SlideShare a Scribd company logo
1 of 9
Download to read offline
Invited talk
Interdisciplinary Colloquium, University of Helsinki, 26-27 September 2003
published in Human Approaches to the Universe, E. Martikainen (ed.) Luther-Agricola
Seura, Helsinki, 2005, pp 66-74.
Reflecting on the huge amount of information provided by his senses
 man is confronted with a very fundamental question: is there a reality that
 can not be reached by senses even not with the aid of sophisticated instru-
 ments? Is there a reality, which does not obey the physical laws of nature?
This is certainly a philosophical question that is answered differently in dif-
ferent metaphysical systems, but as will be shown below, certain experiences
support or make difficult certain metaphysical systems. For example, Aristo-
tle based his metaphysics on the everyday experience of the occurrence of real
changes. In the philosophy of Parmenides these changes were considered to
be only apparent and not based on reality. Hs philosophy, therefore should
                                             i
and has in hct be disregarded.
    Today the empirical hcts have largely been increased, and, what is proba-
bly more important, these hcts are only accessible to a s m d number ofwell-
prepared specialists. How can a philosopher understand these new empirical
facts - often only expressed in the highly formalized language of physicists,
                                    -
mathematicians or other scientists and evaluate their relevance with regard
to his metaphysics?Not to speak about a scientific discussion on the validity
of these hcts.
    In the following an attempt is made to analyze an important mathemati-
cal discovery, the theorem of Godel and to demonstrate that the acceptance
of this theorem has a direct impact on the consistency of metaphysical sys-
tems. It will be shown that there are elements of reality, in this case the hu-
man intellect, that can perform actions that exceed the potential of operators
exclusively subjected to physical laws.
    To make it very clear, the Godel theorem is in the field of pure mathemat-
ics. The philosopher as philosopher can not decide on the rightness of this
theorem. What he, instead can do, is evaluating the general acceptance of this
mathematical finding and reflect on the consistency between consequences
of the mathematical theorem with consequences of his metaphysical view.
    In the following the contribution of three mathematicians will be pre-
sented: first Gode12 himself, then the further elaboration by Turin2 and fi-
nally the consequences for the human mind as worked out by Penrose4.
Schins5,6 presented in several contributions the basic ideas of these authors.
In this paper often use will be made of his argumentations. Finally we will
present a philosophical evaluation.


2. The Godel incompleteness theowm

In order to grasp the impact of the work of Godel one has to consider the
foundation of mathematics at the beginning of the 20h century. There was
a strong school considering mathematics just a product of human logic. In
this view it is principally possible to arrive at any mathematical truth by
applying exclusively a set of axioms and formal deduction. The German
mathematician David Hilbert expresses this conviction by: In Mathematics
there is no I p o r a b i m d . He formulated in 1900 the 10 last real problems
of mathematics to be solved. The last of these, the ~ n a c h e i d u n ~ ~ r o b k m ,
concerned the existence of an algorithm able to solve general classes of
mathematical problemss. The s o h i o n of this problem would be the tri-
umph of the formalistic approach: just following an algorithm, i.e. a se-
quence of deductive steps one would arrive on the solution. The question
of meaning would be irrelevant; as long as the formal procedures would be
used one would arrive at the mathematical truth.
    In his communication of 1931, Godelz, an Austrian mathematician,
demonstrated the fundamental inadequacy of the pure formal approach.
He proved that in every consistent, sufficiently general axiomatic system
(i.e., systems which are based on axioms and specific rules of deduction)

 there always exists a true proposition which cannot be deduced fiom the
 axioms (Godel's incompleteness theorem);
 the consistency of the axioms cannot be deduced from the axioms
 (Godel's consistency theorem).

   In both theorems Godel states that a certain mathematical truth cannot
be obtained exclusively by deduction, i.e. exclusively by a formal approach.
Mathematical meaning and mathematical truth are relevant concepts not
reducible to formal logic. To prove his incompleteness theorem, Godel
provides a proposition whose correctness and truth everyone with a mini-
 mum of mathematical education can confirm, but which is undecidable
 within the formal system in question. It is here not the place to follow in
 detail the proof of Godel; it is, however, worthwhile to express in words
 the so-called Godel proposition in the incompleteness theorem: tbm ncrjts
 no proof$r the Go&/ proposition.
    In order to get a taste of Godel's argumentation one can start with the
observation that the Godel proposition is legitimate (as is demonstrated
 formally by Godel). There are now two alternatives, there is a proof for this
 proposition or not. If there is a proof, a legitimate proposition that is for-
 mulated according the axioms of the formal system is wrong. Consequent-
ly there is a contradiction within the axiomatic system which is impossible
and the assumption has to be rejected. If there is no proof, the proposition
is true and the incompleteness theorem is correct. This is the only alterna-
tive without formal contradiction. One is therefore forced to accept the
validity of a proposition which, being true, is undecidable and cannot be
proven in the formal system.
    It is not so easy to realize the impact of the work of Godel. What direct-
ly is shown is that mathematics goes beyond applying deductive or formal
steps, also insight, intuition or meaning on a higher level come into play.
Further, no formal system is complete, as a mathematician can always -   - pro-
vide true statements-that are formally improvable.
    A first important conclusion can already be drawn now. For some phys-
icist, the rediction of physical reality to a single theory or even a single fbr-
mula would be the ultimate triumph of science. A physical theory, howev-
er, or a formula are part of a forma system, that aft& ~ 6 d ewe know to be
                                                                  l
necessarily incomplete. Reality and also physical reality is by definition
complete. The Grand Unified Theory (GUT) and other ultimate ap-
proaches will be necessarily incomplete and inadequate to describe the full
iichness of physical reality.


3. The contribution of Turing
In 1936 Turing, a mathematician inspired by Godel, conceived the ulti-
mate computer, the Turing machine3. We are used to the fact that every
three years we have a new computer with largely improved capacity. The
Turing machine is the end of any possible evolution with regard to software
as well as hardware: with infinite speed and memory, using digital logic, neu-
 ral networks, quantum logic or any other up to now known or unknown
technology for data processing. It is the best what physical laws and the most
advanced design can offer with in addition unlimited speed and unlimited
memory. With this machine any finite sequence of processing steps could be
carried out in an infinitesimally small amount of time.
     Turing posed himself the question and gave an answer with regard to the
halting-problem. Is there a general algorithm that can predict whether the
Turing machine will stop with a given program and given input? If that
would be possible, one could look for certain prepositions and demonstrate,
whether they are of the Godel-type or not. Once these have been identified,
one could isolate them and could continue with a 'clean' formal system. Tur-
ing showed that this algorithm does not exist, the algorithm that should
mark Godel-type propositions would be caught in an infinite loop in the
Turing machine.
     What can one learn from T ~ r i n g ? ~ Scientists and fiction writers are
speaking about intelligence in man-made apparatus. There is a clear evolu-
tion: increasingly processing speed, memory and code complexity is intro-
duced. But even after evolution and many centuries of future research there
will be mathematical problems, these artificial intelligence (AI) devices can
not solve. For the Turing machine, which exceeds these AI devices by fir, has
been shown to never come up with a result on well-defined algorithmic
problems.
    The question remains, would it not be fantastic if human beings would
have the capacity of the Turing machine. Would this be a step forward or
something destroying humanity in its very root? To answer this question one
should not forget that the Turing machine is the best matter or beings exclu-
sively bound to physical laws can deliver.


4. Penrose and the human mind
In his book The Emperor? new mindPenrose4 uses the results of Godel and
Turing to analyze the cognitive activity of the human mind. His argumenta-
tion is based on meta-mathematics, a level achievable by mathematicians but
not exclusively bound to formal argumentation. His argumentation starts
with two observations well within the field of mathematics.
   There are mathematical results on the truth of certain prepositions, which
can be recognized by any mathematician, but can not formally be proven (for
example the Godel preposition).
   In addition, he learns from ~ u r i nthat the ideal computing device, the
                                         ~,
so-called Turing machine, can only be used for solving problems by a fbrmal
approach.
   Penrose explains:

       The point of view that one can dispense with the meaning of mathematical srarements,
       rrgardingthem as nothing but strings of symbols in some b r d mathematical system,
       is the mathematical standpoint of brrnaism. Some people l i e this idea, whereby
       mathematics becomes a kind of 'meaningless game'. It is not an idea that appeals to me,
       hawever. It is indeed 'meanin+ot       blind algorithmic computation-that gives
       mathematics its substance.'"

    In drawing a conclusion from his meta-mathematical observations, Pen-
rose leaves mathematics and enters the field of anthropology. And his condu-
sion is that the human mind is able to carry out certain activities that artifi-
cial devices, including the Turing machine, can not. It is not the question
whether the human mind is superior in all aspects to the Turing machine, for
example in computing speed even present-day computers exceed by fir hu-
man capacity. The remarkable is that man can do something, f i r example
grasping the meaning of a mathematical truth, a machine never can do. Pen-
rose writes:

      Mathematical truth is not something that we ascertain merely by use of an algorithm. I
      believe, also, that our consciousness is a crucial ingredient in our comprehension of
      mathematical truth. We must 'see' the truth of a mathematical argument to be con-
      vinced of its validity. This 'seeing' is the very essence of consciousness. It must be
      present whenever we directly perceive mathematical truth. W e n we convince our-
      selves of the validity of W d ' s theorem we not only 'see' it, but by so doing we reveal
      the very non-algorithmic nature of the 'seeing' process itself."

   The significance of this 'seeing' a truth becomes even clearer if one uses
the equivalent Latin verb intueri or the derivative 'intuition'. The latter
points to a special intellectual activity that nearly instantaneous in a crea-
tive way is able to understand or conceive a solution to a problem. The
foundation of this peculiar intellectual capacity is, according to Penrose,
related to consciousness. One should, however have in mind that investi-
gating this foundation one is not working any more in the realm of mathe-
matics or even science in general, but more within anthropology or philos-
ophy of man and metaphysics.
    What about artificial intelligence? In the light of Penrose's conclusions
one could speak of a misleading term. A person who is able to memorize
very well or to solve certain formal problems in a rapid way, but who is
missing insight and understanding is not considered to be intelligent. And
the artificial devices like the Turing machine exclusively based on physical
laws, can do it perhaps more rapidly, but with the same fundamental lack
of insight. In stead of AT one should speak of ADP: artificial data proces-
sors.


5. Philosophical evaluation
As already stated in the introduction, the ultimate goal of the philosopher
is to find an overall consistent view where all empirical knowledge could be
integrated. With the work of Godel, Turing and Penrose one is confronted
with two different types of intellectual activity in mathematics, which both
can be carried out by humans. The astonishing thing is not the distinction
between a formalized, logic approach on the one side and intuition, math-
ematical insight and meaning on the other. Being surely relevant for the
philosophy of mathematics it does not have strong implications for the
overall view on reality. Philosophically challenging, however, is the claim
that principally only one of these approaches can be carried out by devices
bound exclusively to the laws of physical reality. Turing machines, namely,
are not able to grasp issues related to mathematical meaning, and these
machines are the best physical laws can offer
    Accepting the evidence provided by mathematics the philosopher
should allow for two aspects of reality in his metaphysics: one exclusively
bound to physical lawsand the other not. A plain, drdinary materialistic
view considering reality restricted to things that are exclusively subjected to
physical laws is not able to incorporate the distinction provided by mathe-
matics. The well-known quote by Karl Marx, Der Mensch kt, was er $3,
(The human is that what he eats) is an example of a metaphysical statement
 that refutes this distinction: a human being is like his food, i.e. something
 exclusively bound to physical laws of nature.
     Accepting the distinction suggested by mathematics the philosopher
 could provide more information about the ontological base of humans that
 allows them carrying out intellectual activities that Turing machines and
 other objects subjected exclusively to physical laws are not able to do. The
 principle of causality expressed in the classical statement agere sequitur esse
 (acting is according to the way of being) indicates that if an activity is ob-
served that exceeds the potential physical laws can offer, there should be a
subject exceeding the potential physical laws can offer. Already some of the
 Greek philosophers like Plato and Aristotle made a distinction between a
material and spiritual reality. Especially Aristotle and later Aquinas studied
the intellectual activity of human beings and found, interesting enough, a
similar distinction in two principal approaches: strict logical argumenta-
tion with syllogism, a kind of formalized, deductive or inductive mental
activity and intuition or in Greek theoria that accounts for insight and cre-
ativity.
     It is interesting to note that in the metaphysics of Aquinas an intellectu-
al activity is possible in pure spiritual beings and in man, who is composed
of a spiritual and material component. According to Aquinas it is the ma-
terial component in man that is responsible for the formal, logic intellectu-
al activity with the aid of syllogism, whereas pure spiritual intellects know
only by intuition. This is a remarkable parallelism with the findings in
mathematics. A Turing machine, being a pure material device, can do the
formalized processing, whereas only the human mind with his spiritual di-
mension according to Aquinas is able to carry out the intuitive intellectual
activity needed to grasp mathematical meaning.
    Aristotle like Aquinas did not know the Gijdel theorem but arrived by a
different analysis at the same conclusions as Penrose. This is, of course, no
proof of the validity of the metaphysics of Aristotle and Aquinas, but an
important consistency check with experience. There are, of course many
other checkpoints, but after Godel, Turing and Penrose this specific one
provided by mathematics should be taken seriously, leading in some cases
to the abandonment of certain metaphysical views, as, for example, provid-
ed by plain materialism.
CAa, E
1997 "Meaning, W and Algorithms: Implications of theTuring Theorem" in Driesen,
                    t
                    y
     A. & Suara, A. (eds.): Matimu&& Undccidnbilig Quantum Nonlocality a d thr
      Question cfdx Exiwnce ofGod. DoDordrt: Muwtr Academic Publishers.

GODEL,K
1931    "&r fbrmal uncntscheidbate S h der Principia Mathemacia und verwandtu Sys-
        tune In in M o ~ ~ f i i r M a t h c m a tudP&k
                                                  ic38.

HIUun; D.
1935 GaammcbAbbdngrn, 111. Band B& Springer Vedag.
                                   e:
1900 Mathuricd h b h (tenth problem). Paris: 2& International Con-          ofM&
     ma&.

l'mmsb R
1989 Thr Empnr,~ Mind. Oxfbrd: O h r d University Press.
               Nnu

SCHINS, J.   M.
1997    "Mathematics:A Pointer to an Independent Wy in Driessen, A. & Suara, A.
                                                        t "
        (eds.): Mathemutical Lh&d&ig      Quanrrm Noduality and& Question of dx Erric-
        mrc o W Do-t:
                f .             Kluwtr Academic Publishers.
2000    Honmlgmc kan & wtemchap uduggcn?Kampcn: Agora.

TURING,k
1936-37 "On Computable Numbers with an Application to the Entscheidungsproblemnin
        l'nndiw @thr London Matkmurical Saety, 42-43.

More Related Content

What's hot

How Physics Became a Blind Science_Crimson Publishers
How Physics Became a Blind Science_Crimson PublishersHow Physics Became a Blind Science_Crimson Publishers
How Physics Became a Blind Science_Crimson PublishersCrimsonPublishersRDMS
 
Social constructivism as a philosophy of mathematics
Social constructivism as a philosophy of mathematicsSocial constructivism as a philosophy of mathematics
Social constructivism as a philosophy of mathematicsPaul Ernest
 
Why anything rather than nothing? The answer of quantum mechnaics
Why anything rather than nothing? The answer of quantum mechnaicsWhy anything rather than nothing? The answer of quantum mechnaics
Why anything rather than nothing? The answer of quantum mechnaicsVasil Penchev
 
IS A FIELD AN INTELLIGENT SYSTEM?
IS A FIELD AN INTELLIGENT SYSTEM?IS A FIELD AN INTELLIGENT SYSTEM?
IS A FIELD AN INTELLIGENT SYSTEM?ijrap
 
Toward A Computational Theory of Everything
Toward A Computational Theory of EverythingToward A Computational Theory of Everything
Toward A Computational Theory of Everythingijrap
 
Complex thinking and the physics
Complex thinking and the physicsComplex thinking and the physics
Complex thinking and the physicsAntonio Perdomo
 
Mathematical foundations of consciousness
Mathematical foundations of consciousnessMathematical foundations of consciousness
Mathematical foundations of consciousnessPronoy Sikdar
 
Proof of impossibility
Proof of impossibilityProof of impossibility
Proof of impossibilityMoloy De
 
Advancement of scientific knowledge and complex thinking
Advancement of scientific knowledge and complex thinkingAdvancement of scientific knowledge and complex thinking
Advancement of scientific knowledge and complex thinkingFernando Alcoforado
 
The Philosophy of mathematics education 2
The Philosophy of mathematics education   2The Philosophy of mathematics education   2
The Philosophy of mathematics education 2Nailul Hasibuan
 
Consciousness as holographic quantised dimension mechanics
Consciousness as holographic quantised dimension mechanicsConsciousness as holographic quantised dimension mechanics
Consciousness as holographic quantised dimension mechanicsIstvan Dienes
 
Affection for certainty
Affection for certaintyAffection for certainty
Affection for certaintyLex Pit
 

What's hot (19)

How Physics Became a Blind Science_Crimson Publishers
How Physics Became a Blind Science_Crimson PublishersHow Physics Became a Blind Science_Crimson Publishers
How Physics Became a Blind Science_Crimson Publishers
 
Social constructivism as a philosophy of mathematics
Social constructivism as a philosophy of mathematicsSocial constructivism as a philosophy of mathematics
Social constructivism as a philosophy of mathematics
 
Why anything rather than nothing? The answer of quantum mechnaics
Why anything rather than nothing? The answer of quantum mechnaicsWhy anything rather than nothing? The answer of quantum mechnaics
Why anything rather than nothing? The answer of quantum mechnaics
 
IS A FIELD AN INTELLIGENT SYSTEM?
IS A FIELD AN INTELLIGENT SYSTEM?IS A FIELD AN INTELLIGENT SYSTEM?
IS A FIELD AN INTELLIGENT SYSTEM?
 
Toward A Computational Theory of Everything
Toward A Computational Theory of EverythingToward A Computational Theory of Everything
Toward A Computational Theory of Everything
 
Constructive Modalities
Constructive ModalitiesConstructive Modalities
Constructive Modalities
 
Complex thinking and the physics
Complex thinking and the physicsComplex thinking and the physics
Complex thinking and the physics
 
Mathematical foundations of consciousness
Mathematical foundations of consciousnessMathematical foundations of consciousness
Mathematical foundations of consciousness
 
Proof of impossibility
Proof of impossibilityProof of impossibility
Proof of impossibility
 
Longo u
Longo uLongo u
Longo u
 
Advancement of scientific knowledge and complex thinking
Advancement of scientific knowledge and complex thinkingAdvancement of scientific knowledge and complex thinking
Advancement of scientific knowledge and complex thinking
 
The Philosophy of mathematics education 2
The Philosophy of mathematics education   2The Philosophy of mathematics education   2
The Philosophy of mathematics education 2
 
Oxford jan 2017
Oxford jan 2017Oxford jan 2017
Oxford jan 2017
 
05 pml
05 pml05 pml
05 pml
 
Constructive Modalities
Constructive ModalitiesConstructive Modalities
Constructive Modalities
 
Philosophy of Mathematics
Philosophy of MathematicsPhilosophy of Mathematics
Philosophy of Mathematics
 
Consciousness as holographic quantised dimension mechanics
Consciousness as holographic quantised dimension mechanicsConsciousness as holographic quantised dimension mechanics
Consciousness as holographic quantised dimension mechanics
 
Set theory
Set theorySet theory
Set theory
 
Affection for certainty
Affection for certaintyAffection for certainty
Affection for certainty
 

Viewers also liked

Evolutie, wetenschappelijk model of seculier geloof
Evolutie, wetenschappelijk model of seculier geloofEvolutie, wetenschappelijk model of seculier geloof
Evolutie, wetenschappelijk model of seculier geloofAlfred Driessen
 
Optredens Arend Landman foto's slideshow
Optredens Arend Landman foto's slideshowOptredens Arend Landman foto's slideshow
Optredens Arend Landman foto's slideshowAndré de Boer
 
De Werken van Barmhartigheid
De Werken van BarmhartigheidDe Werken van Barmhartigheid
De Werken van BarmhartigheidAlfred Driessen
 
Chance and purpose: Can a scientist with tools of his science distinguish bet...
Chance and purpose: Can a scientist with tools of his science distinguish bet...Chance and purpose: Can a scientist with tools of his science distinguish bet...
Chance and purpose: Can a scientist with tools of his science distinguish bet...Alfred Driessen
 
Aquinas' Theory of Perception
Aquinas' Theory of PerceptionAquinas' Theory of Perception
Aquinas' Theory of PerceptionAlfred Driessen
 

Viewers also liked (8)

Cel voor Duitse moeders
Cel voor Duitse moedersCel voor Duitse moeders
Cel voor Duitse moeders
 
Evolutie, wetenschappelijk model of seculier geloof
Evolutie, wetenschappelijk model of seculier geloofEvolutie, wetenschappelijk model of seculier geloof
Evolutie, wetenschappelijk model of seculier geloof
 
Het Paas Mysterie
Het Paas MysterieHet Paas Mysterie
Het Paas Mysterie
 
Optredens Arend Landman foto's slideshow
Optredens Arend Landman foto's slideshowOptredens Arend Landman foto's slideshow
Optredens Arend Landman foto's slideshow
 
De Werken van Barmhartigheid
De Werken van BarmhartigheidDe Werken van Barmhartigheid
De Werken van Barmhartigheid
 
Chance and purpose: Can a scientist with tools of his science distinguish bet...
Chance and purpose: Can a scientist with tools of his science distinguish bet...Chance and purpose: Can a scientist with tools of his science distinguish bet...
Chance and purpose: Can a scientist with tools of his science distinguish bet...
 
What makes us human?
What makes us human?What makes us human?
What makes us human?
 
Aquinas' Theory of Perception
Aquinas' Theory of PerceptionAquinas' Theory of Perception
Aquinas' Theory of Perception
 

Similar to Reflecting on Godel's incompleteness theorem and its implications for metaphysical systems

A Procedural Interpretation Of The Church-Turing Thesis
A Procedural Interpretation Of The Church-Turing ThesisA Procedural Interpretation Of The Church-Turing Thesis
A Procedural Interpretation Of The Church-Turing ThesisDaniel Wachtel
 
Undecidable Problem
Undecidable ProblemUndecidable Problem
Undecidable ProblemMGoodhew
 
The laboratoryandthemarketinee bookchapter10pdf_merged
The laboratoryandthemarketinee bookchapter10pdf_mergedThe laboratoryandthemarketinee bookchapter10pdf_merged
The laboratoryandthemarketinee bookchapter10pdf_mergedJeenaDC
 
Gigerenzer Why Heuristics Work
Gigerenzer Why Heuristics WorkGigerenzer Why Heuristics Work
Gigerenzer Why Heuristics Workandrés Luna
 
General introduction to logic
General introduction to logicGeneral introduction to logic
General introduction to logicMUHAMMAD RIAZ
 
The logic(s) of informal proofs (tyumen, western siberia 2019)
The logic(s) of informal proofs (tyumen, western siberia 2019)The logic(s) of informal proofs (tyumen, western siberia 2019)
The logic(s) of informal proofs (tyumen, western siberia 2019)Brendan Larvor
 
COMMUNICATIONS ON PURE AND APPLIED MATHEMATICS, VOL. XIII, 001.docx
COMMUNICATIONS ON PURE AND APPLIED MATHEMATICS, VOL. XIII, 001.docxCOMMUNICATIONS ON PURE AND APPLIED MATHEMATICS, VOL. XIII, 001.docx
COMMUNICATIONS ON PURE AND APPLIED MATHEMATICS, VOL. XIII, 001.docxpickersgillkayne
 
Argumentation in Artificial Intelligence.pdf
Argumentation in Artificial Intelligence.pdfArgumentation in Artificial Intelligence.pdf
Argumentation in Artificial Intelligence.pdfSabrina Baloi
 
Philosophy and Atrificial Inteligence
Philosophy and Atrificial Inteligence Philosophy and Atrificial Inteligence
Philosophy and Atrificial Inteligence mdabrowski
 
2014 05 unibuc optimization and minimization
2014 05 unibuc optimization and minimization2014 05 unibuc optimization and minimization
2014 05 unibuc optimization and minimizationIoan Muntean
 
Understanding Computers and Cognition
Understanding Computers and CognitionUnderstanding Computers and Cognition
Understanding Computers and CognitionR. Sosa
 
The truth of science for justice and peace(4)
The truth of science for justice and peace(4)The truth of science for justice and peace(4)
The truth of science for justice and peace(4)merlyna
 

Similar to Reflecting on Godel's incompleteness theorem and its implications for metaphysical systems (20)

A Procedural Interpretation Of The Church-Turing Thesis
A Procedural Interpretation Of The Church-Turing ThesisA Procedural Interpretation Of The Church-Turing Thesis
A Procedural Interpretation Of The Church-Turing Thesis
 
Undecidable Problem
Undecidable ProblemUndecidable Problem
Undecidable Problem
 
The laboratoryandthemarketinee bookchapter10pdf_merged
The laboratoryandthemarketinee bookchapter10pdf_mergedThe laboratoryandthemarketinee bookchapter10pdf_merged
The laboratoryandthemarketinee bookchapter10pdf_merged
 
Gigerenzer Why Heuristics Work
Gigerenzer Why Heuristics WorkGigerenzer Why Heuristics Work
Gigerenzer Why Heuristics Work
 
Methodology: a real problem
Methodology: a real problemMethodology: a real problem
Methodology: a real problem
 
General introduction to logic
General introduction to logicGeneral introduction to logic
General introduction to logic
 
Logic
LogicLogic
Logic
 
The logic(s) of informal proofs (tyumen, western siberia 2019)
The logic(s) of informal proofs (tyumen, western siberia 2019)The logic(s) of informal proofs (tyumen, western siberia 2019)
The logic(s) of informal proofs (tyumen, western siberia 2019)
 
COMMUNICATIONS ON PURE AND APPLIED MATHEMATICS, VOL. XIII, 001.docx
COMMUNICATIONS ON PURE AND APPLIED MATHEMATICS, VOL. XIII, 001.docxCOMMUNICATIONS ON PURE AND APPLIED MATHEMATICS, VOL. XIII, 001.docx
COMMUNICATIONS ON PURE AND APPLIED MATHEMATICS, VOL. XIII, 001.docx
 
Prolegomena 4 0
Prolegomena 4 0Prolegomena 4 0
Prolegomena 4 0
 
Argumentation in Artificial Intelligence.pdf
Argumentation in Artificial Intelligence.pdfArgumentation in Artificial Intelligence.pdf
Argumentation in Artificial Intelligence.pdf
 
Philosophy and Atrificial Inteligence
Philosophy and Atrificial Inteligence Philosophy and Atrificial Inteligence
Philosophy and Atrificial Inteligence
 
maths project
maths projectmaths project
maths project
 
2014 05 unibuc optimization and minimization
2014 05 unibuc optimization and minimization2014 05 unibuc optimization and minimization
2014 05 unibuc optimization and minimization
 
Fuzzy logic ppt
Fuzzy logic pptFuzzy logic ppt
Fuzzy logic ppt
 
Understanding Computers and Cognition
Understanding Computers and CognitionUnderstanding Computers and Cognition
Understanding Computers and Cognition
 
The truth of science for justice and peace(4)
The truth of science for justice and peace(4)The truth of science for justice and peace(4)
The truth of science for justice and peace(4)
 
1997 Editor Comments
1997 Editor Comments1997 Editor Comments
1997 Editor Comments
 
Sociology as a science
Sociology as a scienceSociology as a science
Sociology as a science
 
Venezia cs
Venezia csVenezia cs
Venezia cs
 

More from Alfred Driessen

The quest for truth of Stephen Hawking
The quest for truth of Stephen HawkingThe quest for truth of Stephen Hawking
The quest for truth of Stephen HawkingAlfred Driessen
 
Beethoven 9th Symphony: about joy and God
Beethoven 9th  Symphony: about joy and GodBeethoven 9th  Symphony: about joy and God
Beethoven 9th Symphony: about joy and GodAlfred Driessen
 
Vrije wil, alleen een illusie?
Vrije wil, alleen een illusie?Vrije wil, alleen een illusie?
Vrije wil, alleen een illusie?Alfred Driessen
 
Causality from outside Time
Causality from outside TimeCausality from outside Time
Causality from outside TimeAlfred Driessen
 
Het heelal een ontdekkingsreis
Het heelal een ontdekkingsreisHet heelal een ontdekkingsreis
Het heelal een ontdekkingsreisAlfred Driessen
 
Achilles, the Tortoise and Quantum Mechanics
Achilles, the Tortoise and Quantum MechanicsAchilles, the Tortoise and Quantum Mechanics
Achilles, the Tortoise and Quantum MechanicsAlfred Driessen
 
De waarde van het lijden
De waarde van het lijdenDe waarde van het lijden
De waarde van het lijdenAlfred Driessen
 
Overview of Presentations in the Field of Philosophy and Science
Overview of Presentations in the Field of Philosophy and ScienceOverview of Presentations in the Field of Philosophy and Science
Overview of Presentations in the Field of Philosophy and ScienceAlfred Driessen
 
The Universe as a Computer Game
The Universe as a Computer GameThe Universe as a Computer Game
The Universe as a Computer GameAlfred Driessen
 
het huwelijk in de Bijbel
het huwelijk in de Bijbelhet huwelijk in de Bijbel
het huwelijk in de BijbelAlfred Driessen
 
Het dubbele gezicht van de evolutie
Het dubbele gezicht van de evolutie Het dubbele gezicht van de evolutie
Het dubbele gezicht van de evolutie Alfred Driessen
 
Commentaar op de encycliek Spe Salvi van paus Benedictus XVI
Commentaar op de encycliek Spe Salvi van paus Benedictus XVICommentaar op de encycliek Spe Salvi van paus Benedictus XVI
Commentaar op de encycliek Spe Salvi van paus Benedictus XVIAlfred Driessen
 
De deugden, spierballen van de ziel
De deugden, spierballen van de zielDe deugden, spierballen van de ziel
De deugden, spierballen van de zielAlfred Driessen
 
Inleiding op fides et ratio van paus Johannes Paulus II
Inleiding op fides et ratio van paus Johannes Paulus IIInleiding op fides et ratio van paus Johannes Paulus II
Inleiding op fides et ratio van paus Johannes Paulus IIAlfred Driessen
 
The strange properties of photons
The strange properties of photonsThe strange properties of photons
The strange properties of photonsAlfred Driessen
 
Life and Quantum Biology
Life and Quantum BiologyLife and Quantum Biology
Life and Quantum BiologyAlfred Driessen
 

More from Alfred Driessen (20)

The quest for truth of Stephen Hawking
The quest for truth of Stephen HawkingThe quest for truth of Stephen Hawking
The quest for truth of Stephen Hawking
 
Beethoven 9th Symphony: about joy and God
Beethoven 9th  Symphony: about joy and GodBeethoven 9th  Symphony: about joy and God
Beethoven 9th Symphony: about joy and God
 
Vrije wil, alleen een illusie?
Vrije wil, alleen een illusie?Vrije wil, alleen een illusie?
Vrije wil, alleen een illusie?
 
Evolutie en schepping
Evolutie en scheppingEvolutie en schepping
Evolutie en schepping
 
Causality from outside Time
Causality from outside TimeCausality from outside Time
Causality from outside Time
 
Gij zijt Petrus
Gij zijt PetrusGij zijt Petrus
Gij zijt Petrus
 
Het heelal een ontdekkingsreis
Het heelal een ontdekkingsreisHet heelal een ontdekkingsreis
Het heelal een ontdekkingsreis
 
Achilles, the Tortoise and Quantum Mechanics
Achilles, the Tortoise and Quantum MechanicsAchilles, the Tortoise and Quantum Mechanics
Achilles, the Tortoise and Quantum Mechanics
 
De waarde van het lijden
De waarde van het lijdenDe waarde van het lijden
De waarde van het lijden
 
Overview of Presentations in the Field of Philosophy and Science
Overview of Presentations in the Field of Philosophy and ScienceOverview of Presentations in the Field of Philosophy and Science
Overview of Presentations in the Field of Philosophy and Science
 
The Universe as a Computer Game
The Universe as a Computer GameThe Universe as a Computer Game
The Universe as a Computer Game
 
het huwelijk in de Bijbel
het huwelijk in de Bijbelhet huwelijk in de Bijbel
het huwelijk in de Bijbel
 
What about Adam and Eve
What about Adam and EveWhat about Adam and Eve
What about Adam and Eve
 
Het dubbele gezicht van de evolutie
Het dubbele gezicht van de evolutie Het dubbele gezicht van de evolutie
Het dubbele gezicht van de evolutie
 
Commentaar op de encycliek Spe Salvi van paus Benedictus XVI
Commentaar op de encycliek Spe Salvi van paus Benedictus XVICommentaar op de encycliek Spe Salvi van paus Benedictus XVI
Commentaar op de encycliek Spe Salvi van paus Benedictus XVI
 
De deugden, spierballen van de ziel
De deugden, spierballen van de zielDe deugden, spierballen van de ziel
De deugden, spierballen van de ziel
 
Inleiding op fides et ratio van paus Johannes Paulus II
Inleiding op fides et ratio van paus Johannes Paulus IIInleiding op fides et ratio van paus Johannes Paulus II
Inleiding op fides et ratio van paus Johannes Paulus II
 
The strange properties of photons
The strange properties of photonsThe strange properties of photons
The strange properties of photons
 
De heilige Drie-eenheid
De heilige Drie-eenheidDe heilige Drie-eenheid
De heilige Drie-eenheid
 
Life and Quantum Biology
Life and Quantum BiologyLife and Quantum Biology
Life and Quantum Biology
 

Reflecting on Godel's incompleteness theorem and its implications for metaphysical systems

  • 1. Invited talk Interdisciplinary Colloquium, University of Helsinki, 26-27 September 2003 published in Human Approaches to the Universe, E. Martikainen (ed.) Luther-Agricola Seura, Helsinki, 2005, pp 66-74.
  • 2. Reflecting on the huge amount of information provided by his senses man is confronted with a very fundamental question: is there a reality that can not be reached by senses even not with the aid of sophisticated instru- ments? Is there a reality, which does not obey the physical laws of nature? This is certainly a philosophical question that is answered differently in dif- ferent metaphysical systems, but as will be shown below, certain experiences support or make difficult certain metaphysical systems. For example, Aristo- tle based his metaphysics on the everyday experience of the occurrence of real changes. In the philosophy of Parmenides these changes were considered to be only apparent and not based on reality. Hs philosophy, therefore should i and has in hct be disregarded. Today the empirical hcts have largely been increased, and, what is proba- bly more important, these hcts are only accessible to a s m d number ofwell- prepared specialists. How can a philosopher understand these new empirical facts - often only expressed in the highly formalized language of physicists, - mathematicians or other scientists and evaluate their relevance with regard to his metaphysics?Not to speak about a scientific discussion on the validity of these hcts. In the following an attempt is made to analyze an important mathemati- cal discovery, the theorem of Godel and to demonstrate that the acceptance of this theorem has a direct impact on the consistency of metaphysical sys- tems. It will be shown that there are elements of reality, in this case the hu- man intellect, that can perform actions that exceed the potential of operators exclusively subjected to physical laws. To make it very clear, the Godel theorem is in the field of pure mathemat- ics. The philosopher as philosopher can not decide on the rightness of this theorem. What he, instead can do, is evaluating the general acceptance of this mathematical finding and reflect on the consistency between consequences of the mathematical theorem with consequences of his metaphysical view. In the following the contribution of three mathematicians will be pre- sented: first Gode12 himself, then the further elaboration by Turin2 and fi- nally the consequences for the human mind as worked out by Penrose4. Schins5,6 presented in several contributions the basic ideas of these authors.
  • 3. In this paper often use will be made of his argumentations. Finally we will present a philosophical evaluation. 2. The Godel incompleteness theowm In order to grasp the impact of the work of Godel one has to consider the foundation of mathematics at the beginning of the 20h century. There was a strong school considering mathematics just a product of human logic. In this view it is principally possible to arrive at any mathematical truth by applying exclusively a set of axioms and formal deduction. The German mathematician David Hilbert expresses this conviction by: In Mathematics there is no I p o r a b i m d . He formulated in 1900 the 10 last real problems of mathematics to be solved. The last of these, the ~ n a c h e i d u n ~ ~ r o b k m , concerned the existence of an algorithm able to solve general classes of mathematical problemss. The s o h i o n of this problem would be the tri- umph of the formalistic approach: just following an algorithm, i.e. a se- quence of deductive steps one would arrive on the solution. The question of meaning would be irrelevant; as long as the formal procedures would be used one would arrive at the mathematical truth. In his communication of 1931, Godelz, an Austrian mathematician, demonstrated the fundamental inadequacy of the pure formal approach. He proved that in every consistent, sufficiently general axiomatic system (i.e., systems which are based on axioms and specific rules of deduction) there always exists a true proposition which cannot be deduced fiom the axioms (Godel's incompleteness theorem); the consistency of the axioms cannot be deduced from the axioms (Godel's consistency theorem). In both theorems Godel states that a certain mathematical truth cannot be obtained exclusively by deduction, i.e. exclusively by a formal approach. Mathematical meaning and mathematical truth are relevant concepts not reducible to formal logic. To prove his incompleteness theorem, Godel
  • 4. provides a proposition whose correctness and truth everyone with a mini- mum of mathematical education can confirm, but which is undecidable within the formal system in question. It is here not the place to follow in detail the proof of Godel; it is, however, worthwhile to express in words the so-called Godel proposition in the incompleteness theorem: tbm ncrjts no proof$r the Go&/ proposition. In order to get a taste of Godel's argumentation one can start with the observation that the Godel proposition is legitimate (as is demonstrated formally by Godel). There are now two alternatives, there is a proof for this proposition or not. If there is a proof, a legitimate proposition that is for- mulated according the axioms of the formal system is wrong. Consequent- ly there is a contradiction within the axiomatic system which is impossible and the assumption has to be rejected. If there is no proof, the proposition is true and the incompleteness theorem is correct. This is the only alterna- tive without formal contradiction. One is therefore forced to accept the validity of a proposition which, being true, is undecidable and cannot be proven in the formal system. It is not so easy to realize the impact of the work of Godel. What direct- ly is shown is that mathematics goes beyond applying deductive or formal steps, also insight, intuition or meaning on a higher level come into play. Further, no formal system is complete, as a mathematician can always - - pro- vide true statements-that are formally improvable. A first important conclusion can already be drawn now. For some phys- icist, the rediction of physical reality to a single theory or even a single fbr- mula would be the ultimate triumph of science. A physical theory, howev- er, or a formula are part of a forma system, that aft& ~ 6 d ewe know to be l necessarily incomplete. Reality and also physical reality is by definition complete. The Grand Unified Theory (GUT) and other ultimate ap- proaches will be necessarily incomplete and inadequate to describe the full iichness of physical reality. 3. The contribution of Turing In 1936 Turing, a mathematician inspired by Godel, conceived the ulti- mate computer, the Turing machine3. We are used to the fact that every three years we have a new computer with largely improved capacity. The Turing machine is the end of any possible evolution with regard to software
  • 5. as well as hardware: with infinite speed and memory, using digital logic, neu- ral networks, quantum logic or any other up to now known or unknown technology for data processing. It is the best what physical laws and the most advanced design can offer with in addition unlimited speed and unlimited memory. With this machine any finite sequence of processing steps could be carried out in an infinitesimally small amount of time. Turing posed himself the question and gave an answer with regard to the halting-problem. Is there a general algorithm that can predict whether the Turing machine will stop with a given program and given input? If that would be possible, one could look for certain prepositions and demonstrate, whether they are of the Godel-type or not. Once these have been identified, one could isolate them and could continue with a 'clean' formal system. Tur- ing showed that this algorithm does not exist, the algorithm that should mark Godel-type propositions would be caught in an infinite loop in the Turing machine. What can one learn from T ~ r i n g ? ~ Scientists and fiction writers are speaking about intelligence in man-made apparatus. There is a clear evolu- tion: increasingly processing speed, memory and code complexity is intro- duced. But even after evolution and many centuries of future research there will be mathematical problems, these artificial intelligence (AI) devices can not solve. For the Turing machine, which exceeds these AI devices by fir, has been shown to never come up with a result on well-defined algorithmic problems. The question remains, would it not be fantastic if human beings would have the capacity of the Turing machine. Would this be a step forward or something destroying humanity in its very root? To answer this question one should not forget that the Turing machine is the best matter or beings exclu- sively bound to physical laws can deliver. 4. Penrose and the human mind In his book The Emperor? new mindPenrose4 uses the results of Godel and Turing to analyze the cognitive activity of the human mind. His argumenta- tion is based on meta-mathematics, a level achievable by mathematicians but not exclusively bound to formal argumentation. His argumentation starts
  • 6. with two observations well within the field of mathematics. There are mathematical results on the truth of certain prepositions, which can be recognized by any mathematician, but can not formally be proven (for example the Godel preposition). In addition, he learns from ~ u r i nthat the ideal computing device, the ~, so-called Turing machine, can only be used for solving problems by a fbrmal approach. Penrose explains: The point of view that one can dispense with the meaning of mathematical srarements, rrgardingthem as nothing but strings of symbols in some b r d mathematical system, is the mathematical standpoint of brrnaism. Some people l i e this idea, whereby mathematics becomes a kind of 'meaningless game'. It is not an idea that appeals to me, hawever. It is indeed 'meanin+ot blind algorithmic computation-that gives mathematics its substance.'" In drawing a conclusion from his meta-mathematical observations, Pen- rose leaves mathematics and enters the field of anthropology. And his condu- sion is that the human mind is able to carry out certain activities that artifi- cial devices, including the Turing machine, can not. It is not the question whether the human mind is superior in all aspects to the Turing machine, for example in computing speed even present-day computers exceed by fir hu- man capacity. The remarkable is that man can do something, f i r example grasping the meaning of a mathematical truth, a machine never can do. Pen- rose writes: Mathematical truth is not something that we ascertain merely by use of an algorithm. I believe, also, that our consciousness is a crucial ingredient in our comprehension of mathematical truth. We must 'see' the truth of a mathematical argument to be con- vinced of its validity. This 'seeing' is the very essence of consciousness. It must be present whenever we directly perceive mathematical truth. W e n we convince our- selves of the validity of W d ' s theorem we not only 'see' it, but by so doing we reveal the very non-algorithmic nature of the 'seeing' process itself." The significance of this 'seeing' a truth becomes even clearer if one uses the equivalent Latin verb intueri or the derivative 'intuition'. The latter points to a special intellectual activity that nearly instantaneous in a crea-
  • 7. tive way is able to understand or conceive a solution to a problem. The foundation of this peculiar intellectual capacity is, according to Penrose, related to consciousness. One should, however have in mind that investi- gating this foundation one is not working any more in the realm of mathe- matics or even science in general, but more within anthropology or philos- ophy of man and metaphysics. What about artificial intelligence? In the light of Penrose's conclusions one could speak of a misleading term. A person who is able to memorize very well or to solve certain formal problems in a rapid way, but who is missing insight and understanding is not considered to be intelligent. And the artificial devices like the Turing machine exclusively based on physical laws, can do it perhaps more rapidly, but with the same fundamental lack of insight. In stead of AT one should speak of ADP: artificial data proces- sors. 5. Philosophical evaluation As already stated in the introduction, the ultimate goal of the philosopher is to find an overall consistent view where all empirical knowledge could be integrated. With the work of Godel, Turing and Penrose one is confronted with two different types of intellectual activity in mathematics, which both can be carried out by humans. The astonishing thing is not the distinction between a formalized, logic approach on the one side and intuition, math- ematical insight and meaning on the other. Being surely relevant for the philosophy of mathematics it does not have strong implications for the overall view on reality. Philosophically challenging, however, is the claim that principally only one of these approaches can be carried out by devices bound exclusively to the laws of physical reality. Turing machines, namely, are not able to grasp issues related to mathematical meaning, and these machines are the best physical laws can offer Accepting the evidence provided by mathematics the philosopher should allow for two aspects of reality in his metaphysics: one exclusively bound to physical lawsand the other not. A plain, drdinary materialistic view considering reality restricted to things that are exclusively subjected to physical laws is not able to incorporate the distinction provided by mathe- matics. The well-known quote by Karl Marx, Der Mensch kt, was er $3,
  • 8. (The human is that what he eats) is an example of a metaphysical statement that refutes this distinction: a human being is like his food, i.e. something exclusively bound to physical laws of nature. Accepting the distinction suggested by mathematics the philosopher could provide more information about the ontological base of humans that allows them carrying out intellectual activities that Turing machines and other objects subjected exclusively to physical laws are not able to do. The principle of causality expressed in the classical statement agere sequitur esse (acting is according to the way of being) indicates that if an activity is ob- served that exceeds the potential physical laws can offer, there should be a subject exceeding the potential physical laws can offer. Already some of the Greek philosophers like Plato and Aristotle made a distinction between a material and spiritual reality. Especially Aristotle and later Aquinas studied the intellectual activity of human beings and found, interesting enough, a similar distinction in two principal approaches: strict logical argumenta- tion with syllogism, a kind of formalized, deductive or inductive mental activity and intuition or in Greek theoria that accounts for insight and cre- ativity. It is interesting to note that in the metaphysics of Aquinas an intellectu- al activity is possible in pure spiritual beings and in man, who is composed of a spiritual and material component. According to Aquinas it is the ma- terial component in man that is responsible for the formal, logic intellectu- al activity with the aid of syllogism, whereas pure spiritual intellects know only by intuition. This is a remarkable parallelism with the findings in mathematics. A Turing machine, being a pure material device, can do the formalized processing, whereas only the human mind with his spiritual di- mension according to Aquinas is able to carry out the intuitive intellectual activity needed to grasp mathematical meaning. Aristotle like Aquinas did not know the Gijdel theorem but arrived by a different analysis at the same conclusions as Penrose. This is, of course, no proof of the validity of the metaphysics of Aristotle and Aquinas, but an important consistency check with experience. There are, of course many other checkpoints, but after Godel, Turing and Penrose this specific one provided by mathematics should be taken seriously, leading in some cases to the abandonment of certain metaphysical views, as, for example, provid- ed by plain materialism.
  • 9. CAa, E 1997 "Meaning, W and Algorithms: Implications of theTuring Theorem" in Driesen, t y A. & Suara, A. (eds.): Matimu&& Undccidnbilig Quantum Nonlocality a d thr Question cfdx Exiwnce ofGod. DoDordrt: Muwtr Academic Publishers. GODEL,K 1931 "&r fbrmal uncntscheidbate S h der Principia Mathemacia und verwandtu Sys- tune In in M o ~ ~ f i i r M a t h c m a tudP&k ic38. HIUun; D. 1935 GaammcbAbbdngrn, 111. Band B& Springer Vedag. e: 1900 Mathuricd h b h (tenth problem). Paris: 2& International Con- ofM& ma&. l'mmsb R 1989 Thr Empnr,~ Mind. Oxfbrd: O h r d University Press. Nnu SCHINS, J. M. 1997 "Mathematics:A Pointer to an Independent Wy in Driessen, A. & Suara, A. t " (eds.): Mathemutical Lh&d&ig Quanrrm Noduality and& Question of dx Erric- mrc o W Do-t: f . Kluwtr Academic Publishers. 2000 Honmlgmc kan & wtemchap uduggcn?Kampcn: Agora. TURING,k 1936-37 "On Computable Numbers with an Application to the Entscheidungsproblemnin l'nndiw @thr London Matkmurical Saety, 42-43.