) profits made by corporations, which, since not
criminal, are not studied. Michalowski says that criminological
analysis requires class analysis and uses white collar crime as
an example of this. Violent crimes, such as rape or murder, and
property crimes, such as arson or burglary, receive the bulk of
the attention by criminologists, both because it’s the crimes that
people most fear will happen to them and that they’re easier to
spot. White collar crimes, like money laundering and
embezzlement, can take years to be found and (usually) receive
little to no attention. Michalowski sees the irony: white collar
crimes are especially devious in that there is typically no
personal connection with any of the victims of that crime and
the crime was committed solely for malevolent purposes.
Coincidentally, many of the individuals committing these less
visible crimes are the ones controlling the system. The
professional constraint discusses the hardships facing
criminologists trying to hold a job: in order to stay mainstream
in their studies, they have to study mainstream crimes and
prisons which are disproportionately filled with lower income,
underrepresented individuals. There is no criminology without
crime and in order to define crime, an understanding of
criminology is needed. Michalowski says the purpose of
criminology is to analyze the forms of social injury that are
monitored closely by the state with only some having
punishments.
PART TWO
I agreed with the two definitions of crime presented in the
reading. My issue came with the statement that in order to
define crime, an understanding of the purpose of criminology is
needed. Ethical crimes, such as lynching (as discussed in the
reading), are merely misconduct in the eyes of the law but in my
opinion, should still be included in the discussion of crime
despite criminologists not studying it.
PART THREE
1. Should it be the role of policymakers or criminologists to
delve deeper into the effects of ethical crimes?
[Name] 1
[Name]
Professor León
Black and Brown Bodies in CJS
September 9, 2019
Weekly Reading Summary 1
Raymond J. Michalowski’s work called What is Crime?
tackles the question of what would be considered to be a crime
throughout history. With the definition of crime being set it also
could change the way the definition of criminology could be
altered. Michalowski starts the article off by explaining why he
started to dissect the question of what could be considered a
crime. With this question in his mind, he started to think about
the concept of orthodox criminology and goes on to use this
concept within the rest of the article. Using the term towards
finding a clear definition, even if it sounds impossible, for
solutions for “crime problems” as he mentions. Where these
crimes fall under either being a concern for the public or a
crime defined by the state.
Michalowski goes into the history of criminology and some
concepts that were not dared to be explored by sociologists such
as the concept of lynching. Michalowski explains this to be the
concept of ‘constrained criminology’ basically placing the study
of crime into three forms of constraints. The overly controlled
subject of criminology was placed into the categories of legalist
constraint, corporate constraint, and professional constraint,
each giving a point on why they were categorized this way.
Each constraint gives a point to why criminologist strays away
from certain topics involving the law. Legalist constraint going
back to the topic mentioned early such as lynching. This
constraint on criminology explains the difficulty of examining
extreme conditions if they are not going against the law.
Corporate constraints go into the field of corporations and
social class, for example, the case of Big Tobacco companies
having a hand in law-making practices to benefit the companies
and those who invest in these companies. Lastly, Michalowski
talks about professional constraints in studying certain subjects
in criminology. He explained this concept as a danger to one’s
career if they dared to go beyond taboo fields of study in
criminology.
In conclusion with these definitions of constraints and the
history of criminology in the article, Michalowski focuses on
the critiques of furthering the study of certain criminological
themes. Michalowski introduces intriguing points into why
criminology is so limited, especially in the past. Michalowski
wants to embed the idea of changing the way we understand
crime and not just defining it as the usual view of laws being
broken. Since in this case defining crime will ultimately define
criminology as well. Michalowski wants to bring different
factors into defining both crime and criminology and not just
limiting it to the definition of laws and the penal system.
This article kept me on my toes with the concepts it tackled.
Rather than focusing on one topic, it made sure to bring in
different topics and theories to understand the point of the paper
better. Although despite that I found myself stopping to either
re-read a section because it was not clear enough or I just did
not understand it in general. I also had to stop multiple times to
figure out what some words meant but that could also be a
positive since it could help me expand my vocabulary.
· Is it possible for more constraints to be foreseen in the future?
If yes, would the whole idea of how criminology is taught, be
changed?
In Marie Gottschalk’s work labeled Democracy and the Carceral
State in America it starts by talking about Tocqueville and the
history that their work brought. Tocqueville’s work eases the
article into the topic of democracy in America as it gives notes
of his study of the new republic. This article focuses on the
collision the correctional system or ‘Carceral State’ as
Gottschalk claims have born upon American society. Gottschalk
goes into the topic of how the penal system has affected people
along with the floating question of how fair the current, at least
when this article was written, the penal system is. The article
notes on how complicated one’s life could get in they ever find
themselves within the penal system, it can reshape the way their
life would become. For example, people could be denied loans,
housing, and even public service from the government.
Gottschalk also adds the effects it could have towards the
family members of the people who enter the carceral state.
Gottschalk even adds statistics on how children of parents in the
correctional system are affected.
Gottschalk talks about the potential decrease in mass
incarcerations starting at the time of the Great Recession.
During the Great Recession, there were not enough funds to
keep people incarcerated, especially for a long period. This has
started the question of how to control the number of people that
the U.S. places into jail. Even going as far as researching
different countries and how they were able to lower their
incarceration rates. Gottschalk touches upon the topic of the
aspects of lower crime would be by directing the focus on
poverty, unemployment, school systems or even other social
focuses such as race. There is still a sense of urgency to lower
incarceration rates but Gottschalk seems doubtful about it since
it is so embedded into U.S. society.
The article was a great overview recap of the incarceration state
especially with how my former classes last year barely touched
upon the effects it has to be incarcerated. It also gave a great
overview of the ideas of a new policy and how other policies
are being enacted to frame the carceral state better. However,
like the other article, I found myself stopping to go back to
either grasp the concept better or to look up words that I was
unsure about. Not sure if I missed it but also the topic of capital
punishment being noted in the construction on the carceral
state.
· If money was not the problem, would the carceral state even
be considered a problem to be questioned and solved?
[Name]
Professor León
Criminal Justice Seminar 389
September 9th, 2019
Democracy and the Carceral State in America
1. In this article the author makes a clear distinction that the
American penal system has bones in it’s closet, both from the
past and present. It seems that whenever observations are made
about the Carceral State, the findings seem to get swept under
the rug by higher political and economic powers. The Carceral
State here in America seems to have been expanding since the
time of Tocqueville, but appears to have exponentially
expanded since the 1970s. The penal system created by
politicians and other authority figures has led to mass
incarceration of disportionately black and latino communities.
The U.S. penal system enthusiastically locks up minorities
without even considering the negative effects on community,
family, and future of the imprisoned individual. The author
states that there are “nearly 2.3 million people sitting in jail or
prison today in the United States”(Gottschalk 289). This goes to
point out that the United States is leading other nations with the
most amount of its own citizens behind bars. This mass
incarceration of American citizens, predominantly of color, has
led to the American Dream being lost within these communities.
Furthermore, this lost dream is predominantly replaced with
hopelessness, broken families, lost privileges and rights, and an
inability to access things such as public housing and loans. The
author makes the distinction that people who are negatively
affected by the Carceral State are not limited to those locked in
prison or jail, but extends to the many citizens who have a
connection to the criminal justice system, whether it be through
probation, parole, or a family member intertwined within the
system. The author clearly defines the penal system as broken
and in need of fixing. Gottschalk then goes on to show that the
Carceral State is now being treated as a money issue by
politicians, instead of a social justice issue. It is made clear that
the focus should not be on the costs of the carceral system, but
on the fact that it is a broken system, which is currently
destroying the lives of disproportionate members of society.
Because of the high costs of the penal system, it does give
activists the opportunity to help bring down the Carceral State.
However, the single factor of costs alone will never be able to
dismantle such a powerful agency within the United States
government. In conclusion, this article shows that the penal
system in America has been set up in such a way that it targets
demographics of lower minorities, so as long as it does not
affect the pockets of wealthy politicians and those of the upper
class.
2. The author does a good job of providing numbers and
statistics to show precisely how many people are negatively
affected by this unjust system. However, when the author talks
about how many black individuals could be locked up on a
certain day, he does not cross reference it to white individuals,
which most likely would have painted a much more vivid
reality. Furthermore, it did not mention any numbers or facts in
regards to women of color and white women in regards to the
Carceral State.
3. Should we keep individuals in bondage because of their past?
This is in reference to an inmate who has fully served their
sentence, but continues to be discriminated against by being
denied federal benefits, voting rights, and the ability to receive
occupational licenses.
What is Crime?
1. In this article author Raymond J. Michalowski dives into
the meaning of crime, and the practice of criminology and how
it has evolved over the years. He made the realization that crime
is not necessarily about body count, but that it is how certain
groups treat the action which is labeled as a crime. He learned
from studying vehicular homicides, that political power and
economic interests play a crucial role in determining what gets
the attention for something to become a crime and what does
not. Michalowski points out that in society it is most often the
state that determines what is an acceptable action and what is
not, what will be a punishable offense and what will be ignored.
Though the state is the body that makes the final decision on
crime and law, it is often the dominant class in society that gets
its voice heard on what they want legal and what they want
illegal. In most societies, the voice of the lower class and
individuals who are disenfranchised often have no say in the
social ordering of what is crime and what is legal. Therefore,
these lower classes of society are usually negatively affected by
laws which criminalize actions which pertain to people of lower
class status, whereas the rich and elite go unchecked because
they do not back laws that would disproportionately affect their
well-being. When examining this concept through orthodox
criminology, the author pointed to the laws of Jim Crow which
negatively affected people of color, but helped white
supremisitcs retain their control and power in the Deep South.
In this article Michalowski points out the flaws and errors in
regards to orthodox criminology and urges that criminology
should be about social injury and that it is not just about penal
codes. When looking at criminology through a lense of social
injury, it opens the door for criminologists to consider issues
that orthodox criminologists never would have considered such
as social injury through climate change, wrongs committed by
political states, women’s rights, and LGBTQ discrimination. In
conclusion, the author points to the quintessential fact that
crime is not a constant across the board and therefore should be
carefully considered when determining penal code.
2. This article connected brilliantly with “Democracy and the
Carceral State in America” because it shows that the reason why
there is so much ambiguity in regards to the prison system is
because lawmakers do not always consider the interests of the
lower classes, therefore creating laws that result in people of
color being disproportionately incarcerated.
I did feel that the title was somewhat misleading, because it
talked more about understanding the concept of criminology and
studying crime, than it did explaining what is crime.
3. Are there any absolutes when dealing with what is crime? For
instance the U.S believes murder to be wrong and illegal, but
some tribal people would believe that it is okay to murder. Is
there one thing that would be considered a crime everywhere
and always?
https://doi.org/10.1177/0309816818815246
Capital & Class
1 –20
© The Author(s) 2018
Article reuse guidelines:
sagepub.com/journals-permissions
DOI: 10.1177/0309816818815246
journals.sagepub.com/home/cnc
Race, class and persistent
coloniality: US policing
as liberal pacification
Markus Kienscherf
Freie Universität Berlin, Germany
Abstract
This article argues that US policing ends up maintaining and
reinforcing
substantive intersecting racial and class divisions, precisely
because of its
avowed formal neutrality. The article is divided into two main
sections. The
first section sets up a theoretical apparatus for conceptualising
the seeming
contradiction between general and specific social control. This
section argues
that US policing has a colonial genealogy but now serves to
reproduce a neo-
colonial order characterised by both formal legal equality and
substantive racial
and class inequalities. Moreover, this section shows that the
transition from a
colonial to a neo-colonial order has been effected by a change
in policing’s
strategic focus from classical colonial pacification to liberal
pacification, which
combines coercion with developmentalism. Through a
genealogy of US policing,
the second section will demonstrate empirically how US
policing’s shift towards
a strategy of liberal pacification has enabled and continues to
facilitate the (re)
production of a neo-colonial social order. Since this
genealogical section covers
quite a long historical period, it will primarily draw on
secondary sources. By
developing a more nuanced and finely grained policing-as-
pacification model
that highlights both the colonial genealogy and the
contemporary neo-colonial
ontology of US policing, this article helps us better understand
how and why
formally neutral law enforcement ends up producing and
reproducing racial
and class divisions.
Keywords
class struggle, colonialism, liberalism, pacification, police, race
Corresponding author:
Markus Kienscherf, Freie Universität Berlin, Lansstr. 7-9,
14195 Berlin, Germany.
Email: [email protected]
815246 CNC0010.1177/0309816818815246Capital &
ClassKienscherf
research-article2018
Article
https://uk.sagepub.com/en-gb/journals-permissions
https://journals.sagepub.com/home/cnc
http://crossmark.crossref.org/dialog/?doi=10.1177%2F03098168
18815246&domain=pdf&date_stamp=2018-11-27
2 Capital & Class 00(0)
Introduction
In liberal capitalist social formations, policing – ‘the set of
activities aimed at preserving
the security of a particular social order, or social order in
general’ – is characterised by a
fundamental contradiction (Reiner 2010: 5). On the one hand,
state police forces – the
primary institution (albeit not the only one) tasked with
policing – are viewed as largely
neutral, though imperfect, enforcers of existing laws, thus
protecting and serving every-
body irrespective of their race, ethnicity, class, gender or
sexuality. On the other hand,
the police frequently single out particular populations, most
notably the racialised poor,
for much more coercive or even brutal treatment than others. So
policing purports to
ensure the regularity, predictability and security of a general
social order that is said to
serve the common interest and that is predicated on the formal
equality of the rule of
law. At the same time, policing more often than not aims to
secure a specific social order
marked by substantive inequalities along the lines of class, race,
ethnicity, gender and
sexuality (Marenin 1982: 258–259; see also Loader & Walker
2006: 172–175). In
short, policing in advanced capitalist liberal social formations is
torn between general
social control and specific social control, which often amounts
to class and/or racial
control (Reiner 2010: 95).
Whereas liberal police scholarship has traditionally focussed
primarily on the largely
consensual and legitimate aspect of policing (see, for example,
Waddington 1991), a
more radical tradition has pointed out its inherently coercive
and violent character (see
Seigel 2018; Vitale 2017). Yet, any meaningful radical critique
of liberal policing also
needs to tackle policing’s efforts to produce its own legitimacy
and thus also the legiti-
macy of the overall socio-political order through the expansion
of a rationality of neutral
law enforcement that also extends, at least some, police
protection and services to the
racialised poor. In brief, effective radical critique must not just
point out the repressive
aspects of liberal policing but must also engage with its
productive aspects.
This article argues that US policing in particular ends up
maintaining and reinforcing
substantive intersecting racial and class divisions, precisely
because of its avowed formal
neutrality. The article is divided into two main sections. The
first section sets up a theo-
retical apparatus for conceptualising the seeming contradiction
between general and spe-
cific social control. Drawing on the literature on contemporary
coloniality and internal
colonialism, this section argues that US policing has a colonial
genealogy but now serves
to reproduce a neo-colonial order characterised by both formal
legal equality and sub-
stantive racial and class inequalities. Moreover, this section
shows that the transition
from a colonial to a neo-colonial order has been effected by a
change in policing’s strate-
gic focus from classical colonial pacification to liberal
pacification, which combines coer-
cion with developmentalism. The second section will map how
policing in the US
shifted towards a strategy of liberal pacification and how ever
more formally class- and
race-neutral forms of policing have ended up producing and
reinforcing a neo-colonial
social order. Since this genealogical section covers quite a long
historical period, it will
primarily draw on secondary sources.
By developing a more nuanced and finely grained policing-as-
pacification model that
highlights both the colonial genealogy and the contemporary
neo-colonial ontology of
Kienscherf 3
US policing, the article will help us better understand how and
why formally neutral law
enforcement ends up producing and reproducing racial and class
divisions.
Capitalism, (neo-)colonialism and liberal
pacification
Race and class
Policing is the product of conflicting public and private
demands placed on state
police organisations. These conflicting demands are conditioned
by societal conflicts.
In capitalist social formations, class divisions are a key source
of societal conflicts.
Capitalist social formations are societies where the capitalist
mode of production is
the predominant form of economic activity. The capitalist mode
of production is
characterised by private ownership of the means of production
and ‘the generalisation
of the commodity form of labour’ which means that labour
power can be bought and
sold (almost) like any other commodity (Jessop 2002: 12).
Private ownership of the
means of production and the commodification of labour gives
rise to class divisions:
a binary division between the capitalist classes who own the
means of production and
the working classes who must sell their labour power, as well as
more finely grained
class differences that derive from domestic and global divisions
of labour. There are,
however, other sources of societal conflicts besides class
struggles. In capitalist social
formations, conflicts along the lines of race, ethnicity, gender,
sexuality and so on,
become entangled with class struggles even if they cannot be
reduced to them. This
article focuses primarily on how US policing has responded to
and also shaped racial
and class struggles, not because conflicts around gender and
sexuality are less impor-
tant but because race and to a lesser extent class are the main
sticking points in cur-
rent debates about US criminal justice.
The ideology of ‘race’ developed as a direct consequence of the
colonial conquest of
the Americas, where, as Peruvian sociologist Aníbal Quijano
(2000) puts it, ‘[t]he
conquistadors assumed this idea [of race] as the constitutive,
founding element of the
relations of domination that the conquest imposed’ (p. 533). In
the United States, the
ideology of ‘race’ developed through the codification of
differences between free and
enslaved people in order to justify and reproduce slavery ‘in a
republic founded on
radical doctrines of liberty and natural rights, and, more
important a republic in which
those doctrines seemed to represent accurately the world in
which all but a minority
lived’ (Fields & Fields 2014: 141). From the foundation of the
American Republic,
racism and class oppression have been inextricably intertwined.
African Americans
became a ‘race’ because of their oppression, subordination and
exploitation – in short,
because of their violently imposed class position as enslaved
people (Fields & Fields
2014: 266–267). Yet, the ideology of ‘race’ persisted even after
the peculiar class posi-
tion from which it originally derived was abolished. The
ideology of ‘race’ has undoubt-
edly undergone profound historical changes but it still serves to
justify various forms of
racism – that is to say, forms of differential treatment alleged to
result from supposed
and ultimately fictitious innate differences of the individuals
and/or groups who are
4 Capital & Class 00(0)
the victims of discrimination. This is what Karen E Fields and
Barbara J Fields (2014)
call ‘the social alchemy of racecraft [which] transforms racism
into race’ so that ‘[d]
isguised as race, racism becomes something Afro-Americans
are, rather than something
racists do’ (pp. 261, 297). Particular populations are thus
‘racialised’ because they are
the targets of racism and not the other way around. Even though
racism is no longer
directly tied to the class position of enslaved people, in
capitalist social formations in
general and in the United States in particular, racism still serves
to reproduce an easily
exploitable labour force, to segment labour markets and even
‘to exclude populations
from the labor market’ (Grosfoguel 2003: 210).
Contemporary coloniality
Drawing on Aimé Césaire’s (1972: 5) idea of a ‘boomerang
effect of colonization’, schol-
ars have pointed out that attempts to secure social order in the
metropoles have long
been informed by colonial techniques of control (see Arendt
1968; Foucault 2003: 103;
Graham 2010). A number of scholars have noted the cross-
fertilisation of rationalities
and practices of policing between metropole and colony (see,
for example, Brogden
1987; Hönke & Müller 2012; McCoy 2009; Müller 2015). What
has, however, not been
given equal consideration is the idea that contemporary
metropolitan policing may still
serve the largely colonial purpose of producing populations
acquiescent to existing socio-
economic inequities through a targeted application of both
coercion and consent along
the intersecting lines of class and race (McMichael 2017;
Neocleous 2011; 2013; 2014;
Steinmetz et al. 2017; Williams 2011 are notable exceptions).
In their article on ‘American Policing and Colonialism’, Kevin
F Steinmetz et al.
(2017) suggest that ‘contemporary policing in the United States
continues to perpetuate
systems of inequality and domination that, in many ways, mirror
colonial forms of con-
trol’ (p. 9). But does US policing merely ‘mirror colonial forms
of control’? Or is it a
colonial form of control? Is the coloniality of US policing
genealogical or ontological? In
order to answer these questions, we have to briefly consider
what colonialism actually is.
Colonialism is both a form of warfare and rule. The term is
mostly used to describe both
the processes through which an external invader violently
conquers a distant territory
and subdues the local population and the resultant systems of
rule that allow for the
exploitation of geography and people (Blauner 1969; Fanon
2004; Glenn 2015;
Pinderhughes 2011; Steinmetz et al. 2017). Colonial violence
and exploitation were
pivotal for the eventual take-off of the capitalist mode of
production. In Marxian terms,
colonialism was a form of primitive accumulation, a term that
describes the expansion
and concentration of private property in the means of
production. Primitive accumula-
tion did not only provide a large influx of capital into Europe,
which paved the way for
industrialisation, but also violently divested numerous people
from their means of pro-
duction (primarily the land) (Marx 1887: 506–547). Primitive
accumulation occurred
both in the colonies and in Europe, but with a key difference:
whereas in Europe, the
large-scale dispossession of people mostly forced them into
wage labour, the colonised
were frequently forced into forms of unpaid labour. However,
through the global expan-
sion of the capitalist mode of production, colonial forms of
unpaid labour were articu-
lated ‘around the capitalist wage-labor relation’ (Quijano 2000):
Kienscherf 5
This articulation was constitutively colonial, based first on the
assignments of all forms of
unpaid labor to colonial races […]. Second, labor was
controlled through the assignment of
salaried labor to the colonizing whites. (p. 539)
The adjective ‘primitive’ (from the German ursprünglich)
implies that the violent
dispossession of people was merely capitalism’s original sin.
What is more, colonialism is
widely held to have ended with the independence of most
former colonies. Yet, a number
of scholars argue that coloniality persists despite the abolition
of colonial forms of labour
control and the independence of former colonies (Grosfoguel
2003; Pinderhughes 2011;
Quijano 2000). A hierarchical division of labour along the lines
of race and ethnicity
established through colonialism ‘continues to be an integral part
of the contemporary
global division of labour even after independence and the global
expansion of the capital-
ist wage-labour relation’ (Grosfoguel 2003: 146). In fact, ‘the
entanglement of capitalist
accumulation processes with a racial/ethnic hierarchy and its
derivative classifications of
superior/inferior, developed/undeveloped, and
civilized/barbarian people’ constitutes a
global coloniality even in the absence of any formal colonial
system of rule (Grosfoguel
2003: 17; see also Quijano 2000).
This ‘entanglement of capitalist accumulation processes with a
racial/ethnic hierar-
chy’ also marks the domestic situation in the United States as
profoundly colonial. US
scholars and activists developed the concept of internal
colonialism to explain the persis-
tence of racial oppression after the end of settler colonisation
and the abolition of chattel
slavery (Allen 1969, 2005; Blauner 1969; Pinderhughes 2011).
The concept came into
its own during the civil rights struggle and rising Black
militancy in the 1960s but lost
importance after the more radical wings of the civil rights
movement either fizzled out or
were destroyed by the state. In 2005, Robert L Allen, one of the
most prominent propo-
nents of the internal colonialism theory, revisited the arguments
he made in his seminal
1969 book Black Awakening in Capitalist America. In this
article, he argues that the
political successes of the civil rights movement gave rise to a
neo-colonial logic of indirect
rule where a small assimilated Black professional class
increasingly governs African
Americans in the interests of the White capitalist power
structure (Allen 2005: 5–6; see
also Pinderhughes 2011: 249). However, as we will see in the
next section, a neo-colonial
logic of indirect rule evolved well before the onset of mass
urban rebellion in the 1960s.
Since at least the 1920s, this has been the position of northern
urban liberals (Miller
2015). This position manifested itself in efforts to manage
social conflict without
addressing its underlying political-economic causes, but thus
also entailed an extension
of rights and limited self-governance to African Americans. In
short, this was a domestic
variant of developmentalism – developing a capacity for self-
governance in at least a
small group of the colonised so that they can govern their own
populations while repro-
ducing the overall ‘entanglement of capitalist accumulation
processes with a racial/ethnic
hierarchy’ (Grosfoguel 2003: 17); in brief, social peace without
social justice.
So, although African Americans (as well as other racialised
groups who are considered
citizens) now have formally equal rights, although there now is
a sizable Black profes-
sional class and although the United States elected its first
Black president, a racial and
ethnic hierarchy that intersects with and is exacerbated by
massive class divisions remains
firmly in place. In the United States, the racialised poor thus
still find themselves in a
6 Capital & Class 00(0)
colonial situation. Yet, this situation should be termed neo-
colonial in order to highlight
both the ruptures (abolition of colonial labour control, granting
of formally equal rights,
some forms of self-rule etc.) and the continuities (racial/ethnic
division of labour, persis-
tence of racism) between classical colonialism and its
contemporary liberal variant. I
thus have to disagree with Viviane Saleh-Hanna’s (2008: 17–18)
and (Steinmetz et al.
2017, 11n) rejection of the term neo-colonial. Even if the
techniques of control used
for (re-)producing a neo-colonial situation are not new and
clearly derive from classical
colonialism, they are still deployed under conditions that have
undoubtedly changed
partly due to the large-scale global contestations of the
colonised in the latter half of
the 20th century. This is why it is important to distinguish
between a colonial geneal-
ogy and a neo-colonial ontology when it comes to US policing.
Western liberal polic-
ing in general has a clear colonial genealogy because many of
the techniques used for
securing the domestic social order derive from colonial
experience. Yet, contemporary
US policing in particular – and this may well also hold for
policing in other national
territories as well as for international forms of policing (see
Ryan 2013) – deploys these
techniques under new ontological conditions, primarily formal
legal equality and the
absence of colonial forms of labour control.
In short, classical colonialism was primarily about the
expropriation, subordination
and exploitation of racialised populations, whereas with today’s
liberal neo-colonialism,
the idea of development has become more important. Ironically,
through attempts at
development oppression, subordination and exploitation have
become less visible but
perhaps also more entrenched. Globally, the rise of liberal
developmentalism happened
in the context of decolonisation struggles and Cold War rivalry.
Within the United
States, neo-colonial developmentalism arose in response to the
civil rights struggle and
geopolitical concerns about the international image of the
United States. The next sec-
tion will show that liberal pacification became the key strategy
for developing and inte-
grating racialised populations while reproducing a colonial
racial and class hierarchy.
Liberal pacification
Liberalism emerged as a critique of the logic of police along the
lines of political econ-
omy and the rule of law. Police or police science, which arose
across Europe with the
breakdown of feudalism, covered a much broader field than
what we now understand by
the term police. The central concerns of police were to ensure
that resources were allo-
cated in such a way as to increase prosperity and hence also the
strength of the state as
well as to promote the general happiness of the population
(Neocleous 2000: 11–21; see
also Foucault 2007: 311–332). First of all, through the
‘discovery’ of political economy
in the 18th century, prosperity came to be seen as the product of
the generalised pursuit
of private interest rather than as the effect of state regulation.
Second, the 18th century
also saw a major shift in ideas about general happiness.
Philosophers, such as Immanuel
Kant, asked whether a sovereign should (or even could) promote
general happiness as he
(or, perhaps more unlikely, she) saw fit. Ultimately, this gave
rise to the liberal principle
of the rule of law and the argument that sovereignty should be
limited to protecting
security and freedom so that everyone could freely pursue their
own happiness (Neocleous
2000: 22–30). However, the supposed neutrality and formal
equality of the rule of law
Kienscherf 7
also generalised and legitimated the substantively unequal
distribution of private prop-
erty in the means of production which was brought about by
primitive accumulation.
Liberalism thus sought to demarcate a socio-economic sphere of
autonomous human
activity (civil society and the market) from the political sphere
which came itself to be
seen as the product of the convergence of the political interests
of individual autonomous
subjects. At the same time, liberal political thought constantly
problematised the human
capacity for autonomy, for not everybody was considered
equally capable of responsible
self-governance. Women, children, colonial subjects and the
domestic undeserving poor
were frequently seen as either incapable of self-governance or
as not yet able to exercise
their autonomy in a responsible manner (Dean 2000; Rasmussen
2011). Liberal govern-
ment through freedom has thus always depended on a
specifically liberal form of polic-
ing. Liberal policing has sought to control those subjects who
were deemed incapable of
doing so themselves and to (often coercively) promote the
capacity for responsible self-
governance of those who were held to not yet possess it. In fact,
liberal policing rests on
a binary distinction, between safely autonomous subjects and
subjects whose excess of
autonomy is viewed as a threat as well as a hierarchy of liberal
development. Liberal
policing thus hinges both on a temporal scale of development,
of becoming liberal, and
on a spatial distinction between safe and dangerous subjects.
The combination of a rigid binary with a developmental
hierarchy also indicates the
coloniality of liberal policing. For, according to Quijano (2000:
552–553), the articulation
of a rigid binary between primitive and civilised upon a
developmental hierarchy that
ranges from the state of nature to European modernity is also
one of the hallmarks of colo-
nial Eurocentrism. Indeed, liberal policing was profoundly
shaped by colonial experiences.
Not only did the denial of colonised subjects’ capacity for self-
governance provide a con-
venient legitimation for their expropriation, oppression and
exploitation but the actual
experience of producing and ruling colonised subjects also
helped develop and perfect
techniques for coercively regulating the behaviour of domestic
‘problem’ populations.
Indeed, classical liberal political thinkers frequently justified
colonial domination by
referring to what they saw as irreducible racial differences
preventing the colonised from
governing themselves in a responsible manner (the domestic
poor were also often por-
trayed in racialised terms). But with the expansion of the
capitalist mode of production
and its need for ‘free’ labour, essentialist conceptions of
autonomy began to shift towards
more relational markers of autonomy (without ever being fully
replaced by them). The
level of capacity for self-governance has come to be decided by
one’s relation to the mar-
ket, by one’s market utility, by one’s ability and willingness to
freely sell one’s labour
power. Yet, these market-based ascriptions of autonomy still
reproduce the legacy of
racial domination and also produce new forms of inequality. It
is no coincidence that
populations whose autonomy has traditionally been put into
question are now widely
seen as failing the test of the market. The economic plight of
African Americans, their
supposed reliance on welfare and their overrepresentation in the
prison population thus
give a new purportedly colour-blind inflection to traditional
forms of racism that denied
them their capacity for responsible self-governance on purely
racial grounds. It is
precisely around the perceived (in)capacity for self-governance,
now primarily structured
by notions of market competitiveness, that class and race
intersect and mutually rein-
force one another. The political economy that took shape
against the background of the
8 Capital & Class 00(0)
protracted crisis of the 1970s, which came to known as
neoliberalism, prompted a down-
wards pressure on wages, a decreasing demand for unskilled and
semiskilled labour and
a retrenchment of welfare. This had a disproportionate effect on
African Americans.
Neoliberalism has, thus, produced a criminalised sub-
proletarian surplus population
whose irresponsible autonomy is viewed as an obstacle to
capital accumulation.
Consequently, contemporary US policing serves to incapacitate
those members of this
sub-proletarian surplus population whose excessive autonomy is
seen as dangerous, while
– as somewhat of an afterthought – trying to coercively
integrate those members of this
population who are still considered worthy of showing their
responsible autonomy
through participation in the lowest rungs of the labour market.
So, the decline of essentialised ideas about autonomy, which
was brought about both
by changes in capital accumulation and through political
contestations of the oppressed,
also necessitated the need for more developmentalist
interventions in order to develop
autonomy while still reproducing both the overall capitalist
mode of production and its
racial and class hierarchies.
And this is where liberal policing comes in. Liberal policing
aims to develop auton-
omy in those who are deemed incapable of responsible self-
governance, to remove obsta-
cles to responsible self-governance and to eradicate forms of
autonomy that are considered
dangerous.
Liberal policing is thus engaged in what I call liberal
pacification – a strategy for pro-
ducing and reproducing populations capable of responsible self-
governance through the
selective and differentially targeted application of a
combination of coercion, support
and consent. It is perhaps no coincidence that the term
pacification as well as the set of
practices it denotes emerged in the same context as the ideology
of ‘race’, namely, during
the Spanish colonial conquest of America in the late 16th
century (Neocleous 2011:
198). The coercive ordering of unruly, risky, dangerous and,
more often than not, racial-
ised populations through techniques of pacification has ever
since been one of the key
concerns of colonial policing/warfighting and continues to be a
major concern for
Western counterinsurgents (see, for example, US Department of
the Army 2014). In
brief, as Mark Neocleous has pointed out, pacification has been
one of the central tech-
nologies of colonialism and continues to be a key strategy for
reproducing ‘wage labour
as the grounds for accumulation’ (Neocleous 2013: 25).
However, the transition from classical colonialism based on
‘mere’ expropriation and
oppression to a neo-colonial global and domestic order that
combines formal legal equal-
ity with substantive class/racial inequalities calls for a more
nuanced conception of paci-
fication. Indeed, the principle of liberal legal equality, which is
after all based on notions
of autonomy, figures prominently in contemporary liberal
pacification, because liberal
pacification also seeks to develop its targets’ capacities for
responsible liberal self-govern-
ance. Liberal pacification rose to prominence during post-WWII
struggles for national
liberation. The strategy of liberal pacification, which became a
central component of
Western counterinsurgency doctrines from the 1960s, seemed to
offer a solution to the
problem of developing the colonies’ capacities for self-
governance in such a way as to
secure their continuous availability for capitalist exploitation
and geo-strategic domina-
tion in the absence of direct rule. Liberal pacification ought to
be understood as a fusion
of security and development – to secure Western geo-strategic
and geo-economic inter-
ests while developing indigenous capacities for responsible self-
governance in order to
Kienscherf 9
unevenly integrate colonial populations into the global circuits
of capital accumulation
(Duffield 2010; Kienscherf 2013; Shafer 1988). However,
although liberal pacification
came into its own at the cusp of decolonisation after WWII, it
has a much deeper geneal-
ogy based in classic colonialism and domestic class struggle.
Attempts to civilise or mod-
ernise colonies was also a key goal of Western colonial powers,
above all France and
Britain, during the 19th century. And so were strategies of
indirect rule through local
strongmen in the all-too-frequent case that grand civilising
missions failed in the face of
stiff local resistance (see Porch 2013). What is more,
throughout the 19th century, rising
working-class militancy across Western metropoles also
prompted the need for political
strategies that combined the integration of the working classes
into the social order
through development (granting rights, welfare etc.) with efforts
to secure the existing
capitalist class structure (Owens 2015).
What is important to note is that in liberal pacification, the
actual on-the-ground
blend of security and development ultimately depends on the
level and organisation of
local resistance and on the specific politico-economic interests
of the dominant classes.
In short, liberal pacification is a technology of ordering that can
be summarised as social
peace without social justice because it addresses only those
grievances that do not ques-
tion any fundamental structural inequities.
Pacification deploys reasonable and/or minimum necessary
force as one of its key tac-
tics. Ryan (2013) suggests that reasonable force, which is ‘a
mode of persuasion where
force stands as a defensive line behind the progress of
reasonable argument’ is ontological
to police power (p. 435). He further argues that ‘police power
ultimately aims to produce
coherent, self-governing rational actors who perform
productively in […] a globalized
raison d’etat’ (p. 456). Since the use of force by anybody who
does not wield police power
is thus always construed as illegitimate and unreasonable, it
becomes ‘the more reasonable
[…] for police to move up the scale of violence in its reaction’
(p. 456). So, ‘what is reason-
able has become what is necessary’ (p. 443). In fact, minimum
necessary force is one of
the central principles governing the liberal use of violence
(Kienscherf 2016: 1185).
Minimum necessary force is the exact amount of force that is
seen as reasonable in a par-
ticular situation. The more unreasonable the targets of liberal
force appear, for example
because of their militant or even armed resistance against an
oppressive and exploitative
neo-colonial situation, the more force can be used against them.
Minimum necessary
force is what ultimately enables liberal pacification’s other
forms of reasonable force that
seek to produce more pliable subjects without any actual use of
force.
The next section will use the analytic of liberal pacification to
highlight how in the
United States ever more formally class- and race-neutral forms
of policing have ended up
producing and reinforcing a neo-colonial social order marked by
substantive inequalities
along the intersecting lines of race and class.
US policing as liberal pacification
Patrolling racial lines
From its beginnings as a White settler colony, the United States
has been riven by drastic
racial and class divisions. The contours of this racialised and
class-based social order have
undoubtedly changed (both on the basis of shifts in capital
accumulation and through
10 Capital & Class 00(0)
contestation from below), but the institution of chattel slavery
has left indelible marks
on the US social order and thus also on the institution of the
police. Chattel slavery
constituted a classical colonial order defined by the brutal
subordination and oppression
of enslaved people for the purpose of coercively extracting their
labour power. Slavery,
moreover, was entangled with international systems of banking,
insurance and credit and
also contributed to the rise of industrialisation, first in Britain
and later in the American
north (Baptist 2014; Oakes 2016). The size of the slave
population was considered a
massive social control problem. The threat of slave insurrection
and the constant risk of
slave flight led to the emergence of ever more formalised slave
patrols. The first slave
patrols were formed in the 17th century and were informal
bands of volunteers tasked
with recapturing runaway slaves. In the course of the 18th
century, slave patrols became
more organised and were also charged with preventing
insurrection. The Fugitive Slave
Act of 1850 gave state governments wide-ranging authority to
recruit individuals – espe-
cially poor Whites – into slave patrols that now had almost
unlimited coercive powers
over the slave population. Slave patrols were tasked with the
routine surveillance of the
slave population in order to regulate and manage their
movement according to the polit-
ico-economic imperatives of chattel slavery (Bass 2001: 159;
Brucato 2014: 38–39). In
fact, slave patrols were a significant strand in the genealogy of
the US police (Bass 2001;
Brucato 2014; Hadden 2001).
Brutal efforts to control the movement and hence also the
labour power of the Black
population continued after the abolition of slavery. There was,
however, a brief interlude
during which the federal government tried to turn freed people
into citizens and autono-
mous wage labourers through the establishment of the Bureau of
Refugees, Freedmen
and Abandoned Lands, better known as the Freedmen’s Bureau.
The Freedmen’s Bureau
was set up towards the end of the Civil War in March 1865 to
provide immediate relief
to freed people as well as to poor Whites uprooted by the war,
but its mission quickly
expanded to a large-scale and often contradictory effort to
protect freed people’s civil and
political rights, to revive agricultural production in the South
and to turn former slaves
into free wage labourers (often on the same plantations they
used to work on as slaves)
(Goldberg 2007: 31–75). The Freedmen’s Bureau can be
understood as an early, albeit
ultimately failed, attempt at liberal pacification which sought to
develop African
Americans’ capacity for self-governance in order to integrate
them into a Northern capi-
talist order as both citizens and self-dependent but docile wage
labourers. Despite its
chequered track record, the Freedmen’s Bureau started from the
assumption that African
Americans were at least potentially capable of responsible self-
governance. This is per-
haps why W.E.B. Du Bois (2007: 179) praised the Bureau as
‘the most extraordinary and
far-reaching institution of social uplift that America has ever
attempted’, despite the fact
that it also frequently served as an instrument for disciplining
Black labour (Goldberg
2007: 40–42). The Bureau’s efforts to develop African
Americans while also protecting
them from continuing White violence did not go down well with
Southern Whites who
ultimately succeeded in swaying Congress to terminate the
Freedmen’s Bureau in 1872.
Immediately after the end of the Civil War, most Southern
states replaced their Slave
Codes with the so-called Black Codes which were aimed to
severely restrict the freedom
of former slaves and maintain them in a state of quasi-slavery
through extremely low
wages, debt peonage as well as numerous sweeping vagrancy
statutes. After mounting
Kienscherf 11
criticism from Northern States, increasing legal pressure from
the Congress and 11 years
of direct military administration of the Southern States, the
Black Codes were replaced
by Jim Crow in 1877. The Jim Crow laws contained many
provisions that were fre-
quently as, if not more, sweeping than the original Black Codes.
As Sandra Bass (2001)
puts it, ‘Essentially, African Americans lived in a police state in
which every aspect of
shared public life was proscribed. Formal police organizations
under this system were
responsible for upholding the formal and informal social order’
(p. 161). Besides man-
dating strict racial segregation and brutally punishing any
infraction against Whites, Jim
Crow laws also ensured African Americans continuing
availability as docile and easily
exploitable agricultural labour through debt peonage and
convict leasing. What is more,
this brutal colonial regime of racist oppression and exploitation
was ultimately backed
up by both legal and extra-legal violence in the forms of
lynchings (Marable 1983:
108–121).
Pacifying class struggle
The first urban police force in the United States was founded in
New York in 1845 and
was closely modelled on the famous London Metropolitan
Police (Miller 1999;
Monkkonen 1981). The idea of a uniformed urban police force
was also a product of
colonialism. When British Home Secretary Robert Peel set up
the Metropolitan Police of
London in 1829, he drew heavily on his earlier experiences as
Chief Secretary of Ireland
(1812–1818). During his time in Ireland, Peel realised that an
external military force was
ill-suited to pacifying a poor and rebellious colonial population.
This led to experimenta-
tion with ‘a new kind of bureaucracy, located in a social space
midway between an out-
side military force and the group of people to be controlled’ –
the Irish Constabulary
(Monkkonen 1981: 39). A bureaucracy that was modelled on the
military but not (quite)
a military force itself and whose frontline troops were recruited
from the population to
be controlled also offered a more legitimate and thus ultimately
more effective way of
pacifying metropolitan working-class militancy.
Indeed, one of the key tasks of early US urban police forces was
to pacify class strug-
gles as well as intra-class ethnic conflicts brought about by
rapid industrialisation, urban-
isation and immigration in many Northern and Midwestern
cities (Harring 2017; Vitale
2017; Williams 2015). Early municipal police forces also
provided important services to
the communities they controlled. In fact, many urban police
forces ran soup kitchens,
gave shelter to the homeless and searched for lost children
(Monkkonen 1981: 86–128).
As Sidney L Harring (2017) notes, ‘the police institution gains
legitimacy when it makes
some accommodation to the communities being policed’ (p. 16).
In short, through a
combination of coercion and support 19th century urban
policing helped produce, rein-
force and ultimately legitimate a capitalist social formation
based on class subordination
and exploitation.
Early urban police forces were rather decentralised, poorly
trained and engaged in
many off-the-books activities. In fact, throughout the 19th
century, cops frequently
acted as enforcers for corrupt ward bosses and political
machines (Chriss 2011: 28–32).
As many police scholars have it, the progressive era, starting in
the 1890s, marked the
end of the so-called political spoils era of American policing
(Chriss 2011; Kelling &
12 Capital & Class 00(0)
Moore 1988). Throughout the late 19th and early 20th centuries,
police departments
came to be organised along more bureaucratic lines, adopted
more militarised command
and control structures, introduced new technologies and
professionalised police training.
The progressive era also saw increasing police specialisation.
Police began to fashion
themselves as professional law enforcers. Progressive-era police
reform also had a clear
colonial pedigree. Historian Alfred McCoy (2009) shows how
the colonial occupation of
the Philippines in the late 19th and early 20th centuries
prompted numerous innova-
tions in the fields of policing, intelligence, counterintelligence
and surveillance, many of
which were reimported into US domestic policing, eventually
giving rise to what he calls
‘the surveillance state’. McCoy argues that the police apparatus
created by the American
army in the Philippines at the beginning of the 20th century
‘was far more advanced’
than contemporaneous US domestic police forces (p. 61). Many
of the policing practices
honed in the colonial Philippines were brought back into the
United States by colonial
veterans whose racial frame of reference often made them view
America’s ‘ethnic com-
munities not as fellow citizens but as internal colonies requiring
coercive controls’
(McCoy 2009: 294).
According to Harring (2017), the sweeping reforms of US
municipal police depart-
ments towards the beginning of the 20th century occurred
primarily in response to a
growing need to pacify escalating class struggles. At the end of
the 19th century and the
beginning of 20th century, an increasing number of large-scale
strikes led to calls for an
expansion and centralisation of police departments. On the other
hand, there were also
heightened concerns over police corruption as well as a more
general trend towards the
rationalisation and bureaucratisation of urban governance.
Surely, the focus on depoliti-
cised, bureaucratic, centralised and purportedly neutral law
enforcement also served to
make police departments more legitimate in the eyes of the
working classes (Harring
2017: 232). At the same time, law enforcement afforded an
opportunity extensively to
intervene in the lives of working-class people, patrolling the
line between independent
workers and the dependent, criminalised poor. More often than
not this occurred
through the enforcement of sweeping vagrancy statutes that
were modelled on or even
directly taken over from what Marx (1887: 522) called ‘a
bloody legislation against vaga-
bondage’ that was enacted throughout Western Europe form the
15th century in order
to crack down on people who were forcibly dispossessed
through primitive accumulation
(see also Adler 1989; Chambliss 1964). Until the Supreme Court
declared them uncon-
stitutional at the beginning of the 1970s, vagrancy laws
afforded the police a lot of legal
leeway to come down hard on undesirables:
Armed with a roving license to arrest, officials employed
vagrancy laws for a breath-taking array
of purposes: to force the local poor to work or suffer for their
support; to keep out poor or
suspicious strangers, to suppress differences that might be
dangerous; to stop crimes before they
were committed; to keep racial minorities, political
troublemakers, and nonconforming rebels
at bay. (Goluboff 2016: 2–3)
Police reform thus served to generalise and legitimate class
control through an exten-
sion of rationalities and practices of enforcing formally neutral
laws which in practice
only particular groups of people happened to be in violation of.
Even though laws
Kienscherf 13
directed against status-type offences such vagrancy have been
declared unconstitutional,
they have now increasingly been replaced by civility codes that
target behaviours rather
than status. But more often than not these happen to be types of
behaviour, such as
sleeping outdoors, drinking and urinating in public, the
racialised poor are more likely
to engage in than members of the middle classes. Katherine
Beckett and Steve Herbert
(2009) document how new urban social control tools, such as
off-limit orders, park
exclusion laws and new trespass laws ultimately criminalise
complex social problems,
wash up even more people in the criminal justice system and
create a new legal status –
excluded – which is predominantly assigned to the racialised
non-working poor.
Pacifying racial conflict
Although there were much fewer overly segregationist laws in
Northern and Midwestern
cities, there was still a racialised social order based on informal
spatial segregation as well as
the exclusion of African Americans from most well-paying jobs
(Miller 2015: 7–9).
Following growing Black migration from the early 20th century
onwards – due to a crisis
of agricultural production in the South and heightened demand
for unskilled and semi-
skilled labour in the industrial North and Midwest – the Black
population of Northern and
Midwestern cities grew significantly. And, so did the animosity
of local politicians, real
estate agents and White homeowners, who used a variety of
tactics to maintain a racialised
social order through residential segregation. Blacks were
confined to inner-city ghettoes
that served the twin function of excluding them from White
society while including their
exploitable labour power in the industrial economy. All the
while, urban police depart-
ments played an important role in producing and maintaining
this racialised order (Bass
2001; Wacquant 2001). In the context of growing Black urban
populations targeted by
various forms of racism, the ideology of Northern racial
liberalism took shape. According
to Karen Miller (2015), ‘racial liberalism married the same two
components that color-
blind racism does today: an extension of racial inequality
alongside a commitment to the
language of interracial understanding and race neutrality’ (p. 7).
Faced with growing Black
demands for more socio-economic equality, on the one hand,
and the vested interests of
many Whites to maintain racial hierarchies especially in terms
of residential and labour
patterns, on the other, many liberal urban governments thus
sought ‘to regulate race rela-
tions and avoid racial conflicts in the name of urban peace’
(Miller 2015: 9). This amounted
to a strategy of liberal pacification: social peace without social
justice – addressing only
those Black grievances that did not question the overall
racialised capitalist order. In fact,
‘[m]aintaining capitalism thus meant, in part, maintaining racial
inequalities’ (Miller 2015:
145). Indeed, the increasing political significance of Northern
racial liberalism marked the
beginning of a transition from a colonial to a neo-colonial
order.
The ideology of racial liberalism also informed a second wave
of police reform that
slowly took shape against the background of rising Black
liberation struggles starting in
the 1940s. Growing efforts to modernise the criminal justice
system in general and police
in particular were prompted by a liberal desire to pacify racial
conflict. Here, according
to Naomi Murakawa (2014), lies a significant and often
overlooked factor for the emer-
gence of the contemporary US carceral state. From the 1940s,
liberal policymakers
14 Capital & Class 00(0)
increasingly problematised racial tensions – above all White
racist violence in the South
– in terms of law and order. White racist violence in the South
frequently occurred with
the tacit support of or even in direct collusion with local police
or sheriffs’ departments.
But, liberal policymakers viewed racial violence as primarily a
problem of illegitimate,
unlawful and ultimately unreasonable violence and considered
the modernisation and
professionalisation of the organs of state-sanctioned, reasonable
force as an adequate
solution. The articulation of law and order upon race gave rise
to a liberal political
agenda based on ‘tightening hardware’ and ‘healing hearts’; that
is to say, efforts to mod-
ernise and professionalise criminal justice agencies as well as
attempts to bolster state
legitimacy in the eyes of African Americans (Murakawa 2014:
44–53). However, the
liberal law and order agenda proved to be vulnerable to being
hijacked by Southern race
conservatives, who re-framed the supposed link between crime
and race not as a problem
of White racist violence but as a problem of Black criminality –
an astonishing feat of
‘racecraft’ that would have a lasting impact (see Fields & Fields
2014). Hence, there
emerged a strong bipartisan consensus on the need for criminal
justice reform, even
though the ultimate objectives of these reform efforts differed
along partisan lines: creat-
ing more racial fairness was the prime goal of race liberals,
whereas repressing Black
criminality and shoring up the racist colonial order were the
aims of race conservatives
(Murakawa 2014: 74). As President Johnson’s Safe Streets Act
bill went through Congress
in 1967, a number of key changes were introduced by
conservatives. The provisions for
the federal funding of local police contained in the original bill
stipulated for federal-to-
local categorical grants. This would have given the federal
government a lot more say in
how local police and sheriffs’ department would ultimately use
the monies. Yet, through
several amendments in the House and the Senate, this was
changed to federal-to-state
block grants. So, the monies went directly to the states that
could then distribute them
to local law enforcement agencies as they saw fit. The final
piece of legislation – the
Omnibus Crime Control and Safe Streets Act of 1968 –
eventually established the Law
Enforcement Assistance Administration (LEAA) in an effort to
cut crime rates through
the modernisation of local police. The LEAA failed in achieving
its ultimate goal of
reducing crime, but, primarily due to the amendments to the
original bill, resulted in
local police departments’ stockpiling of military-grade gear and
the proliferation of para-
military police units across the country (Murakawa 2014: 85–
90; see also Kraska &
Kappeler 1997; Parenti 1999). The LEAA was also a major step
towards generalising the
Northern model of the professional urban police, though
policing remained highly local-
ised. So, the machinery was definitely tightened. But what
about healing the hearts?
Rising Black militancy, massive ghetto uprisings and the
political successes of the civil
rights movement in the 1960s prompted the re-importation of
many techniques of colo-
nial control into the continental United States. Local police
departments acquired mili-
tary equipment, such as CN and CS gas (originally developed
for use in Vietnam),
helicopters and armoured personnel carriers as well as training
in military tactics (Parenti
1999; Pinto 1971; Quinney 1974). However, it was not just the
coercive techniques of
overseas counterinsurgency operations that were reimported into
domestic US policing
in the late 1960s. More consensual techniques of expeditionary
counterinsurgency also
boomeranged back into the continental United States. This is
exemplified by two
Kienscherf 15
developments: (1) the rise of more consensual approaches to
protest policing and (2) the
emergence of community policing.
From the early 1970s, protest policing changed from ‘escalated
force’ to ‘negotiated
management’ (McPhail et al. 1998; McPhail & McCarthy 2005;
Soule & Davenport
2009). During the 1960s, police response to protest was
overwhelmingly coercive and
included, often unprovoked, mass arrests, the indiscriminate use
of force, and showed
little patience with protesters’ First Amendment rights.
Escalated force frequently led to
property damage, injuries and even deaths, which in turn
prompted rising public criti-
cism of police on the part of both civil liberties groups and
political elites. In the late
1960s and early 1970s, various congressional commissions – the
most famous of which
was the National Commission on Civil Disorder (Kerner
Commission) – found that
violent protest was often exacerbated if not triggered by overly
aggressive policing
(McPhail & McCarthy 2005: 63). In 1967, at request of the
Justice Department, the US
Army Military Police School (USAMPS) set up a Civil
Disturbance Orientation Course
(SEADOC) for municipal police and the National Guard. The
main concern of
SEADOC I, which ran from February 1968 to April 1969, was
with the suppression of
urban riots through an escalation of force. In May 1970,
SEADOC II was launched and
continued until at least 1978. SEADOC II included many of the
recommendations
made by these congressional commissions. The focus was no
longer merely on how to
suppress riots but on how to effectively manage a variety of
different protest events.
SEADOC II centred on the strategic concept of ‘confrontation
management’, which
sought to avoid any overreaction on the part of police to
protesters’ provocations, and on
the tactical principle of ‘minimum necessary force’, which is, as
we have seen, a key com-
ponent of liberal pacification (US Army Military Police School
1972, cited in McPhail
& McCarthy 2005).
Community policing is a much-vaunted policing strategy
supposed to help police (re)
build and (re)establish legitimacy especially in the eyes of
marginalised and impoverished
communities (Herbert 2006). Although most US police
departments officially state that
they do some sort of community policing, it remains unclear
what community policing
actually means in practice (Herbert 2006: 4; Saunders 1999a,
1999b). But as Steve
Herbert (2006) writes, ‘community policing programs generally
seek to help police
departments to improve their connections with citizen groups
and to decentralize their
operations to make better use of input from those groups’ (p. 4).
Community policing
also amounts to a form of liberal pacificion. The author of a
2006 RAND report On
‘Other War’: Lessons from Five Decades of RAND
Counterinsurgency Research suggests that
‘pacification is best thought of as a massively enhanced version
of the “community polic-
ing” technique that emerged in the 1970s (encouraged in part by
RAND research)’
(Long 2006: 53). In his discussion of possible ways of fixing a
broken criminal justice
system, late legal scholar William J Stuntz (2011) suggested
that US counterinsurgency
tactics used in Iraq ‘could have been taken from a community
policing manual’ (p. 293).
And he continued as follows:
Today’s policing conventional wisdom emphasizes the same
three moves: a more public police
street presence in the most violent areas, a problem-solving
approach to local blights like
16 Capital & Class 00(0)
garbage on the streets or gang signs on local buildings, and,
most important of all, the building
of relationships between police officers and local neighborhood
residents. (p. 293)
Stuntz also argued that these policing strategies are not only
effective in reducing
urban crime but could also help curb ‘the state’s seemingly
insatiable desire to punish
young black men’ (p. 310). However, in practice, community
policing hardly offers any
real alternative to mass incarceration. On the contrary, concerns
over ‘urban blights’
frequently lead to massive increases in detentions, arrests and
criminal records for often
minor misdemeanours, such as loitering or drinking in public,
primarily in neglected
and underinvested minority neighbourhoods (Harcourt 2001).
This is also borne out by
an activist report on the Chicago Alternative Policing Strategy
(CAPS) (We Charge
Genocide 2015). CAPS is one of the most ambitious and largest
community policing
programmes in the United States and was officially rolled out in
1993 (Chicago Police
Department 2016). The Counter-CAPS report found that ‘at
CAPS meetings, police
effectively deputise a small group of residents to engage in
surveillance. These residents
are disproportionately white property owners, especially in
gentrifying neighborhoods’
(We Charge Genocide 2015: 4). This seems to be a general
problem of community
policing. The terrain of urban communities remains marked by
substantive inequalities,
which the police are neither able nor willing to tackle; while the
police engage with com-
munities in a highly uneven fashion, and vice versa. In fact, the
police do not seek every-
body’s input equally and some (generally well-heeled)
community groups are in a much
better position to voice their grievances to the police than
others (Herbert 2006; see also
Muñiz 2015). So, despite the pleasant ring of the term and some
genuine democratising
potential inherent in attempts to seek more community input,
community policing
remains, above all, a rhetorical strategy that alongside the use
of some substantive prac-
tices seeks to persuade people of the legitimacy of the state in
general and of the police
in particular (Saunders 1999a, 1999b):
State formation involves not just the practice of state agencies,
but also the active participation
(if not the consent) of state subjects. Community policing is one
such instance, therefore, in
which the capacity for concrete oppression is wedded to
processes of legitimation. (p. 137)
As a consequence, community policing ought to be understood
as an instance of
liberal pacification which uses reasonable force to garner the
participation and consent
of the population in securing the existing social order. However,
reasonable force is still
backed up and ultimately facilitated by the actual violence to be
used against subjects
who prove to be too unreasonable to be swayed by reasonable
force (Ryan 2013).
Community policing thus ultimately reproduces and legitimates
a purportedly colour-
blind and class-neutral neo-colonial order marked by the ‘the
entanglement of capitalist
accumulation processes with a racial/ethnic hierarchy’
(Grosfoguel 2003: 17).
Conclusion
As Manning Marable (1983) wrote, ‘Blacks occupy the lowest
socioeconomic rung in
the ladder of American upward mobility precisely because they
have been integrated all
Kienscherf 17
too well into the system’ (p. 2). As has been shown, the United
States ought to be under-
stood as neo-colonial order based on both formal legal equality
and substantive racial/
class divisions. Through a strategy of liberal pacification aimed
at formally integrating
African Americans into the social order through a combination
of security and develop-
ment, US policing has been and continues to be pivotal for
producing and reinforcing a
neo-colonial order structured around formal legal equality and
substantive racial and
class inequalities. In fact, US policing operates as an instrument
of class and racial
oppression precisely because it aims to coercively integrate
marginalised populations into
a social order characterised by the generalisation of specific
racial/class divisions through
principles of formal legal equality and individual autonomy.
This generalisation of spe-
cific inequalities that are conducive to capitalist accumulation
has been brought about by
means of liberal pacification: some (more often than not
coercive) development for those
who are seen as still having some labour market utility and
incapacitation for those who
have permanently failed the test of the labour market or who are
seen as a threat to capi-
talist accumulation. This market-based ascription of autonomy
and the lack thereof is
precisely what reproduces substantive inequalities within a
system of formal equality.
As Elizabeth Jones (2018) puts it, the US criminal justice
system ‘has always operated
as a mediator between black labour and capitalist modes of
production’ (p. 42). What is
more, ‘racism works both ways: to justify the reproduction of a
cheap labor force and to
exclude populations from the labor market’ (Grosfoguel 2003:
210). Problematisations
of crime and disorder thus serve to criminalise a population
many of whose members are
now structurally condemned permanently to fail the test of the
labour market. Indeed,
racialisation through racist criminalisation is a purportedly
colour-blind mechanism for
upholding a neo-colonial racial and class hierarchy in the
context of de jure equality. But,
despite the best efforts to make it seem so, capitalism has never
been colour-blind.
ORCID iD
Markus Kienscherf https://orcid.org/0000-0001-7202-1482
References
Adler JS (1989) A historical analysis of the law of vagrancy.
Criminology 27(2): 209–229.
Allen RL (1969) Black Awakening in Capitalist America. New
York: Doubleday.
Allen RL (2005) Reassessing the internal (neo) colonialism
theory. The Black Scholar 35(1): 2–11.
Arendt H (1968) Imperialism. New York: Harcourt, Brace &
World.
Baptist EE (2014) The Half Has Never Been Told: Slavery and
the Making of American Capitalism.
New York: Basic Books.
Bass S (2001) Policing space, policing race: Social control
imperatives and police discretionary
decisions. Social Justice 28(1): 156–176.
Beckett K and Herbert S (2009) Banished: The New Social
Control in Urban America. Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Blauner R (1969) Internal colonialism and ghetto revolt. Social
Problems 16(4): 393–408.
Brogden M (1987) The emergence of the police: The colonial
dimension. British Journal of
Criminology 27(1): 4–14.
Brucato B (2014) Fabricating the color line in a white
democracy: From slave catchers to petty
sovereigns. Theoria: A Journal of Social and Political Theory
61(4): 30–54.
18 Capital & Class 00(0)
Césaire A (1972) Discourse on Colonialism. New York:
Monthly Review Press.
Chambliss WJ (1964) A sociological analysis of the law of
vagrancy. Social Problems 12(1): 67–77.
Chicago Police Department (2016) Get involved with CAPS.
Available at: http://home
.chicagopolice.org/get-involved-with-caps/how-caps-
works/what-is-caps/ (accessed 23 January
2018).
Chriss JJ (2011) Beyond Community Policing: From Early
American Beginnings to the 21st Century.
London: Routledge.
Dean M (2000) Liberal government and authoritarianism.
Economy and Society 31(1): 37–61.
Du Bois WEB (2007) Black Reconstruction in America: An
Essay toward a History of the Part Which
Black Folk Played in the Attempt to Reconstruct Democracy in
America, 1860–1880. Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Duffield M (2010) The liberal way of development and the
development-security impasse:
Exploring the global life-chance divide. Security Dialogue
41(1): 53–76.
Fanon F (2004) The Wretched of the Earth. New York: Grove
Press.
Fields KE and Fields BJ (2014) Racecraft: The Soul of
Inequality in American Life. London: Verso
Books.
Foucault M (2003) Society Must Be Defended: Lectures at the
College De France 1975–1976. New
York: Picador.
Foucault M (2007) Security, Territory, Population. Lectures at
the College De France 1977–1978.
Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.
Glenn EN (2015) Settler colonialism as structure: A framework
for comparative studies of U.S.
race and gender formation. Sociology of Race and Ethnicity
1(1): 52–72.
Goldberg CA (2007) Citizens and Paupers: Relief, Rights, and
Race, from the Freedman’s Bureau to
Workfare. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.
Goluboff R (2016) Vagrant Nation: Police Power, Constitutional
Change, and the Making of the
1960s. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Graham S (2010) Cities Under Siege: The New Military
Urbanism. London: Verso Books.
Grosfoguel R (2003) Colonial Subjects: Puerto Ricons in a
Global Perspective. Berkeley: University
of California Press.
Hadden SE (2001) Slave Patrols: Law and Violence in Virginia
and the Carolinas. Harvard, MA:
Harvard University Press.
Harcourt BE (2001) The Illusion of Order: The False Promise of
Broken Windows Policing. Harvard,
MA: Harvard University Press.
Harring SL (2017) Policing a Class Society: The Experience of
American Cities 1865–1915. Chicago:
Haymarket Books.
Herbert S (2006) Citizens, Cops, and Power: Recognizing the
Limits of Community Policing. Chicago:
The University of Chicago Press.
Hönke J and Müller M-M (2012) Governing (in)security in a
postcolonial world: Transnational
entanglements and the worldliness of ‘local’ practice. Security
Dialogue 43(5): 383–401.
Jessop B (2002) The Future of the Capitalist State. Cambridge:
Polity Press.
Jones E (2018) Racism, fines and fees and the US carceral state.
Race & Class 59(3): 38–50.
Kelling GL and Moore MH (1988) The evolving strategy of
policing. Perspectives on Policing 4:
1–16.
Kienscherf M (2013) US Domestic and International Regimes of
Security: Pacifying the Homeland,
Securing the Globe. London: Routledge.
Kienscherf M (2016) Beyond militarization and repression:
Liberal social control as pacification.
Critical Sociology 42(7–8): 1179–1194.
Kraska PB and Kappeler VE (1997) Militarizing American
police: The rise and normalization of
paramilitary units. Social Problems 44(1): 1–18.
Kienscherf 19
Loader I and Walker N (2006) Necessary virtues: The legitimate
place of the state in the produc-
tion of security. In: Wood J and Dupont B (eds) Democracy and
the Governance of Security.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 165–195.
Long A (2006) On ‘Other War’: Lessons from Five Decades of
RAND Counterinsurgency Research.
Santa Monica, CA: RAND Corporation.
McCoy AW (2009) Policing America’s Empire: The United
States, the Philippines and the Rise of the
Surveillance State. Madison: University of Wisconsin Press.
McMichael C (2017) Pacification and police: A critique of the
police militarization thesis. Capital
& Class 41(1): 115–132.
McPhail C and McCarthy JD (2005) Protest mobilization,
protest repression, and their inter-
action. In: Davenport C, Johnston H and Mueller C (eds)
Repression and Mobilization.
Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, pp. 3–32.
McPhail C, Schweingruber D and McCarthy JD (1998) Policing
protest in the United States: 1960–
1995. In: Della Porta D and Reiter H (eds) Policing Protest: The
Control of Mass Demonstrations
in Western Democracies. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota
Press, pp. 49–69.
Marable M (1983) How Capitalism Underdeveloped Black
America: Problems in Race, Political
Economy and Society. Boston, MA: South End Press.
Marenin O (1982) Parking tickets and class repression: The
concept of policing in critical theories
of criminal justice. Contemporary Crises 6(3): 241–266.
Marx K (1887) Capital: A Critique of Political Economy, vol. 1.
Moscow: Progress Publishers.
Miller KR (2015) Managing Inequality: Northern Racial
Liberalism in Interwar Detroit. New York:
New York University Press.
Miller WA (1999) Cops and Bobbies: Police Authority in New
York and London, 1830–1870.
Columbus: Ohio State University Press.
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx
Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx

More Related Content

Similar to Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx

Existentialism From SartreIn our text, Sartre, in effect, provi.docx
Existentialism From SartreIn our text, Sartre, in effect, provi.docxExistentialism From SartreIn our text, Sartre, in effect, provi.docx
Existentialism From SartreIn our text, Sartre, in effect, provi.docxnealwaters20034
 
Existentialism From SartreIn our text, Sartre, in effect, provi.docx
Existentialism From SartreIn our text, Sartre, in effect, provi.docxExistentialism From SartreIn our text, Sartre, in effect, provi.docx
Existentialism From SartreIn our text, Sartre, in effect, provi.docxelbanglis
 
Existentialism Is a Humanism Jean-Paul Sartre Writt.docx
Existentialism Is a Humanism Jean-Paul Sartre  Writt.docxExistentialism Is a Humanism Jean-Paul Sartre  Writt.docx
Existentialism Is a Humanism Jean-Paul Sartre Writt.docxrhetttrevannion
 
The Sartre-Heidegger Controversy on Humanism and Its Importance to Critical P...
The Sartre-Heidegger Controversy on Humanism and Its Importance to Critical P...The Sartre-Heidegger Controversy on Humanism and Its Importance to Critical P...
The Sartre-Heidegger Controversy on Humanism and Its Importance to Critical P...Rauno Huttunen
 
Phenomenology of jean-paul_sartre
Phenomenology of jean-paul_sartrePhenomenology of jean-paul_sartre
Phenomenology of jean-paul_sartreJerick Serandon
 
The Human Person and His Intersubjectivity
The Human Person and His IntersubjectivityThe Human Person and His Intersubjectivity
The Human Person and His Intersubjectivityjoshuasulfo
 
Existentialism & Nihilism.pptx
Existentialism & Nihilism.pptxExistentialism & Nihilism.pptx
Existentialism & Nihilism.pptxlittletranslator
 
Virtual Teacher's Day 2023
 Virtual Teacher's Day 2023 Virtual Teacher's Day 2023
Virtual Teacher's Day 2023Hina Parmar
 
Understanding the Self: Philosophical Perspectives
Understanding the Self: Philosophical PerspectivesUnderstanding the Self: Philosophical Perspectives
Understanding the Self: Philosophical PerspectivesTEACHER RYAN JIMENEZ
 
Values education philosophy(Western)
Values education philosophy(Western)Values education philosophy(Western)
Values education philosophy(Western)Chester Relleve
 

Similar to Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx (10)

Existentialism From SartreIn our text, Sartre, in effect, provi.docx
Existentialism From SartreIn our text, Sartre, in effect, provi.docxExistentialism From SartreIn our text, Sartre, in effect, provi.docx
Existentialism From SartreIn our text, Sartre, in effect, provi.docx
 
Existentialism From SartreIn our text, Sartre, in effect, provi.docx
Existentialism From SartreIn our text, Sartre, in effect, provi.docxExistentialism From SartreIn our text, Sartre, in effect, provi.docx
Existentialism From SartreIn our text, Sartre, in effect, provi.docx
 
Existentialism Is a Humanism Jean-Paul Sartre Writt.docx
Existentialism Is a Humanism Jean-Paul Sartre  Writt.docxExistentialism Is a Humanism Jean-Paul Sartre  Writt.docx
Existentialism Is a Humanism Jean-Paul Sartre Writt.docx
 
The Sartre-Heidegger Controversy on Humanism and Its Importance to Critical P...
The Sartre-Heidegger Controversy on Humanism and Its Importance to Critical P...The Sartre-Heidegger Controversy on Humanism and Its Importance to Critical P...
The Sartre-Heidegger Controversy on Humanism and Its Importance to Critical P...
 
Phenomenology of jean-paul_sartre
Phenomenology of jean-paul_sartrePhenomenology of jean-paul_sartre
Phenomenology of jean-paul_sartre
 
The Human Person and His Intersubjectivity
The Human Person and His IntersubjectivityThe Human Person and His Intersubjectivity
The Human Person and His Intersubjectivity
 
Existentialism & Nihilism.pptx
Existentialism & Nihilism.pptxExistentialism & Nihilism.pptx
Existentialism & Nihilism.pptx
 
Virtual Teacher's Day 2023
 Virtual Teacher's Day 2023 Virtual Teacher's Day 2023
Virtual Teacher's Day 2023
 
Understanding the Self: Philosophical Perspectives
Understanding the Self: Philosophical PerspectivesUnderstanding the Self: Philosophical Perspectives
Understanding the Self: Philosophical Perspectives
 
Values education philosophy(Western)
Values education philosophy(Western)Values education philosophy(Western)
Values education philosophy(Western)
 

More from vrickens

1000 words, 2 referencesBegin conducting research now on your .docx
1000 words, 2 referencesBegin conducting research now on your .docx1000 words, 2 referencesBegin conducting research now on your .docx
1000 words, 2 referencesBegin conducting research now on your .docxvrickens
 
1000 words only due by 5314 at 1200 estthis is a second part to.docx
1000 words only due by 5314 at 1200 estthis is a second part to.docx1000 words only due by 5314 at 1200 estthis is a second part to.docx
1000 words only due by 5314 at 1200 estthis is a second part to.docxvrickens
 
1000 words with refernceBased on the American constitution,” wh.docx
1000 words with refernceBased on the American constitution,” wh.docx1000 words with refernceBased on the American constitution,” wh.docx
1000 words with refernceBased on the American constitution,” wh.docxvrickens
 
10.1. In a t test for a single sample, the samples mean.docx
10.1. In a t test for a single sample, the samples mean.docx10.1. In a t test for a single sample, the samples mean.docx
10.1. In a t test for a single sample, the samples mean.docxvrickens
 
100 WORDS OR MOREConsider your past experiences either as a studen.docx
100 WORDS OR MOREConsider your past experiences either as a studen.docx100 WORDS OR MOREConsider your past experiences either as a studen.docx
100 WORDS OR MOREConsider your past experiences either as a studen.docxvrickens
 
1000 to 2000 words Research Title VII of the Civil Rights Act of.docx
1000 to 2000 words Research Title VII of the Civil Rights Act of.docx1000 to 2000 words Research Title VII of the Civil Rights Act of.docx
1000 to 2000 words Research Title VII of the Civil Rights Act of.docxvrickens
 
1000 word essay MlA Format.. What is our personal responsibility tow.docx
1000 word essay MlA Format.. What is our personal responsibility tow.docx1000 word essay MlA Format.. What is our personal responsibility tow.docx
1000 word essay MlA Format.. What is our personal responsibility tow.docxvrickens
 
100 wordsGoods and services that are not sold in markets.docx
100 wordsGoods and services that are not sold in markets.docx100 wordsGoods and services that are not sold in markets.docx
100 wordsGoods and services that are not sold in markets.docxvrickens
 
100 word responseChicago style citingLink to textbook httpbo.docx
100 word responseChicago style citingLink to textbook httpbo.docx100 word responseChicago style citingLink to textbook httpbo.docx
100 word responseChicago style citingLink to textbook httpbo.docxvrickens
 
100 word response to the followingBoth perspectives that we rea.docx
100 word response to the followingBoth perspectives that we rea.docx100 word response to the followingBoth perspectives that we rea.docx
100 word response to the followingBoth perspectives that we rea.docxvrickens
 
100 word response to the followingThe point that Penetito is tr.docx
100 word response to the followingThe point that Penetito is tr.docx100 word response to the followingThe point that Penetito is tr.docx
100 word response to the followingThe point that Penetito is tr.docxvrickens
 
100 word response to the folowingMust use Chicago style citing an.docx
100 word response to the folowingMust use Chicago style citing an.docx100 word response to the folowingMust use Chicago style citing an.docx
100 word response to the folowingMust use Chicago style citing an.docxvrickens
 
100 word response using textbook Getlein, Mark. Living with Art, 9t.docx
100 word response using textbook Getlein, Mark. Living with Art, 9t.docx100 word response using textbook Getlein, Mark. Living with Art, 9t.docx
100 word response using textbook Getlein, Mark. Living with Art, 9t.docxvrickens
 
100 word response to the following. Must cite properly in MLA.Un.docx
100 word response to the following. Must cite properly in MLA.Un.docx100 word response to the following. Must cite properly in MLA.Un.docx
100 word response to the following. Must cite properly in MLA.Un.docxvrickens
 
100 original, rubric, word count and required readings must be incl.docx
100 original, rubric, word count and required readings must be incl.docx100 original, rubric, word count and required readings must be incl.docx
100 original, rubric, word count and required readings must be incl.docxvrickens
 
100 or more wordsFor this Discussion imagine that you are speaki.docx
100 or more wordsFor this Discussion imagine that you are speaki.docx100 or more wordsFor this Discussion imagine that you are speaki.docx
100 or more wordsFor this Discussion imagine that you are speaki.docxvrickens
 
10. (TCOs 1 and 10) Apple, Inc. a cash basis S corporation in Or.docx
10. (TCOs 1 and 10) Apple, Inc. a cash basis S corporation in Or.docx10. (TCOs 1 and 10) Apple, Inc. a cash basis S corporation in Or.docx
10. (TCOs 1 and 10) Apple, Inc. a cash basis S corporation in Or.docxvrickens
 
10-12 slides with Notes APA Style ReferecesThe prosecutor is getti.docx
10-12 slides with Notes APA Style ReferecesThe prosecutor is getti.docx10-12 slides with Notes APA Style ReferecesThe prosecutor is getti.docx
10-12 slides with Notes APA Style ReferecesThe prosecutor is getti.docxvrickens
 
10-12 page paer onDiscuss the advantages and problems with trailer.docx
10-12 page paer onDiscuss the advantages and problems with trailer.docx10-12 page paer onDiscuss the advantages and problems with trailer.docx
10-12 page paer onDiscuss the advantages and problems with trailer.docxvrickens
 
10. Assume that you are responsible for decontaminating materials in.docx
10. Assume that you are responsible for decontaminating materials in.docx10. Assume that you are responsible for decontaminating materials in.docx
10. Assume that you are responsible for decontaminating materials in.docxvrickens
 

More from vrickens (20)

1000 words, 2 referencesBegin conducting research now on your .docx
1000 words, 2 referencesBegin conducting research now on your .docx1000 words, 2 referencesBegin conducting research now on your .docx
1000 words, 2 referencesBegin conducting research now on your .docx
 
1000 words only due by 5314 at 1200 estthis is a second part to.docx
1000 words only due by 5314 at 1200 estthis is a second part to.docx1000 words only due by 5314 at 1200 estthis is a second part to.docx
1000 words only due by 5314 at 1200 estthis is a second part to.docx
 
1000 words with refernceBased on the American constitution,” wh.docx
1000 words with refernceBased on the American constitution,” wh.docx1000 words with refernceBased on the American constitution,” wh.docx
1000 words with refernceBased on the American constitution,” wh.docx
 
10.1. In a t test for a single sample, the samples mean.docx
10.1. In a t test for a single sample, the samples mean.docx10.1. In a t test for a single sample, the samples mean.docx
10.1. In a t test for a single sample, the samples mean.docx
 
100 WORDS OR MOREConsider your past experiences either as a studen.docx
100 WORDS OR MOREConsider your past experiences either as a studen.docx100 WORDS OR MOREConsider your past experiences either as a studen.docx
100 WORDS OR MOREConsider your past experiences either as a studen.docx
 
1000 to 2000 words Research Title VII of the Civil Rights Act of.docx
1000 to 2000 words Research Title VII of the Civil Rights Act of.docx1000 to 2000 words Research Title VII of the Civil Rights Act of.docx
1000 to 2000 words Research Title VII of the Civil Rights Act of.docx
 
1000 word essay MlA Format.. What is our personal responsibility tow.docx
1000 word essay MlA Format.. What is our personal responsibility tow.docx1000 word essay MlA Format.. What is our personal responsibility tow.docx
1000 word essay MlA Format.. What is our personal responsibility tow.docx
 
100 wordsGoods and services that are not sold in markets.docx
100 wordsGoods and services that are not sold in markets.docx100 wordsGoods and services that are not sold in markets.docx
100 wordsGoods and services that are not sold in markets.docx
 
100 word responseChicago style citingLink to textbook httpbo.docx
100 word responseChicago style citingLink to textbook httpbo.docx100 word responseChicago style citingLink to textbook httpbo.docx
100 word responseChicago style citingLink to textbook httpbo.docx
 
100 word response to the followingBoth perspectives that we rea.docx
100 word response to the followingBoth perspectives that we rea.docx100 word response to the followingBoth perspectives that we rea.docx
100 word response to the followingBoth perspectives that we rea.docx
 
100 word response to the followingThe point that Penetito is tr.docx
100 word response to the followingThe point that Penetito is tr.docx100 word response to the followingThe point that Penetito is tr.docx
100 word response to the followingThe point that Penetito is tr.docx
 
100 word response to the folowingMust use Chicago style citing an.docx
100 word response to the folowingMust use Chicago style citing an.docx100 word response to the folowingMust use Chicago style citing an.docx
100 word response to the folowingMust use Chicago style citing an.docx
 
100 word response using textbook Getlein, Mark. Living with Art, 9t.docx
100 word response using textbook Getlein, Mark. Living with Art, 9t.docx100 word response using textbook Getlein, Mark. Living with Art, 9t.docx
100 word response using textbook Getlein, Mark. Living with Art, 9t.docx
 
100 word response to the following. Must cite properly in MLA.Un.docx
100 word response to the following. Must cite properly in MLA.Un.docx100 word response to the following. Must cite properly in MLA.Un.docx
100 word response to the following. Must cite properly in MLA.Un.docx
 
100 original, rubric, word count and required readings must be incl.docx
100 original, rubric, word count and required readings must be incl.docx100 original, rubric, word count and required readings must be incl.docx
100 original, rubric, word count and required readings must be incl.docx
 
100 or more wordsFor this Discussion imagine that you are speaki.docx
100 or more wordsFor this Discussion imagine that you are speaki.docx100 or more wordsFor this Discussion imagine that you are speaki.docx
100 or more wordsFor this Discussion imagine that you are speaki.docx
 
10. (TCOs 1 and 10) Apple, Inc. a cash basis S corporation in Or.docx
10. (TCOs 1 and 10) Apple, Inc. a cash basis S corporation in Or.docx10. (TCOs 1 and 10) Apple, Inc. a cash basis S corporation in Or.docx
10. (TCOs 1 and 10) Apple, Inc. a cash basis S corporation in Or.docx
 
10-12 slides with Notes APA Style ReferecesThe prosecutor is getti.docx
10-12 slides with Notes APA Style ReferecesThe prosecutor is getti.docx10-12 slides with Notes APA Style ReferecesThe prosecutor is getti.docx
10-12 slides with Notes APA Style ReferecesThe prosecutor is getti.docx
 
10-12 page paer onDiscuss the advantages and problems with trailer.docx
10-12 page paer onDiscuss the advantages and problems with trailer.docx10-12 page paer onDiscuss the advantages and problems with trailer.docx
10-12 page paer onDiscuss the advantages and problems with trailer.docx
 
10. Assume that you are responsible for decontaminating materials in.docx
10. Assume that you are responsible for decontaminating materials in.docx10. Assume that you are responsible for decontaminating materials in.docx
10. Assume that you are responsible for decontaminating materials in.docx
 

Recently uploaded

Introduction to ArtificiaI Intelligence in Higher Education
Introduction to ArtificiaI Intelligence in Higher EducationIntroduction to ArtificiaI Intelligence in Higher Education
Introduction to ArtificiaI Intelligence in Higher Educationpboyjonauth
 
PSYCHIATRIC History collection FORMAT.pptx
PSYCHIATRIC   History collection FORMAT.pptxPSYCHIATRIC   History collection FORMAT.pptx
PSYCHIATRIC History collection FORMAT.pptxPoojaSen20
 
Science 7 - LAND and SEA BREEZE and its Characteristics
Science 7 - LAND and SEA BREEZE and its CharacteristicsScience 7 - LAND and SEA BREEZE and its Characteristics
Science 7 - LAND and SEA BREEZE and its CharacteristicsKarinaGenton
 
Micromeritics - Fundamental and Derived Properties of Powders
Micromeritics - Fundamental and Derived Properties of PowdersMicromeritics - Fundamental and Derived Properties of Powders
Micromeritics - Fundamental and Derived Properties of PowdersChitralekhaTherkar
 
The Most Excellent Way | 1 Corinthians 13
The Most Excellent Way | 1 Corinthians 13The Most Excellent Way | 1 Corinthians 13
The Most Excellent Way | 1 Corinthians 13Steve Thomason
 
Arihant handbook biology for class 11 .pdf
Arihant handbook biology for class 11 .pdfArihant handbook biology for class 11 .pdf
Arihant handbook biology for class 11 .pdfchloefrazer622
 
Hybridoma Technology ( Production , Purification , and Application )
Hybridoma Technology  ( Production , Purification , and Application  ) Hybridoma Technology  ( Production , Purification , and Application  )
Hybridoma Technology ( Production , Purification , and Application ) Sakshi Ghasle
 
Organic Name Reactions for the students and aspirants of Chemistry12th.pptx
Organic Name Reactions  for the students and aspirants of Chemistry12th.pptxOrganic Name Reactions  for the students and aspirants of Chemistry12th.pptx
Organic Name Reactions for the students and aspirants of Chemistry12th.pptxVS Mahajan Coaching Centre
 
Contemporary philippine arts from the regions_PPT_Module_12 [Autosaved] (1).pptx
Contemporary philippine arts from the regions_PPT_Module_12 [Autosaved] (1).pptxContemporary philippine arts from the regions_PPT_Module_12 [Autosaved] (1).pptx
Contemporary philippine arts from the regions_PPT_Module_12 [Autosaved] (1).pptxRoyAbrique
 
Alper Gobel In Media Res Media Component
Alper Gobel In Media Res Media ComponentAlper Gobel In Media Res Media Component
Alper Gobel In Media Res Media ComponentInMediaRes1
 
CARE OF CHILD IN INCUBATOR..........pptx
CARE OF CHILD IN INCUBATOR..........pptxCARE OF CHILD IN INCUBATOR..........pptx
CARE OF CHILD IN INCUBATOR..........pptxGaneshChakor2
 
Incoming and Outgoing Shipments in 1 STEP Using Odoo 17
Incoming and Outgoing Shipments in 1 STEP Using Odoo 17Incoming and Outgoing Shipments in 1 STEP Using Odoo 17
Incoming and Outgoing Shipments in 1 STEP Using Odoo 17Celine George
 
Kisan Call Centre - To harness potential of ICT in Agriculture by answer farm...
Kisan Call Centre - To harness potential of ICT in Agriculture by answer farm...Kisan Call Centre - To harness potential of ICT in Agriculture by answer farm...
Kisan Call Centre - To harness potential of ICT in Agriculture by answer farm...Krashi Coaching
 
_Math 4-Q4 Week 5.pptx Steps in Collecting Data
_Math 4-Q4 Week 5.pptx Steps in Collecting Data_Math 4-Q4 Week 5.pptx Steps in Collecting Data
_Math 4-Q4 Week 5.pptx Steps in Collecting DataJhengPantaleon
 
Mastering the Unannounced Regulatory Inspection
Mastering the Unannounced Regulatory InspectionMastering the Unannounced Regulatory Inspection
Mastering the Unannounced Regulatory InspectionSafetyChain Software
 
Call Girls in Dwarka Mor Delhi Contact Us 9654467111
Call Girls in Dwarka Mor Delhi Contact Us 9654467111Call Girls in Dwarka Mor Delhi Contact Us 9654467111
Call Girls in Dwarka Mor Delhi Contact Us 9654467111Sapana Sha
 
Concept of Vouching. B.Com(Hons) /B.Compdf
Concept of Vouching. B.Com(Hons) /B.CompdfConcept of Vouching. B.Com(Hons) /B.Compdf
Concept of Vouching. B.Com(Hons) /B.CompdfUmakantAnnand
 
How to Make a Pirate ship Primary Education.pptx
How to Make a Pirate ship Primary Education.pptxHow to Make a Pirate ship Primary Education.pptx
How to Make a Pirate ship Primary Education.pptxmanuelaromero2013
 

Recently uploaded (20)

Introduction to ArtificiaI Intelligence in Higher Education
Introduction to ArtificiaI Intelligence in Higher EducationIntroduction to ArtificiaI Intelligence in Higher Education
Introduction to ArtificiaI Intelligence in Higher Education
 
Model Call Girl in Tilak Nagar Delhi reach out to us at 🔝9953056974🔝
Model Call Girl in Tilak Nagar Delhi reach out to us at 🔝9953056974🔝Model Call Girl in Tilak Nagar Delhi reach out to us at 🔝9953056974🔝
Model Call Girl in Tilak Nagar Delhi reach out to us at 🔝9953056974🔝
 
PSYCHIATRIC History collection FORMAT.pptx
PSYCHIATRIC   History collection FORMAT.pptxPSYCHIATRIC   History collection FORMAT.pptx
PSYCHIATRIC History collection FORMAT.pptx
 
Science 7 - LAND and SEA BREEZE and its Characteristics
Science 7 - LAND and SEA BREEZE and its CharacteristicsScience 7 - LAND and SEA BREEZE and its Characteristics
Science 7 - LAND and SEA BREEZE and its Characteristics
 
Micromeritics - Fundamental and Derived Properties of Powders
Micromeritics - Fundamental and Derived Properties of PowdersMicromeritics - Fundamental and Derived Properties of Powders
Micromeritics - Fundamental and Derived Properties of Powders
 
TataKelola dan KamSiber Kecerdasan Buatan v022.pdf
TataKelola dan KamSiber Kecerdasan Buatan v022.pdfTataKelola dan KamSiber Kecerdasan Buatan v022.pdf
TataKelola dan KamSiber Kecerdasan Buatan v022.pdf
 
The Most Excellent Way | 1 Corinthians 13
The Most Excellent Way | 1 Corinthians 13The Most Excellent Way | 1 Corinthians 13
The Most Excellent Way | 1 Corinthians 13
 
Arihant handbook biology for class 11 .pdf
Arihant handbook biology for class 11 .pdfArihant handbook biology for class 11 .pdf
Arihant handbook biology for class 11 .pdf
 
Hybridoma Technology ( Production , Purification , and Application )
Hybridoma Technology  ( Production , Purification , and Application  ) Hybridoma Technology  ( Production , Purification , and Application  )
Hybridoma Technology ( Production , Purification , and Application )
 
Organic Name Reactions for the students and aspirants of Chemistry12th.pptx
Organic Name Reactions  for the students and aspirants of Chemistry12th.pptxOrganic Name Reactions  for the students and aspirants of Chemistry12th.pptx
Organic Name Reactions for the students and aspirants of Chemistry12th.pptx
 
Contemporary philippine arts from the regions_PPT_Module_12 [Autosaved] (1).pptx
Contemporary philippine arts from the regions_PPT_Module_12 [Autosaved] (1).pptxContemporary philippine arts from the regions_PPT_Module_12 [Autosaved] (1).pptx
Contemporary philippine arts from the regions_PPT_Module_12 [Autosaved] (1).pptx
 
Alper Gobel In Media Res Media Component
Alper Gobel In Media Res Media ComponentAlper Gobel In Media Res Media Component
Alper Gobel In Media Res Media Component
 
CARE OF CHILD IN INCUBATOR..........pptx
CARE OF CHILD IN INCUBATOR..........pptxCARE OF CHILD IN INCUBATOR..........pptx
CARE OF CHILD IN INCUBATOR..........pptx
 
Incoming and Outgoing Shipments in 1 STEP Using Odoo 17
Incoming and Outgoing Shipments in 1 STEP Using Odoo 17Incoming and Outgoing Shipments in 1 STEP Using Odoo 17
Incoming and Outgoing Shipments in 1 STEP Using Odoo 17
 
Kisan Call Centre - To harness potential of ICT in Agriculture by answer farm...
Kisan Call Centre - To harness potential of ICT in Agriculture by answer farm...Kisan Call Centre - To harness potential of ICT in Agriculture by answer farm...
Kisan Call Centre - To harness potential of ICT in Agriculture by answer farm...
 
_Math 4-Q4 Week 5.pptx Steps in Collecting Data
_Math 4-Q4 Week 5.pptx Steps in Collecting Data_Math 4-Q4 Week 5.pptx Steps in Collecting Data
_Math 4-Q4 Week 5.pptx Steps in Collecting Data
 
Mastering the Unannounced Regulatory Inspection
Mastering the Unannounced Regulatory InspectionMastering the Unannounced Regulatory Inspection
Mastering the Unannounced Regulatory Inspection
 
Call Girls in Dwarka Mor Delhi Contact Us 9654467111
Call Girls in Dwarka Mor Delhi Contact Us 9654467111Call Girls in Dwarka Mor Delhi Contact Us 9654467111
Call Girls in Dwarka Mor Delhi Contact Us 9654467111
 
Concept of Vouching. B.Com(Hons) /B.Compdf
Concept of Vouching. B.Com(Hons) /B.CompdfConcept of Vouching. B.Com(Hons) /B.Compdf
Concept of Vouching. B.Com(Hons) /B.Compdf
 
How to Make a Pirate ship Primary Education.pptx
How to Make a Pirate ship Primary Education.pptxHow to Make a Pirate ship Primary Education.pptx
How to Make a Pirate ship Primary Education.pptx
 

Jean-Paul SartreWhat is ExistentialismIn his 1945 lecture on .docx

  • 1. Jean-Paul Sartre What is Existentialism? In his 1945 lecture on existentialism and humanism, Jean-Paul Sartre asserts: “existentialism is nothing else but an attempt to draw all the conclusions from a coherent atheist position.” He begins his explication of existentialist philosophy by discussing one of its key concepts: that existence precedes essence. Let us, he says, consider any man-made object, a book or paper cutter, for instance. Here is an object that began as a concept or idea in the mind of the artisan who designed and constructed it. The concept involves the manner by which the paper cutter is constructed and, more importantly, the specific purpose or use to which it is put (in this case, to cut paper). “Therefore,” Sartre concludes, let us say that, for the paper-cutter, essence—that is, the ensemble of both the production routines and the properties which enable it to be both produced and defined—precedes existence…Therefore, we have here a technical view of the world whereby it can be said that production precedes existence. In other words, in the “technical view of the world,” the “essence” of the artifact precedes the actual physical existence of the artifact, in the sense that the blueprint or concept of the paper-cutter already exists in the artisan’s mind before he ever commits to its actual production in his workshop. When we conceive God as the Creator, Sartre continues, He is thought of as a kind of superhuman artisan: God creates the Earth and the human species according to a deliberate and specific plan or idea: “Thus, the concept of man in the mind of God is comparable to the concept of paper-cutter in the mind of
  • 2. the manufacturer, and, following certain techniques and a conception, God produces man, just as the artisan, following a definition and a technique, makes a paper-cutter.” The concept of mankind in the divine intelligence is what we refer to as “human nature”: it defines mankind in terms of what we are and how we are meant to live (as we see, for example, in the natural law teaching of St. Thomas Aquinas). Atheistic existentialism, Sartre claims, is a more coherent doctrine. It states: “if God does not exist, there is at least one being in whom existence precedes essence, a being who exists before he can be defined by any concept, and this being is man…” That is, man first of all exists, “turns up, appears on the scene, and, only afterwards, defines himself.” Because there is no God who conceives the concept “man” and then creates mankind according to that concept, there is no such thing as human nature. There is, in other words, no particular reason “why” we as a species are here. We are indeterminate beings, without any fixed essence of nature, and hence entirely free to live our lives in whatever manner we choose. The first principle of existentialism is that “man is nothing else but what he makes of himself.” Sartre also refers to this principle as “subjectivity.” Let us explore it in greater detail. Unlike inert or non-conscious objects like stones and tables, man has a kind of intrinsic dignity insofar as he is a being who “is at the start a plan which is aware of itself…” “Nothing exists prior to this plan; there is nothing in heaven; man will be what he will have planned to be.” The human being creates his own essence or nature through his freely chosen acts, there being no pre-determined human nature with which he is stamped at conception and to which he must conform his actions. Thus if existence precedes essence, then “man is responsible for what he is.” And to be responsible for our own individuality necessarily entails being “responsible for all men,” for “in creating the man that we want to be… [we] at the same time
  • 3. create an image of man as we think he ought to be.” In other words, when we make a fundamental choice in life, we do so according to a set of personally chosen values which projects a certain image of ourselves as we choose to be, and by extension we are projecting an ideal image of man as we think he ought to be. For example, if I want to marry, to have children; even if this marriage depends solely on my own circumstances or passion or wish, I am involving all humanity in monogamy and not merely myself. Therefore, I am responsible for myself and for everyone else. I am creating a certain image of man of my own choosing. In choosing myself, I choose man. Anguish, Forlornness, Despair By anguish Sartre means that “the man who involves himself and who realizes that he is not only the person he chooses to be, but also a law-maker who is, at the same time, choosing all mankind as well as himself, cannot escape the feeling of his total and deep responsibility.” Because man is free and at the same time responsible, he cannot escape the feeling of immense, deep, and total responsibility not only for his own actions but also for other men, since by choosing himself he assumes the responsibility of creating an image for all of humanity. His actions, therefore, are those of a lawmaker to whom “everything happens as if all mankind had its eyes fixed on him and were guiding itself by what he does.” Of course, many people attempt to flee from anxiety either by renouncing freedom (through relying on the advice of others instead of deciding on our own) or through self-deception (by believing that our actions have no affect on anyone else). If we are truly honest with ourselves, we recognize the disquieting and inescapable fact that we alone must choose what to do, without relying on any external source of guidance, however comforting that may be. Thus, in making a decision, one “cannot help having a certain anguish.”
  • 4. “When we speak of forlornness,” writes Sartre, “we mean only that God does not exist and that we have to face all the consequences of this.” Sartre exposes the naivety of the casual or fashionable atheist who believes one can maintain a secular ethics while dispensing with the need for God altogether. The rationale of these superficial thinkers runs as follows: God is a useless and costly hypothesis; we are discarding it, but meanwhile, in order for there to be an ethics, a society, a civilization, it is essential that certain values be taken seriously and that they be considered as having an a priori existence. It must be obligatory, a priori, to be honest, not to lie, not to beat your wife, to have children, etc., ...In other words…nothing will be changed if God does not exist. We shall find ourselves with the same norms of honesty, progress, and humanism, and we shall have made of God an outdated hypothesis which will peacefully die off by itself. The thoughtless atheist wants to have the best of both worlds— that is, to jettison entirely the belief in God (with all the irksome restraints on our personal liberty such belief necessarily entails) while at the same time preserving the universal moral structure that makes civilization possible (but for which there is absolutely no place in a godless universe). The existentialist, on the other hand, “thinks it very distressing that God does not exist,” for once God is out of the picture, “there can be no longer an a priori Good, since there is no infinite and perfect consciousness to think it.” If God does not exist, then “everything is permitted” because, to invoke St. Thomas Aquinas, there would be no natural and eternal law to define and punish evil and injustice. This key insight “is the very starting point of existentialism,” and as a result man is forlorn, consumed by a feeling of abandonment, “because neither within him nor without does he find anything to cling
  • 5. to.” We are utterly alone in the universe, without any natural (or supernatural) basis by which we can guide and assess our lives (This should remind you of Nietzsche’s “Mad Man and the Death of God”). Hence Sartre’s famous dictum that “man is condemned to be free.” Condemned, because he is not self- created, yet, in other respects free; “because, once thrown into the world, he is responsible for everything he does.” In order to give us a better understanding of forlornness, Sartre refers to one of his students, who sought his advice on whether or not to join the French resistance, rather than stay with his mother. Sartre points out that no world-view or ideology (outside of existentialism) would be of any use to this boy because universal values are too vague and broad for the concrete and specific dilemmas each of us faces in life. For this reason Sartre says: “the only thing left for us is to trust our instincts,” by which he means that, “in the end, feeling is what counts. I ought to choose whichever pushes me in one direction.” His young student, embracing his freedom and responsibility, ought therefore to reach a decision in the following way: If I feel that I love my mother enough to sacrifice everything else for her—my desire for vengeance, for action, for adventure—then I’ll stay with her. If, on the contrary, I feel that my love for my mother isn’t enough, I’ll leave. But how do we determine the value of a “feeling”? For Sartre, it is precisely through action that we determine the value of our “instincts.” By choosing to stay with his mother, the boy’s feeling for her acquires value; but short of an “act which confirms and defines it,” such “feeling” is worthless. In other words, despite what we may think of ourselves in the safety of our imagination, we cannot possibly know how we would act in a given situation until we actually find ourselves in that situation, being forced by circumstances to make a choice one
  • 6. way or the other: “I may say that I like so-and-so well enough to sacrifice a certain amount of money for him, but I may say so only if I’ve done it.” We arrive finally at Sartre’s analysis of despair, which results from our awareness that there are a multitude of factors in life that lie completely beyond our control. Thus when “we want something, we always have to reckon with probabilities.” “The moment,” Sartre continues, “the possibilities I am considering are not rigorously involved by my action, I ought to disengage myself from them, because no God, no scheme, can adapt the world and its possibilities to my will.” Thus no matter how well thought out your plan, no matter how determined your will, there will be contingencies you cannot influence. You may, for example, develop a detailed, long-term plan to become, say, an engineer. You may study hard and get into the best schools. But then one day, as you are driving home late one night after a graduate seminar, someone runs a red light and hits your car on the driver’s side, causing you severe and permanent brain damage, and thus in one stroke destroying your chances of fulfilling your plan to become an engineer. Or perhaps you meet the person you think is your “soul mate,” and you invest much effort and hope in building a life-long relationship with that person, only to find out that after ten years of marriage, your spouse has been cheating on you all along. The lesson here is that it is impossible to conquer chance: hence Descartes’ famous dictum: “Conquer yourself rather than the world,” by which he means that you should accommodate your will to what is probable—knowing full well that circumstances outside of your control may hinder your plans—rather than expect the world (through belief in, for example, Divine Providence, or destiny) to adapt itself to your will, hopes, or desires. “Does this mean,” Sartre asks, “that I should abandon myself to quietism? No. First, I should involve myself; then, act on the old saying, ‘Nothing ventured, nothing gained.’” The
  • 7. existentialist says to himself: “I shall have no illusions and shall do what I can.” This is the very opposite of quietism, since it declares that (in a most fitting end to a chapter on atheistic existentialism) Man is nothing else than his plan; he exists only to the extent that he fulfills himself; he is, therefore, nothing else than the ensemble of his acts, nothing else than his life. BLACK AND BROWN BODIES AND CRIMINAL JUSTICE SYSTEMS Criminal Justice Seminar 389 (01:202:389) Topics in Latino and Caribbean Studies 312 (01:595:312:02) GUIDELINES FOR SUBMITTING WEEKLY READING SUMMARIES (The first weekly reading summary is due via Canvas Upload by 11:59pm EST on MONDAY, SEP 9 for the Gottschalk and Michalowski readings.) FOR EACH READING: Part 1: In your own words, provide an executive summary of the assigned reading. You might do this by succinctly covering the main points, contributions, or overall relevance of the reading(s). (300-500 words per reading.) Note: Direct quotes/excerpts of the article are appropriate if they are brief. The main priority is to summarize the article using your own original perspective and reception. Part 2:
  • 8. 2a: In 1-2 sentences, provide one substantive compliment, reflection, or brief analysis of the assigned reading(s). 2b: In 1-2 sentences, provide one substantive critique, area of improvement, or general assessment of the reading. Note: Stating “it was too long” or “I just hated it in general” does not qualify. Part 3: Based on your reception of the reading(s), list two substantive questions for the instructor to consider. If there is more than one reading assigned, provide at least one question per reading. You may submit these questions in bullet-point format. “Democracy and the Carceral State in America”. Gottschalk, 2014 PART ONE Gottschalk defines the “carceral state” as the prison and jail system as well as any punishments that are imposed for state defined crimes. The author describes the desire to reach the American Dream as the glue that binds society together and says that the United States’ status as a “carceral state” inherently inhibits a large number of individuals (~7 million people, disproportionately affecting racial minorities) from reaching this dream, causing complete disenfranchisement. This disenfranchisement not only includes the individuals with criminal histories, but their children who have had their lives negatively impacted by this negative environment. The 2007
  • 9. Great Recession caused budget cuts to the penal system that has created an optimism about the end of this carceral state, but Gottschalk says this optimism is largely unwarranted. The hope was that due to these budget cuts, the same number of individuals being incarcerated was no longer fiscally feasible, but there has been no clear indication that an end of the carceral state is near. The issue of a carceral state is not based on any fiscal details, but the political implications that surround it. Framing the issue of mass incarceration as a fiscal problem won’t cause any change, in fact, Gottschalk says that there’s no single factor that could dismantle the system because this isn’t a fiscal problem isn’t great enough for it to become a focus in the political system. Political issues such as the War on Drugs have gotten a greater spotlight than the mass incarceration, and this “war” has led to higher incarceration rates among commonly underfunded/underrepresented minorities. Gottschalk goes on to say that The United States will always view crime as a political issue because laws are essentially determined by what’s in the best interest of the state and of the society. To enact real change, the author looks at Finland as a case study. Finland focused their efforts on penal reform, especially on sentencing reform and successfully brought down their also very high incarceration rates. Gottschalk believes that if the goal is to end mass incarceration, then policymakers should stop focusing so heavily on the causes of crime and structural problems within the penal system and start focusing on the punishments for crimes that require jail/prison time. PART TWO I appreciate that Gottschalk used another country as an example when talking about how to lower incarceration rates because it shows what’s been effective for others. However, I think it would have been more effective to delve deeper into how exactly Finland enacted sentencing reform that brought down incarceration rates, especially when the author was trying to convince the reader that the focus of policymakers should be on
  • 10. sentencing. PART THREE 1. Should the US focus on reworking what constitutes a crime or what the punishment for already defined crimes should be? “What is Crime?”. Michalowski, 2016 PART ONE Michalowski begins this reading with discussing his critiques of orthodox criminology. The first, he explains is that there’s a disconnect between harm and crime within the study of criminology. He later goes on to elaborate that just because an act is harmful does not mean that the same act is criminal (legalist constraint). The next critique is that because of anti- communism and the prominence of functionalism within society, there is less of a sociological analysis of laws. Third, he says there’s too great of a focus on the definitions of crime and it’s keeping the victims of these crimes from getting the necessary attention. Fourth, “anti criminology” (Cohen, 1988) emergencies lead to issues balancing the study of crime with other issues that emerge in society that may lead to crime. Last, the study of analogous social injury allows criminologists to learn that while some crimes are especially harmful, some social injustices that aren’t against the law are still more destructive. Michalowski presents two definitions of crime: 1. An act that a state has determined to be wrongful and requires punishment, and 2. An act that is not illegal but is shameful. Crime is usually determined by which acts in human behavior are considered devious. The powers of the state determine which of these acts should receive punishment and what those punishments should be. However, much of the time, these punishments are influenced by the socioeconomic status that
  • 11. most of the offenders of this crime hold. There is discussion about the constraints that hold back the study of criminology. The legalist constraint, as mentioned previously, corporate constraints, and professional constraints. The corporate constraint focuses on the social injuries resulting from corrupt (but not illegal) profits made by corporations, which, since not criminal, are not studied. Michalowski says that criminological analysis requires class analysis and uses white collar crime as an example of this. Violent crimes, such as rape or murder, and property crimes, such as arson or burglary, receive the bulk of the attention by criminologists, both because it’s the crimes that people most fear will happen to them and that they’re easier to spot. White collar crimes, like money laundering and embezzlement, can take years to be found and (usually) receive little to no attention. Michalowski sees the irony: white collar crimes are especially devious in that there is typically no personal connection with any of the victims of that crime and the crime was committed solely for malevolent purposes. Coincidentally, many of the individuals committing these less visible crimes are the ones controlling the system. The professional constraint discusses the hardships facing criminologists trying to hold a job: in order to stay mainstream in their studies, they have to study mainstream crimes and prisons which are disproportionately filled with lower income, underrepresented individuals. There is no criminology without crime and in order to define crime, an understanding of criminology is needed. Michalowski says the purpose of criminology is to analyze the forms of social injury that are monitored closely by the state with only some having punishments. PART TWO I agreed with the two definitions of crime presented in the reading. My issue came with the statement that in order to define crime, an understanding of the purpose of criminology is needed. Ethical crimes, such as lynching (as discussed in the
  • 12. reading), are merely misconduct in the eyes of the law but in my opinion, should still be included in the discussion of crime despite criminologists not studying it. PART THREE 1. Should it be the role of policymakers or criminologists to delve deeper into the effects of ethical crimes? [Name] 1 [Name] Professor León Black and Brown Bodies in CJS September 9, 2019 Weekly Reading Summary 1 Raymond J. Michalowski’s work called What is Crime? tackles the question of what would be considered to be a crime throughout history. With the definition of crime being set it also could change the way the definition of criminology could be altered. Michalowski starts the article off by explaining why he started to dissect the question of what could be considered a crime. With this question in his mind, he started to think about the concept of orthodox criminology and goes on to use this concept within the rest of the article. Using the term towards finding a clear definition, even if it sounds impossible, for solutions for “crime problems” as he mentions. Where these crimes fall under either being a concern for the public or a crime defined by the state. Michalowski goes into the history of criminology and some concepts that were not dared to be explored by sociologists such as the concept of lynching. Michalowski explains this to be the concept of ‘constrained criminology’ basically placing the study of crime into three forms of constraints. The overly controlled subject of criminology was placed into the categories of legalist constraint, corporate constraint, and professional constraint, each giving a point on why they were categorized this way.
  • 13. Each constraint gives a point to why criminologist strays away from certain topics involving the law. Legalist constraint going back to the topic mentioned early such as lynching. This constraint on criminology explains the difficulty of examining extreme conditions if they are not going against the law. Corporate constraints go into the field of corporations and social class, for example, the case of Big Tobacco companies having a hand in law-making practices to benefit the companies and those who invest in these companies. Lastly, Michalowski talks about professional constraints in studying certain subjects in criminology. He explained this concept as a danger to one’s career if they dared to go beyond taboo fields of study in criminology. In conclusion with these definitions of constraints and the history of criminology in the article, Michalowski focuses on the critiques of furthering the study of certain criminological themes. Michalowski introduces intriguing points into why criminology is so limited, especially in the past. Michalowski wants to embed the idea of changing the way we understand crime and not just defining it as the usual view of laws being broken. Since in this case defining crime will ultimately define criminology as well. Michalowski wants to bring different factors into defining both crime and criminology and not just limiting it to the definition of laws and the penal system. This article kept me on my toes with the concepts it tackled. Rather than focusing on one topic, it made sure to bring in different topics and theories to understand the point of the paper better. Although despite that I found myself stopping to either re-read a section because it was not clear enough or I just did not understand it in general. I also had to stop multiple times to figure out what some words meant but that could also be a positive since it could help me expand my vocabulary. · Is it possible for more constraints to be foreseen in the future? If yes, would the whole idea of how criminology is taught, be changed? In Marie Gottschalk’s work labeled Democracy and the Carceral
  • 14. State in America it starts by talking about Tocqueville and the history that their work brought. Tocqueville’s work eases the article into the topic of democracy in America as it gives notes of his study of the new republic. This article focuses on the collision the correctional system or ‘Carceral State’ as Gottschalk claims have born upon American society. Gottschalk goes into the topic of how the penal system has affected people along with the floating question of how fair the current, at least when this article was written, the penal system is. The article notes on how complicated one’s life could get in they ever find themselves within the penal system, it can reshape the way their life would become. For example, people could be denied loans, housing, and even public service from the government. Gottschalk also adds the effects it could have towards the family members of the people who enter the carceral state. Gottschalk even adds statistics on how children of parents in the correctional system are affected. Gottschalk talks about the potential decrease in mass incarcerations starting at the time of the Great Recession. During the Great Recession, there were not enough funds to keep people incarcerated, especially for a long period. This has started the question of how to control the number of people that the U.S. places into jail. Even going as far as researching different countries and how they were able to lower their incarceration rates. Gottschalk touches upon the topic of the aspects of lower crime would be by directing the focus on poverty, unemployment, school systems or even other social focuses such as race. There is still a sense of urgency to lower incarceration rates but Gottschalk seems doubtful about it since it is so embedded into U.S. society. The article was a great overview recap of the incarceration state especially with how my former classes last year barely touched upon the effects it has to be incarcerated. It also gave a great overview of the ideas of a new policy and how other policies are being enacted to frame the carceral state better. However, like the other article, I found myself stopping to go back to
  • 15. either grasp the concept better or to look up words that I was unsure about. Not sure if I missed it but also the topic of capital punishment being noted in the construction on the carceral state. · If money was not the problem, would the carceral state even be considered a problem to be questioned and solved? [Name] Professor León Criminal Justice Seminar 389 September 9th, 2019 Democracy and the Carceral State in America 1. In this article the author makes a clear distinction that the American penal system has bones in it’s closet, both from the past and present. It seems that whenever observations are made about the Carceral State, the findings seem to get swept under the rug by higher political and economic powers. The Carceral State here in America seems to have been expanding since the time of Tocqueville, but appears to have exponentially expanded since the 1970s. The penal system created by politicians and other authority figures has led to mass incarceration of disportionately black and latino communities. The U.S. penal system enthusiastically locks up minorities without even considering the negative effects on community, family, and future of the imprisoned individual. The author states that there are “nearly 2.3 million people sitting in jail or prison today in the United States”(Gottschalk 289). This goes to point out that the United States is leading other nations with the most amount of its own citizens behind bars. This mass incarceration of American citizens, predominantly of color, has led to the American Dream being lost within these communities. Furthermore, this lost dream is predominantly replaced with hopelessness, broken families, lost privileges and rights, and an inability to access things such as public housing and loans. The author makes the distinction that people who are negatively affected by the Carceral State are not limited to those locked in
  • 16. prison or jail, but extends to the many citizens who have a connection to the criminal justice system, whether it be through probation, parole, or a family member intertwined within the system. The author clearly defines the penal system as broken and in need of fixing. Gottschalk then goes on to show that the Carceral State is now being treated as a money issue by politicians, instead of a social justice issue. It is made clear that the focus should not be on the costs of the carceral system, but on the fact that it is a broken system, which is currently destroying the lives of disproportionate members of society. Because of the high costs of the penal system, it does give activists the opportunity to help bring down the Carceral State. However, the single factor of costs alone will never be able to dismantle such a powerful agency within the United States government. In conclusion, this article shows that the penal system in America has been set up in such a way that it targets demographics of lower minorities, so as long as it does not affect the pockets of wealthy politicians and those of the upper class. 2. The author does a good job of providing numbers and statistics to show precisely how many people are negatively affected by this unjust system. However, when the author talks about how many black individuals could be locked up on a certain day, he does not cross reference it to white individuals, which most likely would have painted a much more vivid reality. Furthermore, it did not mention any numbers or facts in regards to women of color and white women in regards to the Carceral State. 3. Should we keep individuals in bondage because of their past? This is in reference to an inmate who has fully served their sentence, but continues to be discriminated against by being denied federal benefits, voting rights, and the ability to receive occupational licenses. What is Crime?
  • 17. 1. In this article author Raymond J. Michalowski dives into the meaning of crime, and the practice of criminology and how it has evolved over the years. He made the realization that crime is not necessarily about body count, but that it is how certain groups treat the action which is labeled as a crime. He learned from studying vehicular homicides, that political power and economic interests play a crucial role in determining what gets the attention for something to become a crime and what does not. Michalowski points out that in society it is most often the state that determines what is an acceptable action and what is not, what will be a punishable offense and what will be ignored. Though the state is the body that makes the final decision on crime and law, it is often the dominant class in society that gets its voice heard on what they want legal and what they want illegal. In most societies, the voice of the lower class and individuals who are disenfranchised often have no say in the social ordering of what is crime and what is legal. Therefore, these lower classes of society are usually negatively affected by laws which criminalize actions which pertain to people of lower class status, whereas the rich and elite go unchecked because they do not back laws that would disproportionately affect their well-being. When examining this concept through orthodox criminology, the author pointed to the laws of Jim Crow which negatively affected people of color, but helped white supremisitcs retain their control and power in the Deep South. In this article Michalowski points out the flaws and errors in regards to orthodox criminology and urges that criminology should be about social injury and that it is not just about penal codes. When looking at criminology through a lense of social injury, it opens the door for criminologists to consider issues that orthodox criminologists never would have considered such as social injury through climate change, wrongs committed by political states, women’s rights, and LGBTQ discrimination. In conclusion, the author points to the quintessential fact that crime is not a constant across the board and therefore should be carefully considered when determining penal code.
  • 18. 2. This article connected brilliantly with “Democracy and the Carceral State in America” because it shows that the reason why there is so much ambiguity in regards to the prison system is because lawmakers do not always consider the interests of the lower classes, therefore creating laws that result in people of color being disproportionately incarcerated. I did feel that the title was somewhat misleading, because it talked more about understanding the concept of criminology and studying crime, than it did explaining what is crime. 3. Are there any absolutes when dealing with what is crime? For instance the U.S believes murder to be wrong and illegal, but some tribal people would believe that it is okay to murder. Is there one thing that would be considered a crime everywhere and always? https://doi.org/10.1177/0309816818815246 Capital & Class 1 –20 © The Author(s) 2018 Article reuse guidelines: sagepub.com/journals-permissions DOI: 10.1177/0309816818815246 journals.sagepub.com/home/cnc Race, class and persistent
  • 19. coloniality: US policing as liberal pacification Markus Kienscherf Freie Universität Berlin, Germany Abstract This article argues that US policing ends up maintaining and reinforcing substantive intersecting racial and class divisions, precisely because of its avowed formal neutrality. The article is divided into two main sections. The first section sets up a theoretical apparatus for conceptualising the seeming contradiction between general and specific social control. This section argues that US policing has a colonial genealogy but now serves to reproduce a neo- colonial order characterised by both formal legal equality and substantive racial and class inequalities. Moreover, this section shows that the transition from a colonial to a neo-colonial order has been effected by a change in policing’s strategic focus from classical colonial pacification to liberal pacification, which combines coercion with developmentalism. Through a genealogy of US policing, the second section will demonstrate empirically how US policing’s shift towards a strategy of liberal pacification has enabled and continues to facilitate the (re) production of a neo-colonial social order. Since this genealogical section covers quite a long historical period, it will primarily draw on
  • 20. secondary sources. By developing a more nuanced and finely grained policing-as- pacification model that highlights both the colonial genealogy and the contemporary neo-colonial ontology of US policing, this article helps us better understand how and why formally neutral law enforcement ends up producing and reproducing racial and class divisions. Keywords class struggle, colonialism, liberalism, pacification, police, race Corresponding author: Markus Kienscherf, Freie Universität Berlin, Lansstr. 7-9, 14195 Berlin, Germany. Email: [email protected] 815246 CNC0010.1177/0309816818815246Capital & ClassKienscherf research-article2018 Article https://uk.sagepub.com/en-gb/journals-permissions https://journals.sagepub.com/home/cnc http://crossmark.crossref.org/dialog/?doi=10.1177%2F03098168 18815246&domain=pdf&date_stamp=2018-11-27 2 Capital & Class 00(0) Introduction In liberal capitalist social formations, policing – ‘the set of activities aimed at preserving the security of a particular social order, or social order in
  • 21. general’ – is characterised by a fundamental contradiction (Reiner 2010: 5). On the one hand, state police forces – the primary institution (albeit not the only one) tasked with policing – are viewed as largely neutral, though imperfect, enforcers of existing laws, thus protecting and serving every- body irrespective of their race, ethnicity, class, gender or sexuality. On the other hand, the police frequently single out particular populations, most notably the racialised poor, for much more coercive or even brutal treatment than others. So policing purports to ensure the regularity, predictability and security of a general social order that is said to serve the common interest and that is predicated on the formal equality of the rule of law. At the same time, policing more often than not aims to secure a specific social order marked by substantive inequalities along the lines of class, race, ethnicity, gender and sexuality (Marenin 1982: 258–259; see also Loader & Walker 2006: 172–175). In short, policing in advanced capitalist liberal social formations is torn between general social control and specific social control, which often amounts to class and/or racial control (Reiner 2010: 95). Whereas liberal police scholarship has traditionally focussed primarily on the largely consensual and legitimate aspect of policing (see, for example, Waddington 1991), a more radical tradition has pointed out its inherently coercive and violent character (see Seigel 2018; Vitale 2017). Yet, any meaningful radical critique
  • 22. of liberal policing also needs to tackle policing’s efforts to produce its own legitimacy and thus also the legiti- macy of the overall socio-political order through the expansion of a rationality of neutral law enforcement that also extends, at least some, police protection and services to the racialised poor. In brief, effective radical critique must not just point out the repressive aspects of liberal policing but must also engage with its productive aspects. This article argues that US policing in particular ends up maintaining and reinforcing substantive intersecting racial and class divisions, precisely because of its avowed formal neutrality. The article is divided into two main sections. The first section sets up a theo- retical apparatus for conceptualising the seeming contradiction between general and spe- cific social control. Drawing on the literature on contemporary coloniality and internal colonialism, this section argues that US policing has a colonial genealogy but now serves to reproduce a neo-colonial order characterised by both formal legal equality and sub- stantive racial and class inequalities. Moreover, this section shows that the transition from a colonial to a neo-colonial order has been effected by a change in policing’s strate- gic focus from classical colonial pacification to liberal pacification, which combines coer- cion with developmentalism. The second section will map how policing in the US shifted towards a strategy of liberal pacification and how ever more formally class- and
  • 23. race-neutral forms of policing have ended up producing and reinforcing a neo-colonial social order. Since this genealogical section covers quite a long historical period, it will primarily draw on secondary sources. By developing a more nuanced and finely grained policing-as- pacification model that highlights both the colonial genealogy and the contemporary neo-colonial ontology of Kienscherf 3 US policing, the article will help us better understand how and why formally neutral law enforcement ends up producing and reproducing racial and class divisions. Capitalism, (neo-)colonialism and liberal pacification Race and class Policing is the product of conflicting public and private demands placed on state police organisations. These conflicting demands are conditioned by societal conflicts. In capitalist social formations, class divisions are a key source of societal conflicts. Capitalist social formations are societies where the capitalist mode of production is the predominant form of economic activity. The capitalist mode of production is characterised by private ownership of the means of production and ‘the generalisation
  • 24. of the commodity form of labour’ which means that labour power can be bought and sold (almost) like any other commodity (Jessop 2002: 12). Private ownership of the means of production and the commodification of labour gives rise to class divisions: a binary division between the capitalist classes who own the means of production and the working classes who must sell their labour power, as well as more finely grained class differences that derive from domestic and global divisions of labour. There are, however, other sources of societal conflicts besides class struggles. In capitalist social formations, conflicts along the lines of race, ethnicity, gender, sexuality and so on, become entangled with class struggles even if they cannot be reduced to them. This article focuses primarily on how US policing has responded to and also shaped racial and class struggles, not because conflicts around gender and sexuality are less impor- tant but because race and to a lesser extent class are the main sticking points in cur- rent debates about US criminal justice. The ideology of ‘race’ developed as a direct consequence of the colonial conquest of the Americas, where, as Peruvian sociologist Aníbal Quijano (2000) puts it, ‘[t]he conquistadors assumed this idea [of race] as the constitutive, founding element of the relations of domination that the conquest imposed’ (p. 533). In the United States, the ideology of ‘race’ developed through the codification of differences between free and
  • 25. enslaved people in order to justify and reproduce slavery ‘in a republic founded on radical doctrines of liberty and natural rights, and, more important a republic in which those doctrines seemed to represent accurately the world in which all but a minority lived’ (Fields & Fields 2014: 141). From the foundation of the American Republic, racism and class oppression have been inextricably intertwined. African Americans became a ‘race’ because of their oppression, subordination and exploitation – in short, because of their violently imposed class position as enslaved people (Fields & Fields 2014: 266–267). Yet, the ideology of ‘race’ persisted even after the peculiar class posi- tion from which it originally derived was abolished. The ideology of ‘race’ has undoubt- edly undergone profound historical changes but it still serves to justify various forms of racism – that is to say, forms of differential treatment alleged to result from supposed and ultimately fictitious innate differences of the individuals and/or groups who are 4 Capital & Class 00(0) the victims of discrimination. This is what Karen E Fields and Barbara J Fields (2014) call ‘the social alchemy of racecraft [which] transforms racism into race’ so that ‘[d] isguised as race, racism becomes something Afro-Americans are, rather than something racists do’ (pp. 261, 297). Particular populations are thus
  • 26. ‘racialised’ because they are the targets of racism and not the other way around. Even though racism is no longer directly tied to the class position of enslaved people, in capitalist social formations in general and in the United States in particular, racism still serves to reproduce an easily exploitable labour force, to segment labour markets and even ‘to exclude populations from the labor market’ (Grosfoguel 2003: 210). Contemporary coloniality Drawing on Aimé Césaire’s (1972: 5) idea of a ‘boomerang effect of colonization’, schol- ars have pointed out that attempts to secure social order in the metropoles have long been informed by colonial techniques of control (see Arendt 1968; Foucault 2003: 103; Graham 2010). A number of scholars have noted the cross- fertilisation of rationalities and practices of policing between metropole and colony (see, for example, Brogden 1987; Hönke & Müller 2012; McCoy 2009; Müller 2015). What has, however, not been given equal consideration is the idea that contemporary metropolitan policing may still serve the largely colonial purpose of producing populations acquiescent to existing socio- economic inequities through a targeted application of both coercion and consent along the intersecting lines of class and race (McMichael 2017; Neocleous 2011; 2013; 2014; Steinmetz et al. 2017; Williams 2011 are notable exceptions). In their article on ‘American Policing and Colonialism’, Kevin F Steinmetz et al.
  • 27. (2017) suggest that ‘contemporary policing in the United States continues to perpetuate systems of inequality and domination that, in many ways, mirror colonial forms of con- trol’ (p. 9). But does US policing merely ‘mirror colonial forms of control’? Or is it a colonial form of control? Is the coloniality of US policing genealogical or ontological? In order to answer these questions, we have to briefly consider what colonialism actually is. Colonialism is both a form of warfare and rule. The term is mostly used to describe both the processes through which an external invader violently conquers a distant territory and subdues the local population and the resultant systems of rule that allow for the exploitation of geography and people (Blauner 1969; Fanon 2004; Glenn 2015; Pinderhughes 2011; Steinmetz et al. 2017). Colonial violence and exploitation were pivotal for the eventual take-off of the capitalist mode of production. In Marxian terms, colonialism was a form of primitive accumulation, a term that describes the expansion and concentration of private property in the means of production. Primitive accumula- tion did not only provide a large influx of capital into Europe, which paved the way for industrialisation, but also violently divested numerous people from their means of pro- duction (primarily the land) (Marx 1887: 506–547). Primitive accumulation occurred both in the colonies and in Europe, but with a key difference: whereas in Europe, the large-scale dispossession of people mostly forced them into wage labour, the colonised
  • 28. were frequently forced into forms of unpaid labour. However, through the global expan- sion of the capitalist mode of production, colonial forms of unpaid labour were articu- lated ‘around the capitalist wage-labor relation’ (Quijano 2000): Kienscherf 5 This articulation was constitutively colonial, based first on the assignments of all forms of unpaid labor to colonial races […]. Second, labor was controlled through the assignment of salaried labor to the colonizing whites. (p. 539) The adjective ‘primitive’ (from the German ursprünglich) implies that the violent dispossession of people was merely capitalism’s original sin. What is more, colonialism is widely held to have ended with the independence of most former colonies. Yet, a number of scholars argue that coloniality persists despite the abolition of colonial forms of labour control and the independence of former colonies (Grosfoguel 2003; Pinderhughes 2011; Quijano 2000). A hierarchical division of labour along the lines of race and ethnicity established through colonialism ‘continues to be an integral part of the contemporary global division of labour even after independence and the global expansion of the capital- ist wage-labour relation’ (Grosfoguel 2003: 146). In fact, ‘the entanglement of capitalist accumulation processes with a racial/ethnic hierarchy and its derivative classifications of
  • 29. superior/inferior, developed/undeveloped, and civilized/barbarian people’ constitutes a global coloniality even in the absence of any formal colonial system of rule (Grosfoguel 2003: 17; see also Quijano 2000). This ‘entanglement of capitalist accumulation processes with a racial/ethnic hierar- chy’ also marks the domestic situation in the United States as profoundly colonial. US scholars and activists developed the concept of internal colonialism to explain the persis- tence of racial oppression after the end of settler colonisation and the abolition of chattel slavery (Allen 1969, 2005; Blauner 1969; Pinderhughes 2011). The concept came into its own during the civil rights struggle and rising Black militancy in the 1960s but lost importance after the more radical wings of the civil rights movement either fizzled out or were destroyed by the state. In 2005, Robert L Allen, one of the most prominent propo- nents of the internal colonialism theory, revisited the arguments he made in his seminal 1969 book Black Awakening in Capitalist America. In this article, he argues that the political successes of the civil rights movement gave rise to a neo-colonial logic of indirect rule where a small assimilated Black professional class increasingly governs African Americans in the interests of the White capitalist power structure (Allen 2005: 5–6; see also Pinderhughes 2011: 249). However, as we will see in the next section, a neo-colonial logic of indirect rule evolved well before the onset of mass urban rebellion in the 1960s.
  • 30. Since at least the 1920s, this has been the position of northern urban liberals (Miller 2015). This position manifested itself in efforts to manage social conflict without addressing its underlying political-economic causes, but thus also entailed an extension of rights and limited self-governance to African Americans. In short, this was a domestic variant of developmentalism – developing a capacity for self- governance in at least a small group of the colonised so that they can govern their own populations while repro- ducing the overall ‘entanglement of capitalist accumulation processes with a racial/ethnic hierarchy’ (Grosfoguel 2003: 17); in brief, social peace without social justice. So, although African Americans (as well as other racialised groups who are considered citizens) now have formally equal rights, although there now is a sizable Black profes- sional class and although the United States elected its first Black president, a racial and ethnic hierarchy that intersects with and is exacerbated by massive class divisions remains firmly in place. In the United States, the racialised poor thus still find themselves in a 6 Capital & Class 00(0) colonial situation. Yet, this situation should be termed neo- colonial in order to highlight both the ruptures (abolition of colonial labour control, granting of formally equal rights,
  • 31. some forms of self-rule etc.) and the continuities (racial/ethnic division of labour, persis- tence of racism) between classical colonialism and its contemporary liberal variant. I thus have to disagree with Viviane Saleh-Hanna’s (2008: 17–18) and (Steinmetz et al. 2017, 11n) rejection of the term neo-colonial. Even if the techniques of control used for (re-)producing a neo-colonial situation are not new and clearly derive from classical colonialism, they are still deployed under conditions that have undoubtedly changed partly due to the large-scale global contestations of the colonised in the latter half of the 20th century. This is why it is important to distinguish between a colonial geneal- ogy and a neo-colonial ontology when it comes to US policing. Western liberal polic- ing in general has a clear colonial genealogy because many of the techniques used for securing the domestic social order derive from colonial experience. Yet, contemporary US policing in particular – and this may well also hold for policing in other national territories as well as for international forms of policing (see Ryan 2013) – deploys these techniques under new ontological conditions, primarily formal legal equality and the absence of colonial forms of labour control. In short, classical colonialism was primarily about the expropriation, subordination and exploitation of racialised populations, whereas with today’s liberal neo-colonialism, the idea of development has become more important. Ironically, through attempts at
  • 32. development oppression, subordination and exploitation have become less visible but perhaps also more entrenched. Globally, the rise of liberal developmentalism happened in the context of decolonisation struggles and Cold War rivalry. Within the United States, neo-colonial developmentalism arose in response to the civil rights struggle and geopolitical concerns about the international image of the United States. The next sec- tion will show that liberal pacification became the key strategy for developing and inte- grating racialised populations while reproducing a colonial racial and class hierarchy. Liberal pacification Liberalism emerged as a critique of the logic of police along the lines of political econ- omy and the rule of law. Police or police science, which arose across Europe with the breakdown of feudalism, covered a much broader field than what we now understand by the term police. The central concerns of police were to ensure that resources were allo- cated in such a way as to increase prosperity and hence also the strength of the state as well as to promote the general happiness of the population (Neocleous 2000: 11–21; see also Foucault 2007: 311–332). First of all, through the ‘discovery’ of political economy in the 18th century, prosperity came to be seen as the product of the generalised pursuit of private interest rather than as the effect of state regulation. Second, the 18th century also saw a major shift in ideas about general happiness. Philosophers, such as Immanuel
  • 33. Kant, asked whether a sovereign should (or even could) promote general happiness as he (or, perhaps more unlikely, she) saw fit. Ultimately, this gave rise to the liberal principle of the rule of law and the argument that sovereignty should be limited to protecting security and freedom so that everyone could freely pursue their own happiness (Neocleous 2000: 22–30). However, the supposed neutrality and formal equality of the rule of law Kienscherf 7 also generalised and legitimated the substantively unequal distribution of private prop- erty in the means of production which was brought about by primitive accumulation. Liberalism thus sought to demarcate a socio-economic sphere of autonomous human activity (civil society and the market) from the political sphere which came itself to be seen as the product of the convergence of the political interests of individual autonomous subjects. At the same time, liberal political thought constantly problematised the human capacity for autonomy, for not everybody was considered equally capable of responsible self-governance. Women, children, colonial subjects and the domestic undeserving poor were frequently seen as either incapable of self-governance or as not yet able to exercise their autonomy in a responsible manner (Dean 2000; Rasmussen 2011). Liberal govern-
  • 34. ment through freedom has thus always depended on a specifically liberal form of polic- ing. Liberal policing has sought to control those subjects who were deemed incapable of doing so themselves and to (often coercively) promote the capacity for responsible self- governance of those who were held to not yet possess it. In fact, liberal policing rests on a binary distinction, between safely autonomous subjects and subjects whose excess of autonomy is viewed as a threat as well as a hierarchy of liberal development. Liberal policing thus hinges both on a temporal scale of development, of becoming liberal, and on a spatial distinction between safe and dangerous subjects. The combination of a rigid binary with a developmental hierarchy also indicates the coloniality of liberal policing. For, according to Quijano (2000: 552–553), the articulation of a rigid binary between primitive and civilised upon a developmental hierarchy that ranges from the state of nature to European modernity is also one of the hallmarks of colo- nial Eurocentrism. Indeed, liberal policing was profoundly shaped by colonial experiences. Not only did the denial of colonised subjects’ capacity for self- governance provide a con- venient legitimation for their expropriation, oppression and exploitation but the actual experience of producing and ruling colonised subjects also helped develop and perfect techniques for coercively regulating the behaviour of domestic ‘problem’ populations. Indeed, classical liberal political thinkers frequently justified
  • 35. colonial domination by referring to what they saw as irreducible racial differences preventing the colonised from governing themselves in a responsible manner (the domestic poor were also often por- trayed in racialised terms). But with the expansion of the capitalist mode of production and its need for ‘free’ labour, essentialist conceptions of autonomy began to shift towards more relational markers of autonomy (without ever being fully replaced by them). The level of capacity for self-governance has come to be decided by one’s relation to the mar- ket, by one’s market utility, by one’s ability and willingness to freely sell one’s labour power. Yet, these market-based ascriptions of autonomy still reproduce the legacy of racial domination and also produce new forms of inequality. It is no coincidence that populations whose autonomy has traditionally been put into question are now widely seen as failing the test of the market. The economic plight of African Americans, their supposed reliance on welfare and their overrepresentation in the prison population thus give a new purportedly colour-blind inflection to traditional forms of racism that denied them their capacity for responsible self-governance on purely racial grounds. It is precisely around the perceived (in)capacity for self-governance, now primarily structured by notions of market competitiveness, that class and race intersect and mutually rein- force one another. The political economy that took shape against the background of the
  • 36. 8 Capital & Class 00(0) protracted crisis of the 1970s, which came to known as neoliberalism, prompted a down- wards pressure on wages, a decreasing demand for unskilled and semiskilled labour and a retrenchment of welfare. This had a disproportionate effect on African Americans. Neoliberalism has, thus, produced a criminalised sub- proletarian surplus population whose irresponsible autonomy is viewed as an obstacle to capital accumulation. Consequently, contemporary US policing serves to incapacitate those members of this sub-proletarian surplus population whose excessive autonomy is seen as dangerous, while – as somewhat of an afterthought – trying to coercively integrate those members of this population who are still considered worthy of showing their responsible autonomy through participation in the lowest rungs of the labour market. So, the decline of essentialised ideas about autonomy, which was brought about both by changes in capital accumulation and through political contestations of the oppressed, also necessitated the need for more developmentalist interventions in order to develop autonomy while still reproducing both the overall capitalist mode of production and its racial and class hierarchies. And this is where liberal policing comes in. Liberal policing aims to develop auton-
  • 37. omy in those who are deemed incapable of responsible self- governance, to remove obsta- cles to responsible self-governance and to eradicate forms of autonomy that are considered dangerous. Liberal policing is thus engaged in what I call liberal pacification – a strategy for pro- ducing and reproducing populations capable of responsible self- governance through the selective and differentially targeted application of a combination of coercion, support and consent. It is perhaps no coincidence that the term pacification as well as the set of practices it denotes emerged in the same context as the ideology of ‘race’, namely, during the Spanish colonial conquest of America in the late 16th century (Neocleous 2011: 198). The coercive ordering of unruly, risky, dangerous and, more often than not, racial- ised populations through techniques of pacification has ever since been one of the key concerns of colonial policing/warfighting and continues to be a major concern for Western counterinsurgents (see, for example, US Department of the Army 2014). In brief, as Mark Neocleous has pointed out, pacification has been one of the central tech- nologies of colonialism and continues to be a key strategy for reproducing ‘wage labour as the grounds for accumulation’ (Neocleous 2013: 25). However, the transition from classical colonialism based on ‘mere’ expropriation and oppression to a neo-colonial global and domestic order that combines formal legal equal-
  • 38. ity with substantive class/racial inequalities calls for a more nuanced conception of paci- fication. Indeed, the principle of liberal legal equality, which is after all based on notions of autonomy, figures prominently in contemporary liberal pacification, because liberal pacification also seeks to develop its targets’ capacities for responsible liberal self-govern- ance. Liberal pacification rose to prominence during post-WWII struggles for national liberation. The strategy of liberal pacification, which became a central component of Western counterinsurgency doctrines from the 1960s, seemed to offer a solution to the problem of developing the colonies’ capacities for self- governance in such a way as to secure their continuous availability for capitalist exploitation and geo-strategic domina- tion in the absence of direct rule. Liberal pacification ought to be understood as a fusion of security and development – to secure Western geo-strategic and geo-economic inter- ests while developing indigenous capacities for responsible self- governance in order to Kienscherf 9 unevenly integrate colonial populations into the global circuits of capital accumulation (Duffield 2010; Kienscherf 2013; Shafer 1988). However, although liberal pacification came into its own at the cusp of decolonisation after WWII, it has a much deeper geneal- ogy based in classic colonialism and domestic class struggle.
  • 39. Attempts to civilise or mod- ernise colonies was also a key goal of Western colonial powers, above all France and Britain, during the 19th century. And so were strategies of indirect rule through local strongmen in the all-too-frequent case that grand civilising missions failed in the face of stiff local resistance (see Porch 2013). What is more, throughout the 19th century, rising working-class militancy across Western metropoles also prompted the need for political strategies that combined the integration of the working classes into the social order through development (granting rights, welfare etc.) with efforts to secure the existing capitalist class structure (Owens 2015). What is important to note is that in liberal pacification, the actual on-the-ground blend of security and development ultimately depends on the level and organisation of local resistance and on the specific politico-economic interests of the dominant classes. In short, liberal pacification is a technology of ordering that can be summarised as social peace without social justice because it addresses only those grievances that do not ques- tion any fundamental structural inequities. Pacification deploys reasonable and/or minimum necessary force as one of its key tac- tics. Ryan (2013) suggests that reasonable force, which is ‘a mode of persuasion where force stands as a defensive line behind the progress of reasonable argument’ is ontological to police power (p. 435). He further argues that ‘police power
  • 40. ultimately aims to produce coherent, self-governing rational actors who perform productively in […] a globalized raison d’etat’ (p. 456). Since the use of force by anybody who does not wield police power is thus always construed as illegitimate and unreasonable, it becomes ‘the more reasonable […] for police to move up the scale of violence in its reaction’ (p. 456). So, ‘what is reason- able has become what is necessary’ (p. 443). In fact, minimum necessary force is one of the central principles governing the liberal use of violence (Kienscherf 2016: 1185). Minimum necessary force is the exact amount of force that is seen as reasonable in a par- ticular situation. The more unreasonable the targets of liberal force appear, for example because of their militant or even armed resistance against an oppressive and exploitative neo-colonial situation, the more force can be used against them. Minimum necessary force is what ultimately enables liberal pacification’s other forms of reasonable force that seek to produce more pliable subjects without any actual use of force. The next section will use the analytic of liberal pacification to highlight how in the United States ever more formally class- and race-neutral forms of policing have ended up producing and reinforcing a neo-colonial social order marked by substantive inequalities along the intersecting lines of race and class. US policing as liberal pacification
  • 41. Patrolling racial lines From its beginnings as a White settler colony, the United States has been riven by drastic racial and class divisions. The contours of this racialised and class-based social order have undoubtedly changed (both on the basis of shifts in capital accumulation and through 10 Capital & Class 00(0) contestation from below), but the institution of chattel slavery has left indelible marks on the US social order and thus also on the institution of the police. Chattel slavery constituted a classical colonial order defined by the brutal subordination and oppression of enslaved people for the purpose of coercively extracting their labour power. Slavery, moreover, was entangled with international systems of banking, insurance and credit and also contributed to the rise of industrialisation, first in Britain and later in the American north (Baptist 2014; Oakes 2016). The size of the slave population was considered a massive social control problem. The threat of slave insurrection and the constant risk of slave flight led to the emergence of ever more formalised slave patrols. The first slave patrols were formed in the 17th century and were informal bands of volunteers tasked with recapturing runaway slaves. In the course of the 18th century, slave patrols became more organised and were also charged with preventing insurrection. The Fugitive Slave
  • 42. Act of 1850 gave state governments wide-ranging authority to recruit individuals – espe- cially poor Whites – into slave patrols that now had almost unlimited coercive powers over the slave population. Slave patrols were tasked with the routine surveillance of the slave population in order to regulate and manage their movement according to the polit- ico-economic imperatives of chattel slavery (Bass 2001: 159; Brucato 2014: 38–39). In fact, slave patrols were a significant strand in the genealogy of the US police (Bass 2001; Brucato 2014; Hadden 2001). Brutal efforts to control the movement and hence also the labour power of the Black population continued after the abolition of slavery. There was, however, a brief interlude during which the federal government tried to turn freed people into citizens and autono- mous wage labourers through the establishment of the Bureau of Refugees, Freedmen and Abandoned Lands, better known as the Freedmen’s Bureau. The Freedmen’s Bureau was set up towards the end of the Civil War in March 1865 to provide immediate relief to freed people as well as to poor Whites uprooted by the war, but its mission quickly expanded to a large-scale and often contradictory effort to protect freed people’s civil and political rights, to revive agricultural production in the South and to turn former slaves into free wage labourers (often on the same plantations they used to work on as slaves) (Goldberg 2007: 31–75). The Freedmen’s Bureau can be understood as an early, albeit
  • 43. ultimately failed, attempt at liberal pacification which sought to develop African Americans’ capacity for self-governance in order to integrate them into a Northern capi- talist order as both citizens and self-dependent but docile wage labourers. Despite its chequered track record, the Freedmen’s Bureau started from the assumption that African Americans were at least potentially capable of responsible self- governance. This is per- haps why W.E.B. Du Bois (2007: 179) praised the Bureau as ‘the most extraordinary and far-reaching institution of social uplift that America has ever attempted’, despite the fact that it also frequently served as an instrument for disciplining Black labour (Goldberg 2007: 40–42). The Bureau’s efforts to develop African Americans while also protecting them from continuing White violence did not go down well with Southern Whites who ultimately succeeded in swaying Congress to terminate the Freedmen’s Bureau in 1872. Immediately after the end of the Civil War, most Southern states replaced their Slave Codes with the so-called Black Codes which were aimed to severely restrict the freedom of former slaves and maintain them in a state of quasi-slavery through extremely low wages, debt peonage as well as numerous sweeping vagrancy statutes. After mounting Kienscherf 11
  • 44. criticism from Northern States, increasing legal pressure from the Congress and 11 years of direct military administration of the Southern States, the Black Codes were replaced by Jim Crow in 1877. The Jim Crow laws contained many provisions that were fre- quently as, if not more, sweeping than the original Black Codes. As Sandra Bass (2001) puts it, ‘Essentially, African Americans lived in a police state in which every aspect of shared public life was proscribed. Formal police organizations under this system were responsible for upholding the formal and informal social order’ (p. 161). Besides man- dating strict racial segregation and brutally punishing any infraction against Whites, Jim Crow laws also ensured African Americans continuing availability as docile and easily exploitable agricultural labour through debt peonage and convict leasing. What is more, this brutal colonial regime of racist oppression and exploitation was ultimately backed up by both legal and extra-legal violence in the forms of lynchings (Marable 1983: 108–121). Pacifying class struggle The first urban police force in the United States was founded in New York in 1845 and was closely modelled on the famous London Metropolitan Police (Miller 1999; Monkkonen 1981). The idea of a uniformed urban police force was also a product of colonialism. When British Home Secretary Robert Peel set up the Metropolitan Police of London in 1829, he drew heavily on his earlier experiences as
  • 45. Chief Secretary of Ireland (1812–1818). During his time in Ireland, Peel realised that an external military force was ill-suited to pacifying a poor and rebellious colonial population. This led to experimenta- tion with ‘a new kind of bureaucracy, located in a social space midway between an out- side military force and the group of people to be controlled’ – the Irish Constabulary (Monkkonen 1981: 39). A bureaucracy that was modelled on the military but not (quite) a military force itself and whose frontline troops were recruited from the population to be controlled also offered a more legitimate and thus ultimately more effective way of pacifying metropolitan working-class militancy. Indeed, one of the key tasks of early US urban police forces was to pacify class strug- gles as well as intra-class ethnic conflicts brought about by rapid industrialisation, urban- isation and immigration in many Northern and Midwestern cities (Harring 2017; Vitale 2017; Williams 2015). Early municipal police forces also provided important services to the communities they controlled. In fact, many urban police forces ran soup kitchens, gave shelter to the homeless and searched for lost children (Monkkonen 1981: 86–128). As Sidney L Harring (2017) notes, ‘the police institution gains legitimacy when it makes some accommodation to the communities being policed’ (p. 16). In short, through a combination of coercion and support 19th century urban policing helped produce, rein- force and ultimately legitimate a capitalist social formation
  • 46. based on class subordination and exploitation. Early urban police forces were rather decentralised, poorly trained and engaged in many off-the-books activities. In fact, throughout the 19th century, cops frequently acted as enforcers for corrupt ward bosses and political machines (Chriss 2011: 28–32). As many police scholars have it, the progressive era, starting in the 1890s, marked the end of the so-called political spoils era of American policing (Chriss 2011; Kelling & 12 Capital & Class 00(0) Moore 1988). Throughout the late 19th and early 20th centuries, police departments came to be organised along more bureaucratic lines, adopted more militarised command and control structures, introduced new technologies and professionalised police training. The progressive era also saw increasing police specialisation. Police began to fashion themselves as professional law enforcers. Progressive-era police reform also had a clear colonial pedigree. Historian Alfred McCoy (2009) shows how the colonial occupation of the Philippines in the late 19th and early 20th centuries prompted numerous innova- tions in the fields of policing, intelligence, counterintelligence and surveillance, many of which were reimported into US domestic policing, eventually giving rise to what he calls
  • 47. ‘the surveillance state’. McCoy argues that the police apparatus created by the American army in the Philippines at the beginning of the 20th century ‘was far more advanced’ than contemporaneous US domestic police forces (p. 61). Many of the policing practices honed in the colonial Philippines were brought back into the United States by colonial veterans whose racial frame of reference often made them view America’s ‘ethnic com- munities not as fellow citizens but as internal colonies requiring coercive controls’ (McCoy 2009: 294). According to Harring (2017), the sweeping reforms of US municipal police depart- ments towards the beginning of the 20th century occurred primarily in response to a growing need to pacify escalating class struggles. At the end of the 19th century and the beginning of 20th century, an increasing number of large-scale strikes led to calls for an expansion and centralisation of police departments. On the other hand, there were also heightened concerns over police corruption as well as a more general trend towards the rationalisation and bureaucratisation of urban governance. Surely, the focus on depoliti- cised, bureaucratic, centralised and purportedly neutral law enforcement also served to make police departments more legitimate in the eyes of the working classes (Harring 2017: 232). At the same time, law enforcement afforded an opportunity extensively to intervene in the lives of working-class people, patrolling the line between independent
  • 48. workers and the dependent, criminalised poor. More often than not this occurred through the enforcement of sweeping vagrancy statutes that were modelled on or even directly taken over from what Marx (1887: 522) called ‘a bloody legislation against vaga- bondage’ that was enacted throughout Western Europe form the 15th century in order to crack down on people who were forcibly dispossessed through primitive accumulation (see also Adler 1989; Chambliss 1964). Until the Supreme Court declared them uncon- stitutional at the beginning of the 1970s, vagrancy laws afforded the police a lot of legal leeway to come down hard on undesirables: Armed with a roving license to arrest, officials employed vagrancy laws for a breath-taking array of purposes: to force the local poor to work or suffer for their support; to keep out poor or suspicious strangers, to suppress differences that might be dangerous; to stop crimes before they were committed; to keep racial minorities, political troublemakers, and nonconforming rebels at bay. (Goluboff 2016: 2–3) Police reform thus served to generalise and legitimate class control through an exten- sion of rationalities and practices of enforcing formally neutral laws which in practice only particular groups of people happened to be in violation of. Even though laws Kienscherf 13
  • 49. directed against status-type offences such vagrancy have been declared unconstitutional, they have now increasingly been replaced by civility codes that target behaviours rather than status. But more often than not these happen to be types of behaviour, such as sleeping outdoors, drinking and urinating in public, the racialised poor are more likely to engage in than members of the middle classes. Katherine Beckett and Steve Herbert (2009) document how new urban social control tools, such as off-limit orders, park exclusion laws and new trespass laws ultimately criminalise complex social problems, wash up even more people in the criminal justice system and create a new legal status – excluded – which is predominantly assigned to the racialised non-working poor. Pacifying racial conflict Although there were much fewer overly segregationist laws in Northern and Midwestern cities, there was still a racialised social order based on informal spatial segregation as well as the exclusion of African Americans from most well-paying jobs (Miller 2015: 7–9). Following growing Black migration from the early 20th century onwards – due to a crisis of agricultural production in the South and heightened demand for unskilled and semi- skilled labour in the industrial North and Midwest – the Black population of Northern and Midwestern cities grew significantly. And, so did the animosity of local politicians, real estate agents and White homeowners, who used a variety of
  • 50. tactics to maintain a racialised social order through residential segregation. Blacks were confined to inner-city ghettoes that served the twin function of excluding them from White society while including their exploitable labour power in the industrial economy. All the while, urban police depart- ments played an important role in producing and maintaining this racialised order (Bass 2001; Wacquant 2001). In the context of growing Black urban populations targeted by various forms of racism, the ideology of Northern racial liberalism took shape. According to Karen Miller (2015), ‘racial liberalism married the same two components that color- blind racism does today: an extension of racial inequality alongside a commitment to the language of interracial understanding and race neutrality’ (p. 7). Faced with growing Black demands for more socio-economic equality, on the one hand, and the vested interests of many Whites to maintain racial hierarchies especially in terms of residential and labour patterns, on the other, many liberal urban governments thus sought ‘to regulate race rela- tions and avoid racial conflicts in the name of urban peace’ (Miller 2015: 9). This amounted to a strategy of liberal pacification: social peace without social justice – addressing only those Black grievances that did not question the overall racialised capitalist order. In fact, ‘[m]aintaining capitalism thus meant, in part, maintaining racial inequalities’ (Miller 2015: 145). Indeed, the increasing political significance of Northern racial liberalism marked the beginning of a transition from a colonial to a neo-colonial
  • 51. order. The ideology of racial liberalism also informed a second wave of police reform that slowly took shape against the background of rising Black liberation struggles starting in the 1940s. Growing efforts to modernise the criminal justice system in general and police in particular were prompted by a liberal desire to pacify racial conflict. Here, according to Naomi Murakawa (2014), lies a significant and often overlooked factor for the emer- gence of the contemporary US carceral state. From the 1940s, liberal policymakers 14 Capital & Class 00(0) increasingly problematised racial tensions – above all White racist violence in the South – in terms of law and order. White racist violence in the South frequently occurred with the tacit support of or even in direct collusion with local police or sheriffs’ departments. But, liberal policymakers viewed racial violence as primarily a problem of illegitimate, unlawful and ultimately unreasonable violence and considered the modernisation and professionalisation of the organs of state-sanctioned, reasonable force as an adequate solution. The articulation of law and order upon race gave rise to a liberal political agenda based on ‘tightening hardware’ and ‘healing hearts’; that is to say, efforts to mod- ernise and professionalise criminal justice agencies as well as
  • 52. attempts to bolster state legitimacy in the eyes of African Americans (Murakawa 2014: 44–53). However, the liberal law and order agenda proved to be vulnerable to being hijacked by Southern race conservatives, who re-framed the supposed link between crime and race not as a problem of White racist violence but as a problem of Black criminality – an astonishing feat of ‘racecraft’ that would have a lasting impact (see Fields & Fields 2014). Hence, there emerged a strong bipartisan consensus on the need for criminal justice reform, even though the ultimate objectives of these reform efforts differed along partisan lines: creat- ing more racial fairness was the prime goal of race liberals, whereas repressing Black criminality and shoring up the racist colonial order were the aims of race conservatives (Murakawa 2014: 74). As President Johnson’s Safe Streets Act bill went through Congress in 1967, a number of key changes were introduced by conservatives. The provisions for the federal funding of local police contained in the original bill stipulated for federal-to- local categorical grants. This would have given the federal government a lot more say in how local police and sheriffs’ department would ultimately use the monies. Yet, through several amendments in the House and the Senate, this was changed to federal-to-state block grants. So, the monies went directly to the states that could then distribute them to local law enforcement agencies as they saw fit. The final piece of legislation – the Omnibus Crime Control and Safe Streets Act of 1968 –
  • 53. eventually established the Law Enforcement Assistance Administration (LEAA) in an effort to cut crime rates through the modernisation of local police. The LEAA failed in achieving its ultimate goal of reducing crime, but, primarily due to the amendments to the original bill, resulted in local police departments’ stockpiling of military-grade gear and the proliferation of para- military police units across the country (Murakawa 2014: 85– 90; see also Kraska & Kappeler 1997; Parenti 1999). The LEAA was also a major step towards generalising the Northern model of the professional urban police, though policing remained highly local- ised. So, the machinery was definitely tightened. But what about healing the hearts? Rising Black militancy, massive ghetto uprisings and the political successes of the civil rights movement in the 1960s prompted the re-importation of many techniques of colo- nial control into the continental United States. Local police departments acquired mili- tary equipment, such as CN and CS gas (originally developed for use in Vietnam), helicopters and armoured personnel carriers as well as training in military tactics (Parenti 1999; Pinto 1971; Quinney 1974). However, it was not just the coercive techniques of overseas counterinsurgency operations that were reimported into domestic US policing in the late 1960s. More consensual techniques of expeditionary counterinsurgency also boomeranged back into the continental United States. This is exemplified by two
  • 54. Kienscherf 15 developments: (1) the rise of more consensual approaches to protest policing and (2) the emergence of community policing. From the early 1970s, protest policing changed from ‘escalated force’ to ‘negotiated management’ (McPhail et al. 1998; McPhail & McCarthy 2005; Soule & Davenport 2009). During the 1960s, police response to protest was overwhelmingly coercive and included, often unprovoked, mass arrests, the indiscriminate use of force, and showed little patience with protesters’ First Amendment rights. Escalated force frequently led to property damage, injuries and even deaths, which in turn prompted rising public criti- cism of police on the part of both civil liberties groups and political elites. In the late 1960s and early 1970s, various congressional commissions – the most famous of which was the National Commission on Civil Disorder (Kerner Commission) – found that violent protest was often exacerbated if not triggered by overly aggressive policing (McPhail & McCarthy 2005: 63). In 1967, at request of the Justice Department, the US Army Military Police School (USAMPS) set up a Civil Disturbance Orientation Course (SEADOC) for municipal police and the National Guard. The main concern of SEADOC I, which ran from February 1968 to April 1969, was
  • 55. with the suppression of urban riots through an escalation of force. In May 1970, SEADOC II was launched and continued until at least 1978. SEADOC II included many of the recommendations made by these congressional commissions. The focus was no longer merely on how to suppress riots but on how to effectively manage a variety of different protest events. SEADOC II centred on the strategic concept of ‘confrontation management’, which sought to avoid any overreaction on the part of police to protesters’ provocations, and on the tactical principle of ‘minimum necessary force’, which is, as we have seen, a key com- ponent of liberal pacification (US Army Military Police School 1972, cited in McPhail & McCarthy 2005). Community policing is a much-vaunted policing strategy supposed to help police (re) build and (re)establish legitimacy especially in the eyes of marginalised and impoverished communities (Herbert 2006). Although most US police departments officially state that they do some sort of community policing, it remains unclear what community policing actually means in practice (Herbert 2006: 4; Saunders 1999a, 1999b). But as Steve Herbert (2006) writes, ‘community policing programs generally seek to help police departments to improve their connections with citizen groups and to decentralize their operations to make better use of input from those groups’ (p. 4). Community policing also amounts to a form of liberal pacificion. The author of a
  • 56. 2006 RAND report On ‘Other War’: Lessons from Five Decades of RAND Counterinsurgency Research suggests that ‘pacification is best thought of as a massively enhanced version of the “community polic- ing” technique that emerged in the 1970s (encouraged in part by RAND research)’ (Long 2006: 53). In his discussion of possible ways of fixing a broken criminal justice system, late legal scholar William J Stuntz (2011) suggested that US counterinsurgency tactics used in Iraq ‘could have been taken from a community policing manual’ (p. 293). And he continued as follows: Today’s policing conventional wisdom emphasizes the same three moves: a more public police street presence in the most violent areas, a problem-solving approach to local blights like 16 Capital & Class 00(0) garbage on the streets or gang signs on local buildings, and, most important of all, the building of relationships between police officers and local neighborhood residents. (p. 293) Stuntz also argued that these policing strategies are not only effective in reducing urban crime but could also help curb ‘the state’s seemingly insatiable desire to punish young black men’ (p. 310). However, in practice, community policing hardly offers any real alternative to mass incarceration. On the contrary, concerns
  • 57. over ‘urban blights’ frequently lead to massive increases in detentions, arrests and criminal records for often minor misdemeanours, such as loitering or drinking in public, primarily in neglected and underinvested minority neighbourhoods (Harcourt 2001). This is also borne out by an activist report on the Chicago Alternative Policing Strategy (CAPS) (We Charge Genocide 2015). CAPS is one of the most ambitious and largest community policing programmes in the United States and was officially rolled out in 1993 (Chicago Police Department 2016). The Counter-CAPS report found that ‘at CAPS meetings, police effectively deputise a small group of residents to engage in surveillance. These residents are disproportionately white property owners, especially in gentrifying neighborhoods’ (We Charge Genocide 2015: 4). This seems to be a general problem of community policing. The terrain of urban communities remains marked by substantive inequalities, which the police are neither able nor willing to tackle; while the police engage with com- munities in a highly uneven fashion, and vice versa. In fact, the police do not seek every- body’s input equally and some (generally well-heeled) community groups are in a much better position to voice their grievances to the police than others (Herbert 2006; see also Muñiz 2015). So, despite the pleasant ring of the term and some genuine democratising potential inherent in attempts to seek more community input, community policing remains, above all, a rhetorical strategy that alongside the use
  • 58. of some substantive prac- tices seeks to persuade people of the legitimacy of the state in general and of the police in particular (Saunders 1999a, 1999b): State formation involves not just the practice of state agencies, but also the active participation (if not the consent) of state subjects. Community policing is one such instance, therefore, in which the capacity for concrete oppression is wedded to processes of legitimation. (p. 137) As a consequence, community policing ought to be understood as an instance of liberal pacification which uses reasonable force to garner the participation and consent of the population in securing the existing social order. However, reasonable force is still backed up and ultimately facilitated by the actual violence to be used against subjects who prove to be too unreasonable to be swayed by reasonable force (Ryan 2013). Community policing thus ultimately reproduces and legitimates a purportedly colour- blind and class-neutral neo-colonial order marked by the ‘the entanglement of capitalist accumulation processes with a racial/ethnic hierarchy’ (Grosfoguel 2003: 17). Conclusion As Manning Marable (1983) wrote, ‘Blacks occupy the lowest socioeconomic rung in the ladder of American upward mobility precisely because they have been integrated all
  • 59. Kienscherf 17 too well into the system’ (p. 2). As has been shown, the United States ought to be under- stood as neo-colonial order based on both formal legal equality and substantive racial/ class divisions. Through a strategy of liberal pacification aimed at formally integrating African Americans into the social order through a combination of security and develop- ment, US policing has been and continues to be pivotal for producing and reinforcing a neo-colonial order structured around formal legal equality and substantive racial and class inequalities. In fact, US policing operates as an instrument of class and racial oppression precisely because it aims to coercively integrate marginalised populations into a social order characterised by the generalisation of specific racial/class divisions through principles of formal legal equality and individual autonomy. This generalisation of spe- cific inequalities that are conducive to capitalist accumulation has been brought about by means of liberal pacification: some (more often than not coercive) development for those who are seen as still having some labour market utility and incapacitation for those who have permanently failed the test of the labour market or who are seen as a threat to capi- talist accumulation. This market-based ascription of autonomy and the lack thereof is precisely what reproduces substantive inequalities within a system of formal equality.
  • 60. As Elizabeth Jones (2018) puts it, the US criminal justice system ‘has always operated as a mediator between black labour and capitalist modes of production’ (p. 42). What is more, ‘racism works both ways: to justify the reproduction of a cheap labor force and to exclude populations from the labor market’ (Grosfoguel 2003: 210). Problematisations of crime and disorder thus serve to criminalise a population many of whose members are now structurally condemned permanently to fail the test of the labour market. Indeed, racialisation through racist criminalisation is a purportedly colour-blind mechanism for upholding a neo-colonial racial and class hierarchy in the context of de jure equality. But, despite the best efforts to make it seem so, capitalism has never been colour-blind. ORCID iD Markus Kienscherf https://orcid.org/0000-0001-7202-1482 References Adler JS (1989) A historical analysis of the law of vagrancy. Criminology 27(2): 209–229. Allen RL (1969) Black Awakening in Capitalist America. New York: Doubleday. Allen RL (2005) Reassessing the internal (neo) colonialism theory. The Black Scholar 35(1): 2–11. Arendt H (1968) Imperialism. New York: Harcourt, Brace & World. Baptist EE (2014) The Half Has Never Been Told: Slavery and the Making of American Capitalism. New York: Basic Books. Bass S (2001) Policing space, policing race: Social control
  • 61. imperatives and police discretionary decisions. Social Justice 28(1): 156–176. Beckett K and Herbert S (2009) Banished: The New Social Control in Urban America. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Blauner R (1969) Internal colonialism and ghetto revolt. Social Problems 16(4): 393–408. Brogden M (1987) The emergence of the police: The colonial dimension. British Journal of Criminology 27(1): 4–14. Brucato B (2014) Fabricating the color line in a white democracy: From slave catchers to petty sovereigns. Theoria: A Journal of Social and Political Theory 61(4): 30–54. 18 Capital & Class 00(0) Césaire A (1972) Discourse on Colonialism. New York: Monthly Review Press. Chambliss WJ (1964) A sociological analysis of the law of vagrancy. Social Problems 12(1): 67–77. Chicago Police Department (2016) Get involved with CAPS. Available at: http://home .chicagopolice.org/get-involved-with-caps/how-caps- works/what-is-caps/ (accessed 23 January 2018). Chriss JJ (2011) Beyond Community Policing: From Early American Beginnings to the 21st Century.
  • 62. London: Routledge. Dean M (2000) Liberal government and authoritarianism. Economy and Society 31(1): 37–61. Du Bois WEB (2007) Black Reconstruction in America: An Essay toward a History of the Part Which Black Folk Played in the Attempt to Reconstruct Democracy in America, 1860–1880. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Duffield M (2010) The liberal way of development and the development-security impasse: Exploring the global life-chance divide. Security Dialogue 41(1): 53–76. Fanon F (2004) The Wretched of the Earth. New York: Grove Press. Fields KE and Fields BJ (2014) Racecraft: The Soul of Inequality in American Life. London: Verso Books. Foucault M (2003) Society Must Be Defended: Lectures at the College De France 1975–1976. New York: Picador. Foucault M (2007) Security, Territory, Population. Lectures at the College De France 1977–1978. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan. Glenn EN (2015) Settler colonialism as structure: A framework for comparative studies of U.S. race and gender formation. Sociology of Race and Ethnicity 1(1): 52–72. Goldberg CA (2007) Citizens and Paupers: Relief, Rights, and
  • 63. Race, from the Freedman’s Bureau to Workfare. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press. Goluboff R (2016) Vagrant Nation: Police Power, Constitutional Change, and the Making of the 1960s. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Graham S (2010) Cities Under Siege: The New Military Urbanism. London: Verso Books. Grosfoguel R (2003) Colonial Subjects: Puerto Ricons in a Global Perspective. Berkeley: University of California Press. Hadden SE (2001) Slave Patrols: Law and Violence in Virginia and the Carolinas. Harvard, MA: Harvard University Press. Harcourt BE (2001) The Illusion of Order: The False Promise of Broken Windows Policing. Harvard, MA: Harvard University Press. Harring SL (2017) Policing a Class Society: The Experience of American Cities 1865–1915. Chicago: Haymarket Books. Herbert S (2006) Citizens, Cops, and Power: Recognizing the Limits of Community Policing. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press. Hönke J and Müller M-M (2012) Governing (in)security in a postcolonial world: Transnational entanglements and the worldliness of ‘local’ practice. Security Dialogue 43(5): 383–401. Jessop B (2002) The Future of the Capitalist State. Cambridge: Polity Press.
  • 64. Jones E (2018) Racism, fines and fees and the US carceral state. Race & Class 59(3): 38–50. Kelling GL and Moore MH (1988) The evolving strategy of policing. Perspectives on Policing 4: 1–16. Kienscherf M (2013) US Domestic and International Regimes of Security: Pacifying the Homeland, Securing the Globe. London: Routledge. Kienscherf M (2016) Beyond militarization and repression: Liberal social control as pacification. Critical Sociology 42(7–8): 1179–1194. Kraska PB and Kappeler VE (1997) Militarizing American police: The rise and normalization of paramilitary units. Social Problems 44(1): 1–18. Kienscherf 19 Loader I and Walker N (2006) Necessary virtues: The legitimate place of the state in the produc- tion of security. In: Wood J and Dupont B (eds) Democracy and the Governance of Security. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 165–195. Long A (2006) On ‘Other War’: Lessons from Five Decades of RAND Counterinsurgency Research. Santa Monica, CA: RAND Corporation. McCoy AW (2009) Policing America’s Empire: The United States, the Philippines and the Rise of the Surveillance State. Madison: University of Wisconsin Press.
  • 65. McMichael C (2017) Pacification and police: A critique of the police militarization thesis. Capital & Class 41(1): 115–132. McPhail C and McCarthy JD (2005) Protest mobilization, protest repression, and their inter- action. In: Davenport C, Johnston H and Mueller C (eds) Repression and Mobilization. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, pp. 3–32. McPhail C, Schweingruber D and McCarthy JD (1998) Policing protest in the United States: 1960– 1995. In: Della Porta D and Reiter H (eds) Policing Protest: The Control of Mass Demonstrations in Western Democracies. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, pp. 49–69. Marable M (1983) How Capitalism Underdeveloped Black America: Problems in Race, Political Economy and Society. Boston, MA: South End Press. Marenin O (1982) Parking tickets and class repression: The concept of policing in critical theories of criminal justice. Contemporary Crises 6(3): 241–266. Marx K (1887) Capital: A Critique of Political Economy, vol. 1. Moscow: Progress Publishers. Miller KR (2015) Managing Inequality: Northern Racial Liberalism in Interwar Detroit. New York: New York University Press. Miller WA (1999) Cops and Bobbies: Police Authority in New York and London, 1830–1870. Columbus: Ohio State University Press.