SlideShare a Scribd company logo
SEXUAL DISORDERS (LE MARSHALL AND H MOULDEN, SECTION EDITORS)
Sex Doll Ownership: An Agenda for Research
Craig A. Harper1
& Rebecca Lievesley1
# The Author(s) 2020
Abstract
Purpose of Review The topic of sex doll ownership is becoming an increasingly discussed issue from both a social and legal
perspective. This review aims to examine the veracity of the existing psychological, sexological, and legal literature in relation to
doll ownership.
Recent Findings Strong views exist across the spectrum of potential socio-legal positions on sex doll ownership. However, there
is an almost total lack of empirical analyses of the psychological characteristics or behavioral implications of doll ownership. As
such, existing arguments appear to represent the philosophical positions of those scholars expressing them, rather than being
rooted in any objective evidence base.
Summary Despite an absence of empirical data on the characteristics and subsequent effects of doll ownership, discussions about
the ethical and legal status of doll ownership continue. This highlights a real and urgent need for a coherent research agenda to be
advanced in this area of work.
Keywords Sex dolls . Sexuality . Sex robots . Sex offending . Sexual abuse prevention
Introduction
The sale of realistic human-like dolls designed for sexual use
is a multi-million dollar global industry [1]. Newer doll
models are fully customizable, and markets are opening up
that allow for dolls to be modeled on real people, including
adult film stars [2]. Some models include artificial intelli-
gence, and the ability to feign communication with their
owners (referred to as sex robots). The emergent scale of sex
doll and robot ownership has led to increasing amounts of
academic, social, and legal attention being directed towards
this topic. The latter of these domains—the law—is increas-
ingly important with growing levels of attention being direct-
ed towards child-like sex dolls, after a number of people have
been convicted for the importation of such objects [3•, 4–6]. In
spite of this growing attention, there exists no review of the
empirical academic evidence about the motivations and ef-
fects of doll ownership. While a small number of papers and
governmental reports have been published that purport to do
this, these are typically short in length, conclude there is no
empirical evidence about doll ownership, and advocate for
restriction of doll sales and availability until evidence does
exist [3•, 7•]. In this paper, our aim is to review the key argu-
ments in relation to the motivations and effects of doll own-
ership, but go further than other papers by offering a critical
evaluation of these arguments. In doing so, we build towards
some research questions and hypotheses that we believe
should form the basis of future research into sex doll and robot
ownership.
Who Are (Potential) Sex Doll Owners?
As it currently stands, the literature around sex doll and robot
ownership appears to suggest that these objects have an over-
whelmingly sexual function [8–11]. While this may be true to
some degree, survey data suggest that purely viewing dolls
and robots of this type through a sexual lens may limit our
understanding of this phenomenon. For example, while up to
70% of sex doll owners cite sexual gratification as the primary
function of their doll, others discuss how their dolls act as a
form of friendship and companionship [1, 2]. In addition, even
among those who did suggest that sex was their doll’s primary
This article is part of the Topical Collection on Sexual Disorders
* Craig A. Harper
craigaharper19@gmail.com
1
Department of Psychology, Nottingham Trent University, 50
Shakespeare Street, Nottingham NG1 4FQ, UK
https://doi.org/10.1007/s11920-020-01177-w
Published online: 15 August 2020
Current Psychiatry Reports (2020) 22: 54
Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.
purpose, this was accompanied by other functions in more
than 80% of cases [1, 12]. In perhaps the most thorough anal-
ysis of doll owner motivations, Su and colleagues analyzed
the forum posts originating from more than 5500 threads on
the world’s largest forum for sex doll owners [13••]. This led
to a corpus of almost 80,000 posts over a timeframe of
14 years, from 2001 to 2015. Coding these posts, a range of
potential motivations emerged. In addition to purely sexual
motivations (i.e., the availability of a “willing” and available
sexual partner whenever sexual gratification is desired),
owners used the forum to discuss using their dolls’ artistic
functions (e.g., photography), as well as how they created
meaningful intimate relationships with them. It is in relation
to this latter function of dolls where they become anthropo-
morphized. At the beginning of their journey, doll owners talk
about the adoption of their new companion, with them creat-
ing identities for them through the application of realistic tat-
too transfers and makeup. Dolls are spoken about in terms that
empower them and give them a voice. According to Su and
colleagues, this provides owners with the illusion of intimacy,
which forms the basis of a close bond between them and their
dolls.
This range of relationship types between humans on the
one hand, and dolls and robots on the other, is reflected in
media representations. That is, human owners are typically
depicted as emotionally disadvantaged and their robot part-
ners take the form of a source of sexual gratification and emo-
tional intimacy [14]. While these themes are present in fiction-
al depictions of doll ownership, they are also reflected in stud-
ies of non-owners who are asked about their intentions to
obtain a sex doll or robot, or the appeal of owning such ob-
jects. For example, men scoring high on indices of otakuism
(operationalized as being shy, reserved, and having a prefer-
ence for indoor activities over outdoor pursuits) show an in-
creased behavioral intention to own a sex robot [15]. Other
work has found that a fear of rejection is associated with
enhanced ratings of robot attractiveness [16], suggesting that
interpersonal deficits may be predictive of a proclivity to en-
gage with sex dolls and robots.
There may be some individuals who become sex doll or
robot owners for medical or psychotherapeutic reasons.
According to data published by Eichenberg and colleagues,
around two-thirds of clinical staff working in the area of sex
therapy may foresee some utility of incorporating dolls into
their practice [17]. Predictions about the efficacy of dolls in
these settings differ, however, with therapists suggesting that
dolls might be more appropriate for use with people who have
sexual anxiety and erectile dysfunction than for those trying to
increase satisfaction with their living partners, or who are
struggling with problematic sexual arousal. Linked to this,
older people in care homes and those with physical and intel-
lectual disabilities who have unmet sexual needs may also
benefit from the incorporation of sex dolls and robots into
their care plans [18]. Others have suggested a role for sex dolls
in initiatives designed for the prevention of sexually transmit-
ted infections [19], highlighting the broad range of uses for
these models in healthcare and education settings.
The Alleged Implications and Effects of Doll
Ownership
An overwhelming proportion of the existing published schol-
arship on sex doll and robot ownership addresses, or at least
seeks to address, the ethics of owning and engaging with sex
dolls and robots. For example, scholars in bioethics, sociolo-
gy, robotics, and legal studies have all cited concerns that sex
dolls and robots encourage the sexual objectification of wom-
en and exacerbate traditional standards of beauty and percep-
tions of attractiveness [9, 10, 15, 20–24], with the ultimate
effect of this being a loss of human intimacy and connection
when it comes to sexual interactions [24–26]. At its extreme,
this collection of work suggests that doll and robot ownership
has the effect of promoting sexual violence and child sexual
abuse, which in much of this work is erroneously synony-
mized as pedophilia [4, 6, 27, 28]. While many of these claims
make sense at face value, their empirical bases are open to
challenge.
Emerging theoretical models of objectification suggest that
this process involves the viewing of a particular entity as a
means to an end, meaning that a defining feature of objectifi-
cation is instrumentality [22, 29–32]. In delineating the nature
of objectification, Orehek and Weaverling suggest that there is
nothing about objectification (as a psychological process) that
is inherently moral or immoral. In fact, objectification may
even be an inevitable mental process, as “to suggest that peo-
ple should not be objectified is to say that they should not be
evaluated” [29]. In this regard, the extent to which objectifi-
cation becomes dependent on some other factor(s), such as the
underpinning values of the person who is labeling something
as objectifying, or the behavioral implications of the objecti-
fying cognitions or acts. That is, if objectification (specifically
of a doll in the current context, or of women more generally as
a result of doll ownership) has no behavioral effects (e.g., an
increased proclivity for sexual aggression), then neither doll
ownership nor the resultant objectification can be considered
to be immoral.
There is a large literature on how the sexual objectification
of women predicts more permissive attitudes towards sexual
aggression [33–35]. However, it is important to stress that
there is currently no empirical evidence that doll ownership
translates into elevated levels of sexual objectification, either
of dolls as objects themselves or of real women. Indeed, ap-
plying data from media effects research in related areas would
suggest that concerns about the transferability of violence
from various forms of mass media to personal behavior might
54 Page 2 of 8 Curr Psychiatry Rep (2020) 22: 54
Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.
be misplaced. Recent analyses of the effects of playing violent
video games [36, 37] and, more relevant to the sex dolls and
robots, the viewing of pornography, suggest that engaging
with these media has little effect on behaviors in the real world
among those with no pre-existing aggressive propensities [38,
39]. More than this, the evidence for the effects of pornogra-
phy appear to show a potentially cathartic effect, where soci-
eties that have higher rates of pornography use demonstrate
lower rates of sexual violence [39, 40].
Linked to the topic of objectification is that of gendered
stereotypes about what constitutes beauty and sexual attrac-
tiveness. According to a thesis by Krizia Puig, female-like sex
dolls represent a form of synthetic hyper femininity that rein-
forces “whiteness, thinness, being cis-gender and being het-
erosexual as what is considered desirable and beautiful” [41].
While this argument self-evidently stems from the epistemo-
logical tradition of intersectional queer theory, it does high-
light the view that the physical characteristics reflect particular
features that are designed to attract male buyers. One sugges-
tion to address this issue of a reinforcement of a single beauty
standard has been to abandon the “unsophisticated” porn star
design of sex dolls and robots, and to instead create “robots
that are more realistic in their representations (both physical
and behavioral) of women, that represent men, and that per-
haps challenge the gender binary” [10].
While several authors have suggested that these features
reinforce socially constructed notions of beauty [9, 10, 25,
41], insights from evolutionary psychology tell a different
story. Gad Saad has pioneered the field of evolutionary con-
sumption, the field that applies evolutionary psychological
theory to the study of consumer behavior. He has presented
a nomological network of cumulative evidence examining the
argument for an evolved male sexual preference for women
with an hourglass body type [42]. These networks consider a
range of evidence from disciplines that appear to converge on
a consistent conclusion. In the case of an hourglass figure
preference for women among men, Saad presented evidence
that the hourglass figure confers biological cues suggestive of
youth and fertility [43, 44], resulting in a cross-cultural sexual
preference among men using a range of psychophysiological
outcomes [45–47]. In the sexual services domain, an hour-
glass figure (operationalized as a waist-to-hip ratio of approx-
imately 0.70) is consistently reported by female sex workers in
their online service advertisements [48], with a figure more
closely matching this ratio being associated with a higher fee
being charged by female escorts [49]. Specifically related to
sex dolls, adult-sized models have been reported to have an
average waist-to-hip ratio of 0.68 [50]. In light of these data,
the argument that sex dolls reinforce socially constructed
beauty ideals is challenged by the competing view that dolls
simply reflect an evolved male preference for a particular
body type, and are thus driven by market demand. In short,
customer preference drives model design, rather than vice
versa. Nonetheless, longitudinal studies investigating the ef-
fects of exposure to sex dolls on indices of objectification and
body type preferences would be a useful starting point for
exploring the relative validity of these competing hypotheses.
As already intimated, there is no research that directly ex-
amines a causal link between sex doll ownership and a pro-
clivity to engage in sexual aggression. Instead, the existing
literature hints towards these links from philosophical, ideo-
logical, and ethical positions [9, 20–22, 28, 51]. Absent this
causal evidence, some philosophical arguments have gone so
far as to consider whether sex with robots should be consid-
ered rape in-and-of itself [4, 27]. For instance, a concept piece
led by Elen Carvalho Nasciemento stated that “sex robots
exploit the female figure - eventually male, and perhaps even
children - for unilateral physical pleasure. The buyer of the
object, a humanized sex toy, possesses these bodies to do what
they want, with no need of consent” [20]. Sinziana Gutiu went
further, suggesting that the programmable nature of sex robots
allows for their owners to in essence practice the act of rape:
… the sex robot looks and feels like a real woman who
is programmed into submission and which functions as
a tool for sexual purposes. The sex robot is an ever-
consenting sexual partner and the user has full control
of the robot and the sexual interaction. By
circumventing any need for consent, sex robots elimi-
nate the need for communication, mutual respect, and
compromise in the sexual relationship. The use of sex
robots results in the dehumanization of sex and intimacy
by allowing users to physically act out rape fantasies and
confirm rape myths. [51]
Extending this line of argument still further, John Danaher
offered a tentative argument in favor of criminalizing sex ro-
bots as tools for “robotic rape and robotic child abuse” [4]. He
does this by considering the potential social effects of sex
robots (see above), before logically pulling together two pre-
mises: that morally wrongful conduct can be criminalized in
law, even when no objective harm to others is caused (the
moralistic premise), and that robotic rape and child abuse
represent morally wrongful conduct (the wrongness premise).
However, Danaher offers no coherent explanation as to why
engaging in sexual activity with a humanoid robot should
constitute “rape” or “child abuse” in its own right, or in a
specific sense.
Eskens addressed this issue more directly, concluding that
sex with robots does not constitute “rape” in the strictest legal
sense, as the normative use of this term involves a consider-
ation of consent. She concluded that robots lack moral value
(by virtue of their artificiality and lack of cognitive capacity
(see also [52, 53]), and thus cannot give (or withhold) consent,
and by extension cannot be victims. In spite of setting out
Page 3 of 8 54
Curr Psychiatry Rep (2020) 22: 54
Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.
these arguments, Eskens tempered her argument by stating
that “although it might not be impermissible to have sex with
robots for the reason that it is non-consensual, it might be
impermissible for other reasons,” invoking those ideas of ob-
jectification, desensitization, and the promotion of offense-
supportive cognitions, as described above.
Child-Like Sex Dolls, Pedophilia, and Child
Sexual Abuse
The philosopher John Danaher examined the issue of child sex
doll and robot criminalization using the perspective of legal
moralism [5]. In essence, this position posits that the immo-
rality of a particular behavior or object should be able to serve
as a basis for its restriction or criminalization, irrespective of
the objective harm (or lack thereof) that it causes other people.
Danaher draws upon the work of Strikwerda to argue that
engaging in sexual activity with a child-like sex doll or robot
encourages and normalizes a non-virtuous form of sexual ac-
tivity, owing to its ostensibly non-consensual and power-
imbalanced nature [6]. In other work, Danaher has gone so
far as to argue that owning child sex dolls and robots indicates
a lack of moral virtue in its own right [4], suggesting that one
potential consequence of ownership could be inclusion in reg-
istration processes currently reserved for individuals with sex-
ual convictions. Danaher is not alone in theorizing about
child-like dolls and robots from such a moralistic position.
In a further attempt to justify the criminalization of the
creation and distribution of child-like sex dolls and robots,
Chatterjee also acknowledged the lack of objective personal
harm caused by these materials. However, she invoked rea-
soning related to “cultural harm” to argue that “permitting a
trade in even abstract child sex dolls and robots could be seen
as sanctioning and facilitating a public atmosphere that en-
courages the portrayal of children as sexual objects, and the
acceptance and normalization of child abuse” [54]. While this
argument makes logical sense, it is telling (and reflective of
the rest of the philosophical literature on child sex dolls and
robots) that it is presented in isolation and without references
to an opposing view related to child sexual abuse prevention.
Some professionals working within forensic health services
have tentatively suggested that child-like dolls and robots
could play a role in the prevention of child sexual abuse (for
discussions, see [3•, 5, 54]). This argument suggests that dolls
and robots offer a sexual outlet without a victim that could
satiate the sexual fantasies of some individuals with sexual
interests in children. While this possibility is mentioned in
some of the philosophical papers cited above, it is quickly
dismissed with doubt, possibly due to an inherent misunder-
standing of the nature of such sexual interests within the phil-
osophical community (see [4, 5, 54, 55]) without any serious
empirical consideration of its merits taking place.
The Australian Institute of Criminology (which operates as
a branch of the Australian Government) commissioned a re-
port, authored by Rick Brown and Jane Shelling, into the
potential behavioral and legal implications of child sex doll
use [3•]. In it, the authors purported to review the available
evidence on child sex doll use and proposed recommendations
on the basis of this review. Specifically, the implications under
investigation included the following:
1. the promotion of the sexualization of children;
2. the extent to which child-like sex doll use is an indicator
of an escalation from using child sexual exploitation ma-
terial (CSEM);
3. the normalization of child sexual abuse (i.e., the causal
link between child-like sex doll use and contact sexual
offending against children); and
4. the risk that child-like sex dolls can be used as a tool for
the sexual grooming of children.
Throughout the report, Brown and Shelling identify no
empirical evidence for any of these hypotheses about the ef-
fects of child-like doll ownership. This was explicitly stated in
sections about the harmfulness of doll ownership (i.e., pro-
moting of sexual offending), while the legal moralism per-
spective of philosophical authors [4–6, 28] was invoked once
again when discussing the implications of dolls on objectifi-
cation and desensitization to themes of child sexual abuse. In a
comparatively short section of their report, they also discussed
the possibility of child-sex sex dolls playing a role in the
prevention of sexual abuse, again highlighting the dearth of
empirical data that directly tests this hypothesis. It is remark-
able, then, given this explicit lack of empirical data, that
Brown and Shelling conclude:
It is reasonable to assume that interaction with child sex
dolls could increase the likelihood of child sexual abuse
by desensitizing the doll user to the physical, emotional
and psychological harm caused by child sexual abuse
and normalizing the behavior in the mind of the abuser.
At the same time, there is no evidence of therapeutic
benefit from child sex doll use. [3•]
Most surprising here is not the assertion that it is perhaps
reasonable to assume a degree of sexual risk among some
people who own child-like sex dolls (see also [5, 6, 54, 55]).
Rather, it is more concerning, and perhaps illuminating of this
area of scholarship, that this conclusion is reached alongside
one pertaining to their lack of therapeutic benefit in light of the
total lack of evidence in either direction. This is perhaps re-
flective of the nature of the authors’ theoretical understanding
about the nature of sexual offending. That is, they cite feminist
and sociological conceptualizations of sexual offending by
arguing that this behavior is driven by primarily by a desire
54 Page 4 of 8 Curr Psychiatry Rep (2020) 22: 54
Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.
to exert dominance, power, and control, and not the achieve-
ment of sexual satisfaction [26, 56, 57]. While a detailed ex-
ploration of this argument is not specifically within the remit
of this review, we direct readers to each of the major multi-
factorial models of sexual offending used within forensic psy-
chological research and practice; all of which contain sexual
interest or arousal as a key causal component [58–63].
This approach was also taken in a review article published
by Chantal Cox-George and Susan Bewley, who sought to
provide a succinct summary of the arguments for and against
the sex robot industry and to assess the potential health impli-
cations that may affect both patient behaviors and clinicians’
professional activity [7•]. Consistent with Brown and
Shelling’s report in Australia [3•], Cox-George and Bewley
discussed the potential risks of using sex dolls and robots in
clinical settings, despite their literature search yielding no em-
pirical studies for them to review. The reasons for these au-
thors taking such a defensive position included police interest
in dolls, potential clinical prosecutions for providing illicit
materials, and the broader possibility of negative public re-
sponses to the use of dolls and robots in clinical settings.
This led Cox-George and Bewley to advise against incorpo-
rating dolls and robots into clinical practice, as this alleviates
the danger of professionals facing repercussions because of
their use.
While the widespread adoption of child-like dolls in foren-
sic and clinical settings in the absence of evidence should not
be promoted, these reviews do suggest a skewed reading of
the literature (for a commentary, see [64]). It is incumbent on
scientists, clinicians, and policy makers to maintain an open
mind on the potential for both benefits and risks until evidence
is available. We now turn our attention to what the beginnings
of a comprehensive research agenda into sex dolls and robots
might look like.
Towards an Agenda for Research
In light of the almost complete absence of empirical research
into the effects of sex dolls and robots on owner attitudes and
behaviors, we close our review with a call for research into
these crucial outcomes. Specifically, research is needed in
several domains, including the following:
1. The different motivations of sex doll and robot owners
2. The effects of sex dolls and robots on sexual cognition
and behavior (e.g., sexual fantasy and aggression)
3. Social attitudes and responses to sex dolls and robots
Considering analyses of qualitative accounts provided by
sex doll and robot owners in existing work [2, 13••], deeper
and more specific analyses of the motivations of owners for
obtaining dolls and robots should be conducted. While the
existing work provides a useful starting point, these papers
are limited by the nature of the data collected. That is,
survey-based and forum data are limited in relation to the level
of explanatory depth that can be obtained. Future studies may
look to conduct interviews with doll and robot owners. This
approach allows for a conversation to be had between the
researcher and the subject, providing the opportunity for deep
phenomenological accounts about the nuanced functions of
dolls and robots to be uncovered. This level of analysis may
also uncover new insights about the types of quantifiable var-
iables that may distinguish doll and robot owners from those
who do not own such objects.
The overwhelming conclusion that emerges from the
existing literature on sex dolls and robots is that there is an
almost total lack of empirical evidence about the psychologi-
cal and behavioral effects of owning these objects. A propen-
sity to engage in increased levels of the sexual objectification
of women, the strengthening of rigid standards of sexual at-
traction, and an increased risk of sexual offending are all cited
as potential implications of doll ownership [3•, 7•, 20, 21, 23,
28, 51]. However, while these arguments make logical sense,
their empirical validity remains untested. Research is urgently
needed to test these assertions. Initially these studies may take
the form of cross-sectional designs exploring whether levels
of sexual objectification or offending proclivity differ between
groups of sex doll owners and non-owner controls. If differ-
ences are discovered, then longitudinal studies investigating
whether doll and robot ownership is causally linked to elevat-
ed risk levels would be required. That is, non-owners who are
considering doll ownership might be followed-up in order to
explore how (or perhaps whether) they change with respect to
indices of potential sexual aggression. Irrespective of the re-
sults of cross-sectional surveys of doll and robot owners, mul-
tifactorial theories of sexual offending could play an important
role in determining the conditions under which such owner-
ship is or is not “safe.” Seto’s motivation–facilitation model,
for example, asserts that a sexual interest may lead to a psy-
chological disposition towards engaging in an offending be-
havior, but that the actual enactment of such behaviors are
facilitated (or hindered) by the presence (or absence) of facil-
itating factors, such as antisocial personality traits or depen-
dency on drugs or alcohol [63]. In applying this to the doll and
robot context, sexual offending proclivity may be predicted
via an interaction between sex doll ownership (a potentially
motivating sexual interest) and the presence (or absence) of
offense-facilitating (or offense-reducing) personality and life-
style factors.
In addition to the potential risks associated with doll and
robot ownership, research should also investigate the various
positive effects that doll ownership may yield. Controlled ac-
cess to dolls in sex and relationship counseling settings may
be a useful starting point for this, so as to explore the effec-
tiveness of dolls in alleviating sexual dysfunction. More con-
troversially, trials of child-like sex dolls may be considered in
Page 5 of 8 54
Curr Psychiatry Rep (2020) 22: 54
Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.
settings geared towards the prevention of sexual abuse among
individuals who are sexually attracted to children. Case study
evidence of this practice should be considered and evaluated
prior to larger trials of the efficacy of dolls as a cathartic sexual
outlet for minor-attracted persons. However, such trials are the
only meaningful way to address the controversies and unan-
swered questions currently posed in the literature.
As highlighted previously, sex dolls and robots have a po-
tential role to play in medical and psychotherapeutic settings
for alleviating feelings of social and emotional isolation, or in
the treatment of sexual dysfunction [11, 17]. However, at
present it is acknowledged that social responses to doll and
robot ownership may act as a blockage to such usage, even if
there was evidence of its effectiveness [7•]. There is minimal
evidence about the nature of social attitudes regarding sex doll
and robot ownership. In the data that are available, men are
typically more accepting of doll ownership and use in clinical
settings [15, 17], as are younger participants [17]. Higher
levels of religiosity have also been associated with more neg-
ative attitudes [65], which may be reflective of the view that
such objects are not a creation of God. However, there cur-
rently exists no standardized measure of attitudes towards sex
dolls and robots, as well as their owners. The development of
such a measure, potentially using inspiration from scales de-
signed to examine stigmatization of other sexual minority
groups, will enable the systematic study of such responses,
and help to identify the types of factors that alter social per-
ceptions of this topic. Such factors may include the apparent
age of the doll (adult-like vs. child-like), the function it is
designed to fulfill (e.g., sexual gratification vs. the treatment
of mental distress), or the personality traits of doll and robot
owners (e.g., levels of psychopathy vs. empathy).
Conclusions
Our aim in this review has been to chart the development of
arguments emerging within the existing literature on the mo-
tivations and effects of sex doll and sex robot ownership. We
further sought to critique these ideas in light of the dearth of
empirical research into this topic, using insights from social,
cognitive, and evolutionary psychology, as well as contempo-
rary theorizing about the etiology of sexual offending. In do-
ing so, we have highlighted how the conclusions reached by
scholars currently writing about this topic are borne out of
ideological and risk-averse starting positions, with this some-
times being explicitly acknowledged by these authors. We
have presented some initial ideas for a research program into
the motivations of sex doll and robot ownership, the behav-
ioral implications of such ownership practices, and social re-
sponses to individuals who may wish to own a sex doll or
robot. It is our hope that social scientists and legal scholars
will use these ideas to engage in more empirical research into
this increasingly contentious social issue.
Compliance with Ethical Standards
Conflict of Interest The authors declare that they have no conflict of
interest.
Human and Animal Rights and Informed Consent This article does not
contain any studies with human or animal subjects performed by any of
the authors.
Open Access This article is licensed under a Creative Commons
Attribution 4.0 International License, which permits use, sharing, adap-
tation, distribution and reproduction in any medium or format, as long as
you give appropriate credit to the original author(s) and the source, pro-
vide a link to the Creative Commons licence, and indicate if changes were
made. The images or other third party material in this article are included
in the article's Creative Commons licence, unless indicated otherwise in a
credit line to the material. If material is not included in the article's
Creative Commons licence and your intended use is not permitted by
statutory regulation or exceeds the permitted use, you will need to obtain
permission directly from the copyright holder. To view a copy of this
licence, visit http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/.
References
Papers of particular interest, published recently, have been
highlighted as:
• Of importance
•• Of major importance
1. Valverde S The modern sex doll owner: a descriptive analysis
[Master’s]. [San Luis Obispo, California]: California Polytechnic
State University; 2012. Available from: https://digitalcommons.
calpoly.edu/theses/849
2. Langcaster-James M, Bentley G. Beyond the sex doll: post-human
companionship and the rise of the ‘allodoll.’. Robotics. 2018;7(4):
62.
3.• Brown R, Shelling J. Exploring the implications of child sex dolls.
Australian Institute of Criminology; 2019. This report represents
one example of the motivated interpretation of a lack of evi-
dence about the effects of sex doll ownership, leading to prema-
ture conclusions and recommendations.
4. Danaher J. Robotic rape and robotic child sexual abuse: should they
be criminalised? Crim Law Philos. 2017;11(1):71–95.
5. Danaher J. Regulating child sex robots: restriction or experimenta-
tion? Med Law Rev. 2019;27(4):553–75.
6. Strikwerda L. Legal and moral implications of child sex robots. In:
Danaher J, McArthur N, editors. Robot sex: social and ethical im-
plications. Cambridge: MIT Press; 2017. p. 133–52.
7.• Cox-George C, Bewley S. I, sex robot: The health implications of
the sex robot industry. BMJ Sex Reprod Health. 2018;44(3):161–4
This piece represents one example of the motivated interpreta-
tion of a lack of evidence about the effects of sex doll ownership,
leading to premature conclusions and recommendations.
8. Ray P. ‘Synthetik love lasts forever’: sex dolls and the
(post?)human condition. In: Banerji D, Paranjape MR, editors.
Critical posthumanism and planetary futures [internet]. New
54 Page 6 of 8 Curr Psychiatry Rep (2020) 22: 54
Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.
Delhi: Springer India; 2016 [cited 2020 Apr 1]. p. 91–112.
Available from: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-81-322-3637-5_6.
9. Danaher J. The symbolic-consequences argument in the sex robot
debate. In: Danaher J, McArthur N, editors. Robot sex: social and
ethical implications. Cambridge: MIT Press; 2017. p. 103–32.
10. Danaher J. Building better sex robots: lessons from feminist por-
nography. In: Zhou Y, Fischer MH, editors. AI love you : develop-
ments in human-robot intimate relationships. Cham: Springer;
2019. p. 133–47.
11. Döring N, Pöschl S. Sex toys, sex dolls, sex robots: our under-
researched bed-fellows. Sexologies. 2018;27(3):e51–5.
12. Ferguson A. The sex doll: a history. McFarland & Company, Inc:
Jefferson; 2014. p. 237.
13.•• Su NM, Lazar A, Bardzell J, Bardzell S. Of dolls and men: antic-
ipating sexual intimacy with robots. ACM Trans Comput-Hum
Interact. 2019;26(3):13 This paper presents a large analysis of
the online forum posts of sex doll owners, illuminating some of
their motivations for doll ownership.
14. Döring N, Pöschl S. Love and sex with robots: a content analysis of
media representations. Int J Soc Robot. 2019;11(4):665–77.
15. Appel M, Marker C, Mara M. Otakuism and the appeal of sex
robots. Front Psychol [Internet]. 2019 [cited 2020 Mar 31];10.
Available from: https://www.frontiersin.org/articles/10.3389/
fpsyg.2019.00569/full
16. Szczuka JM, Krämer NC. Not only the lonely—how men explicitly
and implicitly evaluate the attractiveness of sex robots in compari-
son to the attractiveness of women, and personal characteristics
influencing this evaluation. Multimodal Technol Interact.
2017;1(1):3.
17. Eichenberg C, Khamis M, Hübner L. The attitudes of therapists and
physicians on the use of sex robots in sexual therapy: online survey
and interview study. J Med Internet Res [Internet]. 2019 [cited 2020
Mar 31];21(8). Available from: https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/
pmc/articles/PMC6719485/
18. Fosch-Villaronga E, Poulsen A. Sex care robots: exploring the po-
tential use of sexual robot technologies for disabled and elder care.
Paladyn J Behav Robot. 2020;11(1):1–18.
19. Morgan M. Using anatomical dolls in HIV/AIDS prevention pro-
grams. Am J Sex Educ. 2009;4(1):28–39.
20. Carvalho Nascimento EC, da Silva E, Siqueira-Batista R. The “use”
of sex robots: a bioethical issue. Asian Bioeth Rev. 2018;10(3):
231–40.
21. Richardson K. The asymmetrical “relationship”: parallels between
prostitution and the development of sex robots [Internet].
Association for Computing Machinery; 2016 [cited 2020 Mar 31].
Available from: https://doi.org/10.1145/2874239.2874281.
22. Cassidy V. For the love of doll(s): a patriarchal nightmare of cyborg
couplings. ESC Engl Stud Can. 2016;42(1):203–15.
23. Richardson K. Sex robots: the end of love. Cambridge: Polity Press;
2019.
24. Shokri N, Asl MP. Patriarchal hierarchies of power and the subor-
dination of women: real doll as a replacement of woman figure.
Adv Lang Lit Stud. 2015;6(4):216–20.
25. Ciambrone D, Phua V, Avery E. Gendered synthetic love: real dolls
and the construction of intimacy. Int Rev Mod Sociol [Internet].
2017;43(1). Available from: https://cupola.gettysburg.edu/socfac/
32
26. Facchin F, Barbara G, Cigoli V. Sex robots: the irreplaceable value
of humanity. BMJ [Internet]. 2017 [cited 2020 Mar 31];358.
Available from: https://www.bmj.com/content/358/bmj.j3790
27. Eskens R. Is sex with robots rape? J Pract Ethics. 2017;5(2):62–76.
28. Sparrow R. Robots, rape, and representation. Int J Soc Robot.
2017;9(4):465–77.
29. Orehek E, Weaverling CG. On the nature of objectification: impli-
cations of considering people as means to goals. Perspect Psychol
Sci. 2017;12(5):719–30.
30. Papadaki E(L). Sexual objectification: from Kant to contemporary
feminism. Contemp Polit Theory. 2007;6(3):330–48.
31. MacKinnon CA. Feminism unmodified: discourses on life and law.
Cambridge: Harvard University Press; 1987.
32. Nussbaum MC. Sex and social justice. New York: Oxford
University Press; 1999.
33. Gervais SJ, DiLillo D, McChargue D. Understanding the link be-
tween men’s alcohol use and sexual violence perpetration: the me-
diating role of sexual objectification. Psychol Violence. 2014;4(2):
156–69.
34. Seabrook RC, Ward LM, Giaccardi S. Less than human? Media
use, objectification of women, and men’s acceptance of sexual ag-
gression. Psychol Violence. 2019;9(5):536–45.
35. Vasquez EA, Ball L, Loughnan S, Pina A. The object of my ag-
gression: sexual objectification increases physical aggression to-
ward women. Aggress Behav. 2018;44(1):5–17.
36. Mathur MB, VanderWeele TJ. Finding common ground in meta-
analysis “wars” on violent video games. Perspect Psychol Sci.
2019;14(4):705–8.
37. Hilgard J, Engelhardt CR, Rouder JN. Overstated evidence for
short-term effects of violent games on affect and behavior: a reanal-
ysis of Anderson et al. (2010). Psychol Bull. 2017;143(7):757–74.
38. Malamuth NM, Hald GM, Koss M. Pornography, individual differ-
ences in risk and men’s acceptance of violence against women in a
representative sample. Sex Roles. 2012;66(7):427–39.
39. Fisher WA, Kohut T, Di Gioacchino LA, Fedoroff P. Pornography,
sex crime, and paraphilia. Curr Psychiatry Rep. 2013;15(6):362.
40. Ferguson CJ, Hartley RD. The pleasure is momentary…the ex-
pense damnable? The influence of pornography on rape and sexual
assault. Aggress Violent Behav. 2009;14(5):323–9.
41. Puig K The synthetic hyper femme: on sex dolls, fembots, and the
futures of sex [Master’s]. [San Diego, CA]: San Diego State
University; 2017.
42. Saad G. On the method of evolutionary psychology and its appli-
cability to consumer research. J Mark Res. 2017;54(3):464–77.
43. Lassek WD, Gaulin SJC. Evidence supporting nubility and repro-
ductive value as the key to human female physical attractiveness.
Evol Hum Behav. 2019;40(5):408–19.
44. Butovskaya M, Sorokowska A, Karwowski M, Sabiniewicz A,
Fedenok J, Dronova D, et al. Waist-to-hip ratio, body-mass index,
age and number of children in seven traditional societies. Sci Rep.
2017;7(1):1–9.
45. Dixson BJ, Grimshaw GM, Linklater WL, Dixson AF. Eye-
tracking of men’s preferences for waist-to-hip ratio and breast size
of women. Arch Sex Behav. 2011;40(1):43–50.
46. Del Zotto M, Pegna AJ. Electrophysiological evidence of perceived
sexual attractiveness for human female bodies varying in waist-to-
hip ratio. Cogn Affect Behav Neurosci. 2017;17(3):577–91.
47. Singh D, Dixson BJ, Jessop TS, Morgan B, Dixson AF. Cross-
cultural consensus for waist–hip ratio and women’s attractiveness.
Evol Hum Behav. 2010;31(3):176–81.
48. Saad G. Advertised waist-to-hip ratios of online female escorts: an
evolutionary perspective. Int J E-Collab. 2008;4(3):40–50.
49. Griffith JD, Capiola A, Balotti B, Hart CL, Turner R. Online female
escort advertisements: the cost of sex. Evol Psychol. 2016;14(2):1–
9.
50. Kock N, Hantula DA, Hayne SC, Saad G, Todd PM, Watson RT.
Introduction to Darwinian perspectives on electronic communica-
tion. IEEE Trans Prof Commun. 2008;51(2):133–46.
51. Gutiu S Sex robots and roboticization of consent. In: We Robot
Conference [Internet]. Miami, FL; 2012. Available from: http://
robots.law.miami.edu/wp-content/uploads/2012/01/Gutiu-
Roboticization_of_Consent.pdf
52. Singer P. Practical ethics. 2nd ed. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press; 1993. p. 395.
Page 7 of 8 54
Curr Psychiatry Rep (2020) 22: 54
Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.
53. Kagan S. What’s wrong with speciesism? J Appl Philos.
2016;33(1):1–21.
54. Chatterjee BB. Child sex dolls and robots: challenging the bound-
aries of the child protection framework. Int Rev Law Comput
Technol. 2020;34(1):22–43.
55. Maras M-H, Shapiro LR. Child sex dolls and robots: more than just
an uncanny valley. J Internet Law. 2017;21(5):3–21.
56. Brownmiller S. Against our will: men, women, and rape. New
York: Bantam Books; 1975.
57. Powell A, Henry N. Sexual violence: a feminist criminological
analysis. In: Powell A, Henry N, editors. Sexual violence in a digital
age. London: Palgrave Macmillan; 2017. p. 23–47. (Palgrave
Studies in Cybercrime and Cybersecurity).
58. Finkelhor D. Child sexual abuse: new theory and research. New
York: Free Press; 1984.
59. Marshall WL, Barbaree HE. An integrated theory of the etiology of
sexual offending. In: Marshall WL, Laws DR, Barbaree HE, edi-
tors. Handbook of sexual assault. Boston: Springer; 1990. p. 257–
75.
60. Hall GCN, Hirschman R. Toward a theory of sexual aggression: a
quadripartite model. J Consult Clin Psychol. 1991;59(5):662–9.
61. Ward T, Siegert RJ. Toward a comprehensive theory of child sexual
abuse: a theory knitting perspective. Psychol Crime Law.
2002;8(4):319–51.
62. Ward T, Beech A. An integrated theory of sexual offending.
Aggress Violent Behav. 2006;11(1):44–63.
63. Seto MC. The motivation-facilitation model of sexual offending.
Sex Abus. 2019;31(1):3–24.
64. Eggleton J. Comment on “I, sex robot: the health implications of the
sex robot industry”. BMJ Sex Reprod Health. 2019;45(1):78–9.
65. Knox D, Huff S, Chang IJ. Sex dolls—creepy or healthy? Attitudes
of undergraduates. J Posit Sex. 2017;3(2):32–7.
Publisher’s Note Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdic-
tional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.
54 Page 8 of 8 Curr Psychiatry Rep (2020) 22: 54
Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.
1.
2.
3.
4.
5.
6.
Terms and Conditions
Springer Nature journal content, brought to you courtesy of Springer Nature Customer Service Center GmbH (“Springer Nature”).
Springer Nature supports a reasonable amount of sharing of research papers by authors, subscribers and authorised users (“Users”), for small-
scale personal, non-commercial use provided that all copyright, trade and service marks and other proprietary notices are maintained. By
accessing, sharing, receiving or otherwise using the Springer Nature journal content you agree to these terms of use (“Terms”). For these
purposes, Springer Nature considers academic use (by researchers and students) to be non-commercial.
These Terms are supplementary and will apply in addition to any applicable website terms and conditions, a relevant site licence or a personal
subscription. These Terms will prevail over any conflict or ambiguity with regards to the relevant terms, a site licence or a personal subscription
(to the extent of the conflict or ambiguity only). For Creative Commons-licensed articles, the terms of the Creative Commons license used will
apply.
We collect and use personal data to provide access to the Springer Nature journal content. We may also use these personal data internally within
ResearchGate and Springer Nature and as agreed share it, in an anonymised way, for purposes of tracking, analysis and reporting. We will not
otherwise disclose your personal data outside the ResearchGate or the Springer Nature group of companies unless we have your permission as
detailed in the Privacy Policy.
While Users may use the Springer Nature journal content for small scale, personal non-commercial use, it is important to note that Users may
not:
use such content for the purpose of providing other users with access on a regular or large scale basis or as a means to circumvent access
control;
use such content where to do so would be considered a criminal or statutory offence in any jurisdiction, or gives rise to civil liability, or is
otherwise unlawful;
falsely or misleadingly imply or suggest endorsement, approval , sponsorship, or association unless explicitly agreed to by Springer Nature in
writing;
use bots or other automated methods to access the content or redirect messages
override any security feature or exclusionary protocol; or
share the content in order to create substitute for Springer Nature products or services or a systematic database of Springer Nature journal
content.
In line with the restriction against commercial use, Springer Nature does not permit the creation of a product or service that creates revenue,
royalties, rent or income from our content or its inclusion as part of a paid for service or for other commercial gain. Springer Nature journal
content cannot be used for inter-library loans and librarians may not upload Springer Nature journal content on a large scale into their, or any
other, institutional repository.
These terms of use are reviewed regularly and may be amended at any time. Springer Nature is not obligated to publish any information or
content on this website and may remove it or features or functionality at our sole discretion, at any time with or without notice. Springer Nature
may revoke this licence to you at any time and remove access to any copies of the Springer Nature journal content which have been saved.
To the fullest extent permitted by law, Springer Nature makes no warranties, representations or guarantees to Users, either express or implied
with respect to the Springer nature journal content and all parties disclaim and waive any implied warranties or warranties imposed by law,
including merchantability or fitness for any particular purpose.
Please note that these rights do not automatically extend to content, data or other material published by Springer Nature that may be licensed
from third parties.
If you would like to use or distribute our Springer Nature journal content to a wider audience or on a regular basis or in any other manner not
expressly permitted by these Terms, please contact Springer Nature at
onlineservice@springernature.com

More Related Content

Similar to Sex doll ownership_an_agenda_for_research

social construction of gender
social construction of gendersocial construction of gender
social construction of gender
sumbl khanday
 
Essay On Violence In Schools.pdf
Essay On Violence In Schools.pdfEssay On Violence In Schools.pdf
Essay On Violence In Schools.pdf
Jessica Spyrakis
 
While this weeks topic highlighted the uncertainty of Big Data, th.docx
While this weeks topic highlighted the uncertainty of Big Data, th.docxWhile this weeks topic highlighted the uncertainty of Big Data, th.docx
While this weeks topic highlighted the uncertainty of Big Data, th.docx
harold7fisher61282
 
- Government InvolvementBioethics Environmental Ethics.docx
- Government InvolvementBioethics Environmental Ethics.docx- Government InvolvementBioethics Environmental Ethics.docx
- Government InvolvementBioethics Environmental Ethics.docx
honey725342
 
Essay About Violent Video Games. Videogames and violence essay. Essay about V...
Essay About Violent Video Games. Videogames and violence essay. Essay about V...Essay About Violent Video Games. Videogames and violence essay. Essay about V...
Essay About Violent Video Games. Videogames and violence essay. Essay about V...
Erin Anderson
 
The Impact Of Social Identity On Education
The Impact Of Social Identity On EducationThe Impact Of Social Identity On Education
The Impact Of Social Identity On Education
Lindsey Campbell
 
Digification (1)
Digification (1)Digification (1)
Digification (1)
KseniiaNazarova
 
Essays For Money. Essay on money - Its uses and abuses
Essays For Money. Essay on money - Its uses and abusesEssays For Money. Essay on money - Its uses and abuses
Essays For Money. Essay on money - Its uses and abuses
Melissa Chastain
 
Gender identity
Gender identityGender identity
Gender identity
Luciano Souza
 
Urban Schools Vs Chicago Essay
Urban Schools Vs Chicago EssayUrban Schools Vs Chicago Essay
Urban Schools Vs Chicago Essay
Karen Oliver
 
Dear Santa Letter In Blank Letter Writing Template Fo
Dear Santa Letter In Blank Letter Writing Template FoDear Santa Letter In Blank Letter Writing Template Fo
Dear Santa Letter In Blank Letter Writing Template Fo
Jessica Adams
 
Sociology Essay Ideas
Sociology Essay IdeasSociology Essay Ideas
Sociology Essay Ideas
Best Online Paper Writing Service
 
Sociology Essays Topics
Sociology Essays TopicsSociology Essays Topics
Gay Marriage Essay Thesis. How to Write a Gay Marriage Essay: Persuasive Essa...
Gay Marriage Essay Thesis. How to Write a Gay Marriage Essay: Persuasive Essa...Gay Marriage Essay Thesis. How to Write a Gay Marriage Essay: Persuasive Essa...
Gay Marriage Essay Thesis. How to Write a Gay Marriage Essay: Persuasive Essa...
Sara Roberts
 
Why Become A Teacher Essay.pdf
Why Become A Teacher Essay.pdfWhy Become A Teacher Essay.pdf
Why Become A Teacher Essay.pdf
Christine Love
 
SOC-481Action Research Project ProposalAssignment.docx
SOC-481Action Research Project ProposalAssignment.docxSOC-481Action Research Project ProposalAssignment.docx
SOC-481Action Research Project ProposalAssignment.docx
pbilly1
 

Similar to Sex doll ownership_an_agenda_for_research (16)

social construction of gender
social construction of gendersocial construction of gender
social construction of gender
 
Essay On Violence In Schools.pdf
Essay On Violence In Schools.pdfEssay On Violence In Schools.pdf
Essay On Violence In Schools.pdf
 
While this weeks topic highlighted the uncertainty of Big Data, th.docx
While this weeks topic highlighted the uncertainty of Big Data, th.docxWhile this weeks topic highlighted the uncertainty of Big Data, th.docx
While this weeks topic highlighted the uncertainty of Big Data, th.docx
 
- Government InvolvementBioethics Environmental Ethics.docx
- Government InvolvementBioethics Environmental Ethics.docx- Government InvolvementBioethics Environmental Ethics.docx
- Government InvolvementBioethics Environmental Ethics.docx
 
Essay About Violent Video Games. Videogames and violence essay. Essay about V...
Essay About Violent Video Games. Videogames and violence essay. Essay about V...Essay About Violent Video Games. Videogames and violence essay. Essay about V...
Essay About Violent Video Games. Videogames and violence essay. Essay about V...
 
The Impact Of Social Identity On Education
The Impact Of Social Identity On EducationThe Impact Of Social Identity On Education
The Impact Of Social Identity On Education
 
Digification (1)
Digification (1)Digification (1)
Digification (1)
 
Essays For Money. Essay on money - Its uses and abuses
Essays For Money. Essay on money - Its uses and abusesEssays For Money. Essay on money - Its uses and abuses
Essays For Money. Essay on money - Its uses and abuses
 
Gender identity
Gender identityGender identity
Gender identity
 
Urban Schools Vs Chicago Essay
Urban Schools Vs Chicago EssayUrban Schools Vs Chicago Essay
Urban Schools Vs Chicago Essay
 
Dear Santa Letter In Blank Letter Writing Template Fo
Dear Santa Letter In Blank Letter Writing Template FoDear Santa Letter In Blank Letter Writing Template Fo
Dear Santa Letter In Blank Letter Writing Template Fo
 
Sociology Essay Ideas
Sociology Essay IdeasSociology Essay Ideas
Sociology Essay Ideas
 
Sociology Essays Topics
Sociology Essays TopicsSociology Essays Topics
Sociology Essays Topics
 
Gay Marriage Essay Thesis. How to Write a Gay Marriage Essay: Persuasive Essa...
Gay Marriage Essay Thesis. How to Write a Gay Marriage Essay: Persuasive Essa...Gay Marriage Essay Thesis. How to Write a Gay Marriage Essay: Persuasive Essa...
Gay Marriage Essay Thesis. How to Write a Gay Marriage Essay: Persuasive Essa...
 
Why Become A Teacher Essay.pdf
Why Become A Teacher Essay.pdfWhy Become A Teacher Essay.pdf
Why Become A Teacher Essay.pdf
 
SOC-481Action Research Project ProposalAssignment.docx
SOC-481Action Research Project ProposalAssignment.docxSOC-481Action Research Project ProposalAssignment.docx
SOC-481Action Research Project ProposalAssignment.docx
 

Recently uploaded

DECODING THE RISKS - ALCOHOL, TOBACCO & DRUGS.pdf
DECODING THE RISKS - ALCOHOL, TOBACCO & DRUGS.pdfDECODING THE RISKS - ALCOHOL, TOBACCO & DRUGS.pdf
DECODING THE RISKS - ALCOHOL, TOBACCO & DRUGS.pdf
Dr Rachana Gujar
 
DRAFT Ventilator Rapid Reference version 2.4.pdf
DRAFT Ventilator Rapid Reference  version  2.4.pdfDRAFT Ventilator Rapid Reference  version  2.4.pdf
DRAFT Ventilator Rapid Reference version 2.4.pdf
Robert Cole
 
Bath patient Fundamental of Nursing.pptx
Bath patient Fundamental of Nursing.pptxBath patient Fundamental of Nursing.pptx
Bath patient Fundamental of Nursing.pptx
MianProductions
 
Can coffee help me lose weight? Yes, 25,422 users in the USA use it for that ...
Can coffee help me lose weight? Yes, 25,422 users in the USA use it for that ...Can coffee help me lose weight? Yes, 25,422 users in the USA use it for that ...
Can coffee help me lose weight? Yes, 25,422 users in the USA use it for that ...
nirahealhty
 
Top Rated Massage Center In Ajman Chandrima Spa
Top Rated Massage Center In Ajman Chandrima SpaTop Rated Massage Center In Ajman Chandrima Spa
Top Rated Massage Center In Ajman Chandrima Spa
Chandrima Spa Ajman
 
Gemma Wean- Nutritional solution for Artemia
Gemma Wean- Nutritional solution for ArtemiaGemma Wean- Nutritional solution for Artemia
Gemma Wean- Nutritional solution for Artemia
smuskaan0008
 
Hypotension and role of physiotherapy in it
Hypotension and role of physiotherapy in itHypotension and role of physiotherapy in it
Hypotension and role of physiotherapy in it
Vishal kr Thakur
 
R3 Stem Cell Therapy: A New Hope for Women with Ovarian Failure
R3 Stem Cell Therapy: A New Hope for Women with Ovarian FailureR3 Stem Cell Therapy: A New Hope for Women with Ovarian Failure
R3 Stem Cell Therapy: A New Hope for Women with Ovarian Failure
R3 Stem Cell
 
Champions of Health Spotlight On Leaders Shaping Germany's Healthcare.pdf
Champions of Health Spotlight On Leaders Shaping Germany's Healthcare.pdfChampions of Health Spotlight On Leaders Shaping Germany's Healthcare.pdf
Champions of Health Spotlight On Leaders Shaping Germany's Healthcare.pdf
eurohealthleaders
 
U Part Wigs_ A Natural Look with Minimal Effort Jokerwigs.in.pdf
U Part Wigs_ A Natural Look with Minimal Effort Jokerwigs.in.pdfU Part Wigs_ A Natural Look with Minimal Effort Jokerwigs.in.pdf
U Part Wigs_ A Natural Look with Minimal Effort Jokerwigs.in.pdf
Jokerwigs arts and craft
 
Hypertension and it's role of physiotherapy in it.
Hypertension and it's role of physiotherapy in it.Hypertension and it's role of physiotherapy in it.
Hypertension and it's role of physiotherapy in it.
Vishal kr Thakur
 
Michigan HealthTech Market Map 2024 with Policy Makers, Academic Innovation C...
Michigan HealthTech Market Map 2024 with Policy Makers, Academic Innovation C...Michigan HealthTech Market Map 2024 with Policy Makers, Academic Innovation C...
Michigan HealthTech Market Map 2024 with Policy Makers, Academic Innovation C...
Levi Shapiro
 
Professional Secrecy: Forensic Medicine Lecture
Professional Secrecy: Forensic Medicine LectureProfessional Secrecy: Forensic Medicine Lecture
Professional Secrecy: Forensic Medicine Lecture
DIVYANSHU740006
 
NEEDLE STICK INJURY - JOURNAL CLUB PRESENTATION - DR SHAMIN EABENSON
NEEDLE STICK INJURY - JOURNAL CLUB PRESENTATION - DR SHAMIN EABENSONNEEDLE STICK INJURY - JOURNAL CLUB PRESENTATION - DR SHAMIN EABENSON
NEEDLE STICK INJURY - JOURNAL CLUB PRESENTATION - DR SHAMIN EABENSON
SHAMIN EABENSON
 
TEST BANK FOR Health Assessment in Nursing 7th Edition by Weber Chapters 1 - ...
TEST BANK FOR Health Assessment in Nursing 7th Edition by Weber Chapters 1 - ...TEST BANK FOR Health Assessment in Nursing 7th Edition by Weber Chapters 1 - ...
TEST BANK FOR Health Assessment in Nursing 7th Edition by Weber Chapters 1 - ...
rightmanforbloodline
 
Exploring the Benefits of Binaural Hearing: Why Two Hearing Aids Are Better T...
Exploring the Benefits of Binaural Hearing: Why Two Hearing Aids Are Better T...Exploring the Benefits of Binaural Hearing: Why Two Hearing Aids Are Better T...
Exploring the Benefits of Binaural Hearing: Why Two Hearing Aids Are Better T...
Ear Solutions (ESPL)
 
CCSN_June_06 2024_jones. Cancer Rehabpptx
CCSN_June_06 2024_jones. Cancer RehabpptxCCSN_June_06 2024_jones. Cancer Rehabpptx
CCSN_June_06 2024_jones. Cancer Rehabpptx
Canadian Cancer Survivor Network
 
Comprehensive Rainy Season Advisory: Safety and Preparedness Tips.pdf
Comprehensive Rainy Season Advisory: Safety and Preparedness Tips.pdfComprehensive Rainy Season Advisory: Safety and Preparedness Tips.pdf
Comprehensive Rainy Season Advisory: Safety and Preparedness Tips.pdf
Dr Rachana Gujar
 
Unlocking the Secrets to Safe Patient Handling.pdf
Unlocking the Secrets to Safe Patient Handling.pdfUnlocking the Secrets to Safe Patient Handling.pdf
Unlocking the Secrets to Safe Patient Handling.pdf
Lift Ability
 
CANSA support - Caring for Cancer Patients' Caregivers
CANSA support - Caring for Cancer Patients' CaregiversCANSA support - Caring for Cancer Patients' Caregivers
CANSA support - Caring for Cancer Patients' Caregivers
CANSA The Cancer Association of South Africa
 

Recently uploaded (20)

DECODING THE RISKS - ALCOHOL, TOBACCO & DRUGS.pdf
DECODING THE RISKS - ALCOHOL, TOBACCO & DRUGS.pdfDECODING THE RISKS - ALCOHOL, TOBACCO & DRUGS.pdf
DECODING THE RISKS - ALCOHOL, TOBACCO & DRUGS.pdf
 
DRAFT Ventilator Rapid Reference version 2.4.pdf
DRAFT Ventilator Rapid Reference  version  2.4.pdfDRAFT Ventilator Rapid Reference  version  2.4.pdf
DRAFT Ventilator Rapid Reference version 2.4.pdf
 
Bath patient Fundamental of Nursing.pptx
Bath patient Fundamental of Nursing.pptxBath patient Fundamental of Nursing.pptx
Bath patient Fundamental of Nursing.pptx
 
Can coffee help me lose weight? Yes, 25,422 users in the USA use it for that ...
Can coffee help me lose weight? Yes, 25,422 users in the USA use it for that ...Can coffee help me lose weight? Yes, 25,422 users in the USA use it for that ...
Can coffee help me lose weight? Yes, 25,422 users in the USA use it for that ...
 
Top Rated Massage Center In Ajman Chandrima Spa
Top Rated Massage Center In Ajman Chandrima SpaTop Rated Massage Center In Ajman Chandrima Spa
Top Rated Massage Center In Ajman Chandrima Spa
 
Gemma Wean- Nutritional solution for Artemia
Gemma Wean- Nutritional solution for ArtemiaGemma Wean- Nutritional solution for Artemia
Gemma Wean- Nutritional solution for Artemia
 
Hypotension and role of physiotherapy in it
Hypotension and role of physiotherapy in itHypotension and role of physiotherapy in it
Hypotension and role of physiotherapy in it
 
R3 Stem Cell Therapy: A New Hope for Women with Ovarian Failure
R3 Stem Cell Therapy: A New Hope for Women with Ovarian FailureR3 Stem Cell Therapy: A New Hope for Women with Ovarian Failure
R3 Stem Cell Therapy: A New Hope for Women with Ovarian Failure
 
Champions of Health Spotlight On Leaders Shaping Germany's Healthcare.pdf
Champions of Health Spotlight On Leaders Shaping Germany's Healthcare.pdfChampions of Health Spotlight On Leaders Shaping Germany's Healthcare.pdf
Champions of Health Spotlight On Leaders Shaping Germany's Healthcare.pdf
 
U Part Wigs_ A Natural Look with Minimal Effort Jokerwigs.in.pdf
U Part Wigs_ A Natural Look with Minimal Effort Jokerwigs.in.pdfU Part Wigs_ A Natural Look with Minimal Effort Jokerwigs.in.pdf
U Part Wigs_ A Natural Look with Minimal Effort Jokerwigs.in.pdf
 
Hypertension and it's role of physiotherapy in it.
Hypertension and it's role of physiotherapy in it.Hypertension and it's role of physiotherapy in it.
Hypertension and it's role of physiotherapy in it.
 
Michigan HealthTech Market Map 2024 with Policy Makers, Academic Innovation C...
Michigan HealthTech Market Map 2024 with Policy Makers, Academic Innovation C...Michigan HealthTech Market Map 2024 with Policy Makers, Academic Innovation C...
Michigan HealthTech Market Map 2024 with Policy Makers, Academic Innovation C...
 
Professional Secrecy: Forensic Medicine Lecture
Professional Secrecy: Forensic Medicine LectureProfessional Secrecy: Forensic Medicine Lecture
Professional Secrecy: Forensic Medicine Lecture
 
NEEDLE STICK INJURY - JOURNAL CLUB PRESENTATION - DR SHAMIN EABENSON
NEEDLE STICK INJURY - JOURNAL CLUB PRESENTATION - DR SHAMIN EABENSONNEEDLE STICK INJURY - JOURNAL CLUB PRESENTATION - DR SHAMIN EABENSON
NEEDLE STICK INJURY - JOURNAL CLUB PRESENTATION - DR SHAMIN EABENSON
 
TEST BANK FOR Health Assessment in Nursing 7th Edition by Weber Chapters 1 - ...
TEST BANK FOR Health Assessment in Nursing 7th Edition by Weber Chapters 1 - ...TEST BANK FOR Health Assessment in Nursing 7th Edition by Weber Chapters 1 - ...
TEST BANK FOR Health Assessment in Nursing 7th Edition by Weber Chapters 1 - ...
 
Exploring the Benefits of Binaural Hearing: Why Two Hearing Aids Are Better T...
Exploring the Benefits of Binaural Hearing: Why Two Hearing Aids Are Better T...Exploring the Benefits of Binaural Hearing: Why Two Hearing Aids Are Better T...
Exploring the Benefits of Binaural Hearing: Why Two Hearing Aids Are Better T...
 
CCSN_June_06 2024_jones. Cancer Rehabpptx
CCSN_June_06 2024_jones. Cancer RehabpptxCCSN_June_06 2024_jones. Cancer Rehabpptx
CCSN_June_06 2024_jones. Cancer Rehabpptx
 
Comprehensive Rainy Season Advisory: Safety and Preparedness Tips.pdf
Comprehensive Rainy Season Advisory: Safety and Preparedness Tips.pdfComprehensive Rainy Season Advisory: Safety and Preparedness Tips.pdf
Comprehensive Rainy Season Advisory: Safety and Preparedness Tips.pdf
 
Unlocking the Secrets to Safe Patient Handling.pdf
Unlocking the Secrets to Safe Patient Handling.pdfUnlocking the Secrets to Safe Patient Handling.pdf
Unlocking the Secrets to Safe Patient Handling.pdf
 
CANSA support - Caring for Cancer Patients' Caregivers
CANSA support - Caring for Cancer Patients' CaregiversCANSA support - Caring for Cancer Patients' Caregivers
CANSA support - Caring for Cancer Patients' Caregivers
 

Sex doll ownership_an_agenda_for_research

  • 1. SEXUAL DISORDERS (LE MARSHALL AND H MOULDEN, SECTION EDITORS) Sex Doll Ownership: An Agenda for Research Craig A. Harper1 & Rebecca Lievesley1 # The Author(s) 2020 Abstract Purpose of Review The topic of sex doll ownership is becoming an increasingly discussed issue from both a social and legal perspective. This review aims to examine the veracity of the existing psychological, sexological, and legal literature in relation to doll ownership. Recent Findings Strong views exist across the spectrum of potential socio-legal positions on sex doll ownership. However, there is an almost total lack of empirical analyses of the psychological characteristics or behavioral implications of doll ownership. As such, existing arguments appear to represent the philosophical positions of those scholars expressing them, rather than being rooted in any objective evidence base. Summary Despite an absence of empirical data on the characteristics and subsequent effects of doll ownership, discussions about the ethical and legal status of doll ownership continue. This highlights a real and urgent need for a coherent research agenda to be advanced in this area of work. Keywords Sex dolls . Sexuality . Sex robots . Sex offending . Sexual abuse prevention Introduction The sale of realistic human-like dolls designed for sexual use is a multi-million dollar global industry [1]. Newer doll models are fully customizable, and markets are opening up that allow for dolls to be modeled on real people, including adult film stars [2]. Some models include artificial intelli- gence, and the ability to feign communication with their owners (referred to as sex robots). The emergent scale of sex doll and robot ownership has led to increasing amounts of academic, social, and legal attention being directed towards this topic. The latter of these domains—the law—is increas- ingly important with growing levels of attention being direct- ed towards child-like sex dolls, after a number of people have been convicted for the importation of such objects [3•, 4–6]. In spite of this growing attention, there exists no review of the empirical academic evidence about the motivations and ef- fects of doll ownership. While a small number of papers and governmental reports have been published that purport to do this, these are typically short in length, conclude there is no empirical evidence about doll ownership, and advocate for restriction of doll sales and availability until evidence does exist [3•, 7•]. In this paper, our aim is to review the key argu- ments in relation to the motivations and effects of doll own- ership, but go further than other papers by offering a critical evaluation of these arguments. In doing so, we build towards some research questions and hypotheses that we believe should form the basis of future research into sex doll and robot ownership. Who Are (Potential) Sex Doll Owners? As it currently stands, the literature around sex doll and robot ownership appears to suggest that these objects have an over- whelmingly sexual function [8–11]. While this may be true to some degree, survey data suggest that purely viewing dolls and robots of this type through a sexual lens may limit our understanding of this phenomenon. For example, while up to 70% of sex doll owners cite sexual gratification as the primary function of their doll, others discuss how their dolls act as a form of friendship and companionship [1, 2]. In addition, even among those who did suggest that sex was their doll’s primary This article is part of the Topical Collection on Sexual Disorders * Craig A. Harper craigaharper19@gmail.com 1 Department of Psychology, Nottingham Trent University, 50 Shakespeare Street, Nottingham NG1 4FQ, UK https://doi.org/10.1007/s11920-020-01177-w Published online: 15 August 2020 Current Psychiatry Reports (2020) 22: 54 Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.
  • 2. purpose, this was accompanied by other functions in more than 80% of cases [1, 12]. In perhaps the most thorough anal- ysis of doll owner motivations, Su and colleagues analyzed the forum posts originating from more than 5500 threads on the world’s largest forum for sex doll owners [13••]. This led to a corpus of almost 80,000 posts over a timeframe of 14 years, from 2001 to 2015. Coding these posts, a range of potential motivations emerged. In addition to purely sexual motivations (i.e., the availability of a “willing” and available sexual partner whenever sexual gratification is desired), owners used the forum to discuss using their dolls’ artistic functions (e.g., photography), as well as how they created meaningful intimate relationships with them. It is in relation to this latter function of dolls where they become anthropo- morphized. At the beginning of their journey, doll owners talk about the adoption of their new companion, with them creat- ing identities for them through the application of realistic tat- too transfers and makeup. Dolls are spoken about in terms that empower them and give them a voice. According to Su and colleagues, this provides owners with the illusion of intimacy, which forms the basis of a close bond between them and their dolls. This range of relationship types between humans on the one hand, and dolls and robots on the other, is reflected in media representations. That is, human owners are typically depicted as emotionally disadvantaged and their robot part- ners take the form of a source of sexual gratification and emo- tional intimacy [14]. While these themes are present in fiction- al depictions of doll ownership, they are also reflected in stud- ies of non-owners who are asked about their intentions to obtain a sex doll or robot, or the appeal of owning such ob- jects. For example, men scoring high on indices of otakuism (operationalized as being shy, reserved, and having a prefer- ence for indoor activities over outdoor pursuits) show an in- creased behavioral intention to own a sex robot [15]. Other work has found that a fear of rejection is associated with enhanced ratings of robot attractiveness [16], suggesting that interpersonal deficits may be predictive of a proclivity to en- gage with sex dolls and robots. There may be some individuals who become sex doll or robot owners for medical or psychotherapeutic reasons. According to data published by Eichenberg and colleagues, around two-thirds of clinical staff working in the area of sex therapy may foresee some utility of incorporating dolls into their practice [17]. Predictions about the efficacy of dolls in these settings differ, however, with therapists suggesting that dolls might be more appropriate for use with people who have sexual anxiety and erectile dysfunction than for those trying to increase satisfaction with their living partners, or who are struggling with problematic sexual arousal. Linked to this, older people in care homes and those with physical and intel- lectual disabilities who have unmet sexual needs may also benefit from the incorporation of sex dolls and robots into their care plans [18]. Others have suggested a role for sex dolls in initiatives designed for the prevention of sexually transmit- ted infections [19], highlighting the broad range of uses for these models in healthcare and education settings. The Alleged Implications and Effects of Doll Ownership An overwhelming proportion of the existing published schol- arship on sex doll and robot ownership addresses, or at least seeks to address, the ethics of owning and engaging with sex dolls and robots. For example, scholars in bioethics, sociolo- gy, robotics, and legal studies have all cited concerns that sex dolls and robots encourage the sexual objectification of wom- en and exacerbate traditional standards of beauty and percep- tions of attractiveness [9, 10, 15, 20–24], with the ultimate effect of this being a loss of human intimacy and connection when it comes to sexual interactions [24–26]. At its extreme, this collection of work suggests that doll and robot ownership has the effect of promoting sexual violence and child sexual abuse, which in much of this work is erroneously synony- mized as pedophilia [4, 6, 27, 28]. While many of these claims make sense at face value, their empirical bases are open to challenge. Emerging theoretical models of objectification suggest that this process involves the viewing of a particular entity as a means to an end, meaning that a defining feature of objectifi- cation is instrumentality [22, 29–32]. In delineating the nature of objectification, Orehek and Weaverling suggest that there is nothing about objectification (as a psychological process) that is inherently moral or immoral. In fact, objectification may even be an inevitable mental process, as “to suggest that peo- ple should not be objectified is to say that they should not be evaluated” [29]. In this regard, the extent to which objectifi- cation becomes dependent on some other factor(s), such as the underpinning values of the person who is labeling something as objectifying, or the behavioral implications of the objecti- fying cognitions or acts. That is, if objectification (specifically of a doll in the current context, or of women more generally as a result of doll ownership) has no behavioral effects (e.g., an increased proclivity for sexual aggression), then neither doll ownership nor the resultant objectification can be considered to be immoral. There is a large literature on how the sexual objectification of women predicts more permissive attitudes towards sexual aggression [33–35]. However, it is important to stress that there is currently no empirical evidence that doll ownership translates into elevated levels of sexual objectification, either of dolls as objects themselves or of real women. Indeed, ap- plying data from media effects research in related areas would suggest that concerns about the transferability of violence from various forms of mass media to personal behavior might 54 Page 2 of 8 Curr Psychiatry Rep (2020) 22: 54 Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.
  • 3. be misplaced. Recent analyses of the effects of playing violent video games [36, 37] and, more relevant to the sex dolls and robots, the viewing of pornography, suggest that engaging with these media has little effect on behaviors in the real world among those with no pre-existing aggressive propensities [38, 39]. More than this, the evidence for the effects of pornogra- phy appear to show a potentially cathartic effect, where soci- eties that have higher rates of pornography use demonstrate lower rates of sexual violence [39, 40]. Linked to the topic of objectification is that of gendered stereotypes about what constitutes beauty and sexual attrac- tiveness. According to a thesis by Krizia Puig, female-like sex dolls represent a form of synthetic hyper femininity that rein- forces “whiteness, thinness, being cis-gender and being het- erosexual as what is considered desirable and beautiful” [41]. While this argument self-evidently stems from the epistemo- logical tradition of intersectional queer theory, it does high- light the view that the physical characteristics reflect particular features that are designed to attract male buyers. One sugges- tion to address this issue of a reinforcement of a single beauty standard has been to abandon the “unsophisticated” porn star design of sex dolls and robots, and to instead create “robots that are more realistic in their representations (both physical and behavioral) of women, that represent men, and that per- haps challenge the gender binary” [10]. While several authors have suggested that these features reinforce socially constructed notions of beauty [9, 10, 25, 41], insights from evolutionary psychology tell a different story. Gad Saad has pioneered the field of evolutionary con- sumption, the field that applies evolutionary psychological theory to the study of consumer behavior. He has presented a nomological network of cumulative evidence examining the argument for an evolved male sexual preference for women with an hourglass body type [42]. These networks consider a range of evidence from disciplines that appear to converge on a consistent conclusion. In the case of an hourglass figure preference for women among men, Saad presented evidence that the hourglass figure confers biological cues suggestive of youth and fertility [43, 44], resulting in a cross-cultural sexual preference among men using a range of psychophysiological outcomes [45–47]. In the sexual services domain, an hour- glass figure (operationalized as a waist-to-hip ratio of approx- imately 0.70) is consistently reported by female sex workers in their online service advertisements [48], with a figure more closely matching this ratio being associated with a higher fee being charged by female escorts [49]. Specifically related to sex dolls, adult-sized models have been reported to have an average waist-to-hip ratio of 0.68 [50]. In light of these data, the argument that sex dolls reinforce socially constructed beauty ideals is challenged by the competing view that dolls simply reflect an evolved male preference for a particular body type, and are thus driven by market demand. In short, customer preference drives model design, rather than vice versa. Nonetheless, longitudinal studies investigating the ef- fects of exposure to sex dolls on indices of objectification and body type preferences would be a useful starting point for exploring the relative validity of these competing hypotheses. As already intimated, there is no research that directly ex- amines a causal link between sex doll ownership and a pro- clivity to engage in sexual aggression. Instead, the existing literature hints towards these links from philosophical, ideo- logical, and ethical positions [9, 20–22, 28, 51]. Absent this causal evidence, some philosophical arguments have gone so far as to consider whether sex with robots should be consid- ered rape in-and-of itself [4, 27]. For instance, a concept piece led by Elen Carvalho Nasciemento stated that “sex robots exploit the female figure - eventually male, and perhaps even children - for unilateral physical pleasure. The buyer of the object, a humanized sex toy, possesses these bodies to do what they want, with no need of consent” [20]. Sinziana Gutiu went further, suggesting that the programmable nature of sex robots allows for their owners to in essence practice the act of rape: … the sex robot looks and feels like a real woman who is programmed into submission and which functions as a tool for sexual purposes. The sex robot is an ever- consenting sexual partner and the user has full control of the robot and the sexual interaction. By circumventing any need for consent, sex robots elimi- nate the need for communication, mutual respect, and compromise in the sexual relationship. The use of sex robots results in the dehumanization of sex and intimacy by allowing users to physically act out rape fantasies and confirm rape myths. [51] Extending this line of argument still further, John Danaher offered a tentative argument in favor of criminalizing sex ro- bots as tools for “robotic rape and robotic child abuse” [4]. He does this by considering the potential social effects of sex robots (see above), before logically pulling together two pre- mises: that morally wrongful conduct can be criminalized in law, even when no objective harm to others is caused (the moralistic premise), and that robotic rape and child abuse represent morally wrongful conduct (the wrongness premise). However, Danaher offers no coherent explanation as to why engaging in sexual activity with a humanoid robot should constitute “rape” or “child abuse” in its own right, or in a specific sense. Eskens addressed this issue more directly, concluding that sex with robots does not constitute “rape” in the strictest legal sense, as the normative use of this term involves a consider- ation of consent. She concluded that robots lack moral value (by virtue of their artificiality and lack of cognitive capacity (see also [52, 53]), and thus cannot give (or withhold) consent, and by extension cannot be victims. In spite of setting out Page 3 of 8 54 Curr Psychiatry Rep (2020) 22: 54 Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.
  • 4. these arguments, Eskens tempered her argument by stating that “although it might not be impermissible to have sex with robots for the reason that it is non-consensual, it might be impermissible for other reasons,” invoking those ideas of ob- jectification, desensitization, and the promotion of offense- supportive cognitions, as described above. Child-Like Sex Dolls, Pedophilia, and Child Sexual Abuse The philosopher John Danaher examined the issue of child sex doll and robot criminalization using the perspective of legal moralism [5]. In essence, this position posits that the immo- rality of a particular behavior or object should be able to serve as a basis for its restriction or criminalization, irrespective of the objective harm (or lack thereof) that it causes other people. Danaher draws upon the work of Strikwerda to argue that engaging in sexual activity with a child-like sex doll or robot encourages and normalizes a non-virtuous form of sexual ac- tivity, owing to its ostensibly non-consensual and power- imbalanced nature [6]. In other work, Danaher has gone so far as to argue that owning child sex dolls and robots indicates a lack of moral virtue in its own right [4], suggesting that one potential consequence of ownership could be inclusion in reg- istration processes currently reserved for individuals with sex- ual convictions. Danaher is not alone in theorizing about child-like dolls and robots from such a moralistic position. In a further attempt to justify the criminalization of the creation and distribution of child-like sex dolls and robots, Chatterjee also acknowledged the lack of objective personal harm caused by these materials. However, she invoked rea- soning related to “cultural harm” to argue that “permitting a trade in even abstract child sex dolls and robots could be seen as sanctioning and facilitating a public atmosphere that en- courages the portrayal of children as sexual objects, and the acceptance and normalization of child abuse” [54]. While this argument makes logical sense, it is telling (and reflective of the rest of the philosophical literature on child sex dolls and robots) that it is presented in isolation and without references to an opposing view related to child sexual abuse prevention. Some professionals working within forensic health services have tentatively suggested that child-like dolls and robots could play a role in the prevention of child sexual abuse (for discussions, see [3•, 5, 54]). This argument suggests that dolls and robots offer a sexual outlet without a victim that could satiate the sexual fantasies of some individuals with sexual interests in children. While this possibility is mentioned in some of the philosophical papers cited above, it is quickly dismissed with doubt, possibly due to an inherent misunder- standing of the nature of such sexual interests within the phil- osophical community (see [4, 5, 54, 55]) without any serious empirical consideration of its merits taking place. The Australian Institute of Criminology (which operates as a branch of the Australian Government) commissioned a re- port, authored by Rick Brown and Jane Shelling, into the potential behavioral and legal implications of child sex doll use [3•]. In it, the authors purported to review the available evidence on child sex doll use and proposed recommendations on the basis of this review. Specifically, the implications under investigation included the following: 1. the promotion of the sexualization of children; 2. the extent to which child-like sex doll use is an indicator of an escalation from using child sexual exploitation ma- terial (CSEM); 3. the normalization of child sexual abuse (i.e., the causal link between child-like sex doll use and contact sexual offending against children); and 4. the risk that child-like sex dolls can be used as a tool for the sexual grooming of children. Throughout the report, Brown and Shelling identify no empirical evidence for any of these hypotheses about the ef- fects of child-like doll ownership. This was explicitly stated in sections about the harmfulness of doll ownership (i.e., pro- moting of sexual offending), while the legal moralism per- spective of philosophical authors [4–6, 28] was invoked once again when discussing the implications of dolls on objectifi- cation and desensitization to themes of child sexual abuse. In a comparatively short section of their report, they also discussed the possibility of child-sex sex dolls playing a role in the prevention of sexual abuse, again highlighting the dearth of empirical data that directly tests this hypothesis. It is remark- able, then, given this explicit lack of empirical data, that Brown and Shelling conclude: It is reasonable to assume that interaction with child sex dolls could increase the likelihood of child sexual abuse by desensitizing the doll user to the physical, emotional and psychological harm caused by child sexual abuse and normalizing the behavior in the mind of the abuser. At the same time, there is no evidence of therapeutic benefit from child sex doll use. [3•] Most surprising here is not the assertion that it is perhaps reasonable to assume a degree of sexual risk among some people who own child-like sex dolls (see also [5, 6, 54, 55]). Rather, it is more concerning, and perhaps illuminating of this area of scholarship, that this conclusion is reached alongside one pertaining to their lack of therapeutic benefit in light of the total lack of evidence in either direction. This is perhaps re- flective of the nature of the authors’ theoretical understanding about the nature of sexual offending. That is, they cite feminist and sociological conceptualizations of sexual offending by arguing that this behavior is driven by primarily by a desire 54 Page 4 of 8 Curr Psychiatry Rep (2020) 22: 54 Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.
  • 5. to exert dominance, power, and control, and not the achieve- ment of sexual satisfaction [26, 56, 57]. While a detailed ex- ploration of this argument is not specifically within the remit of this review, we direct readers to each of the major multi- factorial models of sexual offending used within forensic psy- chological research and practice; all of which contain sexual interest or arousal as a key causal component [58–63]. This approach was also taken in a review article published by Chantal Cox-George and Susan Bewley, who sought to provide a succinct summary of the arguments for and against the sex robot industry and to assess the potential health impli- cations that may affect both patient behaviors and clinicians’ professional activity [7•]. Consistent with Brown and Shelling’s report in Australia [3•], Cox-George and Bewley discussed the potential risks of using sex dolls and robots in clinical settings, despite their literature search yielding no em- pirical studies for them to review. The reasons for these au- thors taking such a defensive position included police interest in dolls, potential clinical prosecutions for providing illicit materials, and the broader possibility of negative public re- sponses to the use of dolls and robots in clinical settings. This led Cox-George and Bewley to advise against incorpo- rating dolls and robots into clinical practice, as this alleviates the danger of professionals facing repercussions because of their use. While the widespread adoption of child-like dolls in foren- sic and clinical settings in the absence of evidence should not be promoted, these reviews do suggest a skewed reading of the literature (for a commentary, see [64]). It is incumbent on scientists, clinicians, and policy makers to maintain an open mind on the potential for both benefits and risks until evidence is available. We now turn our attention to what the beginnings of a comprehensive research agenda into sex dolls and robots might look like. Towards an Agenda for Research In light of the almost complete absence of empirical research into the effects of sex dolls and robots on owner attitudes and behaviors, we close our review with a call for research into these crucial outcomes. Specifically, research is needed in several domains, including the following: 1. The different motivations of sex doll and robot owners 2. The effects of sex dolls and robots on sexual cognition and behavior (e.g., sexual fantasy and aggression) 3. Social attitudes and responses to sex dolls and robots Considering analyses of qualitative accounts provided by sex doll and robot owners in existing work [2, 13••], deeper and more specific analyses of the motivations of owners for obtaining dolls and robots should be conducted. While the existing work provides a useful starting point, these papers are limited by the nature of the data collected. That is, survey-based and forum data are limited in relation to the level of explanatory depth that can be obtained. Future studies may look to conduct interviews with doll and robot owners. This approach allows for a conversation to be had between the researcher and the subject, providing the opportunity for deep phenomenological accounts about the nuanced functions of dolls and robots to be uncovered. This level of analysis may also uncover new insights about the types of quantifiable var- iables that may distinguish doll and robot owners from those who do not own such objects. The overwhelming conclusion that emerges from the existing literature on sex dolls and robots is that there is an almost total lack of empirical evidence about the psychologi- cal and behavioral effects of owning these objects. A propen- sity to engage in increased levels of the sexual objectification of women, the strengthening of rigid standards of sexual at- traction, and an increased risk of sexual offending are all cited as potential implications of doll ownership [3•, 7•, 20, 21, 23, 28, 51]. However, while these arguments make logical sense, their empirical validity remains untested. Research is urgently needed to test these assertions. Initially these studies may take the form of cross-sectional designs exploring whether levels of sexual objectification or offending proclivity differ between groups of sex doll owners and non-owner controls. If differ- ences are discovered, then longitudinal studies investigating whether doll and robot ownership is causally linked to elevat- ed risk levels would be required. That is, non-owners who are considering doll ownership might be followed-up in order to explore how (or perhaps whether) they change with respect to indices of potential sexual aggression. Irrespective of the re- sults of cross-sectional surveys of doll and robot owners, mul- tifactorial theories of sexual offending could play an important role in determining the conditions under which such owner- ship is or is not “safe.” Seto’s motivation–facilitation model, for example, asserts that a sexual interest may lead to a psy- chological disposition towards engaging in an offending be- havior, but that the actual enactment of such behaviors are facilitated (or hindered) by the presence (or absence) of facil- itating factors, such as antisocial personality traits or depen- dency on drugs or alcohol [63]. In applying this to the doll and robot context, sexual offending proclivity may be predicted via an interaction between sex doll ownership (a potentially motivating sexual interest) and the presence (or absence) of offense-facilitating (or offense-reducing) personality and life- style factors. In addition to the potential risks associated with doll and robot ownership, research should also investigate the various positive effects that doll ownership may yield. Controlled ac- cess to dolls in sex and relationship counseling settings may be a useful starting point for this, so as to explore the effec- tiveness of dolls in alleviating sexual dysfunction. More con- troversially, trials of child-like sex dolls may be considered in Page 5 of 8 54 Curr Psychiatry Rep (2020) 22: 54 Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.
  • 6. settings geared towards the prevention of sexual abuse among individuals who are sexually attracted to children. Case study evidence of this practice should be considered and evaluated prior to larger trials of the efficacy of dolls as a cathartic sexual outlet for minor-attracted persons. However, such trials are the only meaningful way to address the controversies and unan- swered questions currently posed in the literature. As highlighted previously, sex dolls and robots have a po- tential role to play in medical and psychotherapeutic settings for alleviating feelings of social and emotional isolation, or in the treatment of sexual dysfunction [11, 17]. However, at present it is acknowledged that social responses to doll and robot ownership may act as a blockage to such usage, even if there was evidence of its effectiveness [7•]. There is minimal evidence about the nature of social attitudes regarding sex doll and robot ownership. In the data that are available, men are typically more accepting of doll ownership and use in clinical settings [15, 17], as are younger participants [17]. Higher levels of religiosity have also been associated with more neg- ative attitudes [65], which may be reflective of the view that such objects are not a creation of God. However, there cur- rently exists no standardized measure of attitudes towards sex dolls and robots, as well as their owners. The development of such a measure, potentially using inspiration from scales de- signed to examine stigmatization of other sexual minority groups, will enable the systematic study of such responses, and help to identify the types of factors that alter social per- ceptions of this topic. Such factors may include the apparent age of the doll (adult-like vs. child-like), the function it is designed to fulfill (e.g., sexual gratification vs. the treatment of mental distress), or the personality traits of doll and robot owners (e.g., levels of psychopathy vs. empathy). Conclusions Our aim in this review has been to chart the development of arguments emerging within the existing literature on the mo- tivations and effects of sex doll and sex robot ownership. We further sought to critique these ideas in light of the dearth of empirical research into this topic, using insights from social, cognitive, and evolutionary psychology, as well as contempo- rary theorizing about the etiology of sexual offending. In do- ing so, we have highlighted how the conclusions reached by scholars currently writing about this topic are borne out of ideological and risk-averse starting positions, with this some- times being explicitly acknowledged by these authors. We have presented some initial ideas for a research program into the motivations of sex doll and robot ownership, the behav- ioral implications of such ownership practices, and social re- sponses to individuals who may wish to own a sex doll or robot. It is our hope that social scientists and legal scholars will use these ideas to engage in more empirical research into this increasingly contentious social issue. Compliance with Ethical Standards Conflict of Interest The authors declare that they have no conflict of interest. Human and Animal Rights and Informed Consent This article does not contain any studies with human or animal subjects performed by any of the authors. Open Access This article is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License, which permits use, sharing, adap- tation, distribution and reproduction in any medium or format, as long as you give appropriate credit to the original author(s) and the source, pro- vide a link to the Creative Commons licence, and indicate if changes were made. The images or other third party material in this article are included in the article's Creative Commons licence, unless indicated otherwise in a credit line to the material. If material is not included in the article's Creative Commons licence and your intended use is not permitted by statutory regulation or exceeds the permitted use, you will need to obtain permission directly from the copyright holder. To view a copy of this licence, visit http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/. References Papers of particular interest, published recently, have been highlighted as: • Of importance •• Of major importance 1. Valverde S The modern sex doll owner: a descriptive analysis [Master’s]. [San Luis Obispo, California]: California Polytechnic State University; 2012. Available from: https://digitalcommons. calpoly.edu/theses/849 2. Langcaster-James M, Bentley G. Beyond the sex doll: post-human companionship and the rise of the ‘allodoll.’. Robotics. 2018;7(4): 62. 3.• Brown R, Shelling J. Exploring the implications of child sex dolls. Australian Institute of Criminology; 2019. This report represents one example of the motivated interpretation of a lack of evi- dence about the effects of sex doll ownership, leading to prema- ture conclusions and recommendations. 4. Danaher J. Robotic rape and robotic child sexual abuse: should they be criminalised? Crim Law Philos. 2017;11(1):71–95. 5. Danaher J. Regulating child sex robots: restriction or experimenta- tion? Med Law Rev. 2019;27(4):553–75. 6. Strikwerda L. Legal and moral implications of child sex robots. In: Danaher J, McArthur N, editors. Robot sex: social and ethical im- plications. Cambridge: MIT Press; 2017. p. 133–52. 7.• Cox-George C, Bewley S. I, sex robot: The health implications of the sex robot industry. BMJ Sex Reprod Health. 2018;44(3):161–4 This piece represents one example of the motivated interpreta- tion of a lack of evidence about the effects of sex doll ownership, leading to premature conclusions and recommendations. 8. Ray P. ‘Synthetik love lasts forever’: sex dolls and the (post?)human condition. In: Banerji D, Paranjape MR, editors. Critical posthumanism and planetary futures [internet]. New 54 Page 6 of 8 Curr Psychiatry Rep (2020) 22: 54 Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.
  • 7. Delhi: Springer India; 2016 [cited 2020 Apr 1]. p. 91–112. Available from: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-81-322-3637-5_6. 9. Danaher J. The symbolic-consequences argument in the sex robot debate. In: Danaher J, McArthur N, editors. Robot sex: social and ethical implications. Cambridge: MIT Press; 2017. p. 103–32. 10. Danaher J. Building better sex robots: lessons from feminist por- nography. In: Zhou Y, Fischer MH, editors. AI love you : develop- ments in human-robot intimate relationships. Cham: Springer; 2019. p. 133–47. 11. Döring N, Pöschl S. Sex toys, sex dolls, sex robots: our under- researched bed-fellows. Sexologies. 2018;27(3):e51–5. 12. Ferguson A. The sex doll: a history. McFarland & Company, Inc: Jefferson; 2014. p. 237. 13.•• Su NM, Lazar A, Bardzell J, Bardzell S. Of dolls and men: antic- ipating sexual intimacy with robots. ACM Trans Comput-Hum Interact. 2019;26(3):13 This paper presents a large analysis of the online forum posts of sex doll owners, illuminating some of their motivations for doll ownership. 14. Döring N, Pöschl S. Love and sex with robots: a content analysis of media representations. Int J Soc Robot. 2019;11(4):665–77. 15. Appel M, Marker C, Mara M. Otakuism and the appeal of sex robots. Front Psychol [Internet]. 2019 [cited 2020 Mar 31];10. Available from: https://www.frontiersin.org/articles/10.3389/ fpsyg.2019.00569/full 16. Szczuka JM, Krämer NC. Not only the lonely—how men explicitly and implicitly evaluate the attractiveness of sex robots in compari- son to the attractiveness of women, and personal characteristics influencing this evaluation. Multimodal Technol Interact. 2017;1(1):3. 17. Eichenberg C, Khamis M, Hübner L. The attitudes of therapists and physicians on the use of sex robots in sexual therapy: online survey and interview study. J Med Internet Res [Internet]. 2019 [cited 2020 Mar 31];21(8). Available from: https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/ pmc/articles/PMC6719485/ 18. Fosch-Villaronga E, Poulsen A. Sex care robots: exploring the po- tential use of sexual robot technologies for disabled and elder care. Paladyn J Behav Robot. 2020;11(1):1–18. 19. Morgan M. Using anatomical dolls in HIV/AIDS prevention pro- grams. Am J Sex Educ. 2009;4(1):28–39. 20. Carvalho Nascimento EC, da Silva E, Siqueira-Batista R. The “use” of sex robots: a bioethical issue. Asian Bioeth Rev. 2018;10(3): 231–40. 21. Richardson K. The asymmetrical “relationship”: parallels between prostitution and the development of sex robots [Internet]. Association for Computing Machinery; 2016 [cited 2020 Mar 31]. Available from: https://doi.org/10.1145/2874239.2874281. 22. Cassidy V. For the love of doll(s): a patriarchal nightmare of cyborg couplings. ESC Engl Stud Can. 2016;42(1):203–15. 23. Richardson K. Sex robots: the end of love. Cambridge: Polity Press; 2019. 24. Shokri N, Asl MP. Patriarchal hierarchies of power and the subor- dination of women: real doll as a replacement of woman figure. Adv Lang Lit Stud. 2015;6(4):216–20. 25. Ciambrone D, Phua V, Avery E. Gendered synthetic love: real dolls and the construction of intimacy. Int Rev Mod Sociol [Internet]. 2017;43(1). Available from: https://cupola.gettysburg.edu/socfac/ 32 26. Facchin F, Barbara G, Cigoli V. Sex robots: the irreplaceable value of humanity. BMJ [Internet]. 2017 [cited 2020 Mar 31];358. Available from: https://www.bmj.com/content/358/bmj.j3790 27. Eskens R. Is sex with robots rape? J Pract Ethics. 2017;5(2):62–76. 28. Sparrow R. Robots, rape, and representation. Int J Soc Robot. 2017;9(4):465–77. 29. Orehek E, Weaverling CG. On the nature of objectification: impli- cations of considering people as means to goals. Perspect Psychol Sci. 2017;12(5):719–30. 30. Papadaki E(L). Sexual objectification: from Kant to contemporary feminism. Contemp Polit Theory. 2007;6(3):330–48. 31. MacKinnon CA. Feminism unmodified: discourses on life and law. Cambridge: Harvard University Press; 1987. 32. Nussbaum MC. Sex and social justice. New York: Oxford University Press; 1999. 33. Gervais SJ, DiLillo D, McChargue D. Understanding the link be- tween men’s alcohol use and sexual violence perpetration: the me- diating role of sexual objectification. Psychol Violence. 2014;4(2): 156–69. 34. Seabrook RC, Ward LM, Giaccardi S. Less than human? Media use, objectification of women, and men’s acceptance of sexual ag- gression. Psychol Violence. 2019;9(5):536–45. 35. Vasquez EA, Ball L, Loughnan S, Pina A. The object of my ag- gression: sexual objectification increases physical aggression to- ward women. Aggress Behav. 2018;44(1):5–17. 36. Mathur MB, VanderWeele TJ. Finding common ground in meta- analysis “wars” on violent video games. Perspect Psychol Sci. 2019;14(4):705–8. 37. Hilgard J, Engelhardt CR, Rouder JN. Overstated evidence for short-term effects of violent games on affect and behavior: a reanal- ysis of Anderson et al. (2010). Psychol Bull. 2017;143(7):757–74. 38. Malamuth NM, Hald GM, Koss M. Pornography, individual differ- ences in risk and men’s acceptance of violence against women in a representative sample. Sex Roles. 2012;66(7):427–39. 39. Fisher WA, Kohut T, Di Gioacchino LA, Fedoroff P. Pornography, sex crime, and paraphilia. Curr Psychiatry Rep. 2013;15(6):362. 40. Ferguson CJ, Hartley RD. The pleasure is momentary…the ex- pense damnable? The influence of pornography on rape and sexual assault. Aggress Violent Behav. 2009;14(5):323–9. 41. Puig K The synthetic hyper femme: on sex dolls, fembots, and the futures of sex [Master’s]. [San Diego, CA]: San Diego State University; 2017. 42. Saad G. On the method of evolutionary psychology and its appli- cability to consumer research. J Mark Res. 2017;54(3):464–77. 43. Lassek WD, Gaulin SJC. Evidence supporting nubility and repro- ductive value as the key to human female physical attractiveness. Evol Hum Behav. 2019;40(5):408–19. 44. Butovskaya M, Sorokowska A, Karwowski M, Sabiniewicz A, Fedenok J, Dronova D, et al. Waist-to-hip ratio, body-mass index, age and number of children in seven traditional societies. Sci Rep. 2017;7(1):1–9. 45. Dixson BJ, Grimshaw GM, Linklater WL, Dixson AF. Eye- tracking of men’s preferences for waist-to-hip ratio and breast size of women. Arch Sex Behav. 2011;40(1):43–50. 46. Del Zotto M, Pegna AJ. Electrophysiological evidence of perceived sexual attractiveness for human female bodies varying in waist-to- hip ratio. Cogn Affect Behav Neurosci. 2017;17(3):577–91. 47. Singh D, Dixson BJ, Jessop TS, Morgan B, Dixson AF. Cross- cultural consensus for waist–hip ratio and women’s attractiveness. Evol Hum Behav. 2010;31(3):176–81. 48. Saad G. Advertised waist-to-hip ratios of online female escorts: an evolutionary perspective. Int J E-Collab. 2008;4(3):40–50. 49. Griffith JD, Capiola A, Balotti B, Hart CL, Turner R. Online female escort advertisements: the cost of sex. Evol Psychol. 2016;14(2):1– 9. 50. Kock N, Hantula DA, Hayne SC, Saad G, Todd PM, Watson RT. Introduction to Darwinian perspectives on electronic communica- tion. IEEE Trans Prof Commun. 2008;51(2):133–46. 51. Gutiu S Sex robots and roboticization of consent. In: We Robot Conference [Internet]. Miami, FL; 2012. Available from: http:// robots.law.miami.edu/wp-content/uploads/2012/01/Gutiu- Roboticization_of_Consent.pdf 52. Singer P. Practical ethics. 2nd ed. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; 1993. p. 395. Page 7 of 8 54 Curr Psychiatry Rep (2020) 22: 54 Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.
  • 8. 53. Kagan S. What’s wrong with speciesism? J Appl Philos. 2016;33(1):1–21. 54. Chatterjee BB. Child sex dolls and robots: challenging the bound- aries of the child protection framework. Int Rev Law Comput Technol. 2020;34(1):22–43. 55. Maras M-H, Shapiro LR. Child sex dolls and robots: more than just an uncanny valley. J Internet Law. 2017;21(5):3–21. 56. Brownmiller S. Against our will: men, women, and rape. New York: Bantam Books; 1975. 57. Powell A, Henry N. Sexual violence: a feminist criminological analysis. In: Powell A, Henry N, editors. Sexual violence in a digital age. London: Palgrave Macmillan; 2017. p. 23–47. (Palgrave Studies in Cybercrime and Cybersecurity). 58. Finkelhor D. Child sexual abuse: new theory and research. New York: Free Press; 1984. 59. Marshall WL, Barbaree HE. An integrated theory of the etiology of sexual offending. In: Marshall WL, Laws DR, Barbaree HE, edi- tors. Handbook of sexual assault. Boston: Springer; 1990. p. 257– 75. 60. Hall GCN, Hirschman R. Toward a theory of sexual aggression: a quadripartite model. J Consult Clin Psychol. 1991;59(5):662–9. 61. Ward T, Siegert RJ. Toward a comprehensive theory of child sexual abuse: a theory knitting perspective. Psychol Crime Law. 2002;8(4):319–51. 62. Ward T, Beech A. An integrated theory of sexual offending. Aggress Violent Behav. 2006;11(1):44–63. 63. Seto MC. The motivation-facilitation model of sexual offending. Sex Abus. 2019;31(1):3–24. 64. Eggleton J. Comment on “I, sex robot: the health implications of the sex robot industry”. BMJ Sex Reprod Health. 2019;45(1):78–9. 65. Knox D, Huff S, Chang IJ. Sex dolls—creepy or healthy? Attitudes of undergraduates. J Posit Sex. 2017;3(2):32–7. Publisher’s Note Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdic- tional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations. 54 Page 8 of 8 Curr Psychiatry Rep (2020) 22: 54 Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.
  • 9. 1. 2. 3. 4. 5. 6. Terms and Conditions Springer Nature journal content, brought to you courtesy of Springer Nature Customer Service Center GmbH (“Springer Nature”). Springer Nature supports a reasonable amount of sharing of research papers by authors, subscribers and authorised users (“Users”), for small- scale personal, non-commercial use provided that all copyright, trade and service marks and other proprietary notices are maintained. By accessing, sharing, receiving or otherwise using the Springer Nature journal content you agree to these terms of use (“Terms”). For these purposes, Springer Nature considers academic use (by researchers and students) to be non-commercial. These Terms are supplementary and will apply in addition to any applicable website terms and conditions, a relevant site licence or a personal subscription. These Terms will prevail over any conflict or ambiguity with regards to the relevant terms, a site licence or a personal subscription (to the extent of the conflict or ambiguity only). For Creative Commons-licensed articles, the terms of the Creative Commons license used will apply. We collect and use personal data to provide access to the Springer Nature journal content. We may also use these personal data internally within ResearchGate and Springer Nature and as agreed share it, in an anonymised way, for purposes of tracking, analysis and reporting. We will not otherwise disclose your personal data outside the ResearchGate or the Springer Nature group of companies unless we have your permission as detailed in the Privacy Policy. While Users may use the Springer Nature journal content for small scale, personal non-commercial use, it is important to note that Users may not: use such content for the purpose of providing other users with access on a regular or large scale basis or as a means to circumvent access control; use such content where to do so would be considered a criminal or statutory offence in any jurisdiction, or gives rise to civil liability, or is otherwise unlawful; falsely or misleadingly imply or suggest endorsement, approval , sponsorship, or association unless explicitly agreed to by Springer Nature in writing; use bots or other automated methods to access the content or redirect messages override any security feature or exclusionary protocol; or share the content in order to create substitute for Springer Nature products or services or a systematic database of Springer Nature journal content. In line with the restriction against commercial use, Springer Nature does not permit the creation of a product or service that creates revenue, royalties, rent or income from our content or its inclusion as part of a paid for service or for other commercial gain. Springer Nature journal content cannot be used for inter-library loans and librarians may not upload Springer Nature journal content on a large scale into their, or any other, institutional repository. These terms of use are reviewed regularly and may be amended at any time. Springer Nature is not obligated to publish any information or content on this website and may remove it or features or functionality at our sole discretion, at any time with or without notice. Springer Nature may revoke this licence to you at any time and remove access to any copies of the Springer Nature journal content which have been saved. To the fullest extent permitted by law, Springer Nature makes no warranties, representations or guarantees to Users, either express or implied with respect to the Springer nature journal content and all parties disclaim and waive any implied warranties or warranties imposed by law, including merchantability or fitness for any particular purpose. Please note that these rights do not automatically extend to content, data or other material published by Springer Nature that may be licensed from third parties. If you would like to use or distribute our Springer Nature journal content to a wider audience or on a regular basis or in any other manner not expressly permitted by these Terms, please contact Springer Nature at onlineservice@springernature.com