SlideShare a Scribd company logo
1 of 61
1
3
Chapter 7 SummaryCHAPTER SUMMARY
Contemporary Integrative Theories
This chapter describes theoretical efforts to integrate macro-
level theories that deal with the structures and institutions of
society with micro-level theories of everyday life. These
integrative theories aim to overcome the limitations of either
approach by balancing our understanding that individuals are
free to interpret, influence, and act with our understanding of
organizational and institutional constraints, power, and social
reproduction. Richard Emerson’s exchange theory, Anthony
Giddens’s structuration theory, and Pierre Bourdieu’s theory of
practice each take distinctive approaches to this central problem
in social theory.
A More Integrated Exchange Theory
Building on the work of George Homans, Richard
Emerson (1925-1983) asserted that power was central to
exchange, that actors are not entirely rational, and that social
relations and networks could be used to explain both micro- and
macro-level phenomena. Emerson’s exchange theory focuses on
the rewards and costs of social interaction and takes social
structure as a variable dependent on exchange. The theory
assumes that people act rationally within the context of
situations, thereby allowing the situations to occur. It also
assumes that as people become satiated with the rewards they
obtain from a situation, those situations will be of declining
importance to them. Last, it assumes that benefits obtained
depend on the benefits of exchange.
According to Emerson, social structure is produced and
reproduced through exchange mechanisms. The exchange
network is a web of social relationships that involves a number
of individuals or groups. All individuals and groups have
opportunities to exchange with others. These relationships
interrelate with one another to form network structure. Each
exchange relationship is embedded in a larger exchange
network.
In exchange theory, power is defined as the potential cost that
one actor can induce another to accept. Dependency is the
potential cost that an actor is willing to accept within an
exchange relationship. Mutual dependencies condition the
nature of an interaction. When there is an imbalance of power
and dependency between two actors, the one with more power
and less dependence will have an advantage that can be used to
collect rewards or distribute punishments. Exchange theorists
argue that the relative power of an actor is determined by the
position of an actor in an exchange network. The amount of
dependence of the entire structure on the position will
determine its power. This perspective can be used to examine
both the social behavior of individuals and social structure. It
can also be used to examine how changes in power-dependency
at the micro-level affect macro-level phenomena and vice-versa.
Structuration Theory
Structuration theory focuses on the mutual constitution of
structure and agency. Anthony Giddens (1938- ) argues that
structure and agency are a duality that cannot be conceived of
apart from one another. Human practices are recursive – that is,
through their activities individuals create both their
consciousness and the structural conditions that make their
activities possible. Because social actors are reflexive and
monitor the ongoing flow of activities and structural conditions,
they adapt their actions to their evolving understandings. As a
result, social scientific knowledge of society will actually
change human activities. Giddens calls this dialectical
relationship between social scientific knowledge and human
practices the double hermeneutic.
Actors continually develop routines that give them a sense of
security and enable them to deal efficiently with their social
lives. While their motives provide the overall plan of action, it
is these routine practices that determine what shape the action
will take. Giddens emphasizes that actors have power to shape
their own actions, but that the consequences of actions are often
unintended. Structure is the rules and resources that give
similar social practices a systemic form. Only through the
activities of human actors can structure exist. While Giddens
acknowledges that structure can be constraining to actors, he
thinks that sociologists have exaggerated the importance of
structural constraints. Structures can also enable actors to do
things they would not otherwise be able to do. For Giddens, a
social system is a set of reproduced social practices and
relations between actors.
The concept of structuration underscores the duality of structure
and agency. There can be no agency without structures that
shape motives into practices, but there can also be no structures
independent of the routine practices that create them. Margaret
Archer has criticized the concept of structuration as analytically
insufficient. She thinks it is useful for social scientists to
understand structure and agency as independent, because it
makes it possible to analyze the interrelations between the two
sides. Archer also thinks that Giddens gives short shrift to the
relative autonomy of culture from both structure and agency.
Habitus and Field
A major alternative to structuration theory is Pierre
Bourdieu’s (1930-2002) theory of habitus and field. Bourdieu
sought to bridge subjectivism (the individual) and objectivism
(society) with a perspective called constructivist structuralism.
Structuralism focuses on the objective structures of language
and culture that give shape to human action. Constructivism
looks at the social genesis of schemes of perception, thought,
and action. Bourdieu wants to examine the social construction
of objective structures with an emphasis on how people perceive
and construct their own social world, but without neglecting
how perception and construction is constrained by structures.
An important dynamic in this relationship is the ability of
individual actors to invent and improvise within the structure of
their routines.
The habitus is the mental structure through which people deal
with the social world. It can be thought of as a set of
internalized schemas through which the world is perceived,
understood, appreciated, and evaluated. A habitus is acquired
as the result of the long-term occupation of a position in the
social world. Depending on the position occupied, people will
have a different habitus. The habitus operates as a structure,
but people do not simply respond to it mechanically. When
people change positions, their habitus is sometimes no longer
appropriate, a condition called hysteresis. Bourdieu argues that
the habitus both produces and is produced by the social world.
People internalize external structures, and they externalize
things they have internalized through practices.
The concept of field is the objective complement to the idea of
habitus. A field is a network of social relations among the
objective positions within it. It is not a set of interactions or
intersubjective ties among individuals. The social world has a
great variety of semi-autonomous fields such as art, religion,
and higher education. The field is a type of competitive
marketplace in which economic, cultural, social, and symbolic
powers are used. The preeminent field is the field of politics,
from which a hierarchy of power relationships serves to
structure all other fields. To analyze a field, one must first
understand its relationship to the political field. The next step
is to map the objective positions within a field and, finally, the
nature of the habitus of the agents who occupy particular
positions can be understood. These agents act strategically
depending on their habitus in order to enhance their capital.
Bourdieu is particularly concerned with how powerful positions
within a field can perpetrate symbolic violence on less powerful
actors. Cultural mechanisms such as education impose a
dominant perspective on the rest of the population in order to
legitimate their power.
Bourdieu’s analysis of the aesthetic preferences of different
groups can be found in Distinction. The cultural preferences of
the various groups within society constitute coherent systems
that serve to unify those with similar tastes and differentiate
them from others with divergent tastes. Through the practical
application of preferences, people classify objects and in the
process classify themselves. Bourdieu thinks the field of taste
involves the intersection of social-class relationships and
cultural relationships. He argues that taste is an opportunity to
both experience and assert one’s position in the class hierarchy.
These tastes are engendered in the deep-rooted dispositions of
the habitus. Changes in tastes result from struggles for
dominance within both cultural and social-class fields as
different factions struggle to define high culture and taste.
Introduction from:
Distinction:
A Social Critique of the Judgement of Taste
by Pierre Bourdieu
©1984
Introduction
You said it, my good knight! There ought to be laws to
protect the body of acquired knowledge.
Take one of our good pupils, for example: modest
and diligent, from his earliest grammar classes he’s
kept a little notebook full of phrases.
After hanging on the lips of his teachers for twenty
years, he’s managed to build up an intellectual stock in
trade; doesn’t it belong to him as if it were a house, or
money?
Paul Claudel, Le soulier de satin, Day III, Scene ii
There is an economy of cultural goods, but it has a specific
logic. Sociology
endeavours to establish the conditions in which the consumers
of cultural goods,
and their taste for them, are produced, and at the same time to
describe the
different ways of appropriating such of these objects as are
regarded at a
particular moment as works of art, and the social conditions of
the constitution of
the mode of appropriation that is considered legitimate. But one
cannot fully
understand cultural practices unless ‘culture’, in the restricted,
normative sense of
ordinary usage, is brought back into ‘culture’ in the
anthropological sense, and
the elaborated taste for the most refined objects is reconnected
with the
elementary taste for the flavours of food.
Whereas the ideology of charisma regards taste in legitimate
culture as a gift
of nature, scientific observation shows that cultural needs are
the product of
upbringing and education: surveys establish that all cultural
practices (museum
visits, concert-going, reading etc.), and preferences in
literature, painting or
music, are closely linked to educational level (measured by
qualifications or
length of schooling) and secondarily to social origin.1 The
relative weight of
home background and of formal education (the effectiveness
and duration of
which are closely dependent on social origin) varies according
to the extent to
which the different cultural practices are recognized and taught
by the
educational system, and the influence of social origin is
strongest—other things
being equal—in ‘extra-curricular’ and avant-garde culture. To
the socially
recognized hierarchy of the arts, and within each of them, of
genres, schools or
periods, corresponds a social hierarchy of the consumers. This
predisposes tastes
to function as markers of ‘class’. The manner in which culture
has been acquired
lives on in the manner of using it: the importance attached to
manners can be
1 Bourdieu et al., Un art moyen: essai sur les usages sociaux de
la photographie (Paris,
Ed. de Minuit, 1965); P. Bourdieu and A. Darbel, L’Amour de
l’art: les musées et leur
public (Paris, Ed. de Minuit, 1966).
2
understood once it is seen that it is these imponderables of
practice which
distinguish the different—and ranked—modes of culture
acquisition, early or
late, domestic or scholastic, and the classes of individuals
which they
characterize (such as ‘pedants’ and mondains). Culture also has
its titles of
nobility—awarded by the educational system—and its
pedigrees, measured by
seniority in admission to the nobility.
The definition of cultural nobility is the stake in a struggle
which has gone on
unceasingly, from the seventeenth century to the present day,
between groups
differing in their ideas of culture and of the legitimate relation
to culture and to
works of art, and therefore differing in the conditions of
acquisition of which
these dispositions are the product2 Even in the classroom, the
dominant definition
of the legitimate way of appropriating culture and works of art
favours those who
have had early access to legitimate culture, in a cultured
household, outside of
scholastic disciplines, since even within the educational system
it devalues
scholarly knowledge and interpretation as ‘scholastic’ or even
‘pedantic’ in
favour of direct experience and simple delight.
The logic of what is sometimes called, in typically ‘pedantic’
language, the
‘reading’ of a work of art, offers an objective basis for this
opposition.
Consumption is, in this case, a stage in a process of
communication, that is, an
act of deciphering, decoding, which presupposes practical or
explicit mastery of a
cipher or code. In a sense, one can say that the capacity to see
(voir) is a function
of the knowledge (savoir), or concepts, that is, the words, that
are available to
name visible things, and which are, as it were, programmes for
perception. A
work of art has meaning and interest only for someone who
possesses the cultural
competence, that is, the code, into which it is encoded. The
conscious or
unconscious implementation of explicit or implicit schemes of
perception and
appreciation which constitutes pictorial or musical culture is the
hidden condition
for recognizing the styles characteristic of a period, a school or
an author, and,
more generally, for the familiarity with the internal logic of
works that aesthetic
enjoyment presupposes. A beholder who lacks the specific code
feels lost in a
chaos of sounds and rhythms, colours and lines, without rhyme
or reason. Not
having learnt to adopt the adequate disposition, he stops short at
what Erwin
Panofsky calls the ‘sensible properties’, perceiving a skin as
downy or lace-work
2 The word disposition seems particularly suited to express
what is covered by the
concept of habitus (defined as a system of dispositions)—used
later in this chapter. It
expresses first the result of an organizing action, with a
meaning close to that of words
such as structure; it also designates a way of being, a habitual
state (especially of the
body) and, in particular, a predisposition, tendency, propensity
or inclination. [The
semantic cluster of ‘disposition’ is rather wider in French than
in English, but as this
note—translated literally—shows, the equivalence is adequate.
Translator.] P. Bourdieu,
Outline of a Theory of Practice (Cambridge, Cambridge
UJniversity Press, 1977), p. 214,
n. 1.
3
as delicate, or at the emotional resonances aroused by these
properties, referring
to ‘austere’ colours or a ‘joyful’ melody. He cannot move from
the ‘primary
stratum of the meaning we can grasp on the basis of our
ordinary experience’ to
the ‘stratum of secondary meanings’, i.e., the ‘level of the
meaning of what is
signified’, unless he possesses the concepts which go beyond
the sensible
properties and which identify the specifically stylistic
properties of the work.3
Thus the encounter with a work of art is not ‘love at first sight’
as is generally
supposed, and the act of empathy, Einfühlung, which is the art-
lover’s pleasure,
presupposes an act of cognition, a decoding operation, which
implies the
implementation of a cognitive acquirement, a cultural code.4
This typically intellectualist theory of artistic perception
directly contradicts
the experience of the art-lovers closest to the legitimate
definition; acquisition of
legitimate culture by insensible familiarization within the
family circle tends to
favour an enchanted experience of culture which implies
forgetting the
acquisition.5 The ‘eye’ is a product of history reproduced by
education. This is
true of the mode of artistic perception now accepted as
legitimate, that is, the
aesthetic disposition, the capacity to consider in and for
themselves, as form
rather than function, not only the works designated for such
apprehension, i.e.,
legitimate works of art, but everything in the world, including
cultural objects
which are not yet consecrated—such as, at one time, primitive
arts, or, nowadays,
3 E. Panofsky, ‘Iconography and Iconology: An Introduction to
the Study of Renaissance
Art’, Meaning in the Visual Arts (New York, Doubleday, 1955),
p. 28.
4 It will be seen that this internalized code called culture
functions as cultural capital
owing to the fact that, being unequally distributed, it secures
profits of distinction.
5 The sense of familiarity in no way excludes the ethnocentric
misunderstanding which
results from applying the wrong code. Thus, Michael
Baxandall’s work in historical
ethnology enables us to measure all that separates the
perceptual schemes that now tend
to be applied to Quattrocento paintings and those which their
immediate addressees
applied. The ‘moral and spiritual eye’ of Quattrocento man, that
is, the set of cognitive
and evaluative dispositions which were the basis of his
perception of the world and his
perception of pictorial representation of the world, differs
radically from the ‘pure’ gaze
(purified, first of all, of reference to economic value) with
which the modern cultivated
spectator looks at works of art. As the contracts show, the
clients of Filippo Lippi,
Domenico Ghirlandaio or Piero della Francesca were concerned
to get ‘value for money’.
They approached works of art with the mercantile dispositions
of a businessman who can
calculate quantities and prices at a glance, and they applied
some surprising criteria of
appreciation, such as the expense of the colours, which sets
gold and ultramarine at the
top of the hierarchy. The artists, who shared this world view,
were led to include
arithmetical and geometrical devices in their compositions so as
to flatter this taste for
measurement and calculation; and they tended to exhibit the
technical virtuosity which, in
this context, is the most visible evidence of the quantity and
quality of the labour
provided; M. Baxandall, Painting and Experience in Fifteenth-
Century Italy: A Primer in
the Social History of Pictorial Style (Oxford, Oxford University
Press, 1972).
4
popular photography or kitsch—and natural objects. The ‘pure’
gaze is a
historical invention linked to the emergence of an autonomous
field of artistic
production, that is, a field capable of imposing its own norms
on both the
production and the consumption of its products.6 An art which,
like all Post-
Impressionist painting, is the product of an artistic intention
which asserts the
primacy of the mode of representation over the object of
representation demands
categorically an attention to form which previous art only
demanded
conditionally.
The pure intention of the artist is that of a producer who aims
to be
autonomous, that is, entirely the master of his product, who
tends to reject not
only the ‘programmes’ imposed a priori by scholars and scribes,
but also—
following the old hierarchy of doing and saying—the
interpretations
superimposed a posteriori on his work. The production of an
‘open work’,
intrinsically and deliberately polysemic, can thus be understood
as the final stage
in the conquest of artistic autonomy by poets and, following in
their footsteps, by
painters, who had long been reliant on writers and their work of
‘showing’ and
‘illustrating’. To assert the autonomy of production is to give
primacy to that of
which the artist is master, i.e., form, manner, style, rather than
the ‘subject’, the
external referent, which involves subordination to functions
even if only the most
elementary one, that of representing, signifying, saying
something. It also means
a refusal to recognize any necessity other than that inscribed in
the specific
tradition of the artistic discipline in question: the shift from an
art which imitates
nature to an art which imitates art, deriving from its own history
the exclusive
source of its experiments and even of its breaks with tradition.
An art which ever
increasingly contains reference to its own history demands to be
perceived
historically; it asks to be referred not to an external referent,
the represented or
designated ‘reality’, but to the universe of past and present
works of art. Like
artistic production, in that it is generated in a field, aesthetic
perception is
necessarily historical, inasmuch as it is differential, relational,
attentive to the
deviations (écarts) which make styles. Like the so-called naive
painter who,
operating outside the held and its specific traditions remains
external to the
history of the art, the ‘naive’ spectator cannot attain a specific
grasp of works of
art which only have meaning—or value—in relation to the
specific history of an
artistic tradition. The aesthetic disposition demanded by the
products of a highly
autonomous field of production is inseparable from a specific
cultural
competence. This historical culture functions as a principle of
pertinence which
enables one to identify, among the elements offered to the gaze,
all the distinctive
features and only these, by referring them, consciously or
unconsciously, to the
6 See P. Bourdieu, ‘Le marché des biens symboliques’, L’Anneé
Sociologique, 22 (1973),
49 126; and ‘Outline of a Sociological Theory of Art
Perception’, International Social
Science Journal, 20 (Winter 1968), 589-612.
5
universe of possible alternatives. This mastery is, for the most
part, acquired
simply by contact with works of art—that is, through an implicit
learning
analogous to that which makes it possible to recognize familiar
faces without
explicit rules or criteria—and it generally remains at a practical
level; it is what
makes it possible to identify styles, i.e., modes of expression
characteristic of a
period, a civilization or a school, without having to distinguish
clearly, or state
explicitly, the features which constitute their originality.
Everything seems to
suggest that even among professional valuers, the criteria which
define the
stylistic properties of the ‘typical works’ on which all their
judgements are based
usually remain implicit.
The pure gaze implies a break with the ordinary attitude
towards the world,
which, given the conditions in which it is performed, is also a
social separation.
Orteya y Gasset can be believed when he attributes to modern
art a systematic
refusal of all that is ‘human’, i.e., generic, common—as
opposed to distinctive, or
distinguished—namely, the passions, emotions and feelings
which ‘ordinary’
people invest in their ‘ordinary’ lives. It is as if the ‘popular
aesthetic’ (the
quotation marks are there to indicate that this is an aesthetic ‘in
itself’ not ‘for
itself’) were based on the affirmation of the continuity between
art and life,
which implies the subordination of form to function. This is
seen clearly in the
case of the novel and especially the theatre, where the working-
class audience
refuses any sort of formal experimentation and all the effects
which, by
introducing a distance from the accepted conventions (as
regards scenery, plot
etc.), tend to distance the spectator, preventing him from getting
involved and
fully identifying with the characters (I am thinking of Brechtian
‘alienation’ or
the disruption of plot in the nouveau roman). In contrast to the
detachment and
disinterestedness which aesthetic theory regards as the only way
of recognizing
the work of art for what it is, i.e., autonomous, selbständig, the
‘popular
aesthetic’ ignores or refuses the refusal of ‘facile’ involvement
and ‘vulgar’
enjoyment, a refusal which is the basis of the taste for formal
experiment. And
popular judgements of paintings or photographs spring from an
‘aesthetic’ (in
fact it is an ethos) which is the exact opposite of the Kantian
aesthetic. Whereas,
in order to grasp the specificity of the aesthetic judgement, Kant
strove to
distinguish that which pleases from that which gratifies and,
more generally, to
distinguish disinterestedness, the sole guarantor of the
specifically aesthetic
quality of contemplation, from the interest of reason which
defines the Good,
working-class people expect every image to explicitly perform a
function, if only
that of a sign, and their judgements make reference, often
explicitly, to the norms
of morality or agreeableness. Whether rejecting or praising,
their appreciation
always has an ethical basis.
Popular taste applies the schemes of the ethos, which pertain
in the ordinary
circumstances of life, to legitimate works of art, and so
performs a systematic
reduction of the things of art to the things of life. The very
seriousness (or
6
naivety) which this taste invests in fictions and representations
demonstrates a
contrario that pure taste performs a suspension of ‘naive’
involvement which is
one dimension of a ‘quasi-ludic’ relationship with the
necessities of the world.
Intellectuals could be said to believe in the representation—
literature, theatre,
painting—more than in the things represented, whereas the
people chiefly expect
representations and the conventions which govern them to allow
them to believe
‘naively’ in the things represented. The pure aesthetic is rooted
in an ethic, or
rather, an ethos of elective distance from the necessities of the
natural and social
world, which may take the form of moral agnosticism (visible
when ethical
transgression becomes an artistic parti pris) or of an
aestheticism which presents
the aesthetic disposition as a universally valid principle and
takes the bourgeois
denial of the social world to its limit. The detachment of the
pure gaze cannot be
dissociated from a general disposition towards the world which
is the paradoxical
product of conditioning by negative economic necessities—a
life of ease—that
tends to induce an active distance from necessity.
Although art obviously offers the greatest scope to the
aesthetic disposition,
there is no area of practice in which the aim of purifying,
refining and
sublimating primary needs and impulses cannot assert itself, no
area in which the
stylization of life, that is, the primacy of forms over function,
of manner over
matter, does not produce the same effects. And nothing is more
distinctive, more
distinguished, than the capacity to confer aesthetic status on
objects that are banal
or even ‘common’ (because the ‘common’ people make them
their own,
especially for aesthetic purposes), or the ability to apply the
principles of a ‘pure’
aesthetic to the most everyday choices of everyday life, e.g., in
cooking, clothing
or decoration, completely reversing the popular disposition
which annexes
aesthetics to ethics.
In fact, through the economic and social conditions which they
presuppose,
the different ways of relating to realities and fictions, of
believing in fictions and
the realities they simulate, with more or less distance and
detachment, are very
closely linked to the different possible positions in social space
and,
consequently, bound up with the systems of dispositions
(habitus) characteristic
of the different classes and class fractions. Taste classifies, and
it classifies the
classifier. Social subjects, classified by their classifications,
distinguish
themselves by the distinctions they make, between the beautiful
and the ugly, the
distinguished and the vulgar, in which their position in the
objective
classifications is expressed or betrayed. And statistical analysis
does indeed show
that oppositions similar in structure to those found in cultural
practices also
appear in eating habits. The antithesis between quantity and
quality, substance
and form, corresponds to the opposition—linked to different
distances from
necessity—between the taste of necessity, which favours the
most ‘filling’ and
most economical foods, and the taste of liberty or luxury—
which shifts the
7
emphasis to the manner (of presenting, serving, eating etc.) and
tends to use
stylized forms to deny function.
The science of taste and of cultural consumption begins with a
transgression
that is in no way aesthetic: it has to abolish the sacred frontier
which makes
legitimate culture a separate universe, in order to discover the
intelligible
relations which unite apparently incommensurable ‘choices’,
such as preferences
in music and food, painting and sport, literature and hairstyle.
This barbarous
reintegration of aesthetic consumption into the world of
ordinary consumption
abolishes the opposition, which has been the basis of high
aesthetics since Kant,
between the ‘taste of sense’ and the ‘taste of reflection’, and
between facile
pleasure, pleasure reduced to a pleasure of the senses, and pure
pleasure, pleasure
purified of pleasure, which is predisposed to become a symbol
of moral
excellence and a measure of the capacity for sublimation which
defines the truly
human man. The culture which results from this magical
division is sacred.
Cultural consecration does indeed confer on the objects, persons
and situations it
touches, a sort of ontological promotion akin to a
transubstantiation. Proof
enough of this is found in the two following quotations, which
might almost have
been written for the delight of the sociologist:
‘What struck me most is this: nothing could be obscene on the
stage of our
premier theatre, and the ballerinas of the Opera, even as naked
dancers, sylphs,
sprites or Bacchae, retain an inviolable purity.’7
‘There are obscene postures: the stimulated intercourse which
offends the
eye. Clearly, it is impossible to approve, although the
interpolation of such
gestures in dance routines does give them a symbolic and
aesthetic quality which
is absent from the intimate scenes the cinema daily flaunts
before its spectators’
eyes . . . As for the nude scene, what can one say, except that it
is brief and
theatrically not very effective? I will not say it is chaste or
innocent, for nothing
commercial can be so described. Let us say it is not shocking,
and that the chief
objection is that it serves as a box-office gimmick. . . . In Hair,
the nakedness
fails to be symbolic.’8
The denial of lower, coarse, vulgar, venal, servile—in a word,
natural—
enjoyment, which constitutes the sacred sphere of culture,
implies an affirmation
of the superiority of those who can be satisfied with the
sublimated, refined,
disinterested, gratuitous, distinguished pleasures forever closed
to the profane.
That is why art and cultural consumption are predisposed,
consciously and
deliberately or not, to fulfil a social function of legitimating
social differences.
Translated by Richard Nice
7 O. Merlin, ‘Mlle. Thibon dans la vision de Marguerite’, Le
Monde, 9 December 1965.
8 F. Chenique, ‘Hair est-il immoral?’ Le Monde, 28 January
1970.
Power-Dependence Relations
Author(s): Richard M. Emerson
Reviewed work(s):
Source: American Sociological Review, Vol. 27, No. 1 (Feb.,
1962), pp. 31-41
Published by: American Sociological Association
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2089716 .
Accessed: 28/12/2011 21:47
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the
Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars,
researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of
content in a trusted digital archive. We use information
technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new
forms
of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please
contact [email protected]
American Sociological Association is collaborating with JSTOR
to digitize, preserve and extend access to
American Sociological Review.
http://www.jstor.org
http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=asa
http://www.jstor.org/stable/2089716?origin=JSTOR-pdf
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
POWER-DEPENDENCE RELATIONS
RICHARD M. EMERSON
University of Cincinnati
A simple theory of power relations is developed in an effort to
resolve some of the ambiguities
surrounding "power," "authority," "legitimacy," and power
"structures," through bringing
them together in a coherent scheme. After defining a reciprocal
power-dependence relation,
attention is focused upon properties of balance and "balancing
operations" in such relations.
The theory dictates exactly four generic types of balancing
process, and discussion of these
leads directly into processes of group formation, including the
emergence of group norms, role
structure and status hierarchy, all presented as the outcome of
balancing tendencies in power
relations. Within the framework of this theory, authority
appears quite naturally to be
legitimized power, vested in roles, and "legitimation" is seen as
a special case of the coalition
process through which norms and role-prescriptions are formed.
Finally, through treating
both persons and groups as actors in a power-network (two or
more connected power-
dependence relations) the door is opened for meaningful
analysis of complex power struc-
tures. Brief reference is made to findings from two experiments
pertaining to hypotheses
advanced in this theory.
JUDGING from the frequent occurrence of
such words as power, influence, domi-
nance and submission, status and author-
ity, the importance of power is widely recog-
nized, yet considerable confusion exists
concerning these concepts.' There is an ex-
tensive literature pertaining to power, on both
theoretical and empirical levels, and in small
group 2 as well as large community contexts.3
Unfortunately, this already large and rap-
idly growing body of research has not
achieved the cumulative character desired.
Our integrated knowledge of power does not
significantly surpass the conceptions left by
Max Weber.4
This suggests that there is a place at this
moment for a systematic treatment of social
power. The underdeveloped state of this area
is further suggested by what appears, to this
author, to be a recurrent flaw in common
conceptions of social power; a flaw which
helps to block adequate theoretical develop-
ment as well as meaningful research. That
flaw is the implicit treatment of power as
though it were an attribute of a person or
group ("X is an influential person." "Y is a
powerful group," etc.). Given this concep-
tion, the natural research question becomes
"Who in community X are the power kold-
ers?". The project then proceeds to rank-
order persons by some criterion of power,
and this ordering is called the power-struc-
ture. This is a highly questionable represen-
tation of a "structure," based upon a ques-
tionable assumption of generalized power.5
It is commonly observed that some person
X dominates Y, while being subservient in
relations with Z. Furthermore, these power
relations are frequently intransitive! Hence,
1 See the Communications by Jay Butler and
Paul Harrison on "On Power and Authority: An
Exchange on Concepts," American Sociological
Review, 25 (October, 1960), pp. 731-732. That
both men can be essentially correct in the points
they make yet fail to reconcile these points,
strongly suggests the need for conceptual devel-
opment in the domain of power relations.
2Among many studies, see Ronald Lippitt,
Norman Polansky, Fritz Redl and Sidney Rosen,
"The Dynamics of Power," Human Relations,
5 (February, 1952), pp. 37-64.
3 Floyd Hunter, Community Power Structure,
Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press,
1953.
4 Max Weber, in The Theory of Social and
Economic Organization, New York: Oxford Uni-
versity Press, 1947, presents what is still a classic
formulation of power, authority and legitimacy.
However, it is characteristic of Weber that he
constructs a typology rather than an organized
theory of power.
r See Raymond E. Wolfinger, "Reputation and
Reality in the Study of 'Community Power',"
American Sociological Review, 25 (October,
1960), pp. 636-644, for a well taken critical re-
view of Floyd Hunter's work on these very points.
The notion of "generalized power" which is not
restricted to specific social relations, if taken
literally, is probably meaningless. Power may
indeed be generalized across a finite set of rela-
tions in a power network, but this notion, too,
requires very careful analysis. Are you dealing
with some kind of halo effect (reputations if you
wish), or are the range and boundary of general-
ized power anchored in the power structure itself?
These are questions which must be asked and
answered.
31
32 AMERICAN SOCIOLOGICAL REVIEW
to say that "X has power" is vacant, unless
we specify "over whom." In making these
necessary qualifications we force ourselves
to face up to the obvious: power is a prop-
erty of the social relation; it is not an attri-
bute of the actor.6
In this paper an attempt is made to con-
struct a simple theory of the power aspects
of social relations. Attention is focused upon
characteristics of the relationship as such,
with little or no regard for particular fea-
tures of the persons or groups engaged in
such relations. Personal traits, skills or pos-
sessions (such as wealth) which might be
relevant to power in one relation are infi-
nitely variable across the set of possible re-
lations, and hence have no place in a general
theory.
THE POWER-DEPENDENCE RELATION
While the theory presented here is an-
chored most intimately in small group re-
search, it is meant to apply to more complex
community relations as well. In an effort to
make these conceptions potentially as broadly
applicable as possible, we shall speak of re-
lations among actors, where an actor can be
either a person or a group. Unless otherwise
indicated, any relation discussed might be a
person-person, group-person or group-group
relation.
Social relations commonly entail ties of
mutual dependence between the parties. A
depends upon B if he aspires to goals or
gratifications whose achievement is facili-
tated by appropriate actions on B's part. By
virtue of mutual dependency, it is more or
less imperative to each party that he be
able to control or influence the other's con-
duct. At the same time, these ties of mutual
dependence imply that each party is in a
position, to some degree, to grant or deny,
facilitate or hinder, the other's gratification.
Thus, it would appear that the power to con-
trol or influence the other resides in control
over the things he values, which may range
all the way from oil resources to ego-support,
depending upon the relation in question.
In short, power resides implicitly in the
other's dependency. When this is recognized,
the analysis will of necessity revolve largely
around the concept of dependence.7
Two variables appear to function jointly
in fixing the dependence of one actor upon
another. Since the precise nature of this joint
function is an empirical question, our propo-
sition can do no more than specify the di-
rectional relationships involved:
Dependence (Dab). The dependence of actor
A upon actor B is (1) directly proportional
to A's motivational investment in goals medi-
ated by B, and (2) inversely proportional to
the availability of those goals to A outside
of the A-B relation.
In this proposition "goal" is used in the
broadest possible sense to refer to gratifica-
tions consciously sought as well as rewards
unconsciously obtained through the relation-
ship. The "availability" of such goals out-
side of the relation refers to alternative ave-
nues of goal-achievement, most notably other
social relations. The costs associated with
such alternatives must be included in any
assessment of dependency.8
If the dependence of one party provides
the basis for the power of the other, that
power must be defined as a potential in-
fluence:
Power (Pab). The power of actor A over
actor B is the amount of resistance on the
part of B which can be potentially overcome
by A.
Two points must be made clear about this
definition. First, the power defined here will
not be, of necessity, observable in every in-
teractive episode between A and B, yet we
suggest that it exists nonetheless as a poten-
tial, to be explored, tested, and occasionally
employed by the participants. Pab will be
,'Just as power is often treated as though it
were a property of the person, so leadership, con-
formity, etc., are frequently referred to the per-
sonal traits of "leaders," "conformers" and so on,
as if they were distinguishable types of people. In
a sociological perspective such behavior should be
explicitly treated as an attribute of a relation
rather than a person.
7 The relation between power and dependence is
given similar emphasis in the systematic treatment
by J. Thibaut and H. H. Kelley, The Social
Psychology of Groups, New York: John Wiley
and Sons, 1959.
8 The notion of "opportunity costs" in economics
is a similar idea. If an employee has alternative
employment opportunities, and if these opportunities
have low associated cost (travel, etc.), the em-
ployee's dependence upon his current employer is
reduced.
POWER-DEPENDENCE RELATIONS 33
empirically manifest only if A makes some
demand, and only if this demand runs
counter to B's desires (resistance to be over-
come). Any operational definition must make
reference to change in the conduct of B at-
tributable to demands made by A.
Second, we define power as the "resist-
ance" which can be overcome, without re-
stricting it to any one domain of action.
Thus, if A is dependent upon B for love and
respect, B might then draw A into criminal
activity which he would normally resist. The
reader might object to this formulation, argu-
ing that social power is in fact restricted to
certain channels. If so, the reader is appar-
ently concerned with "legitimized power"
embedded in a social structure. Rather than
begin at this more evolved level, we hope
to derive legitimized power in the theory
itself.
The premise we began with can now be
stated as Pab=Dba; the power of A over B
is equal to, and based upon, the dependence
of B upon A.9 Recognizing the reciprocity
of social relations, we can represent a power-
dependence relation as a pair of equations:
Pab=Dba
Pba=Dab.
Before proceeding further we should em-
phasize that these formulations have been
so worded in the hope that they will apply
across a wide range of social life. At a
glance our conception of dependence con-
tains two variables remarkably like supply
and demand ("availability" and "motiva-
tional investment," respectively).10 We pre-
fer the term dependency over these economic
terms because it facilitates broader applica-
tion, for all we need to do to shift these ideas
from one area of application to another is
change the motivational basis of dependency.
We can speak of the economic dependence
of a home builder upon a loan agency as
varying directly with his desire for the home,
and hence capital, and inversely with the
"availability" of capital from other agencies.
Similarly, a child may be dependent upon
another child based upon motivation toward
the pleasures of collective play, the
availability of alternative playmates, etc.
The same generic power-dependence relation
is involved in each case. The dependency
side of the equation may show itself in
"friendship" among playmates, in "filial
love" between parent and child, in "respect
for treaties" among nations. On the other
side of the equation, I am sure no one doubts
that mothers, lovers, children, and nations
enjoy the power to influence their respective
partners, within the limit set by the partner's
dependence upon them.
Finally, because these concepts are meant
to apply across a wide variety of social sit-
uations, operational definitions cannot be ap-
propriately presented here. Operational defi-
nitions provide the necessary bridge between
generalizing concepts on the one hand, and
the concrete features of a specific research
situation on the other hand. Hence, there is
no one proper operational definition for a
theoretical concept."
BALANCE AND IMBALANCE
The notion of reciprocity in power-de-
pendency relations raises the question of
equality or inequality of power in the rela-
tion. If the power of A over B (Pab) is con-
fronted by equal opposing power of B over
A, is power then neutralized or cancelled
out? We suggest that in such a balanced con-
9 In asserting that power is based upon the
dependency of the other, it might appear that we
are dealing with one of the bases of power
("reward power") listed by John R. P. French,
Jr. and Bertram Raven, "The Bases of Social
Power," Studies in Social Power, D. Cartwright,
editor, Ann Arbor, Michigan: Institute for Social
Research, 1959. However, careful attention to our
highly generalized conception of dependence will
show that it covers most if not all of the forms
of power listed in that study.
10 Professor Alfred Kuhn, Department of Eco-
nomics, University of Cincinnati, has been working
on a theory for power analysis soon to be pub-
lished. The scheme he develops, though very
similar to the one presented here, is put together
in a different way. It is anchored more tightly
to economic concepts, and hence its implications
lead off in different directions from those presented
below.
1" Many different operational definitions can serve
one theoretical concept, and there is no reason to
require that they produce intercorrelated results
when applied in the same research situation. While
the controversies surrounding "operationalism" have
now been largely resolved, there remains some con-
fusion on this point. See, for example, Bernice
Eisman, "Some Operational Measures of Cohesive-
ness and Their Interrelations," Human Relations,
12 (May, 1959), pp. 183-189.
34 AMERICAN SOCIOLOGICAL REVIEW
dition, power is in no way removed from the
relationship. A pattern of "dominance" might
not emerge in the interaction among these
actors, but that does not imply that power is
inoperative in either or both directions. A
balanced relation and an unbalanced relation
are represented respectively as follows:
Pab=Dba Pab=Dba
II II V V
Pba-Dab Pba=Dab
Consider two social relations, both of which
are balanced, but at different levels of de-
pendence (say Loeb and Leopold, as com-
pared with two casual friends). A moment's
thought will reveal the utility of the argu-
ment that balance does not neutralize power,
for each party may continue to exert pro-
found control over the other. It might even
be meaningful to talk about the parties being
controlled by the relation itself.
Rather than cancelling out considerations
of power, reciprocal power provides the basis
for studying three more features of power-
relations: first, a power advantage can be
defined as Pab minus Pba, which can be
either positive or negative (a power disad-
vantage); 12 second, the cohesion of a rela-
tionship can be defined as the average of
Dab and Dba, though this definition can be
refined; 13 and finally, it opens the door to
the study of balancing operations as struc-
tural changes in power-dependence relations
which tend to reduce power advantage.
Discussion of balancing tendencies should
begin with a concrete illustration. In the
unbalanced relation represented symbolically
above, A is the more powerful party because
B is the more dependent of the two. Let
actor B be a rather "unpopular" girl, with
puritanical upbringing, who wants desper-
ately to date; and let A be a young man who
occasionally takes her out, while dating other
girls as well. (The reader can satisfy himself
about A's power advantage in this illustra-
tion by referring to the formulations above.)
Assume further that A "discovers" this
power advantage, and, in exploring for the
limits of his power, makes sexual advances.
In this simplified illustration, these advances
should encounter resistance in B's puritanical
values. Thus, when a power advantage is
used, the weaker member will achieve one
value at the expense of other values.
In this illustration the tensions involved
in an unbalanced relation need not be long
endured. They can be reduced in either of
two ways: (1) the girl might reduce the
psychic costs involved in continuing the rela-
tion by redefining her moral values, with
appropriate rationalizations and shifts in
reference group attachments; or (2) she
might renounce the value of dating, develop
career aspirations, etc., thus reducing A's
power. Notice that the first solution does
not of necessity alter the unbalanced rela-
tion. The weaker member has sidestepped
one painful demand but she is still vulnerable
to new demands. By contrast, the second
solution alters the power relation itself. In
general, it appears that an unbalanced rela-
tion is unstable for it encourages the use of
power which in turn sets in motion processes
which we will call (a) cost reduction and
(b) balancing operations.'4
COST REDUCTION
The "cost" referred to here amounts to
the "resistance" to be overcome in our defini-
tion of power-the cost involved for one
party in meeting the demands made by the
other. The process of cost reduction in power-
dependence relations shows itself in many
varied forms. In the courting relation above
it took the form of alteration in moral atti-
tudes on the part of a girl who wanted to
be popular; in industry it is commonly seen
as the impetus for improved plant efficiency
and technology in reducing the cost of pro-
duction. What we call the "mark of oppres-
sion" in the character structure of members 12 J. Thibaut and H.
H. Kelley, op. cit., pp. 107-
108.
13 This definition of cohesion, based upon depend-
ency, seems to have one advantage over the defini-
tion offered by Leon Festinger, et al., Theory and
Experiment in Social Communication, Ann Arbor:
Research Center for Group Dynamics, University
of Michigan Press, 1950. The Festinger definition
takes into account only one of the two variables
involved in dependency.
14 The "tensions of imbalance," which are as-
sumed to make an unbalanced relation unstable,
are closely related to the idea of "distributive
justice" discussed by George C. Homans, Social
Behavior: Its Elementary Forms, New York:
Harcourt, Brace and World, Inc., 1961. All of
what Homans has to say around this idea could
be fruitfully drawn into the present formulation.
POWER-DEPENDENCE RELATIONS 35
of low social castes (the submissive and
"painless" loss of freedom) might well in-
volve the same power processes, as does the
"internalization of parental codes" in the
socialization process. In fact, the oedipal
conflict might be interpreted as a special
case of the tensions of imbalance in a power-
dependence relation, and cost reduction takes
the form of identification and internalization
as classically described. "Identification with
the aggressor" in any context would appear
to be explainable in terms of cost reduction.
In general, cost reduction is a process in-
volving change in values (personal, social,
economic) which reduces the pains incurred
in meeting the demands of a powerful other.
It must be emphasized, however, that these
adjustments do not necessarily alter the bal-
ance or imbalance of the relation, and, as
a result, they must be distinguished from
the more fundamental balancing operations
described below. It must be recognized that
cost reducing tendencies will take place
even under conditions of balance, and while
this is obvious in economic transactions, it is
equally true of other social relations, where
the "costs" involved are anchored in modi-
fiable attitudes and values. The intense cohe-
sion of a lasting social relation like the Loeb-
Leopold relation mentioned above can be
attributed in part to the cost reduction
processes involved in the progressive forma-
tion of their respective personalities, taking
place in the interest of preserving the valued
relation. We suggest that cost reducing tend-
encies generally will function to deepen and
stabilize social relations over and above the
condition of balance.
BALANCING OPERATIONS
The remainder of this paper will deal with
balancing processes which operate through
changes in the variables which define the
structure of the power-dependence relation
as such. The formal notation adopted here
suggests exactly four generic types of bal-
ancing operation. In the unbalanced relation
Pab=Dba
v v, balance can be restored either by
Pba-Dab
an increase in Dab or by a decrease in Dba.
If we recall that dependence is a joint func-
tion of two variables, the following altera-
tions will move the relation toward a state
of balance:
1. If B reduces motivational investment
in goals mediated by A;
2. If B cultivates alternative sources for
gratification of those goals;
3. If A increases motivational investment
in goals mediated by B;
4. If A is denied alternative sources for
achieving those goals.
While these four types of balancing opera-
tion are dictated by the logic of the scheme,
we suggest that each corresponds to well
known social processes. The first operation
yields balance through motivational with-
drawal by B, the weaker member. The sec-
ond involves the cultivation of alternative
social relations by B. The third is based
upon "giving status" to A, and the fourth
involves coalition and group formation.
In some of these processes the role of
power is well known, while in others it seems
to have escaped notice. In discussing any one
of these balancing operations it must be
remembered that a prediction of which one
(or what combination) of the four will take
place must rest upon analysis of conditions
involved in the concrete case at hand.
In the interest of simplicity and clarity,
we will illustrate each of the four generic
types of balancing operation in relations
among children in the context of play. Con-
sider two children equally motivated toward
the pleasures of collective play and equally
capable of contributing to such play. These
children, A and B, form a balanced relation
if we assume further that each has the other
as his only playmate, and the give-and-take
of their interactions might well be imagined,
involving the emergence of such equalitarian
rules as "taking turns," etc. Suppose now
that a third child, C, moves into the neigh-
borhood and makes the acquaintance of A,
but not B. The A-B relation will be thrown
out of balance by virtue of A's decreased de-
pendence upon B. The reader should con-
vince himself of this fact by referring back
to the proposition on dependence. Without
any of these parties necessarily "understand-
ing" what is going on, we would predict that
A would slowly come to dominate B in the
pattern of their interactions. On more fre-
quent occasions B will find himself deprived
of the pleasures A can offer, thus slowly
36 AMERICAN SOCIOLOGICAL REVIEW
coming to sense his own dependency more
acutely. By the same token A will more
frequently find B saying "yes" instead of
"no" to his proposals, and he will gain in-
creased awareness of his power over B. The
growing self-images of these children will
surely reflect and perpetuate this pattern.
OPERATION NUMBER ONE: WITHDRAWAL
We now have the powerful A making de-
mands of the dependent B. One of the
processes through which the tensions in the
unbalanced A-B relation can be reduced is
motivational withdrawal on the part of B,
for this will reduce Dba and Pab. In this
illustration, child B might lose some of his
interest in collective play under the impact
of frustrations and demands imposed by A.
Such a withdrawal from the play relation
would presumably come about if the other
three balancing operations were blocked by
the circumstances peculiar to the situation.
The same operation was illustrated above
in the case of the girl who might renounce
the value of dating. It would seem to be
involved in the dampened level of aspiration
associated with the "mark of oppression"
referred to above.
In general, the denial of dependency in-
volved in this balancing operation will have
the effect of moving actors away from rela-
tions which are unbalanced to their disad-
vantage. The actor's motivational orienta-
tions and commitments toward different
areas of activity will intimately reflect this
process.
OPERATION NUMBER TWO: EXTENSION OF
POWER NETWORK
Withdrawal as a balancing operation en-
tails subjective alterations in the weaker
actor. The second operation takes place
through alterations in a structure we shall
call a power network, defined as two or more
connected power-dependence relations. As we
have seen in our illustration, when the C-A
relation is connected through A with the
A-B relation, forming a simple linear net-
work C-A-B, the properties of A-B are al-
tered. In this example, a previously balanced
A-B relation is thrown out of balance, giving
A a power advantage. This points up the
general fact that while each relation in a
network will involve interactions which ap-
pear to be independent of other relations
in the network (e.g., A and B are seen to
play together in the absence of C; C and A
in the absence of B), the internal features
of one relation are nonetheless a function of
the entire network. Any adequate conception
of a "power structure" must be based upon
this fact.
In this illustration the form of the network
throws both relations within it out of bal-
ance, thus stimulating one or several of the
balancing operations under discussion. If
balancing operation number two takes place,
the network will be extended by the forma-
tion of new relationships. The tensions of
imbalance in the A-B and A-C relations will
make B and C "ready" to form new friend-
ships (1) with additional children D and E,
thus lengthening a linear network, or (2)
with each other, thus "closing" the network.
It is important to notice that the lengthened
network balances some relations, but not the
network as a whole, while the closed network
is completely balanced under the limiting
assumptions of this illustration. Thus, we
might offer as a corollary to operation num-
ber two: Power networks tend to achieve
closure.'5
If the reader is dissatisfied with this illus-
tration in children's play relations, let A be
the loan agent mentioned earlier, and B, C,
. . . N be home builders or others dependent
upon A for capital. This is the familiar
monopoly situation with the imbalance com-
monly attributed to it. As a network, it is
a set of relations connected only at A. Just
as the children were "ready" to accept new
friends, so the community of actors B, C,
... N is ready to receive new loan agencies.
15 The notion of closed versus open networks as
discussed here can be directly related to research
dealing with communication networks, such as that
reported by Harold J. Leavitt, "Some Effects of
Communication Patterns on Group Performance,"
Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology, 46
(January, 1951), pp. 38-50, in which the limiting
assumptions involved in this discussion are fully
met by experimental controls. In discussing those
experiments in terms of the concepts in this theory
we would consider each actor's dependence upon
other actors for information. A formal treatment of
such networks is suggested by A. Bavelas, "A
Mathematical Model For Group Structure," Ap-
plied Anthropology, 7 (Summer, 1948), pp. 16-30.
POWER-DEPENDENCE RELATIONS 37
Balancing operation number 2 involves in
all cases the diffusion of dependency into
new relations in a network. A final illustra-
tion of this principle can be found in institu-
tionalized form in some kinship systems in-
volving the extended family. In the case of
the Hopi, for example, Dorothy Eggan has
described at length the diffusion of child
dependency among many' "mothers," thus
draining off much of the force of oedipal
conflicts in that society.'6 We have already
suggested that oedipal conflict may be taken
as a special case of the tension of imbalance,
which in this case appears to be institution-
ally handled in a manner resembling opera-
tion number two. This is not to be taken,
however, as an assertion that the institution
evolved as a balancing process, though this
is clearly open for consideration.
It is convenient at this juncture to take
up balancing operation number 4, leaving
number 3 to the last.
OPERATION NUMBER FOUR: COALITION
FORMATION
Let us continue with the same illustration.
When the B-C relation forms, closing the
C-A-B network in the process of balancing,
we have what appears to be a coalition of
the two weaker against the one stronger.
This, however, is not technically the case,
for A is not involved in the B-C interactions;
he simply exists as an alternative playmate
for both B and C.
The proper representation of coalitions
in a triad would be (AB)-C, (AC)-B, or
(BC)-A. That is, a triadic network reduces
to a coalition only if two members unite as
a single actor in the process of dealing
directly with the third. The difference in-
volved here may be very small in behavioral
terms, and the distinction may seem overly
refined, but it goes to the heart of an im-
portant conceptual problem (the difference
between a closed "network" and a "group"),
and it rests upon the fact that two very
different balancing operations are involved.
The C-A-B network is balanced through the
addition of a third relation (C-B) in opera-
tion number two, but it is still just a power
network. In operation number 4 it achieves
balance through collapsing the two-relational
network into one group-person relation with
the emergence of a "collective actor." Opera-
tion number two reduces the power of the
stronger actor, while number 4 increases the
power of weaker actors through collectiviza-
tion. If the rewards mediated by A are such
that they can be jointly enjoyed by B and C,
then the tensions of imbalance in the A-B
and A-C relations can be resolved in the
(BC)-A coalition.
In a general way, Marx was asking for
balancing operation number 4 in his call to
"Workers of the world," and the collectiviza-
tion of labor can be taken as an illustration
of this balancing tendency as an historic
process. Among the balancing operations
described here, coalition formation is the one
most commonly recognized as a power proc-
ess. However, the more general significance
of this balancing operation seems to have es-
caped notice, for the typical coalition is only
one of the many forms this same operation
takes. For this reason the next section will
explore coalition processes further.
THE ORGANIZED GROUP
We wish to suggest that the coalition
process is basically involved in all organized
group functioning, whether the group be
called a coalition or not. We believe this
illuminates the role which power processes
play in the emergence and maintenance of
group structure in general.
In the typical coalition pattern, (AB)-C,
A and B constitute a collective actor in the
sense that they act as one, presenting them-
selves to their common environment as a sin-
gle unit. A coalition, as one type of group,
is characterized by the fact that (a) the
common environment is an actor to be
controlled, and (b) its unity is historically
based upon efforts to achieve that control.
Now, all we need do to blend this type of
group with groups in general is to dehumanize
the environmental problem which the group
collectively encounters. Thus, instead of
having the control of actor C as its end,
the group attempts to control C in the
interest of achieving X, some "group goal."
Now, if C also aspires toward X, and if C
is dependent upon the group for achieving X,
C might well be one of the group members-
any member; Thus, in a three-member group
16 Dorothy Eggan, "The General Problem of Hopi
Adjustment," American Anthropologist, 45 (July-
September, 1943), pp. 357-373.
38 AMERICAN SOCIOLOGICAL REVIEW
we have three coalition structures as intra-
group relations, each representable as
([AB] -C)-X, with A, B and C interchange-
able.
The situation involved here is reminiscent
of the rapidly forming and reforming coali-
tions in unconsolidated children's play
groups. As the group consolidates, these co-
alitions do not drop out of the picture; they
become stabilized features of group struc-
ture, and the stabilization process is identical
with "norm formation." In fact, the demands
made by (AB) of C in the power process
within ([AB]-C) are exactly what we nor-
mally call group norms and role-prescrip-
tions. Such norms are properly viewed as
the "voice" of a collective actor, standing in
coalition against the object of its demands.
This reasoning suggests an idealized con-
ception of group structure, based upon two
types of collective demands:
(1) Role-Prescriptions. Specifications of be-
havior which all group members expect
(demand) of one or more but not all
members.
(2) Group Norms. Specifications of behavior
which all group members expect of all
group members.
Certain actions, when performed by some
member or members, need not be performed
by all other members to properly facilitate
group functioning. These will tend to be in-
corporated in role-prescriptions, which, taken
together, provide a division of labor in a role
structure. Roles are defined and enforced
through a consolidation of power in coalition
formation. Likewise with group norms. Thus,
the structure of a group (its norms and pre-
scriptions) will specify the makeup of the
coalition a member would face for any
group-relevant act he might perform.
This conception of group structure is ideal-
ized in the sense that it describes complete
consensus among members, even to the point
of group identification and internalization of
collective demands (members expect things
of themselves in the above definitions). Bal-
ancing operations, along with cost reduction,
should move group structure toward this
ideal.
AUTHORITY
It should be clear that in introducing con-
ceptions of group structure we have in no
way digressed from our discussion of power
processes, for the emergence of these struc-
tural forms is attributed directly to operation
number four, closely resembling coalition
formation. Even the most formalized role-
prescription is properly viewed as the "voice"
of all members standing as a coalition in
making its demand of the occupant of the
role. Whenever a specific member finds occa-
sion to remind another member of his
"proper" job in terms of such prescriptions,
he speaks with the authority of the group
behind him; he is "authorized" to speak for
them. In this sense, every member has au-
thority of a kind (as in civil arrest), but
authority is usually used to refer to power
vested in an office or role. The situation is
basically the same, however, in either case.
The occupant of such a role has simply been
singled out and commissioned more explicitly
to speak for the group in the group's deal-
ings with its members. That authority is
limited power follows from logical necessity
when role-prescriptions are treated as they
are here. A dean, for example, can force
faculty member A to turn in his grades on
time because the demand is "legitimate,"
that is, supported by a coalition of all other
faculty members joining with the dean in
making the demand. If that dean, however,
were to employ sanctions in an effort to
induce that member to polish the dean's
private car, the "coalition" would immedi-
ately re-form around the faculty member, as
expressed in role-prescriptions defining the
boundary of "legitimate power" or authority.
The dean's authority is power contained and
restricted through balancing operation num-
ber four, coalition formation.
The notion of legitimacy is important, for
authority is more than balanced power; it is
directed power which can be employed
(legitimately) only in channels defined by
the norms of the group. A person holding
such authority is commissioned; he does not
simply have the right to rule or govern-he
is obliged to. Thus, authority emerges as a
transformation of power in a process called
"legitimation," and that process is one spe-
cial case of balancing operation number
four.17
17 The process of legitimation has sometimes been
described as a tactic employed by a person aspiring
POWER-DEPENDENCE RELATIONS 39
Earlier in this section we referred to the
common phenomenon of rapidly forming
and re-forming coalitions in children's play
groups. Our reasoning suggests that it is
precisely through these coalition processes
that unifying norms emerge. These fluctu-
ating coalitions can be taken as the proto-
type of organized group life wherein the
tempo of coalition realignment is accelerated
to the point of being a blur before our eyes.
Stated more accurately, the norms and pre-
scriptions define implicitly the membership
of the coalition which would either support
or oppose any member if he were to perform
any action relevant to those norms.
OPERATION NUMBER THREE: EMERGENCE
OF STATUS
One important feature of group structure
remains to be discussed: status and status
hierarchies. It is interesting that the one
remaining balancing operation provided in
this theory takes us naturally to the emer-
gence of status ordering. Operation number
three increases the weaker member's power
to control the formerly more powerful mem-
ber through increasing the latter's motiva-
tional investment in the relation. This is
normally accomplished through giving him
status recognition in one or more of its
many forms, from ego-gratifications to mone-
tary differentials. The ego-rewards, such as
prestige, loom large in this process because
they are highly valued by many recipients
while given at low cost to the giver.
The discussion of status hierarchies forces
us to consider intra-group relations, and how
this can be done in a theory which treats
the group in the singular as an actor. The
answer is contained in the idealized concep-
tion of group structure outlined above. That
conception implies that every intra-group
relation involves at once every member of
the group. Thus, in a group with members
A, B, C, and D, the relations A-B, A-C, etc.
do not exist. Any interactions between A and
B, for example, lie outside of the social sys-
tem in question unless one or both of these
persons "represents" the group in his actions,
as in the coalition pattern discussed at length
above. The relations which do exist are
(ABCD)-A, (ABCD)-B, (ABCD)-C and
(ABCD)-D as a minimum, plus whatever
relations of the (ABCD)-(AB) type may
be involved in the peculiar structure of the
group in question. Thus, in a group of N
members we have theoretical reason for deal-
ing with N group-member relations rather
N(N-1)
than considering all of the possible
2
member-member relations. Each of these
group-member relations can now be ex-
pressed in the familiar equations for a power-
dependence relation:
Pgmi=Dmig
Pmig=Dgmi.
To account for the emergence of a status
hierarchy within a group of N members, we
start with a set of N group-member relations
of this type and consider balancing opera-
tions in these relations.
Let us imagine a five member group and
proceed on three assumptions: (1) status
involves differential valuation of members
(or roles) by the group, and this valuation
is equivalent to, or an expression of, Dgmi;
(2) a member who is highly valued by the
group is highly valued in other similar
groups he belongs to or might freely join;
and (3) all five members have the same mo-
tivational investment in the group at the
outset. Assumptions 2 and 3 are empirical,
and when they are true they imply that Dgm
and Dmg are inversely related across the N
group-member relations. This in turn implies
a state of imbalance of a very precarious
nature so far as group stability is concerned.
to power or trying to hold his power, rather than
a process through which persons are granted
restricted power. For example, C. Wright Mills
states: "Those in authority attempt to justify their
rule over institutions by linking it, as if it were a
necessary consequence, with widely believed in
moral symbols, sacred emblems, legal formulae.
These central conceptions may refer to god or gods,
the 'vote of the majority,' 'the will of the people,'
'the aristocracy of talent or wealth,' to the 'divine
right of kings,' or to the allegedly extraordinary
endowments of the ruler himself. Social scientists,
following Weber, call such conceptions 'legitima-
tions,' or sometimes 'symbols of justification."'
(The Sociological Imagination, New York: Oxford
University Press, 1959, p. 36). Whether we view
the process of legitimation in the context of the
formation of such collective conceptions, or in the
context of calling upon them to justify action, the
process is fundamentally that of mobilizing collec-
tive support to oppose those who challenge power.
Power so supported is authority, and the process
fits the general model of coalition formation.
40 AMERICAN SOCIOLOGICAL REVIEW
The least dependent member of a group will
be the first to break from the group, and
these members are precisely the most valued
members. It is this situation which balancing
operation number three alleviates through
"giving status" to the highly valued mem-
bers, thus gaining the power to keep and
control those members.
These ideas are illustrated with hypotheti-
cal values in Table 1, with imbalance repre-
sented as power advantage (PA). Balancing
operations will tend to move PA toward zero,
as shown in column 6 after the highly valued
members A and B have come to depend upon
the group for the special rewards of status,
and in column 9 after the least valued mem-
bers D and E have withdrawn some of their
TABLE 1. HYPOTHETICAL VALUES SHOWING TEE
RELATION BETWEEN DGM AND DMG IN A
GROUP WITH FIVE MEMBERS
Before Balancing After Operation #3 After Operation # 1
1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9
Member Dgm Dmg* PAgm** Dgm Dmg PAgm** Dgm Dmg
PAgm**
A 5 1 -4 5 5 0 5 5 0
B 4 2 -2 4 4 0 4 4 0
C 3 3 0 3 3 0 3 3 0
D 2 4 2 2 4 2 2 2 0
E 1 5 4 1 5 4 1 1 0
*Assuming that all members have the same motivational
investment in the group at the outset,
and that highly valued members (A and B) are valued in other
groups as well.
** Power Advantage PAgm=Dmg-Dgm.
original motivational investment in the
group. The table presents three stages in
status crystallization, and the process of
crystallization is seen as a balancing process.
The final stage (columns 7, 8, and 9) should
be achieved only in groups with very low
membership turnover. The middle stage
might well be perpetual in groups with new
members continually coming in at the lower
levels. In such "open" groups, status striving
should be a characteristic feature and can
be taken as a direct manifestation of the
tensions of imbalance. In the final stage, such
strivers have either succeeded or withdrawn
from the struggle.
Among the factors involved in status or-
dering, this theory focuses attention upon
the extreme importance of the availability
factor in dependency as a determinant of
status position and the values employed in
status ordering. In considering Dgm (the
relative value or importance the group at-
taches to member roles), it is notably difficult
to rely upon a functional explanation. Is the
pitcher more highly valued than the center
fielder because he is functionally more im-
portant or because good pitchers are harder
to find? Is the physicist valued over the
plumber because of a "more important" func-
tional contribution to the social system, or
because physicists are more difficult to re-
place, more costly to obtain, etc.? The latter
considerations involve the availability factor.
We suggest here that the values people use
in ordering roles or persons express the de-
pendence of the system upon those roles, and
that the availability factor in dependency
plays the decisive part in historically shap-
ing those values."8
CONCLUSION
The theory put forth in this paper is in
large part contained implicitly in the ties
of mutual dependence which bind actors to-
gether in social systems. Its principal value
seems to be its ability to pull together a
wide variety of social events, ranging from
the internalization of parental codes to soci-
ety-wide movements, like the collectivization
of labor, in terms of a few very simple prin-
ciples. Most important, the concepts involved
are subject to operational formulation. Two
18 "Motivational investment" and "availability,"
which jointly determine dependency at any point
in time, are functionally related through time. This
is implied in our balancing operations. While these
two variables can be readily distinguished in the
case of Dmg, they are too intimately fused in Dgm
to be clearly separated. The values by which a
group sees a given role as "important" at time 2,
evolve from felt scarcity in that role and similar
roles at time 1.
CHOICE IN INTERPERSONAL RELATIONS 41
experiments testing certain propositions dis-
cussed above led to the following results:
L Conformity (Pgm) varies directly with
motivational investment in the group;
2. Conformity varies inversely with accept-
ance in alternative groups;
3. Conformity is high at both status extremes
in groups with membership turnover (see
column 5, Table 1);
4. Highly valued members of a group are
strong conformers only if they are valued
by other groups as well. (This supports
the notion that special status rewards are
used to hold the highly valued member
who does not depend heavily upon the
group, and that in granting him such re-
wards power is obtained over him.);
5. Coalitions form among the weak to con-
trol the strong (balancing operation num-
ber three);
6. The greatest rewards within a coalition
are given to the less dependent member
of the coalition (balancing operation num-
ber three, analogous to "status giving").
Once the basic ideas in this theory have
been adequately validated and refined, both
theoretical and empirical work must be ex-
tended in two main directions. First, the in-
teraction process should be studied to locate
carefully the factors leading to perceived
power and dependency in self and others,
and the conditions under which power, as a
potential, will be employed in action. Sec-
ondly, and, in the long run, more important,
will be study of power networks more com-
plex than those referred to here, leading to
more adequate understanding of complex
power structures. The theory presented here
does no more than provide the basic under-
pinning to the study of complex networks.
There is every reason to believe that modern
mathematics, graph theory in particular,"'
can be fruitfully employed in the analysis of
complex networks and predicting the out-
come of power plays within such networks.
19 F. Harary and R. Norman, Graph Theory as
a Mathematical Model in the Social Sciences. Ann
Arbor: Institute for Social Research, 1953. An
effort to apply such a model to power relations can
be found in John R. P. French, Jr., "A Formal
Theory of Social Power," The Psychological Re-
view, 63 (May, 1956), pp. 181-194.
PATTERNS OF CHOICE IN INTERPERSONAL RELATIONS
PETER M. BLAU
University of Chicago
How do people's attributes influence the interpersonal choices
among them? Data on work
groups are used to examine the regularities revealed by 17 items
on four types of interpersonal
choice-respect, consultation, sociable attraction, and informal
acceptance. Four main pat-
terns could be discerned: (1) Items that had a differentiating
effect on respect also had
differentiating effects on consultation and attraction but usually
not on informal acceptance;
(2) Orientations toward work had a segregating effect on
respect, but only orientations with
pronounced significance for respect also had segregating effects
on other interpersonal choices;
(3) Attributes that differentiated consultants from others
without producing a corresponding
differentiation of respect to legitimate the status of consultant
created segregating barriers
to sociability; (4) Measures of approach to people had a
segregating effect on consultation,
like others salient orientations, but they had a differentiating
effect on attraction, probably
because an informal approach made a worker a more attractive
companion. The four groups
of independent variables in this analysis are shown to represent
orthogonal dimensions.
RELATIONSHIPS between persons acting in
social roles constitute the matrix of
social structures. The systematic in-
vestigation of interpersonal relations, there-
fore, promises to contribute much to a
better understanding of social structure. The
data to be explained in this schema are dis-
* I am greatly indebted for many suggestions and
for assistance with technical problems of analysis to
my colleagues Otis Dudley Duncan, Elihu Katz,
Jack Sawyer, Fred L. Strodtbeck, and Harrison C.
White. I also want to acknowledge financial sup-
port from the Ford Foundation and the help of
Robert A. Gordon, who did the factor analysis, and
of Robert W. Hodge and Philip M. Marcus, who
worked on the computations,
Article
Contentsp.31p.32p.33p.34p.35p.36p.37p.38p.39p.40p.41Issue
Table of ContentsAmerican Sociological Review, Vol. 27, No. 1
(Feb., 1962), pp. 1-154Front Matter [pp.1-4]Toward a Theory of
Revolution [pp.5-19]Mass Society and Extremist Politics
[pp.19-30]Power-Dependence Relations [pp.31-41]Patterns of
Choice in Interpersonal Relations [pp.41-55]Nurse-Patient
Social Distance and the Structural Context of a Mental Hospital
[pp.56-65]Value-Behavior Discrepancies Regarding Premarital
Coitus in Three Western Cultures [pp.66-74]The Local
Community: A Survey Approach [pp.75-84]Research Reports
and NotesIndependent Causation in Multivariate Analysis: The
Case of Political Alienation and Attitude Toward a School Bond
Issue [pp.85-87]The Occupational Characteristics of Migrants to
Duluth: A Retest of Rose's Hypothesis [pp.87-90]Errata and
Clarifications [pp.91-92]Errata and Clarifications [pp.92-
93]Errata and Clarifications [p.93]Errata and Clarifications
[pp.93-94]Errata and Clarifications [p.94]Communications
[pp.95-98]Book Reviewsuntitled [pp.99-100]untitled
[p.100]untitled [pp.100-101]untitled [p.101]untitled [pp.101-
102]untitled [p.102]untitled [pp.102-103]untitled [pp.103-
104]untitled [pp.104-105]untitled [pp.105-106]untitled
[p.106]untitled [pp.106-107]untitled [p.107]untitled [pp.107-
108]untitled [pp.108-109]untitled [p.109]untitled [pp.109-
110]untitled [pp.110-111]untitled [p.111]untitled [pp.111-
113]untitled [p.113]untitled [pp.113-114]untitled
[p.114]untitled [pp.114-115]untitled [p.115]untitled [pp.115-
116]untitled [pp.116-117]untitled [p.117]untitled [pp.117-
118]untitled [pp.118-119]untitled [pp.119-120]untitled [pp.120-
121]untitled [p.121]untitled [p.122]untitled [pp.122-
123]untitled [pp.123-124]untitled [p.124]untitled [pp.124-
125]untitled [p.125]untitled [pp.125-126]untitled
[p.126]untitled [pp.126-127]untitled [pp.127-128]untitled
[pp.128-129]untitled [p.129]untitled [pp.129-130]untitled
[pp.130-131]untitled [p.131]untitled [pp.131-132]untitled
[p.132]untitled [p.133]untitled [pp.133-134]untitled
[p.134]untitled [pp.134-135]untitled [p.135]untitled
[p.135]Book Notes [pp.135-142]Publications Received [pp.142-
146]The Profession: Reports and Opinion [pp.147-154]Back
Matter

More Related Content

Similar to 13Chapter 7 SummaryCHAPTER SUMMARYContemporary Integ.docx

Social theory complete may 2014
Social theory complete may 2014Social theory complete may 2014
Social theory complete may 2014Eric Strayer
 
Understanding the concepts of culture, society and politics
Understanding the concepts of culture, society and politicsUnderstanding the concepts of culture, society and politics
Understanding the concepts of culture, society and politicsMaryjoydailo
 
8. Social Structure.pptx
8. Social Structure.pptx8. Social Structure.pptx
8. Social Structure.pptxAyeshaMahmud3
 
2.-CONCEPT-OF-SOCIETY.pptx
2.-CONCEPT-OF-SOCIETY.pptx2.-CONCEPT-OF-SOCIETY.pptx
2.-CONCEPT-OF-SOCIETY.pptxRoseAnnZaratan1
 
GROUP 3_PPT.pdf Ksjsjsjsjjsjsjsjsjjsjsjdjjdjdndndnjd
GROUP 3_PPT.pdf KsjsjsjsjjsjsjsjsjjsjsjdjjdjdndndnjdGROUP 3_PPT.pdf Ksjsjsjsjjsjsjsjsjjsjsjdjjdjdndndnjd
GROUP 3_PPT.pdf KsjsjsjsjjsjsjsjsjjsjsjdjjdjdndndnjdJeanneArroyo
 
MAX WEBER Key Concepts I Sociology is a science which at.docx
MAX WEBER Key Concepts I Sociology is a science which at.docxMAX WEBER Key Concepts I Sociology is a science which at.docx
MAX WEBER Key Concepts I Sociology is a science which at.docxandreecapon
 
Socio-cultural Tradition of Communication
Socio-cultural Tradition of CommunicationSocio-cultural Tradition of Communication
Socio-cultural Tradition of CommunicationMichael Chiquillo
 
WEEK 5-6 DISS FINAL.pptx
WEEK 5-6 DISS FINAL.pptxWEEK 5-6 DISS FINAL.pptx
WEEK 5-6 DISS FINAL.pptxabigailedale1
 
Social science lecture 1(part-2) ppt summer 2011
Social science lecture 1(part-2) ppt summer 2011Social science lecture 1(part-2) ppt summer 2011
Social science lecture 1(part-2) ppt summer 2011Sajib
 
Theories on Sociological Perspective
Theories on Sociological PerspectiveTheories on Sociological Perspective
Theories on Sociological PerspectiveLei Veluz
 
Symbolic interactionism
Symbolic interactionism Symbolic interactionism
Symbolic interactionism Leslie Méndez
 

Similar to 13Chapter 7 SummaryCHAPTER SUMMARYContemporary Integ.docx (20)

Social theory complete may 2014
Social theory complete may 2014Social theory complete may 2014
Social theory complete may 2014
 
SociologyExchange.co.uk Shared Resource
SociologyExchange.co.uk Shared ResourceSociologyExchange.co.uk Shared Resource
SociologyExchange.co.uk Shared Resource
 
Lecture 3
Lecture 3Lecture 3
Lecture 3
 
Giddens
GiddensGiddens
Giddens
 
Understanding the concepts of culture, society and politics
Understanding the concepts of culture, society and politicsUnderstanding the concepts of culture, society and politics
Understanding the concepts of culture, society and politics
 
8. Social Structure.pptx
8. Social Structure.pptx8. Social Structure.pptx
8. Social Structure.pptx
 
2.-CONCEPT-OF-SOCIETY.pptx
2.-CONCEPT-OF-SOCIETY.pptx2.-CONCEPT-OF-SOCIETY.pptx
2.-CONCEPT-OF-SOCIETY.pptx
 
GROUP 3_PPT.pdf Ksjsjsjsjjsjsjsjsjjsjsjdjjdjdndndnjd
GROUP 3_PPT.pdf KsjsjsjsjjsjsjsjsjjsjsjdjjdjdndndnjdGROUP 3_PPT.pdf Ksjsjsjsjjsjsjsjsjjsjsjdjjdjdndndnjd
GROUP 3_PPT.pdf Ksjsjsjsjjsjsjsjsjjsjsjdjjdjdndndnjd
 
Social Structure
Social StructureSocial Structure
Social Structure
 
4 1-introduction to sociology
4 1-introduction to sociology4 1-introduction to sociology
4 1-introduction to sociology
 
Unit 1
Unit 1Unit 1
Unit 1
 
MAX WEBER Key Concepts I Sociology is a science which at.docx
MAX WEBER Key Concepts I Sociology is a science which at.docxMAX WEBER Key Concepts I Sociology is a science which at.docx
MAX WEBER Key Concepts I Sociology is a science which at.docx
 
Socio-cultural Tradition of Communication
Socio-cultural Tradition of CommunicationSocio-cultural Tradition of Communication
Socio-cultural Tradition of Communication
 
Sociology Part 2
Sociology Part 2Sociology Part 2
Sociology Part 2
 
WEEK 5-6 DISS FINAL.pptx
WEEK 5-6 DISS FINAL.pptxWEEK 5-6 DISS FINAL.pptx
WEEK 5-6 DISS FINAL.pptx
 
Sociology introduction
Sociology introductionSociology introduction
Sociology introduction
 
Social science lecture 1(part-2) ppt summer 2011
Social science lecture 1(part-2) ppt summer 2011Social science lecture 1(part-2) ppt summer 2011
Social science lecture 1(part-2) ppt summer 2011
 
Theories on Sociological Perspective
Theories on Sociological PerspectiveTheories on Sociological Perspective
Theories on Sociological Perspective
 
Symbolic interactionism
Symbolic interactionism Symbolic interactionism
Symbolic interactionism
 
Chapter01
Chapter01Chapter01
Chapter01
 

More from drennanmicah

Case Study RubricCriterionStrongAverageWeakInt.docx
Case Study RubricCriterionStrongAverageWeakInt.docxCase Study RubricCriterionStrongAverageWeakInt.docx
Case Study RubricCriterionStrongAverageWeakInt.docxdrennanmicah
 
Case Study Rubric  Directly respond to each questi.docx
Case Study Rubric   Directly respond to each questi.docxCase Study Rubric   Directly respond to each questi.docx
Case Study Rubric  Directly respond to each questi.docxdrennanmicah
 
Case Study Scenario Part 3IntroductionThis media piece exp.docx
Case Study Scenario Part 3IntroductionThis media piece exp.docxCase Study Scenario Part 3IntroductionThis media piece exp.docx
Case Study Scenario Part 3IntroductionThis media piece exp.docxdrennanmicah
 
Case Study RubricYour case study will be assessed as follows•.docx
Case Study RubricYour case study will be assessed as follows•.docxCase Study RubricYour case study will be assessed as follows•.docx
Case Study RubricYour case study will be assessed as follows•.docxdrennanmicah
 
Case study RubricCriterionOutstanding 3.75Very Good 3 .docx
Case study RubricCriterionOutstanding  3.75Very Good  3 .docxCase study RubricCriterionOutstanding  3.75Very Good  3 .docx
Case study RubricCriterionOutstanding 3.75Very Good 3 .docxdrennanmicah
 
CASE STUDY RUBRIC MICROBIOLOGY For the Case Study assig.docx
CASE STUDY RUBRIC MICROBIOLOGY  For the Case Study assig.docxCASE STUDY RUBRIC MICROBIOLOGY  For the Case Study assig.docx
CASE STUDY RUBRIC MICROBIOLOGY For the Case Study assig.docxdrennanmicah
 
Case Study Rubric .docx
Case Study Rubric                                                 .docxCase Study Rubric                                                 .docx
Case Study Rubric .docxdrennanmicah
 
Case Study ReflectionWrite a 4-5 page paper. Your written assi.docx
Case Study ReflectionWrite a 4-5 page paper. Your written assi.docxCase Study ReflectionWrite a 4-5 page paper. Your written assi.docx
Case Study ReflectionWrite a 4-5 page paper. Your written assi.docxdrennanmicah
 
Case Study Questions (Each question is worth 6 marks)1. Defi.docx
Case Study Questions (Each question is worth 6 marks)1. Defi.docxCase Study Questions (Each question is worth 6 marks)1. Defi.docx
Case Study Questions (Each question is worth 6 marks)1. Defi.docxdrennanmicah
 
Case Study Reorganizing Human Resources at ASP SoftwareRead the.docx
Case Study Reorganizing Human Resources at ASP SoftwareRead the.docxCase Study Reorganizing Human Resources at ASP SoftwareRead the.docx
Case Study Reorganizing Human Resources at ASP SoftwareRead the.docxdrennanmicah
 
Case Study Report Rubric CriterionWeakAverageStrongIdent.docx
Case Study Report Rubric CriterionWeakAverageStrongIdent.docxCase Study Report Rubric CriterionWeakAverageStrongIdent.docx
Case Study Report Rubric CriterionWeakAverageStrongIdent.docxdrennanmicah
 
Case Study Project (A) Hefty Hardware - Be sure to address each .docx
Case Study Project (A) Hefty Hardware - Be sure to address each .docxCase Study Project (A) Hefty Hardware - Be sure to address each .docx
Case Study Project (A) Hefty Hardware - Be sure to address each .docxdrennanmicah
 
Case Study Proposing a Data Gathering Approach at TLG Solutions (.docx
Case Study Proposing a Data Gathering Approach at TLG Solutions (.docxCase Study Proposing a Data Gathering Approach at TLG Solutions (.docx
Case Study Proposing a Data Gathering Approach at TLG Solutions (.docxdrennanmicah
 
Case Study Project Part I Declared JurisdictionTemplate Sta.docx
Case Study Project Part I   Declared JurisdictionTemplate Sta.docxCase Study Project Part I   Declared JurisdictionTemplate Sta.docx
Case Study Project Part I Declared JurisdictionTemplate Sta.docxdrennanmicah
 
Case Study Proposing a Data Gathering Approach at TLG Solutions.docx
Case Study Proposing a Data Gathering Approach at TLG Solutions.docxCase Study Proposing a Data Gathering Approach at TLG Solutions.docx
Case Study Proposing a Data Gathering Approach at TLG Solutions.docxdrennanmicah
 
Case Study Peer Comments In each case study, you are expected.docx
Case Study Peer Comments In each case study, you are expected.docxCase Study Peer Comments In each case study, you are expected.docx
Case Study Peer Comments In each case study, you are expected.docxdrennanmicah
 
Case Study ProblemLeadership appears as a popular agenda it.docx
Case Study ProblemLeadership appears as a popular agenda it.docxCase Study ProblemLeadership appears as a popular agenda it.docx
Case Study ProblemLeadership appears as a popular agenda it.docxdrennanmicah
 
Case Study Planning for GrowthKelly’s Sandwich Stop is one of t.docx
Case Study Planning for GrowthKelly’s Sandwich Stop is one of t.docxCase Study Planning for GrowthKelly’s Sandwich Stop is one of t.docx
Case Study Planning for GrowthKelly’s Sandwich Stop is one of t.docxdrennanmicah
 
Case Study People v. Smith, 470 NW2d 70, Michigan Supreme Court (19.docx
Case Study People v. Smith, 470 NW2d 70, Michigan Supreme Court (19.docxCase Study People v. Smith, 470 NW2d 70, Michigan Supreme Court (19.docx
Case Study People v. Smith, 470 NW2d 70, Michigan Supreme Court (19.docxdrennanmicah
 
Case Study OneBMGT 464 Portfolio Activity TwoPurposeIn thi.docx
Case Study OneBMGT 464 Portfolio Activity TwoPurposeIn thi.docxCase Study OneBMGT 464 Portfolio Activity TwoPurposeIn thi.docx
Case Study OneBMGT 464 Portfolio Activity TwoPurposeIn thi.docxdrennanmicah
 

More from drennanmicah (20)

Case Study RubricCriterionStrongAverageWeakInt.docx
Case Study RubricCriterionStrongAverageWeakInt.docxCase Study RubricCriterionStrongAverageWeakInt.docx
Case Study RubricCriterionStrongAverageWeakInt.docx
 
Case Study Rubric  Directly respond to each questi.docx
Case Study Rubric   Directly respond to each questi.docxCase Study Rubric   Directly respond to each questi.docx
Case Study Rubric  Directly respond to each questi.docx
 
Case Study Scenario Part 3IntroductionThis media piece exp.docx
Case Study Scenario Part 3IntroductionThis media piece exp.docxCase Study Scenario Part 3IntroductionThis media piece exp.docx
Case Study Scenario Part 3IntroductionThis media piece exp.docx
 
Case Study RubricYour case study will be assessed as follows•.docx
Case Study RubricYour case study will be assessed as follows•.docxCase Study RubricYour case study will be assessed as follows•.docx
Case Study RubricYour case study will be assessed as follows•.docx
 
Case study RubricCriterionOutstanding 3.75Very Good 3 .docx
Case study RubricCriterionOutstanding  3.75Very Good  3 .docxCase study RubricCriterionOutstanding  3.75Very Good  3 .docx
Case study RubricCriterionOutstanding 3.75Very Good 3 .docx
 
CASE STUDY RUBRIC MICROBIOLOGY For the Case Study assig.docx
CASE STUDY RUBRIC MICROBIOLOGY  For the Case Study assig.docxCASE STUDY RUBRIC MICROBIOLOGY  For the Case Study assig.docx
CASE STUDY RUBRIC MICROBIOLOGY For the Case Study assig.docx
 
Case Study Rubric .docx
Case Study Rubric                                                 .docxCase Study Rubric                                                 .docx
Case Study Rubric .docx
 
Case Study ReflectionWrite a 4-5 page paper. Your written assi.docx
Case Study ReflectionWrite a 4-5 page paper. Your written assi.docxCase Study ReflectionWrite a 4-5 page paper. Your written assi.docx
Case Study ReflectionWrite a 4-5 page paper. Your written assi.docx
 
Case Study Questions (Each question is worth 6 marks)1. Defi.docx
Case Study Questions (Each question is worth 6 marks)1. Defi.docxCase Study Questions (Each question is worth 6 marks)1. Defi.docx
Case Study Questions (Each question is worth 6 marks)1. Defi.docx
 
Case Study Reorganizing Human Resources at ASP SoftwareRead the.docx
Case Study Reorganizing Human Resources at ASP SoftwareRead the.docxCase Study Reorganizing Human Resources at ASP SoftwareRead the.docx
Case Study Reorganizing Human Resources at ASP SoftwareRead the.docx
 
Case Study Report Rubric CriterionWeakAverageStrongIdent.docx
Case Study Report Rubric CriterionWeakAverageStrongIdent.docxCase Study Report Rubric CriterionWeakAverageStrongIdent.docx
Case Study Report Rubric CriterionWeakAverageStrongIdent.docx
 
Case Study Project (A) Hefty Hardware - Be sure to address each .docx
Case Study Project (A) Hefty Hardware - Be sure to address each .docxCase Study Project (A) Hefty Hardware - Be sure to address each .docx
Case Study Project (A) Hefty Hardware - Be sure to address each .docx
 
Case Study Proposing a Data Gathering Approach at TLG Solutions (.docx
Case Study Proposing a Data Gathering Approach at TLG Solutions (.docxCase Study Proposing a Data Gathering Approach at TLG Solutions (.docx
Case Study Proposing a Data Gathering Approach at TLG Solutions (.docx
 
Case Study Project Part I Declared JurisdictionTemplate Sta.docx
Case Study Project Part I   Declared JurisdictionTemplate Sta.docxCase Study Project Part I   Declared JurisdictionTemplate Sta.docx
Case Study Project Part I Declared JurisdictionTemplate Sta.docx
 
Case Study Proposing a Data Gathering Approach at TLG Solutions.docx
Case Study Proposing a Data Gathering Approach at TLG Solutions.docxCase Study Proposing a Data Gathering Approach at TLG Solutions.docx
Case Study Proposing a Data Gathering Approach at TLG Solutions.docx
 
Case Study Peer Comments In each case study, you are expected.docx
Case Study Peer Comments In each case study, you are expected.docxCase Study Peer Comments In each case study, you are expected.docx
Case Study Peer Comments In each case study, you are expected.docx
 
Case Study ProblemLeadership appears as a popular agenda it.docx
Case Study ProblemLeadership appears as a popular agenda it.docxCase Study ProblemLeadership appears as a popular agenda it.docx
Case Study ProblemLeadership appears as a popular agenda it.docx
 
Case Study Planning for GrowthKelly’s Sandwich Stop is one of t.docx
Case Study Planning for GrowthKelly’s Sandwich Stop is one of t.docxCase Study Planning for GrowthKelly’s Sandwich Stop is one of t.docx
Case Study Planning for GrowthKelly’s Sandwich Stop is one of t.docx
 
Case Study People v. Smith, 470 NW2d 70, Michigan Supreme Court (19.docx
Case Study People v. Smith, 470 NW2d 70, Michigan Supreme Court (19.docxCase Study People v. Smith, 470 NW2d 70, Michigan Supreme Court (19.docx
Case Study People v. Smith, 470 NW2d 70, Michigan Supreme Court (19.docx
 
Case Study OneBMGT 464 Portfolio Activity TwoPurposeIn thi.docx
Case Study OneBMGT 464 Portfolio Activity TwoPurposeIn thi.docxCase Study OneBMGT 464 Portfolio Activity TwoPurposeIn thi.docx
Case Study OneBMGT 464 Portfolio Activity TwoPurposeIn thi.docx
 

Recently uploaded

ENGLISH 7_Q4_LESSON 2_ Employing a Variety of Strategies for Effective Interp...
ENGLISH 7_Q4_LESSON 2_ Employing a Variety of Strategies for Effective Interp...ENGLISH 7_Q4_LESSON 2_ Employing a Variety of Strategies for Effective Interp...
ENGLISH 7_Q4_LESSON 2_ Employing a Variety of Strategies for Effective Interp...JhezDiaz1
 
Full Stack Web Development Course for Beginners
Full Stack Web Development Course  for BeginnersFull Stack Web Development Course  for Beginners
Full Stack Web Development Course for BeginnersSabitha Banu
 
call girls in Kamla Market (DELHI) 🔝 >༒9953330565🔝 genuine Escort Service 🔝✔️✔️
call girls in Kamla Market (DELHI) 🔝 >༒9953330565🔝 genuine Escort Service 🔝✔️✔️call girls in Kamla Market (DELHI) 🔝 >༒9953330565🔝 genuine Escort Service 🔝✔️✔️
call girls in Kamla Market (DELHI) 🔝 >༒9953330565🔝 genuine Escort Service 🔝✔️✔️9953056974 Low Rate Call Girls In Saket, Delhi NCR
 
Choosing the Right CBSE School A Comprehensive Guide for Parents
Choosing the Right CBSE School A Comprehensive Guide for ParentsChoosing the Right CBSE School A Comprehensive Guide for Parents
Choosing the Right CBSE School A Comprehensive Guide for Parentsnavabharathschool99
 
Karra SKD Conference Presentation Revised.pptx
Karra SKD Conference Presentation Revised.pptxKarra SKD Conference Presentation Revised.pptx
Karra SKD Conference Presentation Revised.pptxAshokKarra1
 
Influencing policy (training slides from Fast Track Impact)
Influencing policy (training slides from Fast Track Impact)Influencing policy (training slides from Fast Track Impact)
Influencing policy (training slides from Fast Track Impact)Mark Reed
 
GRADE 4 - SUMMATIVE TEST QUARTER 4 ALL SUBJECTS
GRADE 4 - SUMMATIVE TEST QUARTER 4 ALL SUBJECTSGRADE 4 - SUMMATIVE TEST QUARTER 4 ALL SUBJECTS
GRADE 4 - SUMMATIVE TEST QUARTER 4 ALL SUBJECTSJoshuaGantuangco2
 
How to do quick user assign in kanban in Odoo 17 ERP
How to do quick user assign in kanban in Odoo 17 ERPHow to do quick user assign in kanban in Odoo 17 ERP
How to do quick user assign in kanban in Odoo 17 ERPCeline George
 
Field Attribute Index Feature in Odoo 17
Field Attribute Index Feature in Odoo 17Field Attribute Index Feature in Odoo 17
Field Attribute Index Feature in Odoo 17Celine George
 
Judging the Relevance and worth of ideas part 2.pptx
Judging the Relevance  and worth of ideas part 2.pptxJudging the Relevance  and worth of ideas part 2.pptx
Judging the Relevance and worth of ideas part 2.pptxSherlyMaeNeri
 
Earth Day Presentation wow hello nice great
Earth Day Presentation wow hello nice greatEarth Day Presentation wow hello nice great
Earth Day Presentation wow hello nice greatYousafMalik24
 
MULTIDISCIPLINRY NATURE OF THE ENVIRONMENTAL STUDIES.pptx
MULTIDISCIPLINRY NATURE OF THE ENVIRONMENTAL STUDIES.pptxMULTIDISCIPLINRY NATURE OF THE ENVIRONMENTAL STUDIES.pptx
MULTIDISCIPLINRY NATURE OF THE ENVIRONMENTAL STUDIES.pptxAnupkumar Sharma
 
USPS® Forced Meter Migration - How to Know if Your Postage Meter Will Soon be...
USPS® Forced Meter Migration - How to Know if Your Postage Meter Will Soon be...USPS® Forced Meter Migration - How to Know if Your Postage Meter Will Soon be...
USPS® Forced Meter Migration - How to Know if Your Postage Meter Will Soon be...Postal Advocate Inc.
 
Proudly South Africa powerpoint Thorisha.pptx
Proudly South Africa powerpoint Thorisha.pptxProudly South Africa powerpoint Thorisha.pptx
Proudly South Africa powerpoint Thorisha.pptxthorishapillay1
 
Difference Between Search & Browse Methods in Odoo 17
Difference Between Search & Browse Methods in Odoo 17Difference Between Search & Browse Methods in Odoo 17
Difference Between Search & Browse Methods in Odoo 17Celine George
 
DATA STRUCTURE AND ALGORITHM for beginners
DATA STRUCTURE AND ALGORITHM for beginnersDATA STRUCTURE AND ALGORITHM for beginners
DATA STRUCTURE AND ALGORITHM for beginnersSabitha Banu
 
Like-prefer-love -hate+verb+ing & silent letters & citizenship text.pdf
Like-prefer-love -hate+verb+ing & silent letters & citizenship text.pdfLike-prefer-love -hate+verb+ing & silent letters & citizenship text.pdf
Like-prefer-love -hate+verb+ing & silent letters & citizenship text.pdfMr Bounab Samir
 

Recently uploaded (20)

ENGLISH 7_Q4_LESSON 2_ Employing a Variety of Strategies for Effective Interp...
ENGLISH 7_Q4_LESSON 2_ Employing a Variety of Strategies for Effective Interp...ENGLISH 7_Q4_LESSON 2_ Employing a Variety of Strategies for Effective Interp...
ENGLISH 7_Q4_LESSON 2_ Employing a Variety of Strategies for Effective Interp...
 
Full Stack Web Development Course for Beginners
Full Stack Web Development Course  for BeginnersFull Stack Web Development Course  for Beginners
Full Stack Web Development Course for Beginners
 
call girls in Kamla Market (DELHI) 🔝 >༒9953330565🔝 genuine Escort Service 🔝✔️✔️
call girls in Kamla Market (DELHI) 🔝 >༒9953330565🔝 genuine Escort Service 🔝✔️✔️call girls in Kamla Market (DELHI) 🔝 >༒9953330565🔝 genuine Escort Service 🔝✔️✔️
call girls in Kamla Market (DELHI) 🔝 >༒9953330565🔝 genuine Escort Service 🔝✔️✔️
 
Choosing the Right CBSE School A Comprehensive Guide for Parents
Choosing the Right CBSE School A Comprehensive Guide for ParentsChoosing the Right CBSE School A Comprehensive Guide for Parents
Choosing the Right CBSE School A Comprehensive Guide for Parents
 
Model Call Girl in Tilak Nagar Delhi reach out to us at 🔝9953056974🔝
Model Call Girl in Tilak Nagar Delhi reach out to us at 🔝9953056974🔝Model Call Girl in Tilak Nagar Delhi reach out to us at 🔝9953056974🔝
Model Call Girl in Tilak Nagar Delhi reach out to us at 🔝9953056974🔝
 
Karra SKD Conference Presentation Revised.pptx
Karra SKD Conference Presentation Revised.pptxKarra SKD Conference Presentation Revised.pptx
Karra SKD Conference Presentation Revised.pptx
 
YOUVE GOT EMAIL_FINALS_EL_DORADO_2024.pptx
YOUVE GOT EMAIL_FINALS_EL_DORADO_2024.pptxYOUVE GOT EMAIL_FINALS_EL_DORADO_2024.pptx
YOUVE GOT EMAIL_FINALS_EL_DORADO_2024.pptx
 
Influencing policy (training slides from Fast Track Impact)
Influencing policy (training slides from Fast Track Impact)Influencing policy (training slides from Fast Track Impact)
Influencing policy (training slides from Fast Track Impact)
 
GRADE 4 - SUMMATIVE TEST QUARTER 4 ALL SUBJECTS
GRADE 4 - SUMMATIVE TEST QUARTER 4 ALL SUBJECTSGRADE 4 - SUMMATIVE TEST QUARTER 4 ALL SUBJECTS
GRADE 4 - SUMMATIVE TEST QUARTER 4 ALL SUBJECTS
 
How to do quick user assign in kanban in Odoo 17 ERP
How to do quick user assign in kanban in Odoo 17 ERPHow to do quick user assign in kanban in Odoo 17 ERP
How to do quick user assign in kanban in Odoo 17 ERP
 
Field Attribute Index Feature in Odoo 17
Field Attribute Index Feature in Odoo 17Field Attribute Index Feature in Odoo 17
Field Attribute Index Feature in Odoo 17
 
Judging the Relevance and worth of ideas part 2.pptx
Judging the Relevance  and worth of ideas part 2.pptxJudging the Relevance  and worth of ideas part 2.pptx
Judging the Relevance and worth of ideas part 2.pptx
 
Earth Day Presentation wow hello nice great
Earth Day Presentation wow hello nice greatEarth Day Presentation wow hello nice great
Earth Day Presentation wow hello nice great
 
MULTIDISCIPLINRY NATURE OF THE ENVIRONMENTAL STUDIES.pptx
MULTIDISCIPLINRY NATURE OF THE ENVIRONMENTAL STUDIES.pptxMULTIDISCIPLINRY NATURE OF THE ENVIRONMENTAL STUDIES.pptx
MULTIDISCIPLINRY NATURE OF THE ENVIRONMENTAL STUDIES.pptx
 
USPS® Forced Meter Migration - How to Know if Your Postage Meter Will Soon be...
USPS® Forced Meter Migration - How to Know if Your Postage Meter Will Soon be...USPS® Forced Meter Migration - How to Know if Your Postage Meter Will Soon be...
USPS® Forced Meter Migration - How to Know if Your Postage Meter Will Soon be...
 
Proudly South Africa powerpoint Thorisha.pptx
Proudly South Africa powerpoint Thorisha.pptxProudly South Africa powerpoint Thorisha.pptx
Proudly South Africa powerpoint Thorisha.pptx
 
YOUVE_GOT_EMAIL_PRELIMS_EL_DORADO_2024.pptx
YOUVE_GOT_EMAIL_PRELIMS_EL_DORADO_2024.pptxYOUVE_GOT_EMAIL_PRELIMS_EL_DORADO_2024.pptx
YOUVE_GOT_EMAIL_PRELIMS_EL_DORADO_2024.pptx
 
Difference Between Search & Browse Methods in Odoo 17
Difference Between Search & Browse Methods in Odoo 17Difference Between Search & Browse Methods in Odoo 17
Difference Between Search & Browse Methods in Odoo 17
 
DATA STRUCTURE AND ALGORITHM for beginners
DATA STRUCTURE AND ALGORITHM for beginnersDATA STRUCTURE AND ALGORITHM for beginners
DATA STRUCTURE AND ALGORITHM for beginners
 
Like-prefer-love -hate+verb+ing & silent letters & citizenship text.pdf
Like-prefer-love -hate+verb+ing & silent letters & citizenship text.pdfLike-prefer-love -hate+verb+ing & silent letters & citizenship text.pdf
Like-prefer-love -hate+verb+ing & silent letters & citizenship text.pdf
 

13Chapter 7 SummaryCHAPTER SUMMARYContemporary Integ.docx

  • 1. 1 3 Chapter 7 SummaryCHAPTER SUMMARY Contemporary Integrative Theories This chapter describes theoretical efforts to integrate macro- level theories that deal with the structures and institutions of society with micro-level theories of everyday life. These integrative theories aim to overcome the limitations of either approach by balancing our understanding that individuals are free to interpret, influence, and act with our understanding of organizational and institutional constraints, power, and social reproduction. Richard Emerson’s exchange theory, Anthony Giddens’s structuration theory, and Pierre Bourdieu’s theory of practice each take distinctive approaches to this central problem in social theory. A More Integrated Exchange Theory Building on the work of George Homans, Richard Emerson (1925-1983) asserted that power was central to exchange, that actors are not entirely rational, and that social relations and networks could be used to explain both micro- and macro-level phenomena. Emerson’s exchange theory focuses on the rewards and costs of social interaction and takes social structure as a variable dependent on exchange. The theory assumes that people act rationally within the context of situations, thereby allowing the situations to occur. It also assumes that as people become satiated with the rewards they obtain from a situation, those situations will be of declining importance to them. Last, it assumes that benefits obtained depend on the benefits of exchange. According to Emerson, social structure is produced and
  • 2. reproduced through exchange mechanisms. The exchange network is a web of social relationships that involves a number of individuals or groups. All individuals and groups have opportunities to exchange with others. These relationships interrelate with one another to form network structure. Each exchange relationship is embedded in a larger exchange network. In exchange theory, power is defined as the potential cost that one actor can induce another to accept. Dependency is the potential cost that an actor is willing to accept within an exchange relationship. Mutual dependencies condition the nature of an interaction. When there is an imbalance of power and dependency between two actors, the one with more power and less dependence will have an advantage that can be used to collect rewards or distribute punishments. Exchange theorists argue that the relative power of an actor is determined by the position of an actor in an exchange network. The amount of dependence of the entire structure on the position will determine its power. This perspective can be used to examine both the social behavior of individuals and social structure. It can also be used to examine how changes in power-dependency at the micro-level affect macro-level phenomena and vice-versa. Structuration Theory Structuration theory focuses on the mutual constitution of structure and agency. Anthony Giddens (1938- ) argues that structure and agency are a duality that cannot be conceived of apart from one another. Human practices are recursive – that is, through their activities individuals create both their consciousness and the structural conditions that make their activities possible. Because social actors are reflexive and monitor the ongoing flow of activities and structural conditions, they adapt their actions to their evolving understandings. As a result, social scientific knowledge of society will actually change human activities. Giddens calls this dialectical relationship between social scientific knowledge and human practices the double hermeneutic.
  • 3. Actors continually develop routines that give them a sense of security and enable them to deal efficiently with their social lives. While their motives provide the overall plan of action, it is these routine practices that determine what shape the action will take. Giddens emphasizes that actors have power to shape their own actions, but that the consequences of actions are often unintended. Structure is the rules and resources that give similar social practices a systemic form. Only through the activities of human actors can structure exist. While Giddens acknowledges that structure can be constraining to actors, he thinks that sociologists have exaggerated the importance of structural constraints. Structures can also enable actors to do things they would not otherwise be able to do. For Giddens, a social system is a set of reproduced social practices and relations between actors. The concept of structuration underscores the duality of structure and agency. There can be no agency without structures that shape motives into practices, but there can also be no structures independent of the routine practices that create them. Margaret Archer has criticized the concept of structuration as analytically insufficient. She thinks it is useful for social scientists to understand structure and agency as independent, because it makes it possible to analyze the interrelations between the two sides. Archer also thinks that Giddens gives short shrift to the relative autonomy of culture from both structure and agency. Habitus and Field A major alternative to structuration theory is Pierre Bourdieu’s (1930-2002) theory of habitus and field. Bourdieu sought to bridge subjectivism (the individual) and objectivism (society) with a perspective called constructivist structuralism. Structuralism focuses on the objective structures of language and culture that give shape to human action. Constructivism looks at the social genesis of schemes of perception, thought, and action. Bourdieu wants to examine the social construction of objective structures with an emphasis on how people perceive and construct their own social world, but without neglecting
  • 4. how perception and construction is constrained by structures. An important dynamic in this relationship is the ability of individual actors to invent and improvise within the structure of their routines. The habitus is the mental structure through which people deal with the social world. It can be thought of as a set of internalized schemas through which the world is perceived, understood, appreciated, and evaluated. A habitus is acquired as the result of the long-term occupation of a position in the social world. Depending on the position occupied, people will have a different habitus. The habitus operates as a structure, but people do not simply respond to it mechanically. When people change positions, their habitus is sometimes no longer appropriate, a condition called hysteresis. Bourdieu argues that the habitus both produces and is produced by the social world. People internalize external structures, and they externalize things they have internalized through practices. The concept of field is the objective complement to the idea of habitus. A field is a network of social relations among the objective positions within it. It is not a set of interactions or intersubjective ties among individuals. The social world has a great variety of semi-autonomous fields such as art, religion, and higher education. The field is a type of competitive marketplace in which economic, cultural, social, and symbolic powers are used. The preeminent field is the field of politics, from which a hierarchy of power relationships serves to structure all other fields. To analyze a field, one must first understand its relationship to the political field. The next step is to map the objective positions within a field and, finally, the nature of the habitus of the agents who occupy particular positions can be understood. These agents act strategically depending on their habitus in order to enhance their capital. Bourdieu is particularly concerned with how powerful positions within a field can perpetrate symbolic violence on less powerful actors. Cultural mechanisms such as education impose a dominant perspective on the rest of the population in order to
  • 5. legitimate their power. Bourdieu’s analysis of the aesthetic preferences of different groups can be found in Distinction. The cultural preferences of the various groups within society constitute coherent systems that serve to unify those with similar tastes and differentiate them from others with divergent tastes. Through the practical application of preferences, people classify objects and in the process classify themselves. Bourdieu thinks the field of taste involves the intersection of social-class relationships and cultural relationships. He argues that taste is an opportunity to both experience and assert one’s position in the class hierarchy. These tastes are engendered in the deep-rooted dispositions of the habitus. Changes in tastes result from struggles for dominance within both cultural and social-class fields as different factions struggle to define high culture and taste. Introduction from: Distinction: A Social Critique of the Judgement of Taste by Pierre Bourdieu ©1984 Introduction You said it, my good knight! There ought to be laws to protect the body of acquired knowledge. Take one of our good pupils, for example: modest
  • 6. and diligent, from his earliest grammar classes he’s kept a little notebook full of phrases. After hanging on the lips of his teachers for twenty years, he’s managed to build up an intellectual stock in trade; doesn’t it belong to him as if it were a house, or money? Paul Claudel, Le soulier de satin, Day III, Scene ii There is an economy of cultural goods, but it has a specific logic. Sociology endeavours to establish the conditions in which the consumers of cultural goods, and their taste for them, are produced, and at the same time to describe the different ways of appropriating such of these objects as are regarded at a particular moment as works of art, and the social conditions of the constitution of the mode of appropriation that is considered legitimate. But one cannot fully understand cultural practices unless ‘culture’, in the restricted, normative sense of ordinary usage, is brought back into ‘culture’ in the anthropological sense, and the elaborated taste for the most refined objects is reconnected with the elementary taste for the flavours of food. Whereas the ideology of charisma regards taste in legitimate culture as a gift of nature, scientific observation shows that cultural needs are the product of upbringing and education: surveys establish that all cultural practices (museum visits, concert-going, reading etc.), and preferences in
  • 7. literature, painting or music, are closely linked to educational level (measured by qualifications or length of schooling) and secondarily to social origin.1 The relative weight of home background and of formal education (the effectiveness and duration of which are closely dependent on social origin) varies according to the extent to which the different cultural practices are recognized and taught by the educational system, and the influence of social origin is strongest—other things being equal—in ‘extra-curricular’ and avant-garde culture. To the socially recognized hierarchy of the arts, and within each of them, of genres, schools or periods, corresponds a social hierarchy of the consumers. This predisposes tastes to function as markers of ‘class’. The manner in which culture has been acquired lives on in the manner of using it: the importance attached to manners can be 1 Bourdieu et al., Un art moyen: essai sur les usages sociaux de la photographie (Paris, Ed. de Minuit, 1965); P. Bourdieu and A. Darbel, L’Amour de l’art: les musées et leur public (Paris, Ed. de Minuit, 1966). 2 understood once it is seen that it is these imponderables of
  • 8. practice which distinguish the different—and ranked—modes of culture acquisition, early or late, domestic or scholastic, and the classes of individuals which they characterize (such as ‘pedants’ and mondains). Culture also has its titles of nobility—awarded by the educational system—and its pedigrees, measured by seniority in admission to the nobility. The definition of cultural nobility is the stake in a struggle which has gone on unceasingly, from the seventeenth century to the present day, between groups differing in their ideas of culture and of the legitimate relation to culture and to works of art, and therefore differing in the conditions of acquisition of which these dispositions are the product2 Even in the classroom, the dominant definition of the legitimate way of appropriating culture and works of art favours those who have had early access to legitimate culture, in a cultured household, outside of scholastic disciplines, since even within the educational system it devalues scholarly knowledge and interpretation as ‘scholastic’ or even ‘pedantic’ in favour of direct experience and simple delight. The logic of what is sometimes called, in typically ‘pedantic’ language, the ‘reading’ of a work of art, offers an objective basis for this opposition. Consumption is, in this case, a stage in a process of communication, that is, an act of deciphering, decoding, which presupposes practical or
  • 9. explicit mastery of a cipher or code. In a sense, one can say that the capacity to see (voir) is a function of the knowledge (savoir), or concepts, that is, the words, that are available to name visible things, and which are, as it were, programmes for perception. A work of art has meaning and interest only for someone who possesses the cultural competence, that is, the code, into which it is encoded. The conscious or unconscious implementation of explicit or implicit schemes of perception and appreciation which constitutes pictorial or musical culture is the hidden condition for recognizing the styles characteristic of a period, a school or an author, and, more generally, for the familiarity with the internal logic of works that aesthetic enjoyment presupposes. A beholder who lacks the specific code feels lost in a chaos of sounds and rhythms, colours and lines, without rhyme or reason. Not having learnt to adopt the adequate disposition, he stops short at what Erwin Panofsky calls the ‘sensible properties’, perceiving a skin as downy or lace-work 2 The word disposition seems particularly suited to express what is covered by the concept of habitus (defined as a system of dispositions)—used later in this chapter. It expresses first the result of an organizing action, with a meaning close to that of words such as structure; it also designates a way of being, a habitual state (especially of the
  • 10. body) and, in particular, a predisposition, tendency, propensity or inclination. [The semantic cluster of ‘disposition’ is rather wider in French than in English, but as this note—translated literally—shows, the equivalence is adequate. Translator.] P. Bourdieu, Outline of a Theory of Practice (Cambridge, Cambridge UJniversity Press, 1977), p. 214, n. 1. 3 as delicate, or at the emotional resonances aroused by these properties, referring to ‘austere’ colours or a ‘joyful’ melody. He cannot move from the ‘primary stratum of the meaning we can grasp on the basis of our ordinary experience’ to the ‘stratum of secondary meanings’, i.e., the ‘level of the meaning of what is signified’, unless he possesses the concepts which go beyond the sensible properties and which identify the specifically stylistic properties of the work.3 Thus the encounter with a work of art is not ‘love at first sight’ as is generally supposed, and the act of empathy, Einfühlung, which is the art- lover’s pleasure, presupposes an act of cognition, a decoding operation, which implies the implementation of a cognitive acquirement, a cultural code.4 This typically intellectualist theory of artistic perception directly contradicts
  • 11. the experience of the art-lovers closest to the legitimate definition; acquisition of legitimate culture by insensible familiarization within the family circle tends to favour an enchanted experience of culture which implies forgetting the acquisition.5 The ‘eye’ is a product of history reproduced by education. This is true of the mode of artistic perception now accepted as legitimate, that is, the aesthetic disposition, the capacity to consider in and for themselves, as form rather than function, not only the works designated for such apprehension, i.e., legitimate works of art, but everything in the world, including cultural objects which are not yet consecrated—such as, at one time, primitive arts, or, nowadays, 3 E. Panofsky, ‘Iconography and Iconology: An Introduction to the Study of Renaissance Art’, Meaning in the Visual Arts (New York, Doubleday, 1955), p. 28. 4 It will be seen that this internalized code called culture functions as cultural capital owing to the fact that, being unequally distributed, it secures profits of distinction. 5 The sense of familiarity in no way excludes the ethnocentric misunderstanding which results from applying the wrong code. Thus, Michael Baxandall’s work in historical ethnology enables us to measure all that separates the perceptual schemes that now tend to be applied to Quattrocento paintings and those which their immediate addressees applied. The ‘moral and spiritual eye’ of Quattrocento man, that
  • 12. is, the set of cognitive and evaluative dispositions which were the basis of his perception of the world and his perception of pictorial representation of the world, differs radically from the ‘pure’ gaze (purified, first of all, of reference to economic value) with which the modern cultivated spectator looks at works of art. As the contracts show, the clients of Filippo Lippi, Domenico Ghirlandaio or Piero della Francesca were concerned to get ‘value for money’. They approached works of art with the mercantile dispositions of a businessman who can calculate quantities and prices at a glance, and they applied some surprising criteria of appreciation, such as the expense of the colours, which sets gold and ultramarine at the top of the hierarchy. The artists, who shared this world view, were led to include arithmetical and geometrical devices in their compositions so as to flatter this taste for measurement and calculation; and they tended to exhibit the technical virtuosity which, in this context, is the most visible evidence of the quantity and quality of the labour provided; M. Baxandall, Painting and Experience in Fifteenth- Century Italy: A Primer in the Social History of Pictorial Style (Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1972). 4 popular photography or kitsch—and natural objects. The ‘pure’
  • 13. gaze is a historical invention linked to the emergence of an autonomous field of artistic production, that is, a field capable of imposing its own norms on both the production and the consumption of its products.6 An art which, like all Post- Impressionist painting, is the product of an artistic intention which asserts the primacy of the mode of representation over the object of representation demands categorically an attention to form which previous art only demanded conditionally. The pure intention of the artist is that of a producer who aims to be autonomous, that is, entirely the master of his product, who tends to reject not only the ‘programmes’ imposed a priori by scholars and scribes, but also— following the old hierarchy of doing and saying—the interpretations superimposed a posteriori on his work. The production of an ‘open work’, intrinsically and deliberately polysemic, can thus be understood as the final stage in the conquest of artistic autonomy by poets and, following in their footsteps, by painters, who had long been reliant on writers and their work of ‘showing’ and ‘illustrating’. To assert the autonomy of production is to give primacy to that of which the artist is master, i.e., form, manner, style, rather than the ‘subject’, the external referent, which involves subordination to functions even if only the most
  • 14. elementary one, that of representing, signifying, saying something. It also means a refusal to recognize any necessity other than that inscribed in the specific tradition of the artistic discipline in question: the shift from an art which imitates nature to an art which imitates art, deriving from its own history the exclusive source of its experiments and even of its breaks with tradition. An art which ever increasingly contains reference to its own history demands to be perceived historically; it asks to be referred not to an external referent, the represented or designated ‘reality’, but to the universe of past and present works of art. Like artistic production, in that it is generated in a field, aesthetic perception is necessarily historical, inasmuch as it is differential, relational, attentive to the deviations (écarts) which make styles. Like the so-called naive painter who, operating outside the held and its specific traditions remains external to the history of the art, the ‘naive’ spectator cannot attain a specific grasp of works of art which only have meaning—or value—in relation to the specific history of an artistic tradition. The aesthetic disposition demanded by the products of a highly autonomous field of production is inseparable from a specific cultural competence. This historical culture functions as a principle of pertinence which enables one to identify, among the elements offered to the gaze, all the distinctive
  • 15. features and only these, by referring them, consciously or unconsciously, to the 6 See P. Bourdieu, ‘Le marché des biens symboliques’, L’Anneé Sociologique, 22 (1973), 49 126; and ‘Outline of a Sociological Theory of Art Perception’, International Social Science Journal, 20 (Winter 1968), 589-612. 5 universe of possible alternatives. This mastery is, for the most part, acquired simply by contact with works of art—that is, through an implicit learning analogous to that which makes it possible to recognize familiar faces without explicit rules or criteria—and it generally remains at a practical level; it is what makes it possible to identify styles, i.e., modes of expression characteristic of a period, a civilization or a school, without having to distinguish clearly, or state explicitly, the features which constitute their originality. Everything seems to suggest that even among professional valuers, the criteria which define the stylistic properties of the ‘typical works’ on which all their judgements are based usually remain implicit. The pure gaze implies a break with the ordinary attitude towards the world,
  • 16. which, given the conditions in which it is performed, is also a social separation. Orteya y Gasset can be believed when he attributes to modern art a systematic refusal of all that is ‘human’, i.e., generic, common—as opposed to distinctive, or distinguished—namely, the passions, emotions and feelings which ‘ordinary’ people invest in their ‘ordinary’ lives. It is as if the ‘popular aesthetic’ (the quotation marks are there to indicate that this is an aesthetic ‘in itself’ not ‘for itself’) were based on the affirmation of the continuity between art and life, which implies the subordination of form to function. This is seen clearly in the case of the novel and especially the theatre, where the working- class audience refuses any sort of formal experimentation and all the effects which, by introducing a distance from the accepted conventions (as regards scenery, plot etc.), tend to distance the spectator, preventing him from getting involved and fully identifying with the characters (I am thinking of Brechtian ‘alienation’ or the disruption of plot in the nouveau roman). In contrast to the detachment and disinterestedness which aesthetic theory regards as the only way of recognizing the work of art for what it is, i.e., autonomous, selbständig, the ‘popular aesthetic’ ignores or refuses the refusal of ‘facile’ involvement and ‘vulgar’ enjoyment, a refusal which is the basis of the taste for formal experiment. And
  • 17. popular judgements of paintings or photographs spring from an ‘aesthetic’ (in fact it is an ethos) which is the exact opposite of the Kantian aesthetic. Whereas, in order to grasp the specificity of the aesthetic judgement, Kant strove to distinguish that which pleases from that which gratifies and, more generally, to distinguish disinterestedness, the sole guarantor of the specifically aesthetic quality of contemplation, from the interest of reason which defines the Good, working-class people expect every image to explicitly perform a function, if only that of a sign, and their judgements make reference, often explicitly, to the norms of morality or agreeableness. Whether rejecting or praising, their appreciation always has an ethical basis. Popular taste applies the schemes of the ethos, which pertain in the ordinary circumstances of life, to legitimate works of art, and so performs a systematic reduction of the things of art to the things of life. The very seriousness (or 6 naivety) which this taste invests in fictions and representations demonstrates a contrario that pure taste performs a suspension of ‘naive’ involvement which is one dimension of a ‘quasi-ludic’ relationship with the
  • 18. necessities of the world. Intellectuals could be said to believe in the representation— literature, theatre, painting—more than in the things represented, whereas the people chiefly expect representations and the conventions which govern them to allow them to believe ‘naively’ in the things represented. The pure aesthetic is rooted in an ethic, or rather, an ethos of elective distance from the necessities of the natural and social world, which may take the form of moral agnosticism (visible when ethical transgression becomes an artistic parti pris) or of an aestheticism which presents the aesthetic disposition as a universally valid principle and takes the bourgeois denial of the social world to its limit. The detachment of the pure gaze cannot be dissociated from a general disposition towards the world which is the paradoxical product of conditioning by negative economic necessities—a life of ease—that tends to induce an active distance from necessity. Although art obviously offers the greatest scope to the aesthetic disposition, there is no area of practice in which the aim of purifying, refining and sublimating primary needs and impulses cannot assert itself, no area in which the stylization of life, that is, the primacy of forms over function, of manner over matter, does not produce the same effects. And nothing is more distinctive, more distinguished, than the capacity to confer aesthetic status on objects that are banal
  • 19. or even ‘common’ (because the ‘common’ people make them their own, especially for aesthetic purposes), or the ability to apply the principles of a ‘pure’ aesthetic to the most everyday choices of everyday life, e.g., in cooking, clothing or decoration, completely reversing the popular disposition which annexes aesthetics to ethics. In fact, through the economic and social conditions which they presuppose, the different ways of relating to realities and fictions, of believing in fictions and the realities they simulate, with more or less distance and detachment, are very closely linked to the different possible positions in social space and, consequently, bound up with the systems of dispositions (habitus) characteristic of the different classes and class fractions. Taste classifies, and it classifies the classifier. Social subjects, classified by their classifications, distinguish themselves by the distinctions they make, between the beautiful and the ugly, the distinguished and the vulgar, in which their position in the objective classifications is expressed or betrayed. And statistical analysis does indeed show that oppositions similar in structure to those found in cultural practices also appear in eating habits. The antithesis between quantity and quality, substance and form, corresponds to the opposition—linked to different distances from necessity—between the taste of necessity, which favours the
  • 20. most ‘filling’ and most economical foods, and the taste of liberty or luxury— which shifts the 7 emphasis to the manner (of presenting, serving, eating etc.) and tends to use stylized forms to deny function. The science of taste and of cultural consumption begins with a transgression that is in no way aesthetic: it has to abolish the sacred frontier which makes legitimate culture a separate universe, in order to discover the intelligible relations which unite apparently incommensurable ‘choices’, such as preferences in music and food, painting and sport, literature and hairstyle. This barbarous reintegration of aesthetic consumption into the world of ordinary consumption abolishes the opposition, which has been the basis of high aesthetics since Kant, between the ‘taste of sense’ and the ‘taste of reflection’, and between facile pleasure, pleasure reduced to a pleasure of the senses, and pure pleasure, pleasure purified of pleasure, which is predisposed to become a symbol of moral excellence and a measure of the capacity for sublimation which defines the truly human man. The culture which results from this magical division is sacred.
  • 21. Cultural consecration does indeed confer on the objects, persons and situations it touches, a sort of ontological promotion akin to a transubstantiation. Proof enough of this is found in the two following quotations, which might almost have been written for the delight of the sociologist: ‘What struck me most is this: nothing could be obscene on the stage of our premier theatre, and the ballerinas of the Opera, even as naked dancers, sylphs, sprites or Bacchae, retain an inviolable purity.’7 ‘There are obscene postures: the stimulated intercourse which offends the eye. Clearly, it is impossible to approve, although the interpolation of such gestures in dance routines does give them a symbolic and aesthetic quality which is absent from the intimate scenes the cinema daily flaunts before its spectators’ eyes . . . As for the nude scene, what can one say, except that it is brief and theatrically not very effective? I will not say it is chaste or innocent, for nothing commercial can be so described. Let us say it is not shocking, and that the chief objection is that it serves as a box-office gimmick. . . . In Hair, the nakedness fails to be symbolic.’8 The denial of lower, coarse, vulgar, venal, servile—in a word, natural— enjoyment, which constitutes the sacred sphere of culture, implies an affirmation of the superiority of those who can be satisfied with the sublimated, refined, disinterested, gratuitous, distinguished pleasures forever closed
  • 22. to the profane. That is why art and cultural consumption are predisposed, consciously and deliberately or not, to fulfil a social function of legitimating social differences. Translated by Richard Nice 7 O. Merlin, ‘Mlle. Thibon dans la vision de Marguerite’, Le Monde, 9 December 1965. 8 F. Chenique, ‘Hair est-il immoral?’ Le Monde, 28 January 1970. Power-Dependence Relations Author(s): Richard M. Emerson Reviewed work(s): Source: American Sociological Review, Vol. 27, No. 1 (Feb., 1962), pp. 31-41 Published by: American Sociological Association Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2089716 . Accessed: 28/12/2011 21:47 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new
  • 23. forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected] American Sociological Association is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to American Sociological Review. http://www.jstor.org http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=asa http://www.jstor.org/stable/2089716?origin=JSTOR-pdf http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp POWER-DEPENDENCE RELATIONS RICHARD M. EMERSON University of Cincinnati A simple theory of power relations is developed in an effort to resolve some of the ambiguities surrounding "power," "authority," "legitimacy," and power "structures," through bringing them together in a coherent scheme. After defining a reciprocal power-dependence relation, attention is focused upon properties of balance and "balancing operations" in such relations. The theory dictates exactly four generic types of balancing process, and discussion of these leads directly into processes of group formation, including the emergence of group norms, role structure and status hierarchy, all presented as the outcome of balancing tendencies in power relations. Within the framework of this theory, authority appears quite naturally to be
  • 24. legitimized power, vested in roles, and "legitimation" is seen as a special case of the coalition process through which norms and role-prescriptions are formed. Finally, through treating both persons and groups as actors in a power-network (two or more connected power- dependence relations) the door is opened for meaningful analysis of complex power struc- tures. Brief reference is made to findings from two experiments pertaining to hypotheses advanced in this theory. JUDGING from the frequent occurrence of such words as power, influence, domi- nance and submission, status and author- ity, the importance of power is widely recog- nized, yet considerable confusion exists concerning these concepts.' There is an ex- tensive literature pertaining to power, on both theoretical and empirical levels, and in small group 2 as well as large community contexts.3 Unfortunately, this already large and rap- idly growing body of research has not achieved the cumulative character desired. Our integrated knowledge of power does not significantly surpass the conceptions left by Max Weber.4 This suggests that there is a place at this moment for a systematic treatment of social power. The underdeveloped state of this area is further suggested by what appears, to this author, to be a recurrent flaw in common conceptions of social power; a flaw which
  • 25. helps to block adequate theoretical develop- ment as well as meaningful research. That flaw is the implicit treatment of power as though it were an attribute of a person or group ("X is an influential person." "Y is a powerful group," etc.). Given this concep- tion, the natural research question becomes "Who in community X are the power kold- ers?". The project then proceeds to rank- order persons by some criterion of power, and this ordering is called the power-struc- ture. This is a highly questionable represen- tation of a "structure," based upon a ques- tionable assumption of generalized power.5 It is commonly observed that some person X dominates Y, while being subservient in relations with Z. Furthermore, these power relations are frequently intransitive! Hence, 1 See the Communications by Jay Butler and Paul Harrison on "On Power and Authority: An Exchange on Concepts," American Sociological Review, 25 (October, 1960), pp. 731-732. That both men can be essentially correct in the points they make yet fail to reconcile these points, strongly suggests the need for conceptual devel- opment in the domain of power relations. 2Among many studies, see Ronald Lippitt, Norman Polansky, Fritz Redl and Sidney Rosen, "The Dynamics of Power," Human Relations, 5 (February, 1952), pp. 37-64. 3 Floyd Hunter, Community Power Structure, Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press,
  • 26. 1953. 4 Max Weber, in The Theory of Social and Economic Organization, New York: Oxford Uni- versity Press, 1947, presents what is still a classic formulation of power, authority and legitimacy. However, it is characteristic of Weber that he constructs a typology rather than an organized theory of power. r See Raymond E. Wolfinger, "Reputation and Reality in the Study of 'Community Power'," American Sociological Review, 25 (October, 1960), pp. 636-644, for a well taken critical re- view of Floyd Hunter's work on these very points. The notion of "generalized power" which is not restricted to specific social relations, if taken literally, is probably meaningless. Power may indeed be generalized across a finite set of rela- tions in a power network, but this notion, too, requires very careful analysis. Are you dealing with some kind of halo effect (reputations if you wish), or are the range and boundary of general- ized power anchored in the power structure itself? These are questions which must be asked and answered. 31 32 AMERICAN SOCIOLOGICAL REVIEW to say that "X has power" is vacant, unless we specify "over whom." In making these necessary qualifications we force ourselves
  • 27. to face up to the obvious: power is a prop- erty of the social relation; it is not an attri- bute of the actor.6 In this paper an attempt is made to con- struct a simple theory of the power aspects of social relations. Attention is focused upon characteristics of the relationship as such, with little or no regard for particular fea- tures of the persons or groups engaged in such relations. Personal traits, skills or pos- sessions (such as wealth) which might be relevant to power in one relation are infi- nitely variable across the set of possible re- lations, and hence have no place in a general theory. THE POWER-DEPENDENCE RELATION While the theory presented here is an- chored most intimately in small group re- search, it is meant to apply to more complex community relations as well. In an effort to make these conceptions potentially as broadly applicable as possible, we shall speak of re- lations among actors, where an actor can be either a person or a group. Unless otherwise indicated, any relation discussed might be a person-person, group-person or group-group relation. Social relations commonly entail ties of mutual dependence between the parties. A depends upon B if he aspires to goals or gratifications whose achievement is facili- tated by appropriate actions on B's part. By
  • 28. virtue of mutual dependency, it is more or less imperative to each party that he be able to control or influence the other's con- duct. At the same time, these ties of mutual dependence imply that each party is in a position, to some degree, to grant or deny, facilitate or hinder, the other's gratification. Thus, it would appear that the power to con- trol or influence the other resides in control over the things he values, which may range all the way from oil resources to ego-support, depending upon the relation in question. In short, power resides implicitly in the other's dependency. When this is recognized, the analysis will of necessity revolve largely around the concept of dependence.7 Two variables appear to function jointly in fixing the dependence of one actor upon another. Since the precise nature of this joint function is an empirical question, our propo- sition can do no more than specify the di- rectional relationships involved: Dependence (Dab). The dependence of actor A upon actor B is (1) directly proportional to A's motivational investment in goals medi- ated by B, and (2) inversely proportional to the availability of those goals to A outside of the A-B relation. In this proposition "goal" is used in the broadest possible sense to refer to gratifica- tions consciously sought as well as rewards unconsciously obtained through the relation-
  • 29. ship. The "availability" of such goals out- side of the relation refers to alternative ave- nues of goal-achievement, most notably other social relations. The costs associated with such alternatives must be included in any assessment of dependency.8 If the dependence of one party provides the basis for the power of the other, that power must be defined as a potential in- fluence: Power (Pab). The power of actor A over actor B is the amount of resistance on the part of B which can be potentially overcome by A. Two points must be made clear about this definition. First, the power defined here will not be, of necessity, observable in every in- teractive episode between A and B, yet we suggest that it exists nonetheless as a poten- tial, to be explored, tested, and occasionally employed by the participants. Pab will be ,'Just as power is often treated as though it were a property of the person, so leadership, con- formity, etc., are frequently referred to the per- sonal traits of "leaders," "conformers" and so on, as if they were distinguishable types of people. In a sociological perspective such behavior should be explicitly treated as an attribute of a relation rather than a person. 7 The relation between power and dependence is given similar emphasis in the systematic treatment
  • 30. by J. Thibaut and H. H. Kelley, The Social Psychology of Groups, New York: John Wiley and Sons, 1959. 8 The notion of "opportunity costs" in economics is a similar idea. If an employee has alternative employment opportunities, and if these opportunities have low associated cost (travel, etc.), the em- ployee's dependence upon his current employer is reduced. POWER-DEPENDENCE RELATIONS 33 empirically manifest only if A makes some demand, and only if this demand runs counter to B's desires (resistance to be over- come). Any operational definition must make reference to change in the conduct of B at- tributable to demands made by A. Second, we define power as the "resist- ance" which can be overcome, without re- stricting it to any one domain of action. Thus, if A is dependent upon B for love and respect, B might then draw A into criminal activity which he would normally resist. The reader might object to this formulation, argu- ing that social power is in fact restricted to certain channels. If so, the reader is appar- ently concerned with "legitimized power" embedded in a social structure. Rather than begin at this more evolved level, we hope to derive legitimized power in the theory itself.
  • 31. The premise we began with can now be stated as Pab=Dba; the power of A over B is equal to, and based upon, the dependence of B upon A.9 Recognizing the reciprocity of social relations, we can represent a power- dependence relation as a pair of equations: Pab=Dba Pba=Dab. Before proceeding further we should em- phasize that these formulations have been so worded in the hope that they will apply across a wide range of social life. At a glance our conception of dependence con- tains two variables remarkably like supply and demand ("availability" and "motiva- tional investment," respectively).10 We pre- fer the term dependency over these economic terms because it facilitates broader applica- tion, for all we need to do to shift these ideas from one area of application to another is change the motivational basis of dependency. We can speak of the economic dependence of a home builder upon a loan agency as varying directly with his desire for the home, and hence capital, and inversely with the "availability" of capital from other agencies. Similarly, a child may be dependent upon another child based upon motivation toward the pleasures of collective play, the availability of alternative playmates, etc. The same generic power-dependence relation is involved in each case. The dependency
  • 32. side of the equation may show itself in "friendship" among playmates, in "filial love" between parent and child, in "respect for treaties" among nations. On the other side of the equation, I am sure no one doubts that mothers, lovers, children, and nations enjoy the power to influence their respective partners, within the limit set by the partner's dependence upon them. Finally, because these concepts are meant to apply across a wide variety of social sit- uations, operational definitions cannot be ap- propriately presented here. Operational defi- nitions provide the necessary bridge between generalizing concepts on the one hand, and the concrete features of a specific research situation on the other hand. Hence, there is no one proper operational definition for a theoretical concept." BALANCE AND IMBALANCE The notion of reciprocity in power-de- pendency relations raises the question of equality or inequality of power in the rela- tion. If the power of A over B (Pab) is con- fronted by equal opposing power of B over A, is power then neutralized or cancelled out? We suggest that in such a balanced con- 9 In asserting that power is based upon the dependency of the other, it might appear that we are dealing with one of the bases of power ("reward power") listed by John R. P. French, Jr. and Bertram Raven, "The Bases of Social
  • 33. Power," Studies in Social Power, D. Cartwright, editor, Ann Arbor, Michigan: Institute for Social Research, 1959. However, careful attention to our highly generalized conception of dependence will show that it covers most if not all of the forms of power listed in that study. 10 Professor Alfred Kuhn, Department of Eco- nomics, University of Cincinnati, has been working on a theory for power analysis soon to be pub- lished. The scheme he develops, though very similar to the one presented here, is put together in a different way. It is anchored more tightly to economic concepts, and hence its implications lead off in different directions from those presented below. 1" Many different operational definitions can serve one theoretical concept, and there is no reason to require that they produce intercorrelated results when applied in the same research situation. While the controversies surrounding "operationalism" have now been largely resolved, there remains some con- fusion on this point. See, for example, Bernice Eisman, "Some Operational Measures of Cohesive- ness and Their Interrelations," Human Relations, 12 (May, 1959), pp. 183-189. 34 AMERICAN SOCIOLOGICAL REVIEW dition, power is in no way removed from the relationship. A pattern of "dominance" might not emerge in the interaction among these actors, but that does not imply that power is
  • 34. inoperative in either or both directions. A balanced relation and an unbalanced relation are represented respectively as follows: Pab=Dba Pab=Dba II II V V Pba-Dab Pba=Dab Consider two social relations, both of which are balanced, but at different levels of de- pendence (say Loeb and Leopold, as com- pared with two casual friends). A moment's thought will reveal the utility of the argu- ment that balance does not neutralize power, for each party may continue to exert pro- found control over the other. It might even be meaningful to talk about the parties being controlled by the relation itself. Rather than cancelling out considerations of power, reciprocal power provides the basis for studying three more features of power- relations: first, a power advantage can be defined as Pab minus Pba, which can be either positive or negative (a power disad- vantage); 12 second, the cohesion of a rela- tionship can be defined as the average of Dab and Dba, though this definition can be refined; 13 and finally, it opens the door to the study of balancing operations as struc- tural changes in power-dependence relations which tend to reduce power advantage. Discussion of balancing tendencies should begin with a concrete illustration. In the
  • 35. unbalanced relation represented symbolically above, A is the more powerful party because B is the more dependent of the two. Let actor B be a rather "unpopular" girl, with puritanical upbringing, who wants desper- ately to date; and let A be a young man who occasionally takes her out, while dating other girls as well. (The reader can satisfy himself about A's power advantage in this illustra- tion by referring to the formulations above.) Assume further that A "discovers" this power advantage, and, in exploring for the limits of his power, makes sexual advances. In this simplified illustration, these advances should encounter resistance in B's puritanical values. Thus, when a power advantage is used, the weaker member will achieve one value at the expense of other values. In this illustration the tensions involved in an unbalanced relation need not be long endured. They can be reduced in either of two ways: (1) the girl might reduce the psychic costs involved in continuing the rela- tion by redefining her moral values, with appropriate rationalizations and shifts in reference group attachments; or (2) she might renounce the value of dating, develop career aspirations, etc., thus reducing A's power. Notice that the first solution does not of necessity alter the unbalanced rela- tion. The weaker member has sidestepped one painful demand but she is still vulnerable to new demands. By contrast, the second solution alters the power relation itself. In
  • 36. general, it appears that an unbalanced rela- tion is unstable for it encourages the use of power which in turn sets in motion processes which we will call (a) cost reduction and (b) balancing operations.'4 COST REDUCTION The "cost" referred to here amounts to the "resistance" to be overcome in our defini- tion of power-the cost involved for one party in meeting the demands made by the other. The process of cost reduction in power- dependence relations shows itself in many varied forms. In the courting relation above it took the form of alteration in moral atti- tudes on the part of a girl who wanted to be popular; in industry it is commonly seen as the impetus for improved plant efficiency and technology in reducing the cost of pro- duction. What we call the "mark of oppres- sion" in the character structure of members 12 J. Thibaut and H. H. Kelley, op. cit., pp. 107- 108. 13 This definition of cohesion, based upon depend- ency, seems to have one advantage over the defini- tion offered by Leon Festinger, et al., Theory and Experiment in Social Communication, Ann Arbor: Research Center for Group Dynamics, University of Michigan Press, 1950. The Festinger definition takes into account only one of the two variables involved in dependency. 14 The "tensions of imbalance," which are as-
  • 37. sumed to make an unbalanced relation unstable, are closely related to the idea of "distributive justice" discussed by George C. Homans, Social Behavior: Its Elementary Forms, New York: Harcourt, Brace and World, Inc., 1961. All of what Homans has to say around this idea could be fruitfully drawn into the present formulation. POWER-DEPENDENCE RELATIONS 35 of low social castes (the submissive and "painless" loss of freedom) might well in- volve the same power processes, as does the "internalization of parental codes" in the socialization process. In fact, the oedipal conflict might be interpreted as a special case of the tensions of imbalance in a power- dependence relation, and cost reduction takes the form of identification and internalization as classically described. "Identification with the aggressor" in any context would appear to be explainable in terms of cost reduction. In general, cost reduction is a process in- volving change in values (personal, social, economic) which reduces the pains incurred in meeting the demands of a powerful other. It must be emphasized, however, that these adjustments do not necessarily alter the bal- ance or imbalance of the relation, and, as a result, they must be distinguished from the more fundamental balancing operations described below. It must be recognized that cost reducing tendencies will take place
  • 38. even under conditions of balance, and while this is obvious in economic transactions, it is equally true of other social relations, where the "costs" involved are anchored in modi- fiable attitudes and values. The intense cohe- sion of a lasting social relation like the Loeb- Leopold relation mentioned above can be attributed in part to the cost reduction processes involved in the progressive forma- tion of their respective personalities, taking place in the interest of preserving the valued relation. We suggest that cost reducing tend- encies generally will function to deepen and stabilize social relations over and above the condition of balance. BALANCING OPERATIONS The remainder of this paper will deal with balancing processes which operate through changes in the variables which define the structure of the power-dependence relation as such. The formal notation adopted here suggests exactly four generic types of bal- ancing operation. In the unbalanced relation Pab=Dba v v, balance can be restored either by Pba-Dab an increase in Dab or by a decrease in Dba. If we recall that dependence is a joint func- tion of two variables, the following altera- tions will move the relation toward a state of balance:
  • 39. 1. If B reduces motivational investment in goals mediated by A; 2. If B cultivates alternative sources for gratification of those goals; 3. If A increases motivational investment in goals mediated by B; 4. If A is denied alternative sources for achieving those goals. While these four types of balancing opera- tion are dictated by the logic of the scheme, we suggest that each corresponds to well known social processes. The first operation yields balance through motivational with- drawal by B, the weaker member. The sec- ond involves the cultivation of alternative social relations by B. The third is based upon "giving status" to A, and the fourth involves coalition and group formation. In some of these processes the role of power is well known, while in others it seems to have escaped notice. In discussing any one of these balancing operations it must be remembered that a prediction of which one (or what combination) of the four will take place must rest upon analysis of conditions involved in the concrete case at hand. In the interest of simplicity and clarity, we will illustrate each of the four generic types of balancing operation in relations among children in the context of play. Con-
  • 40. sider two children equally motivated toward the pleasures of collective play and equally capable of contributing to such play. These children, A and B, form a balanced relation if we assume further that each has the other as his only playmate, and the give-and-take of their interactions might well be imagined, involving the emergence of such equalitarian rules as "taking turns," etc. Suppose now that a third child, C, moves into the neigh- borhood and makes the acquaintance of A, but not B. The A-B relation will be thrown out of balance by virtue of A's decreased de- pendence upon B. The reader should con- vince himself of this fact by referring back to the proposition on dependence. Without any of these parties necessarily "understand- ing" what is going on, we would predict that A would slowly come to dominate B in the pattern of their interactions. On more fre- quent occasions B will find himself deprived of the pleasures A can offer, thus slowly 36 AMERICAN SOCIOLOGICAL REVIEW coming to sense his own dependency more acutely. By the same token A will more frequently find B saying "yes" instead of "no" to his proposals, and he will gain in- creased awareness of his power over B. The growing self-images of these children will surely reflect and perpetuate this pattern. OPERATION NUMBER ONE: WITHDRAWAL
  • 41. We now have the powerful A making de- mands of the dependent B. One of the processes through which the tensions in the unbalanced A-B relation can be reduced is motivational withdrawal on the part of B, for this will reduce Dba and Pab. In this illustration, child B might lose some of his interest in collective play under the impact of frustrations and demands imposed by A. Such a withdrawal from the play relation would presumably come about if the other three balancing operations were blocked by the circumstances peculiar to the situation. The same operation was illustrated above in the case of the girl who might renounce the value of dating. It would seem to be involved in the dampened level of aspiration associated with the "mark of oppression" referred to above. In general, the denial of dependency in- volved in this balancing operation will have the effect of moving actors away from rela- tions which are unbalanced to their disad- vantage. The actor's motivational orienta- tions and commitments toward different areas of activity will intimately reflect this process. OPERATION NUMBER TWO: EXTENSION OF POWER NETWORK Withdrawal as a balancing operation en- tails subjective alterations in the weaker
  • 42. actor. The second operation takes place through alterations in a structure we shall call a power network, defined as two or more connected power-dependence relations. As we have seen in our illustration, when the C-A relation is connected through A with the A-B relation, forming a simple linear net- work C-A-B, the properties of A-B are al- tered. In this example, a previously balanced A-B relation is thrown out of balance, giving A a power advantage. This points up the general fact that while each relation in a network will involve interactions which ap- pear to be independent of other relations in the network (e.g., A and B are seen to play together in the absence of C; C and A in the absence of B), the internal features of one relation are nonetheless a function of the entire network. Any adequate conception of a "power structure" must be based upon this fact. In this illustration the form of the network throws both relations within it out of bal- ance, thus stimulating one or several of the balancing operations under discussion. If balancing operation number two takes place, the network will be extended by the forma- tion of new relationships. The tensions of imbalance in the A-B and A-C relations will make B and C "ready" to form new friend- ships (1) with additional children D and E, thus lengthening a linear network, or (2) with each other, thus "closing" the network. It is important to notice that the lengthened
  • 43. network balances some relations, but not the network as a whole, while the closed network is completely balanced under the limiting assumptions of this illustration. Thus, we might offer as a corollary to operation num- ber two: Power networks tend to achieve closure.'5 If the reader is dissatisfied with this illus- tration in children's play relations, let A be the loan agent mentioned earlier, and B, C, . . . N be home builders or others dependent upon A for capital. This is the familiar monopoly situation with the imbalance com- monly attributed to it. As a network, it is a set of relations connected only at A. Just as the children were "ready" to accept new friends, so the community of actors B, C, ... N is ready to receive new loan agencies. 15 The notion of closed versus open networks as discussed here can be directly related to research dealing with communication networks, such as that reported by Harold J. Leavitt, "Some Effects of Communication Patterns on Group Performance," Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology, 46 (January, 1951), pp. 38-50, in which the limiting assumptions involved in this discussion are fully met by experimental controls. In discussing those experiments in terms of the concepts in this theory we would consider each actor's dependence upon other actors for information. A formal treatment of such networks is suggested by A. Bavelas, "A Mathematical Model For Group Structure," Ap- plied Anthropology, 7 (Summer, 1948), pp. 16-30.
  • 44. POWER-DEPENDENCE RELATIONS 37 Balancing operation number 2 involves in all cases the diffusion of dependency into new relations in a network. A final illustra- tion of this principle can be found in institu- tionalized form in some kinship systems in- volving the extended family. In the case of the Hopi, for example, Dorothy Eggan has described at length the diffusion of child dependency among many' "mothers," thus draining off much of the force of oedipal conflicts in that society.'6 We have already suggested that oedipal conflict may be taken as a special case of the tension of imbalance, which in this case appears to be institution- ally handled in a manner resembling opera- tion number two. This is not to be taken, however, as an assertion that the institution evolved as a balancing process, though this is clearly open for consideration. It is convenient at this juncture to take up balancing operation number 4, leaving number 3 to the last. OPERATION NUMBER FOUR: COALITION FORMATION Let us continue with the same illustration. When the B-C relation forms, closing the C-A-B network in the process of balancing, we have what appears to be a coalition of
  • 45. the two weaker against the one stronger. This, however, is not technically the case, for A is not involved in the B-C interactions; he simply exists as an alternative playmate for both B and C. The proper representation of coalitions in a triad would be (AB)-C, (AC)-B, or (BC)-A. That is, a triadic network reduces to a coalition only if two members unite as a single actor in the process of dealing directly with the third. The difference in- volved here may be very small in behavioral terms, and the distinction may seem overly refined, but it goes to the heart of an im- portant conceptual problem (the difference between a closed "network" and a "group"), and it rests upon the fact that two very different balancing operations are involved. The C-A-B network is balanced through the addition of a third relation (C-B) in opera- tion number two, but it is still just a power network. In operation number 4 it achieves balance through collapsing the two-relational network into one group-person relation with the emergence of a "collective actor." Opera- tion number two reduces the power of the stronger actor, while number 4 increases the power of weaker actors through collectiviza- tion. If the rewards mediated by A are such that they can be jointly enjoyed by B and C, then the tensions of imbalance in the A-B and A-C relations can be resolved in the (BC)-A coalition.
  • 46. In a general way, Marx was asking for balancing operation number 4 in his call to "Workers of the world," and the collectiviza- tion of labor can be taken as an illustration of this balancing tendency as an historic process. Among the balancing operations described here, coalition formation is the one most commonly recognized as a power proc- ess. However, the more general significance of this balancing operation seems to have es- caped notice, for the typical coalition is only one of the many forms this same operation takes. For this reason the next section will explore coalition processes further. THE ORGANIZED GROUP We wish to suggest that the coalition process is basically involved in all organized group functioning, whether the group be called a coalition or not. We believe this illuminates the role which power processes play in the emergence and maintenance of group structure in general. In the typical coalition pattern, (AB)-C, A and B constitute a collective actor in the sense that they act as one, presenting them- selves to their common environment as a sin- gle unit. A coalition, as one type of group, is characterized by the fact that (a) the common environment is an actor to be controlled, and (b) its unity is historically based upon efforts to achieve that control. Now, all we need do to blend this type of group with groups in general is to dehumanize
  • 47. the environmental problem which the group collectively encounters. Thus, instead of having the control of actor C as its end, the group attempts to control C in the interest of achieving X, some "group goal." Now, if C also aspires toward X, and if C is dependent upon the group for achieving X, C might well be one of the group members- any member; Thus, in a three-member group 16 Dorothy Eggan, "The General Problem of Hopi Adjustment," American Anthropologist, 45 (July- September, 1943), pp. 357-373. 38 AMERICAN SOCIOLOGICAL REVIEW we have three coalition structures as intra- group relations, each representable as ([AB] -C)-X, with A, B and C interchange- able. The situation involved here is reminiscent of the rapidly forming and reforming coali- tions in unconsolidated children's play groups. As the group consolidates, these co- alitions do not drop out of the picture; they become stabilized features of group struc- ture, and the stabilization process is identical with "norm formation." In fact, the demands made by (AB) of C in the power process within ([AB]-C) are exactly what we nor- mally call group norms and role-prescrip- tions. Such norms are properly viewed as the "voice" of a collective actor, standing in
  • 48. coalition against the object of its demands. This reasoning suggests an idealized con- ception of group structure, based upon two types of collective demands: (1) Role-Prescriptions. Specifications of be- havior which all group members expect (demand) of one or more but not all members. (2) Group Norms. Specifications of behavior which all group members expect of all group members. Certain actions, when performed by some member or members, need not be performed by all other members to properly facilitate group functioning. These will tend to be in- corporated in role-prescriptions, which, taken together, provide a division of labor in a role structure. Roles are defined and enforced through a consolidation of power in coalition formation. Likewise with group norms. Thus, the structure of a group (its norms and pre- scriptions) will specify the makeup of the coalition a member would face for any group-relevant act he might perform. This conception of group structure is ideal- ized in the sense that it describes complete consensus among members, even to the point of group identification and internalization of collective demands (members expect things of themselves in the above definitions). Bal- ancing operations, along with cost reduction, should move group structure toward this
  • 49. ideal. AUTHORITY It should be clear that in introducing con- ceptions of group structure we have in no way digressed from our discussion of power processes, for the emergence of these struc- tural forms is attributed directly to operation number four, closely resembling coalition formation. Even the most formalized role- prescription is properly viewed as the "voice" of all members standing as a coalition in making its demand of the occupant of the role. Whenever a specific member finds occa- sion to remind another member of his "proper" job in terms of such prescriptions, he speaks with the authority of the group behind him; he is "authorized" to speak for them. In this sense, every member has au- thority of a kind (as in civil arrest), but authority is usually used to refer to power vested in an office or role. The situation is basically the same, however, in either case. The occupant of such a role has simply been singled out and commissioned more explicitly to speak for the group in the group's deal- ings with its members. That authority is limited power follows from logical necessity when role-prescriptions are treated as they are here. A dean, for example, can force faculty member A to turn in his grades on time because the demand is "legitimate," that is, supported by a coalition of all other faculty members joining with the dean in
  • 50. making the demand. If that dean, however, were to employ sanctions in an effort to induce that member to polish the dean's private car, the "coalition" would immedi- ately re-form around the faculty member, as expressed in role-prescriptions defining the boundary of "legitimate power" or authority. The dean's authority is power contained and restricted through balancing operation num- ber four, coalition formation. The notion of legitimacy is important, for authority is more than balanced power; it is directed power which can be employed (legitimately) only in channels defined by the norms of the group. A person holding such authority is commissioned; he does not simply have the right to rule or govern-he is obliged to. Thus, authority emerges as a transformation of power in a process called "legitimation," and that process is one spe- cial case of balancing operation number four.17 17 The process of legitimation has sometimes been described as a tactic employed by a person aspiring POWER-DEPENDENCE RELATIONS 39 Earlier in this section we referred to the common phenomenon of rapidly forming and re-forming coalitions in children's play groups. Our reasoning suggests that it is precisely through these coalition processes
  • 51. that unifying norms emerge. These fluctu- ating coalitions can be taken as the proto- type of organized group life wherein the tempo of coalition realignment is accelerated to the point of being a blur before our eyes. Stated more accurately, the norms and pre- scriptions define implicitly the membership of the coalition which would either support or oppose any member if he were to perform any action relevant to those norms. OPERATION NUMBER THREE: EMERGENCE OF STATUS One important feature of group structure remains to be discussed: status and status hierarchies. It is interesting that the one remaining balancing operation provided in this theory takes us naturally to the emer- gence of status ordering. Operation number three increases the weaker member's power to control the formerly more powerful mem- ber through increasing the latter's motiva- tional investment in the relation. This is normally accomplished through giving him status recognition in one or more of its many forms, from ego-gratifications to mone- tary differentials. The ego-rewards, such as prestige, loom large in this process because they are highly valued by many recipients while given at low cost to the giver. The discussion of status hierarchies forces us to consider intra-group relations, and how this can be done in a theory which treats
  • 52. the group in the singular as an actor. The answer is contained in the idealized concep- tion of group structure outlined above. That conception implies that every intra-group relation involves at once every member of the group. Thus, in a group with members A, B, C, and D, the relations A-B, A-C, etc. do not exist. Any interactions between A and B, for example, lie outside of the social sys- tem in question unless one or both of these persons "represents" the group in his actions, as in the coalition pattern discussed at length above. The relations which do exist are (ABCD)-A, (ABCD)-B, (ABCD)-C and (ABCD)-D as a minimum, plus whatever relations of the (ABCD)-(AB) type may be involved in the peculiar structure of the group in question. Thus, in a group of N members we have theoretical reason for deal- ing with N group-member relations rather N(N-1) than considering all of the possible 2 member-member relations. Each of these group-member relations can now be ex- pressed in the familiar equations for a power- dependence relation: Pgmi=Dmig Pmig=Dgmi. To account for the emergence of a status hierarchy within a group of N members, we start with a set of N group-member relations
  • 53. of this type and consider balancing opera- tions in these relations. Let us imagine a five member group and proceed on three assumptions: (1) status involves differential valuation of members (or roles) by the group, and this valuation is equivalent to, or an expression of, Dgmi; (2) a member who is highly valued by the group is highly valued in other similar groups he belongs to or might freely join; and (3) all five members have the same mo- tivational investment in the group at the outset. Assumptions 2 and 3 are empirical, and when they are true they imply that Dgm and Dmg are inversely related across the N group-member relations. This in turn implies a state of imbalance of a very precarious nature so far as group stability is concerned. to power or trying to hold his power, rather than a process through which persons are granted restricted power. For example, C. Wright Mills states: "Those in authority attempt to justify their rule over institutions by linking it, as if it were a necessary consequence, with widely believed in moral symbols, sacred emblems, legal formulae. These central conceptions may refer to god or gods, the 'vote of the majority,' 'the will of the people,' 'the aristocracy of talent or wealth,' to the 'divine right of kings,' or to the allegedly extraordinary endowments of the ruler himself. Social scientists, following Weber, call such conceptions 'legitima- tions,' or sometimes 'symbols of justification."' (The Sociological Imagination, New York: Oxford University Press, 1959, p. 36). Whether we view
  • 54. the process of legitimation in the context of the formation of such collective conceptions, or in the context of calling upon them to justify action, the process is fundamentally that of mobilizing collec- tive support to oppose those who challenge power. Power so supported is authority, and the process fits the general model of coalition formation. 40 AMERICAN SOCIOLOGICAL REVIEW The least dependent member of a group will be the first to break from the group, and these members are precisely the most valued members. It is this situation which balancing operation number three alleviates through "giving status" to the highly valued mem- bers, thus gaining the power to keep and control those members. These ideas are illustrated with hypotheti- cal values in Table 1, with imbalance repre- sented as power advantage (PA). Balancing operations will tend to move PA toward zero, as shown in column 6 after the highly valued members A and B have come to depend upon the group for the special rewards of status, and in column 9 after the least valued mem- bers D and E have withdrawn some of their TABLE 1. HYPOTHETICAL VALUES SHOWING TEE RELATION BETWEEN DGM AND DMG IN A GROUP WITH FIVE MEMBERS Before Balancing After Operation #3 After Operation # 1
  • 55. 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 Member Dgm Dmg* PAgm** Dgm Dmg PAgm** Dgm Dmg PAgm** A 5 1 -4 5 5 0 5 5 0 B 4 2 -2 4 4 0 4 4 0 C 3 3 0 3 3 0 3 3 0 D 2 4 2 2 4 2 2 2 0 E 1 5 4 1 5 4 1 1 0 *Assuming that all members have the same motivational investment in the group at the outset, and that highly valued members (A and B) are valued in other groups as well. ** Power Advantage PAgm=Dmg-Dgm. original motivational investment in the group. The table presents three stages in status crystallization, and the process of crystallization is seen as a balancing process. The final stage (columns 7, 8, and 9) should be achieved only in groups with very low membership turnover. The middle stage might well be perpetual in groups with new members continually coming in at the lower levels. In such "open" groups, status striving should be a characteristic feature and can be taken as a direct manifestation of the tensions of imbalance. In the final stage, such strivers have either succeeded or withdrawn from the struggle. Among the factors involved in status or- dering, this theory focuses attention upon
  • 56. the extreme importance of the availability factor in dependency as a determinant of status position and the values employed in status ordering. In considering Dgm (the relative value or importance the group at- taches to member roles), it is notably difficult to rely upon a functional explanation. Is the pitcher more highly valued than the center fielder because he is functionally more im- portant or because good pitchers are harder to find? Is the physicist valued over the plumber because of a "more important" func- tional contribution to the social system, or because physicists are more difficult to re- place, more costly to obtain, etc.? The latter considerations involve the availability factor. We suggest here that the values people use in ordering roles or persons express the de- pendence of the system upon those roles, and that the availability factor in dependency plays the decisive part in historically shap- ing those values."8 CONCLUSION The theory put forth in this paper is in large part contained implicitly in the ties of mutual dependence which bind actors to- gether in social systems. Its principal value seems to be its ability to pull together a wide variety of social events, ranging from the internalization of parental codes to soci- ety-wide movements, like the collectivization of labor, in terms of a few very simple prin- ciples. Most important, the concepts involved
  • 57. are subject to operational formulation. Two 18 "Motivational investment" and "availability," which jointly determine dependency at any point in time, are functionally related through time. This is implied in our balancing operations. While these two variables can be readily distinguished in the case of Dmg, they are too intimately fused in Dgm to be clearly separated. The values by which a group sees a given role as "important" at time 2, evolve from felt scarcity in that role and similar roles at time 1. CHOICE IN INTERPERSONAL RELATIONS 41 experiments testing certain propositions dis- cussed above led to the following results: L Conformity (Pgm) varies directly with motivational investment in the group; 2. Conformity varies inversely with accept- ance in alternative groups; 3. Conformity is high at both status extremes in groups with membership turnover (see column 5, Table 1); 4. Highly valued members of a group are strong conformers only if they are valued by other groups as well. (This supports the notion that special status rewards are used to hold the highly valued member who does not depend heavily upon the
  • 58. group, and that in granting him such re- wards power is obtained over him.); 5. Coalitions form among the weak to con- trol the strong (balancing operation num- ber three); 6. The greatest rewards within a coalition are given to the less dependent member of the coalition (balancing operation num- ber three, analogous to "status giving"). Once the basic ideas in this theory have been adequately validated and refined, both theoretical and empirical work must be ex- tended in two main directions. First, the in- teraction process should be studied to locate carefully the factors leading to perceived power and dependency in self and others, and the conditions under which power, as a potential, will be employed in action. Sec- ondly, and, in the long run, more important, will be study of power networks more com- plex than those referred to here, leading to more adequate understanding of complex power structures. The theory presented here does no more than provide the basic under- pinning to the study of complex networks. There is every reason to believe that modern mathematics, graph theory in particular,"' can be fruitfully employed in the analysis of complex networks and predicting the out- come of power plays within such networks. 19 F. Harary and R. Norman, Graph Theory as
  • 59. a Mathematical Model in the Social Sciences. Ann Arbor: Institute for Social Research, 1953. An effort to apply such a model to power relations can be found in John R. P. French, Jr., "A Formal Theory of Social Power," The Psychological Re- view, 63 (May, 1956), pp. 181-194. PATTERNS OF CHOICE IN INTERPERSONAL RELATIONS PETER M. BLAU University of Chicago How do people's attributes influence the interpersonal choices among them? Data on work groups are used to examine the regularities revealed by 17 items on four types of interpersonal choice-respect, consultation, sociable attraction, and informal acceptance. Four main pat- terns could be discerned: (1) Items that had a differentiating effect on respect also had differentiating effects on consultation and attraction but usually not on informal acceptance; (2) Orientations toward work had a segregating effect on respect, but only orientations with pronounced significance for respect also had segregating effects on other interpersonal choices; (3) Attributes that differentiated consultants from others without producing a corresponding differentiation of respect to legitimate the status of consultant created segregating barriers to sociability; (4) Measures of approach to people had a segregating effect on consultation, like others salient orientations, but they had a differentiating effect on attraction, probably because an informal approach made a worker a more attractive companion. The four groups
  • 60. of independent variables in this analysis are shown to represent orthogonal dimensions. RELATIONSHIPS between persons acting in social roles constitute the matrix of social structures. The systematic in- vestigation of interpersonal relations, there- fore, promises to contribute much to a better understanding of social structure. The data to be explained in this schema are dis- * I am greatly indebted for many suggestions and for assistance with technical problems of analysis to my colleagues Otis Dudley Duncan, Elihu Katz, Jack Sawyer, Fred L. Strodtbeck, and Harrison C. White. I also want to acknowledge financial sup- port from the Ford Foundation and the help of Robert A. Gordon, who did the factor analysis, and of Robert W. Hodge and Philip M. Marcus, who worked on the computations, Article Contentsp.31p.32p.33p.34p.35p.36p.37p.38p.39p.40p.41Issue Table of ContentsAmerican Sociological Review, Vol. 27, No. 1 (Feb., 1962), pp. 1-154Front Matter [pp.1-4]Toward a Theory of Revolution [pp.5-19]Mass Society and Extremist Politics [pp.19-30]Power-Dependence Relations [pp.31-41]Patterns of Choice in Interpersonal Relations [pp.41-55]Nurse-Patient Social Distance and the Structural Context of a Mental Hospital [pp.56-65]Value-Behavior Discrepancies Regarding Premarital Coitus in Three Western Cultures [pp.66-74]The Local Community: A Survey Approach [pp.75-84]Research Reports and NotesIndependent Causation in Multivariate Analysis: The Case of Political Alienation and Attitude Toward a School Bond
  • 61. Issue [pp.85-87]The Occupational Characteristics of Migrants to Duluth: A Retest of Rose's Hypothesis [pp.87-90]Errata and Clarifications [pp.91-92]Errata and Clarifications [pp.92- 93]Errata and Clarifications [p.93]Errata and Clarifications [pp.93-94]Errata and Clarifications [p.94]Communications [pp.95-98]Book Reviewsuntitled [pp.99-100]untitled [p.100]untitled [pp.100-101]untitled [p.101]untitled [pp.101- 102]untitled [p.102]untitled [pp.102-103]untitled [pp.103- 104]untitled [pp.104-105]untitled [pp.105-106]untitled [p.106]untitled [pp.106-107]untitled [p.107]untitled [pp.107- 108]untitled [pp.108-109]untitled [p.109]untitled [pp.109- 110]untitled [pp.110-111]untitled [p.111]untitled [pp.111- 113]untitled [p.113]untitled [pp.113-114]untitled [p.114]untitled [pp.114-115]untitled [p.115]untitled [pp.115- 116]untitled [pp.116-117]untitled [p.117]untitled [pp.117- 118]untitled [pp.118-119]untitled [pp.119-120]untitled [pp.120- 121]untitled [p.121]untitled [p.122]untitled [pp.122- 123]untitled [pp.123-124]untitled [p.124]untitled [pp.124- 125]untitled [p.125]untitled [pp.125-126]untitled [p.126]untitled [pp.126-127]untitled [pp.127-128]untitled [pp.128-129]untitled [p.129]untitled [pp.129-130]untitled [pp.130-131]untitled [p.131]untitled [pp.131-132]untitled [p.132]untitled [p.133]untitled [pp.133-134]untitled [p.134]untitled [pp.134-135]untitled [p.135]untitled [p.135]Book Notes [pp.135-142]Publications Received [pp.142- 146]The Profession: Reports and Opinion [pp.147-154]Back Matter