SlideShare a Scribd company logo
1 of 85
The Uses of Neoliberalism
James Ferguson
Department of Anthropology, Stanford University;
[email protected]
Abstract: The term “neoliberalism” has come to be used in a
wide variety of partly overlapping
and partly contradictory ways. This essay seeks to clarify some
of the analytical and political
work that the term does in its different usages. It then goes on
to suggest that making an analytical
distinction between neoliberal “arts of government” and the
class-based ideological “project”
of neoliberalism can allow us to identify some surprising (and
perhaps hopeful) new forms of
politics that illustrate how fundamentally polyvalent neoliberal
mechanisms of government can
be. A range of empirical examples are discussed, mostly coming
from my recent work on social
policy and anti-poverty politics in southern Africa.
Keywords: neoliberalism, governmentality, South Africa, basic
income, poverty
In thinking about the rapidly expanding literature on
neoliberalism, I
am struck by how much of the critical scholarship on topic
arrives
in the end at the very same conclusion—a conclusion that might
be
expressed in its simplest form as: “neoliberalism is bad for poor
and
working people, therefore we must oppose it.” It is not that I
disagree
with this conclusion. On the contrary. But I sometimes wonder
why I
should bother to read one after another extended scholarly
analysis only
to reach, again and again, such an unsurprising conclusion.
This problem in recent progressive scholarship strikes me as
related
to a parallel problem in progressive politics more broadly. For
over
the last couple of decades, what we call “the Left” has come to
be
organized, in large part, around a project of resisting and
refusing
harmful new developments in the world. This is understandable,
since
so many new developments have indeed been highly
objectionable. But
it has left us with a politics largely defined by negation and
disdain,
and centered on what I will call “the antis.” Anti-globalization,
anti-
neoliberalism, anti-privatization, anti-imperialism, anti-Bush,
perhaps
even anti-capitalism—but always “anti”, not “pro”. This is good
enough,
perhaps, if one’s political goal is simply to denounce “the
system” and to
decry its current tendencies. And, indeed, some seem satisfied
with such
a politics. In my own disciplines of anthropology and African
Studies,
for instance, studies of state and development tend, with
depressing
predictability, to conclude (in tones of righteous indignation)
that the
rich are benefiting and the poor are getting screwed. The
powerless,
it seems, are getting the short end of the stick. This is not
exactly a
Antipode Vol. 41 No. S1 2009 ISSN 0066-4812, pp 166–184
doi: 10.1111/j.1467-8330.2009.00721.x
C© 2009 The Authors
Journal compilation C© 2009 Editorial Board of Antipode.
The Uses of Neoliberalism 167
surprising finding, of course (isn’t it precisely because they are
on the
losing end of things that we call them “powerless” in the first
place?).
Yet this sort of work styles itself as “critique”, and imagines
itself to be
very “political”.
But what if politics is really not about expressing indignation or
denouncing the powerful? What if it is, instead, about getting
what you
want? Then we progressives must ask: what do we want? This is
a
quite different question (and a far more difficult question) than:
what
are we against? What do we want? Such a question brings us
very
quickly to the question of government. Denunciatory analyses
often
treat government as the simple expression of power or
domination—
the implication apparently being that it is politically
objectionable that
people should be governed at all. But any realistic sort of
progressive
politics that would seek a serious answer to the question “what
do
we want?” will have to involve an exploration of the
contemporary
possibilities for developing genuinely progressive arts of
government.
In his 1979 lectures on neoliberalism (2008), Michel Foucault
famously spoke of the “absence of a socialist art of
government”, and the
historic failure of the left to develop an “autonomous
governmentality”
comparable to liberalism. Stated as starkly as this, the point is
no doubt
debatable. Various forms of democratic socialism and social
democracy
(including but not limited to the German case treated in the
lectures) may
perhaps leave us with a richer trove of governmental arts than
Foucault’s
very schematic account acknowledged, and the diverse histories
of
“unhappy symbiosis” of socialism with liberalism that he
referred to
parenthetically (2008:94n) may well have a greater originality
than
his analysis allowed. But what seems less open to dispute is that
any
program for governing from the left today faces an obstacle that
we
could describe (in Foucaultian terms) as a failure to develop
new arts
of government adequate to the challenges of our time. New
progressive
approaches to the problem of government are necessary, it now
seems
clear, because neither the governmental mechanisms, nor the
political
strategies of mobilization, that the left came to rely upon in the
twentieth
century (and which characterized, in different ways, both
socialist and
social democratic or “welfare state” regimes) are capable of
getting the
sort of traction that they once did. There are at least two
reasons for this
that are relevant both to my broader argument here, and to the
particular
topic of social assistance that I will address in the latter part of
this
article.
The first reason is the increasing prominence (especially in the
region
of my own special interest, Africa, but not only there) of urban
masses
who are not, and are not likely to become, formal wage
laborers. Such
people (variously, and inadequately, described as “the informal
sector”,
“the lumpen”, “the youth”, and so on) now constitute the
majority of the
population in many African cities, and a very substantial
proportion in
C© 2009 The Authors
Journal compilation C© 2009 Editorial Board of Antipode.
168 Antipode
much of the rest of the world, as Mike Davis (2007) has
recently pointed
out in his usual alarmist style. The twentieth-century social
democracies,
on the other hand (and still more so the state socialist regimes),
were
built on the putatively universal figure of “the worker”. The
Keynesian
welfare state, as we know, was founded on a pact between
capital and
organized labor, and the domain we have come to know as “the
social”
was constructed on the foundation of the able-bodied worker.
Indeed, the
list of those requiring “social” intervention (the elderly, the
infirm, the
child, the disabled, the dependent reproductive woman) sketches
a kind
of photographic negative of the figure of the wage-earning man.
Today,
however, the question of social assistance is transformed in
societies
where young, able-bodied men look in vain for work, and are as
much
in need of assistance as everyone else. A compact between
capital
and labor, meanwhile, even were it politically possible, risks
leaving
out most of the population. New approaches to distribution, and
new
approaches to the question of social assistance, will need to be
based
on a fundamental rethinking that gives a new prominence to
those hard-
to-categorize urban improvisers who have for so long been
relegated to
the margins both of society, and of social analysis.
The second challenge to progressive thought and politics that I
would
like to identify is the rise of what we might call transnational
forms of
government, and particularly of the philanthropic funding of
what we
used to call “the social”. Much has been written about the
governmental
role played by international organizations like the IMF and the
World Bank. But the last couple of decades have also seen an
explosion
in de facto government carried out by an extraordinary swarm of
NGOs,
voluntary organizations, and private foundations. The Gates
Foundation
in Mozambique, to take just one example,1 is carrying out a
wide range
of projects (in health, hygiene, education, sanitation, etc) that
looks
something like the twentieth century “social” of the social
welfare state.
But there is obviously a very different relation to the nation-
state here,
and to the national political arena. Social policy and nation-
state are, to
a very significant degree, decoupled, and we are only beginning
to find
ways to think about this.
More generally, technical prescriptions for “making poverty
history”
often seem almost irrelevant because they presume the central
actors
to be states—and certain sorts of states at that: well-financed,
bureaucratically capable, poverty-fighting states that resemble
nothing
so much as twentieth century European welfare states. Couldn’t
the
Democratic Republic of the Congo solve all its problems,
reformers
seems to say, if only its government would start to behave like
that of
Sweden? Well, maybe so, but it’s the sort of ahistorical and
asociological
formulation that is worse than useless. Yet what happens when
states of
the imagined, poverty-fighting kind are simply not present?
How can
poverty policy be effective where states are (as the political
scientists,
C© 2009 The Authors
Journal compilation C© 2009 Editorial Board of Antipode.
The Uses of Neoliberalism 169
rather misleadingly, say) “weak”, or even actively anti-
developmental?
Where financial capacity is tiny and needs are enormous? What
happens
when the key implementers of poverty policy are not national
states at
all, but transnational NGOs, or private transnational
foundations? What
would count as progressive politics here?
One response here—understandable in the wake of the
neoliberal
restructuring of recent decades—is to call for the reinstating of
old-style
developmental states, effectively undoing the neoliberal
transformations
of the 1980s and 1990s and going back to the 1970s. I am
skeptical
that this is an adequate response—partly because the supposedly
developmental states I know from the 1970s in Africa were
pretty
awful, and partly because I doubt that you can run history
backward
(as if you could just hit the rewind button and try again). The
world
has changed, and simply re-asserting Third World sovereignty
will
not get us very far in dealing with a fundamentally reconfigured
politico-spatial world order. Imperialism is undoubtedly alive
and
well. But I don’t think we have a good analysis of, say, the
Gates
Foundation, or the Soros Foundation, if we see them simply as
the
imperial tools of the global rich, undermining the sovereignty of
African
governments. It is much more complicated than that—and
perhaps
also more hopeful. Can we find ways of thinking creatively
about the
progressive possibilities (and not only the reactionary dangers)
of this
new terrain of transnational organization of funds, energies, and
affect?
Can we imagine new “arts of government” that might take
advantage of
(rather than simply denouncing or resisting) recent
transformations in
the spatial organization of government and social assistance?
Most broadly, can we engage with these new configurations of
governmental power in a way that goes beyond the politics of
denunciation, the politics of the “anti”? Can we develop new
ways
of thinking through the problem of government that are
genuinely
progressive, but that don’t take for granted the absolute solidity
or
centrality of those two figures of twentieth-century left common
sense:
the worker and the nation-state?
It is here that we have to look more carefully at the “arts of
government” that have so radically reconfigured the world in
the last few
decades, and I think we have to come up with something more
interesting
to say about them than just that we’re against them. With
respect to
poverty and social policy, for instance (my particular interest
here), it is
simply not the case (as is often suggested) that neoliberal
government
ignores poverty, or leaves it to “the market”. (Later in this
essay, I
will discuss a range of welfare-like interventions and social
payments
that coexist with—and may, in fact, be necessary complements
to—
neoliberal economic models.) At the same time, there is
sometimes room
(in part because of the political spaces opened up by
“democracy” as
the characteristic mode of legitimation of neoliberal regimes)
for social
C© 2009 The Authors
Journal compilation C© 2009 Editorial Board of Antipode.
170 Antipode
movements and pro-poor organizations to have some real
influence on
matters of “social policy”. (Hence my current interest in the
“Basic
Income Grant” (BIG) campaign in South Africa, which I’ll
discuss in a
moment.) To understand the political possibilities and dangers
that such
emergent phenomena contain, we will surely need empirical
research
on the actual political processes at work. But beyond this, there
is a
palpable need for conceptual work, for new and better ways of
thinking
about practices of government and how they might be linked in
new
ways to the aspirations and demands of the economically and
socially
marginalized people who constitute the majority of the
population in
much of the world.
It is in this spirit, then, that I want to consider what I am calling
“the uses of neoliberalism”. I begin with a consideration of
“uses” in
the literal sense of semantic usage, as the wide variation in the
way
the term is used forces some clarification before we can begin
to ask
some new questions that might bring to light the surprising
affinity of
some aspects of what we call “neoliberalism” with certain forms
of
progressive politics.
As even a cursory inspection reveals, there is huge variation in
the
way the word, “neoliberalism” is used in contemporary
scholarship. In
perhaps the strictest sense, neoliberalism refers to a
macroeconomic
doctrine (and is, in this sense, a true “-ism”). The key elements
of
the doctrine are variously described, but always include a
valorization
of private enterprise and suspicion of the state, along with what
is
sometimes called “free-market fetishism” and the advocacy of
tariff
elimination, currency deregulation, and the deployment of
“enterprise
models” that would allow the state itself to be “run like a
business”.
(See Peck 2008 for an illuminating review of the rise and
dissemination
of this doctrine.)
A related usage would have “neoliberalism” refer to a regime of
policies and practices associated with or claiming fealty to the
doctrine
referenced above. Such a regime of practice is obviously
different from
the doctrine itself. Indeed, as David Harvey (2005) has argued,
this
divergence is, in fact, necessary, since neoliberal doctrine, if
applied
consistently, implies a world that could never, in fact, exist
(which leads
Harvey to term it “utopian”). Rather than purely applying the
utopian
neoliberal doctrine, Harvey points out that dominant groups
around the
world have used neoliberal arguments to carry out what is in
fact a class
project. “Neoliberalism”, in this sense, has become the name for
a set of
highly interested public policies that have vastly enriched the
holders of
capital, while leading to increasing inequality, insecurity, loss
of public
services, and a general deterioration of quality of life for the
poor and
working classes.
But the policies of neoliberal states have often diverged from
neoliberal doctrine for other reasons as well—reasons which
have
C© 2009 The Authors
Journal compilation C© 2009 Editorial Board of Antipode.
The Uses of Neoliberalism 171
less to do with straightforward power grabs by the rich than
with
the contingencies of democratic politics. This no doubt helps to
account for the otherwise paradoxical fact that a number of
regimes
pursuing undoubtedly neoliberal macroeconomic policies have
also
seen substantial recent rises in social spending (examples
include India,
Brazil, and South Africa, among others). Neoliberal policy is
thus much
more complicated than a reading of neoliberal doctrine might
suggest.
Finally, it is perhaps worth mentioning, if only schematically,
some
other common uses of the term. One is as a sloppy synonym for
capitalism itself, or as a kind of shorthand for the world
economy and
its inequalities. In much current anthropological usage,
“neoliberalism”
appears in this way, as a kind of abstract causal force that
comes
in from outside (much as “the world system” was reckoned to
do at an earlier theoretical moment) to decimate local
livelihoods.
Another, more interesting, usage sees “neoliberalism” as the
name
of a broad, global cultural formation characteristic of a new era
of
“millennial capitalism”—a kind of global meta-culture,
characteristic
of our newly de-regulated, insecure, and speculative times (eg
Comaroff
and Comaroff 2000). And finally, “neoliberalism” can be
indexed to a
sort of “rationality” in the Foucauldian sense, linked less to
economic
dogmas or class projects than to specific mechanisms of
government,
and recognizable modes of creating subjects. (I will have more
to say
about this last usage shortly.)
It is, then, possible to identify many quite distinct referents for
the
same widely used term. This has some obvious dangers, of
course. There
is plainly a danger of simple confusion, since the meaning of
the term
can slip in the course of an argument being passed from author
to reader
(or, indeed, even in the course of an argument made by a single
author).
There is also another danger, only slightly less obvious, which
is that
such an all-encompassing entity can easily come to appear as a
kind
of gigantic, all-powerful first cause (as categories like
“Modernity” or
“Capitalism” have done before it)—that malevolent force that
causes
everything else to happen. This yields empty analysis (since to
say
that all our problems are caused by “neoliberalism” is really not
to say
much), and may also lead to an ineffectual politics—since all
one can do
with such a gigantic, malevolent “thing” as “neoliberalism”
conceived
in this way is to denounce it. (And that, the evidence suggests,
doesn’t
seem to do much good).
One response would be to stop using the word altogether. This
is
indeed very tempting. If the word is so ambiguous, perhaps we
should
just be careful to be more specific, and use less all-
encompassing terms.
When the term “neoliberalism” is used as imprecisely as it is in
many
texts, one is tempted to pencil one’s objections in the margins
as one
might in reading a student essay: “What do you mean by
‘neoliberalism’
here? Do you mean the liberalization of trade policies? Then
say
C© 2009 The Authors
Journal compilation C© 2009 Editorial Board of Antipode.
172 Antipode
so! Do you mean techniques of government that work through
the
creation of responsibilized citizen-subjects? Then say that! The
two
don’t necessarily go together. Say what you mean, and don’t
presume
that they are all united in some giant package called
‘neoliberalism’.”
Such insistence on specificity and precision would undoubtedly
improve
the analytical clarity of many of our discussions.
But there is also some utility in words that bring together more
than
one meaning. As long as we can avoid the mistake of simply
confusing
the different meanings, the word can be an occasion for
reflecting on how
the rather different things to which it refers may be related. In
particular,
I would like to use this confusing, conflating word as an
occasion for
thinking about the relation between the following two things:
First, we may consider the new governmental rationalities that
emerged through the Thatcher–Reagan assaults on the North
Atlantic,
post-war welfare state. Key here was the deployment of market
mechanisms and “enterprise” models to reform government,
restructure
the state, and pioneer new modes of government and
subjectification.
(See, eg, Barry, Osborne and Rose 1996; Rose 1999; Cruikshank
1999;
Miller and Rose 2008.) There is a clear analysis in this
literature of
what it is that distinguishes “neoliberalism” from liberalism.
Liberalism,
in this account, was always about finding the right balance
between
two spheres understood as properly distinct, if always related:
state
and market, public and private, the realm of the king and the
proper
domain of the merchant. Neoliberalism, in contrast, puts
governmental
mechanisms developed in the private sphere to work within the
state
itself, so that even core functions of the state are either
subcontracted
out to private providers, or run (as the saying has it) “like a
business”.
The question of what should be public and what private
becomes blurred,
as the state itself increasingly organizes itself around “profit
centers”,
“enterprise models”, and so on. Rather than shifting the line
between
state and market, then, neoliberalism in this account involved
the
deployment of new, market-based techniques of government
within the
terrain of the state itself. At the same time, new constructions
of “active”
and “responsible” citizens and communities are deployed to
produce
governmental results that do not depend on direct state
intervention.
The “responsibilized” citizen comes to operate as a miniature
firm,
responding to incentives, rationally assessing risks, and
prudently
choosing from among different courses of action.
Against this understanding of the neoliberal, consider what we
might call neoliberalism in the African sense. Here,
neoliberalism has
meant first of all the policy measures that were forced on
African
states in the 1980s by banks and international lending agencies,
under
the name of “structural adjustment”. Reforms focused on
removing
tariffs, deregulating currency markets, and removing the state
from
production and distribution (via dismantling of state marketing
boards
C© 2009 The Authors
Journal compilation C© 2009 Editorial Board of Antipode.
The Uses of Neoliberalism 173
and parastatals). This did involve privatization, and an
ideological
celebration of markets. But the development of new
technologies of
government, responsibilized prudential subjects, and so on (all
the things
that Nikolas Rose and other “Anglo-Foucauldians” tend to
emphasize)
was very limited. Neoliberalism here was (in these terms) not
very “neo”
at all. It was, in fact, largely a matter of old-style laissez-faire
liberalism
in the service of imperial capital. And it had disastrous and
wildly
unpopular results (especially, the selling off of precious state
assets
to foreign firms at fire-sale prices, massive deindustrialization,
and
increased unemployment). Across much of the continent, it has
raised
the specter of a kind of recolonization. The result is that
“neoliberalism”
in Africa refers to a quite fundamentally different situation than
it
does in Western Europe and North America. The hasty and
uncritical
application of ideas of neoliberalism-as-rationality to Africa is
thus
clearly a mistake, based on a simple confusion (an art of
government
versus a crude battering open of Third World markets).
But bringing these two different referents together can be more
interesting, if we don’t just equate them, but instead reflect on
the conceptual themes they share (broadly, a technical reliance
on
market mechanisms coupled with an ideological valorization of
“private
enterprise” and a suspicion of the state), and use such a
reflection
to ask if the new “arts of government” developed within First
World
neoliberalism might take on new life in other contexts, in the
process
opening up new political possibilities.
Can we on the left do what the right has, in recent decades,
done
so successfully, that is, to develop new modes and mechanisms
of
government? And (perhaps more provocatively) are the
neoliberal “arts
of government” that have transformed the way that states work
in so
many places around the world inherently and necessarily
conservative,
or can they be put to different uses? To ask such questions
requires us
to be willing at least to imagine the possibility of a truly
progressive
politics that would also draw on governmental mechanisms that
we have
become used to terming “neoliberal”.
I have been led to these questions by my current interest in anti-
poverty programs in southern Africa that seek to provide cash
support
for incomes, and thus (in theory) harness markets to the task of
meeting the needs of the poor. This is happening in several
African
countries, but also in a great many other postcolonial states—
from
Brazil and Venezuela to Mexico and Bangladesh—where leftist
and
rightist regimes alike have seen fit to introduce policies that
transfer
cash directly into the hands of the poor. (See Fiszbein and
Schady
2009; Standing 2008 [2007] for reviews.) The South African
Basic
Income Grant campaign is the example I will explore here. The
proposal, which I will discuss in some detail shortly, is to deal
with
a crisis of persistent poverty by providing an unconditional
minimum
C© 2009 The Authors
Journal compilation C© 2009 Editorial Board of Antipode.
174 Antipode
monthly payment to all. The argument goes like this: markets
aren’t
working for poor people because they’re too poor to participate
in them;
government programs aren’t working because the state is
inefficient.
So, provide income support directly, in the form of cash, and
then say
to the poor: “you are now empowered to solve your own
problems
in the way you see best”. In contrast to older forms of “welfare”
assistance, the claim is that such grants rely on poor people’s
own
ability to solve their own problems, without imposing the
policing,
paternalism, and surveillance of the traditional welfare state.
More
broadly, similar new lines of thought are calling for an
increased role
for direct cash transfers in many forms of social and
humanitarian
policy (eg famine relief, which will be briefly discussed
shortly).
The reasoning here often includes recognizably neoliberal
elements,
including the valorization of market efficiency, individual
choice, and
autonomy; themes of entrepreneurship; and skepticism about the
state
as a service provider. But the politics are avowedly (and, I
think, on
balance, genuinely) “pro-poor” (as the phrase has it). “Pro-
poor” and
neoliberal—it is the strangeness of this conjunction that is of
interest
here. For the sorts of new progressive initiatives I have in mind
seem
to involve not just opposing “the neoliberal project”, but
appropriating
key elements of neoliberal reasoning for different ends. We
can’t think
about this (or even acknowledge its possibility) if we continue
to treat
“neoliberal” simply as a synonym for “evil”. Instead, I suggest
(and
this is a deliberate provocation) that some innovative (and
possible
effective) forms of new politics in these times may be showing
us how
fundamentally polyvalent the neoliberal arts of government can
be.
Let me emphasize that to say that certain political initiatives
and
programs borrow from the neoliberal bag of tricks doesn’t mean
that
these political projects are in league with the ideological project
of
neoliberalism (in David Harvey’s sense)—only that they
appropriate
certain characteristic neoliberal “moves” (and I think of these
discursive
and programmatic moves as analogous to the moves one might
make
in a game). These moves are recognizable enough to look
“neoliberal”,
but they can, I suggest, be used for quite different purposes than
that
term usually implies. In this connection, one might think of
statistical
techniques for calculating the probabilities of workplace
injuries. These
were originally developed in the nineteenth century by large
employers
to control costs (Ewald 1986), but they eventually became the
technical
basis for social insurance, and ultimately for the welfare state
(which
brought unprecedented gains to the working class across much
of the
world). Techniques, that is to say, can “migrate” across
strategic camps,
and devices of government that were invented to serve one
purpose
have often enough ended up, though history’s irony, being
harnessed to
another. Might we see a similar re-appropriation of “market”
techniques
of government (which were, like workplace statistics,
undoubtedly
C© 2009 The Authors
Journal compilation C© 2009 Editorial Board of Antipode.
The Uses of Neoliberalism 175
conservative in their original uses) for different, and more
progressive
sorts of ends? Maybe not—one should remain genuinely open-
minded
about this—but it is perhaps worth at least considering. Let me
present
two empirical examples from southern Africa as a way of
making this
proposition perhaps a bit more plausible.
Basic Income
My principal example is the basic income grant (BIG) campaign
in
South Africa. For historical reasons, South Africa came to
democratic
independence in 1994 with a quite well developed system of
social
grants and pensions (which I am not able to describe here for
reasons of
space). In recent years, as neoliberal restructuring has led to
widening
inequality and very high rates of unemployment, these social
grants
have substantially expanded, and have been instrumental in
holding
together what might otherwise be an explosive situation (a fact
of which
the ANC government appears to be acutely aware). But planners
have
been bothered by the patchy and arbitrary spread of the
coverage, and
the inefficiency and cost of administering a host of cumbersome
and
bureaucratic targeted programs.
It is in this context that proposals emerged for a far-reaching
new
comprehensive system of income support, anchored by a BIG to
be
paid to all South Africans (Department of Social Development
2002).
The idea of a BIG was first put forward by the labor union
federation,
COSATU, in 1998, and it acquired new legitimacy when it was
embraced
in 2002 by a government-appointed committee (the Taylor
Committee)
charged with recommending measures for the rationalization of
the
system of social assistance (see Barchiesi 2007; Department of
Social
Development 2002; Ferguson 2007; Tilton 2005). The proposal
has been
advocated from 2001 onward by a formal coalition of church
groups and
labor, the BIG Coalition).2
The proposal was for a modest payment of about R100 (at that
time,
about $16) per person per month, to be paid to all South
Africans,
irrespective of age or income. Advocates insist that a universal
system
of direct payments is by far the most efficient way to direct
assistance
to all poor South Africans. Means testing, in their view, would
not
be necessary; better off South Africans would also receive the
grant, but
the funds they received (and then some) would be recuperated
through
the tax system. Economic analyses prepared by BIG advocates
(eg
Standing and Samson 2003) argue that the measure could be
funded
through increases in either the income tax or the VAT, as well
as by
savings created by rationalizing the existing system of pensions.
The
idea of a BIG has been supported by church groups, NGOs, and
the
powerful Congress of South African Trade Unions (COSATU);
and
a watered down version has even been endorsed by the main
(and
historically white) opposition party, the Democratic Alliance.
The ruling
C© 2009 The Authors
Journal compilation C© 2009 Editorial Board of Antipode.
176 Antipode
ANC, however, has thus far rejected the plan, though it does
enjoy
support from at least some key players within the party
(including the
Minster for Social Development, Dr Zola Skweyiya).
The BIG campaign is significant not only as an interesting and
potentially progressive policy proposal, but also as an
illustration of
some new ways of thinking about questions of poverty and
welfare that
bring neoliberal themes to bear on the question of social
assistance in
ways that are very different from those we have become
accustomed to
in the last few decades. I begin by acknowledging that the
arguments for
a basic income grant in South Africa have been many sided and
complex,
and they are not reducible to a single logic or rationality
(neoliberal or
otherwise). Older languages of social democracy and solidarity
continue
to have significant currency, and a reading of pro-BIG
documents shows
that traditional welfare-state arguments are regularly deployed.
These
include themes of social solidarity and moral obligation; the
advantages
of social cohesion and dangers of class war; Keynesian
arguments about
stimulating demand; and labor-rights arguments about giving
workers
the security to say no to dangerous and demeaning work.3 Yet
these
lines of argument lie side by side with others, which are
markedly
different from social democratic reasoning, and surprisingly
similar
to the neoliberal rationality that we more usually associate with
anti-
welfare discourses. The intermingling of these different themes
speaks
to the complex political struggles around the BIG, which have
been
discussed by others (eg Mattisonn and Seekings 2003; Barchiesi
2007).
My interest here, though, is not in analyzing these politics, but
in
identifying some surprising ways in which certain discursive
“moves”
that we can readily identify as neoliberal are being put to work
in the
service of apparently pro-poor and pro-welfare political
arguments. To
make this process visible, it is useful to pull some of these
neoliberal
“moves” out of the broader mix of BIG arguments so that we
can see the
work that they are doing. (Note that the following is a highly
condensed
summary. For a more detailed analysis that includes citations of
specific
texts, see Ferguson 2007.)
One of the most important themes in arguments in favor of a
BIG
is the idea of “investment in human capital”. A BIG, supporters
say,
would enable poor South Africans to increase their spending on
such
things as nutrition, education, and health care. And this,
advocates insist,
should be understood as an “investment” in a kind of “capital”.
Such
“investment”, they insist, will bring handsome returns, in the
form of
productivity gains. The poor individual is in this way
conceived, in
classic neoliberal fashion, as a kind of micro-enterprise, earning
a rate
of return on invested capital.
More surprising is the way that pro-BIG arguments neatly
reverse
the usual right-wing arguments against social payments by
insisting
that basic income can be justified precisely as a way of
combating
C© 2009 The Authors
Journal compilation C© 2009 Editorial Board of Antipode.
The Uses of Neoliberalism 177
“dependency”. The existing “safety net”, the BIG promoters
argue,
relies on very destructive forms of dependency, since any
economically
productive poor person is surrounded by relatives and other
dependents
who must be supported. This is destructive, in economic terms,
because
it constitutes an effective “tax” on the productivity of the poor.
The
worker whose wages are soaked up by dependents in this way
suffers
from both a disincentive to work, and a drag on his or her
ability
to build up human capital. The “dependency” of absolute
poverty in
this way hurts productivity, and also makes it hard for workers
to
be economically active, to search for better jobs, etc. The
passivity
associated with this predicament, moreover, inhibits
entrepreneurship
and “risk-taking behaviors”. Providing basic income security
for all, it is
claimed, will enable the poor to behave as proper neoliberal
subjects (ie
as entrepreneurs and risk takers); the status quo prevents it, and
promotes
“dependency”. In this way, the BIG would provide not a “safety
net”
(the circus image of old-style welfare as protection against
hazard) but
a “springboard”—a facilitator of risky (but presumably
empowering)
neoliberal flight.
Equally striking is the way that basic income arguments
appropriate
neoliberal critiques of welfare paternalism and put them in the
service of
a pro-welfare argument. Echoing the old Margaret Thatcher
complaint
about the “nanny state” that tries to run everybody’s life in the
name
of the needs of “society”, BIG advocates point out that South
Africa’s
existing social assistance system makes moralizing judgments
about
“the undeserving poor”, and requires (at great expense) the
surveillance
and normalization of grant recipients, who are publicly labeled
as such,
and thus potentially stigmatized. In contrast to all this, the BIG
would
be paid to everyone; citizens would access their funds (in the
ideal
scheme) by simply swiping their national identity cards at at
automatic
cash dispenser. They would not need the government to tell
them how
to spend the funds. They would use them (like good rational
actors) in
the way they saw best. There would be no “nanny state”: no
policing of
conduct, no stigmatizing labels, no social workers coming into
homes—
and no costly bureaucracy to sort out who does or doesn’t
qualify. Grant
recipients, in this vision, appear as sensible people who know
their
problems and predicaments better than any bureaucrat could.
The state,
meanwhile, appears as both omnipresent and minimal—
universally
engaged (as a kind of direct provider for each and every citizen)
and
maximally disengaged (taking no real interest in shaping the
conduct
of those under its care, who are seen as knowing their own
needs better
than the state does).
Finally, the most radical shift from traditional social democracy
visible in the arguments for a BIG is the explicit rejection of
formal
employment as the “normal” frame of reference for social
policy
(let alone as an entitlement to which all have rights). The 2002
Taylor
C© 2009 The Authors
Journal compilation C© 2009 Editorial Board of Antipode.
178 Antipode
Committee Report projected that, even with strong economic
growth,
formal sector employment in South Africa was not likely to
expand at the
sort of rate that would be necessary for anything close to full
employment
(a prediction that recent developments have certainly borne
out). On
the contrary, it forecast that developing countries like South
Africa
were likely, over the long term, to see an inexorable shift away
from
(and not toward) formal employment. According to the report:
In developing countries, where stable full-time waged formal
sector
labour was never the norm, it is increasingly unlikely that it
will
become the norm (Department of Social Development 2002:38).
The reality is that in the developing world formal sector
employment
may never become the norm that it is in Europe (ibid 2002:154).
The need for assistance, then, is not about being “between jobs”
or
correcting for dips in the business cycle; it is part of a world in
which
many, or even most, people, for the foreseeable future, will lack
formal
sector employment. Social assistance is here radically
decoupled from
expectations of employment, and, indeed, from “insurance”
rationality
altogether. Instead, the Taylor Committee Report re-understands
the
condition of unemployment not as a hazard, but as the normal
condition.
Yet unemployment, in this understanding, need not imply
idleness
or a lack of productivity. On the contrary, in a world where
livelihoods
in the “informal economy” will become increasingly important,
small
expenditures on minimum income support (like the BIG) can
have
big payoffs in enabling and enhancing economic action in that
domain. Social payments, in this optic, are most significant not
as
temporary substitutes for employment, but as a way of
promoting greater
productivity, enterprise, and risk-taking in the “informal”
domain within
which more and more South Africans are expected to make their
living.
I hope to have identified some recognizably neoliberal motifs
here.
But I hope it is also clear that this is not the neoliberalism we
love
to hate, the so-called “neoliberal project” identified by Harvey
(2005).
It’s something else—a set of much harder to place arguments
that link
markets, enterprise, welfare, and social payments in a novel
way. It
leaves us neither with something to hate, nor something to love,
but
rather something to ponder. I will return to the question of the
perils and
promise of the BIG in the conclusion to this article, but for the
moment,
let us try to hold in our minds the apparently paradoxical idea
that a
major policy initiative might be, all at once, “pro-poor”,
redistributive,
and neoliberal.
Food Aid and Cash Transfers
It may be helpful to briefly discuss one additional example, to
help
suggest something I am increasingly convinced is the case: that
the BIG
C© 2009 The Authors
Journal compilation C© 2009 Editorial Board of Antipode.
The Uses of Neoliberalism 179
campaign is part of a much wider, worldwide shift in thinking
about
poverty and social and humanitarian assistance. The example I
have in
mind is the increasingly influential argument that hunger is best
dealt
with by boosting the purchasing power of those at risk, rather
than by
distributing in-kind food aid.
The current international food aid system is based on the
subsidized
overproduction of agricultural crops (especially grain) in rich
countries
like the USA. Food aid programs then take this surplus grain
and
transport it to places (largely in Africa) where it is distributed
to
people who are at risk of hunger due to drought, natural
disasters,
political violence, or other sorts of humanitarian emergency.
Critics like
Amartya Sen have long noted the (largely unintended) negative
impacts
of such policies, which tend to depress producer prices for local
farmers,
while damaging local institutions for producing and distributing
food
crops. Once food aid has arrived, local food production may
never
recover. Too often, what was supposed to be a “temporary”
crisis
becomes a long-term decline in food self-sufficiency (see, eg
Sen 1983;
Dreze and Sen 1991).
As an alternative, Sen’s followers have pushed for cash
payments to
be made directly to those at risk of food deficit (either via
employment
guarantees, or through direct cash transfers). People with money
in
their pockets, these advocates point out, usually don’t starve.
And cash
support allows famine victims to preserve or restore productive
assets
(eg livestock) in ways that simply supplying a certain number of
calories
does not. What is more, the economic chain of events that is set
in motion
by boosting purchasing power not only avoids the destructive
effects of
food aid, but creates a virtuous cycle, in which market forces
lead to
increased capacity for local production and distribution. A
number of
pilot projects have been launched putting these principles into
practice
in recent years. Among the best known is the Cash for Relief
Programme
in Ethiopia, which used cash payments to enable households
that had
been hit by crop failure to rebuild their assets and regenerate
their
livelihoods, and not only to eat (USAID/OFDA 2004). Another
widely
discussed project has been the Kalomo Social Cash Transfer
Scheme
in Zambia. Here, too, cash took the place of food aid, with the
result
that recipients were able to meet non-nutritional as well as
nutritional
needs, including education, transportation, and health care
(Schubert and
Goldberg 2004). An impressive range of similar projects are
reviewed
in Standing (2008 [2007]) and Farrington and Slater (2006).
(See also
the review of the potential for cash transfers in “unstable
situations” that
was recently done by Harvey and Holmes (2007) for the UK
Department
for International Development.)
The arguments made by the increasingly numerous promoters of
such programs are in many ways similar to those made on
behalf of
the South African BIG. Dispensing cash, they insist, is in the
first
C© 2009 The Authors
Journal compilation C© 2009 Editorial Board of Antipode.
180 Antipode
place more efficient and less expensive than other sorts of
assistance,
and often requires less infrastructure and institutional capacity.
In any
case, they argue, why should bureaucrats decide on behalf of
recipients
what their needs are? Cash transfers provide hungry people with
the
flexibility to access a broad range of goods and services
available on
the market to meet their needs. And poor people, in this
conception,
are good judges of how to do that—using money to go to the
clinic
this month, to pay school fees for a child the next, to buy a bag
of maize meal the next, and so on. Rather than wasting the
money
on frivolous expenditure, advocates insist, recipients generally
apply
their scant cash resources very rationally, and even make canny
small
investments. As one PowerPoint presentation on the Kalomo
project put
it: “The ‘grannies’ turned out to be excellent economists!”
Top-down, state-planned attempts to directly meet nutritional
needs
through trucking in food, in this view, are bound to be clumsy,
inefficient,
and wasteful. Cash transfers, on the other hand, put more
decision-
making power in the hands of those who know their predicament
best—the hunger afflicted—and empower them to use the
flexibility
and efficiency of markets to help solve their own problems.
Unlike
direct food aid, cash transfers can have a catalytic effect on
many
other income-gaining activities, thereby contributing powerfully
to the
“multiple livelihood strategies” that are so important in keeping
the
poorest households afloat.
Such arguments recall Jane Guyer’s (1989) groundbreaking
work on
feeding African cities. Consider, Guyer suggests, how food ends
up
finding its way to consumers’ plates in the vast megacities of
West
Africa such as Lagos. The logistical task of moving thousands
of tons
of food each day from thousands of local producers to millions
of urban
consumers would be beyond the organizational capacity of any
state
(to say nothing of the less-than-exemplary Nigerian one). Here,
market
mechanisms, drawing on the power of vast self-organizing
networks,
are very powerful, and very efficient. Such forms of
organization
must appear especially attractive where states lack capacity
(and let
us remember how many progressive dreams in Africa have
crashed on
the rocks of low state capacity).
Why should relying on this sort of mechanism be inherently
right-
wing, or suspect in the eyes of progressives? The answer is, of
course,
not far to find: markets serve only those with purchasing power.
Market-
based solutions are thus likely to be true “solutions” only for
the better-
off, whose needs are so effectively catered to by markets. But
the food
aid example shows a way of redirecting markets toward the
poor, by
intervening not to restrict the market, but to boost purchasing
power.
I have become convinced that (at least in the case of food aid)
this is
probably good public policy. Is it also neoliberal? Perhaps that
is not
the right question. Perhaps we should rather ask: are there
specific sorts
C© 2009 The Authors
Journal compilation C© 2009 Editorial Board of Antipode.
The Uses of Neoliberalism 181
of social policy that might draw on characteristic neoliberal
“moves”
(like using markets to deliver services) that would also be
genuinely
progressive? That seems like a question worth asking, even if
we are at
this point not fully ready to answer it.
Let me be clear that none of the examples discussed here are (in
my view) unequivocally good (or unequivocally bad, for that
matter).
Instead, they leave us feeling uneasy, unsure of our moorings.
They
leave us less with strong opinions than with the sense that we
need to
think about them a bit more. They do not permit the simple
denunciations
(Aha! Neoliberalism!) that have become so familiar a part of the
politics
of the “anti-”, even as they clearly require us to turn a
thoughtfully critical
and skeptical eye toward their dangers and ambiguities.
I also want to emphasize as clearly as possible that none of
these
examples is a matter of “leaving it to the market”. All require
major
non-market interventions (either by states or by state-like
entities such
as foundations or international agencies), and all are premised
on the
principle that public policy must play a major redistributive
role. But
they are interventions that create a situation where markets can
arguably
serve progressive ends, in ways that may require us to revise
some of
our prejudices that automatically associate market mechanisms
with the
interests of the well-to-do.
The Point is to Change It!
If we are seeking, as this special issue of Antipode aspires to
do, to link
our critical analyses to the world of grounded political
struggle—not
only to interpret the world in various ways, but also to change
it—then
there is much to be said for focusing, as I have here, on
mundane, real-
world debates around policy and politics, even if doing so
inevitably puts
us on the compromised and reformist terrain of the possible,
rather than
the seductive high ground of revolutionary ideals and utopian
desires.
But I would also insist that there is more at stake in the
examples I
have discussed here than simply a slightly better way to
ameliorate the
miseries of the chronically poor, or a technically superior
method for
relieving the suffering of famine victims.
My point in discussing the South African BIG campaign, for
instance,
is not really to argue for its implementation. There is much in
the
campaign that is appealing, to be sure. But one can just as
easily identify
a series of worries that would bring the whole proposal into
doubt. Does
not, for instance, the decoupling of the question of assistance
from the
issue of labor, and the associated valorization of the “informal”,
help
provide a kind of alibi for the failures of the South African
regime to
pursue policies that would do more to create jobs? Would not
the creation
of a basic income benefit tied to national citizenship simply
exacerbate
the vicious xenophobia that already divides the South African
poor,
C© 2009 The Authors
Journal compilation C© 2009 Editorial Board of Antipode.
182 Antipode
in a context where many of the poorest are not citizens, and
would
thus not be eligible for the BIG? Perhaps even more
fundamentally,
is the idea of basic income really capable of commanding the
mass
support that alone could make it a central pillar of a new
approach to
distribution? The record to date gives powerful reasons to doubt
it. So
far, the technocrats’ dreams of relieving poverty through
efficient cash
transfers have attracted little support from actual poor people,
who seem
to find that vision a bit pale and washed out, compared with the
vivid
(if vague) populist promises of jobs and personalistic social
inclusion
long offered by the ANC patronage machine, and lately
personified by
Jacob Zuma (Ferguson forthcoming).
My real interest in the policy proposals discussed here, in fact,
has
little to do with the narrow policy questions to which they seek
to provide
answers. For what is most significant, for my purposes, is not
whether
or not these are good policies, but the way that they illustrate a
process
through which specific governmental devices and modes of
reasoning
that we have become used to associating with a very particular
(and
conservative) political agenda (“neoliberalism”) may be in the
process
of being peeled away from that agenda, and put to very different
uses.
Any progressive who takes seriously the challenge I pointed to
at the
start of this essay, the challenge of developing new progressive
arts of
government, ought to find this turn of events of considerable
interest.
As Steven Collier (2005) has recently pointed out, it is
important to
question the assumption that there is, or must be, a neat or
automatic fit
between a hegemonic “neoliberal” political-economic project
(however
that might be characterized), on the one hand, and specific
“neoliberal”
techniques, on the other. Close attention to particular
techniques
(such as the use of quantitative calculation, free choice, and
price
driven by supply and demand) in particular settings (in Collier’s
case,
fiscal and budgetary reform in post-Soviet Russia) shows that
the
relationship between the technical and the political-economic
“is much
more polymorphous and unstable than is assumed in much
critical
geographical work”, and that neoliberal technical mechanisms
are in
fact “deployed in relation to diverse political projects and social
norms”
(2005:2).
As I suggested in referencing the role of statistics and
techniques for
pooling risk in the creation of social democratic welfare states,
social
technologies need not have any essential or eternal loyalty to
the political
formations within which they were first developed. Insurance
rationality
at the end of the nineteenth century had no essential vocation to
provide
security and solidarity to the working class; it was turned to
that purpose
(in some substantial measure) because it was available, in the
right place
at the right time, to be appropriated for that use. Specific ways
of solving
or posing governmental problems, specific institutional and
intellectual
mechanisms, can be combined in an almost infinite variety of
ways, to
C© 2009 The Authors
Journal compilation C© 2009 Editorial Board of Antipode.
The Uses of Neoliberalism 183
accomplish different social ends. With social, as with any other
sort of
technology, it is not the machines or the mechanisms that decide
what
they will be used to do.
Foucault (2008:94) concluded his discussion of socialist
government-
ality by insisting that the answers to the Left’s governmental
problems
require not yet another search through our sacred texts, but a
process of
conceptual and institutional innovation. “[I]f there is a really
socialist
governmentality, then it is not hidden within socialism and its
texts. It
cannot be deduced from them. It must be invented”. But
invention in
the domain of governmental technique is rarely something
worked up
out of whole cloth. More often, it involves a kind of bricolage
(Lévi-
Strauss 1966), a piecing together of something new out of
scavenged
parts originally intended for some other purpose. As we pursue
such
a process of improvisatory invention, we might begin by making
an
inventory of the parts available for such tinkering, keeping all
the while
an open mind about how different mechanisms might be put to
work, and
what kinds of purposes they might serve. If we can go beyond
seeing in
“neoliberalism” an evil essence or an automatic unity, and
instead learn
to see a field of specific governmental techniques, we may be
surprised
to find that some of them can be repurposed, and put to work in
the
service of political projects very different from those usually
associated
with that word. If so, we may find that the cabinet of
governmental arts
available to us is a bit less bare than first appeared, and that
some rather
useful little mechanisms may be nearer to hand than we thought.
Endnotes
1 I refer here to the remarkable PhD research now being carried
out by Ramah McKay
(Department of Anthropology, Stanford University).
2 Barchiesi (2007) gives a detailed and illuminating account of
the origins of the BIG
campaign and the Taylor Committee report.
3 As Barchiesi (2007) noted, some more conservative
formulations of the BIG campaign
have also made the contrary argument, that it would help move
unemployed people into
very low wage jobs. He also points out another important theme
that I do not explore
here: the implicit or explicit moralism of much of the discussion
around “the social
question” in South Africa.
References
Barchiesi F (2007) South African debates on the Basic Income
Grant: Wage labour and
the post-apartheid social policy. Journal of Southern African
Studies 33(3):561–575
Barry A, Osborne T and Rose N (eds.) (1996) Foucault and
Political Reason: Liberalism,
Neo-liberalism and Rationalities of Government. Chicago:
University of Chicago
Press
Collier S (2005) The Spatial Forms and Social Norms of
“Actually Existing
Neoliberalism”: Toward a Substantive Analytics. International
Affairs Working Paper.
New York: New School University
C© 2009 The Authors
Journal compilation C© 2009 Editorial Board of Antipode.
184 Antipode
Comaroff J and Comaroff J (2000) Millennial capitalism: First
thoughts on a second
coming. Public Culture 12(2):291–343
Cruikshank B (1999) The Will to Empower: Democratic
Citizens and Other Subject.
Ithaca: Cornell University Press
Davis M (2007) Planet of Slums. New York: Verso
Department of Social Development (2002) Transforming the
Present—Protecting the
Future: Report of the Committee of Inquiry into a
Comprehensive System of Social
Security for South Africa. Pretoria: Government Printer
Dreze J and Sen A (1991) Hunger and Public Action. New York:
Oxford University
Press
Ewald F (1986) L’etat Providence. Paris: Bernard Grasset
Farrington J and Slater R (2006) Cash transfers: Panacea for
poverty reduction or money
down the drain? Development Policy Review 24(5):499–511
Ferguson J (2007) Formalities of poverty: Thinking about social
assistance in neoliberal
South Africa. African Studies Review 50(2):71–86
Ferguson J (forthcoming) Declarations of dependence: Labor,
personhood, and welfare
in South Africa
Fiszbein A and Schady N (2009) Conditional Cash Transfers:
Reducing Present and
Future Poverty. Washington DC: The World Bank
Foucault M (2008) The Birth of Biopolitics: Lectures at the
College de France, 1978–
1979. Translated by Graham Burchell. New York: Palgrave
MacMillan
Guyer J (ed) (1989) Feeding African Cities: Studies in Regional
Social History.
Manchester: Manchester University Press
Harvey D (2005) A Brief History of Neoliberalism. New York:
Oxford University Press
Harvey P and Holmes R (2007) The Potential for Joint
Programmes for Long-term Cash
Transfers in Unstable Situations: A Report Commissioned by
the Fragile States Team
and the Equity and Rights Team of the UK Department for
International Development.
London: Humanitarian Policy Group, Overseas Development
Institute
Lévi-Strauss C (1966) The Savage Mind. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press
Mattisonn H and Seekings J (2003) The politics of a basic
income grant in South Africa,
1996–2002. In G Standing and M Samson (eds) A Basic Income
Grant for South
Africa (pp 56–76). Cape Town: University of Cape Town Press
Miller P and Rose N (2008) Governing the Present. Malden,
Massachusetts: Polity
Press
Peck J (2008) Remaking laissez-faire. Progress in Human
Geography 32(1):3–43
Rose N (1999) Powers of Freedom: Reframing Political
Thought. New York: Cambridge
University Press
Schubert B and Goldberg J (2004) The Pilot Social Cash
Transfer Scheme: Zambia.
Lusaka: GTZ (Deutsche Gesellschaft für Technische
Zusammenarbeit)
Sen A (1983) Poverty and Famines: An Essay on Entitlement
and Deprivation. New
York: Oxford University Press
Standing G (2008 [2007]) How Cash Transfers Boost Work and
Economic Security.
DESA Working Paper No. 50. New York: United Nations
Department of Economic
and Social Affairs
Standing G and Samson M (eds) (2003) A Basic Income Grant
for South Africa. Cape
Town: University of Cape Town Press
Tilton D (2005) BIG Fact Sheet #1,
http://www.big.org.za/index.php?option=articles&
task=viewarticle&artid=5 Accessed 11 September 2005
USAID/OFDA (2004) Evaluation of OFDA Cash for Relief
Intervention in Ethiopia.
Prepared by Robert H. Brandstetter. Washington DC: United
States Agency for
International Development (USAID)
C© 2009 The Authors
Journal compilation C© 2009 Editorial Board of Antipode.
Copyright of Antipode is the property of Wiley-Blackwell and
its content may not be copied or emailed to
multiple sites or posted to a listserv without the copyright
holder's express written permission. However, users
may print, download, or email articles for individual use.
The Case of Jesse Gelsinger
The Story
When Jesse Gelsinger was growing up in New Jersey, he was
diagnosed at the Children’s Hospital of Philadelphia with OTC
(ornithine transcarbamylase) deficiency, a rare genetic disorder
affecting about one of every eighty thousand babies. An OTC
deficiency means a person lacks an enzyme in liver cells that
converts the nitrogen, generated when the body absorbs protein,
into urea that can be excreted by the kidneys. Unless this
conversion occurs the nitrogen builds up in the blood as
excessive ammonia, and this causes neurological damage and
liver problems. Most babies with OTC deficiency die not long
after birth.
The genetic mutation that causes this problem is located on the
X chromosome. Women have two X chromosomes, so a
defective gene on one of them makes them carriers but with few
or no symptoms because their normal gene usually functions
well. Men, however, have only one X chromosome, so if they
happen to receive the defective X chromosome from their
mothers (a 50 percent chance), they inherit the life-threatening
OTC deficiency disease.
Jesse’s mother, however, was not a carrier. Doctors therefore
attributed his OTC deficiency to spontaneous mutations in some
of his liver cells. Hence, his OTC deficiency was mild and his
disease was manageable as long as he stayed on a low-protein
diet and took his medications.
In September 1998, when Jesse was seventeen and living in
Arizona with his father, Paul, and his stepmother, a physician
monitoring his disease at a metabolic clinic informed him and
his father that researchers at the University of Pennsylvania
were working on a clinical trial to see whether they could find a
cure for OTC deficiency. The physician described the trial as
“gene therapy.” The subject of the clinical trial and “gene
therapy” came up again during Jesse’s visit to the metabolic
clinic in April 1999. Both Jesse and Paul were interested in
pursuing it and, since the family was already planning a trip to
New Jersey in June, they agreed to visit the Institute for Human
Gene Therapy (IHGT) at the University of Pennsylvania to see
whether Jesse would be a candidate for the “gene therapy”
clinical trial, which was already under way.
The design of the clinical trial, titled “Recombinant Adenovirus
Gene Transfer in Adults with Partial Ornithine
Transcarbamylase Deficiency,” was relatively simple.
Researchers were engineering an adenovirus (which gives us
colds by working its way into our cells) so it would not
replicate once it invaded the liver cells. Then they inserted good
genes with the OTC capability into the altered virus and infused
the altered virus carrying the good genes into the liver.
Researchers hoped that the healthy genes in the liver would
soon produce enough OTC to overcome the deficiency and
prevent ammonia from building up in the body. At this point
researchers were conducting only a phase I trial, that is, a trial
to see how high a load of the OTC gene-bearing viruses they
could safely infuse into people’s livers without causing adverse
reactions.
For the phase I trial they were looking to recruit eighteen adults
who either had some OTC deficiency or who were carriers.
Originally researchers had hoped to try the experiment on
babies suffering from the OTC deficiency, but a well-known
ethicist who was then at the university, Arthur Caplan, had
raised objections to this plan. Caplan argued that the parents of
children dying from OTC deficiency would be so devastated
that many would agree to enroll their child in a clinical trial out
of desperation, and their informed consent would not be truly
voluntary. Moreover, the proposed trial was a phase I study
where the goal was not to evaluate a therapeutic benefit but to
see whether the intervention had unacceptable side effects, a
distinction that desperate parents might not well understand.
Researchers planned to divide the eighteen participants into
groups of three, with two women and one man in each group.
Their plan was to give the three people in the first group a low
dose of the altered virus and then monitor them for side effects
for at least three weeks. If all went well, they would give the
second group of three a higher dose of the altered virus and
monitor them for three weeks, then infuse the third group with
an even higher dose, and so forth. The women would receive the
virus first, and only if the dose did not cause adverse reactions
in them would the researchers give it to the man in the group,
who would be more seriously affected by the OTC deficiency.
Researchers were now nearing the end of the phase I clinical
study; Jesse would be the third member of the sixth group, the
last person to receive the altered virus.
In June 1999 Jesse and his father met with Dr. Steven Raper at
the University of Pennsylvania. Since Jesse turned eighteen that
month, he would be old enough to give voluntary informed
consent for the clinical trial. Raper, a surgeon involved with the
gene transfer trial, explained the procedure to him and his
father. He would insert a catheter into the artery leading to
Jesse’s liver and a second one into a vein leading from his liver.
He would put the modified adenovirus with the healthy genes
into the artery leading to the liver. Hopefully the virus with the
genes would invade liver cells and thus deliver the good genes.
A check of the blood in the vein leaving the liver would
indicate how much of the gene-bearing virus remained in the
liver. By measuring the viral input and output researchers could
determine whether the liver was absorbing the virus with the
good genes embedded in it. A week later they would do a needle
biopsy of the liver to confirm the results of the attempted gene
transfer.
Dr. Raper told Jesse that there were risks involved. He would
probably develop some flu-like symptoms after the infusion of
the virus and there was some small chance of hepatitis, which
he said could be treated. There was also a remote possibility
that Jesse might die from the liver biopsy (Dr. Raper told him
that the risk of death from a liver biopsy is about one in ten
thousand). Dr. Raper also made it clear that the clinical trial,
even if it worked as they hoped, would not reverse Jesse’s OTC
deficiency because his immune system would reject the virus
with the healthy genes in a matter of weeks. On the other hand,
if the gene transfer was successful, then it would be a big step
forward toward developing a genetic therapy for babies with the
OTC deficiency as well as for dozens of other genetic diseases
affecting the liver. Both Paul and Jesse agreed to participate if
tests showed that Jesse would be a good candidate for the
clinical trial.
A month later Dr. Mark Batshaw, another one of the physicians
conducting the study, wrote both Paul and Jesse in Arizona
about the clinical trial and then spoke with them by phone.
According to Paul Gelsinger, Dr. Batshaw said that the
treatment had worked temporarily in mice, even preventing
death when mice were injected with lethal doses of ammonia.
He also said that there were about twenty-five other liver
disorders affecting five hundred thousand people in the United
States and 12 million worldwide that could be treated with the
same technique if it worked and that a recent human participant
in the study had experienced a 50 percent increase in her ability
to excrete ammonia. In other words, the research was showing
signs of therapeutic value that could benefit millions of people.
This clinched it for Jesse and his father; they considered this
promising news and became excited about participating in the
“genetic therapy” research at IHGT.
The chief investigator in the study was Dr. James Wilson, the
head of the IHGT at the University of Pennsylvania. He had
become interested in developing genetic therapies for liver
diseases after reading about a well-known patient named
Stormie Jones, a young girl whose liver cells had a genetic
mutation that prevented the liver from removing LDL
cholesterol from the blood. This genetic defect allows high
levels of the dangerous LDL cholesterol (the “bad” cholesterol)
to develop in the body, and most patients suffering from it die
prematurely from heart attacks. Stormie was in imminent danger
of dying from very high LDL cholesterol levels when she
received a heart and liver transplant. The transplanted liver
began removing LDL from her blood stream and the healthy
transplanted heart gave her a new lease on life. Wilson began to
think it would be better for patients if a way could be found to
insert normal cells into their liver rather than transplanting a
liver.
In experiments on human participants, which began in 1992,
Wilson and other researchers surgically removed part of the
person’s liver, cultured cells from it in the laboratory, used
retroviruses to convey healthy genes into the DNA of these liver
cells, and then infused the modified cells back into the liver
through a catheter in the artery leading to the liver. Eighteen
months after performing the procedure on a twenty-eight-year-
old research subject, Wilson reported in 1994 that the genetic
intervention was safe and had successfully lowered the person’s
LDL level.
Wilson realized, however, that removing cells from a patient,
modifying them in vitro, and then putting them back into the
patient would have limited use in genetic therapy. A more
promising procedure would be the development of what he
called “injectable genes.” Doctors would be able to transfer
healthy genes directly into the body’s liver cells, perhaps by
viruses. If it worked, this would be an in vivo genetic therapy.
In animal experiments, Wilson was actually able to lower the
cholesterol level of rabbits by injecting healthy genes into their
bloodstream.
Wilson soon began working on another genetic disease of liver
cells, the OTC deficiency. He thought he could overcome this
deficiency by using modified viruses to carry healthy cells with
the OTC enzyme directly into the liver so there would be no
need to remove part of the liver and add the genes in the
laboratory. Scientists and biotech companies were watching his
work with great interest. If it worked many people could be
cured of diseases caused by deleterious mutations on the genes
in liver cells and biotech companies could make a lot of money
thanks to patent protection for the engineered viruses that could
reverse the diseases.
Jesse flew to Philadelphia on September 10, 1999. Dr. Raper
inserted the catheters on the following Monday, and a large
dose of the modified virus with the healthy genes flowed into
Jesse’s liver. As expected, Jesse suffered flu-like symptoms that
evening. Soon, however, things got worse. He spiked a high
fever and rapidly deteriorated. Before long he was in a coma, on
a ventilator, and receiving dialysis. Then he needed
extracorporeal membrane oxygenation. By Thursday he was so
bloated that his father hardly recognized him. On Friday
morning it was obvious that he had suffered massive brain
damage and that his organs were shutting down. After the
family gathered and a chaplain said a prayer, a doctor withdrew
the life support and Jesse was pronounced dead at 2:30 p.m.
An autopsy failed to identify the cause of the problem that led
to his death. Obviously the infusion of the altered viruses
caused a reaction that killed him, but doctors could not figure
out why. Paul Gelsinger, shocked over the loss of his son,
nonetheless supported the doctors and felt that they had done
the best they could.
The doctors at IHGT promised to conduct a complete
investigation and to inform Paul of everything they discovered.
About two months after Jesse’s funeral, Dr. Wilson, the head of
the Institute and the sponsor and chief investigator of the OTC
deficiency study, flew to Arizona and met with Paul Gelsinger.
He explained that Jesse’s death was totally unexpected and still
remained unexplained. He spoke of how important the work of
his IHGT was, and he sought Paul’s continued support. He
asked Paul to come to a three-day meeting of RAC in December
that would be reviewing the clinical trial. Paul agreed and flew
to Philadelphia where he visited Wilson’s IHGT and then drove
to Bethesda, Maryland, the next day for the RAC meetings.
As the RAC meeting progressed, however, Paul began to see
another side of the clinical trial that took the life of his son. He
heard FDA officials say that Jesse should not have been infused
with the virus because his ammonia level was too high at that
time. Originally candidates with blood ammonia levels of more
than 50 were not considered eligible to participate; later
researchers raised that level to 70. When Jesse arrived in
Philadelphia for the clinical procedure, his blood ammonia level
was 114, and NIH officials said that he should not have been
considered eligible for the trial. However, researchers had
lowered his level somewhat with medication before they infused
the virus.
Paul also learned that researchers had failed to report to the
FDA in a timely manner or to inform him and his son that some
earlier participants experienced significant side effects from the
viral infusions. He also learned that the informed consent form
that Jesse signed differed from the one the FDA had approved,
and it in fact omitted the important information that two
monkeys had died in animal studies after being given high doses
of the virus.
Paul now began to think that Jesse had signed the informed
consent form without being well informed about possible side
effects and risks. He also heard that the viral infusions had not
provided any clinically significant therapeutic impact on earlier
participants, something that raised questions in his mind about
Dr. Batshaw’s remarks that one woman achieved a 50 percent
gain in ammonia excretion. Based on that remark, both he and
Jesse had thought the research was showing some sign of
therapeutic advantage. Paul was also upset to learn that
researchers had not provided NIH, which funded the study, or
the FDA, which monitored it, or the IRB at the University that
oversaw it with other information in a timely manner, as was
required by federal regulations.
In remarks to reporters outside the RAC meeting Dr. Wilson
objected to the FDA criticisms. He insisted that no data from
either animal or human studies foretold that Jesse would die;
that the FDA was eventually told of the two participants who
experienced the side effects before Jesse was infused, yet it did
not stop the study; and that the ammonia level in Jesse’s liver
was functioning within the protocol parameters when he was
enrolled in the study three months before his infusion. Wilson,
however, did not respond to criticisms about the informed
consent form and he declined to take questions.
On February 14, 2000, the IHGT responded formally to FDA
criticisms and pointed out, among other things, that every
patient did give informed consent for the clinical trial; that the
two monkeys who died were in a genetic experiment for a
different problem, colorectal cancer; and that there was no
evidence that the high ammonia level in Jesse was a cause of his
death. However, these remarks still left important questions
unanswered. Simply because there is a record of informed
consent does not mean that the person actually had all the
information he needed to give informed consent. And the issue
about the two monkeys is not that they received a different gene
for a different problem but that they received a similar viral
vector to transport genes into their bodies. And it is true that
there is no evidence that Jesse’s high ammonia level caused his
death, but the point of the FDA criticism was that the approved
protocol did not allow researchers to infuse the virus into
participants with such high ammonia levels, and researchers are
expected to abide by the approved protocols.
After months of publicly supporting the doctors at the
university and their research despite the loss of his son, Paul
Gelsinger now became their critic and soon sought legal
redress. Before looking at what happened next, we consider the
case from an ethical point of view.
Ethical Analysis
Situational awareness. We are aware of the following facts in
the Gelsinger story:
1. When Jesse was seventeen, both he and his father heard of
some important “gene therapy” research at the University of
Pennsylvania for people suffering from OTC deficiency, a
genetic condition that takes the life of so many afflicted
children. He and his father were interested in participating in
the “gene therapy” research because they believed it might save
the lives of babies and might even lead to something down the
road that would help Jesse so he could eat a normal diet and not
need medications to control his condition. When he turned
eighteen, Jesse visited the Institute for Human Gene Therapy at
the University and consented to becoming a participant in the
phase I trial. According to his father, part of his reason was to
do something that would allow development of a genetic
therapy to help prevent future babies from being ravaged by the
deadly disease.
2. Unlike most children with OTC deficiency, Jesse’s disease
was controlled with medications and a low-protein diet.
However, the teenager found taking his medications was a
hassle. He did not always take them on schedule or stay on his
diet, and he suffered occasional relapses. Dealing with his
disease sometimes left him frustrated and angry. At one point,
he actually jumped out of his father’s vehicle in a fit of anger
while it was still moving, and his arm ended up under a wheel.
It is possible that Jesse hoped for a long shot—that enough
progress could be made so a genetic therapy might actually
benefit him by allowing him to go off his medications and enjoy
a normal diet.
3. Dr. James Wilson, chief of Molecular Medicine and Genetics
at the University of Pennsylvania and head of its Institute for
Human Gene Therapy, was a leading researcher in the field of
genetic research on liver diseases. Wilson thought it might be
possible to transfer healthy liver genes into patients.
4. Jesse was the eighteenth and last participant in the phase I
OTC deficiency clinical trial, and he would receive the highest
dose of the viral vector with the healthy genes.
5. NIH funded the clinical trial and the FDA approved it. The
FDA provided oversight and required progress reports,
especially about adverse reactions if they occurred. There was
some hesitation when the trial was first proposed because
putting large amounts (trillions) of viruses into people is risky
business. Viruses will trigger, and may overload, the immune
system even though the viruses have been engineered not to
replicate. Actually some earlier participants in the OTC trial did
experience some adverse effects that should have been reported
to the FDA, but the doctors did not inform the Gelsingers of
this.
6. Researchers at the University of Pennsylvania were also
doing animal studies that used adenoviruses to transfer genes.
Two monkeys in one experiment had died and a third became
ill, but the physicians did not inform the Gelsingers of these
deaths.
7. Inserting genes into a person’s body is a major challenge.
Genes are mostly in the nucleus of our cells, and there is much
we do not yet know about the DNA molecule that harbors them.
Viruses have the capability of getting into the DNA of our cells
(an adenovirus is what causes the common cold), so they are
promising vehicles for transferring genes. The trick, of course,
is to render the virus harmless and then use it to transport
healthy genes into the DNA of the cells.
8. Genetic research is more challenging than drug research
because we have to study not only the impact of the agent (the
altered genes) on the body but also the impact of the vehicle we
use to transfer the altered genes into the body. The vehicle, or
“vector” as it is called, is often a virus, and putting massive
doses of viruses into a person’s body even without any altered
genes can trigger or even overwhelm the immune system.
9. The Bayh–Dole Act of 1980 allows universities to patent
their discoveries and then assign patent rights to biotech
companies in order to develop the discoveries into commercial
products. The universities like the Bayh–Dole Act because it
allows them to collect license fees and royalties from the
biotech products their researchers develop. Academic
researchers like the act because it allows them an opportunity to
profit from their research by investing in biotech companies that
could support their research and then market what might be
commercially viable. Both the university and Dr. Wilson had
invested in a company known as Genovo, a biotechnology
company that Wilson and others had founded. The university’s
equity share in Genovo was 5 percent and Wilson’s share was
30 percent.
We are also aware of numerous good and bad features in the
case:
1. Clinical trials with human participants are essential for
medical progress, and they have done a tremendous amount of
good. Medical research cannot progress very far without them,
especially when it comes to drugs, medical devices, and genetic
alterations.
2. People who volunteer for clinical trials do so for a number of
reasons. Some are dying and will try anything, some do it for
money (some trials pay the participants) or free health care,
some do it in the hope they will receive therapeutic benefit, and
some do it with a sense of altruism because they want to help
researchers find a cure for diseases that afflict or kill others.
Jesse was not dying and he did not do it for the money. His
father indicated that Jesse had a desire to help find a cure for
the lethal disease that affects babies as well as hope that
researchers might find something that could benefit him. These
motivations are morally sound in a virtue-based ethics that
focuses on flourishing and helping others to flourish.
3. Medical researchers inevitably find themselves enmeshed in
numerous conflicts of interest. A major interest of ethical
research is, or should be, protecting human participants from
harm, but numerous other interests can conflict with this. First,
good medical researchers have an intense interest in
accomplishing successful breakthroughs, and this can clash with
their responsibility to protect human participants in research
from harm. Second, researchers often have an interest in
winning recognition for their work and in seeing it published
and accepted, and this can clash with protecting human
participants. Third, medical researchers, especially if they are
trained physicians, often have an interest in finding something
that will help many future patients, and this can clash with
protecting the small number of human participants in their
clinical trials. Fourth, in the more than thirty years since the
1980 Bayh–Dole Act, many researchers and their nonprofit
academic institutions have developed an intense interest in
profiting financially when they develop something with great
commercial value. Obviously the desire to bring a treatment to
market rapidly can clash with the responsibility to protect
carefully the people enrolled in the clinical trials.
4. Researchers had a moral responsibility to provide adequate
and honest information to the Gelsingers when they recruited
Jesse for the clinical trial. They also had a responsibility to
provide timely information about adverse events to the
university IRB, to the NIH, and to the FDA. They also had a
responsibility to adhere strictly to the approved protocols for
the clinical research. Published reports indicate numerous
lapses of their responsibilities in these areas, and this is bad for
the participants in the research and it is bad for clinical trials in
general because people will not volunteer if they think doctors
are acting irresponsibly.
Prudential Reasoning in the Gelsinger Story
Participant’s perspective.Is it morally reasonable for a teenage
person in Jesse’s position to agree to enter a clinical trial such
as this? Based on the information he was given and the guidance
of his father, it is hard to fault his decision to enter the trial. He
expected flu-like symptoms that would pass. The informed
consent form also noted that the altered virus could be toxic to
his liver, but he was reassured that this could be treated. His
biggest worry seemed to be the liver biopsy, with its very slight
risk of death. The problem, of course, is that he and his father
did not receive important information about the adverse effects
of the virus transfer in monkeys or in previous participants in
the trial, nor did they receive any concrete information about
the financial arrangements involving Dr. Wilson, the IHDT, and
the University of Pennsylvania. It should be noted that at the
end of the eleven-page informed consent form was a statement
indicating that both Dr. Wilson and the university had
“financial interest in a successful outcome.” The problem, of
course, is that Jesse and his father had no idea what that interest
was or that it involved millions of dollars.
Parent’s perspective. Jesse’s father, Paul, provided a great deal
of guidance and support for his son. It is hard to fault his role
based on the information he was given. Later he pursued legal
action against the researchers, which also is morally reasonable
in a case such as this because the researchers did not disclose
important information and great harm was done: the clinical
trial caused the death of a relatively healthy teenager who had
no need of genetic therapy to control his genetic disease. Paul
has continued to speak and write about the tragedy, and this has
served to call attention to the need to improve patient protection
in clinical trials.
Researchers’ perspective. There are good moral reasons for
doing research with human participants designed to develop
genetic therapies correcting mutations in human liver cells.
Someday genetic research might lead to a significant revolution
in medicine that will help many human beings. It is not morally
reasonable, however, for researchers not to meticulously follow
the approved protocols; not to inform prospective participants
of adverse reactions in previous subjects, or of animal deaths in
viral transfers, or of financial arrangements relevant to clinical
research; and not to provide timely information required by the
protocols and by regulations to the NIH, the FDA, and the local
IRB that oversee the clinical trial.
University’s perspective. Officials at the University of
Pennsylvania were aware of some of the conflicts of interest
between Wilson’s work as a university faculty member and his
significant financial stake in Genovo, a company he cofounded
to market the products of his research. In 1994 the university’s
Conflicts of Interest Standing Committee (CISC) had looked
into the conflicts of interest that would exist between Wilson’s
research and the potential for great financial gain for him and
his company that the research could generate. The CISC made
an effort to reduce the potential negative impact of this conflict
by imposing some restrictions on Wilson: he could not sit on
Genovo’s scientific board, he could not be paid for his work as
a consultant for Genovo, and he could not do clinical studies
funded by Genovo. Yet the university allowed Dr. Wilson to
own 30 percent of Genovo stock, and it accepted an equity share
in Genovo for itself. The university also agreed that the IHGT
could accept $4 million a year for five years from Genovo for
genetic research, and in return it allowed Genovo to seek
licenses and patents and to earn profit on future developments
by the IHGT or its researchers. They also agreed to accept
$25,000 a year from Genovo toward the salary of Arthur
Caplan, the well-known bioethicist then at the university.
Professor Caplan was professor of bioethics in the Department
of Molecular and Cellular Engineering, which Dr. Wilson
chaired at that time.
The Aftermath
In December 1999 the NIH and the FDA held the hearings in
Bethesda regarding the clinical trial, and Paul Gelsinger
attended. After investigating the circumstances surrounding
Jesse Gelsinger’s death, the NIH reminded all researchers with
similar genetic experiments that federal regulations required
them to report adverse events that occur in the trials. Up to that
point 39 adverse events in genetic experiments had been
reported; after the NIH reminder the number suddenly jumped
to 691! Clearly scientists were routinely disregarding the NIH
reporting regulations.
On January 21, 2000, the FDA shut down all clinical genetic
trials at the University of Pennsylvania due to numerous
regulatory violations.
In August 2000 Targeted Genetics Corporation, a biotech
company, acquired Genovo. Published reports indicate that
Wilson’s equity interest in Genovo brought him $13.5 million in
Targeted Genetics stock and that the university’s equity interest
in the company was worth $1.4 million at the time of the sale.
In September 2000, one year after Jesse died, his family brought
a wrongful death/fraud/intentional misrepresentation lawsuit
against the university, the Children’s National Medical Center
(CNMC) in Washington, the Children’s Hospital of
Philadelphia, doctors Wilson, Raper, Batshaw, and Kelley (the
dean of the medical school), Genovo, and the bioethicist Arthur
Caplan. The suit alleged, among other things, that the informed
consent process was seriously flawed because the defendants
failed to inform Jesse and his family of the risks to him
suggested by the illness and death of the monkeys and failed to
disclose the adverse effects the virus had caused in some earlier
human participants. It also alleged that the defendants failed to
disclose adequately the conflict of interest that existed on the
part of Dr. Wilson and the university due to their financial
interests in seeing Genovo succeed by bringing the viral vector
to market as rapidly as possible. The implication of the lawsuit
was that the researchers and the university cut corners in the
clinical trial in their haste to develop what would be a
blockbuster biotech product.
The defendants in the lawsuit decided not to defend their
actions in court. About a month after the lawsuit was filed, they
quickly agreed to settle the case out of court and paid the
Gelsinger family an undisclosed amount of money, estimated by
some reports to be in the neighborhood of $10 million. Both the
FDA and the Justice Department continued their investigations,
In February 2002 the FDA formally notified Dr. Wilson that he
had failed to address adequately numerous issues that the FDA
had raised about the clinical trial, among them:
• The study was not stopped as required by the approved
protocol after some participants developed grade 3 or higher
toxicities.
• Researchers injected the virus into subjects that did not meet
the criteria required by the approved protocol.
• Researchers injected the virus into a male as the second
person in a group of three despite written agreement that the
sequence in each group of three would be two females followed
by one male (males with the disease are more at risk than
female carriers).
• Researchers failed to perform prestudy ammonia tests on three
days and one day before the viral infusion on all participants as
required by the protocol.
• Researchers failed to submit accurate and timely reports to the
IRB. In the annual report to the IRB in August 1997 Dr. Wilson
stated that the first person in the study developed mild anemia
probably because so much blood was drawn and that the next
two participants did not develop anemia after the amount of
blood drawn was reduced. In fact, however, those two
participants actually did develop grade 1 anemias, but this was
not reported. In the annual IRB report of August 1998, after the
first ten participants had received the virus, Dr. Wilson stated
that “there have been no significant treatment-related or
procedure-related toxicities,” when in fact a significant adverse
event had occurred on June 25, 1998. Also, the 1998 annual
report did not present a table of adverse events according to the
protocol; this information was not submitted until the 1999
annual report. In the annual report of August 1999 Dr. Wilson
stated: “No serious adverse effects have occurred as a result of
this study.” The FDA alleged this statement is false because the
record shows there were some serious adverse effects, namely,
grade 3 toxicities in six participants.
• The protocol stated that researchers will halt the study if a
single participant develops a grade 3 or higher toxicity, yet they
did not halt the study despite instances of grade 3 toxicities in
dose cohorts 4, 5, and 6.
• Researchers failed to obtain proper informed consent in accord
with federal regulations. The FDA requested that Dr. Wilson
inform participants not to donate blood or gametes, and he
confirmed in writing that he had added that information to the
consent form when in fact this information was not in the
informed consent form. Researchers also failed to inform
potential participants that higher doses of the virus were
associated with DIC (disseminated intravascular coagulation—a
life-threatening generalized bleeding that is hard to stop) in
monkeys and might cause a similar problem for humans. Three
monkeys received viral vectors in late 1998; one received the
same virus vector as the humans and the other two a different
vector, but all three developed DIC. Yet the consent form was
never changed to reflect this important fact, and Jessie did in
fact develop DIC after he received the virus. Researchers also
failed to inform the later participants in the trial that, in
addition to “flu-like symptoms,” they were likely to experience
significant periods of chills, nausea, and vomiting. Moreover,
the protocol said that they would be given only Tylenol for
discomfort when in fact researchers had to use other pain
medications to reduce the discomfort participants were
experiencing.
In April 2002 Wilson relinquished his post as director of the
IHGT. In September 2002 Dateline NBC did a program on
Jesse’s death and the family’s search for answers. In February
2003 BBC Two devoted a program to the tragic story.
In February 2005 the US Department of Justice announced a
civil settlement in the case that the department had brought
against the institutions and the researchers involved in the OTC
trial. The Department of Justice had accused the researchers
(Wilson, Raper, and Batshaw) and their institutions (the
University of Pennsylvania and CNMC) of violating the civil
False Claims Act between July 1998 and September 1999 by (1)
submitting false statements and claims on the grant
applications, progress reports, and annual reports submitted to
the NIH; (2) submitting false statements and claims to the FDA,
which was monitoring the research; (3) submitting false
statements to the IRBs, which reviewed the research over a
period of several years; and (4) submitting false statements and
claims that prevented the human research participants from
giving properly informed consent.
In the settlement with the Department of Justice the University
of Pennsylvania agreed to pay a fine of $517,496 and CNMC
agreed to pay a fine of $514,622. The Department of Justice
settlement did not require Dr. Wilson and the other physicians
to pay fines, but it did impose restrictions on their work. Dr.
Wilson, as the sponsor of the FDA-regulated clinical trial paid
for by NIH, had to agree not to participate in research involving
human subjects until he completed training in protecting human
subjects. He also had to accept severe restrictions on his
research with human participants until February 2010. Dr.
Wilson also agreed in the settlement to lecture and write an
article on the lessons learned from the OTC study, and to
include statements from the Gelsinger family in the article.
Wilson’s article on lessons learned from OTC trial in which
Jesse Gelsinger died was published online and in print four
years later, in 2009.
Two other physicians involved in the research, Mark Batshaw
and Steven Raper, were also required to complete training in
protecting human subjects, and both had restrictions placed on
their clinical research for three years. As is customary in this
kind of settlement, the accused parties (the two institutions and
the three physicians) did not admit the allegations and
contended that their behavior was at all times lawful and
appropriate.
In January 2008 Dr. Wilson, as the editor-in-chief of the journal
Human Gene Therapy, wrote an editorial on adverse events in
gene transfer trials in which he encouraged “genetic therapy”
organizations to put in place more effective ways for human
participants in clinical trials to have “a full and unbiased
understanding of the risks and benefits of their participation.”
The editorial mentioned the adverse events in the severe
combined immune deficiency (SCID) and arthritis trials
discussed in the next section but did not mention the adverse
events and the death of Jesse Gelsinger in his OTC trial at the
University of Pennsylvania.
In the same issue of Human Gene Therapy, two authors
recommended the appointment of advocates to help people
considering participation in genetic experiments to understand
the risks of genetic research and to advise them whether
participation in a study is truly in their best interest. Yet more
than a participant-advocate was needed in the Gelsinger case.
Jesse needed to know about numerous major problems in his
clinical trial—namely, the failure of researchers to provide
information about the recent monkey deaths; the failure of
researchers to inform him (and the IRBs, the FDA, and the NIH)
The Uses of Neoliberalism: Rethinking Progressive Politics and Government in the Global South
The Uses of Neoliberalism: Rethinking Progressive Politics and Government in the Global South
The Uses of Neoliberalism: Rethinking Progressive Politics and Government in the Global South
The Uses of Neoliberalism: Rethinking Progressive Politics and Government in the Global South
The Uses of Neoliberalism: Rethinking Progressive Politics and Government in the Global South
The Uses of Neoliberalism: Rethinking Progressive Politics and Government in the Global South
The Uses of Neoliberalism: Rethinking Progressive Politics and Government in the Global South
The Uses of Neoliberalism: Rethinking Progressive Politics and Government in the Global South
The Uses of Neoliberalism: Rethinking Progressive Politics and Government in the Global South
The Uses of Neoliberalism: Rethinking Progressive Politics and Government in the Global South
The Uses of Neoliberalism: Rethinking Progressive Politics and Government in the Global South
The Uses of Neoliberalism: Rethinking Progressive Politics and Government in the Global South
The Uses of Neoliberalism: Rethinking Progressive Politics and Government in the Global South
The Uses of Neoliberalism: Rethinking Progressive Politics and Government in the Global South
The Uses of Neoliberalism: Rethinking Progressive Politics and Government in the Global South

More Related Content

Similar to The Uses of Neoliberalism: Rethinking Progressive Politics and Government in the Global South

1Anarchism Its Aims and PurposesAnarchism versus econ.docx
1Anarchism Its Aims and PurposesAnarchism versus econ.docx1Anarchism Its Aims and PurposesAnarchism versus econ.docx
1Anarchism Its Aims and PurposesAnarchism versus econ.docxaulasnilda
 
Social media and counter democracy
Social media  and counter democracySocial media  and counter democracy
Social media and counter democracyTalew GUALU
 
03_english_rccs annual review_e_estanque_rev2
  03_english_rccs annual review_e_estanque_rev2  03_english_rccs annual review_e_estanque_rev2
03_english_rccs annual review_e_estanque_rev2Elisio Estanque
 
Middle class rebellions_2015
Middle class rebellions_2015Middle class rebellions_2015
Middle class rebellions_2015Elisio Estanque
 
Libertarian Theory
Libertarian TheoryLibertarian Theory
Libertarian TheoryAmin Sadeghi
 
Globalization, Neoliberal Ethics and the Black Body
Globalization, Neoliberal Ethics and the Black BodyGlobalization, Neoliberal Ethics and the Black Body
Globalization, Neoliberal Ethics and the Black BodyTaitu Heron
 
From the Logic of the Particular to the Plea of Minority: A Philosophical App...
From the Logic of the Particular to the Plea of Minority: A Philosophical App...From the Logic of the Particular to the Plea of Minority: A Philosophical App...
From the Logic of the Particular to the Plea of Minority: A Philosophical App...AJHSSR Journal
 

Similar to The Uses of Neoliberalism: Rethinking Progressive Politics and Government in the Global South (9)

1Anarchism Its Aims and PurposesAnarchism versus econ.docx
1Anarchism Its Aims and PurposesAnarchism versus econ.docx1Anarchism Its Aims and PurposesAnarchism versus econ.docx
1Anarchism Its Aims and PurposesAnarchism versus econ.docx
 
Social media and counter democracy
Social media  and counter democracySocial media  and counter democracy
Social media and counter democracy
 
03_english_rccs annual review_e_estanque_rev2
  03_english_rccs annual review_e_estanque_rev2  03_english_rccs annual review_e_estanque_rev2
03_english_rccs annual review_e_estanque_rev2
 
Middle class rebellions_2015
Middle class rebellions_2015Middle class rebellions_2015
Middle class rebellions_2015
 
Libertarian Theory
Libertarian TheoryLibertarian Theory
Libertarian Theory
 
Globalization, Neoliberal Ethics and the Black Body
Globalization, Neoliberal Ethics and the Black BodyGlobalization, Neoliberal Ethics and the Black Body
Globalization, Neoliberal Ethics and the Black Body
 
From the Logic of the Particular to the Plea of Minority: A Philosophical App...
From the Logic of the Particular to the Plea of Minority: A Philosophical App...From the Logic of the Particular to the Plea of Minority: A Philosophical App...
From the Logic of the Particular to the Plea of Minority: A Philosophical App...
 
Populism: Demand and Supply
Populism: Demand and SupplyPopulism: Demand and Supply
Populism: Demand and Supply
 
Old Ghosts in New Sheets
Old Ghosts in New SheetsOld Ghosts in New Sheets
Old Ghosts in New Sheets
 

More from arnoldmeredith47041

Write a scholarly paper in which you apply the concepts of epide.docx
Write a scholarly paper in which you apply the concepts of epide.docxWrite a scholarly paper in which you apply the concepts of epide.docx
Write a scholarly paper in which you apply the concepts of epide.docxarnoldmeredith47041
 
Write a S.M.A.R.T. goal to improve the Habit 5 Seek First to .docx
Write a S.M.A.R.T. goal to improve the Habit 5 Seek First to .docxWrite a S.M.A.R.T. goal to improve the Habit 5 Seek First to .docx
Write a S.M.A.R.T. goal to improve the Habit 5 Seek First to .docxarnoldmeredith47041
 
Write a Risk Management Plan for a School FacilityInclude th.docx
Write a Risk Management Plan for a School FacilityInclude th.docxWrite a Risk Management Plan for a School FacilityInclude th.docx
Write a Risk Management Plan for a School FacilityInclude th.docxarnoldmeredith47041
 
Write a review that 750 - 1000 words in length about one chapter in .docx
Write a review that 750 - 1000 words in length about one chapter in .docxWrite a review that 750 - 1000 words in length about one chapter in .docx
Write a review that 750 - 1000 words in length about one chapter in .docxarnoldmeredith47041
 
write a resume using the example belowCONTACT INFOFirs.docx
write a resume using the example belowCONTACT INFOFirs.docxwrite a resume using the example belowCONTACT INFOFirs.docx
write a resume using the example belowCONTACT INFOFirs.docxarnoldmeredith47041
 
Write a resume and cover letter for the following positionOnline.docx
Write a resume and cover letter for the following positionOnline.docxWrite a resume and cover letter for the following positionOnline.docx
Write a resume and cover letter for the following positionOnline.docxarnoldmeredith47041
 
Write a response to the peers post based on the readings. Origi.docx
Write a response to the peers post based on the readings. Origi.docxWrite a response to the peers post based on the readings. Origi.docx
Write a response to the peers post based on the readings. Origi.docxarnoldmeredith47041
 
Write a response to the following prompt.Analyze the characteriz.docx
Write a response to the following prompt.Analyze the characteriz.docxWrite a response to the following prompt.Analyze the characteriz.docx
Write a response to the following prompt.Analyze the characteriz.docxarnoldmeredith47041
 
Write a response to a peers post that adds or extends to the discus.docx
Write a response to a peers post that adds or extends to the discus.docxWrite a response to a peers post that adds or extends to the discus.docx
Write a response to a peers post that adds or extends to the discus.docxarnoldmeredith47041
 
Write a response mini-essay of at least 150 to 300 words on  the dis.docx
Write a response mini-essay of at least 150 to 300 words on  the dis.docxWrite a response mini-essay of at least 150 to 300 words on  the dis.docx
Write a response mini-essay of at least 150 to 300 words on  the dis.docxarnoldmeredith47041
 
Write a response for each document.Instructions Your post sho.docx
Write a response for each document.Instructions Your post sho.docxWrite a response for each document.Instructions Your post sho.docx
Write a response for each document.Instructions Your post sho.docxarnoldmeredith47041
 
write a resonse paper mla styleHAIRHair deeply affects people,.docx
write a resonse paper mla styleHAIRHair deeply affects people,.docxwrite a resonse paper mla styleHAIRHair deeply affects people,.docx
write a resonse paper mla styleHAIRHair deeply affects people,.docxarnoldmeredith47041
 
Write a response about the topic in the reading (see attached) and m.docx
Write a response about the topic in the reading (see attached) and m.docxWrite a response about the topic in the reading (see attached) and m.docx
Write a response about the topic in the reading (see attached) and m.docxarnoldmeredith47041
 
Write a research report based on a hypothetical research study.  Con.docx
Write a research report based on a hypothetical research study.  Con.docxWrite a research report based on a hypothetical research study.  Con.docx
Write a research report based on a hypothetical research study.  Con.docxarnoldmeredith47041
 
Write a Research Paper with the topic Pregnancy in the adolesce.docx
Write a Research Paper with the topic Pregnancy in the adolesce.docxWrite a Research Paper with the topic Pregnancy in the adolesce.docx
Write a Research Paper with the topic Pregnancy in the adolesce.docxarnoldmeredith47041
 
Write a Research Paper with the topic Autism a major problem. T.docx
Write a Research Paper with the topic Autism a major problem. T.docxWrite a Research Paper with the topic Autism a major problem. T.docx
Write a Research Paper with the topic Autism a major problem. T.docxarnoldmeredith47041
 
Write a research paper that explains how Information Technology (IT).docx
Write a research paper that explains how Information Technology (IT).docxWrite a research paper that explains how Information Technology (IT).docx
Write a research paper that explains how Information Technology (IT).docxarnoldmeredith47041
 
Write a research paper outlining possible career paths in the field .docx
Write a research paper outlining possible career paths in the field .docxWrite a research paper outlining possible career paths in the field .docx
Write a research paper outlining possible career paths in the field .docxarnoldmeredith47041
 
Write a Research paper on the Legal issues associated with pentestin.docx
Write a Research paper on the Legal issues associated with pentestin.docxWrite a Research paper on the Legal issues associated with pentestin.docx
Write a Research paper on the Legal issues associated with pentestin.docxarnoldmeredith47041
 
Write a research paper on one of the following topics .docx
Write a research paper on one of the following topics .docxWrite a research paper on one of the following topics .docx
Write a research paper on one of the following topics .docxarnoldmeredith47041
 

More from arnoldmeredith47041 (20)

Write a scholarly paper in which you apply the concepts of epide.docx
Write a scholarly paper in which you apply the concepts of epide.docxWrite a scholarly paper in which you apply the concepts of epide.docx
Write a scholarly paper in which you apply the concepts of epide.docx
 
Write a S.M.A.R.T. goal to improve the Habit 5 Seek First to .docx
Write a S.M.A.R.T. goal to improve the Habit 5 Seek First to .docxWrite a S.M.A.R.T. goal to improve the Habit 5 Seek First to .docx
Write a S.M.A.R.T. goal to improve the Habit 5 Seek First to .docx
 
Write a Risk Management Plan for a School FacilityInclude th.docx
Write a Risk Management Plan for a School FacilityInclude th.docxWrite a Risk Management Plan for a School FacilityInclude th.docx
Write a Risk Management Plan for a School FacilityInclude th.docx
 
Write a review that 750 - 1000 words in length about one chapter in .docx
Write a review that 750 - 1000 words in length about one chapter in .docxWrite a review that 750 - 1000 words in length about one chapter in .docx
Write a review that 750 - 1000 words in length about one chapter in .docx
 
write a resume using the example belowCONTACT INFOFirs.docx
write a resume using the example belowCONTACT INFOFirs.docxwrite a resume using the example belowCONTACT INFOFirs.docx
write a resume using the example belowCONTACT INFOFirs.docx
 
Write a resume and cover letter for the following positionOnline.docx
Write a resume and cover letter for the following positionOnline.docxWrite a resume and cover letter for the following positionOnline.docx
Write a resume and cover letter for the following positionOnline.docx
 
Write a response to the peers post based on the readings. Origi.docx
Write a response to the peers post based on the readings. Origi.docxWrite a response to the peers post based on the readings. Origi.docx
Write a response to the peers post based on the readings. Origi.docx
 
Write a response to the following prompt.Analyze the characteriz.docx
Write a response to the following prompt.Analyze the characteriz.docxWrite a response to the following prompt.Analyze the characteriz.docx
Write a response to the following prompt.Analyze the characteriz.docx
 
Write a response to a peers post that adds or extends to the discus.docx
Write a response to a peers post that adds or extends to the discus.docxWrite a response to a peers post that adds or extends to the discus.docx
Write a response to a peers post that adds or extends to the discus.docx
 
Write a response mini-essay of at least 150 to 300 words on  the dis.docx
Write a response mini-essay of at least 150 to 300 words on  the dis.docxWrite a response mini-essay of at least 150 to 300 words on  the dis.docx
Write a response mini-essay of at least 150 to 300 words on  the dis.docx
 
Write a response for each document.Instructions Your post sho.docx
Write a response for each document.Instructions Your post sho.docxWrite a response for each document.Instructions Your post sho.docx
Write a response for each document.Instructions Your post sho.docx
 
write a resonse paper mla styleHAIRHair deeply affects people,.docx
write a resonse paper mla styleHAIRHair deeply affects people,.docxwrite a resonse paper mla styleHAIRHair deeply affects people,.docx
write a resonse paper mla styleHAIRHair deeply affects people,.docx
 
Write a response about the topic in the reading (see attached) and m.docx
Write a response about the topic in the reading (see attached) and m.docxWrite a response about the topic in the reading (see attached) and m.docx
Write a response about the topic in the reading (see attached) and m.docx
 
Write a research report based on a hypothetical research study.  Con.docx
Write a research report based on a hypothetical research study.  Con.docxWrite a research report based on a hypothetical research study.  Con.docx
Write a research report based on a hypothetical research study.  Con.docx
 
Write a Research Paper with the topic Pregnancy in the adolesce.docx
Write a Research Paper with the topic Pregnancy in the adolesce.docxWrite a Research Paper with the topic Pregnancy in the adolesce.docx
Write a Research Paper with the topic Pregnancy in the adolesce.docx
 
Write a Research Paper with the topic Autism a major problem. T.docx
Write a Research Paper with the topic Autism a major problem. T.docxWrite a Research Paper with the topic Autism a major problem. T.docx
Write a Research Paper with the topic Autism a major problem. T.docx
 
Write a research paper that explains how Information Technology (IT).docx
Write a research paper that explains how Information Technology (IT).docxWrite a research paper that explains how Information Technology (IT).docx
Write a research paper that explains how Information Technology (IT).docx
 
Write a research paper outlining possible career paths in the field .docx
Write a research paper outlining possible career paths in the field .docxWrite a research paper outlining possible career paths in the field .docx
Write a research paper outlining possible career paths in the field .docx
 
Write a Research paper on the Legal issues associated with pentestin.docx
Write a Research paper on the Legal issues associated with pentestin.docxWrite a Research paper on the Legal issues associated with pentestin.docx
Write a Research paper on the Legal issues associated with pentestin.docx
 
Write a research paper on one of the following topics .docx
Write a research paper on one of the following topics .docxWrite a research paper on one of the following topics .docx
Write a research paper on one of the following topics .docx
 

Recently uploaded

_Math 4-Q4 Week 5.pptx Steps in Collecting Data
_Math 4-Q4 Week 5.pptx Steps in Collecting Data_Math 4-Q4 Week 5.pptx Steps in Collecting Data
_Math 4-Q4 Week 5.pptx Steps in Collecting DataJhengPantaleon
 
Introduction to ArtificiaI Intelligence in Higher Education
Introduction to ArtificiaI Intelligence in Higher EducationIntroduction to ArtificiaI Intelligence in Higher Education
Introduction to ArtificiaI Intelligence in Higher Educationpboyjonauth
 
Presiding Officer Training module 2024 lok sabha elections
Presiding Officer Training module 2024 lok sabha electionsPresiding Officer Training module 2024 lok sabha elections
Presiding Officer Training module 2024 lok sabha electionsanshu789521
 
A Critique of the Proposed National Education Policy Reform
A Critique of the Proposed National Education Policy ReformA Critique of the Proposed National Education Policy Reform
A Critique of the Proposed National Education Policy ReformChameera Dedduwage
 
ENGLISH5 QUARTER4 MODULE1 WEEK1-3 How Visual and Multimedia Elements.pptx
ENGLISH5 QUARTER4 MODULE1 WEEK1-3 How Visual and Multimedia Elements.pptxENGLISH5 QUARTER4 MODULE1 WEEK1-3 How Visual and Multimedia Elements.pptx
ENGLISH5 QUARTER4 MODULE1 WEEK1-3 How Visual and Multimedia Elements.pptxAnaBeatriceAblay2
 
Alper Gobel In Media Res Media Component
Alper Gobel In Media Res Media ComponentAlper Gobel In Media Res Media Component
Alper Gobel In Media Res Media ComponentInMediaRes1
 
EPANDING THE CONTENT OF AN OUTLINE using notes.pptx
EPANDING THE CONTENT OF AN OUTLINE using notes.pptxEPANDING THE CONTENT OF AN OUTLINE using notes.pptx
EPANDING THE CONTENT OF AN OUTLINE using notes.pptxRaymartEstabillo3
 
Biting mechanism of poisonous snakes.pdf
Biting mechanism of poisonous snakes.pdfBiting mechanism of poisonous snakes.pdf
Biting mechanism of poisonous snakes.pdfadityarao40181
 
POINT- BIOCHEMISTRY SEM 2 ENZYMES UNIT 5.pptx
POINT- BIOCHEMISTRY SEM 2 ENZYMES UNIT 5.pptxPOINT- BIOCHEMISTRY SEM 2 ENZYMES UNIT 5.pptx
POINT- BIOCHEMISTRY SEM 2 ENZYMES UNIT 5.pptxSayali Powar
 
internship ppt on smartinternz platform as salesforce developer
internship ppt on smartinternz platform as salesforce developerinternship ppt on smartinternz platform as salesforce developer
internship ppt on smartinternz platform as salesforce developerunnathinaik
 
Crayon Activity Handout For the Crayon A
Crayon Activity Handout For the Crayon ACrayon Activity Handout For the Crayon A
Crayon Activity Handout For the Crayon AUnboundStockton
 
Class 11 Legal Studies Ch-1 Concept of State .pdf
Class 11 Legal Studies Ch-1 Concept of State .pdfClass 11 Legal Studies Ch-1 Concept of State .pdf
Class 11 Legal Studies Ch-1 Concept of State .pdfakmcokerachita
 
Enzyme, Pharmaceutical Aids, Miscellaneous Last Part of Chapter no 5th.pdf
Enzyme, Pharmaceutical Aids, Miscellaneous Last Part of Chapter no 5th.pdfEnzyme, Pharmaceutical Aids, Miscellaneous Last Part of Chapter no 5th.pdf
Enzyme, Pharmaceutical Aids, Miscellaneous Last Part of Chapter no 5th.pdfSumit Tiwari
 
Painted Grey Ware.pptx, PGW Culture of India
Painted Grey Ware.pptx, PGW Culture of IndiaPainted Grey Ware.pptx, PGW Culture of India
Painted Grey Ware.pptx, PGW Culture of IndiaVirag Sontakke
 
Final demo Grade 9 for demo Plan dessert.pptx
Final demo Grade 9 for demo Plan dessert.pptxFinal demo Grade 9 for demo Plan dessert.pptx
Final demo Grade 9 for demo Plan dessert.pptxAvyJaneVismanos
 
Mastering the Unannounced Regulatory Inspection
Mastering the Unannounced Regulatory InspectionMastering the Unannounced Regulatory Inspection
Mastering the Unannounced Regulatory InspectionSafetyChain Software
 
History Class XII Ch. 3 Kinship, Caste and Class (1).pptx
History Class XII Ch. 3 Kinship, Caste and Class (1).pptxHistory Class XII Ch. 3 Kinship, Caste and Class (1).pptx
History Class XII Ch. 3 Kinship, Caste and Class (1).pptxsocialsciencegdgrohi
 
“Oh GOSH! Reflecting on Hackteria's Collaborative Practices in a Global Do-It...
“Oh GOSH! Reflecting on Hackteria's Collaborative Practices in a Global Do-It...“Oh GOSH! Reflecting on Hackteria's Collaborative Practices in a Global Do-It...
“Oh GOSH! Reflecting on Hackteria's Collaborative Practices in a Global Do-It...Marc Dusseiller Dusjagr
 
Science 7 - LAND and SEA BREEZE and its Characteristics
Science 7 - LAND and SEA BREEZE and its CharacteristicsScience 7 - LAND and SEA BREEZE and its Characteristics
Science 7 - LAND and SEA BREEZE and its CharacteristicsKarinaGenton
 

Recently uploaded (20)

_Math 4-Q4 Week 5.pptx Steps in Collecting Data
_Math 4-Q4 Week 5.pptx Steps in Collecting Data_Math 4-Q4 Week 5.pptx Steps in Collecting Data
_Math 4-Q4 Week 5.pptx Steps in Collecting Data
 
Introduction to ArtificiaI Intelligence in Higher Education
Introduction to ArtificiaI Intelligence in Higher EducationIntroduction to ArtificiaI Intelligence in Higher Education
Introduction to ArtificiaI Intelligence in Higher Education
 
Presiding Officer Training module 2024 lok sabha elections
Presiding Officer Training module 2024 lok sabha electionsPresiding Officer Training module 2024 lok sabha elections
Presiding Officer Training module 2024 lok sabha elections
 
A Critique of the Proposed National Education Policy Reform
A Critique of the Proposed National Education Policy ReformA Critique of the Proposed National Education Policy Reform
A Critique of the Proposed National Education Policy Reform
 
ENGLISH5 QUARTER4 MODULE1 WEEK1-3 How Visual and Multimedia Elements.pptx
ENGLISH5 QUARTER4 MODULE1 WEEK1-3 How Visual and Multimedia Elements.pptxENGLISH5 QUARTER4 MODULE1 WEEK1-3 How Visual and Multimedia Elements.pptx
ENGLISH5 QUARTER4 MODULE1 WEEK1-3 How Visual and Multimedia Elements.pptx
 
Alper Gobel In Media Res Media Component
Alper Gobel In Media Res Media ComponentAlper Gobel In Media Res Media Component
Alper Gobel In Media Res Media Component
 
EPANDING THE CONTENT OF AN OUTLINE using notes.pptx
EPANDING THE CONTENT OF AN OUTLINE using notes.pptxEPANDING THE CONTENT OF AN OUTLINE using notes.pptx
EPANDING THE CONTENT OF AN OUTLINE using notes.pptx
 
Biting mechanism of poisonous snakes.pdf
Biting mechanism of poisonous snakes.pdfBiting mechanism of poisonous snakes.pdf
Biting mechanism of poisonous snakes.pdf
 
POINT- BIOCHEMISTRY SEM 2 ENZYMES UNIT 5.pptx
POINT- BIOCHEMISTRY SEM 2 ENZYMES UNIT 5.pptxPOINT- BIOCHEMISTRY SEM 2 ENZYMES UNIT 5.pptx
POINT- BIOCHEMISTRY SEM 2 ENZYMES UNIT 5.pptx
 
Staff of Color (SOC) Retention Efforts DDSD
Staff of Color (SOC) Retention Efforts DDSDStaff of Color (SOC) Retention Efforts DDSD
Staff of Color (SOC) Retention Efforts DDSD
 
internship ppt on smartinternz platform as salesforce developer
internship ppt on smartinternz platform as salesforce developerinternship ppt on smartinternz platform as salesforce developer
internship ppt on smartinternz platform as salesforce developer
 
Crayon Activity Handout For the Crayon A
Crayon Activity Handout For the Crayon ACrayon Activity Handout For the Crayon A
Crayon Activity Handout For the Crayon A
 
Class 11 Legal Studies Ch-1 Concept of State .pdf
Class 11 Legal Studies Ch-1 Concept of State .pdfClass 11 Legal Studies Ch-1 Concept of State .pdf
Class 11 Legal Studies Ch-1 Concept of State .pdf
 
Enzyme, Pharmaceutical Aids, Miscellaneous Last Part of Chapter no 5th.pdf
Enzyme, Pharmaceutical Aids, Miscellaneous Last Part of Chapter no 5th.pdfEnzyme, Pharmaceutical Aids, Miscellaneous Last Part of Chapter no 5th.pdf
Enzyme, Pharmaceutical Aids, Miscellaneous Last Part of Chapter no 5th.pdf
 
Painted Grey Ware.pptx, PGW Culture of India
Painted Grey Ware.pptx, PGW Culture of IndiaPainted Grey Ware.pptx, PGW Culture of India
Painted Grey Ware.pptx, PGW Culture of India
 
Final demo Grade 9 for demo Plan dessert.pptx
Final demo Grade 9 for demo Plan dessert.pptxFinal demo Grade 9 for demo Plan dessert.pptx
Final demo Grade 9 for demo Plan dessert.pptx
 
Mastering the Unannounced Regulatory Inspection
Mastering the Unannounced Regulatory InspectionMastering the Unannounced Regulatory Inspection
Mastering the Unannounced Regulatory Inspection
 
History Class XII Ch. 3 Kinship, Caste and Class (1).pptx
History Class XII Ch. 3 Kinship, Caste and Class (1).pptxHistory Class XII Ch. 3 Kinship, Caste and Class (1).pptx
History Class XII Ch. 3 Kinship, Caste and Class (1).pptx
 
“Oh GOSH! Reflecting on Hackteria's Collaborative Practices in a Global Do-It...
“Oh GOSH! Reflecting on Hackteria's Collaborative Practices in a Global Do-It...“Oh GOSH! Reflecting on Hackteria's Collaborative Practices in a Global Do-It...
“Oh GOSH! Reflecting on Hackteria's Collaborative Practices in a Global Do-It...
 
Science 7 - LAND and SEA BREEZE and its Characteristics
Science 7 - LAND and SEA BREEZE and its CharacteristicsScience 7 - LAND and SEA BREEZE and its Characteristics
Science 7 - LAND and SEA BREEZE and its Characteristics
 

The Uses of Neoliberalism: Rethinking Progressive Politics and Government in the Global South

  • 1. The Uses of Neoliberalism James Ferguson Department of Anthropology, Stanford University; [email protected] Abstract: The term “neoliberalism” has come to be used in a wide variety of partly overlapping and partly contradictory ways. This essay seeks to clarify some of the analytical and political work that the term does in its different usages. It then goes on to suggest that making an analytical distinction between neoliberal “arts of government” and the class-based ideological “project” of neoliberalism can allow us to identify some surprising (and perhaps hopeful) new forms of politics that illustrate how fundamentally polyvalent neoliberal mechanisms of government can be. A range of empirical examples are discussed, mostly coming from my recent work on social policy and anti-poverty politics in southern Africa. Keywords: neoliberalism, governmentality, South Africa, basic income, poverty In thinking about the rapidly expanding literature on neoliberalism, I am struck by how much of the critical scholarship on topic arrives in the end at the very same conclusion—a conclusion that might be expressed in its simplest form as: “neoliberalism is bad for poor
  • 2. and working people, therefore we must oppose it.” It is not that I disagree with this conclusion. On the contrary. But I sometimes wonder why I should bother to read one after another extended scholarly analysis only to reach, again and again, such an unsurprising conclusion. This problem in recent progressive scholarship strikes me as related to a parallel problem in progressive politics more broadly. For over the last couple of decades, what we call “the Left” has come to be organized, in large part, around a project of resisting and refusing harmful new developments in the world. This is understandable, since so many new developments have indeed been highly objectionable. But it has left us with a politics largely defined by negation and disdain, and centered on what I will call “the antis.” Anti-globalization, anti- neoliberalism, anti-privatization, anti-imperialism, anti-Bush, perhaps even anti-capitalism—but always “anti”, not “pro”. This is good enough, perhaps, if one’s political goal is simply to denounce “the system” and to decry its current tendencies. And, indeed, some seem satisfied with such a politics. In my own disciplines of anthropology and African Studies, for instance, studies of state and development tend, with
  • 3. depressing predictability, to conclude (in tones of righteous indignation) that the rich are benefiting and the poor are getting screwed. The powerless, it seems, are getting the short end of the stick. This is not exactly a Antipode Vol. 41 No. S1 2009 ISSN 0066-4812, pp 166–184 doi: 10.1111/j.1467-8330.2009.00721.x C© 2009 The Authors Journal compilation C© 2009 Editorial Board of Antipode. The Uses of Neoliberalism 167 surprising finding, of course (isn’t it precisely because they are on the losing end of things that we call them “powerless” in the first place?). Yet this sort of work styles itself as “critique”, and imagines itself to be very “political”. But what if politics is really not about expressing indignation or denouncing the powerful? What if it is, instead, about getting what you want? Then we progressives must ask: what do we want? This is a quite different question (and a far more difficult question) than: what are we against? What do we want? Such a question brings us very quickly to the question of government. Denunciatory analyses often
  • 4. treat government as the simple expression of power or domination— the implication apparently being that it is politically objectionable that people should be governed at all. But any realistic sort of progressive politics that would seek a serious answer to the question “what do we want?” will have to involve an exploration of the contemporary possibilities for developing genuinely progressive arts of government. In his 1979 lectures on neoliberalism (2008), Michel Foucault famously spoke of the “absence of a socialist art of government”, and the historic failure of the left to develop an “autonomous governmentality” comparable to liberalism. Stated as starkly as this, the point is no doubt debatable. Various forms of democratic socialism and social democracy (including but not limited to the German case treated in the lectures) may perhaps leave us with a richer trove of governmental arts than Foucault’s very schematic account acknowledged, and the diverse histories of “unhappy symbiosis” of socialism with liberalism that he referred to parenthetically (2008:94n) may well have a greater originality than his analysis allowed. But what seems less open to dispute is that any program for governing from the left today faces an obstacle that we
  • 5. could describe (in Foucaultian terms) as a failure to develop new arts of government adequate to the challenges of our time. New progressive approaches to the problem of government are necessary, it now seems clear, because neither the governmental mechanisms, nor the political strategies of mobilization, that the left came to rely upon in the twentieth century (and which characterized, in different ways, both socialist and social democratic or “welfare state” regimes) are capable of getting the sort of traction that they once did. There are at least two reasons for this that are relevant both to my broader argument here, and to the particular topic of social assistance that I will address in the latter part of this article. The first reason is the increasing prominence (especially in the region of my own special interest, Africa, but not only there) of urban masses who are not, and are not likely to become, formal wage laborers. Such people (variously, and inadequately, described as “the informal sector”, “the lumpen”, “the youth”, and so on) now constitute the majority of the population in many African cities, and a very substantial proportion in C© 2009 The Authors Journal compilation C© 2009 Editorial Board of Antipode.
  • 6. 168 Antipode much of the rest of the world, as Mike Davis (2007) has recently pointed out in his usual alarmist style. The twentieth-century social democracies, on the other hand (and still more so the state socialist regimes), were built on the putatively universal figure of “the worker”. The Keynesian welfare state, as we know, was founded on a pact between capital and organized labor, and the domain we have come to know as “the social” was constructed on the foundation of the able-bodied worker. Indeed, the list of those requiring “social” intervention (the elderly, the infirm, the child, the disabled, the dependent reproductive woman) sketches a kind of photographic negative of the figure of the wage-earning man. Today, however, the question of social assistance is transformed in societies where young, able-bodied men look in vain for work, and are as much in need of assistance as everyone else. A compact between capital and labor, meanwhile, even were it politically possible, risks leaving out most of the population. New approaches to distribution, and new approaches to the question of social assistance, will need to be
  • 7. based on a fundamental rethinking that gives a new prominence to those hard- to-categorize urban improvisers who have for so long been relegated to the margins both of society, and of social analysis. The second challenge to progressive thought and politics that I would like to identify is the rise of what we might call transnational forms of government, and particularly of the philanthropic funding of what we used to call “the social”. Much has been written about the governmental role played by international organizations like the IMF and the World Bank. But the last couple of decades have also seen an explosion in de facto government carried out by an extraordinary swarm of NGOs, voluntary organizations, and private foundations. The Gates Foundation in Mozambique, to take just one example,1 is carrying out a wide range of projects (in health, hygiene, education, sanitation, etc) that looks something like the twentieth century “social” of the social welfare state. But there is obviously a very different relation to the nation- state here, and to the national political arena. Social policy and nation- state are, to a very significant degree, decoupled, and we are only beginning to find ways to think about this.
  • 8. More generally, technical prescriptions for “making poverty history” often seem almost irrelevant because they presume the central actors to be states—and certain sorts of states at that: well-financed, bureaucratically capable, poverty-fighting states that resemble nothing so much as twentieth century European welfare states. Couldn’t the Democratic Republic of the Congo solve all its problems, reformers seems to say, if only its government would start to behave like that of Sweden? Well, maybe so, but it’s the sort of ahistorical and asociological formulation that is worse than useless. Yet what happens when states of the imagined, poverty-fighting kind are simply not present? How can poverty policy be effective where states are (as the political scientists, C© 2009 The Authors Journal compilation C© 2009 Editorial Board of Antipode. The Uses of Neoliberalism 169 rather misleadingly, say) “weak”, or even actively anti- developmental? Where financial capacity is tiny and needs are enormous? What happens when the key implementers of poverty policy are not national states at all, but transnational NGOs, or private transnational foundations? What
  • 9. would count as progressive politics here? One response here—understandable in the wake of the neoliberal restructuring of recent decades—is to call for the reinstating of old-style developmental states, effectively undoing the neoliberal transformations of the 1980s and 1990s and going back to the 1970s. I am skeptical that this is an adequate response—partly because the supposedly developmental states I know from the 1970s in Africa were pretty awful, and partly because I doubt that you can run history backward (as if you could just hit the rewind button and try again). The world has changed, and simply re-asserting Third World sovereignty will not get us very far in dealing with a fundamentally reconfigured politico-spatial world order. Imperialism is undoubtedly alive and well. But I don’t think we have a good analysis of, say, the Gates Foundation, or the Soros Foundation, if we see them simply as the imperial tools of the global rich, undermining the sovereignty of African governments. It is much more complicated than that—and perhaps also more hopeful. Can we find ways of thinking creatively about the progressive possibilities (and not only the reactionary dangers) of this new terrain of transnational organization of funds, energies, and affect?
  • 10. Can we imagine new “arts of government” that might take advantage of (rather than simply denouncing or resisting) recent transformations in the spatial organization of government and social assistance? Most broadly, can we engage with these new configurations of governmental power in a way that goes beyond the politics of denunciation, the politics of the “anti”? Can we develop new ways of thinking through the problem of government that are genuinely progressive, but that don’t take for granted the absolute solidity or centrality of those two figures of twentieth-century left common sense: the worker and the nation-state? It is here that we have to look more carefully at the “arts of government” that have so radically reconfigured the world in the last few decades, and I think we have to come up with something more interesting to say about them than just that we’re against them. With respect to poverty and social policy, for instance (my particular interest here), it is simply not the case (as is often suggested) that neoliberal government ignores poverty, or leaves it to “the market”. (Later in this essay, I will discuss a range of welfare-like interventions and social payments that coexist with—and may, in fact, be necessary complements to— neoliberal economic models.) At the same time, there is
  • 11. sometimes room (in part because of the political spaces opened up by “democracy” as the characteristic mode of legitimation of neoliberal regimes) for social C© 2009 The Authors Journal compilation C© 2009 Editorial Board of Antipode. 170 Antipode movements and pro-poor organizations to have some real influence on matters of “social policy”. (Hence my current interest in the “Basic Income Grant” (BIG) campaign in South Africa, which I’ll discuss in a moment.) To understand the political possibilities and dangers that such emergent phenomena contain, we will surely need empirical research on the actual political processes at work. But beyond this, there is a palpable need for conceptual work, for new and better ways of thinking about practices of government and how they might be linked in new ways to the aspirations and demands of the economically and socially marginalized people who constitute the majority of the population in much of the world. It is in this spirit, then, that I want to consider what I am calling “the uses of neoliberalism”. I begin with a consideration of
  • 12. “uses” in the literal sense of semantic usage, as the wide variation in the way the term is used forces some clarification before we can begin to ask some new questions that might bring to light the surprising affinity of some aspects of what we call “neoliberalism” with certain forms of progressive politics. As even a cursory inspection reveals, there is huge variation in the way the word, “neoliberalism” is used in contemporary scholarship. In perhaps the strictest sense, neoliberalism refers to a macroeconomic doctrine (and is, in this sense, a true “-ism”). The key elements of the doctrine are variously described, but always include a valorization of private enterprise and suspicion of the state, along with what is sometimes called “free-market fetishism” and the advocacy of tariff elimination, currency deregulation, and the deployment of “enterprise models” that would allow the state itself to be “run like a business”. (See Peck 2008 for an illuminating review of the rise and dissemination of this doctrine.) A related usage would have “neoliberalism” refer to a regime of policies and practices associated with or claiming fealty to the doctrine
  • 13. referenced above. Such a regime of practice is obviously different from the doctrine itself. Indeed, as David Harvey (2005) has argued, this divergence is, in fact, necessary, since neoliberal doctrine, if applied consistently, implies a world that could never, in fact, exist (which leads Harvey to term it “utopian”). Rather than purely applying the utopian neoliberal doctrine, Harvey points out that dominant groups around the world have used neoliberal arguments to carry out what is in fact a class project. “Neoliberalism”, in this sense, has become the name for a set of highly interested public policies that have vastly enriched the holders of capital, while leading to increasing inequality, insecurity, loss of public services, and a general deterioration of quality of life for the poor and working classes. But the policies of neoliberal states have often diverged from neoliberal doctrine for other reasons as well—reasons which have C© 2009 The Authors Journal compilation C© 2009 Editorial Board of Antipode. The Uses of Neoliberalism 171 less to do with straightforward power grabs by the rich than with
  • 14. the contingencies of democratic politics. This no doubt helps to account for the otherwise paradoxical fact that a number of regimes pursuing undoubtedly neoliberal macroeconomic policies have also seen substantial recent rises in social spending (examples include India, Brazil, and South Africa, among others). Neoliberal policy is thus much more complicated than a reading of neoliberal doctrine might suggest. Finally, it is perhaps worth mentioning, if only schematically, some other common uses of the term. One is as a sloppy synonym for capitalism itself, or as a kind of shorthand for the world economy and its inequalities. In much current anthropological usage, “neoliberalism” appears in this way, as a kind of abstract causal force that comes in from outside (much as “the world system” was reckoned to do at an earlier theoretical moment) to decimate local livelihoods. Another, more interesting, usage sees “neoliberalism” as the name of a broad, global cultural formation characteristic of a new era of “millennial capitalism”—a kind of global meta-culture, characteristic of our newly de-regulated, insecure, and speculative times (eg Comaroff and Comaroff 2000). And finally, “neoliberalism” can be indexed to a sort of “rationality” in the Foucauldian sense, linked less to economic
  • 15. dogmas or class projects than to specific mechanisms of government, and recognizable modes of creating subjects. (I will have more to say about this last usage shortly.) It is, then, possible to identify many quite distinct referents for the same widely used term. This has some obvious dangers, of course. There is plainly a danger of simple confusion, since the meaning of the term can slip in the course of an argument being passed from author to reader (or, indeed, even in the course of an argument made by a single author). There is also another danger, only slightly less obvious, which is that such an all-encompassing entity can easily come to appear as a kind of gigantic, all-powerful first cause (as categories like “Modernity” or “Capitalism” have done before it)—that malevolent force that causes everything else to happen. This yields empty analysis (since to say that all our problems are caused by “neoliberalism” is really not to say much), and may also lead to an ineffectual politics—since all one can do with such a gigantic, malevolent “thing” as “neoliberalism” conceived in this way is to denounce it. (And that, the evidence suggests, doesn’t seem to do much good).
  • 16. One response would be to stop using the word altogether. This is indeed very tempting. If the word is so ambiguous, perhaps we should just be careful to be more specific, and use less all- encompassing terms. When the term “neoliberalism” is used as imprecisely as it is in many texts, one is tempted to pencil one’s objections in the margins as one might in reading a student essay: “What do you mean by ‘neoliberalism’ here? Do you mean the liberalization of trade policies? Then say C© 2009 The Authors Journal compilation C© 2009 Editorial Board of Antipode. 172 Antipode so! Do you mean techniques of government that work through the creation of responsibilized citizen-subjects? Then say that! The two don’t necessarily go together. Say what you mean, and don’t presume that they are all united in some giant package called ‘neoliberalism’.” Such insistence on specificity and precision would undoubtedly improve the analytical clarity of many of our discussions. But there is also some utility in words that bring together more than one meaning. As long as we can avoid the mistake of simply
  • 17. confusing the different meanings, the word can be an occasion for reflecting on how the rather different things to which it refers may be related. In particular, I would like to use this confusing, conflating word as an occasion for thinking about the relation between the following two things: First, we may consider the new governmental rationalities that emerged through the Thatcher–Reagan assaults on the North Atlantic, post-war welfare state. Key here was the deployment of market mechanisms and “enterprise” models to reform government, restructure the state, and pioneer new modes of government and subjectification. (See, eg, Barry, Osborne and Rose 1996; Rose 1999; Cruikshank 1999; Miller and Rose 2008.) There is a clear analysis in this literature of what it is that distinguishes “neoliberalism” from liberalism. Liberalism, in this account, was always about finding the right balance between two spheres understood as properly distinct, if always related: state and market, public and private, the realm of the king and the proper domain of the merchant. Neoliberalism, in contrast, puts governmental mechanisms developed in the private sphere to work within the state itself, so that even core functions of the state are either subcontracted out to private providers, or run (as the saying has it) “like a
  • 18. business”. The question of what should be public and what private becomes blurred, as the state itself increasingly organizes itself around “profit centers”, “enterprise models”, and so on. Rather than shifting the line between state and market, then, neoliberalism in this account involved the deployment of new, market-based techniques of government within the terrain of the state itself. At the same time, new constructions of “active” and “responsible” citizens and communities are deployed to produce governmental results that do not depend on direct state intervention. The “responsibilized” citizen comes to operate as a miniature firm, responding to incentives, rationally assessing risks, and prudently choosing from among different courses of action. Against this understanding of the neoliberal, consider what we might call neoliberalism in the African sense. Here, neoliberalism has meant first of all the policy measures that were forced on African states in the 1980s by banks and international lending agencies, under the name of “structural adjustment”. Reforms focused on removing tariffs, deregulating currency markets, and removing the state from production and distribution (via dismantling of state marketing boards
  • 19. C© 2009 The Authors Journal compilation C© 2009 Editorial Board of Antipode. The Uses of Neoliberalism 173 and parastatals). This did involve privatization, and an ideological celebration of markets. But the development of new technologies of government, responsibilized prudential subjects, and so on (all the things that Nikolas Rose and other “Anglo-Foucauldians” tend to emphasize) was very limited. Neoliberalism here was (in these terms) not very “neo” at all. It was, in fact, largely a matter of old-style laissez-faire liberalism in the service of imperial capital. And it had disastrous and wildly unpopular results (especially, the selling off of precious state assets to foreign firms at fire-sale prices, massive deindustrialization, and increased unemployment). Across much of the continent, it has raised the specter of a kind of recolonization. The result is that “neoliberalism” in Africa refers to a quite fundamentally different situation than it does in Western Europe and North America. The hasty and uncritical application of ideas of neoliberalism-as-rationality to Africa is thus clearly a mistake, based on a simple confusion (an art of
  • 20. government versus a crude battering open of Third World markets). But bringing these two different referents together can be more interesting, if we don’t just equate them, but instead reflect on the conceptual themes they share (broadly, a technical reliance on market mechanisms coupled with an ideological valorization of “private enterprise” and a suspicion of the state), and use such a reflection to ask if the new “arts of government” developed within First World neoliberalism might take on new life in other contexts, in the process opening up new political possibilities. Can we on the left do what the right has, in recent decades, done so successfully, that is, to develop new modes and mechanisms of government? And (perhaps more provocatively) are the neoliberal “arts of government” that have transformed the way that states work in so many places around the world inherently and necessarily conservative, or can they be put to different uses? To ask such questions requires us to be willing at least to imagine the possibility of a truly progressive politics that would also draw on governmental mechanisms that we have become used to terming “neoliberal”. I have been led to these questions by my current interest in anti-
  • 21. poverty programs in southern Africa that seek to provide cash support for incomes, and thus (in theory) harness markets to the task of meeting the needs of the poor. This is happening in several African countries, but also in a great many other postcolonial states— from Brazil and Venezuela to Mexico and Bangladesh—where leftist and rightist regimes alike have seen fit to introduce policies that transfer cash directly into the hands of the poor. (See Fiszbein and Schady 2009; Standing 2008 [2007] for reviews.) The South African Basic Income Grant campaign is the example I will explore here. The proposal, which I will discuss in some detail shortly, is to deal with a crisis of persistent poverty by providing an unconditional minimum C© 2009 The Authors Journal compilation C© 2009 Editorial Board of Antipode. 174 Antipode monthly payment to all. The argument goes like this: markets aren’t working for poor people because they’re too poor to participate in them; government programs aren’t working because the state is inefficient. So, provide income support directly, in the form of cash, and then say to the poor: “you are now empowered to solve your own
  • 22. problems in the way you see best”. In contrast to older forms of “welfare” assistance, the claim is that such grants rely on poor people’s own ability to solve their own problems, without imposing the policing, paternalism, and surveillance of the traditional welfare state. More broadly, similar new lines of thought are calling for an increased role for direct cash transfers in many forms of social and humanitarian policy (eg famine relief, which will be briefly discussed shortly). The reasoning here often includes recognizably neoliberal elements, including the valorization of market efficiency, individual choice, and autonomy; themes of entrepreneurship; and skepticism about the state as a service provider. But the politics are avowedly (and, I think, on balance, genuinely) “pro-poor” (as the phrase has it). “Pro- poor” and neoliberal—it is the strangeness of this conjunction that is of interest here. For the sorts of new progressive initiatives I have in mind seem to involve not just opposing “the neoliberal project”, but appropriating key elements of neoliberal reasoning for different ends. We can’t think about this (or even acknowledge its possibility) if we continue to treat “neoliberal” simply as a synonym for “evil”. Instead, I suggest (and
  • 23. this is a deliberate provocation) that some innovative (and possible effective) forms of new politics in these times may be showing us how fundamentally polyvalent the neoliberal arts of government can be. Let me emphasize that to say that certain political initiatives and programs borrow from the neoliberal bag of tricks doesn’t mean that these political projects are in league with the ideological project of neoliberalism (in David Harvey’s sense)—only that they appropriate certain characteristic neoliberal “moves” (and I think of these discursive and programmatic moves as analogous to the moves one might make in a game). These moves are recognizable enough to look “neoliberal”, but they can, I suggest, be used for quite different purposes than that term usually implies. In this connection, one might think of statistical techniques for calculating the probabilities of workplace injuries. These were originally developed in the nineteenth century by large employers to control costs (Ewald 1986), but they eventually became the technical basis for social insurance, and ultimately for the welfare state (which brought unprecedented gains to the working class across much of the world). Techniques, that is to say, can “migrate” across
  • 24. strategic camps, and devices of government that were invented to serve one purpose have often enough ended up, though history’s irony, being harnessed to another. Might we see a similar re-appropriation of “market” techniques of government (which were, like workplace statistics, undoubtedly C© 2009 The Authors Journal compilation C© 2009 Editorial Board of Antipode. The Uses of Neoliberalism 175 conservative in their original uses) for different, and more progressive sorts of ends? Maybe not—one should remain genuinely open- minded about this—but it is perhaps worth at least considering. Let me present two empirical examples from southern Africa as a way of making this proposition perhaps a bit more plausible. Basic Income My principal example is the basic income grant (BIG) campaign in South Africa. For historical reasons, South Africa came to democratic independence in 1994 with a quite well developed system of social grants and pensions (which I am not able to describe here for reasons of space). In recent years, as neoliberal restructuring has led to
  • 25. widening inequality and very high rates of unemployment, these social grants have substantially expanded, and have been instrumental in holding together what might otherwise be an explosive situation (a fact of which the ANC government appears to be acutely aware). But planners have been bothered by the patchy and arbitrary spread of the coverage, and the inefficiency and cost of administering a host of cumbersome and bureaucratic targeted programs. It is in this context that proposals emerged for a far-reaching new comprehensive system of income support, anchored by a BIG to be paid to all South Africans (Department of Social Development 2002). The idea of a BIG was first put forward by the labor union federation, COSATU, in 1998, and it acquired new legitimacy when it was embraced in 2002 by a government-appointed committee (the Taylor Committee) charged with recommending measures for the rationalization of the system of social assistance (see Barchiesi 2007; Department of Social Development 2002; Ferguson 2007; Tilton 2005). The proposal has been advocated from 2001 onward by a formal coalition of church groups and labor, the BIG Coalition).2
  • 26. The proposal was for a modest payment of about R100 (at that time, about $16) per person per month, to be paid to all South Africans, irrespective of age or income. Advocates insist that a universal system of direct payments is by far the most efficient way to direct assistance to all poor South Africans. Means testing, in their view, would not be necessary; better off South Africans would also receive the grant, but the funds they received (and then some) would be recuperated through the tax system. Economic analyses prepared by BIG advocates (eg Standing and Samson 2003) argue that the measure could be funded through increases in either the income tax or the VAT, as well as by savings created by rationalizing the existing system of pensions. The idea of a BIG has been supported by church groups, NGOs, and the powerful Congress of South African Trade Unions (COSATU); and a watered down version has even been endorsed by the main (and historically white) opposition party, the Democratic Alliance. The ruling C© 2009 The Authors Journal compilation C© 2009 Editorial Board of Antipode.
  • 27. 176 Antipode ANC, however, has thus far rejected the plan, though it does enjoy support from at least some key players within the party (including the Minster for Social Development, Dr Zola Skweyiya). The BIG campaign is significant not only as an interesting and potentially progressive policy proposal, but also as an illustration of some new ways of thinking about questions of poverty and welfare that bring neoliberal themes to bear on the question of social assistance in ways that are very different from those we have become accustomed to in the last few decades. I begin by acknowledging that the arguments for a basic income grant in South Africa have been many sided and complex, and they are not reducible to a single logic or rationality (neoliberal or otherwise). Older languages of social democracy and solidarity continue to have significant currency, and a reading of pro-BIG documents shows that traditional welfare-state arguments are regularly deployed. These include themes of social solidarity and moral obligation; the advantages of social cohesion and dangers of class war; Keynesian arguments about stimulating demand; and labor-rights arguments about giving workers the security to say no to dangerous and demeaning work.3 Yet
  • 28. these lines of argument lie side by side with others, which are markedly different from social democratic reasoning, and surprisingly similar to the neoliberal rationality that we more usually associate with anti- welfare discourses. The intermingling of these different themes speaks to the complex political struggles around the BIG, which have been discussed by others (eg Mattisonn and Seekings 2003; Barchiesi 2007). My interest here, though, is not in analyzing these politics, but in identifying some surprising ways in which certain discursive “moves” that we can readily identify as neoliberal are being put to work in the service of apparently pro-poor and pro-welfare political arguments. To make this process visible, it is useful to pull some of these neoliberal “moves” out of the broader mix of BIG arguments so that we can see the work that they are doing. (Note that the following is a highly condensed summary. For a more detailed analysis that includes citations of specific texts, see Ferguson 2007.) One of the most important themes in arguments in favor of a BIG is the idea of “investment in human capital”. A BIG, supporters say, would enable poor South Africans to increase their spending on
  • 29. such things as nutrition, education, and health care. And this, advocates insist, should be understood as an “investment” in a kind of “capital”. Such “investment”, they insist, will bring handsome returns, in the form of productivity gains. The poor individual is in this way conceived, in classic neoliberal fashion, as a kind of micro-enterprise, earning a rate of return on invested capital. More surprising is the way that pro-BIG arguments neatly reverse the usual right-wing arguments against social payments by insisting that basic income can be justified precisely as a way of combating C© 2009 The Authors Journal compilation C© 2009 Editorial Board of Antipode. The Uses of Neoliberalism 177 “dependency”. The existing “safety net”, the BIG promoters argue, relies on very destructive forms of dependency, since any economically productive poor person is surrounded by relatives and other dependents who must be supported. This is destructive, in economic terms, because it constitutes an effective “tax” on the productivity of the poor. The
  • 30. worker whose wages are soaked up by dependents in this way suffers from both a disincentive to work, and a drag on his or her ability to build up human capital. The “dependency” of absolute poverty in this way hurts productivity, and also makes it hard for workers to be economically active, to search for better jobs, etc. The passivity associated with this predicament, moreover, inhibits entrepreneurship and “risk-taking behaviors”. Providing basic income security for all, it is claimed, will enable the poor to behave as proper neoliberal subjects (ie as entrepreneurs and risk takers); the status quo prevents it, and promotes “dependency”. In this way, the BIG would provide not a “safety net” (the circus image of old-style welfare as protection against hazard) but a “springboard”—a facilitator of risky (but presumably empowering) neoliberal flight. Equally striking is the way that basic income arguments appropriate neoliberal critiques of welfare paternalism and put them in the service of a pro-welfare argument. Echoing the old Margaret Thatcher complaint about the “nanny state” that tries to run everybody’s life in the name of the needs of “society”, BIG advocates point out that South Africa’s
  • 31. existing social assistance system makes moralizing judgments about “the undeserving poor”, and requires (at great expense) the surveillance and normalization of grant recipients, who are publicly labeled as such, and thus potentially stigmatized. In contrast to all this, the BIG would be paid to everyone; citizens would access their funds (in the ideal scheme) by simply swiping their national identity cards at at automatic cash dispenser. They would not need the government to tell them how to spend the funds. They would use them (like good rational actors) in the way they saw best. There would be no “nanny state”: no policing of conduct, no stigmatizing labels, no social workers coming into homes— and no costly bureaucracy to sort out who does or doesn’t qualify. Grant recipients, in this vision, appear as sensible people who know their problems and predicaments better than any bureaucrat could. The state, meanwhile, appears as both omnipresent and minimal— universally engaged (as a kind of direct provider for each and every citizen) and maximally disengaged (taking no real interest in shaping the conduct of those under its care, who are seen as knowing their own needs better than the state does).
  • 32. Finally, the most radical shift from traditional social democracy visible in the arguments for a BIG is the explicit rejection of formal employment as the “normal” frame of reference for social policy (let alone as an entitlement to which all have rights). The 2002 Taylor C© 2009 The Authors Journal compilation C© 2009 Editorial Board of Antipode. 178 Antipode Committee Report projected that, even with strong economic growth, formal sector employment in South Africa was not likely to expand at the sort of rate that would be necessary for anything close to full employment (a prediction that recent developments have certainly borne out). On the contrary, it forecast that developing countries like South Africa were likely, over the long term, to see an inexorable shift away from (and not toward) formal employment. According to the report: In developing countries, where stable full-time waged formal sector labour was never the norm, it is increasingly unlikely that it will become the norm (Department of Social Development 2002:38). The reality is that in the developing world formal sector employment
  • 33. may never become the norm that it is in Europe (ibid 2002:154). The need for assistance, then, is not about being “between jobs” or correcting for dips in the business cycle; it is part of a world in which many, or even most, people, for the foreseeable future, will lack formal sector employment. Social assistance is here radically decoupled from expectations of employment, and, indeed, from “insurance” rationality altogether. Instead, the Taylor Committee Report re-understands the condition of unemployment not as a hazard, but as the normal condition. Yet unemployment, in this understanding, need not imply idleness or a lack of productivity. On the contrary, in a world where livelihoods in the “informal economy” will become increasingly important, small expenditures on minimum income support (like the BIG) can have big payoffs in enabling and enhancing economic action in that domain. Social payments, in this optic, are most significant not as temporary substitutes for employment, but as a way of promoting greater productivity, enterprise, and risk-taking in the “informal” domain within which more and more South Africans are expected to make their living. I hope to have identified some recognizably neoliberal motifs
  • 34. here. But I hope it is also clear that this is not the neoliberalism we love to hate, the so-called “neoliberal project” identified by Harvey (2005). It’s something else—a set of much harder to place arguments that link markets, enterprise, welfare, and social payments in a novel way. It leaves us neither with something to hate, nor something to love, but rather something to ponder. I will return to the question of the perils and promise of the BIG in the conclusion to this article, but for the moment, let us try to hold in our minds the apparently paradoxical idea that a major policy initiative might be, all at once, “pro-poor”, redistributive, and neoliberal. Food Aid and Cash Transfers It may be helpful to briefly discuss one additional example, to help suggest something I am increasingly convinced is the case: that the BIG C© 2009 The Authors Journal compilation C© 2009 Editorial Board of Antipode. The Uses of Neoliberalism 179 campaign is part of a much wider, worldwide shift in thinking about poverty and social and humanitarian assistance. The example I
  • 35. have in mind is the increasingly influential argument that hunger is best dealt with by boosting the purchasing power of those at risk, rather than by distributing in-kind food aid. The current international food aid system is based on the subsidized overproduction of agricultural crops (especially grain) in rich countries like the USA. Food aid programs then take this surplus grain and transport it to places (largely in Africa) where it is distributed to people who are at risk of hunger due to drought, natural disasters, political violence, or other sorts of humanitarian emergency. Critics like Amartya Sen have long noted the (largely unintended) negative impacts of such policies, which tend to depress producer prices for local farmers, while damaging local institutions for producing and distributing food crops. Once food aid has arrived, local food production may never recover. Too often, what was supposed to be a “temporary” crisis becomes a long-term decline in food self-sufficiency (see, eg Sen 1983; Dreze and Sen 1991). As an alternative, Sen’s followers have pushed for cash payments to be made directly to those at risk of food deficit (either via
  • 36. employment guarantees, or through direct cash transfers). People with money in their pockets, these advocates point out, usually don’t starve. And cash support allows famine victims to preserve or restore productive assets (eg livestock) in ways that simply supplying a certain number of calories does not. What is more, the economic chain of events that is set in motion by boosting purchasing power not only avoids the destructive effects of food aid, but creates a virtuous cycle, in which market forces lead to increased capacity for local production and distribution. A number of pilot projects have been launched putting these principles into practice in recent years. Among the best known is the Cash for Relief Programme in Ethiopia, which used cash payments to enable households that had been hit by crop failure to rebuild their assets and regenerate their livelihoods, and not only to eat (USAID/OFDA 2004). Another widely discussed project has been the Kalomo Social Cash Transfer Scheme in Zambia. Here, too, cash took the place of food aid, with the result that recipients were able to meet non-nutritional as well as nutritional needs, including education, transportation, and health care (Schubert and Goldberg 2004). An impressive range of similar projects are
  • 37. reviewed in Standing (2008 [2007]) and Farrington and Slater (2006). (See also the review of the potential for cash transfers in “unstable situations” that was recently done by Harvey and Holmes (2007) for the UK Department for International Development.) The arguments made by the increasingly numerous promoters of such programs are in many ways similar to those made on behalf of the South African BIG. Dispensing cash, they insist, is in the first C© 2009 The Authors Journal compilation C© 2009 Editorial Board of Antipode. 180 Antipode place more efficient and less expensive than other sorts of assistance, and often requires less infrastructure and institutional capacity. In any case, they argue, why should bureaucrats decide on behalf of recipients what their needs are? Cash transfers provide hungry people with the flexibility to access a broad range of goods and services available on the market to meet their needs. And poor people, in this conception, are good judges of how to do that—using money to go to the clinic this month, to pay school fees for a child the next, to buy a bag
  • 38. of maize meal the next, and so on. Rather than wasting the money on frivolous expenditure, advocates insist, recipients generally apply their scant cash resources very rationally, and even make canny small investments. As one PowerPoint presentation on the Kalomo project put it: “The ‘grannies’ turned out to be excellent economists!” Top-down, state-planned attempts to directly meet nutritional needs through trucking in food, in this view, are bound to be clumsy, inefficient, and wasteful. Cash transfers, on the other hand, put more decision- making power in the hands of those who know their predicament best—the hunger afflicted—and empower them to use the flexibility and efficiency of markets to help solve their own problems. Unlike direct food aid, cash transfers can have a catalytic effect on many other income-gaining activities, thereby contributing powerfully to the “multiple livelihood strategies” that are so important in keeping the poorest households afloat. Such arguments recall Jane Guyer’s (1989) groundbreaking work on feeding African cities. Consider, Guyer suggests, how food ends up finding its way to consumers’ plates in the vast megacities of West Africa such as Lagos. The logistical task of moving thousands
  • 39. of tons of food each day from thousands of local producers to millions of urban consumers would be beyond the organizational capacity of any state (to say nothing of the less-than-exemplary Nigerian one). Here, market mechanisms, drawing on the power of vast self-organizing networks, are very powerful, and very efficient. Such forms of organization must appear especially attractive where states lack capacity (and let us remember how many progressive dreams in Africa have crashed on the rocks of low state capacity). Why should relying on this sort of mechanism be inherently right- wing, or suspect in the eyes of progressives? The answer is, of course, not far to find: markets serve only those with purchasing power. Market- based solutions are thus likely to be true “solutions” only for the better- off, whose needs are so effectively catered to by markets. But the food aid example shows a way of redirecting markets toward the poor, by intervening not to restrict the market, but to boost purchasing power. I have become convinced that (at least in the case of food aid) this is probably good public policy. Is it also neoliberal? Perhaps that is not the right question. Perhaps we should rather ask: are there
  • 40. specific sorts C© 2009 The Authors Journal compilation C© 2009 Editorial Board of Antipode. The Uses of Neoliberalism 181 of social policy that might draw on characteristic neoliberal “moves” (like using markets to deliver services) that would also be genuinely progressive? That seems like a question worth asking, even if we are at this point not fully ready to answer it. Let me be clear that none of the examples discussed here are (in my view) unequivocally good (or unequivocally bad, for that matter). Instead, they leave us feeling uneasy, unsure of our moorings. They leave us less with strong opinions than with the sense that we need to think about them a bit more. They do not permit the simple denunciations (Aha! Neoliberalism!) that have become so familiar a part of the politics of the “anti-”, even as they clearly require us to turn a thoughtfully critical and skeptical eye toward their dangers and ambiguities. I also want to emphasize as clearly as possible that none of these examples is a matter of “leaving it to the market”. All require major non-market interventions (either by states or by state-like
  • 41. entities such as foundations or international agencies), and all are premised on the principle that public policy must play a major redistributive role. But they are interventions that create a situation where markets can arguably serve progressive ends, in ways that may require us to revise some of our prejudices that automatically associate market mechanisms with the interests of the well-to-do. The Point is to Change It! If we are seeking, as this special issue of Antipode aspires to do, to link our critical analyses to the world of grounded political struggle—not only to interpret the world in various ways, but also to change it—then there is much to be said for focusing, as I have here, on mundane, real- world debates around policy and politics, even if doing so inevitably puts us on the compromised and reformist terrain of the possible, rather than the seductive high ground of revolutionary ideals and utopian desires. But I would also insist that there is more at stake in the examples I have discussed here than simply a slightly better way to ameliorate the miseries of the chronically poor, or a technically superior method for relieving the suffering of famine victims.
  • 42. My point in discussing the South African BIG campaign, for instance, is not really to argue for its implementation. There is much in the campaign that is appealing, to be sure. But one can just as easily identify a series of worries that would bring the whole proposal into doubt. Does not, for instance, the decoupling of the question of assistance from the issue of labor, and the associated valorization of the “informal”, help provide a kind of alibi for the failures of the South African regime to pursue policies that would do more to create jobs? Would not the creation of a basic income benefit tied to national citizenship simply exacerbate the vicious xenophobia that already divides the South African poor, C© 2009 The Authors Journal compilation C© 2009 Editorial Board of Antipode. 182 Antipode in a context where many of the poorest are not citizens, and would thus not be eligible for the BIG? Perhaps even more fundamentally, is the idea of basic income really capable of commanding the mass support that alone could make it a central pillar of a new approach to distribution? The record to date gives powerful reasons to doubt
  • 43. it. So far, the technocrats’ dreams of relieving poverty through efficient cash transfers have attracted little support from actual poor people, who seem to find that vision a bit pale and washed out, compared with the vivid (if vague) populist promises of jobs and personalistic social inclusion long offered by the ANC patronage machine, and lately personified by Jacob Zuma (Ferguson forthcoming). My real interest in the policy proposals discussed here, in fact, has little to do with the narrow policy questions to which they seek to provide answers. For what is most significant, for my purposes, is not whether or not these are good policies, but the way that they illustrate a process through which specific governmental devices and modes of reasoning that we have become used to associating with a very particular (and conservative) political agenda (“neoliberalism”) may be in the process of being peeled away from that agenda, and put to very different uses. Any progressive who takes seriously the challenge I pointed to at the start of this essay, the challenge of developing new progressive arts of government, ought to find this turn of events of considerable interest.
  • 44. As Steven Collier (2005) has recently pointed out, it is important to question the assumption that there is, or must be, a neat or automatic fit between a hegemonic “neoliberal” political-economic project (however that might be characterized), on the one hand, and specific “neoliberal” techniques, on the other. Close attention to particular techniques (such as the use of quantitative calculation, free choice, and price driven by supply and demand) in particular settings (in Collier’s case, fiscal and budgetary reform in post-Soviet Russia) shows that the relationship between the technical and the political-economic “is much more polymorphous and unstable than is assumed in much critical geographical work”, and that neoliberal technical mechanisms are in fact “deployed in relation to diverse political projects and social norms” (2005:2). As I suggested in referencing the role of statistics and techniques for pooling risk in the creation of social democratic welfare states, social technologies need not have any essential or eternal loyalty to the political formations within which they were first developed. Insurance rationality at the end of the nineteenth century had no essential vocation to provide
  • 45. security and solidarity to the working class; it was turned to that purpose (in some substantial measure) because it was available, in the right place at the right time, to be appropriated for that use. Specific ways of solving or posing governmental problems, specific institutional and intellectual mechanisms, can be combined in an almost infinite variety of ways, to C© 2009 The Authors Journal compilation C© 2009 Editorial Board of Antipode. The Uses of Neoliberalism 183 accomplish different social ends. With social, as with any other sort of technology, it is not the machines or the mechanisms that decide what they will be used to do. Foucault (2008:94) concluded his discussion of socialist government- ality by insisting that the answers to the Left’s governmental problems require not yet another search through our sacred texts, but a process of conceptual and institutional innovation. “[I]f there is a really socialist governmentality, then it is not hidden within socialism and its texts. It cannot be deduced from them. It must be invented”. But invention in the domain of governmental technique is rarely something
  • 46. worked up out of whole cloth. More often, it involves a kind of bricolage (Lévi- Strauss 1966), a piecing together of something new out of scavenged parts originally intended for some other purpose. As we pursue such a process of improvisatory invention, we might begin by making an inventory of the parts available for such tinkering, keeping all the while an open mind about how different mechanisms might be put to work, and what kinds of purposes they might serve. If we can go beyond seeing in “neoliberalism” an evil essence or an automatic unity, and instead learn to see a field of specific governmental techniques, we may be surprised to find that some of them can be repurposed, and put to work in the service of political projects very different from those usually associated with that word. If so, we may find that the cabinet of governmental arts available to us is a bit less bare than first appeared, and that some rather useful little mechanisms may be nearer to hand than we thought. Endnotes 1 I refer here to the remarkable PhD research now being carried out by Ramah McKay (Department of Anthropology, Stanford University). 2 Barchiesi (2007) gives a detailed and illuminating account of the origins of the BIG campaign and the Taylor Committee report.
  • 47. 3 As Barchiesi (2007) noted, some more conservative formulations of the BIG campaign have also made the contrary argument, that it would help move unemployed people into very low wage jobs. He also points out another important theme that I do not explore here: the implicit or explicit moralism of much of the discussion around “the social question” in South Africa. References Barchiesi F (2007) South African debates on the Basic Income Grant: Wage labour and the post-apartheid social policy. Journal of Southern African Studies 33(3):561–575 Barry A, Osborne T and Rose N (eds.) (1996) Foucault and Political Reason: Liberalism, Neo-liberalism and Rationalities of Government. Chicago: University of Chicago Press Collier S (2005) The Spatial Forms and Social Norms of “Actually Existing Neoliberalism”: Toward a Substantive Analytics. International Affairs Working Paper. New York: New School University C© 2009 The Authors Journal compilation C© 2009 Editorial Board of Antipode. 184 Antipode
  • 48. Comaroff J and Comaroff J (2000) Millennial capitalism: First thoughts on a second coming. Public Culture 12(2):291–343 Cruikshank B (1999) The Will to Empower: Democratic Citizens and Other Subject. Ithaca: Cornell University Press Davis M (2007) Planet of Slums. New York: Verso Department of Social Development (2002) Transforming the Present—Protecting the Future: Report of the Committee of Inquiry into a Comprehensive System of Social Security for South Africa. Pretoria: Government Printer Dreze J and Sen A (1991) Hunger and Public Action. New York: Oxford University Press Ewald F (1986) L’etat Providence. Paris: Bernard Grasset Farrington J and Slater R (2006) Cash transfers: Panacea for poverty reduction or money down the drain? Development Policy Review 24(5):499–511 Ferguson J (2007) Formalities of poverty: Thinking about social assistance in neoliberal South Africa. African Studies Review 50(2):71–86 Ferguson J (forthcoming) Declarations of dependence: Labor, personhood, and welfare in South Africa Fiszbein A and Schady N (2009) Conditional Cash Transfers: Reducing Present and
  • 49. Future Poverty. Washington DC: The World Bank Foucault M (2008) The Birth of Biopolitics: Lectures at the College de France, 1978– 1979. Translated by Graham Burchell. New York: Palgrave MacMillan Guyer J (ed) (1989) Feeding African Cities: Studies in Regional Social History. Manchester: Manchester University Press Harvey D (2005) A Brief History of Neoliberalism. New York: Oxford University Press Harvey P and Holmes R (2007) The Potential for Joint Programmes for Long-term Cash Transfers in Unstable Situations: A Report Commissioned by the Fragile States Team and the Equity and Rights Team of the UK Department for International Development. London: Humanitarian Policy Group, Overseas Development Institute Lévi-Strauss C (1966) The Savage Mind. Chicago: University of Chicago Press Mattisonn H and Seekings J (2003) The politics of a basic income grant in South Africa, 1996–2002. In G Standing and M Samson (eds) A Basic Income Grant for South Africa (pp 56–76). Cape Town: University of Cape Town Press Miller P and Rose N (2008) Governing the Present. Malden, Massachusetts: Polity Press Peck J (2008) Remaking laissez-faire. Progress in Human
  • 50. Geography 32(1):3–43 Rose N (1999) Powers of Freedom: Reframing Political Thought. New York: Cambridge University Press Schubert B and Goldberg J (2004) The Pilot Social Cash Transfer Scheme: Zambia. Lusaka: GTZ (Deutsche Gesellschaft für Technische Zusammenarbeit) Sen A (1983) Poverty and Famines: An Essay on Entitlement and Deprivation. New York: Oxford University Press Standing G (2008 [2007]) How Cash Transfers Boost Work and Economic Security. DESA Working Paper No. 50. New York: United Nations Department of Economic and Social Affairs Standing G and Samson M (eds) (2003) A Basic Income Grant for South Africa. Cape Town: University of Cape Town Press Tilton D (2005) BIG Fact Sheet #1, http://www.big.org.za/index.php?option=articles& task=viewarticle&artid=5 Accessed 11 September 2005 USAID/OFDA (2004) Evaluation of OFDA Cash for Relief Intervention in Ethiopia. Prepared by Robert H. Brandstetter. Washington DC: United States Agency for International Development (USAID) C© 2009 The Authors
  • 51. Journal compilation C© 2009 Editorial Board of Antipode. Copyright of Antipode is the property of Wiley-Blackwell and its content may not be copied or emailed to multiple sites or posted to a listserv without the copyright holder's express written permission. However, users may print, download, or email articles for individual use. The Case of Jesse Gelsinger The Story When Jesse Gelsinger was growing up in New Jersey, he was diagnosed at the Children’s Hospital of Philadelphia with OTC (ornithine transcarbamylase) deficiency, a rare genetic disorder affecting about one of every eighty thousand babies. An OTC deficiency means a person lacks an enzyme in liver cells that converts the nitrogen, generated when the body absorbs protein, into urea that can be excreted by the kidneys. Unless this conversion occurs the nitrogen builds up in the blood as excessive ammonia, and this causes neurological damage and liver problems. Most babies with OTC deficiency die not long after birth. The genetic mutation that causes this problem is located on the X chromosome. Women have two X chromosomes, so a defective gene on one of them makes them carriers but with few or no symptoms because their normal gene usually functions well. Men, however, have only one X chromosome, so if they happen to receive the defective X chromosome from their
  • 52. mothers (a 50 percent chance), they inherit the life-threatening OTC deficiency disease. Jesse’s mother, however, was not a carrier. Doctors therefore attributed his OTC deficiency to spontaneous mutations in some of his liver cells. Hence, his OTC deficiency was mild and his disease was manageable as long as he stayed on a low-protein diet and took his medications. In September 1998, when Jesse was seventeen and living in Arizona with his father, Paul, and his stepmother, a physician monitoring his disease at a metabolic clinic informed him and his father that researchers at the University of Pennsylvania were working on a clinical trial to see whether they could find a cure for OTC deficiency. The physician described the trial as “gene therapy.” The subject of the clinical trial and “gene therapy” came up again during Jesse’s visit to the metabolic clinic in April 1999. Both Jesse and Paul were interested in pursuing it and, since the family was already planning a trip to New Jersey in June, they agreed to visit the Institute for Human Gene Therapy (IHGT) at the University of Pennsylvania to see whether Jesse would be a candidate for the “gene therapy” clinical trial, which was already under way. The design of the clinical trial, titled “Recombinant Adenovirus Gene Transfer in Adults with Partial Ornithine Transcarbamylase Deficiency,” was relatively simple. Researchers were engineering an adenovirus (which gives us colds by working its way into our cells) so it would not replicate once it invaded the liver cells. Then they inserted good genes with the OTC capability into the altered virus and infused the altered virus carrying the good genes into the liver. Researchers hoped that the healthy genes in the liver would soon produce enough OTC to overcome the deficiency and prevent ammonia from building up in the body. At this point researchers were conducting only a phase I trial, that is, a trial
  • 53. to see how high a load of the OTC gene-bearing viruses they could safely infuse into people’s livers without causing adverse reactions. For the phase I trial they were looking to recruit eighteen adults who either had some OTC deficiency or who were carriers. Originally researchers had hoped to try the experiment on babies suffering from the OTC deficiency, but a well-known ethicist who was then at the university, Arthur Caplan, had raised objections to this plan. Caplan argued that the parents of children dying from OTC deficiency would be so devastated that many would agree to enroll their child in a clinical trial out of desperation, and their informed consent would not be truly voluntary. Moreover, the proposed trial was a phase I study where the goal was not to evaluate a therapeutic benefit but to see whether the intervention had unacceptable side effects, a distinction that desperate parents might not well understand. Researchers planned to divide the eighteen participants into groups of three, with two women and one man in each group. Their plan was to give the three people in the first group a low dose of the altered virus and then monitor them for side effects for at least three weeks. If all went well, they would give the second group of three a higher dose of the altered virus and monitor them for three weeks, then infuse the third group with an even higher dose, and so forth. The women would receive the virus first, and only if the dose did not cause adverse reactions in them would the researchers give it to the man in the group, who would be more seriously affected by the OTC deficiency. Researchers were now nearing the end of the phase I clinical study; Jesse would be the third member of the sixth group, the last person to receive the altered virus. In June 1999 Jesse and his father met with Dr. Steven Raper at the University of Pennsylvania. Since Jesse turned eighteen that month, he would be old enough to give voluntary informed
  • 54. consent for the clinical trial. Raper, a surgeon involved with the gene transfer trial, explained the procedure to him and his father. He would insert a catheter into the artery leading to Jesse’s liver and a second one into a vein leading from his liver. He would put the modified adenovirus with the healthy genes into the artery leading to the liver. Hopefully the virus with the genes would invade liver cells and thus deliver the good genes. A check of the blood in the vein leaving the liver would indicate how much of the gene-bearing virus remained in the liver. By measuring the viral input and output researchers could determine whether the liver was absorbing the virus with the good genes embedded in it. A week later they would do a needle biopsy of the liver to confirm the results of the attempted gene transfer. Dr. Raper told Jesse that there were risks involved. He would probably develop some flu-like symptoms after the infusion of the virus and there was some small chance of hepatitis, which he said could be treated. There was also a remote possibility that Jesse might die from the liver biopsy (Dr. Raper told him that the risk of death from a liver biopsy is about one in ten thousand). Dr. Raper also made it clear that the clinical trial, even if it worked as they hoped, would not reverse Jesse’s OTC deficiency because his immune system would reject the virus with the healthy genes in a matter of weeks. On the other hand, if the gene transfer was successful, then it would be a big step forward toward developing a genetic therapy for babies with the OTC deficiency as well as for dozens of other genetic diseases affecting the liver. Both Paul and Jesse agreed to participate if tests showed that Jesse would be a good candidate for the clinical trial. A month later Dr. Mark Batshaw, another one of the physicians conducting the study, wrote both Paul and Jesse in Arizona about the clinical trial and then spoke with them by phone. According to Paul Gelsinger, Dr. Batshaw said that the
  • 55. treatment had worked temporarily in mice, even preventing death when mice were injected with lethal doses of ammonia. He also said that there were about twenty-five other liver disorders affecting five hundred thousand people in the United States and 12 million worldwide that could be treated with the same technique if it worked and that a recent human participant in the study had experienced a 50 percent increase in her ability to excrete ammonia. In other words, the research was showing signs of therapeutic value that could benefit millions of people. This clinched it for Jesse and his father; they considered this promising news and became excited about participating in the “genetic therapy” research at IHGT. The chief investigator in the study was Dr. James Wilson, the head of the IHGT at the University of Pennsylvania. He had become interested in developing genetic therapies for liver diseases after reading about a well-known patient named Stormie Jones, a young girl whose liver cells had a genetic mutation that prevented the liver from removing LDL cholesterol from the blood. This genetic defect allows high levels of the dangerous LDL cholesterol (the “bad” cholesterol) to develop in the body, and most patients suffering from it die prematurely from heart attacks. Stormie was in imminent danger of dying from very high LDL cholesterol levels when she received a heart and liver transplant. The transplanted liver began removing LDL from her blood stream and the healthy transplanted heart gave her a new lease on life. Wilson began to think it would be better for patients if a way could be found to insert normal cells into their liver rather than transplanting a liver. In experiments on human participants, which began in 1992, Wilson and other researchers surgically removed part of the person’s liver, cultured cells from it in the laboratory, used retroviruses to convey healthy genes into the DNA of these liver cells, and then infused the modified cells back into the liver
  • 56. through a catheter in the artery leading to the liver. Eighteen months after performing the procedure on a twenty-eight-year- old research subject, Wilson reported in 1994 that the genetic intervention was safe and had successfully lowered the person’s LDL level. Wilson realized, however, that removing cells from a patient, modifying them in vitro, and then putting them back into the patient would have limited use in genetic therapy. A more promising procedure would be the development of what he called “injectable genes.” Doctors would be able to transfer healthy genes directly into the body’s liver cells, perhaps by viruses. If it worked, this would be an in vivo genetic therapy. In animal experiments, Wilson was actually able to lower the cholesterol level of rabbits by injecting healthy genes into their bloodstream. Wilson soon began working on another genetic disease of liver cells, the OTC deficiency. He thought he could overcome this deficiency by using modified viruses to carry healthy cells with the OTC enzyme directly into the liver so there would be no need to remove part of the liver and add the genes in the laboratory. Scientists and biotech companies were watching his work with great interest. If it worked many people could be cured of diseases caused by deleterious mutations on the genes in liver cells and biotech companies could make a lot of money thanks to patent protection for the engineered viruses that could reverse the diseases. Jesse flew to Philadelphia on September 10, 1999. Dr. Raper inserted the catheters on the following Monday, and a large dose of the modified virus with the healthy genes flowed into Jesse’s liver. As expected, Jesse suffered flu-like symptoms that evening. Soon, however, things got worse. He spiked a high fever and rapidly deteriorated. Before long he was in a coma, on a ventilator, and receiving dialysis. Then he needed
  • 57. extracorporeal membrane oxygenation. By Thursday he was so bloated that his father hardly recognized him. On Friday morning it was obvious that he had suffered massive brain damage and that his organs were shutting down. After the family gathered and a chaplain said a prayer, a doctor withdrew the life support and Jesse was pronounced dead at 2:30 p.m. An autopsy failed to identify the cause of the problem that led to his death. Obviously the infusion of the altered viruses caused a reaction that killed him, but doctors could not figure out why. Paul Gelsinger, shocked over the loss of his son, nonetheless supported the doctors and felt that they had done the best they could. The doctors at IHGT promised to conduct a complete investigation and to inform Paul of everything they discovered. About two months after Jesse’s funeral, Dr. Wilson, the head of the Institute and the sponsor and chief investigator of the OTC deficiency study, flew to Arizona and met with Paul Gelsinger. He explained that Jesse’s death was totally unexpected and still remained unexplained. He spoke of how important the work of his IHGT was, and he sought Paul’s continued support. He asked Paul to come to a three-day meeting of RAC in December that would be reviewing the clinical trial. Paul agreed and flew to Philadelphia where he visited Wilson’s IHGT and then drove to Bethesda, Maryland, the next day for the RAC meetings. As the RAC meeting progressed, however, Paul began to see another side of the clinical trial that took the life of his son. He heard FDA officials say that Jesse should not have been infused with the virus because his ammonia level was too high at that time. Originally candidates with blood ammonia levels of more than 50 were not considered eligible to participate; later researchers raised that level to 70. When Jesse arrived in Philadelphia for the clinical procedure, his blood ammonia level was 114, and NIH officials said that he should not have been
  • 58. considered eligible for the trial. However, researchers had lowered his level somewhat with medication before they infused the virus. Paul also learned that researchers had failed to report to the FDA in a timely manner or to inform him and his son that some earlier participants experienced significant side effects from the viral infusions. He also learned that the informed consent form that Jesse signed differed from the one the FDA had approved, and it in fact omitted the important information that two monkeys had died in animal studies after being given high doses of the virus. Paul now began to think that Jesse had signed the informed consent form without being well informed about possible side effects and risks. He also heard that the viral infusions had not provided any clinically significant therapeutic impact on earlier participants, something that raised questions in his mind about Dr. Batshaw’s remarks that one woman achieved a 50 percent gain in ammonia excretion. Based on that remark, both he and Jesse had thought the research was showing some sign of therapeutic advantage. Paul was also upset to learn that researchers had not provided NIH, which funded the study, or the FDA, which monitored it, or the IRB at the University that oversaw it with other information in a timely manner, as was required by federal regulations. In remarks to reporters outside the RAC meeting Dr. Wilson objected to the FDA criticisms. He insisted that no data from either animal or human studies foretold that Jesse would die; that the FDA was eventually told of the two participants who experienced the side effects before Jesse was infused, yet it did not stop the study; and that the ammonia level in Jesse’s liver was functioning within the protocol parameters when he was enrolled in the study three months before his infusion. Wilson, however, did not respond to criticisms about the informed
  • 59. consent form and he declined to take questions. On February 14, 2000, the IHGT responded formally to FDA criticisms and pointed out, among other things, that every patient did give informed consent for the clinical trial; that the two monkeys who died were in a genetic experiment for a different problem, colorectal cancer; and that there was no evidence that the high ammonia level in Jesse was a cause of his death. However, these remarks still left important questions unanswered. Simply because there is a record of informed consent does not mean that the person actually had all the information he needed to give informed consent. And the issue about the two monkeys is not that they received a different gene for a different problem but that they received a similar viral vector to transport genes into their bodies. And it is true that there is no evidence that Jesse’s high ammonia level caused his death, but the point of the FDA criticism was that the approved protocol did not allow researchers to infuse the virus into participants with such high ammonia levels, and researchers are expected to abide by the approved protocols. After months of publicly supporting the doctors at the university and their research despite the loss of his son, Paul Gelsinger now became their critic and soon sought legal redress. Before looking at what happened next, we consider the case from an ethical point of view. Ethical Analysis Situational awareness. We are aware of the following facts in the Gelsinger story: 1. When Jesse was seventeen, both he and his father heard of some important “gene therapy” research at the University of Pennsylvania for people suffering from OTC deficiency, a genetic condition that takes the life of so many afflicted
  • 60. children. He and his father were interested in participating in the “gene therapy” research because they believed it might save the lives of babies and might even lead to something down the road that would help Jesse so he could eat a normal diet and not need medications to control his condition. When he turned eighteen, Jesse visited the Institute for Human Gene Therapy at the University and consented to becoming a participant in the phase I trial. According to his father, part of his reason was to do something that would allow development of a genetic therapy to help prevent future babies from being ravaged by the deadly disease. 2. Unlike most children with OTC deficiency, Jesse’s disease was controlled with medications and a low-protein diet. However, the teenager found taking his medications was a hassle. He did not always take them on schedule or stay on his diet, and he suffered occasional relapses. Dealing with his disease sometimes left him frustrated and angry. At one point, he actually jumped out of his father’s vehicle in a fit of anger while it was still moving, and his arm ended up under a wheel. It is possible that Jesse hoped for a long shot—that enough progress could be made so a genetic therapy might actually benefit him by allowing him to go off his medications and enjoy a normal diet. 3. Dr. James Wilson, chief of Molecular Medicine and Genetics at the University of Pennsylvania and head of its Institute for Human Gene Therapy, was a leading researcher in the field of genetic research on liver diseases. Wilson thought it might be possible to transfer healthy liver genes into patients. 4. Jesse was the eighteenth and last participant in the phase I OTC deficiency clinical trial, and he would receive the highest dose of the viral vector with the healthy genes. 5. NIH funded the clinical trial and the FDA approved it. The
  • 61. FDA provided oversight and required progress reports, especially about adverse reactions if they occurred. There was some hesitation when the trial was first proposed because putting large amounts (trillions) of viruses into people is risky business. Viruses will trigger, and may overload, the immune system even though the viruses have been engineered not to replicate. Actually some earlier participants in the OTC trial did experience some adverse effects that should have been reported to the FDA, but the doctors did not inform the Gelsingers of this. 6. Researchers at the University of Pennsylvania were also doing animal studies that used adenoviruses to transfer genes. Two monkeys in one experiment had died and a third became ill, but the physicians did not inform the Gelsingers of these deaths. 7. Inserting genes into a person’s body is a major challenge. Genes are mostly in the nucleus of our cells, and there is much we do not yet know about the DNA molecule that harbors them. Viruses have the capability of getting into the DNA of our cells (an adenovirus is what causes the common cold), so they are promising vehicles for transferring genes. The trick, of course, is to render the virus harmless and then use it to transport healthy genes into the DNA of the cells. 8. Genetic research is more challenging than drug research because we have to study not only the impact of the agent (the altered genes) on the body but also the impact of the vehicle we use to transfer the altered genes into the body. The vehicle, or “vector” as it is called, is often a virus, and putting massive doses of viruses into a person’s body even without any altered genes can trigger or even overwhelm the immune system. 9. The Bayh–Dole Act of 1980 allows universities to patent their discoveries and then assign patent rights to biotech
  • 62. companies in order to develop the discoveries into commercial products. The universities like the Bayh–Dole Act because it allows them to collect license fees and royalties from the biotech products their researchers develop. Academic researchers like the act because it allows them an opportunity to profit from their research by investing in biotech companies that could support their research and then market what might be commercially viable. Both the university and Dr. Wilson had invested in a company known as Genovo, a biotechnology company that Wilson and others had founded. The university’s equity share in Genovo was 5 percent and Wilson’s share was 30 percent. We are also aware of numerous good and bad features in the case: 1. Clinical trials with human participants are essential for medical progress, and they have done a tremendous amount of good. Medical research cannot progress very far without them, especially when it comes to drugs, medical devices, and genetic alterations. 2. People who volunteer for clinical trials do so for a number of reasons. Some are dying and will try anything, some do it for money (some trials pay the participants) or free health care, some do it in the hope they will receive therapeutic benefit, and some do it with a sense of altruism because they want to help researchers find a cure for diseases that afflict or kill others. Jesse was not dying and he did not do it for the money. His father indicated that Jesse had a desire to help find a cure for the lethal disease that affects babies as well as hope that researchers might find something that could benefit him. These motivations are morally sound in a virtue-based ethics that focuses on flourishing and helping others to flourish. 3. Medical researchers inevitably find themselves enmeshed in
  • 63. numerous conflicts of interest. A major interest of ethical research is, or should be, protecting human participants from harm, but numerous other interests can conflict with this. First, good medical researchers have an intense interest in accomplishing successful breakthroughs, and this can clash with their responsibility to protect human participants in research from harm. Second, researchers often have an interest in winning recognition for their work and in seeing it published and accepted, and this can clash with protecting human participants. Third, medical researchers, especially if they are trained physicians, often have an interest in finding something that will help many future patients, and this can clash with protecting the small number of human participants in their clinical trials. Fourth, in the more than thirty years since the 1980 Bayh–Dole Act, many researchers and their nonprofit academic institutions have developed an intense interest in profiting financially when they develop something with great commercial value. Obviously the desire to bring a treatment to market rapidly can clash with the responsibility to protect carefully the people enrolled in the clinical trials. 4. Researchers had a moral responsibility to provide adequate and honest information to the Gelsingers when they recruited Jesse for the clinical trial. They also had a responsibility to provide timely information about adverse events to the university IRB, to the NIH, and to the FDA. They also had a responsibility to adhere strictly to the approved protocols for the clinical research. Published reports indicate numerous lapses of their responsibilities in these areas, and this is bad for the participants in the research and it is bad for clinical trials in general because people will not volunteer if they think doctors are acting irresponsibly. Prudential Reasoning in the Gelsinger Story Participant’s perspective.Is it morally reasonable for a teenage
  • 64. person in Jesse’s position to agree to enter a clinical trial such as this? Based on the information he was given and the guidance of his father, it is hard to fault his decision to enter the trial. He expected flu-like symptoms that would pass. The informed consent form also noted that the altered virus could be toxic to his liver, but he was reassured that this could be treated. His biggest worry seemed to be the liver biopsy, with its very slight risk of death. The problem, of course, is that he and his father did not receive important information about the adverse effects of the virus transfer in monkeys or in previous participants in the trial, nor did they receive any concrete information about the financial arrangements involving Dr. Wilson, the IHDT, and the University of Pennsylvania. It should be noted that at the end of the eleven-page informed consent form was a statement indicating that both Dr. Wilson and the university had “financial interest in a successful outcome.” The problem, of course, is that Jesse and his father had no idea what that interest was or that it involved millions of dollars. Parent’s perspective. Jesse’s father, Paul, provided a great deal of guidance and support for his son. It is hard to fault his role based on the information he was given. Later he pursued legal action against the researchers, which also is morally reasonable in a case such as this because the researchers did not disclose important information and great harm was done: the clinical trial caused the death of a relatively healthy teenager who had no need of genetic therapy to control his genetic disease. Paul has continued to speak and write about the tragedy, and this has served to call attention to the need to improve patient protection in clinical trials. Researchers’ perspective. There are good moral reasons for doing research with human participants designed to develop genetic therapies correcting mutations in human liver cells. Someday genetic research might lead to a significant revolution in medicine that will help many human beings. It is not morally
  • 65. reasonable, however, for researchers not to meticulously follow the approved protocols; not to inform prospective participants of adverse reactions in previous subjects, or of animal deaths in viral transfers, or of financial arrangements relevant to clinical research; and not to provide timely information required by the protocols and by regulations to the NIH, the FDA, and the local IRB that oversee the clinical trial. University’s perspective. Officials at the University of Pennsylvania were aware of some of the conflicts of interest between Wilson’s work as a university faculty member and his significant financial stake in Genovo, a company he cofounded to market the products of his research. In 1994 the university’s Conflicts of Interest Standing Committee (CISC) had looked into the conflicts of interest that would exist between Wilson’s research and the potential for great financial gain for him and his company that the research could generate. The CISC made an effort to reduce the potential negative impact of this conflict by imposing some restrictions on Wilson: he could not sit on Genovo’s scientific board, he could not be paid for his work as a consultant for Genovo, and he could not do clinical studies funded by Genovo. Yet the university allowed Dr. Wilson to own 30 percent of Genovo stock, and it accepted an equity share in Genovo for itself. The university also agreed that the IHGT could accept $4 million a year for five years from Genovo for genetic research, and in return it allowed Genovo to seek licenses and patents and to earn profit on future developments by the IHGT or its researchers. They also agreed to accept $25,000 a year from Genovo toward the salary of Arthur Caplan, the well-known bioethicist then at the university. Professor Caplan was professor of bioethics in the Department of Molecular and Cellular Engineering, which Dr. Wilson chaired at that time. The Aftermath
  • 66. In December 1999 the NIH and the FDA held the hearings in Bethesda regarding the clinical trial, and Paul Gelsinger attended. After investigating the circumstances surrounding Jesse Gelsinger’s death, the NIH reminded all researchers with similar genetic experiments that federal regulations required them to report adverse events that occur in the trials. Up to that point 39 adverse events in genetic experiments had been reported; after the NIH reminder the number suddenly jumped to 691! Clearly scientists were routinely disregarding the NIH reporting regulations. On January 21, 2000, the FDA shut down all clinical genetic trials at the University of Pennsylvania due to numerous regulatory violations. In August 2000 Targeted Genetics Corporation, a biotech company, acquired Genovo. Published reports indicate that Wilson’s equity interest in Genovo brought him $13.5 million in Targeted Genetics stock and that the university’s equity interest in the company was worth $1.4 million at the time of the sale. In September 2000, one year after Jesse died, his family brought a wrongful death/fraud/intentional misrepresentation lawsuit against the university, the Children’s National Medical Center (CNMC) in Washington, the Children’s Hospital of Philadelphia, doctors Wilson, Raper, Batshaw, and Kelley (the dean of the medical school), Genovo, and the bioethicist Arthur Caplan. The suit alleged, among other things, that the informed consent process was seriously flawed because the defendants failed to inform Jesse and his family of the risks to him suggested by the illness and death of the monkeys and failed to disclose the adverse effects the virus had caused in some earlier human participants. It also alleged that the defendants failed to disclose adequately the conflict of interest that existed on the part of Dr. Wilson and the university due to their financial interests in seeing Genovo succeed by bringing the viral vector
  • 67. to market as rapidly as possible. The implication of the lawsuit was that the researchers and the university cut corners in the clinical trial in their haste to develop what would be a blockbuster biotech product. The defendants in the lawsuit decided not to defend their actions in court. About a month after the lawsuit was filed, they quickly agreed to settle the case out of court and paid the Gelsinger family an undisclosed amount of money, estimated by some reports to be in the neighborhood of $10 million. Both the FDA and the Justice Department continued their investigations, In February 2002 the FDA formally notified Dr. Wilson that he had failed to address adequately numerous issues that the FDA had raised about the clinical trial, among them: • The study was not stopped as required by the approved protocol after some participants developed grade 3 or higher toxicities. • Researchers injected the virus into subjects that did not meet the criteria required by the approved protocol. • Researchers injected the virus into a male as the second person in a group of three despite written agreement that the sequence in each group of three would be two females followed by one male (males with the disease are more at risk than female carriers). • Researchers failed to perform prestudy ammonia tests on three days and one day before the viral infusion on all participants as required by the protocol. • Researchers failed to submit accurate and timely reports to the IRB. In the annual report to the IRB in August 1997 Dr. Wilson stated that the first person in the study developed mild anemia probably because so much blood was drawn and that the next two participants did not develop anemia after the amount of blood drawn was reduced. In fact, however, those two participants actually did develop grade 1 anemias, but this was
  • 68. not reported. In the annual IRB report of August 1998, after the first ten participants had received the virus, Dr. Wilson stated that “there have been no significant treatment-related or procedure-related toxicities,” when in fact a significant adverse event had occurred on June 25, 1998. Also, the 1998 annual report did not present a table of adverse events according to the protocol; this information was not submitted until the 1999 annual report. In the annual report of August 1999 Dr. Wilson stated: “No serious adverse effects have occurred as a result of this study.” The FDA alleged this statement is false because the record shows there were some serious adverse effects, namely, grade 3 toxicities in six participants. • The protocol stated that researchers will halt the study if a single participant develops a grade 3 or higher toxicity, yet they did not halt the study despite instances of grade 3 toxicities in dose cohorts 4, 5, and 6. • Researchers failed to obtain proper informed consent in accord with federal regulations. The FDA requested that Dr. Wilson inform participants not to donate blood or gametes, and he confirmed in writing that he had added that information to the consent form when in fact this information was not in the informed consent form. Researchers also failed to inform potential participants that higher doses of the virus were associated with DIC (disseminated intravascular coagulation—a life-threatening generalized bleeding that is hard to stop) in monkeys and might cause a similar problem for humans. Three monkeys received viral vectors in late 1998; one received the same virus vector as the humans and the other two a different vector, but all three developed DIC. Yet the consent form was never changed to reflect this important fact, and Jessie did in fact develop DIC after he received the virus. Researchers also failed to inform the later participants in the trial that, in addition to “flu-like symptoms,” they were likely to experience significant periods of chills, nausea, and vomiting. Moreover, the protocol said that they would be given only Tylenol for discomfort when in fact researchers had to use other pain
  • 69. medications to reduce the discomfort participants were experiencing. In April 2002 Wilson relinquished his post as director of the IHGT. In September 2002 Dateline NBC did a program on Jesse’s death and the family’s search for answers. In February 2003 BBC Two devoted a program to the tragic story. In February 2005 the US Department of Justice announced a civil settlement in the case that the department had brought against the institutions and the researchers involved in the OTC trial. The Department of Justice had accused the researchers (Wilson, Raper, and Batshaw) and their institutions (the University of Pennsylvania and CNMC) of violating the civil False Claims Act between July 1998 and September 1999 by (1) submitting false statements and claims on the grant applications, progress reports, and annual reports submitted to the NIH; (2) submitting false statements and claims to the FDA, which was monitoring the research; (3) submitting false statements to the IRBs, which reviewed the research over a period of several years; and (4) submitting false statements and claims that prevented the human research participants from giving properly informed consent. In the settlement with the Department of Justice the University of Pennsylvania agreed to pay a fine of $517,496 and CNMC agreed to pay a fine of $514,622. The Department of Justice settlement did not require Dr. Wilson and the other physicians to pay fines, but it did impose restrictions on their work. Dr. Wilson, as the sponsor of the FDA-regulated clinical trial paid for by NIH, had to agree not to participate in research involving human subjects until he completed training in protecting human subjects. He also had to accept severe restrictions on his research with human participants until February 2010. Dr. Wilson also agreed in the settlement to lecture and write an article on the lessons learned from the OTC study, and to
  • 70. include statements from the Gelsinger family in the article. Wilson’s article on lessons learned from OTC trial in which Jesse Gelsinger died was published online and in print four years later, in 2009. Two other physicians involved in the research, Mark Batshaw and Steven Raper, were also required to complete training in protecting human subjects, and both had restrictions placed on their clinical research for three years. As is customary in this kind of settlement, the accused parties (the two institutions and the three physicians) did not admit the allegations and contended that their behavior was at all times lawful and appropriate. In January 2008 Dr. Wilson, as the editor-in-chief of the journal Human Gene Therapy, wrote an editorial on adverse events in gene transfer trials in which he encouraged “genetic therapy” organizations to put in place more effective ways for human participants in clinical trials to have “a full and unbiased understanding of the risks and benefits of their participation.” The editorial mentioned the adverse events in the severe combined immune deficiency (SCID) and arthritis trials discussed in the next section but did not mention the adverse events and the death of Jesse Gelsinger in his OTC trial at the University of Pennsylvania. In the same issue of Human Gene Therapy, two authors recommended the appointment of advocates to help people considering participation in genetic experiments to understand the risks of genetic research and to advise them whether participation in a study is truly in their best interest. Yet more than a participant-advocate was needed in the Gelsinger case. Jesse needed to know about numerous major problems in his clinical trial—namely, the failure of researchers to provide information about the recent monkey deaths; the failure of researchers to inform him (and the IRBs, the FDA, and the NIH)