SlideShare a Scribd company logo
1 of 102
Confirming Pages
THE PRACTICAL SKEPTIC
CORE CONCEPTS IN SOCIOLOGY
Sixth Edit ion
Lisa J. McIntyre
Washington State University
mcI26873_fm_i-xiv.indd imcI26873_fm_i-xiv.indd i
19/04/13 3:51 AM19/04/13 3:51 AM
Rev. Confirming Pages
THE PRACTICAL SKEPTIC: CORE CONCEPTS IN
SOCIOLOGY, SIXTH EDITION
Published by McGraw-Hill Education, 2 Penn Plaza, New York,
NY 10121. Copyright © 2 014 by
McGraw-Hill Education. All rights reserved. Printed in the
United States of America. Previous
editions © 2 011, 2008, and 2006. No part of this publication
may be reproduced or distributed in
any form or by any means, or stored in a database or retrieval
system, without the prior written
consent of McGraw-Hill Education, including, but not limited
to, in any network or other
electronic storage or transmission, or broadcast for distance
learning.
Some ancillaries, including electronic and print components,
may not be available to customers
outside the United States.
This book is printed on acid-free paper.
1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 0 DOC/DOC 1 0 9 8 7 6 5 4 3
ISBN 978-0-07-802687-4
MHID 0-07-802687-3
Senior Vice President, Products & Markets: Kurt L. Strand
Vice President, General Manager, Products & Markets: Michael
Ryan
Vice President, Content Production & Technology Services:
Kimberly Meriwether David
Managing Director: Gina Boedeker
Brand Manager: Courtney Austermehle
Director of Development: Rhona Robbin
Freelance Development Editor: Nomi Sofer
Marketing Manager: Philip Weaver
Marketing Coordinator: Ryan Viviani
Director, Content Production: Terri Schiesl
Content Project Manager: Mary Jane Lampe
Buyer: Nichole Birkenholz
Cover Designer: Studio Montage, St. Louis, MO
Cover Image: Digital Vision / Getty Images
Typeface: 10/12 Palatino
Compositor: Laserwords Private Limited
Printer: R. R. Donnelley
All credits appearing on page or at the end of the book are
considered to be an extension of the
copyright page.
Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data
McIntyre, Lisa J.
The practical skeptic : core concepts in sociology / Lisa J.
McIntyre, Washington State
University. — Sixth edition.
pages cm
ISBN 978-0-07-802687-4 (alk. paper)
1. Sociology. I. Title.
HM586.M55 2014
301—dc23
2013008264
The Internet addresses listed in the text were accurate at the
time of publication. The inclusion of a
website does not indicate an endorsement by the authors or
McGraw-Hill Education, and McGraw-
Hill Education does not guarantee the accuracy of the
information presented at these sites.
www.mhhe.com
mcI26873_fm_i-xiv.indd iimcI26873_fm_i-xiv.indd ii
4/22/13 11:46 AM4/22/13 11:46 AM
Confirming Pages
iii
CONTENTS
Preface x
Introduction 1
So, What Is Sociology? 2
The Value of Sociology to Students 3
Tips for Studying Sociology—and an
Invitation 4
Chapter 1 Responding to Chaos: A Brief History
of Sociology 5
Inquiries into the Physical World 6
Technology, Urbanization, and Social
Upheaval 10
The Origins of Modern Sociology in France:
Émile Durkheim 13
E xcerpt: É mile D urkheim, From Suicide (1897)
and The Rules of the Sociological Method (1904) 14
The Origins of Modern Sociology in Germany:
Ferdinand Tönnies, Max Weber, and Karl Marx 16
E xcerpt: F erdinand T önnies, From
Gemeinschaft and Gesellschaft (1887) 17
Karl Marx 20
The Origins of Modern Sociology in England:
Herbert Spencer 22
Sociology in the United States 23
mcI26873_fm_i-xiv.indd iiimcI26873_fm_i-xiv.indd iii
19/04/13 3:51 AM19/04/13 3:51 AM
Confirming Pages
iv CONTENTS
B ox: One Small Step for Sociology 25
The Place of Sociology in Modern Society 26
Chapter Review 26
Stop & Review: Answers and Discussion 27
Chapter 2 The Sociological Eye 29
The Focus on the Social 29
B ox: Agency and Structure 34
Skepticism 35
B ox: Nail Down That Distinction Between
Manifest and Latent Functions! 37
Chapter Review 38
Stop & Review: Answers and Discussion 39
Chapter 3 Science and Fuzzy Objects: Specialization
in Sociology 40
Dividing Up the Task 42
Topic Area or Subject Matter 43
Theoretical Perspectives (Paradigms):
Functionalist, Conflict, and Symbolic
Interactionist 43
The Functionalist Paradigm 43
The Conflict Paradigm 44
The Symbolic Interactionist Paradigm 44
Which Paradigm Is Correct? 45
Levels of Analysis: Microsociology
and Macrosociology 46
Chapter Review 47
Stop & Review: Answers and Discussion 48
Chapter 4 Who’s Afraid of Sociology? 49
The Empirical World and Inconvenient Facts 50
Ethnocentrism 52
Avoiding Ethnocentrism Can Be Difficult 54
Cultural Relativism 56
Chapter Review 57
Stop & Review: Answers and Discussion 57
Chapter 5 The Vocabulary of Science 58
Concepts and Constructs 58
Variables 59
mcI26873_fm_i-xiv.indd ivmcI26873_fm_i-xiv.indd iv
19/04/13 3:51 AM19/04/13 3:51 AM
Confirming Pages
CONTENTS v
Hypotheses 61
Kinds of Variables: Independent Versus
Dependent 63
Kinds of Relationships: Directionality 65
Operational Definitions 66
Tables and Figures 68
A Note on Common Statistics 72
Correlation Versus Causation 74
Chapter Review 75
Stop & Review: Answers and Discussion 76
Chapter 6 Doing Social Research 81
Two Traditions: Quantitative and Qualitative
Research 81
First Things First: The Lit Review 82
The Survey 84
Types of Survey Questions 85
B ox: Six Guidelines for Crafting Survey
Questions 87
The Art of Asking Questions 88
Observation 88
Unobtrusive (Nonreactive) Research 90
Artifacts 90
Use of Existing Statistics 91
Content Analysis 91
The Importance of Triangulation 92
Box: Ethnography 93
Sampling 96
B ox: Ethics and Social Research 97
Chapter Review 98
Stop & Review: Answers and Discussion 99
Chapter 7 Culture 101
Material and Nonmaterial Culture 102
Nonmaterial Culture 102
Symbols 102
Language 103
Norms 104
Types of Norms 105
Sanctions 105
B ox: The Power of Informal Sanctions 106
Values 107
mcI26873_fm_i-xiv.indd vmcI26873_fm_i-xiv.indd v
19/04/13 3:51 AM19/04/13 3:51 AM
Confirming Pages
vi CONTENTS
B ox: What Do Americans Value? 107
B ox: Ideology 108
B ox: Ponder 109
B ox: Statements of Belief 109
Ideas and Beliefs 109
How It Adds Up 109
Culture as a Product of Action 110
Culture as a Conditioning Element of Further
Action 111
B ox: Problems Identified and Resolved in All
Known Cultures 112
B ox: Varieties of Cultural Wisdom 112
Social Institutions 113
Social Change: Cultural Diffusion and
Leveling 114
Subcultures and Countercultures 114
Idiocultures 116
Chapter Review 118
Stop & Review: Answers and Discussion 119
Chapter 8 Social Structure 121
Statuses 121
Roles 123
Tricky Situation 1: Role Strain 124
Tricky Situation 2: Status Inconsistency 124
Tricky Situation 3: Role Conflict 125
Master Status 126
Groups 127
Primary and Secondary Groups 128
Formal Organizations and Bureaucracies 130
Ideal-Type Bureaucracies 130
Chapter Review 133
Stop & Review: Answers and Discussion 134
Chapter 9 Society and Social Institutions 136
Societal Needs 139
The Nature of Social Institutions 142
Institutions Are Generally Unplanned; They
Develop Gradually 142
Institutions Are Inherently Conservative; They
Change, but Slowly 144
mcI26873_fm_i-xiv.indd vimcI26873_fm_i-xiv.indd vi
19/04/13 3:51 AM19/04/13 3:51 AM
Confirming Pages
CONTENTS vii
A Particular Society’s Institutions Are
Interdependent; Because of This, Change in
One Institution Tends to Bring About Change in
Others 147
The Statuses, Roles, Values, and Norms Associated
with an Institution in One Society Frequently
Bear Little Resemblance to Those in Another
Society 148
B ox: Polygamy and Monogamy 149
Social Change: The Trend Toward Increasing
Specialization 149
Chapter Review 150
Stop & Review: Answers and Discussion 150
Chapter 10 Socialization 152
Nature and Nurture: Biological and Social
Processes 152
How Socialization Works 154
The Looking-Glass Self: Charles Horton
Cooley 155
The “I” and the “Me”: George Herbert
Mead 157
Family 160
School 161
Mass Media 162
Peer Groups 163
The Workplace 164
B ox: Rites of Passage 165
Resocialization and Total Institutions 166
B ox: Ponder 167
Chapter Review 167
Stop & Review: Answers and Discussion 168
Chapter 11 Deviance and Social Control 169
The Relativity of Deviance (What We
Already Know) 169
Nonsociological Theories of
Deviance 171
Sociological Theories of Deviance: Émile
Durkheim and Suicide 173
The Collective Conscience and Structural
Strain 173
Egoism and Anomie 174
mcI26873_fm_i-xiv.indd viimcI26873_fm_i-xiv.indd vii
19/04/13 3:51 AM19/04/13 3:51 AM
Confirming Pages
viii CONTENTS
More Structural Strain: Robert Merton and
Anomie 176
Anomie and Modern Social Structure 176
Responses to Anomie 177
Legitimate Versus Illegitimate Means 179
Learning to Be Deviant: Howard Becker’s Study
of Marijuana Use 179
Learning to Smoke 180
Learning to Perceive the Effects 181
Learning to Enjoy the Effects 182
The Societal Reaction Perspective: Labeling
Theory 183
The Functions of Deviance: Maintenance of the
Status Quo and Social Change 187
B ox: Ponder 187
A Caution About Crime Data 188
Deviance Is Not Immutable 189
Gays in the Military 191
Chapter Review 192
Stop & Review: Answers and Discussion 193
Chapter 12 Stratification and Inequality 195
Caste Systems 196
Estate Systems 199
B ox: A Year in the Life of the Peasant 200
Class Systems 202
Theoretical Conceptions of Class 203
B ox: Ponder 204
Some Words About Slavery 207
Social Mobility and Open Versus Closed
Systems 209
Chapter Review 210
Stop & Review: Answers and Discussion 212
Chapter 13 Inequality and Achievement: Social
Class 213
B ox: The Matthew Effect 217
Explaining Social Stratification 218
Cultural Explanations 219
Structural Explanations 220
mcI26873_fm_i-xiv.indd viiimcI26873_fm_i-xiv.indd viii
19/04/13 3:51 AM19/04/13 3:51 AM
Rev. Confirming Pages
CONTENTS ix
B ox: Beyond Academics 223
The Pygmalion Effect: The Power of
Expectations 227
The Fallacy of Hard Work 228
B ox: Ponder 229
Social Mobility, Social Structure, and Social
Change 230
B ox: Measuring Inequality 231
Chapter Review 232
Stop & Review: Answers and Discussion 234
Chapter 14 Inequality and Ascription: Race, Ethnicity,
and Gender 237
Why a Dollar Is Not Always a Dollar 238
”Racial Surtax” on Mortgages 242
Prejudice 245
Discrimination 246
Discrimination and “Isms” 249
The Social Construction of Minority
Groups 254
Gender 257
B ox: Sex or Gender? 259
What to Do with What You’ve Learned? 260
Chapter Review 262
Stop & Review: Answers and Discussion 263
Afterword 266
References 268
Credits 278
Glossary/Index 279
mcI26873_fm_i-xiv.indd ixmcI26873_fm_i-xiv.indd ix
4/22/13 11:46 AM4/22/13 11:46 AM
Confirming Pages
PREFACE
I t wasn’t until I was about halfway through my first decade of
teaching that I finally had the opportunity to teach Introduction
to Sociology. Did I want to teach Intro? You bet! I was
ecstatic. I had
been teaching various upper-division classes—research
methods,
social theory, criminology, law and society—but I wanted to be
the one who introduced sociology to students. I wanted to share
with students the enthusiasm that I felt for the entire sociologi-
cal enterprise and to expose them to the power of sociological
thought.
I tried to create an introductory course that would speak to the
typical first-year student who isn’t planning on majoring in
soci-
ology and, indeed, may not even know what sociology is. Even
among sociology majors, very few plan on becoming
sociologists.
Each semester, I ask my beginning students, “Why are you
here?
What is it about sociology that interests you?” The very
charitable
say, “I don’t know what sociology is, but I am sure that it will
be
interesting.” Mostly, students are honest: “I’m here to fulfill my
general education requirements.” A few are more specific: “I
have
to take a social science class and my advisor said that sociology
is
easier than economics or political science.”
I knew that once these students discovered sociology, they
would find merit in it. Even if they didn’t major in sociology,
they
would come away from the class with some important life
knowl-
edge. I quote Robert Bierstedt in my syllabus: “Sociology owns
a proper place not only among the sciences, but also among the
arts that liberate the human mind” (1960, 3). I paraphrase Peter
Berger to suggest that students will find one of the most impor-
tant lessons of sociology to be that “things are not what they
x
mcI26873_fm_i-xiv.indd xmcI26873_fm_i-xiv.indd x
19/04/13 3:51 AM19/04/13 3:51 AM
Confirming Pages
PREFACE xi
seem” (1963, 23)—that sociological training encourages people
to look beyond the surface and to be suspicious of what “every-
body knows.” I tell them that it hardly matters what sort of
career
they are working toward: learning how to be skeptical and how
to think like a sociologist will help them understand and resolve
complex and abstract problems on the job.
So, I knew how I wanted to structure the course—we would
learn the basic concepts and then talk and read about how these
worked in the real world. But I couldn’t find a textbook whose
author had anticipated my wishes. I wanted a book that would
introduce students to sociology’s foundational concepts—the
sci-
entific method, culture, social structure, socialization, deviance,
inequality. I wanted a book that would not bury those concepts
inside tons of empirical information but would present them in
such a way that students could gain enough understanding to
apply them to what they read elsewhere and what they encoun-
tered in life. It was the sociological perspective I wanted these
students to come away with, not the details.
I was encouraged to pursue this vision by something I read
in an article by Frederick Campbell, a sociologist from the Uni-
versity of Washington. In the book he co-edited with Hubert
Blalock and Reece McGee, Campbell wrote that undergraduate
courses in sociology ought to focus on principles rather than
facts:
“The mastery of sociology has a different meaning in the con-
text of undergraduate education than in vocational training or a
graduate program. A baccalaureate degree in sociology seldom
prepares a student for a specific occupation or to pursue inde-
pendent research. Emphasis on the subject matter, then, has lit-
tle value if it means memorizing material that will soon go out
of date for a job that does not exist. Mastery should move away
from factual material and focus instead on the development of
the mind” (1985, 13).
The longer I taught introductory sociology, however, the
greater became my frustration with the available instructional
material. So, one summer, I sat down to write some introductory
and background materials for my students. My idea was that
I would introduce them to the concepts that sociologists use,
and we would then apply these to what we read in a variety of
sociological articles and to what we encountered in real life
(and
in the media). My goal was to provide my students with the
tools they needed to understand the social world through the
eyes of sociologists. As everyone who has taught introductory
courses probably knows, the foundational concepts of our dis-
cipline are not simple ones, and many students resist them. My
goal was not to simplify the concepts but to make them acces-
sible to students.
mcI26873_fm_i-xiv.indd ximcI26873_fm_i-xiv.indd xi
19/04/13 3:51 AM19/04/13 3:51 AM
Rev. Confirming Pages
xii PREFACE
The set of essays I wrote that summer—on the history of soci-
ology and the vocabulary of science, culture, social structure,
socialization, deviance, and inequality—seemed to serve my
students well. After students read them, we moved on with our
shared vocabulary to other works by sociologists and to discus-
sions of how these concepts applied to the real world. It
worked.
It was as Peter Berger had promised in his Invitation to
Sociology:
“It is not the excitement of coming upon the totally unfamiliar,
but rather the excitement of finding the familiar becoming
trans-
formed in its meaning. The fascination of sociology lies in the
fact
that its perspective makes us see in a new light the very world
in
which we have lived all our lives” (1963, 21). Although I omit-
ted much that is found in the typical sociology text (there are no
chapters on family, religion, or politics), the concepts I did
focus
on (institutions, roles, values, and so on) allowed us to have
rela-
tively sophisticated discussions of those topics.
Be warned: I am not one of those sociologists who write in
what Peter Berger called “a barbaric dialect.” I’ve taken C.
Wright
Mills’s caution to heart: “To get beyond sociological prose we
must get beyond the sociologist’s pose” (1959).
Notwithstanding
the fact that I once had a book rejected by a noted university
press
because it was “too much of a good read,” I’ve persisted in my
casual style and, whenever I couldn’t help it, have indulged my
odd sense of humor. Many sociological concepts are very com-
plex, and I think I have done justice to that complexity, but I
have
tried to do it in ways that are accessible to students.
NEW TO THIS EDITION
This edition uses updated statistics from the most recent
census
and other agencies. In response to suggestions from my readers,
I
continue to augment the discussions of topics that many
students
find difficult. In this edition, you will find new sections on the
relationship between correlation and causation, ethnography,
the
mutability of deviance and the relationship between gender and
income.
The goal of the book remains the same: to introduce students to
sociology in a way that makes the core concepts of our
discipline
accessible without losing the crucial complexity of these
concepts
in translation. Along the way, I hope that I have managed as
well
to convey my enthusiasm for sociology.
SUPPLEMENTS
Visit our Online Learning Center Web site at
http://www.mhhe
.com/mcintyre6e for student and instructor resources. This is a
mcI26873_fm_i-xiv.indd xiimcI26873_fm_i-xiv.indd xii
4/22/13 11:46 AM4/22/13 11:46 AM
Confirming Pages
PREFACE xiii
combined Web site for both The Practical Skeptic: Core
Concepts in
Sociology, and its companion reader, The Practical Skeptic:
Readings
in Sociology.
For Students
Student resources include comprehensive self-quizzes for both
the text and reader.
For Instructors
The password-protected instructor portion of the Web site in-
cludes the instructor’s manual (written by the author), contain-
ing discussion questions and activities, examples of lectures,
tips
specifically targeting new instructors, a comprehensive test
bank,
and all the tools available to students. Also included is a sepa-
rate test bank for the reader with multiple choice, true/false, and
essay questions for each reading.
THE COMPANION READER
Created to serve as a companion to the text, The Practical
Skeptic:
Core Concepts in Sociology, this reader, The Practical
Skeptic: Read-
ings in Sociology, includes classic sociological writings as well
as
recent writings on fascinating topics of interest to students.
Cor-
responding to the conceptual organization of the text, each of
the
readings serves to illustrate key sociological concepts and ideas.
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
My largest thanks go to the hundreds of students who have
read
The Practical Skeptic and shared their views of the text with
me.
Many thanks to the following reviewers whose comments and
suggestions shaped the sixth edition: Peter Adler, University of
Denver; Mitch Berbrier, University of Alabama in Huntsville;
Joslyn Brenton, North Carolina State University; Margaret
Dele-
hanty Kelly, University of Minnesota; Stacy Evans, Berkshire
Community College; Susan Eichenberger, Seton Hill University;
Catherine Leone, University of Wisconsin-Manitowoc; Pamela
McMullin-Messier, Central Washington University; Janice L.
Milner,
Century College; Megan Peterson, William Rainey Harper
College;
Carly Sebastian, Mount Wachusett Community College.
Thank you to the following reviewers whose helpful comments
and suggestions helped us in our preparation of the fifth edition:
Elizabeth Larsen, California University of Pennsylvania; Lynda
Dickson, University of Colorado at Colorado Springs; Kiren
Ghei, Delta College; Thomas B. Gold, University of California
at
Berkeley; Patti Guiffre, Texas State University; Michael
Collins,
mcI26873_fm_i-xiv.indd xiiimcI26873_fm_i-xiv.indd xiii
19/04/13 3:51 AM19/04/13 3:51 AM
Confirming Pages
xiv PREFACE
UW Fox Valley in Menasha; Linda C. Evans, Drake University;
Carolyn Kapinus, Ball State University; Carla Norris-Raynbird,
Bemidji State University, C. Stephen Glennon, Iowa Western
Community College; Doug Degher, North Arizona University;
Kim Hennessee, Ball State University.
The fourth edition manuscript was reviewed by the following
people, who responded with suggestions and pointed out neces-
sary revisions, for which I am deeply grateful: Diane C. Bates,
The
College of New Jersey; Gretchen DeHart, Community College
of
Vermont; Esther Horrocks, Villa Julie College; Michael C.
Maher,
Spoon River College; Lida V. Nedilsky, North Park University;
Deborah Thorne, Ohio University; and Craig Tollini, Western
Illi-
nois University.
I also appreciate the help of the third edition reviewers who
offered many helpful comments and suggestions: Deborah A.
Abowitz, Bucknell; Cheryl Albers, Buffalo State; Sue Cox,
Belle-
vue Community College; Derek Greenfield, Highline
Community
College; Tiffany Hayes, Green River Community College;
Barbara
Karcher, Kennesaw; Susan Ross, Lycoming College; and Ann S.
Stein, College of Charleston.
I thank the reviewers of the second edition for their thoughtful
reading: Jerry Barrish, Bellevue Community College; Debra
Cornelius,
Shippensburg University; Jamie Dangler, SUNY Cortland;
Laurel R.
Davis, Springfield College; Gloria Y. Gadsden, Fairleigh
Dickinson
University; Alan G. Hill, Delta College; Susan E. Humphers-
Ginther,
Moorhead State University; Katherine Johnson, Niagara County
Com-
munity College; Barbara Karcher, Kennesaw State University;
Debra
C. Lemke, Western Maryland College; Patricia A. Masters,
George
Mason University; Susan McWilliams, University of Southern
Maine;
Dan Pence, Southern Utah University; Marcella Thompson,
Univer-
sity of Arkansas; Georgeanna M. Tryban, Indiana State
University;
and Brenda S. Zicha, Charles Stewart Mott Community College.
I would also like to thank the reviewers of the first edition:
Peter Adler, University of Denver; Sheila M. Cordray, Oregon
State University; Mary Patrice Erdmans, University of North
Carolina–Greensboro; Valerie Jenness, University of
California–
Irvine; Frances V. Moulder, Three Rivers Community–
Technical
College; Karl T. Pfeiffer, University of Alaska; Martha L.
Shockey,
St. Ambrose University; Lisa Troyer, University of Iowa; and
Georgeanna M. Tryban, Indiana State University.
Lisa J. McIntyre
mcI26873_fm_i-xiv.indd xivmcI26873_fm_i-xiv.indd xiv
19/04/13 3:51 AM19/04/13 3:51 AM
Confirming Pages
1
INTRODUCTION
H ave you ever caught yourself thinking about things that
people do? Have you ever asked yourself, for example,
questions about everyday things like these:
Why do some students always sit in the back of the classroom
while others always sit in the front?
Why do African Americans on predominantly white college
campuses frequently say “hi” to other African Americans,
even if they don’t know them?
Why do we dress baby girls in pink and baby boys in blue?
Why do people generally not look at one another in
elevators—and always face front?
Why do young men, but not young women, spit?
Why do we go to such lengths to pretend we aren’t embar-
rassed when we have to get naked in front of a doctor?
Why do people from small towns tend to act differently from
people from big cities?
Why are most people less willing to seek professional help for
mental or emotional problems than for physical problems?
Sociologists are trained to find answers to questions about
people’s behavior. We are especially interested in
understanding
the effects that people have on one another.
Sociologists are convinced that much of people’s behavior is a
result of what other people do. A sociologist reviewing the
ques-
tions just listed would likely say that many of these behaviors
result from how people are influenced by others.
mcI26873_intro_001-004.indd 1mcI26873_intro_001-004.indd
1 4/9/13 12:57 PM4/9/13 12:57 PM
Confirming Pages
2 INTRODUCTION
This sociological conviction might offend you. Certainly, I like
to think of myself as independent minded; you, too, may like to
think that your behaviors are the results of choices you have
made
of your own free will. But allow me to persuade you that to
under-
stand people’s behavior and the choices they make, it is
important
to take into account the influence of others in their
environment.
Even when you think you are making your own choices, often
you are picking only from the fairly limited range of options
that
others allow you. The simple fact is that, depending on your
position
in society—your age, gender, race, social class, and so on—
people
expect and allow you to act in various ways. Society places
restric-
tions on your behavior with very little regard for your
preferences.
Of course, you can choose not to live up to society’s
expectations,
but if you decide to be contrary, you will pay a price. And,
depending
on the seriousness of your infraction, that price can range from
end-
less nagging by your parents to a prison sentence and even to
death!
Consider marriage. Surely, the decisions whether to get mar-
ried, whom to marry, and when are very personal decisions.
Actu-
ally, they are not. Examine this matter carefully and you will
find
that your marital choices are rather restricted. For example, in
the
United States, you can be married to only one person at a time.
And
(at least for the time being) you can marry only a person of the
opposite sex—unless you live in one of the several states that
allow
same-sex marriage. Until the late 1960s, many states even had
laws
requiring people to marry within their own racial group—if you
broke these laws, you could be sent to prison or exiled from the
state. 1
Chances are, your family places even more restrictions on your
marriage choices. Have you noticed that there are, in effect,
family
“rules” about whom you can marry? These rules may be
unspoken
but clear: Your parents may wish you to wed someone of your
own
race and religion and from the same educational and social-class
back-
ground. Of course, there is no law that says family rules must
be fol-
lowed, but we all know that families have ways of making us
suffer.
Even your friends may restrict your marriage (and dating)
choices. Consider how they would make you suffer if you
started
to date some seriously weird geek.
You really have to wonder, why does everyone care so much
about whom we marry? Now that is a sociological question!
So, What Is Sociology?
Here is a technical definition of sociology: Sociology is the
scientific
study of interactions and relations among human beings.
1 Some states have never rescinded these laws, but because
such racial restrictions
were ruled unconstitutional by the U.S. Supreme Court in 1967,
even where they do
exist, they do not have the force of law.
mcI26873_intro_001-004.indd 2mcI26873_intro_001-004.indd
2 4/9/13 12:57 PM4/9/13 12:57 PM
Confirming Pages
The Value of Sociology to Students 3
I hope the word scientific caught your attention. Including
that
word in the definition is a reminder that …
American Society for Legal History
Bringing the Law Back into the History of the Civil Rights
Movement
Author(s): KENNETH W. MACK
Source: Law and History Review, Vol. 27, No. 3 (Fall 2009),
pp. 657-669
Published by: American Society for Legal History
Stable URL: https://www.jstor.org/stable/40646061
Accessed: 31-12-2018 15:35 UTC
REFERENCES
Linked references are available on JSTOR for this article:
https://www.jstor.org/stable/40646061?seq=1&cid=pdf-
reference#references_tab_contents
You may need to log in to JSTOR to access the linked
references.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars,
researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information
technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about
JSTOR, please contact [email protected]
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the
Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms
American Society for Legal History is collaborating with
JSTOR to digitize, preserve and
extend access to Law and History Review
This content downloaded from 72.79.39.18 on Mon, 31 Dec
2018 15:35:26 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Bringing the Law Back into the History
of the Civil Rights Movement
KENNETH W. MACK
It is a pleasure to comment on Nancy MacLean's hugely
important book
Freedom is Not Enough: The Opening of the American
Workplace1 as an
example of what I might call "bringing the law back in" to the
history of
the civil rights movement. A generation ago, the idea that law
needed to
be introduced into this history would have seemed nonsensical.
At that
time, law provided one of the central touchstones in the
historical nar-
rative of the struggle for racial equality in American life.
Scholarship in
this area built on C. Vann Woodward's pioneering work on the
rise of Jim
Crow, which itself was written shortly after Woodward's
participation in
the Brown v. Board of Education litigation.2 The dominant
narrative began
with the legal construction of Jim Crow in the late nineteenth
century and
continued with the founding of the NAACP. Other actors came
along at
various points in the story, prominent among them New Deal-
era racial
liberals, World War II-era activists, midcentury social
scientists, Southern
civil rights leaders and movements, and eventually black
power. The end
point was marked by the litigation and legislative victories of
the 1950s
and '60s, which finally wrote back into law what had been
taken away by
segregationist white Southerners and a compliant Supreme
Court in the
1 . Nancy MacLean, Freedom is Not Enough: The Opening of
the American Workplace
(Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2006).
2. C. Vann Woodward, The Strange Career of Jim Crow, 3rd
rev. ed. (New York: Oxford
University Press, 1974).
Kenneth W. Mack is a professor of law at Harvard Law School
<[email protected]
.harvard.edu>.
Law and History Review Fall 2009, Vol. 27, No. 3
© 2009 by the Board of Trustees of the University of Illinois
This content downloaded from 72.79.39.18 on Mon, 31 Dec
2018 15:35:26 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
658 Law and History Review, Fall 2009
late nineteenth century. The implicit methodological take on
law was that
state and federal statutes, as well as court decisions, provided
an impor-
tant impetus, or at the very least a validation, for racial change
- first for
white Southerners as they created the Jim Crow legal regime
and later for
segregation's opponents as they reinscribed racial equality onto
the core
narrative of American life.3
In the last generation, however, this central preoccupation with
law has
come under attack. In the social history of the civil rights
movement, the
new model that emerged trained its sights on community-level
protest and
organization. Its central project was to decenter the NAACP,
the Supreme
Court, Congress, Martin Luther King, Jr., and the Congress of
Racial Equal-
ity (CORE) as the central players in the story. Instead, scholars
focused on
the ways that activists and local actors built up movements and
alliances
outside the bounds of, or in conflict with, the figures and
organizations
who once dominated the story.4 Of course, there were other
new brands
of civil rights scholarship, inflected through labor history,
international
history, and the history of white Northerners and Southerners
during the
civil rights era. In taking on the old scholarship on its own turf,
however,
local studies - particularly those of the Southern movement -
often set the
tone. If there was a methodological take on law in the new
histories, it was
often that law was epiphenomenal, not that important to local
movement
actors, and sometimes even corrosive of local community
organizing.5
3. See, for example, Harvard Sitkoff, The Struggle for Black
Equality, 1954-1980 (New
York: Farar, Straus and Giroux; Hill and Wang, 1981);
Woodward, Strange Career.
4. See, for example, Charles M. Payne, I've Got the Light of
Freedom: The Organizing
Tradition and the Mississippi Freedom Struggle (1995;
Berkeley: University of California
Press, 2007); John Dittmer, Local People: The Struggle for
Civil Rights in Mississippi (Urbana:
University of Illinois Press, 1994). For good summaries of this
scholarly shift, see Tomiko
Brown-Nagin, "The Impact of Lawyer-Client Disengagement on
the NAACP's Campaign to
Implement Brown v. Board of Education in Atlanta," in From
the Grassroots to the Supreme
Court: Brown v. Board of Education and American Democracy,
ed. Peter Lau (Durham: Duke
University Press, 2004), 227, 228; Payne, I've Got the Light of
Freedom, 413^1; Steven
Lawson, "Freedom Then, Freedom Now: The Historiography of
the Civil Rights Movement,"
American Historical Review 96 (1991): 456.
5. Payne, I've Got the Light of Freedom, 315; Doug Me Adam,
Political Process and the
Development of Black Insurgency 1930-1970, 2nd ed.
(Chicago: University of Chicago Press,
1999), 133-34, 184-85; Aldon D. Morris, The Origins of the
Civil Rights Movement: Black
Communities Organizing for Change (New York: Free Press,
1984), 35-37. By contrast, many
scholars who focus on the Northern civil rights movement,
which operated in a region without
explicit legal segregation, have explicitly grappled with law as
a site of organization and as a
means of structuring the choices made by movement actors and
their opponents. Thomas J.
Sugrue, Sweet Land of Liberty: The Forgotten Struggle for
Civil Rights in the North (New York:
Random House, 2008); Martha Biondi, To Stand and Fight: The
Struggle for Civil Rights in
New York City (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2003);
Robert Self, American Babylon:
This content downloaded from 72.79.39.18 on Mon, 31 Dec
2018 15:35:26 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Bringing the Law Back 659
The legal history of the civil rights movement moved in the
opposite
direction, and focused on the NAACP and the Supreme Court.
Institutional
histories of the NAACP and biographies of famous civil rights
figures domi-
nated the field. In its latest incarnation, this work has diverged
completely
from the central concerns of historians, and, most notably in
the work of
Michael Klarman, has focused on the political science-inspired
question
of whether the Supreme Court, acting alone, can effect social
change.6
The genius of Nancy's book - aside from its breadth, depth and
subtle-
ty - is that it is the first major synthesis to bring law back into
the social
history of civil rights politics. Nancy comes from the tradition
of social
history, with its focus on how people remake their political
worlds in ev-
eryday life. But the centerpiece of her story is Title VII of the
Civil Rights
Act of 1964 and how ordinary people responded to the bare
grant of legal
freedom that the statute conferred and found that it was not
enough. Be-
ginning in the mid-1960s, these activists and other actors began
to remake
what Nancy calls the "common sense" of America's ordinary
expectations
of race, gender, and place in the workforce, and by extension in
the larger
realm of public life (2). In fact, Freedom is Not Enough could
take its place
alongside the mainstream 1980s and 1990s legal histories
written outside
the civil rights context - with its model of law as an arena of
struggle in
which contending groups and individuals try to put their own
stamp on
what citizenship means in American life.7
Indeed, the story as it emerges here compliments some of the
newest
work in the legal history of the civil rights movement. For
instance, Nancy
shows how both NAACP and Legal Defense Fund (LDF)
lawyers were key
Race and the Struggle for Postwar Oakland (Princeton:
Princeton University Press, 2003);
Jeanne Theoharis and Komozi Woodard, Freedom North: Black
Freedom Struggles Outside
the South 1940-1980 (New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2003).
6. Michael J. Klarman, From Jim Crow to Civil Rights: The
Supreme Court and the Struggle
for Racial Equality (New York: Oxford University Press,
2004); Mark V. Tushnet, Making
Civil Rights Law: Thurgood Marshall and the Supreme Court,
1936-1961 (Oxford University
Press, 1994); Genna Rae McNeil, Groundwork: Charles
Hamilton Houston and the Struggle
for Civil Rights (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania
Press, 1983); Gilbert Ware, Wil-
liam Hastie: Grace Under Pressure (New York: Oxford
University Press, 1984). Klarman
generalized the argument first put forth in Gerald N.
Rosenberg, The Hollow Hope: Can
Courts Bring About Social Change? (Chicago: University of
Chicago Press, 1991), especially
pages 157-69, 336-42. Mark Tushnet's history of the NAACP's
desegregation campaign
was an important exception, with its grounding of the campaign
in its connection to local
communities. Mark V. Tushnet, The NAACP's Legal Strategy
Against Segregated Education,
1925-1950 (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press,
1987).
7. lhe most prominent examples or that vein or legal history are
the essays collected in
the bicentennial issue of the Journal of American History,
republished as The Constitution
and American Life, ed. David Thelen (Ithaca: Cornell
University Press, 1988).
This content downloaded from 72.79.39.18 on Mon, 31 Dec
2018 15:35:26 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
660 Law and History Review, Fall 2009
players in perhaps the most successful of the early movements
for racial
equality in the workplace - that which focused on
desegregating Southern
mill workforces (76-90, 108-9). She challenges the common
interpretation of
the NAACP as a unitary, elite-driven organization caught up in
noneconomic
rights and the struggle to implement Brown in the South, and
which ceded
the cutting edge to other groups. Some NAACP and LDF
leaders, notably
Roy Wilkins and Thurgood Marshall, coexisted uneasily with
newer players
on the scene as the direct action phase of the movement heated
up. Both
organizations, however, contained a variety of individuals and
institutional
frameworks for advancing their agendas, and both found new
roles for their
advocates and lawyers at the leading edge of reform once Title
VII offered
them the chance to work with activists and movements on the
ground and
change the common sense that governed the American
workplace. There
simply hasn't been enough exploration of the NAACP archives
in the years
before and after Brown, as the main line of scholarship has
followed the
familiar school desegregation litigation tracks.8
Some of the new work that has done this, notably by Risa
Goluboff, Da-
vid Engstrom, Sophia Lee, and Paul Frymer, has described an
NAACP that
drove the economic agenda of civil rights in a number of fields
and institu-
tions in the post-World War II era. Goluboff has uncovered the
organiza-
tion's labor discrimination litigation of the 1940s which helped
redefine just
what "civil rights" meant in American legal discourse.
Engstrom has found
that the NAACP was a leading player in defining the structure
and agenda
of the state-level FEPCs that proliferated once the drive for a
permanent
federal FEPC stalled in the late 1940s, and that this agenda
yielded legisla-
tive proposals that were sometimes innovative even by post-
1964 standards.
Lee has examined the NAACP's Cold War-era administrative
litigation
before the National Labor Relations Board that ultimately
resulted in a rul-
ing that incorporated a nondiscrimination mandate into unions'
duty of fair
representation. Frymer has briefly surveyed the NAACP's labor
advocacy
during the two decades after World War II and has found an
organization
that mobilized a variety of aggressive strategies in and out of
court that,
by the 1960s, began to produce litigation that was far more
radical than
anything the legislature or executive branch was prepared to
entertain.9
While Goluboff argues that the labor cases that she chronicles
disappeared
8. For an essential corrective to the standard scholarly
orientation, see Patricia Sullivan,
Lift Every Voice: The NAACP and the Making of the Civil
Rights Movement (New York:
The New Press, 2009).
9. Risa Goluboff, The Lost Promise of Civil Rights (Cambodge:
Harvard University Press,
2007); David Freeman Engstrom, "The Taft Proposal of 1946
and the (Non-) Making of
American Fair Employment Law," Green Bag 2d 9 (2006): 181;
David Freeman Engstrom,
"The Lost Origins of American Fair Employment Law: State
Fair Employment Practices
This content downloaded from 72.79.39.18 on Mon, 31 Dec
2018 15:35:26 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Bringing the Law Back 661
around 1950, taken together the work of these scholars suggest,
as I have
argued elsewhere, that there are "reasons to doubt" the standard
narrative
of a "pervasive, coherent, and stable legal liberalism" emerging
by 1950
that replaced the social democratic civil rights politics of the
previous de-
cades with a focus on Brown, formal noneconomic rights, and
elite visions
of civil rights politics.10 Nancy takes this story straight
through the 1970s,
and points to an underemphasized aspect of this process: civil
rights advo-
cates changed everyday understandings of ordinary Americans
about who
belongs in what jobs, producing a ripple effect that continues
to transform
the nation's workforces and its public life.
Nancy's book also nicely compliments current work in legal
history in
showing how labor market regulation was key to the attack that
civil rights
activists launched against racial exclusion in the mill and
construction
industries in the aftermath of Title VII. Government contracts
are a crucial
factor in her story and provided the lever that allowed activists
to hold a
potential club over the heads of both private employers and
unions - and
just as importantly, to offer an ideological justification for that
position
that fit comfortably within the tenets of post-New Deal liberal
politics (82,
95-96). Indeed, she takes forward the story that has been
mapped out in
the work of scholars such Willie Forbath, Risa Goluboff, and
myself, who
have argued that New Deal-era labor market regulation and
government
contracts provided the opening wedge that allowed civil rights
progressives
to begin to describe and attack race discrimination in private
life.11
Bureaus and the Politics of Regulatory Design, 1943-1964"
(PhD. diss., Yale University,
2006), 24-264; Sophia Z. Lee, "Hotspots in a Cold War: The
NAACP's Postwar Workplace
Constitutionalism, 1948-1964," Law and History Review 26
(2008): 327; Paul Frymer, Black
and Blue: African Americans, the Labor Movement, and the
Decline of the Democratic Party
(Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2008).
10. Kenneth W. Mack, "Rethinking Civil Rights Lawyering and
Politics in the Era before
Brown, Yale Law Journal 1 15 (2005): 256, 353. Of course, one
can debate the economic and
political consequences of the NAACP's workplace advocacy, as
do both Judith Stein and
Paul Frymer in asserting that the civil rights bar's creative
advocacy was channeled by the
structure of the political and legal system into channels that
blunted its radical potential. Stein
argues that Title VII litigation was conducted within a narrow
framework that contributed to
the decline of the industrial workforce. Frymer is far more
admiring of the radicalism of the
civil rights lawyers' efforts, but argues that those efforts,
guided by existing state structures,
drove a wedge between the civil rights movement and
organized labor. Judith Stein, Running
Steel, Running America: Race, Economic Policy, and the
Decline of Liberalism (Chapel Hill:
University of North Carolina Press, 1998), 69-91; Frymer,
Black and Blue, 44-97.
1 1 . William Forbath, "Caste, Class, and Equal Citizenship,"
Michigan Law Review 98
(1999): 1; Goluboff, Lost Promise of Civil Rights, 81-1 10;
Mack, "Rethinking Civil Rights
Lawyering and Politics," 331^-2; Kenneth W. Mack, "Law and
Mass Politics in the Making
of the Civil Rights Lawyer, 1931-1941," Journal of American
History 93 (2006): 37, 62.
This content downloaded from 72.79.39.18 on Mon, 31 Dec
2018 15:35:26 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
662 Law and History Review, Fall 2009
Perhaps the most important of these progressives was Charles
Houston
who, shortly before his untimely death in 1950, offered a vision
of New
Deal-era regulation of economic life as a basis for attacking
race discrimi-
nation by private actors in a wide swath of industry. Houston
emerged as
perhaps the dominant player in shaping the approach of liberal
organiza-
tions to the emerging state-level FEPC regime.12 His
unfinished work gives
us much to consider as we contemplate the federal government
taking a
financial stake in large sectors of the twenty-first-century
economy, and
as we consider the new racial politics that may attach to the
nation's first
African American president.
Finally, Nancy's book is important for its amazingly broad
scope. Tak-
ing in African Americans, Mexican Americans, women's rights
reformers,
Jewish activists, and political conservatives in one book shows
one way
to move beyond what historians such as Scott Kurashige have
called the
"binary logic" of race relations history, and to cover more
ground than
would ordinarily seem possible to do in one monograph.13
I'd like to use the remainder of my space to return to
methodological
questions raised by the fact that Nancy is a social historian,
and to offer
some thoughts on how a legal historian might react to the book.
To make
my own methodological commitments clear, I come from the
Legal Real-
ist tradition, and thus tend to focus my efforts on the gaps,
conflicts, and
ambiguities in formal law, and on the legal contours of social
life outside
formal institutions of law. I'd like to suggest that a realist
perspective may
have something to contribute to Nancy's pathbreaking work.14
The framing device encompassed in Freedom is Not Enough is
actually
a formalist, rather than a realist one. The book is framed by
Lyndon John-
son's famous 1965 speech at Howard University, where the
President told
Americans bluntly that the recent civil rights legislation had
forced them
to face up to the proposition that "freedom is not enough" to
guaranty true
racial equality. Johnson told his mostly black listeners, as well
as the na-
tion, that Title VII and its accompanying legislation merely
granted formal
equality - freedom from facially exclusionary practices - to
members of
previously subordinated racial groups (5, 73-74). Nancy's book
picks up on
this interpretation to argue that the issue of substantive
equality - the actual
12. Mack, "Rethinking Civil Rights Lawyering and Politics,"
344-45; David Freeman
Engstrom, "The Lost Origins of American Fair Employment
Law: Regulatory Choice and
the Making of Modern Civil Rights, 1943-1964" (unpublished
paper, 2009), 63 & n. 277.
13. Scott Kurashige, The Shifting Grounds of Race: Black and
Japanese Americans in
the Making of Multiethnic Los Angeles (Princeton: Princeton
University Press, 2008), 6.
14. The exact definitions of Legal Realism and formalism
remain hotly contested to this
day. My description of realism is strongly influenced by the
big-tent definition offered in
William W. Fisher III, Morton J. Horwitz, and Thomas Reed,
eds., American Legal Realism
(New York: Oxford University Press, 1993), xi-xv.
This content downloaded from 72.79.39.18 on Mon, 31 Dec
2018 15:35:26 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Bringing the Law Back 663
guaranty of inclusion in workplaces around the nation - would
come to the
fore only when activists entered the fray in the years following
the statute's
enactment. At one level, the book might be simply stating a
truism known to
lawyers and nonlawyers alike - that statutes are not self-
executing without
some further action.15 But I think that, given the weight which
this framing
device bears in the text, she means more than this. The book
seems to rely
on the distinction between one kind of equality that the statute
confers, and
another type of equality that only comes to the fore once
ordinary people
and activists - who tend to drive the story in much of social
history - come
into play.
In black politics, the analogue to the distinction that Johnson
mobilized
was Bayard Rustin's famous essay, "From Protest to Politics,"
which ap-
peared not long before Johnson delivered his speech. Rustin
divided the
civil rights movement into its classical phase (1954-64), when
African
Americans pushed for the removal of formal barriers to
equality, and its
political phase, when they began to push for substantive
equality in eco-
nomic life, education, and other areas.16 Both Johnson and
Rustin relied
on the distinction between formal equality (removing explicit
barriers to
participation) and substantive equality (actual African
American participa-
tion in the nation's institutions). In their telling, the issue of
substantive
equality emerges only when social movements try to put formal
rights into
practice. I'd like to suggest that the distinction isn't so neat.
In fact, the book's interpretation of the period before Title VII
was enacted
is somewhat conventional (unlike what it does with the statute's
aftermath).
In this telling, the rejection of a permanent federal FEPC in the
late 1940s
signaled the end of the road for nondiscrimination rights in the
workplace
until 1964. There was advocacy around these issues, to be sure
- for in-
stance, in state FEPCs, in the labor movement, and within the
Truman ad-
ministration. There was no real debate, however, about the
legal contours of
the right to nondiscriminatory employment until social
movement activists
renewed the fight during the 1960s (30, 38^4).
However, recent work in legal history calls this periodization
into ques-
tion. For instance, Sophia Lee has shown that the lawyers and
activists
within the NAACP's national office were steadily working their
way to-
15. Indeed, NAACP labor activist Herbert Hill made this exact
point in the aftermath
of the statute's enactment: "Title VII not self-enforcing."
Nancy MacLean, "Achieving the
Promise of the Civil Rights Act: Herbert Hill and the NAACP's
Fight for Jobs and Justice,"
Labor: Studies in Working-Class History of the Americas 3
(2006): 13, 14.
16. "From Protest to Politics: The Future of the Civil Rights
Movement," in Time on Two
Crosses: The Collected Writings of Bayard Rustin, ed. Devon
W. Carbado and Donald Weise
(San Francisco: Cleis Press, 2003), 1 16. Rustin's recent
biographer notes that Johnson's Howard
speech "framed civil rights in terms that Rustin himself might
have crafted." John D'Emilio,
Lost Prophet: The Life and Times of Bayard Rustin (New York:
Free Press, 2003), 417.
This content downloaded from 72.79.39.18 on Mon, 31 Dec
2018 15:35:26 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
664 Law and History Review, Fall 2009
wards the issue of substantive equality as early as the 1950s, in
little-known
labor union litigation before the National Labor Relations
Board. They
took on, as well, another problem that is typically seen as not
reemerging
until the 1960s - the question of whether legal mandates
reached putatively
private conduct by discriminatory unions. Anthony Chen has
done com-
plimentary work in his recent article on opposition to state-
level FEPCs,
where opponents charged that nondiscrimination mandates
would result in
"quotas" that would guarantee minority inclusion in the
workforce. In 1946,
Republican Senator Robert Taft went so far as to propose a new
federal
FEPC that would have been empowered to grant relief that,
under some
circumstances, might fairly be read to include group-based
representation in
the workplace. From the moment the FEPCs were proposed,
they brought
to the table the question of what form of "equality" they were
supposed to
foster. Indeed, the debate goes even further back to the New
Deal era, when
the black boycott movements for jobs in African American
neighborhoods
and the movement for racial equality within the government
contracting
workforce demanded, and received, mandates for the inclusion
of specific
numbers of African Americans in the workplace.17
I'd like to suggest that Rustin, and Johnson, exhibited a degree
of histori-
cal blindness when they argued that the previous movement had
focused
solely on formal equality, while substantive equality was the
work of the
future. As a veteran of the left branch of civil rights politics,
Rustin must
have known this to be untrue. There is a good chance that
Johnson and
his aides did also. Indeed, Richard Goodwin, the White House
aide who
helped draft Johnson's speech, was a lawyer and a former law
clerk to
Justice Felix Frankfurter, who himself had been a proto-realist
figure in his
youth. By 1965, however, Rustin was shedding his own
vagabond past and
moving to a more respectable place within the movement, while
Johnson
and his advisors were trying to convince the American public
that the
struggle for racial equality was not over. Each had powerful
incentives to
17. Lee, "Hotspots in a Cold War," 328, 366-68; Anthony
Chen, "The Hitlerian Rule of
Quotas': Racial Conservatism and the Politics of Fair
Employment Legislation in New York
State, 1941-1945," Journal of American History 92 (2006):
1238; David Engstrom, "The
Taft Proposal of 1946"; Michèle F. Pacifico, '"Don't Buy
Where You Can't Work' : The New
Negro Alliance of Washington," Washington History 6 (1994):
67, 79-80; Robert Weaver,
"An Experiment in Negro Labor," Opportunity 14 (October
1936): 295; Marc W. Kruman,
"Quotas for Blacks: The Public Works Administration and the
Black Construction Worker,"
Labor History 16 (1975): 37, 44; Paul Moreno, From Direct
Action to Affirmative Action:
Fair Employment Law and Policy in America, 1933-1972
(Baton Rouge: LSU Press, 1997),
30-65. Taft's proposal was inartfully drafted, but group
representation is one fair reading of
its language. A number of observers within the NAACP and the
labor movement read it as
contemplating group-based relief and were uneasy with it for
that reason. Engstrom, "Lost
Origins of American Fair Employment Law," 151-53.
This content downloaded from 72.79.39.18 on Mon, 31 Dec
2018 15:35:26 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Bringing the Law Back 665
suppress some of the contingency and malleability in the
history of civil
rights politics up to 1964, and at least some of that suppression
has made
it into our own histories of the movement.18
In addition, I'd like to note that in Nancy's narrative, the debate
over
substantive equality emerges "away" from law, as social
movement activ-
ists try to transform the formal rights encompassed within the
statute into
practical inclusion in the workforce. For a book about the
social conse-
quences that attach to a particular legal enactment, there is
only a limited
discussion of the enactment itself and the complex history and
debates that
preceded it. In Freedom is Not Enough, the engine that moves
the story
along is encompassed in the words and deeds of the job
seekers, workers
and activists who struggle with the statutory mandate of formal
equality.
But it's not at all clear that the statute itself grants only formal
rights - or
at least, that the issue of substantive equality emerges only
outside of the
formal bounds of law. Just to take one example, the legal
scholar Owen
Fiss spent the early part of his career showing that the equality
principle
encompassed in any nondiscrimination mandate actually
consists of two
principles, not one: (1) removal of formal barriers to
participation, and (2)
actual inclusion in American institutions.19 Indeed, as early as
1971, Fiss
argued that the employment law regime that emerged in the
aftermath of
Title VII was amenable to both interpretations.20 So it may
very well be …
Excerpts from the Majority Opinion in the Dred Scott Case
(1857) by Chief Justice Taney
The question is simply this: Can a negro, whose ancestors were
imported into this country, and sold as slaves, become a member
of the political community formed and brought into existence by
the Constitution of the United States, and as such become
entitled to all the rights, and privileges, and immunities,
guarantied by that instrument to the citizen? One of which
rights is the privilege of suing in a court of the United States in
the cases specified in the Constitution....
We think [people of African ancestry] are not, and that they are
not included, and were not intended to be included, under the
word "citizens" in the Constitution, and can therefore claim
none of the rights and privileges which that instrument provides
for and secures to citizens of the United States…
For if they were so received, and entitled to the privileges and
immunities of citizens, it would exempt them from the operation
of the special laws and from the police regulations which they
considered to be necessary for their own safety. It would give to
persons of the negro race, who were recognized as citizens in
any one State of the Union, the right to enter every other State
whenever they pleased, singly or in companies, without pass or
passport, and without obstruction, to sojourn there as long as
they pleased, to go where they pleased at every hour of the day
or night without molestation, unless they committed some
violation of law for which a white man would be punished; and
it would give them the full liberty of speech in public and in
private upon all subjects upon which its own citizens might
speak; to hold public meetings upon political affairs, and to
keep and carry arms wherever they went. And all of this would
be done in the face of the subject race of the same color, both
free and slaves, and inevitably producing discontent and
insubordination among them, and endangering the peace and
safety of the State.
The act of Congress, upon which the plaintiff relies, declares
that slavery and involuntary servitude, except as a punishment
for crime, shall be forever prohibited in all that part of the
territory ceded by France, under the name of Louisiana, which
lies northand not included within the limits of Missouri. And
the difficulty which meets us at the threshold of this part of the
inquiry is, whether Congress was authorized to pass this law
under any of the powers granted to it by the Constitution; for if
the authority is not given by that instrument, it is the duty of
this court to declare it void and inoperative, and incapable of
conferring freedom upon any one who is held as a slave under
the laws of any one of the States.
The power to expand the territory of the United States by the
admission of new states is plainly given. But the power of
Congress over the person or property of a citizen [is] regulated
and plainly defined by the Constitution itself. And when the
Territory becomes a part of the United States, the Federal
Government enters upon it with its powers over the citizen
strictly defined, and limited by the Constitution.It has no power
of any kind beyond it; and it cannot, when it enters a Territory
of the United States, put off its character, and assume
discretionary or despotic powers which the Constitution has
denied to it.
. . . [T]he rights of private property have been guarded with . . .
care. Thus the rights of property are united with the rights of
person, and placed on the same ground by the fifth amendment
to the Constitution, which provides that no person shall be
deprived of life, liberty, and property, without due process of
law. And an act of Congress which deprives a citizen of the
United States of his liberty or property, merely because he came
himself or brought his property into a particular Territory of the
United States, and who had committed no offence against the
laws, could hardly be dignified with the name of due process of
law.
Excerpts from the Majority Opinion in Elk v. Wilkins (1884) by
Justice Gray
The petition . . . clearly implies that he was born a member of
one of the Indian tribes within the limits of the United States
which still exists and is recognized as a tribe by the government
of the United States. Though the plaintiff alleges that he 'had
fully and completely surrendered himself to the jurisdiction of
the United States,' he does not allege that the United States
accepted his surrender, or that he has ever been naturalized, or
taxed, or in any way recognized or treated as a citizen by the
state or by the United States. Nor is it contended by his counsel
that there is any statute or treaty that makes him a citizen.
The Indian tribes, being within the territorial limits of the
United States, were not, strictly speaking, foreign states; but
they were alien nations, distinct political communities, with
whom the United States might and habitually did deal, as they
thought fit, either through treaties made by the president and
senate, or through acts of congress in the ordinary forms of
legislation.
Chief Justice TANEY, in the passage cited for the plaintiff from
his opinion in Scott v. Sandford, 19 How. 393, 404, did not
affirm or imply that either the Indian tribes, or individual
members of those tribes, had the right, beyond other foreigners,
to become citizens of their own will, without being naturalized
by the United States. His words were: 'They' (the Indian tribes)
'may without doubt, like the subjects of any foreign
government, be naturalized by the authority of congress, and
become citizens of a state, and of the United States; and if an
individual should leave his nation or tribe, and take up his
abode among the white population, he would be entitled to all
the rights and privileges which would belong to an emigrant
from any other foreign people.' But an emigrant from any
foreign state cannot become a citizen of the United States
without a formal renunciation of his old allegiance, and an
acceptance by the United States of that renunciation through
such form of naturalization as may be required law.
The main object of the opening sentence of the fourteenth
amendment was to settle the question, upon which there had
been a difference of opinion throughout the country and in this
court, as to the citizenship of free negroes, (Scott v. Sandford,
19 How. 393;) and to put it beyond doubt that all persons, white
or black, and whether formerly slaves or not, born or
naturalized in the United States, and owing no allegiance to any
alien power, should be citizens of the United States and of the
state in which they reside.
Persons not thus subject to the jurisdiction of the United States
at the time of birth cannot become so afterwards, except by
being naturalized, either individually, as by proceedings under
the naturalization acts; or collectively, as by the force of a
treaty by which foreign territory is acquired. Indians born
within the territorial limits of the United States, members of,
and owing immediate allegiance to, one of the Indiana tribes,
(an alien though dependent power,) although in a geographical
sense born in the United States, are no more 'born in the United
States and subject to the jurisdiction thereof,' within the
meaning of the first section of the fourteenth amendment, than
the children of subjects of any foreign government born within
the domain of that government, or the children born within the
United States, of ambassadors or other public ministers of
foreign nations. This view is confirmed by the second section
of the fourteenth amendment, which provides that
'representatives shall be apportioned among the several states
according to their respective numbers, counting the whole
number of persons in each state, excluding Indians not taxed.'
Slavery having been abolished, and the persons formerly held as
slaves made citizens, this clauses fixing the apportionment of
representatives has abrogated so much of the corresponding
clause of the original constitution as counted only three-fifths
of such persons. But Indians not taxed are still excluded from
the count, for the reason that they are not citizens. Their
absolute exclusion from the basis of representation, in which all
other persons are now included, is wholly inconsistent with
their being considered citizens.
Since the ratification of the fourteenth amendment, congress has
passed several acts for naturalizing Indians of certain tribes,
which would have been superfluous if they were, or might
become without any action of the government, citizens of the
United States.
'But an Indian cannot make himself a citizen of the United
States without the consent and co-operation of the government.
The fact that he has abandoned his nomadic life or tribal
relations, and adopted the habits and manners of civilized
people, may be a good reason why he should be made a citizen
of the United States, but does not of itself make him one. To be
a citizen of the United States is a political privilege which no
one, not born to, can assume without its consent in some form.
The plaintiff, not being a citizen of the United States under the
fourteenth amendment of the constitution, has been deprived of
no right secured by the fifteenth amendment, and cannot
maintain this action. Judgment affirmed.
Excerpts from the Dissenting Opinion in Elk v. Wilkins (1884)
by Justice Harlan
At the adoption of the constitution there were, in many of the
states, Indians, not members of any tribe, who constituted a part
of the people for whose benefit the state governments were
established. This is apparent from that clause of article 1, § 3,
which requires, in the apportionment of representatives and
direct taxes among the several states 'according to their
respective numbers,' the exclusion of 'Indians not taxed.' This
implies that there were, at that time, in the United States,
Indians who were taxed; that is, were subject to taxation by the
laws of the state of which they were residents. Indians not taxed
were those who held tribal relations, and therefore were not
subject to the authority of any state, and were subject only to
the authority of the United States, under the power conferred
upon congress in reference to Indian tribes in this country. The
same provision is retained in the fourteenth amendment.
By the act of April 9, 1866, entitled 'An act to protect all
persons in the United States in their civil rights, and furnish
means for their vindication,' (14 St. 27,) it is provided that 'all
persons born in the United States, and not subject to any foreign
power, excluding Indians not taxed, are hereby declared to be
citizens of the United States.' This, so far as we are aware, is
the first general enactment making persons of the Indian race
citizens of the United States. Numerous statutes and treaties
previously provided for all the individual members of particular
Indian tribes becoming, in certain contingencies, citizens of the
United States. But the act of 1866 reached Indians not in tribal
relations. Beyond question, by that act, national citizenship was
conferred directly upon all persons in this country, of whatever
race, (excluding only 'Indians not taxed,') who were born within
the territorial limits of the United States, and were not subject
to any foreign power.
The entire debate (Over the Civil Rights Act of 1866) shows,
with singular clearness, indeed, with absolute certainty, that no
senator who participated in it, whether in favor of or in
opposition to the measure, doubted that the bill as passed
admitted, and was intended to admit, to national citizenship
Indians who abandoned their tribal relations and became
residents of one of the states or territories, within the full
jurisdiction of the United States. It was so interpreted by
President Johnson, who, in his veto message, said: 'By the first
section of the bill all persons born in the United States, and not
subject to any foreign power, excluding Indians not taxed, are
declared to be citizens of the United States. This provision
comprehends the Chinese of the Pacific states, Indians subject
to taxation, the people called gypsies, as well as the entire race
designated as blacks, persons of color, negroes, mulattoes, and
persons of African blood. Every individual of those races, born
in the United States, is, by the bill, made a citizen of the United
States.'
If it be also said that, since the adoption of the fourteenth
amendment, congress has enacted statutes providing for the
citizenship of Indians, our answer is that those statutes had
reference to tribes, the members of which could not, while they
continued in tribal relations, acquire the citizenship granted by
the fourteenth amendment. Those statutes did not deal with
individual Indians who had severed their tribal connections and
were residents within the states of the Union, under the
complete jurisdiction of the United States. There is nothing in
the history of the adoption of the fourteenth amendment which,
in our opinion, justifies the conclusion that only those Indians
are included in its grant of citizenship who were, at the time of
their birth, subject to the complete jurisdiction of the United
States. As already stated, according to the doctrines of the
court, in this case,—if we do not wholly misapprehend the
effect of its decision,—the plaintiff, if born while his parents
were members of an Indian tribe, would not be embraced by the
amendment even had he been, at the time it was adopted, a
permanent resident of one of the states, subject to taxation, and,
in fact, paying property and personal taxes, to the full extent
required of the white race in the same state.
It seems to us that the fourteenth amendment, in so far as it was
intended to confer national citizenship upon persons of the
Indian race, is robbed of its vital force by a construction which
excludes from such citizenship those who, although born in
tribal relations, are within the complete jurisdiction of the
United States. There were, in some of our states and territories
at the time the amendment was submitted by congress, many
Indians who had finally left their tribes and come within the
complete jurisdiction of the United States. They were as fully
prepared for citizenship as were or are vast numbers of the
white and colored races in the same localities. Is it conceivable
that the statesmen who framed, the congress which submitted,
and the people who adopted that amendment intended to confer
citizenship, national and state, upon the entire population in this
country of African descent, (the larger part of which was shortly
before held in slavery,) and, by the same constitutional
provision, to exclude from such citizenship Indians who had
never been in slavery, and who, by becoming bona fide
residents of states and territories within the complete
jurisdiction of the United States, had evinced a purpose to
abandon their former mode of life, and become a part of the
people of the United States? If this question be answered in the
negative, as we think it must be, then we are justified in
withholding our assent to the doctrine which excludes the
plaintiff from the body of citizens of the United States upon the
ground that his parents were, when he was born, members of an
Indian tribe; for, if he can be excluded upon any such ground, it
must necessarily follow that the fourteenth amendment did not
grant citizenship even to Indians who, although born in tribal
relations, were, at its adoption, severed from their tribes,
subject to the complete jurisdiction as well of the United States
as of the state or territory in which they resided.
Excerpts from the Majority Opinion in U.S. v. Wong Kim Ark
(1898) by Justice Gray
The Fourteenth Amendment of the Constitution, in the
declaration that
all persons born or naturalized in the United States, and subject
to the jurisdiction thereof, are citizens of the United States and
of the State wherein they reside,
contemplates two sources of citizenship, and two only: birth and
naturalization. Citizenship by naturalization can only be
acquired by naturalization under the authority and in the forms
of law. But citizenship by birth is established by the mere fact
of birth under the circumstances defined in the Constitution.
Every person born in the United States, and subject to the
jurisdiction thereof, becomes at once a citizen of the United
States, and needs no naturalization. A person born out of the
jurisdiction of the United States can only become a citizen by
being naturalized, either by treaty, as in the case[p703] of the
annexation of foreign territory, or by authority of Congress,
exercised either by declaring certain classes of persons to be
citizens, as in the enactments conferring citizenship upon
foreign-born children of citizens, or by enabling foreigners
individually to become citizens by proceedings in the judicial
tribunals, as in the ordinary provisions of the naturalization
acts.
The power of naturalization, vested in Congress by the
Constitution, is a power to confer citizenship, not a power to
take it away. "A naturalized citizen," said Chief Justice
Marshall,
becomes a member of the society, possessing all the rights of a
native citizen, and standing, in the view of the Constitution, on
the footing of a native. The Constitution does not authorize
Congress to enlarge or abridge those rights. The simple power
of the National Legislature is to prescribe a uniform rule of
naturalization, and the exercise of this power exhausts it so far
as respects the individual. The Constitution then takes him up,
and, among other rights, extends to him the capacity of suing in
the courts of the United States, precisely under the same
circumstances under which a native might sue.
Osborn v. United States Bank, 9 Wheat. 738, 827. Congress
having no power to abridge the rights conferred by the
Constitution upon those who have become naturalized citizens
by virtue of acts of Congress, a fortiori no act or omission of
Congress, as to providing for the naturalization of parents or
children of a particular race, can affect citizenship acquired as a
birthright, by virtue of the Constitution itself, without any aid
of legislation. The Fourteenth Amendment, while it leaves the
power where it was before, in Congress, to regulate
naturalization, has conferred no authority upon Congress to
restrict the effect of birth, declared by the Constitution to
constitute a sufficient and complete right to citizenship.
No one doubts that the Amendment, as soon as it was
promulgated, applied to persons of African descent born in the
United States, wherever the birthplace of their parents might
have been, and yet, for two years afterwards, there was no
statute authorizing persons of that race to be naturalized. If the
omission or the refusal of Congress to permit certain[p704]
classes of persons to be made citizens by naturalization could
be allowed the effect of correspondingly restricting the classes
of persons who should become citizens.by birth, it would be in
the power of Congress, at any time, by striking negroes out of
the naturalization laws, and limiting those laws, as they were
formerly limited, to white persons only, to defeat the main
purpose of the Constitutional Amendment.
The fact, therefore, that acts of Congress or treaties have not
permitted Chinese persons born out of this country to become
citizens by naturalization, cannot exclude Chinese persons born
in this country from the operation of the broad and clear words
of the Constitution, "All persons born in the United States, and
subject to the jurisdiction thereof, are citizens of the United
States."
VII. Upon the facts agreed in this case, the American
citizenship which Wong Kim Ark acquired by birth within the
United States has not been lost or taken away by anything
happening since his birth. No doubt he might himself, after
coming of age, renounce this citizenship and become a citizen
of the country of his parents, or of any other country; for, by
our law, as solemnly declared by Congress, "the right of
expatriation is a natural and inherent right of all people," and
any declaration, instruction, opinion, order or direction of any
officer of the United States which denies, restricts, impairs or
questions the right of expatriation, is declared inconsistent with
the fundamental principles of the Republic.
. . .
Whether any act of himself or of his parents during his minority
could have the same effect is at least doubtful. But it would be
out of place to pursue that inquiry, inasmuch as it is expressly
agreed that his residence has always been in the United States,
and not elsewhere; that each of his temporary visits to China,
the one for some months when he was about seventeen years
old, and the other for something like a year about the time of
his coming of age, was made with the intention of returning,
and was followed by his actual return, to the United States, and
that said Wong Kim Ark has not, either by himself or his
parents acting[p705] for him, ever renounced his allegiance to
the United States, and that he has never done or committed any
act or thing to exclude him therefrom.
The evident intention, and the necessary effect, of the
submission of this case to the decision of the court upon the
facts agreed by the parties were to present for determination the
single question stated at the beginning of this opinion, namely,
whether a child born in the United States, of parent of Chinese
descent, who, at the time of his birth, are subjects of the
Emperor of China, but have a permanent domicil and residence
in the United States, and are there carrying on business, and are
not employed in any diplomatic or official capacity under the
Emperor of China, becomes at the time of his birth a citizen of
the United States. For the reasons above stated, this court is of
opinion that the question must be answered in the affirmative.
Excerpts from the Majority Opinion in Downes v. Bidwell by
Justice Brown (1901)
Excerpts from the Dissenting Opinion in Downes v. Bidwell by
Justice Harlan (1901)
In the opinion to which I have referred it is suggested that
conditions may arise when the annexation of distant possessions
may be desirable. 'If,' says that opinion, 'those possessions are
inhabited by alien races, differing from us in religion, customs,
laws, methods of taxation, and modes of thought, the
administration of government and justice, according to Anglo-
Saxon principles, may for a time be impossible; and the
question at once arises whether large concessions ought not to
be made for a time, that ultimately our own theories may be
carried out, and the blessings of a free government under the
Constitution extended to them. We decline to hold that there is
anything in the Constitution to forbid such action.' In my
judgment, the Constitution does not sustain any such theory of
our governmental system. Whether a particular race will or will
not assimilate with our people, and whether they can or cannot
with safety to our institutions be brought within the operation of
the Constitution, is a matter to be thought of when it is
proposed to acquire their territory by treaty. A mistake in the
acquisition of territory, although such acquisition seemed at the
time to be necessary, cannot be made the ground for violating
the Constitution or refusing to give full effect to its provisions.
The Constitution is not to be obeyed or disobeyed as the
circumstances of a particular crisis in our history may suggest
the one or the other course to be pursued. The People have
decreed that it shall be the supreme law of the land at all times.
When the acquisition of territory becomes complete, by cession,
the Constitution necessarily becomes the supreme law of such
new territory, and no power exists in any department of the
government to make 'concessions' that are inconsistent with its
provisions. The authority to make such concessions implies the
existence in Congress of power to declare that constitutional
provisions may be ignored under special or [182 U.S. 244, 385]
embarrassing circumstances. No such dispensing power exists in
any branch of our government. The Constitution is supreme over
every foot of territory, wherever situated, under the jurisdiction
of the United States, and its full operation cannot be stayed by
any branch of the government in order to meet what some may
suppose to be extraordinary emergencies. If the Constitution is
in force in any territory, it is in force there for every purpose
embraced by the objects for which the government was
ordained. Its authority cannot be displaced by concessions, even
if it be true, as asserted in argument in some of these cases, that
if the tariff act took effect in the Philippines of its own force,
the inhabitants of Mandanao, who live on imported rice, would
starve, because the import duty is many fold more than the
ordinary cost of the grain to them. The meaning of the
Constitution cannot depend upon accidental circumstances
arising out of the products of other countries or of this country.
We cannot violate the Constitution in order to serve particular
interests in our own or in foreign lands. Even this court, with its
tremendous power, must heed the mandate of the Constitution.
No one in official station, to whatever department of the
government he belongs, can disobey its commands without
violating the obligation of the oath he has taken. By
whomsoever and wherever power is exercised in the name and
under the authority of the United States, or of any branch of its
government, the validity or invalidity of that which is done
must be determined by the Constitution.
It would seem, according to the theories of some, that even if
Porto Rico is in and of the United States for many important
purposes, it is yet not a part of this country with the privilege of
protesting against a rule of taxation which Congress is expressly
forbidden by the Constitution from adopting as to any part of
the 'United States.' And this result comes from the failure of
Congress to use the word 'incorporate' in the Foraker act,
although by the same act all power exercised by the civil
government in Porto Rico is by authority of the United States,
and although this court has been given jurisdiction by writ of
error or appeal to re-examine the final judgments of the district
court of the United States established by Congress for that
territory. Suppose Congress had passed this act: 'Be it enacted
by the Senate and House of Representatives in Congress
assembled, That Porto Rico be and is hereby incorporated into
the United States as a territory,' would such a statute have
enlarged the scope or effect of the Foraker act? Would such a
statute have accomplished more than the Foraker act has done?
Indeed, would not such legislation have been regarded as most
extraordinary as well as unnecessary?
I am constrained to say that this idea of 'incorporation' has some
occult meaning which my mind does not apprehend. It is
enveloped in some mystery which I am unable to unravel.
In my opinion Porto Rico became, at least after the ratification
of the treaty with Spain, a part of and subject to the jurisdiction
of the United States in respect of all its territory and people,
and that Congress could not thereafter impose any duty, impost,
or excise with respect to that island and its inhabitants, which
departed from the rule of uniformity established by the
Constitution.
Excerpts from the Decision in Regan v. King by Judge
Adolphus St. Sure (1943)
ST. SURE, District Judge.
Plaintiff, a citizen of the United States and of the State of
California, a registered voter of San Francisco, sues the
Registrar of Voters of the City and County of San Francisco,
alleging that more than "2600 Japanese of the full blood born in
the United States and the State of California, of alien parents
born in the Empire of Japan," are erroneously registered to vote
in San Francisco. He further alleges that his rights and
privileges as an elector, secured to him by law, are impaired by
permitting ineligible persons [Japanese] to exercise the rights
and privileges of electors of the State of California. He prays
that the Registrar be directed to strike the names of all Japanese
from the register of voters on the ground that they are enemy
aliens, citizens of Japan, and therefore ineligible to citizenship
and the right to vote.
Defendant Registrar answers that Japanese born here are
citizens of the United States and as such are entitled to be
registered as voters, and asks to be dismissed with his costs.
This case is exceptional because the sole question it presents to
this court is one which has been definitely decided by the
United States Supreme Court: Is a person of the Japanese race,
born within the United States, a citizen? The question has been
answered in the affirmative in United States v. Wong Kim Ark, ,
18 S. Ct. 456, 42 L. Ed. 890; Morrison v. California, , 54 S. Ct.
281, 78 L. Ed. 664; and Perkins v. Elg, , 59 S. Ct. 884, 83 L.
Ed. 1320.
Counsel for plaintiff frankly stated that he was asking this court
to overrule the leading case of United States v. Wong Kim Ark,
supra, because he believed the decision was erroneous. Since
the decision was rendered it has been twice cited with approval
by the Supreme Court in Morrison v. California, supra, and in
Perkins v. Elg, supra. In the Morrison case Justice Cardozo,
speaking for the Court, said [, 54 S. Ct. 283, 78 L.Ed. 664]: "A
person of the Japanese race is a citizen of the United States …
Excerpts from the Majority Opinion in the Slaughterhouse Cases
(1873) by Justice Miller
It is that the distinction between citizenship of the United States
and citizenship of a State is clearly recognized and
established.Not only may a man be a citizen of the United
States without being a citizen of a State, but an important
element is necessary to convert the former into the latter. He
must reside within the State to make him a citizen of it, but it is
only necessary that he should be born or naturalized in the
United States to be a citizen of the Union.
It is quite clear, then, that there is a citizenship of the United
States, and a citizenship of a State, which are distinct from each
other, and which depend upon different characteristics or
circumstances in the individual.
We think this distinction and its explicit recognition in this
amendment of great weight in this argument, because the next
paragraph of this same section, which is the one mainly relied
on by the plaintiffs in error, speaks only of privileges and
immunities of citizens of the United States, and does not speak
of those of citizens of the several States. The argument,
however, in favor of the plaintiffs rests wholly on the
assumption that the citizenship is the same, and the privileges
and immunities guaranteed by the clause are the same.
The language is, "No State shall make or enforce any law which
shall abridge the privileges or immunities of citizens of the
United States." It is a little remarkable, if this clause was
intended as a protection to the citizen of a State against the
legislative power of his own State, that the word citizen of the
State should be left out when it is so carefully used, and used in
contradistinction to citizens of the United States in the very
sentence which precedes it. It is too clear for argument that the
change in phraseology was adopted understandingly and, with a
purpose.
Of the privileges and immunities of the citizen of the United
States, and of the privileges and immunities of the citizen of the
State, and what they respectively are, we will presently
consider; but we wish to state here that it is only the former
which are placed by this clause under the protection of the
Federal Constitution, and that the latter, whatever they may be,
are not intended to have any additional protection by this
paragraph of the amendment.
Was it the purpose of the fourteenth amendment, by the simple
declaration that no State should make or enforce any law which
shall abridge the privileges and immunities of citizens of the
United States, to transfer the security and protection of all the
civil rights which we have mentioned, from the States to the
Federal government? And where it is declared that Congress
Shall have the power to enforce that article, was it intended to
bring within the power of Congress the entire domain of civil
rights heretofore belonging exclusively to the States?
We are convinced that no such results were intended by the
Congress which proposed these amendments, nor by the
legislatures of the States which ratified them.
Having shown that the privileges and immunities relied on in
the argument are those which belong to citizens of the States as
such, and that they are left to the State governments for security
and protection, and not by this article placed under the special
care of the Federal government, we may hold ourselves excused
from defining the privilegesand immunities of citizens of the
United States which no State can abridge until some case
involving those privileges may make it necessary to do so.
But lest it should be said that no such privileges and immunities
are to he found if those we have been considering are excluded,
we venture to suggest some which owe their existence to the
Federal government, its national character, its Constitution, or
its laws.
Excerpts from the Dissenting Opinion in the Slaughterhouse
Cases (1873) by Justice Field
The provisions of the fourteenth amendment, which is properly
a supplement to the thirteenth, cover, in my judgment, the case
before us, and inhibit any legislation which confers special and
exclusive privileges like these under consideration. The
amendment was adopted to obviate objections which had been
raised and pressed with great force to the validity of the Civil
Rights Act, and to place the common rights of American
citizens under the protection of the National government.
The first clause of the fourteenth amendment changes this whole
subject, and removes it from the region of discussion and doubt.
It recognizes in express terms, if it does not create, citizens of
the United States, and it makes their citizenship dependent upon
the place of their birth, or the fact of their adoption, and not
upon the constitution or laws of any State or the condition of
their ancestry. A citizen of a State is now only a citizen of the
United States residing in that State. The fundamental rights,
privileges, and immunities which belong to him as a free man
and a free citizen now belong to him as a citizen of the United
States, and are not dependent upon his citizenship of any State.
The exercise of these rights and privileges, and the degree of
enjoyment received from such exercise, are always more or less
affected by the condition and the local institutions of the State,
or city, or town where he resides. They are thus affected in a
State by the wisdom of its laws, the ability of its officers, the
efficiency of its magistrates, the education and morals of its
people, and by many other considerations. This is a result which
follows from the constitution of society, and can never be
avoided, but in no other way can they be affected by the action
of the State, or by the residence of the citizen therein. They do
not derive their existence from its legislation, and cannot be
destroyed by its power.
The amendment does not attempt to confer any new privileges
or immunities upon citizens, or to enumerate or define those
already existing. It assumes that there are such privileges and
immunities which belong of right to citizens as such, and
ordains that they shall not be abridged by State legislation. If
this inhibition has no reference to privileges and immunities of
this character, but only refers, as held by the majority of the
court in their opinion, to such privileges and immunities as were
before its adoption specially designated in the Constitution or
necessarily implied as belonging to citizens of the United
States, it was a vain and idle enactment, which accomplished
nothing and most unnecessarily excited Congress and the people
on its passage. With privileges and immunities thus designated
or implied no State could ever have interfered by its laws, and
no new constitutional provision was required to inhibit such
interference. The supremacy of the Constitution and the laws of
the United States always controlled any State legislation of that
character. But if the amendment refers to the natural and
inalienable rights which belong to all citizens, the inhibition has
a profound significance and consequence.
Equality of right, with exemption from all disparaging and
partial enactments, in the lawful pursuits of life, throughout the
whole country, is the distinguishing privilege of citizens of the
United States. To them, everywhere, all pursuits, all
professions, all avocations are open without other restrictions
than such as are imposed equally upon all others of the same
age, sex, and condition. The State may prescribe such
regulations for every pursuit and calling of life as will promote
the public health, secure the good order and advance the general
prosperity of society, but, when once prescribed, the pursuit or
calling must be free to be followed by every citizen who is
within the conditions designated, and will conform to the
regulations. This is the fundamental idea upon which our
institutions rest, and, unless adhered to in the legislation of the
country, our government will be a republic only in name. The
fourteenth amendment, in my judgment, makes it essential to
the validity of the legislation of every State that this equality of
right should be respected. How widely this equality has been
departed from, how entirely rejected and trampled upon by the
act of Louisiana, I have already shown. And it is to me a matter
of profound regret that its validity is recognized by a majority
of this court, for by it the right of free labor, one of the most
sacred and imprescriptible rights of man, is violated.
Excerpts from the Majority Opinion in U.S. v. Cruikshank
(1875) by Justice Waite
We have in our political system a government of the United
States and a government of each of the several States. Each one
of these governments is distinct from the others, and each has
citizens of its own who owe it allegiance, and whose rights,
within its jurisdiction, it must protect. The same person may be
at the same time a citizen of the United States and a citizen of a
State, but his rights of citizenship under one of these
governments will be different from those he has under the other.
Citizens are the members of the political community to which
they belong. They are the people who compose the community,
and who, in their associated capacity, have established or
submitted themselves to the dominion of a government for the
promotion of their general welfare and the protection of their
individual as well as their collective rights. In the formation of
a government, the people may confer upon it such powers as
they choose. The government, when so formed, may, and when
called upon should, exercise all the powers it has for the
protection of the rights of its citizens and the people within its
jurisdiction; but it can exercise no other. The duty of a
government to afford protection is limited always by the power
it possesses for that purpose.
The fourteenth amendment prohibits a State from depriving any
person of life, liberty, or property, without due process of law;
but this adds nothing to the rights of one citizen as against
another. It simply furnishes an additional guaranty against any
encroachment by the States upon the fundamental rights which
belong to every citizen as a member of society.
The fourth and twelfth counts charge the intent to have been to
prevent and hinder the citizens named, who were of African
descent and persons of color, in 'the free exercise and
enjoyment of their several right and privilege to the full and
equal benefit of all laws and proceedings, then and there, before
that time, enacted or ordained by the said State of Louisiana and
by the United States; and then and there, at that time, being in
force in the said State and District of Louisiana aforesaid, for
the security of their respective persons and property, then and
there, at that time enjoyed at and within said State and District
of Louisiana by white persons, being citizens of said State of
Louisiana and the United States, for the protection of the
persons and property of said white citizens.' There is no
allegation that this was done because of the race or color of the
persons conspired against. When stripped of its verbiage, the
case as presented amounts to nothing more than that the
defendants conspired to prevent certain citizens of the United
States, being within the State of Louisiana, from enjoying the
equal protection of the laws of the State and of the United
States.
The fourteenth amendment prohibits a State from denying to
any person within its jurisdiction the equal protection of the
laws; but this provision does not, any more than the one which
precedes it, and which we have just considered, add any thing to
the rights which one citizen has under the Constitution against
another. The equality of the rights of citizens is a principle of
republicanism. Every republican government is in duty bound to
protect all its citizens in the enjoyment of this principle, if
within its power. That duty was originally assumed by the
States; and it still remains there. The only obligation resting
upon the United States is to see that the States do not deny the
right. This the amendment guarantees, but no more. The power
of the national government is limited to the enforcement of this
guaranty.
Excerpts from the Majority Opinion in The Civil Rights Cases
(1883) by Justice Bradley
Individual invasion of individual rights is not the subject-matter
of the [Fourteenth] Amendment. It has a deeper and broader
scope. It nullifies and makes void all state legislation, and state
action of every kind, which impairs the privileges and
immunities of citizens of the United States, or which injures
them in life, liberty or property without due process of law, or
which denies to any of them the equal protection of the laws. ...
It does not invest congress with power to legislate upon subjects
which are within the domain of state legislation; but to provide
modes of relief against state legislation, or state action, of the
kind referred to. It does not authorize congress to create a code
of municipal law for the regulation of private rights; but to
Confirming Pages  THE PRACTICAL SKEPTIC  CORE CONCEP.docx
Confirming Pages  THE PRACTICAL SKEPTIC  CORE CONCEP.docx
Confirming Pages  THE PRACTICAL SKEPTIC  CORE CONCEP.docx
Confirming Pages  THE PRACTICAL SKEPTIC  CORE CONCEP.docx
Confirming Pages  THE PRACTICAL SKEPTIC  CORE CONCEP.docx
Confirming Pages  THE PRACTICAL SKEPTIC  CORE CONCEP.docx
Confirming Pages  THE PRACTICAL SKEPTIC  CORE CONCEP.docx
Confirming Pages  THE PRACTICAL SKEPTIC  CORE CONCEP.docx
Confirming Pages  THE PRACTICAL SKEPTIC  CORE CONCEP.docx
Confirming Pages  THE PRACTICAL SKEPTIC  CORE CONCEP.docx
Confirming Pages  THE PRACTICAL SKEPTIC  CORE CONCEP.docx
Confirming Pages  THE PRACTICAL SKEPTIC  CORE CONCEP.docx
Confirming Pages  THE PRACTICAL SKEPTIC  CORE CONCEP.docx
Confirming Pages  THE PRACTICAL SKEPTIC  CORE CONCEP.docx
Confirming Pages  THE PRACTICAL SKEPTIC  CORE CONCEP.docx
Confirming Pages  THE PRACTICAL SKEPTIC  CORE CONCEP.docx
Confirming Pages  THE PRACTICAL SKEPTIC  CORE CONCEP.docx
Confirming Pages  THE PRACTICAL SKEPTIC  CORE CONCEP.docx
Confirming Pages  THE PRACTICAL SKEPTIC  CORE CONCEP.docx
Confirming Pages  THE PRACTICAL SKEPTIC  CORE CONCEP.docx
Confirming Pages  THE PRACTICAL SKEPTIC  CORE CONCEP.docx
Confirming Pages  THE PRACTICAL SKEPTIC  CORE CONCEP.docx
Confirming Pages  THE PRACTICAL SKEPTIC  CORE CONCEP.docx
Confirming Pages  THE PRACTICAL SKEPTIC  CORE CONCEP.docx
Confirming Pages  THE PRACTICAL SKEPTIC  CORE CONCEP.docx
Confirming Pages  THE PRACTICAL SKEPTIC  CORE CONCEP.docx
Confirming Pages  THE PRACTICAL SKEPTIC  CORE CONCEP.docx

More Related Content

Similar to Confirming Pages THE PRACTICAL SKEPTIC CORE CONCEP.docx

Criminological TheorySeventh Edition2For o.docx
Criminological TheorySeventh Edition2For o.docxCriminological TheorySeventh Edition2For o.docx
Criminological TheorySeventh Edition2For o.docxrobert345678
 
Samples of Student EthnographiesFrom previous terms.docx
Samples of Student EthnographiesFrom previous terms.docxSamples of Student EthnographiesFrom previous terms.docx
Samples of Student EthnographiesFrom previous terms.docxtodd331
 
Stress SurveySCI163 Version 62University of Phoenix Mat.docx
Stress SurveySCI163 Version 62University of Phoenix Mat.docxStress SurveySCI163 Version 62University of Phoenix Mat.docx
Stress SurveySCI163 Version 62University of Phoenix Mat.docxjohniemcm5zt
 
D O I N G E T H I C S‘’Moral Reasoning and Contem
D O I N G  E T H I C S‘’Moral Reasoning and ContemD O I N G  E T H I C S‘’Moral Reasoning and Contem
D O I N G E T H I C S‘’Moral Reasoning and ContemOllieShoresna
 
And Then the Internet Happened Prospective Thoughts about Concept Mapping in ...
And Then the Internet Happened Prospective Thoughts about Concept Mapping in ...And Then the Internet Happened Prospective Thoughts about Concept Mapping in ...
And Then the Internet Happened Prospective Thoughts about Concept Mapping in ...Daniel McLinden
 
Contested_Knowledge_Chapter0-7.ppt
Contested_Knowledge_Chapter0-7.pptContested_Knowledge_Chapter0-7.ppt
Contested_Knowledge_Chapter0-7.pptUjjwalKumarTiwari4
 
Handbook of the sociology of religion (3sn@)
Handbook of the sociology of religion (3sn@)Handbook of the sociology of religion (3sn@)
Handbook of the sociology of religion (3sn@)Trisna Nurdiaman
 
And Then the Internet Happened Prospective Thoughts about Concept Mapping in ...
And Then the Internet Happened Prospective Thoughts about Concept Mapping in ...And Then the Internet Happened Prospective Thoughts about Concept Mapping in ...
And Then the Internet Happened Prospective Thoughts about Concept Mapping in ...Daniel McLinden
 
Human Behavior and the Social Environment IIHuman
Human Behavior and the Social Environment IIHuman Human Behavior and the Social Environment IIHuman
Human Behavior and the Social Environment IIHuman LizbethQuinonez813
 
Human Behavior and the Social Environment IIHuman
Human Behavior and the Social Environment IIHuman Human Behavior and the Social Environment IIHuman
Human Behavior and the Social Environment IIHuman NarcisaBrandenburg70
 
Chapter 28 Opening Institution: Uncertainty and Ambiguity in the 21st century
Chapter 28 Opening Institution: Uncertainty and Ambiguity in the 21st centuryChapter 28 Opening Institution: Uncertainty and Ambiguity in the 21st century
Chapter 28 Opening Institution: Uncertainty and Ambiguity in the 21st centurySokhret Sorn
 
Clinical Psychology and Counseling Psychology1.docx
Clinical Psychology and Counseling Psychology1.docxClinical Psychology and Counseling Psychology1.docx
Clinical Psychology and Counseling Psychology1.docxbartholomeocoombs
 
Sociological TopicsThere are various research topics that I .docx
Sociological TopicsThere are various research topics that I .docxSociological TopicsThere are various research topics that I .docx
Sociological TopicsThere are various research topics that I .docxjensgosney
 
WK1 DQ 1The first step in the research process is selecting a to.docx
WK1 DQ 1The first step in the research process is selecting a to.docxWK1 DQ 1The first step in the research process is selecting a to.docx
WK1 DQ 1The first step in the research process is selecting a to.docxericbrooks84875
 
SociologyTwelfth EditionFor Zach, Seth, and Haze.docx
SociologyTwelfth EditionFor Zach, Seth, and Haze.docxSociologyTwelfth EditionFor Zach, Seth, and Haze.docx
SociologyTwelfth EditionFor Zach, Seth, and Haze.docxlillie234567
 

Similar to Confirming Pages THE PRACTICAL SKEPTIC CORE CONCEP.docx (20)

Criminological TheorySeventh Edition2For o.docx
Criminological TheorySeventh Edition2For o.docxCriminological TheorySeventh Edition2For o.docx
Criminological TheorySeventh Edition2For o.docx
 
Samples of Student EthnographiesFrom previous terms.docx
Samples of Student EthnographiesFrom previous terms.docxSamples of Student EthnographiesFrom previous terms.docx
Samples of Student EthnographiesFrom previous terms.docx
 
2015Swoy_Madison
2015Swoy_Madison2015Swoy_Madison
2015Swoy_Madison
 
Stress SurveySCI163 Version 62University of Phoenix Mat.docx
Stress SurveySCI163 Version 62University of Phoenix Mat.docxStress SurveySCI163 Version 62University of Phoenix Mat.docx
Stress SurveySCI163 Version 62University of Phoenix Mat.docx
 
Thinking different
Thinking differentThinking different
Thinking different
 
D O I N G E T H I C S‘’Moral Reasoning and Contem
D O I N G  E T H I C S‘’Moral Reasoning and ContemD O I N G  E T H I C S‘’Moral Reasoning and Contem
D O I N G E T H I C S‘’Moral Reasoning and Contem
 
And Then the Internet Happened Prospective Thoughts about Concept Mapping in ...
And Then the Internet Happened Prospective Thoughts about Concept Mapping in ...And Then the Internet Happened Prospective Thoughts about Concept Mapping in ...
And Then the Internet Happened Prospective Thoughts about Concept Mapping in ...
 
Development theories and approaches
Development theories and approachesDevelopment theories and approaches
Development theories and approaches
 
Contested_Knowledge_Chapter0-7.ppt
Contested_Knowledge_Chapter0-7.pptContested_Knowledge_Chapter0-7.ppt
Contested_Knowledge_Chapter0-7.ppt
 
AGS Masters Thesis
AGS Masters  ThesisAGS Masters  Thesis
AGS Masters Thesis
 
Handbook of the sociology of religion (3sn@)
Handbook of the sociology of religion (3sn@)Handbook of the sociology of religion (3sn@)
Handbook of the sociology of religion (3sn@)
 
And Then the Internet Happened Prospective Thoughts about Concept Mapping in ...
And Then the Internet Happened Prospective Thoughts about Concept Mapping in ...And Then the Internet Happened Prospective Thoughts about Concept Mapping in ...
And Then the Internet Happened Prospective Thoughts about Concept Mapping in ...
 
Human Behavior and the Social Environment IIHuman
Human Behavior and the Social Environment IIHuman Human Behavior and the Social Environment IIHuman
Human Behavior and the Social Environment IIHuman
 
Human Behavior and the Social Environment IIHuman
Human Behavior and the Social Environment IIHuman Human Behavior and the Social Environment IIHuman
Human Behavior and the Social Environment IIHuman
 
Postcritical research
Postcritical researchPostcritical research
Postcritical research
 
Chapter 28 Opening Institution: Uncertainty and Ambiguity in the 21st century
Chapter 28 Opening Institution: Uncertainty and Ambiguity in the 21st centuryChapter 28 Opening Institution: Uncertainty and Ambiguity in the 21st century
Chapter 28 Opening Institution: Uncertainty and Ambiguity in the 21st century
 
Clinical Psychology and Counseling Psychology1.docx
Clinical Psychology and Counseling Psychology1.docxClinical Psychology and Counseling Psychology1.docx
Clinical Psychology and Counseling Psychology1.docx
 
Sociological TopicsThere are various research topics that I .docx
Sociological TopicsThere are various research topics that I .docxSociological TopicsThere are various research topics that I .docx
Sociological TopicsThere are various research topics that I .docx
 
WK1 DQ 1The first step in the research process is selecting a to.docx
WK1 DQ 1The first step in the research process is selecting a to.docxWK1 DQ 1The first step in the research process is selecting a to.docx
WK1 DQ 1The first step in the research process is selecting a to.docx
 
SociologyTwelfth EditionFor Zach, Seth, and Haze.docx
SociologyTwelfth EditionFor Zach, Seth, and Haze.docxSociologyTwelfth EditionFor Zach, Seth, and Haze.docx
SociologyTwelfth EditionFor Zach, Seth, and Haze.docx
 

More from margaretr5

Consider assessment tools that would be appropriate for continui.docx
Consider assessment tools that would be appropriate for continui.docxConsider assessment tools that would be appropriate for continui.docx
Consider assessment tools that would be appropriate for continui.docxmargaretr5
 
Consider at least two companies that successfully adopted this b.docx
Consider at least two companies that successfully adopted this b.docxConsider at least two companies that successfully adopted this b.docx
Consider at least two companies that successfully adopted this b.docxmargaretr5
 
Consider applying the simple electronic polarizability and Clasius-M.docx
Consider applying the simple electronic polarizability and Clasius-M.docxConsider applying the simple electronic polarizability and Clasius-M.docx
Consider applying the simple electronic polarizability and Clasius-M.docxmargaretr5
 
Consider and identify a hazard that presents a major risk to your ow.docx
Consider and identify a hazard that presents a major risk to your ow.docxConsider and identify a hazard that presents a major risk to your ow.docx
Consider and identify a hazard that presents a major risk to your ow.docxmargaretr5
 
Consider any one of this semester’s American authors Anne Bradstree.docx
Consider any one of this semester’s American authors Anne Bradstree.docxConsider any one of this semester’s American authors Anne Bradstree.docx
Consider any one of this semester’s American authors Anne Bradstree.docxmargaretr5
 
Consider an obstacle or barrier to the implementation of evidence-ba.docx
Consider an obstacle or barrier to the implementation of evidence-ba.docxConsider an obstacle or barrier to the implementation of evidence-ba.docx
Consider an obstacle or barrier to the implementation of evidence-ba.docxmargaretr5
 
Consider an example of yourself as a member of team (as a volunt.docx
Consider an example of yourself as a member of team (as a volunt.docxConsider an example of yourself as a member of team (as a volunt.docx
Consider an example of yourself as a member of team (as a volunt.docxmargaretr5
 
consider an artifact that is prominently displayed by a friend or co.docx
consider an artifact that is prominently displayed by a friend or co.docxconsider an artifact that is prominently displayed by a friend or co.docx
consider an artifact that is prominently displayed by a friend or co.docxmargaretr5
 
Consider again the market for Atlantic lobster presented in Q#1 of t.docx
Consider again the market for Atlantic lobster presented in Q#1 of t.docxConsider again the market for Atlantic lobster presented in Q#1 of t.docx
Consider again the market for Atlantic lobster presented in Q#1 of t.docxmargaretr5
 
Consider a space rocket travelling towards a planet at speed c2 wit.docx
Consider a space rocket travelling towards a planet at speed c2 wit.docxConsider a space rocket travelling towards a planet at speed c2 wit.docx
Consider a space rocket travelling towards a planet at speed c2 wit.docxmargaretr5
 
Consider a social worker who conducted a single subject design a.docx
Consider a social worker who conducted a single subject design a.docxConsider a social worker who conducted a single subject design a.docx
Consider a social worker who conducted a single subject design a.docxmargaretr5
 
Consider a recent event, either in your personal life or in the news.docx
Consider a recent event, either in your personal life or in the news.docxConsider a recent event, either in your personal life or in the news.docx
Consider a recent event, either in your personal life or in the news.docxmargaretr5
 
Consider a company that has sales in May, June, and July of $11 mill.docx
Consider a company that has sales in May, June, and July of $11 mill.docxConsider a company that has sales in May, June, and July of $11 mill.docx
Consider a company that has sales in May, June, and July of $11 mill.docxmargaretr5
 
ConservationPreservation in National Parks Perform research in f.docx
ConservationPreservation in National Parks Perform research in f.docxConservationPreservation in National Parks Perform research in f.docx
ConservationPreservation in National Parks Perform research in f.docxmargaretr5
 
Conns syndrome is an endocrine disorder brought about by a tumor of.docx
Conns syndrome is an endocrine disorder brought about by a tumor of.docxConns syndrome is an endocrine disorder brought about by a tumor of.docx
Conns syndrome is an endocrine disorder brought about by a tumor of.docxmargaretr5
 
Cons of ContraceptivesInstructionsFor this assignment, complet.docx
Cons of ContraceptivesInstructionsFor this assignment, complet.docxCons of ContraceptivesInstructionsFor this assignment, complet.docx
Cons of ContraceptivesInstructionsFor this assignment, complet.docxmargaretr5
 
Consequential CourtsJUDICIAL ROLES IN GLOBAL PERSPECTIVE.docx
Consequential CourtsJUDICIAL ROLES IN GLOBAL PERSPECTIVE.docxConsequential CourtsJUDICIAL ROLES IN GLOBAL PERSPECTIVE.docx
Consequential CourtsJUDICIAL ROLES IN GLOBAL PERSPECTIVE.docxmargaretr5
 
Consensus Policy Resource CommunityEmail PolicyFree Use .docx
Consensus Policy Resource CommunityEmail PolicyFree Use .docxConsensus Policy Resource CommunityEmail PolicyFree Use .docx
Consensus Policy Resource CommunityEmail PolicyFree Use .docxmargaretr5
 
Connie FarrisProject Performance and Quality Assurance(M.docx
Connie FarrisProject Performance and Quality Assurance(M.docxConnie FarrisProject Performance and Quality Assurance(M.docx
Connie FarrisProject Performance and Quality Assurance(M.docxmargaretr5
 
CONNECTIONSCore competenciesAnalytic InquiryUse of .docx
CONNECTIONSCore competenciesAnalytic InquiryUse of .docxCONNECTIONSCore competenciesAnalytic InquiryUse of .docx
CONNECTIONSCore competenciesAnalytic InquiryUse of .docxmargaretr5
 

More from margaretr5 (20)

Consider assessment tools that would be appropriate for continui.docx
Consider assessment tools that would be appropriate for continui.docxConsider assessment tools that would be appropriate for continui.docx
Consider assessment tools that would be appropriate for continui.docx
 
Consider at least two companies that successfully adopted this b.docx
Consider at least two companies that successfully adopted this b.docxConsider at least two companies that successfully adopted this b.docx
Consider at least two companies that successfully adopted this b.docx
 
Consider applying the simple electronic polarizability and Clasius-M.docx
Consider applying the simple electronic polarizability and Clasius-M.docxConsider applying the simple electronic polarizability and Clasius-M.docx
Consider applying the simple electronic polarizability and Clasius-M.docx
 
Consider and identify a hazard that presents a major risk to your ow.docx
Consider and identify a hazard that presents a major risk to your ow.docxConsider and identify a hazard that presents a major risk to your ow.docx
Consider and identify a hazard that presents a major risk to your ow.docx
 
Consider any one of this semester’s American authors Anne Bradstree.docx
Consider any one of this semester’s American authors Anne Bradstree.docxConsider any one of this semester’s American authors Anne Bradstree.docx
Consider any one of this semester’s American authors Anne Bradstree.docx
 
Consider an obstacle or barrier to the implementation of evidence-ba.docx
Consider an obstacle or barrier to the implementation of evidence-ba.docxConsider an obstacle or barrier to the implementation of evidence-ba.docx
Consider an obstacle or barrier to the implementation of evidence-ba.docx
 
Consider an example of yourself as a member of team (as a volunt.docx
Consider an example of yourself as a member of team (as a volunt.docxConsider an example of yourself as a member of team (as a volunt.docx
Consider an example of yourself as a member of team (as a volunt.docx
 
consider an artifact that is prominently displayed by a friend or co.docx
consider an artifact that is prominently displayed by a friend or co.docxconsider an artifact that is prominently displayed by a friend or co.docx
consider an artifact that is prominently displayed by a friend or co.docx
 
Consider again the market for Atlantic lobster presented in Q#1 of t.docx
Consider again the market for Atlantic lobster presented in Q#1 of t.docxConsider again the market for Atlantic lobster presented in Q#1 of t.docx
Consider again the market for Atlantic lobster presented in Q#1 of t.docx
 
Consider a space rocket travelling towards a planet at speed c2 wit.docx
Consider a space rocket travelling towards a planet at speed c2 wit.docxConsider a space rocket travelling towards a planet at speed c2 wit.docx
Consider a space rocket travelling towards a planet at speed c2 wit.docx
 
Consider a social worker who conducted a single subject design a.docx
Consider a social worker who conducted a single subject design a.docxConsider a social worker who conducted a single subject design a.docx
Consider a social worker who conducted a single subject design a.docx
 
Consider a recent event, either in your personal life or in the news.docx
Consider a recent event, either in your personal life or in the news.docxConsider a recent event, either in your personal life or in the news.docx
Consider a recent event, either in your personal life or in the news.docx
 
Consider a company that has sales in May, June, and July of $11 mill.docx
Consider a company that has sales in May, June, and July of $11 mill.docxConsider a company that has sales in May, June, and July of $11 mill.docx
Consider a company that has sales in May, June, and July of $11 mill.docx
 
ConservationPreservation in National Parks Perform research in f.docx
ConservationPreservation in National Parks Perform research in f.docxConservationPreservation in National Parks Perform research in f.docx
ConservationPreservation in National Parks Perform research in f.docx
 
Conns syndrome is an endocrine disorder brought about by a tumor of.docx
Conns syndrome is an endocrine disorder brought about by a tumor of.docxConns syndrome is an endocrine disorder brought about by a tumor of.docx
Conns syndrome is an endocrine disorder brought about by a tumor of.docx
 
Cons of ContraceptivesInstructionsFor this assignment, complet.docx
Cons of ContraceptivesInstructionsFor this assignment, complet.docxCons of ContraceptivesInstructionsFor this assignment, complet.docx
Cons of ContraceptivesInstructionsFor this assignment, complet.docx
 
Consequential CourtsJUDICIAL ROLES IN GLOBAL PERSPECTIVE.docx
Consequential CourtsJUDICIAL ROLES IN GLOBAL PERSPECTIVE.docxConsequential CourtsJUDICIAL ROLES IN GLOBAL PERSPECTIVE.docx
Consequential CourtsJUDICIAL ROLES IN GLOBAL PERSPECTIVE.docx
 
Consensus Policy Resource CommunityEmail PolicyFree Use .docx
Consensus Policy Resource CommunityEmail PolicyFree Use .docxConsensus Policy Resource CommunityEmail PolicyFree Use .docx
Consensus Policy Resource CommunityEmail PolicyFree Use .docx
 
Connie FarrisProject Performance and Quality Assurance(M.docx
Connie FarrisProject Performance and Quality Assurance(M.docxConnie FarrisProject Performance and Quality Assurance(M.docx
Connie FarrisProject Performance and Quality Assurance(M.docx
 
CONNECTIONSCore competenciesAnalytic InquiryUse of .docx
CONNECTIONSCore competenciesAnalytic InquiryUse of .docxCONNECTIONSCore competenciesAnalytic InquiryUse of .docx
CONNECTIONSCore competenciesAnalytic InquiryUse of .docx
 

Recently uploaded

Interactive Powerpoint_How to Master effective communication
Interactive Powerpoint_How to Master effective communicationInteractive Powerpoint_How to Master effective communication
Interactive Powerpoint_How to Master effective communicationnomboosow
 
Presiding Officer Training module 2024 lok sabha elections
Presiding Officer Training module 2024 lok sabha electionsPresiding Officer Training module 2024 lok sabha elections
Presiding Officer Training module 2024 lok sabha electionsanshu789521
 
Sanyam Choudhary Chemistry practical.pdf
Sanyam Choudhary Chemistry practical.pdfSanyam Choudhary Chemistry practical.pdf
Sanyam Choudhary Chemistry practical.pdfsanyamsingh5019
 
Enzyme, Pharmaceutical Aids, Miscellaneous Last Part of Chapter no 5th.pdf
Enzyme, Pharmaceutical Aids, Miscellaneous Last Part of Chapter no 5th.pdfEnzyme, Pharmaceutical Aids, Miscellaneous Last Part of Chapter no 5th.pdf
Enzyme, Pharmaceutical Aids, Miscellaneous Last Part of Chapter no 5th.pdfSumit Tiwari
 
Mastering the Unannounced Regulatory Inspection
Mastering the Unannounced Regulatory InspectionMastering the Unannounced Regulatory Inspection
Mastering the Unannounced Regulatory InspectionSafetyChain Software
 
How to Make a Pirate ship Primary Education.pptx
How to Make a Pirate ship Primary Education.pptxHow to Make a Pirate ship Primary Education.pptx
How to Make a Pirate ship Primary Education.pptxmanuelaromero2013
 
microwave assisted reaction. General introduction
microwave assisted reaction. General introductionmicrowave assisted reaction. General introduction
microwave assisted reaction. General introductionMaksud Ahmed
 
Separation of Lanthanides/ Lanthanides and Actinides
Separation of Lanthanides/ Lanthanides and ActinidesSeparation of Lanthanides/ Lanthanides and Actinides
Separation of Lanthanides/ Lanthanides and ActinidesFatimaKhan178732
 
Organic Name Reactions for the students and aspirants of Chemistry12th.pptx
Organic Name Reactions  for the students and aspirants of Chemistry12th.pptxOrganic Name Reactions  for the students and aspirants of Chemistry12th.pptx
Organic Name Reactions for the students and aspirants of Chemistry12th.pptxVS Mahajan Coaching Centre
 
SOCIAL AND HISTORICAL CONTEXT - LFTVD.pptx
SOCIAL AND HISTORICAL CONTEXT - LFTVD.pptxSOCIAL AND HISTORICAL CONTEXT - LFTVD.pptx
SOCIAL AND HISTORICAL CONTEXT - LFTVD.pptxiammrhaywood
 
18-04-UA_REPORT_MEDIALITERAСY_INDEX-DM_23-1-final-eng.pdf
18-04-UA_REPORT_MEDIALITERAСY_INDEX-DM_23-1-final-eng.pdf18-04-UA_REPORT_MEDIALITERAСY_INDEX-DM_23-1-final-eng.pdf
18-04-UA_REPORT_MEDIALITERAСY_INDEX-DM_23-1-final-eng.pdfssuser54595a
 
Solving Puzzles Benefits Everyone (English).pptx
Solving Puzzles Benefits Everyone (English).pptxSolving Puzzles Benefits Everyone (English).pptx
Solving Puzzles Benefits Everyone (English).pptxOH TEIK BIN
 
The Most Excellent Way | 1 Corinthians 13
The Most Excellent Way | 1 Corinthians 13The Most Excellent Way | 1 Corinthians 13
The Most Excellent Way | 1 Corinthians 13Steve Thomason
 
BASLIQ CURRENT LOOKBOOK LOOKBOOK(1) (1).pdf
BASLIQ CURRENT LOOKBOOK  LOOKBOOK(1) (1).pdfBASLIQ CURRENT LOOKBOOK  LOOKBOOK(1) (1).pdf
BASLIQ CURRENT LOOKBOOK LOOKBOOK(1) (1).pdfSoniaTolstoy
 
Contemporary philippine arts from the regions_PPT_Module_12 [Autosaved] (1).pptx
Contemporary philippine arts from the regions_PPT_Module_12 [Autosaved] (1).pptxContemporary philippine arts from the regions_PPT_Module_12 [Autosaved] (1).pptx
Contemporary philippine arts from the regions_PPT_Module_12 [Autosaved] (1).pptxRoyAbrique
 
KSHARA STURA .pptx---KSHARA KARMA THERAPY (CAUSTIC THERAPY)————IMP.OF KSHARA ...
KSHARA STURA .pptx---KSHARA KARMA THERAPY (CAUSTIC THERAPY)————IMP.OF KSHARA ...KSHARA STURA .pptx---KSHARA KARMA THERAPY (CAUSTIC THERAPY)————IMP.OF KSHARA ...
KSHARA STURA .pptx---KSHARA KARMA THERAPY (CAUSTIC THERAPY)————IMP.OF KSHARA ...M56BOOKSTORE PRODUCT/SERVICE
 
MENTAL STATUS EXAMINATION format.docx
MENTAL     STATUS EXAMINATION format.docxMENTAL     STATUS EXAMINATION format.docx
MENTAL STATUS EXAMINATION format.docxPoojaSen20
 
Paris 2024 Olympic Geographies - an activity
Paris 2024 Olympic Geographies - an activityParis 2024 Olympic Geographies - an activity
Paris 2024 Olympic Geographies - an activityGeoBlogs
 
mini mental status format.docx
mini    mental       status     format.docxmini    mental       status     format.docx
mini mental status format.docxPoojaSen20
 

Recently uploaded (20)

Interactive Powerpoint_How to Master effective communication
Interactive Powerpoint_How to Master effective communicationInteractive Powerpoint_How to Master effective communication
Interactive Powerpoint_How to Master effective communication
 
Presiding Officer Training module 2024 lok sabha elections
Presiding Officer Training module 2024 lok sabha electionsPresiding Officer Training module 2024 lok sabha elections
Presiding Officer Training module 2024 lok sabha elections
 
Sanyam Choudhary Chemistry practical.pdf
Sanyam Choudhary Chemistry practical.pdfSanyam Choudhary Chemistry practical.pdf
Sanyam Choudhary Chemistry practical.pdf
 
Enzyme, Pharmaceutical Aids, Miscellaneous Last Part of Chapter no 5th.pdf
Enzyme, Pharmaceutical Aids, Miscellaneous Last Part of Chapter no 5th.pdfEnzyme, Pharmaceutical Aids, Miscellaneous Last Part of Chapter no 5th.pdf
Enzyme, Pharmaceutical Aids, Miscellaneous Last Part of Chapter no 5th.pdf
 
Código Creativo y Arte de Software | Unidad 1
Código Creativo y Arte de Software | Unidad 1Código Creativo y Arte de Software | Unidad 1
Código Creativo y Arte de Software | Unidad 1
 
Mastering the Unannounced Regulatory Inspection
Mastering the Unannounced Regulatory InspectionMastering the Unannounced Regulatory Inspection
Mastering the Unannounced Regulatory Inspection
 
How to Make a Pirate ship Primary Education.pptx
How to Make a Pirate ship Primary Education.pptxHow to Make a Pirate ship Primary Education.pptx
How to Make a Pirate ship Primary Education.pptx
 
microwave assisted reaction. General introduction
microwave assisted reaction. General introductionmicrowave assisted reaction. General introduction
microwave assisted reaction. General introduction
 
Separation of Lanthanides/ Lanthanides and Actinides
Separation of Lanthanides/ Lanthanides and ActinidesSeparation of Lanthanides/ Lanthanides and Actinides
Separation of Lanthanides/ Lanthanides and Actinides
 
Organic Name Reactions for the students and aspirants of Chemistry12th.pptx
Organic Name Reactions  for the students and aspirants of Chemistry12th.pptxOrganic Name Reactions  for the students and aspirants of Chemistry12th.pptx
Organic Name Reactions for the students and aspirants of Chemistry12th.pptx
 
SOCIAL AND HISTORICAL CONTEXT - LFTVD.pptx
SOCIAL AND HISTORICAL CONTEXT - LFTVD.pptxSOCIAL AND HISTORICAL CONTEXT - LFTVD.pptx
SOCIAL AND HISTORICAL CONTEXT - LFTVD.pptx
 
18-04-UA_REPORT_MEDIALITERAСY_INDEX-DM_23-1-final-eng.pdf
18-04-UA_REPORT_MEDIALITERAСY_INDEX-DM_23-1-final-eng.pdf18-04-UA_REPORT_MEDIALITERAСY_INDEX-DM_23-1-final-eng.pdf
18-04-UA_REPORT_MEDIALITERAСY_INDEX-DM_23-1-final-eng.pdf
 
Solving Puzzles Benefits Everyone (English).pptx
Solving Puzzles Benefits Everyone (English).pptxSolving Puzzles Benefits Everyone (English).pptx
Solving Puzzles Benefits Everyone (English).pptx
 
The Most Excellent Way | 1 Corinthians 13
The Most Excellent Way | 1 Corinthians 13The Most Excellent Way | 1 Corinthians 13
The Most Excellent Way | 1 Corinthians 13
 
BASLIQ CURRENT LOOKBOOK LOOKBOOK(1) (1).pdf
BASLIQ CURRENT LOOKBOOK  LOOKBOOK(1) (1).pdfBASLIQ CURRENT LOOKBOOK  LOOKBOOK(1) (1).pdf
BASLIQ CURRENT LOOKBOOK LOOKBOOK(1) (1).pdf
 
Contemporary philippine arts from the regions_PPT_Module_12 [Autosaved] (1).pptx
Contemporary philippine arts from the regions_PPT_Module_12 [Autosaved] (1).pptxContemporary philippine arts from the regions_PPT_Module_12 [Autosaved] (1).pptx
Contemporary philippine arts from the regions_PPT_Module_12 [Autosaved] (1).pptx
 
KSHARA STURA .pptx---KSHARA KARMA THERAPY (CAUSTIC THERAPY)————IMP.OF KSHARA ...
KSHARA STURA .pptx---KSHARA KARMA THERAPY (CAUSTIC THERAPY)————IMP.OF KSHARA ...KSHARA STURA .pptx---KSHARA KARMA THERAPY (CAUSTIC THERAPY)————IMP.OF KSHARA ...
KSHARA STURA .pptx---KSHARA KARMA THERAPY (CAUSTIC THERAPY)————IMP.OF KSHARA ...
 
MENTAL STATUS EXAMINATION format.docx
MENTAL     STATUS EXAMINATION format.docxMENTAL     STATUS EXAMINATION format.docx
MENTAL STATUS EXAMINATION format.docx
 
Paris 2024 Olympic Geographies - an activity
Paris 2024 Olympic Geographies - an activityParis 2024 Olympic Geographies - an activity
Paris 2024 Olympic Geographies - an activity
 
mini mental status format.docx
mini    mental       status     format.docxmini    mental       status     format.docx
mini mental status format.docx
 

Confirming Pages THE PRACTICAL SKEPTIC CORE CONCEP.docx

  • 1. Confirming Pages THE PRACTICAL SKEPTIC CORE CONCEPTS IN SOCIOLOGY Sixth Edit ion Lisa J. McIntyre Washington State University mcI26873_fm_i-xiv.indd imcI26873_fm_i-xiv.indd i 19/04/13 3:51 AM19/04/13 3:51 AM Rev. Confirming Pages THE PRACTICAL SKEPTIC: CORE CONCEPTS IN SOCIOLOGY, SIXTH EDITION Published by McGraw-Hill Education, 2 Penn Plaza, New York, NY 10121. Copyright © 2 014 by McGraw-Hill Education. All rights reserved. Printed in the United States of America. Previous editions © 2 011, 2008, and 2006. No part of this publication may be reproduced or distributed in any form or by any means, or stored in a database or retrieval system, without the prior written consent of McGraw-Hill Education, including, but not limited to, in any network or other
  • 2. electronic storage or transmission, or broadcast for distance learning. Some ancillaries, including electronic and print components, may not be available to customers outside the United States. This book is printed on acid-free paper. 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 0 DOC/DOC 1 0 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 ISBN 978-0-07-802687-4 MHID 0-07-802687-3 Senior Vice President, Products & Markets: Kurt L. Strand Vice President, General Manager, Products & Markets: Michael Ryan Vice President, Content Production & Technology Services: Kimberly Meriwether David Managing Director: Gina Boedeker Brand Manager: Courtney Austermehle Director of Development: Rhona Robbin Freelance Development Editor: Nomi Sofer Marketing Manager: Philip Weaver Marketing Coordinator: Ryan Viviani Director, Content Production: Terri Schiesl Content Project Manager: Mary Jane Lampe Buyer: Nichole Birkenholz Cover Designer: Studio Montage, St. Louis, MO Cover Image: Digital Vision / Getty Images Typeface: 10/12 Palatino Compositor: Laserwords Private Limited Printer: R. R. Donnelley All credits appearing on page or at the end of the book are considered to be an extension of the
  • 3. copyright page. Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data McIntyre, Lisa J. The practical skeptic : core concepts in sociology / Lisa J. McIntyre, Washington State University. — Sixth edition. pages cm ISBN 978-0-07-802687-4 (alk. paper) 1. Sociology. I. Title. HM586.M55 2014 301—dc23 2013008264 The Internet addresses listed in the text were accurate at the time of publication. The inclusion of a website does not indicate an endorsement by the authors or McGraw-Hill Education, and McGraw- Hill Education does not guarantee the accuracy of the information presented at these sites. www.mhhe.com mcI26873_fm_i-xiv.indd iimcI26873_fm_i-xiv.indd ii 4/22/13 11:46 AM4/22/13 11:46 AM Confirming Pages iii CONTENTS Preface x
  • 4. Introduction 1 So, What Is Sociology? 2 The Value of Sociology to Students 3 Tips for Studying Sociology—and an Invitation 4 Chapter 1 Responding to Chaos: A Brief History of Sociology 5 Inquiries into the Physical World 6 Technology, Urbanization, and Social Upheaval 10 The Origins of Modern Sociology in France: Émile Durkheim 13 E xcerpt: É mile D urkheim, From Suicide (1897) and The Rules of the Sociological Method (1904) 14 The Origins of Modern Sociology in Germany: Ferdinand Tönnies, Max Weber, and Karl Marx 16 E xcerpt: F erdinand T önnies, From Gemeinschaft and Gesellschaft (1887) 17 Karl Marx 20 The Origins of Modern Sociology in England: Herbert Spencer 22 Sociology in the United States 23 mcI26873_fm_i-xiv.indd iiimcI26873_fm_i-xiv.indd iii 19/04/13 3:51 AM19/04/13 3:51 AM Confirming Pages iv CONTENTS
  • 5. B ox: One Small Step for Sociology 25 The Place of Sociology in Modern Society 26 Chapter Review 26 Stop & Review: Answers and Discussion 27 Chapter 2 The Sociological Eye 29 The Focus on the Social 29 B ox: Agency and Structure 34 Skepticism 35 B ox: Nail Down That Distinction Between Manifest and Latent Functions! 37 Chapter Review 38 Stop & Review: Answers and Discussion 39 Chapter 3 Science and Fuzzy Objects: Specialization in Sociology 40 Dividing Up the Task 42 Topic Area or Subject Matter 43 Theoretical Perspectives (Paradigms): Functionalist, Conflict, and Symbolic Interactionist 43 The Functionalist Paradigm 43 The Conflict Paradigm 44 The Symbolic Interactionist Paradigm 44 Which Paradigm Is Correct? 45 Levels of Analysis: Microsociology and Macrosociology 46 Chapter Review 47 Stop & Review: Answers and Discussion 48 Chapter 4 Who’s Afraid of Sociology? 49
  • 6. The Empirical World and Inconvenient Facts 50 Ethnocentrism 52 Avoiding Ethnocentrism Can Be Difficult 54 Cultural Relativism 56 Chapter Review 57 Stop & Review: Answers and Discussion 57 Chapter 5 The Vocabulary of Science 58 Concepts and Constructs 58 Variables 59 mcI26873_fm_i-xiv.indd ivmcI26873_fm_i-xiv.indd iv 19/04/13 3:51 AM19/04/13 3:51 AM Confirming Pages CONTENTS v Hypotheses 61 Kinds of Variables: Independent Versus Dependent 63 Kinds of Relationships: Directionality 65 Operational Definitions 66 Tables and Figures 68 A Note on Common Statistics 72 Correlation Versus Causation 74 Chapter Review 75 Stop & Review: Answers and Discussion 76 Chapter 6 Doing Social Research 81
  • 7. Two Traditions: Quantitative and Qualitative Research 81 First Things First: The Lit Review 82 The Survey 84 Types of Survey Questions 85 B ox: Six Guidelines for Crafting Survey Questions 87 The Art of Asking Questions 88 Observation 88 Unobtrusive (Nonreactive) Research 90 Artifacts 90 Use of Existing Statistics 91 Content Analysis 91 The Importance of Triangulation 92 Box: Ethnography 93 Sampling 96 B ox: Ethics and Social Research 97 Chapter Review 98 Stop & Review: Answers and Discussion 99 Chapter 7 Culture 101 Material and Nonmaterial Culture 102 Nonmaterial Culture 102 Symbols 102 Language 103 Norms 104 Types of Norms 105 Sanctions 105
  • 8. B ox: The Power of Informal Sanctions 106 Values 107 mcI26873_fm_i-xiv.indd vmcI26873_fm_i-xiv.indd v 19/04/13 3:51 AM19/04/13 3:51 AM Confirming Pages vi CONTENTS B ox: What Do Americans Value? 107 B ox: Ideology 108 B ox: Ponder 109 B ox: Statements of Belief 109 Ideas and Beliefs 109 How It Adds Up 109 Culture as a Product of Action 110 Culture as a Conditioning Element of Further Action 111 B ox: Problems Identified and Resolved in All Known Cultures 112 B ox: Varieties of Cultural Wisdom 112 Social Institutions 113 Social Change: Cultural Diffusion and Leveling 114 Subcultures and Countercultures 114 Idiocultures 116 Chapter Review 118 Stop & Review: Answers and Discussion 119 Chapter 8 Social Structure 121
  • 9. Statuses 121 Roles 123 Tricky Situation 1: Role Strain 124 Tricky Situation 2: Status Inconsistency 124 Tricky Situation 3: Role Conflict 125 Master Status 126 Groups 127 Primary and Secondary Groups 128 Formal Organizations and Bureaucracies 130 Ideal-Type Bureaucracies 130 Chapter Review 133 Stop & Review: Answers and Discussion 134 Chapter 9 Society and Social Institutions 136 Societal Needs 139 The Nature of Social Institutions 142 Institutions Are Generally Unplanned; They Develop Gradually 142 Institutions Are Inherently Conservative; They Change, but Slowly 144 mcI26873_fm_i-xiv.indd vimcI26873_fm_i-xiv.indd vi 19/04/13 3:51 AM19/04/13 3:51 AM Confirming Pages CONTENTS vii
  • 10. A Particular Society’s Institutions Are Interdependent; Because of This, Change in One Institution Tends to Bring About Change in Others 147 The Statuses, Roles, Values, and Norms Associated with an Institution in One Society Frequently Bear Little Resemblance to Those in Another Society 148 B ox: Polygamy and Monogamy 149 Social Change: The Trend Toward Increasing Specialization 149 Chapter Review 150 Stop & Review: Answers and Discussion 150 Chapter 10 Socialization 152 Nature and Nurture: Biological and Social Processes 152 How Socialization Works 154 The Looking-Glass Self: Charles Horton Cooley 155 The “I” and the “Me”: George Herbert Mead 157 Family 160 School 161 Mass Media 162 Peer Groups 163 The Workplace 164 B ox: Rites of Passage 165
  • 11. Resocialization and Total Institutions 166 B ox: Ponder 167 Chapter Review 167 Stop & Review: Answers and Discussion 168 Chapter 11 Deviance and Social Control 169 The Relativity of Deviance (What We Already Know) 169 Nonsociological Theories of Deviance 171 Sociological Theories of Deviance: Émile Durkheim and Suicide 173 The Collective Conscience and Structural Strain 173 Egoism and Anomie 174 mcI26873_fm_i-xiv.indd viimcI26873_fm_i-xiv.indd vii 19/04/13 3:51 AM19/04/13 3:51 AM Confirming Pages viii CONTENTS More Structural Strain: Robert Merton and Anomie 176 Anomie and Modern Social Structure 176
  • 12. Responses to Anomie 177 Legitimate Versus Illegitimate Means 179 Learning to Be Deviant: Howard Becker’s Study of Marijuana Use 179 Learning to Smoke 180 Learning to Perceive the Effects 181 Learning to Enjoy the Effects 182 The Societal Reaction Perspective: Labeling Theory 183 The Functions of Deviance: Maintenance of the Status Quo and Social Change 187 B ox: Ponder 187 A Caution About Crime Data 188 Deviance Is Not Immutable 189 Gays in the Military 191 Chapter Review 192 Stop & Review: Answers and Discussion 193 Chapter 12 Stratification and Inequality 195 Caste Systems 196 Estate Systems 199 B ox: A Year in the Life of the Peasant 200 Class Systems 202 Theoretical Conceptions of Class 203 B ox: Ponder 204 Some Words About Slavery 207 Social Mobility and Open Versus Closed Systems 209 Chapter Review 210 Stop & Review: Answers and Discussion 212
  • 13. Chapter 13 Inequality and Achievement: Social Class 213 B ox: The Matthew Effect 217 Explaining Social Stratification 218 Cultural Explanations 219 Structural Explanations 220 mcI26873_fm_i-xiv.indd viiimcI26873_fm_i-xiv.indd viii 19/04/13 3:51 AM19/04/13 3:51 AM Rev. Confirming Pages CONTENTS ix B ox: Beyond Academics 223 The Pygmalion Effect: The Power of Expectations 227 The Fallacy of Hard Work 228 B ox: Ponder 229 Social Mobility, Social Structure, and Social Change 230 B ox: Measuring Inequality 231 Chapter Review 232 Stop & Review: Answers and Discussion 234 Chapter 14 Inequality and Ascription: Race, Ethnicity, and Gender 237 Why a Dollar Is Not Always a Dollar 238 ”Racial Surtax” on Mortgages 242
  • 14. Prejudice 245 Discrimination 246 Discrimination and “Isms” 249 The Social Construction of Minority Groups 254 Gender 257 B ox: Sex or Gender? 259 What to Do with What You’ve Learned? 260 Chapter Review 262 Stop & Review: Answers and Discussion 263 Afterword 266 References 268 Credits 278 Glossary/Index 279 mcI26873_fm_i-xiv.indd ixmcI26873_fm_i-xiv.indd ix 4/22/13 11:46 AM4/22/13 11:46 AM Confirming Pages PREFACE I t wasn’t until I was about halfway through my first decade of teaching that I finally had the opportunity to teach Introduction to Sociology. Did I want to teach Intro? You bet! I was ecstatic. I had been teaching various upper-division classes—research methods, social theory, criminology, law and society—but I wanted to be the one who introduced sociology to students. I wanted to share with students the enthusiasm that I felt for the entire sociologi- cal enterprise and to expose them to the power of sociological thought.
  • 15. I tried to create an introductory course that would speak to the typical first-year student who isn’t planning on majoring in soci- ology and, indeed, may not even know what sociology is. Even among sociology majors, very few plan on becoming sociologists. Each semester, I ask my beginning students, “Why are you here? What is it about sociology that interests you?” The very charitable say, “I don’t know what sociology is, but I am sure that it will be interesting.” Mostly, students are honest: “I’m here to fulfill my general education requirements.” A few are more specific: “I have to take a social science class and my advisor said that sociology is easier than economics or political science.” I knew that once these students discovered sociology, they would find merit in it. Even if they didn’t major in sociology, they would come away from the class with some important life knowl- edge. I quote Robert Bierstedt in my syllabus: “Sociology owns a proper place not only among the sciences, but also among the arts that liberate the human mind” (1960, 3). I paraphrase Peter Berger to suggest that students will find one of the most impor- tant lessons of sociology to be that “things are not what they x mcI26873_fm_i-xiv.indd xmcI26873_fm_i-xiv.indd x 19/04/13 3:51 AM19/04/13 3:51 AM
  • 16. Confirming Pages PREFACE xi seem” (1963, 23)—that sociological training encourages people to look beyond the surface and to be suspicious of what “every- body knows.” I tell them that it hardly matters what sort of career they are working toward: learning how to be skeptical and how to think like a sociologist will help them understand and resolve complex and abstract problems on the job. So, I knew how I wanted to structure the course—we would learn the basic concepts and then talk and read about how these worked in the real world. But I couldn’t find a textbook whose author had anticipated my wishes. I wanted a book that would introduce students to sociology’s foundational concepts—the sci- entific method, culture, social structure, socialization, deviance, inequality. I wanted a book that would not bury those concepts inside tons of empirical information but would present them in such a way that students could gain enough understanding to apply them to what they read elsewhere and what they encoun- tered in life. It was the sociological perspective I wanted these students to come away with, not the details. I was encouraged to pursue this vision by something I read in an article by Frederick Campbell, a sociologist from the Uni- versity of Washington. In the book he co-edited with Hubert Blalock and Reece McGee, Campbell wrote that undergraduate courses in sociology ought to focus on principles rather than facts: “The mastery of sociology has a different meaning in the con- text of undergraduate education than in vocational training or a
  • 17. graduate program. A baccalaureate degree in sociology seldom prepares a student for a specific occupation or to pursue inde- pendent research. Emphasis on the subject matter, then, has lit- tle value if it means memorizing material that will soon go out of date for a job that does not exist. Mastery should move away from factual material and focus instead on the development of the mind” (1985, 13). The longer I taught introductory sociology, however, the greater became my frustration with the available instructional material. So, one summer, I sat down to write some introductory and background materials for my students. My idea was that I would introduce them to the concepts that sociologists use, and we would then apply these to what we read in a variety of sociological articles and to what we encountered in real life (and in the media). My goal was to provide my students with the tools they needed to understand the social world through the eyes of sociologists. As everyone who has taught introductory courses probably knows, the foundational concepts of our dis- cipline are not simple ones, and many students resist them. My goal was not to simplify the concepts but to make them acces- sible to students. mcI26873_fm_i-xiv.indd ximcI26873_fm_i-xiv.indd xi 19/04/13 3:51 AM19/04/13 3:51 AM Rev. Confirming Pages xii PREFACE The set of essays I wrote that summer—on the history of soci- ology and the vocabulary of science, culture, social structure, socialization, deviance, and inequality—seemed to serve my
  • 18. students well. After students read them, we moved on with our shared vocabulary to other works by sociologists and to discus- sions of how these concepts applied to the real world. It worked. It was as Peter Berger had promised in his Invitation to Sociology: “It is not the excitement of coming upon the totally unfamiliar, but rather the excitement of finding the familiar becoming trans- formed in its meaning. The fascination of sociology lies in the fact that its perspective makes us see in a new light the very world in which we have lived all our lives” (1963, 21). Although I omit- ted much that is found in the typical sociology text (there are no chapters on family, religion, or politics), the concepts I did focus on (institutions, roles, values, and so on) allowed us to have rela- tively sophisticated discussions of those topics. Be warned: I am not one of those sociologists who write in what Peter Berger called “a barbaric dialect.” I’ve taken C. Wright Mills’s caution to heart: “To get beyond sociological prose we must get beyond the sociologist’s pose” (1959). Notwithstanding the fact that I once had a book rejected by a noted university press because it was “too much of a good read,” I’ve persisted in my casual style and, whenever I couldn’t help it, have indulged my odd sense of humor. Many sociological concepts are very com- plex, and I think I have done justice to that complexity, but I have tried to do it in ways that are accessible to students.
  • 19. NEW TO THIS EDITION This edition uses updated statistics from the most recent census and other agencies. In response to suggestions from my readers, I continue to augment the discussions of topics that many students find difficult. In this edition, you will find new sections on the relationship between correlation and causation, ethnography, the mutability of deviance and the relationship between gender and income. The goal of the book remains the same: to introduce students to sociology in a way that makes the core concepts of our discipline accessible without losing the crucial complexity of these concepts in translation. Along the way, I hope that I have managed as well to convey my enthusiasm for sociology. SUPPLEMENTS Visit our Online Learning Center Web site at http://www.mhhe .com/mcintyre6e for student and instructor resources. This is a mcI26873_fm_i-xiv.indd xiimcI26873_fm_i-xiv.indd xii 4/22/13 11:46 AM4/22/13 11:46 AM Confirming Pages
  • 20. PREFACE xiii combined Web site for both The Practical Skeptic: Core Concepts in Sociology, and its companion reader, The Practical Skeptic: Readings in Sociology. For Students Student resources include comprehensive self-quizzes for both the text and reader. For Instructors The password-protected instructor portion of the Web site in- cludes the instructor’s manual (written by the author), contain- ing discussion questions and activities, examples of lectures, tips specifically targeting new instructors, a comprehensive test bank, and all the tools available to students. Also included is a sepa- rate test bank for the reader with multiple choice, true/false, and essay questions for each reading. THE COMPANION READER Created to serve as a companion to the text, The Practical Skeptic: Core Concepts in Sociology, this reader, The Practical Skeptic: Read- ings in Sociology, includes classic sociological writings as well as recent writings on fascinating topics of interest to students. Cor- responding to the conceptual organization of the text, each of the readings serves to illustrate key sociological concepts and ideas.
  • 21. ACKNOWLEDGMENTS My largest thanks go to the hundreds of students who have read The Practical Skeptic and shared their views of the text with me. Many thanks to the following reviewers whose comments and suggestions shaped the sixth edition: Peter Adler, University of Denver; Mitch Berbrier, University of Alabama in Huntsville; Joslyn Brenton, North Carolina State University; Margaret Dele- hanty Kelly, University of Minnesota; Stacy Evans, Berkshire Community College; Susan Eichenberger, Seton Hill University; Catherine Leone, University of Wisconsin-Manitowoc; Pamela McMullin-Messier, Central Washington University; Janice L. Milner, Century College; Megan Peterson, William Rainey Harper College; Carly Sebastian, Mount Wachusett Community College. Thank you to the following reviewers whose helpful comments and suggestions helped us in our preparation of the fifth edition: Elizabeth Larsen, California University of Pennsylvania; Lynda Dickson, University of Colorado at Colorado Springs; Kiren Ghei, Delta College; Thomas B. Gold, University of California at Berkeley; Patti Guiffre, Texas State University; Michael Collins, mcI26873_fm_i-xiv.indd xiiimcI26873_fm_i-xiv.indd xiii 19/04/13 3:51 AM19/04/13 3:51 AM
  • 22. Confirming Pages xiv PREFACE UW Fox Valley in Menasha; Linda C. Evans, Drake University; Carolyn Kapinus, Ball State University; Carla Norris-Raynbird, Bemidji State University, C. Stephen Glennon, Iowa Western Community College; Doug Degher, North Arizona University; Kim Hennessee, Ball State University. The fourth edition manuscript was reviewed by the following people, who responded with suggestions and pointed out neces- sary revisions, for which I am deeply grateful: Diane C. Bates, The College of New Jersey; Gretchen DeHart, Community College of Vermont; Esther Horrocks, Villa Julie College; Michael C. Maher, Spoon River College; Lida V. Nedilsky, North Park University; Deborah Thorne, Ohio University; and Craig Tollini, Western Illi- nois University. I also appreciate the help of the third edition reviewers who offered many helpful comments and suggestions: Deborah A. Abowitz, Bucknell; Cheryl Albers, Buffalo State; Sue Cox, Belle- vue Community College; Derek Greenfield, Highline Community College; Tiffany Hayes, Green River Community College; Barbara Karcher, Kennesaw; Susan Ross, Lycoming College; and Ann S. Stein, College of Charleston. I thank the reviewers of the second edition for their thoughtful reading: Jerry Barrish, Bellevue Community College; Debra
  • 23. Cornelius, Shippensburg University; Jamie Dangler, SUNY Cortland; Laurel R. Davis, Springfield College; Gloria Y. Gadsden, Fairleigh Dickinson University; Alan G. Hill, Delta College; Susan E. Humphers- Ginther, Moorhead State University; Katherine Johnson, Niagara County Com- munity College; Barbara Karcher, Kennesaw State University; Debra C. Lemke, Western Maryland College; Patricia A. Masters, George Mason University; Susan McWilliams, University of Southern Maine; Dan Pence, Southern Utah University; Marcella Thompson, Univer- sity of Arkansas; Georgeanna M. Tryban, Indiana State University; and Brenda S. Zicha, Charles Stewart Mott Community College. I would also like to thank the reviewers of the first edition: Peter Adler, University of Denver; Sheila M. Cordray, Oregon State University; Mary Patrice Erdmans, University of North Carolina–Greensboro; Valerie Jenness, University of California– Irvine; Frances V. Moulder, Three Rivers Community– Technical College; Karl T. Pfeiffer, University of Alaska; Martha L. Shockey, St. Ambrose University; Lisa Troyer, University of Iowa; and Georgeanna M. Tryban, Indiana State University. Lisa J. McIntyre mcI26873_fm_i-xiv.indd xivmcI26873_fm_i-xiv.indd xiv
  • 24. 19/04/13 3:51 AM19/04/13 3:51 AM Confirming Pages 1 INTRODUCTION H ave you ever caught yourself thinking about things that people do? Have you ever asked yourself, for example, questions about everyday things like these: Why do some students always sit in the back of the classroom while others always sit in the front? Why do African Americans on predominantly white college campuses frequently say “hi” to other African Americans, even if they don’t know them? Why do we dress baby girls in pink and baby boys in blue? Why do people generally not look at one another in elevators—and always face front? Why do young men, but not young women, spit? Why do we go to such lengths to pretend we aren’t embar- rassed when we have to get naked in front of a doctor? Why do people from small towns tend to act differently from people from big cities? Why are most people less willing to seek professional help for
  • 25. mental or emotional problems than for physical problems? Sociologists are trained to find answers to questions about people’s behavior. We are especially interested in understanding the effects that people have on one another. Sociologists are convinced that much of people’s behavior is a result of what other people do. A sociologist reviewing the ques- tions just listed would likely say that many of these behaviors result from how people are influenced by others. mcI26873_intro_001-004.indd 1mcI26873_intro_001-004.indd 1 4/9/13 12:57 PM4/9/13 12:57 PM Confirming Pages 2 INTRODUCTION This sociological conviction might offend you. Certainly, I like to think of myself as independent minded; you, too, may like to think that your behaviors are the results of choices you have made of your own free will. But allow me to persuade you that to under- stand people’s behavior and the choices they make, it is important to take into account the influence of others in their environment. Even when you think you are making your own choices, often you are picking only from the fairly limited range of options that
  • 26. others allow you. The simple fact is that, depending on your position in society—your age, gender, race, social class, and so on— people expect and allow you to act in various ways. Society places restric- tions on your behavior with very little regard for your preferences. Of course, you can choose not to live up to society’s expectations, but if you decide to be contrary, you will pay a price. And, depending on the seriousness of your infraction, that price can range from end- less nagging by your parents to a prison sentence and even to death! Consider marriage. Surely, the decisions whether to get mar- ried, whom to marry, and when are very personal decisions. Actu- ally, they are not. Examine this matter carefully and you will find that your marital choices are rather restricted. For example, in the United States, you can be married to only one person at a time. And (at least for the time being) you can marry only a person of the opposite sex—unless you live in one of the several states that allow same-sex marriage. Until the late 1960s, many states even had laws requiring people to marry within their own racial group—if you broke these laws, you could be sent to prison or exiled from the state. 1
  • 27. Chances are, your family places even more restrictions on your marriage choices. Have you noticed that there are, in effect, family “rules” about whom you can marry? These rules may be unspoken but clear: Your parents may wish you to wed someone of your own race and religion and from the same educational and social-class back- ground. Of course, there is no law that says family rules must be fol- lowed, but we all know that families have ways of making us suffer. Even your friends may restrict your marriage (and dating) choices. Consider how they would make you suffer if you started to date some seriously weird geek. You really have to wonder, why does everyone care so much about whom we marry? Now that is a sociological question! So, What Is Sociology? Here is a technical definition of sociology: Sociology is the scientific study of interactions and relations among human beings. 1 Some states have never rescinded these laws, but because such racial restrictions were ruled unconstitutional by the U.S. Supreme Court in 1967, even where they do exist, they do not have the force of law. mcI26873_intro_001-004.indd 2mcI26873_intro_001-004.indd 2 4/9/13 12:57 PM4/9/13 12:57 PM
  • 28. Confirming Pages The Value of Sociology to Students 3 I hope the word scientific caught your attention. Including that word in the definition is a reminder that … American Society for Legal History Bringing the Law Back into the History of the Civil Rights Movement Author(s): KENNETH W. MACK Source: Law and History Review, Vol. 27, No. 3 (Fall 2009), pp. 657-669 Published by: American Society for Legal History Stable URL: https://www.jstor.org/stable/40646061 Accessed: 31-12-2018 15:35 UTC REFERENCES Linked references are available on JSTOR for this article: https://www.jstor.org/stable/40646061?seq=1&cid=pdf- reference#references_tab_contents You may need to log in to JSTOR to access the linked references. JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars,
  • 29. researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected] Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at https://about.jstor.org/terms American Society for Legal History is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Law and History Review This content downloaded from 72.79.39.18 on Mon, 31 Dec 2018 15:35:26 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms Bringing the Law Back into the History of the Civil Rights Movement KENNETH W. MACK It is a pleasure to comment on Nancy MacLean's hugely important book Freedom is Not Enough: The Opening of the American Workplace1 as an example of what I might call "bringing the law back in" to the history of the civil rights movement. A generation ago, the idea that law needed to
  • 30. be introduced into this history would have seemed nonsensical. At that time, law provided one of the central touchstones in the historical nar- rative of the struggle for racial equality in American life. Scholarship in this area built on C. Vann Woodward's pioneering work on the rise of Jim Crow, which itself was written shortly after Woodward's participation in the Brown v. Board of Education litigation.2 The dominant narrative began with the legal construction of Jim Crow in the late nineteenth century and continued with the founding of the NAACP. Other actors came along at various points in the story, prominent among them New Deal- era racial liberals, World War II-era activists, midcentury social scientists, Southern civil rights leaders and movements, and eventually black power. The end point was marked by the litigation and legislative victories of the 1950s and '60s, which finally wrote back into law what had been taken away by segregationist white Southerners and a compliant Supreme Court in the 1 . Nancy MacLean, Freedom is Not Enough: The Opening of the American Workplace (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2006). 2. C. Vann Woodward, The Strange Career of Jim Crow, 3rd rev. ed. (New York: Oxford University Press, 1974).
  • 31. Kenneth W. Mack is a professor of law at Harvard Law School <[email protected] .harvard.edu>. Law and History Review Fall 2009, Vol. 27, No. 3 © 2009 by the Board of Trustees of the University of Illinois This content downloaded from 72.79.39.18 on Mon, 31 Dec 2018 15:35:26 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 658 Law and History Review, Fall 2009 late nineteenth century. The implicit methodological take on law was that state and federal statutes, as well as court decisions, provided an impor- tant impetus, or at the very least a validation, for racial change - first for white Southerners as they created the Jim Crow legal regime and later for segregation's opponents as they reinscribed racial equality onto the core narrative of American life.3 In the last generation, however, this central preoccupation with law has come under attack. In the social history of the civil rights movement, the new model that emerged trained its sights on community-level protest and organization. Its central project was to decenter the NAACP, the Supreme
  • 32. Court, Congress, Martin Luther King, Jr., and the Congress of Racial Equal- ity (CORE) as the central players in the story. Instead, scholars focused on the ways that activists and local actors built up movements and alliances outside the bounds of, or in conflict with, the figures and organizations who once dominated the story.4 Of course, there were other new brands of civil rights scholarship, inflected through labor history, international history, and the history of white Northerners and Southerners during the civil rights era. In taking on the old scholarship on its own turf, however, local studies - particularly those of the Southern movement - often set the tone. If there was a methodological take on law in the new histories, it was often that law was epiphenomenal, not that important to local movement actors, and sometimes even corrosive of local community organizing.5 3. See, for example, Harvard Sitkoff, The Struggle for Black Equality, 1954-1980 (New York: Farar, Straus and Giroux; Hill and Wang, 1981); Woodward, Strange Career. 4. See, for example, Charles M. Payne, I've Got the Light of Freedom: The Organizing Tradition and the Mississippi Freedom Struggle (1995; Berkeley: University of California Press, 2007); John Dittmer, Local People: The Struggle for Civil Rights in Mississippi (Urbana:
  • 33. University of Illinois Press, 1994). For good summaries of this scholarly shift, see Tomiko Brown-Nagin, "The Impact of Lawyer-Client Disengagement on the NAACP's Campaign to Implement Brown v. Board of Education in Atlanta," in From the Grassroots to the Supreme Court: Brown v. Board of Education and American Democracy, ed. Peter Lau (Durham: Duke University Press, 2004), 227, 228; Payne, I've Got the Light of Freedom, 413^1; Steven Lawson, "Freedom Then, Freedom Now: The Historiography of the Civil Rights Movement," American Historical Review 96 (1991): 456. 5. Payne, I've Got the Light of Freedom, 315; Doug Me Adam, Political Process and the Development of Black Insurgency 1930-1970, 2nd ed. (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1999), 133-34, 184-85; Aldon D. Morris, The Origins of the Civil Rights Movement: Black Communities Organizing for Change (New York: Free Press, 1984), 35-37. By contrast, many scholars who focus on the Northern civil rights movement, which operated in a region without explicit legal segregation, have explicitly grappled with law as a site of organization and as a means of structuring the choices made by movement actors and their opponents. Thomas J. Sugrue, Sweet Land of Liberty: The Forgotten Struggle for Civil Rights in the North (New York: Random House, 2008); Martha Biondi, To Stand and Fight: The Struggle for Civil Rights in New York City (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2003); Robert Self, American Babylon: This content downloaded from 72.79.39.18 on Mon, 31 Dec
  • 34. 2018 15:35:26 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms Bringing the Law Back 659 The legal history of the civil rights movement moved in the opposite direction, and focused on the NAACP and the Supreme Court. Institutional histories of the NAACP and biographies of famous civil rights figures domi- nated the field. In its latest incarnation, this work has diverged completely from the central concerns of historians, and, most notably in the work of Michael Klarman, has focused on the political science-inspired question of whether the Supreme Court, acting alone, can effect social change.6 The genius of Nancy's book - aside from its breadth, depth and subtle- ty - is that it is the first major synthesis to bring law back into the social history of civil rights politics. Nancy comes from the tradition of social history, with its focus on how people remake their political worlds in ev- eryday life. But the centerpiece of her story is Title VII of the Civil Rights Act of 1964 and how ordinary people responded to the bare grant of legal freedom that the statute conferred and found that it was not enough. Be-
  • 35. ginning in the mid-1960s, these activists and other actors began to remake what Nancy calls the "common sense" of America's ordinary expectations of race, gender, and place in the workforce, and by extension in the larger realm of public life (2). In fact, Freedom is Not Enough could take its place alongside the mainstream 1980s and 1990s legal histories written outside the civil rights context - with its model of law as an arena of struggle in which contending groups and individuals try to put their own stamp on what citizenship means in American life.7 Indeed, the story as it emerges here compliments some of the newest work in the legal history of the civil rights movement. For instance, Nancy shows how both NAACP and Legal Defense Fund (LDF) lawyers were key Race and the Struggle for Postwar Oakland (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2003); Jeanne Theoharis and Komozi Woodard, Freedom North: Black Freedom Struggles Outside the South 1940-1980 (New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2003). 6. Michael J. Klarman, From Jim Crow to Civil Rights: The Supreme Court and the Struggle for Racial Equality (New York: Oxford University Press, 2004); Mark V. Tushnet, Making Civil Rights Law: Thurgood Marshall and the Supreme Court, 1936-1961 (Oxford University Press, 1994); Genna Rae McNeil, Groundwork: Charles
  • 36. Hamilton Houston and the Struggle for Civil Rights (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1983); Gilbert Ware, Wil- liam Hastie: Grace Under Pressure (New York: Oxford University Press, 1984). Klarman generalized the argument first put forth in Gerald N. Rosenberg, The Hollow Hope: Can Courts Bring About Social Change? (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1991), especially pages 157-69, 336-42. Mark Tushnet's history of the NAACP's desegregation campaign was an important exception, with its grounding of the campaign in its connection to local communities. Mark V. Tushnet, The NAACP's Legal Strategy Against Segregated Education, 1925-1950 (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1987). 7. lhe most prominent examples or that vein or legal history are the essays collected in the bicentennial issue of the Journal of American History, republished as The Constitution and American Life, ed. David Thelen (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1988). This content downloaded from 72.79.39.18 on Mon, 31 Dec 2018 15:35:26 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 660 Law and History Review, Fall 2009 players in perhaps the most successful of the early movements for racial equality in the workplace - that which focused on
  • 37. desegregating Southern mill workforces (76-90, 108-9). She challenges the common interpretation of the NAACP as a unitary, elite-driven organization caught up in noneconomic rights and the struggle to implement Brown in the South, and which ceded the cutting edge to other groups. Some NAACP and LDF leaders, notably Roy Wilkins and Thurgood Marshall, coexisted uneasily with newer players on the scene as the direct action phase of the movement heated up. Both organizations, however, contained a variety of individuals and institutional frameworks for advancing their agendas, and both found new roles for their advocates and lawyers at the leading edge of reform once Title VII offered them the chance to work with activists and movements on the ground and change the common sense that governed the American workplace. There simply hasn't been enough exploration of the NAACP archives in the years before and after Brown, as the main line of scholarship has followed the familiar school desegregation litigation tracks.8 Some of the new work that has done this, notably by Risa Goluboff, Da- vid Engstrom, Sophia Lee, and Paul Frymer, has described an NAACP that drove the economic agenda of civil rights in a number of fields and institu- tions in the post-World War II era. Goluboff has uncovered the
  • 38. organiza- tion's labor discrimination litigation of the 1940s which helped redefine just what "civil rights" meant in American legal discourse. Engstrom has found that the NAACP was a leading player in defining the structure and agenda of the state-level FEPCs that proliferated once the drive for a permanent federal FEPC stalled in the late 1940s, and that this agenda yielded legisla- tive proposals that were sometimes innovative even by post- 1964 standards. Lee has examined the NAACP's Cold War-era administrative litigation before the National Labor Relations Board that ultimately resulted in a rul- ing that incorporated a nondiscrimination mandate into unions' duty of fair representation. Frymer has briefly surveyed the NAACP's labor advocacy during the two decades after World War II and has found an organization that mobilized a variety of aggressive strategies in and out of court that, by the 1960s, began to produce litigation that was far more radical than anything the legislature or executive branch was prepared to entertain.9 While Goluboff argues that the labor cases that she chronicles disappeared 8. For an essential corrective to the standard scholarly orientation, see Patricia Sullivan, Lift Every Voice: The NAACP and the Making of the Civil Rights Movement (New York:
  • 39. The New Press, 2009). 9. Risa Goluboff, The Lost Promise of Civil Rights (Cambodge: Harvard University Press, 2007); David Freeman Engstrom, "The Taft Proposal of 1946 and the (Non-) Making of American Fair Employment Law," Green Bag 2d 9 (2006): 181; David Freeman Engstrom, "The Lost Origins of American Fair Employment Law: State Fair Employment Practices This content downloaded from 72.79.39.18 on Mon, 31 Dec 2018 15:35:26 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms Bringing the Law Back 661 around 1950, taken together the work of these scholars suggest, as I have argued elsewhere, that there are "reasons to doubt" the standard narrative of a "pervasive, coherent, and stable legal liberalism" emerging by 1950 that replaced the social democratic civil rights politics of the previous de- cades with a focus on Brown, formal noneconomic rights, and elite visions of civil rights politics.10 Nancy takes this story straight through the 1970s, and points to an underemphasized aspect of this process: civil rights advo- cates changed everyday understandings of ordinary Americans about who belongs in what jobs, producing a ripple effect that continues
  • 40. to transform the nation's workforces and its public life. Nancy's book also nicely compliments current work in legal history in showing how labor market regulation was key to the attack that civil rights activists launched against racial exclusion in the mill and construction industries in the aftermath of Title VII. Government contracts are a crucial factor in her story and provided the lever that allowed activists to hold a potential club over the heads of both private employers and unions - and just as importantly, to offer an ideological justification for that position that fit comfortably within the tenets of post-New Deal liberal politics (82, 95-96). Indeed, she takes forward the story that has been mapped out in the work of scholars such Willie Forbath, Risa Goluboff, and myself, who have argued that New Deal-era labor market regulation and government contracts provided the opening wedge that allowed civil rights progressives to begin to describe and attack race discrimination in private life.11 Bureaus and the Politics of Regulatory Design, 1943-1964" (PhD. diss., Yale University, 2006), 24-264; Sophia Z. Lee, "Hotspots in a Cold War: The NAACP's Postwar Workplace Constitutionalism, 1948-1964," Law and History Review 26
  • 41. (2008): 327; Paul Frymer, Black and Blue: African Americans, the Labor Movement, and the Decline of the Democratic Party (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2008). 10. Kenneth W. Mack, "Rethinking Civil Rights Lawyering and Politics in the Era before Brown, Yale Law Journal 1 15 (2005): 256, 353. Of course, one can debate the economic and political consequences of the NAACP's workplace advocacy, as do both Judith Stein and Paul Frymer in asserting that the civil rights bar's creative advocacy was channeled by the structure of the political and legal system into channels that blunted its radical potential. Stein argues that Title VII litigation was conducted within a narrow framework that contributed to the decline of the industrial workforce. Frymer is far more admiring of the radicalism of the civil rights lawyers' efforts, but argues that those efforts, guided by existing state structures, drove a wedge between the civil rights movement and organized labor. Judith Stein, Running Steel, Running America: Race, Economic Policy, and the Decline of Liberalism (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1998), 69-91; Frymer, Black and Blue, 44-97. 1 1 . William Forbath, "Caste, Class, and Equal Citizenship," Michigan Law Review 98 (1999): 1; Goluboff, Lost Promise of Civil Rights, 81-1 10; Mack, "Rethinking Civil Rights Lawyering and Politics," 331^-2; Kenneth W. Mack, "Law and Mass Politics in the Making of the Civil Rights Lawyer, 1931-1941," Journal of American History 93 (2006): 37, 62.
  • 42. This content downloaded from 72.79.39.18 on Mon, 31 Dec 2018 15:35:26 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 662 Law and History Review, Fall 2009 Perhaps the most important of these progressives was Charles Houston who, shortly before his untimely death in 1950, offered a vision of New Deal-era regulation of economic life as a basis for attacking race discrimi- nation by private actors in a wide swath of industry. Houston emerged as perhaps the dominant player in shaping the approach of liberal organiza- tions to the emerging state-level FEPC regime.12 His unfinished work gives us much to consider as we contemplate the federal government taking a financial stake in large sectors of the twenty-first-century economy, and as we consider the new racial politics that may attach to the nation's first African American president. Finally, Nancy's book is important for its amazingly broad scope. Tak- ing in African Americans, Mexican Americans, women's rights reformers, Jewish activists, and political conservatives in one book shows one way to move beyond what historians such as Scott Kurashige have
  • 43. called the "binary logic" of race relations history, and to cover more ground than would ordinarily seem possible to do in one monograph.13 I'd like to use the remainder of my space to return to methodological questions raised by the fact that Nancy is a social historian, and to offer some thoughts on how a legal historian might react to the book. To make my own methodological commitments clear, I come from the Legal Real- ist tradition, and thus tend to focus my efforts on the gaps, conflicts, and ambiguities in formal law, and on the legal contours of social life outside formal institutions of law. I'd like to suggest that a realist perspective may have something to contribute to Nancy's pathbreaking work.14 The framing device encompassed in Freedom is Not Enough is actually a formalist, rather than a realist one. The book is framed by Lyndon John- son's famous 1965 speech at Howard University, where the President told Americans bluntly that the recent civil rights legislation had forced them to face up to the proposition that "freedom is not enough" to guaranty true racial equality. Johnson told his mostly black listeners, as well as the na- tion, that Title VII and its accompanying legislation merely granted formal equality - freedom from facially exclusionary practices - to
  • 44. members of previously subordinated racial groups (5, 73-74). Nancy's book picks up on this interpretation to argue that the issue of substantive equality - the actual 12. Mack, "Rethinking Civil Rights Lawyering and Politics," 344-45; David Freeman Engstrom, "The Lost Origins of American Fair Employment Law: Regulatory Choice and the Making of Modern Civil Rights, 1943-1964" (unpublished paper, 2009), 63 & n. 277. 13. Scott Kurashige, The Shifting Grounds of Race: Black and Japanese Americans in the Making of Multiethnic Los Angeles (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2008), 6. 14. The exact definitions of Legal Realism and formalism remain hotly contested to this day. My description of realism is strongly influenced by the big-tent definition offered in William W. Fisher III, Morton J. Horwitz, and Thomas Reed, eds., American Legal Realism (New York: Oxford University Press, 1993), xi-xv. This content downloaded from 72.79.39.18 on Mon, 31 Dec 2018 15:35:26 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms Bringing the Law Back 663 guaranty of inclusion in workplaces around the nation - would come to the
  • 45. fore only when activists entered the fray in the years following the statute's enactment. At one level, the book might be simply stating a truism known to lawyers and nonlawyers alike - that statutes are not self- executing without some further action.15 But I think that, given the weight which this framing device bears in the text, she means more than this. The book seems to rely on the distinction between one kind of equality that the statute confers, and another type of equality that only comes to the fore once ordinary people and activists - who tend to drive the story in much of social history - come into play. In black politics, the analogue to the distinction that Johnson mobilized was Bayard Rustin's famous essay, "From Protest to Politics," which ap- peared not long before Johnson delivered his speech. Rustin divided the civil rights movement into its classical phase (1954-64), when African Americans pushed for the removal of formal barriers to equality, and its political phase, when they began to push for substantive equality in eco- nomic life, education, and other areas.16 Both Johnson and Rustin relied on the distinction between formal equality (removing explicit barriers to participation) and substantive equality (actual African American participa-
  • 46. tion in the nation's institutions). In their telling, the issue of substantive equality emerges only when social movements try to put formal rights into practice. I'd like to suggest that the distinction isn't so neat. In fact, the book's interpretation of the period before Title VII was enacted is somewhat conventional (unlike what it does with the statute's aftermath). In this telling, the rejection of a permanent federal FEPC in the late 1940s signaled the end of the road for nondiscrimination rights in the workplace until 1964. There was advocacy around these issues, to be sure - for in- stance, in state FEPCs, in the labor movement, and within the Truman ad- ministration. There was no real debate, however, about the legal contours of the right to nondiscriminatory employment until social movement activists renewed the fight during the 1960s (30, 38^4). However, recent work in legal history calls this periodization into ques- tion. For instance, Sophia Lee has shown that the lawyers and activists within the NAACP's national office were steadily working their way to- 15. Indeed, NAACP labor activist Herbert Hill made this exact point in the aftermath of the statute's enactment: "Title VII not self-enforcing." Nancy MacLean, "Achieving the
  • 47. Promise of the Civil Rights Act: Herbert Hill and the NAACP's Fight for Jobs and Justice," Labor: Studies in Working-Class History of the Americas 3 (2006): 13, 14. 16. "From Protest to Politics: The Future of the Civil Rights Movement," in Time on Two Crosses: The Collected Writings of Bayard Rustin, ed. Devon W. Carbado and Donald Weise (San Francisco: Cleis Press, 2003), 1 16. Rustin's recent biographer notes that Johnson's Howard speech "framed civil rights in terms that Rustin himself might have crafted." John D'Emilio, Lost Prophet: The Life and Times of Bayard Rustin (New York: Free Press, 2003), 417. This content downloaded from 72.79.39.18 on Mon, 31 Dec 2018 15:35:26 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 664 Law and History Review, Fall 2009 wards the issue of substantive equality as early as the 1950s, in little-known labor union litigation before the National Labor Relations Board. They took on, as well, another problem that is typically seen as not reemerging until the 1960s - the question of whether legal mandates reached putatively private conduct by discriminatory unions. Anthony Chen has done com- plimentary work in his recent article on opposition to state- level FEPCs,
  • 48. where opponents charged that nondiscrimination mandates would result in "quotas" that would guarantee minority inclusion in the workforce. In 1946, Republican Senator Robert Taft went so far as to propose a new federal FEPC that would have been empowered to grant relief that, under some circumstances, might fairly be read to include group-based representation in the workplace. From the moment the FEPCs were proposed, they brought to the table the question of what form of "equality" they were supposed to foster. Indeed, the debate goes even further back to the New Deal era, when the black boycott movements for jobs in African American neighborhoods and the movement for racial equality within the government contracting workforce demanded, and received, mandates for the inclusion of specific numbers of African Americans in the workplace.17 I'd like to suggest that Rustin, and Johnson, exhibited a degree of histori- cal blindness when they argued that the previous movement had focused solely on formal equality, while substantive equality was the work of the future. As a veteran of the left branch of civil rights politics, Rustin must have known this to be untrue. There is a good chance that Johnson and his aides did also. Indeed, Richard Goodwin, the White House aide who
  • 49. helped draft Johnson's speech, was a lawyer and a former law clerk to Justice Felix Frankfurter, who himself had been a proto-realist figure in his youth. By 1965, however, Rustin was shedding his own vagabond past and moving to a more respectable place within the movement, while Johnson and his advisors were trying to convince the American public that the struggle for racial equality was not over. Each had powerful incentives to 17. Lee, "Hotspots in a Cold War," 328, 366-68; Anthony Chen, "The Hitlerian Rule of Quotas': Racial Conservatism and the Politics of Fair Employment Legislation in New York State, 1941-1945," Journal of American History 92 (2006): 1238; David Engstrom, "The Taft Proposal of 1946"; Michèle F. Pacifico, '"Don't Buy Where You Can't Work' : The New Negro Alliance of Washington," Washington History 6 (1994): 67, 79-80; Robert Weaver, "An Experiment in Negro Labor," Opportunity 14 (October 1936): 295; Marc W. Kruman, "Quotas for Blacks: The Public Works Administration and the Black Construction Worker," Labor History 16 (1975): 37, 44; Paul Moreno, From Direct Action to Affirmative Action: Fair Employment Law and Policy in America, 1933-1972 (Baton Rouge: LSU Press, 1997), 30-65. Taft's proposal was inartfully drafted, but group representation is one fair reading of its language. A number of observers within the NAACP and the labor movement read it as contemplating group-based relief and were uneasy with it for
  • 50. that reason. Engstrom, "Lost Origins of American Fair Employment Law," 151-53. This content downloaded from 72.79.39.18 on Mon, 31 Dec 2018 15:35:26 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms Bringing the Law Back 665 suppress some of the contingency and malleability in the history of civil rights politics up to 1964, and at least some of that suppression has made it into our own histories of the movement.18 In addition, I'd like to note that in Nancy's narrative, the debate over substantive equality emerges "away" from law, as social movement activ- ists try to transform the formal rights encompassed within the statute into practical inclusion in the workforce. For a book about the social conse- quences that attach to a particular legal enactment, there is only a limited discussion of the enactment itself and the complex history and debates that preceded it. In Freedom is Not Enough, the engine that moves the story along is encompassed in the words and deeds of the job seekers, workers and activists who struggle with the statutory mandate of formal equality. But it's not at all clear that the statute itself grants only formal
  • 51. rights - or at least, that the issue of substantive equality emerges only outside of the formal bounds of law. Just to take one example, the legal scholar Owen Fiss spent the early part of his career showing that the equality principle encompassed in any nondiscrimination mandate actually consists of two principles, not one: (1) removal of formal barriers to participation, and (2) actual inclusion in American institutions.19 Indeed, as early as 1971, Fiss argued that the employment law regime that emerged in the aftermath of Title VII was amenable to both interpretations.20 So it may very well be … Excerpts from the Majority Opinion in the Dred Scott Case (1857) by Chief Justice Taney The question is simply this: Can a negro, whose ancestors were imported into this country, and sold as slaves, become a member of the political community formed and brought into existence by the Constitution of the United States, and as such become entitled to all the rights, and privileges, and immunities, guarantied by that instrument to the citizen? One of which rights is the privilege of suing in a court of the United States in the cases specified in the Constitution.... We think [people of African ancestry] are not, and that they are not included, and were not intended to be included, under the word "citizens" in the Constitution, and can therefore claim none of the rights and privileges which that instrument provides for and secures to citizens of the United States…
  • 52. For if they were so received, and entitled to the privileges and immunities of citizens, it would exempt them from the operation of the special laws and from the police regulations which they considered to be necessary for their own safety. It would give to persons of the negro race, who were recognized as citizens in any one State of the Union, the right to enter every other State whenever they pleased, singly or in companies, without pass or passport, and without obstruction, to sojourn there as long as they pleased, to go where they pleased at every hour of the day or night without molestation, unless they committed some violation of law for which a white man would be punished; and it would give them the full liberty of speech in public and in private upon all subjects upon which its own citizens might speak; to hold public meetings upon political affairs, and to keep and carry arms wherever they went. And all of this would be done in the face of the subject race of the same color, both free and slaves, and inevitably producing discontent and insubordination among them, and endangering the peace and safety of the State. The act of Congress, upon which the plaintiff relies, declares that slavery and involuntary servitude, except as a punishment for crime, shall be forever prohibited in all that part of the territory ceded by France, under the name of Louisiana, which lies northand not included within the limits of Missouri. And the difficulty which meets us at the threshold of this part of the inquiry is, whether Congress was authorized to pass this law under any of the powers granted to it by the Constitution; for if the authority is not given by that instrument, it is the duty of this court to declare it void and inoperative, and incapable of conferring freedom upon any one who is held as a slave under the laws of any one of the States. The power to expand the territory of the United States by the admission of new states is plainly given. But the power of Congress over the person or property of a citizen [is] regulated and plainly defined by the Constitution itself. And when the Territory becomes a part of the United States, the Federal
  • 53. Government enters upon it with its powers over the citizen strictly defined, and limited by the Constitution.It has no power of any kind beyond it; and it cannot, when it enters a Territory of the United States, put off its character, and assume discretionary or despotic powers which the Constitution has denied to it. . . . [T]he rights of private property have been guarded with . . . care. Thus the rights of property are united with the rights of person, and placed on the same ground by the fifth amendment to the Constitution, which provides that no person shall be deprived of life, liberty, and property, without due process of law. And an act of Congress which deprives a citizen of the United States of his liberty or property, merely because he came himself or brought his property into a particular Territory of the United States, and who had committed no offence against the laws, could hardly be dignified with the name of due process of law. Excerpts from the Majority Opinion in Elk v. Wilkins (1884) by Justice Gray The petition . . . clearly implies that he was born a member of one of the Indian tribes within the limits of the United States which still exists and is recognized as a tribe by the government of the United States. Though the plaintiff alleges that he 'had fully and completely surrendered himself to the jurisdiction of the United States,' he does not allege that the United States accepted his surrender, or that he has ever been naturalized, or taxed, or in any way recognized or treated as a citizen by the
  • 54. state or by the United States. Nor is it contended by his counsel that there is any statute or treaty that makes him a citizen. The Indian tribes, being within the territorial limits of the United States, were not, strictly speaking, foreign states; but they were alien nations, distinct political communities, with whom the United States might and habitually did deal, as they thought fit, either through treaties made by the president and senate, or through acts of congress in the ordinary forms of legislation. Chief Justice TANEY, in the passage cited for the plaintiff from his opinion in Scott v. Sandford, 19 How. 393, 404, did not affirm or imply that either the Indian tribes, or individual members of those tribes, had the right, beyond other foreigners, to become citizens of their own will, without being naturalized by the United States. His words were: 'They' (the Indian tribes) 'may without doubt, like the subjects of any foreign government, be naturalized by the authority of congress, and become citizens of a state, and of the United States; and if an individual should leave his nation or tribe, and take up his abode among the white population, he would be entitled to all the rights and privileges which would belong to an emigrant from any other foreign people.' But an emigrant from any foreign state cannot become a citizen of the United States without a formal renunciation of his old allegiance, and an acceptance by the United States of that renunciation through such form of naturalization as may be required law. The main object of the opening sentence of the fourteenth amendment was to settle the question, upon which there had been a difference of opinion throughout the country and in this court, as to the citizenship of free negroes, (Scott v. Sandford, 19 How. 393;) and to put it beyond doubt that all persons, white or black, and whether formerly slaves or not, born or naturalized in the United States, and owing no allegiance to any
  • 55. alien power, should be citizens of the United States and of the state in which they reside. Persons not thus subject to the jurisdiction of the United States at the time of birth cannot become so afterwards, except by being naturalized, either individually, as by proceedings under the naturalization acts; or collectively, as by the force of a treaty by which foreign territory is acquired. Indians born within the territorial limits of the United States, members of, and owing immediate allegiance to, one of the Indiana tribes, (an alien though dependent power,) although in a geographical sense born in the United States, are no more 'born in the United States and subject to the jurisdiction thereof,' within the meaning of the first section of the fourteenth amendment, than the children of subjects of any foreign government born within the domain of that government, or the children born within the United States, of ambassadors or other public ministers of foreign nations. This view is confirmed by the second section of the fourteenth amendment, which provides that 'representatives shall be apportioned among the several states according to their respective numbers, counting the whole number of persons in each state, excluding Indians not taxed.' Slavery having been abolished, and the persons formerly held as slaves made citizens, this clauses fixing the apportionment of representatives has abrogated so much of the corresponding clause of the original constitution as counted only three-fifths of such persons. But Indians not taxed are still excluded from the count, for the reason that they are not citizens. Their absolute exclusion from the basis of representation, in which all other persons are now included, is wholly inconsistent with their being considered citizens. Since the ratification of the fourteenth amendment, congress has passed several acts for naturalizing Indians of certain tribes, which would have been superfluous if they were, or might become without any action of the government, citizens of the
  • 56. United States. 'But an Indian cannot make himself a citizen of the United States without the consent and co-operation of the government. The fact that he has abandoned his nomadic life or tribal relations, and adopted the habits and manners of civilized people, may be a good reason why he should be made a citizen of the United States, but does not of itself make him one. To be a citizen of the United States is a political privilege which no one, not born to, can assume without its consent in some form. The plaintiff, not being a citizen of the United States under the fourteenth amendment of the constitution, has been deprived of no right secured by the fifteenth amendment, and cannot maintain this action. Judgment affirmed. Excerpts from the Dissenting Opinion in Elk v. Wilkins (1884) by Justice Harlan At the adoption of the constitution there were, in many of the
  • 57. states, Indians, not members of any tribe, who constituted a part of the people for whose benefit the state governments were established. This is apparent from that clause of article 1, § 3, which requires, in the apportionment of representatives and direct taxes among the several states 'according to their respective numbers,' the exclusion of 'Indians not taxed.' This implies that there were, at that time, in the United States, Indians who were taxed; that is, were subject to taxation by the laws of the state of which they were residents. Indians not taxed were those who held tribal relations, and therefore were not subject to the authority of any state, and were subject only to the authority of the United States, under the power conferred upon congress in reference to Indian tribes in this country. The same provision is retained in the fourteenth amendment. By the act of April 9, 1866, entitled 'An act to protect all persons in the United States in their civil rights, and furnish means for their vindication,' (14 St. 27,) it is provided that 'all persons born in the United States, and not subject to any foreign power, excluding Indians not taxed, are hereby declared to be citizens of the United States.' This, so far as we are aware, is the first general enactment making persons of the Indian race citizens of the United States. Numerous statutes and treaties previously provided for all the individual members of particular Indian tribes becoming, in certain contingencies, citizens of the United States. But the act of 1866 reached Indians not in tribal relations. Beyond question, by that act, national citizenship was conferred directly upon all persons in this country, of whatever race, (excluding only 'Indians not taxed,') who were born within the territorial limits of the United States, and were not subject to any foreign power. The entire debate (Over the Civil Rights Act of 1866) shows, with singular clearness, indeed, with absolute certainty, that no senator who participated in it, whether in favor of or in opposition to the measure, doubted that the bill as passed
  • 58. admitted, and was intended to admit, to national citizenship Indians who abandoned their tribal relations and became residents of one of the states or territories, within the full jurisdiction of the United States. It was so interpreted by President Johnson, who, in his veto message, said: 'By the first section of the bill all persons born in the United States, and not subject to any foreign power, excluding Indians not taxed, are declared to be citizens of the United States. This provision comprehends the Chinese of the Pacific states, Indians subject to taxation, the people called gypsies, as well as the entire race designated as blacks, persons of color, negroes, mulattoes, and persons of African blood. Every individual of those races, born in the United States, is, by the bill, made a citizen of the United States.' If it be also said that, since the adoption of the fourteenth amendment, congress has enacted statutes providing for the citizenship of Indians, our answer is that those statutes had reference to tribes, the members of which could not, while they continued in tribal relations, acquire the citizenship granted by the fourteenth amendment. Those statutes did not deal with individual Indians who had severed their tribal connections and were residents within the states of the Union, under the complete jurisdiction of the United States. There is nothing in the history of the adoption of the fourteenth amendment which, in our opinion, justifies the conclusion that only those Indians are included in its grant of citizenship who were, at the time of their birth, subject to the complete jurisdiction of the United States. As already stated, according to the doctrines of the court, in this case,—if we do not wholly misapprehend the effect of its decision,—the plaintiff, if born while his parents were members of an Indian tribe, would not be embraced by the amendment even had he been, at the time it was adopted, a permanent resident of one of the states, subject to taxation, and, in fact, paying property and personal taxes, to the full extent required of the white race in the same state.
  • 59. It seems to us that the fourteenth amendment, in so far as it was intended to confer national citizenship upon persons of the Indian race, is robbed of its vital force by a construction which excludes from such citizenship those who, although born in tribal relations, are within the complete jurisdiction of the United States. There were, in some of our states and territories at the time the amendment was submitted by congress, many Indians who had finally left their tribes and come within the complete jurisdiction of the United States. They were as fully prepared for citizenship as were or are vast numbers of the white and colored races in the same localities. Is it conceivable that the statesmen who framed, the congress which submitted, and the people who adopted that amendment intended to confer citizenship, national and state, upon the entire population in this country of African descent, (the larger part of which was shortly before held in slavery,) and, by the same constitutional provision, to exclude from such citizenship Indians who had never been in slavery, and who, by becoming bona fide residents of states and territories within the complete jurisdiction of the United States, had evinced a purpose to abandon their former mode of life, and become a part of the people of the United States? If this question be answered in the negative, as we think it must be, then we are justified in withholding our assent to the doctrine which excludes the plaintiff from the body of citizens of the United States upon the ground that his parents were, when he was born, members of an Indian tribe; for, if he can be excluded upon any such ground, it must necessarily follow that the fourteenth amendment did not grant citizenship even to Indians who, although born in tribal relations, were, at its adoption, severed from their tribes, subject to the complete jurisdiction as well of the United States as of the state or territory in which they resided.
  • 60. Excerpts from the Majority Opinion in U.S. v. Wong Kim Ark (1898) by Justice Gray The Fourteenth Amendment of the Constitution, in the declaration that all persons born or naturalized in the United States, and subject to the jurisdiction thereof, are citizens of the United States and of the State wherein they reside, contemplates two sources of citizenship, and two only: birth and naturalization. Citizenship by naturalization can only be acquired by naturalization under the authority and in the forms of law. But citizenship by birth is established by the mere fact of birth under the circumstances defined in the Constitution. Every person born in the United States, and subject to the jurisdiction thereof, becomes at once a citizen of the United States, and needs no naturalization. A person born out of the jurisdiction of the United States can only become a citizen by being naturalized, either by treaty, as in the case[p703] of the annexation of foreign territory, or by authority of Congress, exercised either by declaring certain classes of persons to be citizens, as in the enactments conferring citizenship upon foreign-born children of citizens, or by enabling foreigners individually to become citizens by proceedings in the judicial tribunals, as in the ordinary provisions of the naturalization acts. The power of naturalization, vested in Congress by the Constitution, is a power to confer citizenship, not a power to take it away. "A naturalized citizen," said Chief Justice Marshall, becomes a member of the society, possessing all the rights of a native citizen, and standing, in the view of the Constitution, on the footing of a native. The Constitution does not authorize Congress to enlarge or abridge those rights. The simple power of the National Legislature is to prescribe a uniform rule of
  • 61. naturalization, and the exercise of this power exhausts it so far as respects the individual. The Constitution then takes him up, and, among other rights, extends to him the capacity of suing in the courts of the United States, precisely under the same circumstances under which a native might sue. Osborn v. United States Bank, 9 Wheat. 738, 827. Congress having no power to abridge the rights conferred by the Constitution upon those who have become naturalized citizens by virtue of acts of Congress, a fortiori no act or omission of Congress, as to providing for the naturalization of parents or children of a particular race, can affect citizenship acquired as a birthright, by virtue of the Constitution itself, without any aid of legislation. The Fourteenth Amendment, while it leaves the power where it was before, in Congress, to regulate naturalization, has conferred no authority upon Congress to restrict the effect of birth, declared by the Constitution to constitute a sufficient and complete right to citizenship. No one doubts that the Amendment, as soon as it was promulgated, applied to persons of African descent born in the United States, wherever the birthplace of their parents might have been, and yet, for two years afterwards, there was no statute authorizing persons of that race to be naturalized. If the omission or the refusal of Congress to permit certain[p704] classes of persons to be made citizens by naturalization could be allowed the effect of correspondingly restricting the classes of persons who should become citizens.by birth, it would be in the power of Congress, at any time, by striking negroes out of the naturalization laws, and limiting those laws, as they were formerly limited, to white persons only, to defeat the main purpose of the Constitutional Amendment. The fact, therefore, that acts of Congress or treaties have not permitted Chinese persons born out of this country to become citizens by naturalization, cannot exclude Chinese persons born in this country from the operation of the broad and clear words of the Constitution, "All persons born in the United States, and subject to the jurisdiction thereof, are citizens of the United
  • 62. States." VII. Upon the facts agreed in this case, the American citizenship which Wong Kim Ark acquired by birth within the United States has not been lost or taken away by anything happening since his birth. No doubt he might himself, after coming of age, renounce this citizenship and become a citizen of the country of his parents, or of any other country; for, by our law, as solemnly declared by Congress, "the right of expatriation is a natural and inherent right of all people," and any declaration, instruction, opinion, order or direction of any officer of the United States which denies, restricts, impairs or questions the right of expatriation, is declared inconsistent with the fundamental principles of the Republic. . . . Whether any act of himself or of his parents during his minority could have the same effect is at least doubtful. But it would be out of place to pursue that inquiry, inasmuch as it is expressly agreed that his residence has always been in the United States, and not elsewhere; that each of his temporary visits to China, the one for some months when he was about seventeen years old, and the other for something like a year about the time of his coming of age, was made with the intention of returning, and was followed by his actual return, to the United States, and that said Wong Kim Ark has not, either by himself or his parents acting[p705] for him, ever renounced his allegiance to the United States, and that he has never done or committed any act or thing to exclude him therefrom. The evident intention, and the necessary effect, of the submission of this case to the decision of the court upon the facts agreed by the parties were to present for determination the single question stated at the beginning of this opinion, namely, whether a child born in the United States, of parent of Chinese descent, who, at the time of his birth, are subjects of the Emperor of China, but have a permanent domicil and residence in the United States, and are there carrying on business, and are not employed in any diplomatic or official capacity under the
  • 63. Emperor of China, becomes at the time of his birth a citizen of the United States. For the reasons above stated, this court is of opinion that the question must be answered in the affirmative. Excerpts from the Majority Opinion in Downes v. Bidwell by Justice Brown (1901)
  • 64. Excerpts from the Dissenting Opinion in Downes v. Bidwell by Justice Harlan (1901) In the opinion to which I have referred it is suggested that conditions may arise when the annexation of distant possessions may be desirable. 'If,' says that opinion, 'those possessions are inhabited by alien races, differing from us in religion, customs, laws, methods of taxation, and modes of thought, the administration of government and justice, according to Anglo- Saxon principles, may for a time be impossible; and the question at once arises whether large concessions ought not to be made for a time, that ultimately our own theories may be carried out, and the blessings of a free government under the Constitution extended to them. We decline to hold that there is anything in the Constitution to forbid such action.' In my judgment, the Constitution does not sustain any such theory of our governmental system. Whether a particular race will or will not assimilate with our people, and whether they can or cannot with safety to our institutions be brought within the operation of the Constitution, is a matter to be thought of when it is proposed to acquire their territory by treaty. A mistake in the acquisition of territory, although such acquisition seemed at the time to be necessary, cannot be made the ground for violating the Constitution or refusing to give full effect to its provisions. The Constitution is not to be obeyed or disobeyed as the circumstances of a particular crisis in our history may suggest the one or the other course to be pursued. The People have decreed that it shall be the supreme law of the land at all times. When the acquisition of territory becomes complete, by cession, the Constitution necessarily becomes the supreme law of such new territory, and no power exists in any department of the government to make 'concessions' that are inconsistent with its provisions. The authority to make such concessions implies the existence in Congress of power to declare that constitutional provisions may be ignored under special or [182 U.S. 244, 385]
  • 65. embarrassing circumstances. No such dispensing power exists in any branch of our government. The Constitution is supreme over every foot of territory, wherever situated, under the jurisdiction of the United States, and its full operation cannot be stayed by any branch of the government in order to meet what some may suppose to be extraordinary emergencies. If the Constitution is in force in any territory, it is in force there for every purpose embraced by the objects for which the government was ordained. Its authority cannot be displaced by concessions, even if it be true, as asserted in argument in some of these cases, that if the tariff act took effect in the Philippines of its own force, the inhabitants of Mandanao, who live on imported rice, would starve, because the import duty is many fold more than the ordinary cost of the grain to them. The meaning of the Constitution cannot depend upon accidental circumstances arising out of the products of other countries or of this country. We cannot violate the Constitution in order to serve particular interests in our own or in foreign lands. Even this court, with its tremendous power, must heed the mandate of the Constitution. No one in official station, to whatever department of the government he belongs, can disobey its commands without violating the obligation of the oath he has taken. By whomsoever and wherever power is exercised in the name and under the authority of the United States, or of any branch of its government, the validity or invalidity of that which is done must be determined by the Constitution. It would seem, according to the theories of some, that even if Porto Rico is in and of the United States for many important purposes, it is yet not a part of this country with the privilege of protesting against a rule of taxation which Congress is expressly forbidden by the Constitution from adopting as to any part of the 'United States.' And this result comes from the failure of Congress to use the word 'incorporate' in the Foraker act, although by the same act all power exercised by the civil government in Porto Rico is by authority of the United States,
  • 66. and although this court has been given jurisdiction by writ of error or appeal to re-examine the final judgments of the district court of the United States established by Congress for that territory. Suppose Congress had passed this act: 'Be it enacted by the Senate and House of Representatives in Congress assembled, That Porto Rico be and is hereby incorporated into the United States as a territory,' would such a statute have enlarged the scope or effect of the Foraker act? Would such a statute have accomplished more than the Foraker act has done? Indeed, would not such legislation have been regarded as most extraordinary as well as unnecessary? I am constrained to say that this idea of 'incorporation' has some occult meaning which my mind does not apprehend. It is enveloped in some mystery which I am unable to unravel. In my opinion Porto Rico became, at least after the ratification of the treaty with Spain, a part of and subject to the jurisdiction of the United States in respect of all its territory and people, and that Congress could not thereafter impose any duty, impost, or excise with respect to that island and its inhabitants, which departed from the rule of uniformity established by the Constitution. Excerpts from the Decision in Regan v. King by Judge
  • 67. Adolphus St. Sure (1943) ST. SURE, District Judge. Plaintiff, a citizen of the United States and of the State of California, a registered voter of San Francisco, sues the Registrar of Voters of the City and County of San Francisco, alleging that more than "2600 Japanese of the full blood born in the United States and the State of California, of alien parents born in the Empire of Japan," are erroneously registered to vote in San Francisco. He further alleges that his rights and privileges as an elector, secured to him by law, are impaired by permitting ineligible persons [Japanese] to exercise the rights and privileges of electors of the State of California. He prays that the Registrar be directed to strike the names of all Japanese from the register of voters on the ground that they are enemy aliens, citizens of Japan, and therefore ineligible to citizenship and the right to vote. Defendant Registrar answers that Japanese born here are citizens of the United States and as such are entitled to be registered as voters, and asks to be dismissed with his costs. This case is exceptional because the sole question it presents to this court is one which has been definitely decided by the United States Supreme Court: Is a person of the Japanese race, born within the United States, a citizen? The question has been answered in the affirmative in United States v. Wong Kim Ark, , 18 S. Ct. 456, 42 L. Ed. 890; Morrison v. California, , 54 S. Ct. 281, 78 L. Ed. 664; and Perkins v. Elg, , 59 S. Ct. 884, 83 L. Ed. 1320. Counsel for plaintiff frankly stated that he was asking this court to overrule the leading case of United States v. Wong Kim Ark, supra, because he believed the decision was erroneous. Since the decision was rendered it has been twice cited with approval by the Supreme Court in Morrison v. California, supra, and in Perkins v. Elg, supra. In the Morrison case Justice Cardozo, speaking for the Court, said [, 54 S. Ct. 283, 78 L.Ed. 664]: "A
  • 68. person of the Japanese race is a citizen of the United States … Excerpts from the Majority Opinion in the Slaughterhouse Cases (1873) by Justice Miller It is that the distinction between citizenship of the United States and citizenship of a State is clearly recognized and established.Not only may a man be a citizen of the United States without being a citizen of a State, but an important element is necessary to convert the former into the latter. He must reside within the State to make him a citizen of it, but it is only necessary that he should be born or naturalized in the United States to be a citizen of the Union. It is quite clear, then, that there is a citizenship of the United States, and a citizenship of a State, which are distinct from each other, and which depend upon different characteristics or circumstances in the individual. We think this distinction and its explicit recognition in this amendment of great weight in this argument, because the next paragraph of this same section, which is the one mainly relied on by the plaintiffs in error, speaks only of privileges and immunities of citizens of the United States, and does not speak of those of citizens of the several States. The argument, however, in favor of the plaintiffs rests wholly on the assumption that the citizenship is the same, and the privileges and immunities guaranteed by the clause are the same. The language is, "No State shall make or enforce any law which shall abridge the privileges or immunities of citizens of the United States." It is a little remarkable, if this clause was intended as a protection to the citizen of a State against the legislative power of his own State, that the word citizen of the State should be left out when it is so carefully used, and used in contradistinction to citizens of the United States in the very sentence which precedes it. It is too clear for argument that the change in phraseology was adopted understandingly and, with a purpose.
  • 69. Of the privileges and immunities of the citizen of the United States, and of the privileges and immunities of the citizen of the State, and what they respectively are, we will presently consider; but we wish to state here that it is only the former which are placed by this clause under the protection of the Federal Constitution, and that the latter, whatever they may be, are not intended to have any additional protection by this paragraph of the amendment. Was it the purpose of the fourteenth amendment, by the simple declaration that no State should make or enforce any law which shall abridge the privileges and immunities of citizens of the United States, to transfer the security and protection of all the civil rights which we have mentioned, from the States to the Federal government? And where it is declared that Congress Shall have the power to enforce that article, was it intended to bring within the power of Congress the entire domain of civil rights heretofore belonging exclusively to the States? We are convinced that no such results were intended by the Congress which proposed these amendments, nor by the legislatures of the States which ratified them. Having shown that the privileges and immunities relied on in the argument are those which belong to citizens of the States as such, and that they are left to the State governments for security and protection, and not by this article placed under the special care of the Federal government, we may hold ourselves excused from defining the privilegesand immunities of citizens of the United States which no State can abridge until some case involving those privileges may make it necessary to do so. But lest it should be said that no such privileges and immunities are to he found if those we have been considering are excluded, we venture to suggest some which owe their existence to the Federal government, its national character, its Constitution, or its laws.
  • 70. Excerpts from the Dissenting Opinion in the Slaughterhouse Cases (1873) by Justice Field The provisions of the fourteenth amendment, which is properly a supplement to the thirteenth, cover, in my judgment, the case before us, and inhibit any legislation which confers special and exclusive privileges like these under consideration. The amendment was adopted to obviate objections which had been raised and pressed with great force to the validity of the Civil Rights Act, and to place the common rights of American citizens under the protection of the National government. The first clause of the fourteenth amendment changes this whole subject, and removes it from the region of discussion and doubt. It recognizes in express terms, if it does not create, citizens of the United States, and it makes their citizenship dependent upon the place of their birth, or the fact of their adoption, and not
  • 71. upon the constitution or laws of any State or the condition of their ancestry. A citizen of a State is now only a citizen of the United States residing in that State. The fundamental rights, privileges, and immunities which belong to him as a free man and a free citizen now belong to him as a citizen of the United States, and are not dependent upon his citizenship of any State. The exercise of these rights and privileges, and the degree of enjoyment received from such exercise, are always more or less affected by the condition and the local institutions of the State, or city, or town where he resides. They are thus affected in a State by the wisdom of its laws, the ability of its officers, the efficiency of its magistrates, the education and morals of its people, and by many other considerations. This is a result which follows from the constitution of society, and can never be avoided, but in no other way can they be affected by the action of the State, or by the residence of the citizen therein. They do not derive their existence from its legislation, and cannot be destroyed by its power. The amendment does not attempt to confer any new privileges or immunities upon citizens, or to enumerate or define those already existing. It assumes that there are such privileges and immunities which belong of right to citizens as such, and ordains that they shall not be abridged by State legislation. If this inhibition has no reference to privileges and immunities of this character, but only refers, as held by the majority of the court in their opinion, to such privileges and immunities as were before its adoption specially designated in the Constitution or necessarily implied as belonging to citizens of the United States, it was a vain and idle enactment, which accomplished nothing and most unnecessarily excited Congress and the people on its passage. With privileges and immunities thus designated or implied no State could ever have interfered by its laws, and no new constitutional provision was required to inhibit such interference. The supremacy of the Constitution and the laws of the United States always controlled any State legislation of that character. But if the amendment refers to the natural and
  • 72. inalienable rights which belong to all citizens, the inhibition has a profound significance and consequence. Equality of right, with exemption from all disparaging and partial enactments, in the lawful pursuits of life, throughout the whole country, is the distinguishing privilege of citizens of the United States. To them, everywhere, all pursuits, all professions, all avocations are open without other restrictions than such as are imposed equally upon all others of the same age, sex, and condition. The State may prescribe such regulations for every pursuit and calling of life as will promote the public health, secure the good order and advance the general prosperity of society, but, when once prescribed, the pursuit or calling must be free to be followed by every citizen who is within the conditions designated, and will conform to the regulations. This is the fundamental idea upon which our institutions rest, and, unless adhered to in the legislation of the country, our government will be a republic only in name. The fourteenth amendment, in my judgment, makes it essential to the validity of the legislation of every State that this equality of right should be respected. How widely this equality has been departed from, how entirely rejected and trampled upon by the act of Louisiana, I have already shown. And it is to me a matter of profound regret that its validity is recognized by a majority of this court, for by it the right of free labor, one of the most sacred and imprescriptible rights of man, is violated.
  • 73. Excerpts from the Majority Opinion in U.S. v. Cruikshank (1875) by Justice Waite We have in our political system a government of the United States and a government of each of the several States. Each one of these governments is distinct from the others, and each has citizens of its own who owe it allegiance, and whose rights, within its jurisdiction, it must protect. The same person may be at the same time a citizen of the United States and a citizen of a
  • 74. State, but his rights of citizenship under one of these governments will be different from those he has under the other. Citizens are the members of the political community to which they belong. They are the people who compose the community, and who, in their associated capacity, have established or submitted themselves to the dominion of a government for the promotion of their general welfare and the protection of their individual as well as their collective rights. In the formation of a government, the people may confer upon it such powers as they choose. The government, when so formed, may, and when called upon should, exercise all the powers it has for the protection of the rights of its citizens and the people within its jurisdiction; but it can exercise no other. The duty of a government to afford protection is limited always by the power it possesses for that purpose. The fourteenth amendment prohibits a State from depriving any person of life, liberty, or property, without due process of law; but this adds nothing to the rights of one citizen as against another. It simply furnishes an additional guaranty against any encroachment by the States upon the fundamental rights which belong to every citizen as a member of society. The fourth and twelfth counts charge the intent to have been to prevent and hinder the citizens named, who were of African descent and persons of color, in 'the free exercise and enjoyment of their several right and privilege to the full and equal benefit of all laws and proceedings, then and there, before that time, enacted or ordained by the said State of Louisiana and by the United States; and then and there, at that time, being in force in the said State and District of Louisiana aforesaid, for the security of their respective persons and property, then and there, at that time enjoyed at and within said State and District of Louisiana by white persons, being citizens of said State of Louisiana and the United States, for the protection of the persons and property of said white citizens.' There is no allegation that this was done because of the race or color of the
  • 75. persons conspired against. When stripped of its verbiage, the case as presented amounts to nothing more than that the defendants conspired to prevent certain citizens of the United States, being within the State of Louisiana, from enjoying the equal protection of the laws of the State and of the United States. The fourteenth amendment prohibits a State from denying to any person within its jurisdiction the equal protection of the laws; but this provision does not, any more than the one which precedes it, and which we have just considered, add any thing to the rights which one citizen has under the Constitution against another. The equality of the rights of citizens is a principle of republicanism. Every republican government is in duty bound to protect all its citizens in the enjoyment of this principle, if within its power. That duty was originally assumed by the States; and it still remains there. The only obligation resting upon the United States is to see that the States do not deny the right. This the amendment guarantees, but no more. The power of the national government is limited to the enforcement of this guaranty. Excerpts from the Majority Opinion in The Civil Rights Cases (1883) by Justice Bradley Individual invasion of individual rights is not the subject-matter of the [Fourteenth] Amendment. It has a deeper and broader scope. It nullifies and makes void all state legislation, and state action of every kind, which impairs the privileges and immunities of citizens of the United States, or which injures them in life, liberty or property without due process of law, or which denies to any of them the equal protection of the laws. ... It does not invest congress with power to legislate upon subjects which are within the domain of state legislation; but to provide modes of relief against state legislation, or state action, of the kind referred to. It does not authorize congress to create a code of municipal law for the regulation of private rights; but to