SlideShare a Scribd company logo
1 of 27
Cognitive Ability and Vulnerability to Fake News
https://getpocket.com/explore/item/cognitive-ability-and-
vulnerability-to-fake-news?utm_source=pocket-newtab
Researchers identify a major risk factor for pernicious effects of
misinformation.
Scientific American
· David Z. Hambrick
· Madeline Marquardt
Photo by gguy44 / Getty Images.
“Fake news” is Donald Trump’s favorite catchphrase. Since the
2016 election, it has appeared in hundreds of tweets by the
President, decrying everything from accusations of sexual
assault against him to the Russian collusion investigation to
reports that he watches up to eight hours of television a day.
Trump may just use “fake news” as a rhetorical device to
discredit stories he doesn’t like, but there is evidence that real
fake news is a serious problem. As one alarming example, an
analysis by the internet media company Buzzfeed revealed that
during the final three months of the 2016 U.S. presidential
campaign, the 20 most popular false election stories generated
around 1.3 million more Facebook engagements—shares,
reactions, and comments—than did the 20 most popular
legitimate stories. The most popular fake story was “Pope
Francis Shocks World, Endorses Donald Trump for President.”
Fake news can distort people’s beliefs even after being
debunked. For example, repeated over and over, a story such as
the one about the Pope endorsing Trump can create a glow
around a political candidate that persists long after the story is
exposed as fake. A 2017 study published in the journal
Intelligence suggests that some people may have an especially
difficult time rejecting misinformation. Asked to rate a
fictitious person on a range of character traits, people who
scored low on a test of cognitive ability continued to be
influenced by damaging information about the person even after
they were explicitly told the information was false. The study is
significant because it identifies what may be a major risk factor
for vulnerability to fake news.
Ghent University researchers Jonas De keersmaecker and Arne
Roets first had over 400 subjects take a personality test. They
then randomly assigned each subject to one of two conditions.
In the experimental condition, the subjects read a biographical
description of a young woman named Nathalie. The bio
explained that Nathalie, a nurse at a local hospital, “was
arrested for stealing drugs from the hospital; she has been
stealing drugs for 2 years and selling them on the street in order
to buy designer clothes.” The subjects then rated Nathalie on
traits such as trustworthiness and sincerity, after which they
took a test of cognitive ability. Finally, the subjects saw a
message on their computer screen explicitly stating that the
information about Nathalie stealing drugs and getting arrested
was not true, and then rated her again on the same traits. The
control condition was identical, except that subjects were not
given the paragraph with the false information and rated
Nathalie only once.
The subjects in the experimental condition initially rated
Nathalie much more negatively than did the subjects in the
control condition. This was not surprising, considering that they
had just learned she was a thief and a drug dealer. The
interesting question was whether cognitive ability would predict
attitude adjustment—that is, the degree to which the subjects in
the experimental condition would rate Nathalie more favorably
after being told that this information was false. It did: subjects
high in cognitive ability adjusted their ratings more than did
those lower in cognitive ability. The subjects with lower
cognitive ability had more trouble shaking their negative first
impression of Nathalie. This was true even after the researchers
statistically controlled for the subjects’ level of open-
mindedness (their willingness to change their mind when
wrong) and right-wing authoritarianism (their intolerance
toward others), as assessed by the personality test. Thus, even if
a person was open-minded and tolerant, a low level of cognitive
ability put them at risk for being unjustifiably harsh in their
second evaluation of Nathalie.
One possible explanation for this finding is based on the theory
that a person’s cognitive ability reflects how well they can
regulate the contents of working memory—their “mental
workspace” for processing information. First proposed by the
cognitive psychologists Lynn Hasher and Rose Zacks, this
theory holds that some people are more prone to “mental
clutter” than other people. In other words, some people are less
able to discard (or “inhibit”) information from their working
memory that is no longer relevant to the task at hand—or, as in
the case of Nathalie, information that has been discredited.
Research on cognitive aging indicates that, in adulthood, this
ability declines considerably with advancing age, suggesting
that older adults may also be especially vulnerable to fake news.
Another reason why cognitive ability may predict vulnerability
to fake news is that it correlates highly with education. Through
education, people may develop meta-cognitive skills—strategies
for monitoring and regulating one’s own thinking—that can be
used to combat the effects of misinformation.
Meanwhile, other research is shedding light on the mechanisms
underlying the effects of misinformation. Repeating a false
claim increases its believability, giving it an air of what
Stephen Colbert famously called “truthiness.” Known as the
illusion of truth effect, this phenomenon was first demonstrated
in the laboratory by Hasher and her colleagues. On each of three
days, subjects listened to plausible-sounding statements and
rated each on whether they thought it was true. Half of the
statements were in fact true, such as Australia is approximately
equal in area to the continental United States, whereas the other
half were false, such as Zachary Taylor was the first president
to die in office (it was William Henry Harrison). Some of the
statements were repeated across days, whereas others were
presented only once. The results showed that the average truth
rating increased from day to day for the repeated statements, but
remained constant for the non-repeated statements, indicating
that subjects mistook familiarity for verity.
More recent research reveals that even knowledge of the truth
doesn’t necessarily protect against the illusion of truth. In a
2015 study published in the Journal of Experimental
Psychology: General, Lisa Fazio and her colleagues asked
subjects to rate a set of statements on how interesting they
found them. Following Hasher and colleagues’ procedure, some
of the statements were true, whereas others were false. The
subjects then rated a second set of statements for truthfulness
on a six-point scale, from definitely false to definitely true.
Some of the statements were repeated from the first set, whereas
others were new. Finally, the subjects took a knowledge test
that included questions based on the statements. The results
revealed that repetition increased the subjects’ perception of the
truthfulness of false statements, even for statements they knew
to be false. For example, even if a subject correctly answered
Pacific Ocean to the question What is the largest ocean on
Earth? on the knowledge test, they still tended to give the false
statement The Atlantic Ocean is the largest ocean on Earth a
higher truth rating if it was repeated. When a claim was made to
feel familiar through repetition, subjects neglected to consult
their own knowledge base in rating the claim’s truthfulness.
These studies add to scientific understanding of the fake news
problem, which is providing a foundation for an evidenced-
based approach to addressing the problem. A recommendation
that follows from research on the illusion of truth effect is to
serve as your own fact checker. If you are convinced that some
claim is true, ask yourself why. Is it because you have credible
evidence that the claim is true, or is it just because you’ve
encountered the claim over and over? Also ask yourself if you
know of any evidence that refutes the claim. (You just might be
surprised to find that you do.) This type of recommendation
could be promoted through public service announcements,
which have been shown to be effective for things like getting
people to litter less and recycle more. For its part, research on
individual differences in susceptibility to fake news, such as the
study by De keersmaecker and Roets, can help to identify
people who are particularly important to reach through this type
of informational campaign.
At a more general level, this research underscores the threat that
fake news poses to democratic society. The aim of using fake
news as propaganda is to make people think and behave in ways
they wouldn’t otherwise—for example, hold a view that is
contradicted by overwhelming scientific consensus. When this
nefarious aim is achieved, citizens no longer have the ability to
act in their own self-interest. In the logic of democracy, this
isn’t just bad for that citizen—it’s bad for society.
David Z. Hambrick is a professor in the department of
psychology at Michigan State University. His research focuses
on individual differences in cognitive ability and complex skill.
Madeline Marquardt graduated Michigan State University in
2018 with a degree in Neuroscience and additional degree in
Professional Writing and is now a TEFL Peace Corps Volunteer
in Armenia.
Advertisement
More from Scientific American
This post originally appeared on Scientific American and was
published February 5, 2018. This article is republished here
with permission.
Chapter 8. Do We Have Free Will?
20
Chapter 8
Do We Have Free Will?
Read the section after page ten
Copyright by Paul Herrick, 2020. For class use only. Not for
distribution. This chapter: 26 pages of reading.
1. A Sign of the Times
More and more people are giving up the traditional belief in
free will. Public intellectuals with large followings such as Sam
Harris are a sign of the times. After describing the horrific
home invasion murder spree in 2007 that earned two criminals
named Hayes and Komisarjevsky six consecutive life sentences
without parole for their cold-blooded murders of a defenseless
family, Harris, a prominent New Atheist writes the following
about the killers in his best-selling book Free Will:
Whatever their conscious motives, those men cannot know why
they are as they are. Nor can we account for why we are not like
them. As sickening as I find their behavior, I have to admit that
if I were to trade places with one of them, atom for atom, I
would be him: There is no extra part of me [such as an
immaterial soul] that could decide to see the world differently
or to resist the impulse to victimize other people. . . . If I had
truly been in Komisarjevsky’s shoes on July 23, 2007—that is,
if I had his genes and life experience and an identical brain. . . .
in an identical state—I would have acted exactly as he did. . . .
The role of luck, therefore, appears to be decisive.
Harris concludes from this:
Free will is an illusion. Our wills are simply not of our own
making. Thoughts and intentions emerge from background
causes of which we are unaware and over which we exert no
conscious control.
We must also give up our belief in moral responsibility:
The men and women on death row have some combination of
bad genes, bad parents, bad environment, and bad ideas (and the
innocent, of course, have supremely bad luck). Which of these
quantities, exactly, were they responsible for? No human being
is responsible for his genes or his upbringing, yet we have every
reason to believe these factors determine his character.
(emphasis added)
In short, lacking free will, no one deserves either credit or
blame for anything they’ve done.
How much credit does a person deserve for not being lazy?
None at all. Laziness, like diligence, is a neurological condition
. . . [Again] free will is an illusion.
If Harris is correct, no one has free will, no one is morally
responsible for his choices or his character, no matter what he
does, and no one deserves praise, blame, reward or punishment
for anything he has done. Luck, rather than choice, is “decisive”
in life. If a young student from a difficult background works
hard, sacrifices, and graduates from college with honors, he or
she deserves no credit or praise—his accomplishment is due to
luck not his own free will. If someone robs a bank and shoots
three tellers as they plead for their lives, he deserves neither
blame nor punishment. His action is due to unfortunate
circumstances, for (again) luck, rather than character, choice, or
effort, “appears to be decisive.” Each of us would have done the
same thing—robbed the bank and shot all three tellers—if we
had the same genes and had grown up in the same background.
The unspoken implication, I believe, is that no one can
justifiably say that he or she is a better person than a serial
killer, a carjacker, or a bank robber.
Are free will and moral responsibility illusions, as Sam Harris
and others in the New Atheist movement claim? Are they
outdated myths held over from ignorant times? Is it time to give
up the traditional beliefs in free will and personal
accountability? These are the big questions of this chapter—
questions that go to the heart of what kind of beings we really
are. We’ll approach the issue in stages, beginning with a
thought experiment that will help make even more vivid the
fundamental concepts at stake.
2. The Psychology Student
In his thought-provoking book, The Strangeness of the
Ordinary: Problems and Issues in Contemporary Metaphysics,
the philosopher Robert Coburn (1931–2018) asks us to imagine
the following scenario: A group of scientists have discovered a
way to send radio signals to an experimental subject’s brain and
activate individual brain cells.
They also know which kinds of actions are caused by which
groups of brain cells. So they know that if they send signal X
into a certain region in the brain, the subject will automatically
stand up, if they send signal Y, he will eat a hamburger, and so
forth. By targeting specific brain cells, they can manipulate a
test subject as if he is a puppet on a string.
Coburn next asks us to imagine that an undergrad in psychology
volunteers to be an experimental guinea pig. Everything the
volunteer will do during the next month will be caused remotely
by these scientists from their laboratory.
So, with the consent forms signed and the electrodes in place,
the experiment begins. On the first day, the scientists send
signals into the student’s brain that cause him to watch reruns
of the 1950s TV series Gunsmoke. On the second day, they
cause him to order takeout online, and so forth. At any moment,
there is only one thing the test subject can do—that which the
scientists at that moment cause him to do. The subject cannot do
anything but exactly what he is caused to do by the radio
signals sent by the scientists.
Was the student acting of his own free will during the
experiment? Would we hold him morally responsible for his
actions during the test month? Would we blame him if the
scientists caused him to rob a bank? Would we give him credit
if they made him rescue someone drowning in a lake? These
questions are asked within the context of our ordinary, everyday
moral thinking.
Surely we would not hold the student accountable if the
scientists caused him to rob a bank or steal a car. Nor would we
give him praise or credit if the scientists caused him to do a
good deed such as saving a life. And the reason we would not is
that at each moment during the experiment, the student couldn’t
do anything other than exactly what he was caused to do.
The general principle we apply here is this: If a person does
something and the person could not possibly have done anything
else at the moment, given the causes at work just prior to the
moment of action, then the person is not acting of his or her
own free will, the person is not morally responsible, and the
person deserves neither praise nor blame.
Next, Coburn brings in our ordinary concept of causation. In
everyday life, we assume that every event has a cause. If your
car’s engine dies, you naturally suppose that something caused
it to die. If you get sick, you assume that something caused your
illness. But we also assume that human actions have causes. If
someone does something odd, we say, “I wonder what caused
him do that?” Sometimes we say to ourselves, “What made me
to do such a thing?” or “What got into me?”
Coburn now asks a great question: Does it make any difference,
with respect to free will, praise, blame, and moral
responsibility, whether (a) our actions are caused by scientists
in a remote lab sending signals into our brains, or (b) our
actions are caused by our social environment, our genes, the
wiring in our brains, and the sum total of all previous causes at
work in the universe? Aren’t we unfree in either case? But
doesn’t everything have a cause? If so, how is it even possible
we have free will or moral responsibility?
3. Definitions Before We Proceed
Our discussion so far has brought to the surface several key
concepts. Each needs to be sharpened before we proceed, or
things will get murky and lines of reasoning will fray.
Moral Responsibility
Suppose that Pat is admiring a painting at an art museum when
someone rushes up behind her and without warning violently
pushes her into the painting. Would we blame her for the
damage? Would we hold her morally responsible? Or would we
blame the person who pushed her? Surely we would not blame
the victim here. And the reason we would not is obvious: once
she was violently pushed from behind without warning, she
could not have done otherwise (than fall into the painting). Two
principles are at work in this case: the first is known in
philosophy as the “principle of alternate possibilities”; the
second we’ll call the “praise and blame principle.”
Both reflect our moral common sense.
The Principle of Alternate Possibilities: If a person on a
particular occasion performs an action and the person at the
moment could not have done otherwise, then the person is not
morally responsible for performing the action.
This is logically equivalent to the following:
If a person on a particular occasion is morally responsible for
performing an action, then the person could have done
otherwise at the time.
Next:
The Praise and Blame Principle: If a person is not morally
responsible for performing an action, then that person deserves
neither praise nor blame for the action.
These ideas lead us to think about the meaning of free will. This
is a very difficult concept.
Toward an Account of Free Will
Suppose that a person who suffers from epilepsy has a seizure
and uncontrollably falls to the ground. We would not ordinarily
say the person fell of his or her own free will. And the reason
we would not is surely that once the seizure occurred, that
person could not have done anything else but fall. This suggests
the following principle:
If a person at a particular moment does something and the
person could not possibly have done otherwise at that moment,
given all the prior conditions that led up to the moment, then
the individual was not acting of his or her own free will.
This is logically equivalent to the following statement:
If a person at a particular moment does something of his or her
own free will, then that individual could have done otherwise,
given the very same antecedent conditions leading up to the
moment.
An important consequence follows. If a person performs an
action at a time t and that person could have done otherwise at
t, given the very same antecedent causes and conditions, then at
time t the person had the power to do what he did, call it
“action A,” and at the same time and with the same antecedent
conditions, the person also had the power to do something else
instead, call it “action B.” These thoughts suggest a tentative
account of free will:
A person P has free will at a moment in time t if, and only if, at
time t, P has it within his or her power to do one thing, action
A, and at the same time and under the same conditions, and
given the same antecedent causes and conditions, P also has it
within his or her power to do something else instead, action B.
For example, suppose someone orders a salad in a restaurant.
We would say the person “freely” ordered the salad if we
believe that (a) at the moment the person placed his order he
had it within his power to order the salad, and (b) at the same
time the person also had the power to order something else
instead, or nothing at all. This is a “two-power” account of free
will. On the basis of a similar idea, the philosopher Robert Kane
describes free will as the possession of “dual power.” Some
philosophers express the same idea when they define free will
concisely as “the ability to have done otherwise.”
Let’s incorporate these thoughts into our account by saying that
a person has free will if, on at least some occasions, the person
possesses two powers at the same time: the power or ability to
perform one action A and the power or ability to perform an
alternative action B under the same conditions and given the
same past causes and conditions. If you have dual power, then
on some occasions, you do one thing, but at the same time, with
the past exactly as it was and present conditions exactly as they
are, you could have done something else instead. Put
differently, you act of your own free will if you do something
while at the same time possessing the (unactualized) power to
have done something else instead, given the same antecedent
circumstances and past events. This is an analysis of the
common account of free will.
We are often urged to take ownership of our actions, and we
often say things like, “That was my bad,” “It’s up to you” and
“You own that one.” The common account of free will just
outlined helps explain the sense in which our free actions are
truly our own, the sense in which our actions are up to us in the
final analysis. For on this account, we are the causes of our free
actions. Whether we have free will or not, this would seem to be
the kind of freedom required by our ordinary notions of free
will, praise, blame, and moral responsibility.
Cause and Effect
What do we ordinarily mean when we say that A “caused” B?
We normally mean that the occurrence of A was a sufficient
condition for the occurrence of B. If A is a sufficient condition
for some event B, then once A happens, or obtains, B must
happen, in the same sense that a normal cube of sugar must melt
once it is dropped into a cup of boiling water, or an ordinary
wine glass must shatter if it is dropped from twenty feet above
onto a concrete surface.
If B must occur once A has occurred, then nothing else but B
can occur (once A has occurred). Put still another way, if A is
sufficient for B, then once A exists, B is inevitable.
The point is so important it must be reinforced with a visual
image. Imagine a row of dominoes lined up so that when the
first one falls, it will knock over the second one, and so on
down the line. Once the first domino is pushed, it is only a
matter of time before the last domino inevitably falls. Similarly,
if A causes B and B causes C and so on to Z, then once A
happens, Z must eventually occur; Z is inevitable.
Determinism
One final building block idea remains to be explained.
Determinism is the view that every event, including the
occurrence of every human action, has a sufficient cause
(hereinafter “cause” for short), which in turn has a cause, and so
forth back and back as far as cause and effect go. If
determinism is true, then we live in a “deterministic universe.”
As we’ve seen, cosmologists have already traced an unbroken
chain of physical causes and effects back fourteen billion years
to the Big Bang. Thus, according to determinism informed by
science, every event that occurs today—including every human
action--can be traced back, through a chain of deterministic
causes and effects, fourteen billion years to the Big Bang. If we
live in a deterministic universe, then the event consisting of you
reading this sentence this moment was already set to occur
fourteen billion years ago. Indeed, if determinism is true, every
event in your life was already set to occur before you were
born.
Now, with these fundamental concepts sharpened, we are ready
for the big arguments. In modern philosophy, there are four
major positions on the question of free will, standardly named
“hard determinism,” “soft determinism” (also called
“compatibilism”), “simple indeterminism,” and “agent
causation.” Just about every theory of free will under discussion
today is a variation on, or is derived from, one of these four
major viewpoints.
Questions for Reflection and Discussion 8.1
1. In the thought experiment at the beginning of this chapter, is
the student acting of his own free will during the experiment?
Discuss.
2. Is the student responsible for his actions during the
experiment? Discuss.
3. Does the student ever deserve praise or blame during the
experiment? Discuss.
4. According to the common account, when are we morally
responsible for our actions?
5. On the common account, when do we deserve praise or blame
for our actions?
6. According to the common notion, what is a free action? What
is free will?
7. What is dual power alleged to be?
8. Does it matter whether we have free will? “What difference
does it make?”
9. At this point in the discussion, do you believe we have free
will? Why or why not?
10. This may require some research. At this point in the
discussion, were Hayes and Komisarjevsky morally responsible
for their crime? Did they deserve to be punished? Were they
acting of their own free will? What is your opinion? Discuss.
4. Hard Determinism
Consider the following argument:
1. Determinism is true, that is to say, every event, including the
occurrence of every human action, has a determining or
sufficient cause, which has a cause, and so forth back and back
billions of years, as far back as cause and effect go.
2. If A caused B, then once A happened, B had to happen in the
sense that nothing but B could happen next. Put another way,
once A happened, B became inevitable.
3. It follows that at any moment in time, when a person
performs an action, that person could not have done otherwise
at the moment.
4. If at a moment in time a person could not have done
otherwise, then at that moment the person was not acting of his
or her own free will. (This is the common account of free will.)
5. If a person could not have done otherwise in a situation, then
that person is not morally responsible for what he or she has
done. (This is the principle of alternate possibilities.)
6. If a person is not morally responsible for his action, then he
deserves neither praise nor blame. (This is the praise and blame
principle.)
7. Therefore, it follows necessarily that no one has free will, no
one is morally responsible for his or her actions, and no one
ever deserves praise or blame, reward or punishment.
If you accept the premises and conclusion of this deductive
argument, your philosophical position is called “hard
determinism” and you are a “hard determinist.” Notice that hard
determinists accept the common definitions of free will and
moral responsibility—they just believe these definitions apply
to no one. In other words, like Sam Harris, they believe that
free will and moral responsibility, although they can be defined,
are illusions.
The seven-step argument for hard determinism just stated is
deductively valid (if its premises are true, its conclusion must
be true). The only question is therefore, Is it sound? (In
addition to being valid, are its premises true?)
Incompatibilism
If you read books on hard determinism, you’ll notice that hard
determinists are sometimes called “incompatibilists.”
Incompatibilism in this context is the view that freedom and
determinism are logically incompatible. What does this mean?
Two statements P and Q are logically incompatible if it is
impossible that both are true. Incompatibilism with respect to
free will and determinism is therefore the claim that it is
impossible that determinism is true and at the same time we
have free will. So, when hard determinism is under discussion,
incompatibilism is the claim that if we are free, then we are not
determined, and if we are determined, then we are not free.
Here is an argument for incompatibilism:
1. If at a moment in time a person performs an action and at that
moment the person could not have done otherwise, then the
person was not acting of his or her own free will.
2. If at a moment in time a person performs an action and at that
moment the person could have done otherwise, then the person
was acting of his or her own free will.
3. If determinism is true, then at each moment in time, no one
could have done otherwise.
4. Thus, if determinism is true, no one has free will, and if we
sometimes act of our own free will, then determinism is false.
5. Therefore, freedom and determinism are logically
incompatible—they cannot both be true.
The hard determinist endorses incompatibilism, for he believes
that we cannot be both free and determined. With
incompatibilisim defined, a shorter argument for hard
determinism can be given.
1. Determinism is true.
2. Incompatibilism is true.
3. Therefore, necessarily no one has free will.
This argument, like the longer argument for hard determinism,
is valid. But is it sound?
<Box> Hard Determinism’s Early Boosters
Baron Paul Henri d’Holbach (1723–1789), a famous eighteenth-
century German intellectual, gave hard determinism one of its
first modern expressions. On the assumption that the principle
of universal determinism is true, Holbach argued:
In whatever manner man is considered, he is connected to
universal nature, and submitted to the necessary and immutable
laws that she imposes on all the beings she contains . . . Man’s
life is a line that nature commands him to outline upon the
surface of the earth, without his ever being able to swerve from
it, even for an instant. He is born without his own consent; his
organization does in nowise depend upon himself; his ideas
come to him involuntarily; his habits are in the power of those
who cause him to contract them; he is unceasingly modified by
causes, whether visible or concealed, over which he has no
control, which necessarily regulate his mode of existence, give
the hue to his way of thinking, and determine his manner of
acting. He is good or bad . . . without his will counting for
anything in these various states.
From this he concluded that free will and moral responsibility
do not exist.
At about the same time, the French mathematical physicist P. S.
Laplace (1749–1827) illustrated the idea of hard determinism
with a colorful example. In The System of the World, Laplace
used calculus and Newton’s mathematical laws of motion to
calculate the future paths of the planets with precision. After
this accomplishment, he assumed that his calculations apply to
the entire universe, including each human action. Human
actions, he concluded, are as predictable as the motions of the
planets. Thus, if a superintelligence were to know all the laws
of physics and the position and momentum of every particle of
matter in the universe, including every particle of matter
composing every human body, it could predict every future
event, including every future human action. Laplace wrote:
Given for one instant an intelligence which could comprehend
all the forces by which nature is animated and the respective
situations of the beings who compose it—an intelligence
sufficiently vast to submit these data to analysis—it would
embrace in the same formula the movements of the greatest
bodies of the universe and those of the lightest atom; for it,
nothing would be uncertain and the future, as the past, would be
present to its eyes.
Claims like these, coming from respected scholars and
scientists, convinced many people during the eighteenth and
nineteenth centuries that hard determinism is true and thus that
free will and moral responsibility are illusions. There was just
one problem. Holbach never gave an argument for his key
claim, namely, that literally everything, including each human
action, is determined. His key claim was simply an
unsubstantiated assumption—it was backed by no argument at
all.
Likewise, Laplace gave no argument for his key claim, that
everything in the universe is determined including every human
action. He simply assumed it without any scientific proof or
evidence at all. The principle of universal determinism had not
been proved by the science of the day, and it has not to this day
been proved. Indeed, we now know that it cannot be proved by
science alone, for it is a metaphysical, rather than a scientific,
claim.
Both men also assumed without argument that human actions
are natural events caused in the same way everything else is
caused—by physical sequences of cause and effect. This, too,
had not been proved by science and has not been proved by
science to this day, as we saw in the previous chapter. Despite
their scientific pretensions, neither Holbach nor Laplace offered
a scientific proof for their deterministic and materialist
assumptions. There is a word for this kind of thinking: it is
called “dogmatism.” It can also be called “sophistry.” <End
Box>
5. Two Philosophical Arguments against Hard Determinism
Van Inwagen’s Deliberation Argument
Although science has not proved that hard determinism is true,
there are philosophical arguments that claim to show that it is
false. Peter van Inwagen offers one in the form of a thought
experiment.
Imagine you are seated in a windowless room with no exits
other than two solid steel doors in front of you. You are told
that one of the two doors is welded shut, but you do not know
which of the two this is. Given these details, try to imagine
deliberating over which door to exit by.
Van Inwagen argues that, although it would make sense to
deliberate about which of the two doors to try to exit by, that is,
which door handle to try to turn, it would not make sense to
deliberate about which door to exit by. Why? I am paraphrasing
his answer:
You cannot rationally deliberate over whether to take one
course of action (call it “A”) or an alternative, incompatible
course of action B unless you believe at some level that at the
moment of choice you have it within your power to do A, and at
the same time you also have it within your power to do B. If
you know that of two incompatible courses of action A and B,
one of the two is impossible, then it makes no sense to
deliberate over which of the two courses of action to actually
take. You might deliberate over which course of action to
attempt, but not over which course of action to take.
Now imagine a different setup. This time you know that both
doors are unlocked. If you turn the knob on the first door, it
will open. If you turn the knob on the second door, it will open.
In this case, it makes sense to imagine deliberating over which
door to exit by.
This thought experiment, argues van Inwagen, uncovers an
important logical truth about human action, namely, that you
cannot rationally deliberate about whether to do A or to do B
unless you believe at some level that both courses of action are
open to you, that is, are possible at the moment. In other words,
unless you believe that you can do A and you can do B.
Assuming the common sense “two powers” account of free will,
van Inwagen’s claim implies that you cannot rationally
deliberate unless you at least believe you have free will.
Next, van Inwagen observes, human behavior can manifest an
unstated and even an unacknowledged belief. If Joe acts
frightened and runs away every time a dog approaches, his
behavior expresses a belief that dogs are dangerous, even if he
has never stated or admitted it. Likewise, when a person
sincerely deliberates over whether to do A or B, that person’s
behavior manifests a belief in free will, even if the person says
that he does not believe in free will and even if that person has
never thought about the issue.
But each of us deliberates. We deliberate hundreds of times
each day. Two things follow. First, at some level, everyone
believes in free will. Second, every time the hard determinist
deliberates, his own behavior expresses a belief in free will that
contradicts his professed belief in hard determinism. Thus, if
you endorse hard determinism, you contradict yourself every
time you make a deliberate choice.
Hard determinism is thus a philosophical doctrine that cannot
consistently be lived. It is also a doctrine that cannot
consistently be professed.
To a hard determinist, then, we might argue, “Since deliberation
is a necessary part of life and since deliberation presupposes a
belief in free will, you cannot live and be logically consistent
and at the same time assert hard determinism. But you can give
up hard determinism and assert free will without any
inconsistency. You should therefore give up hard determinism,
since that is the only one of the two options that can
consistently be dropped.”
If this argument is cogent, the hard determinist’s life is absurd
in the sense that it contains a logical conflict between belief and
action, pretension and reality. To accept hard determinism and
deny free will, van Inwagen concludes, is to condemn yourself
to a life of constant self-contradiction.
Of course, a hard determinist can bite the bullet and reply,
“This doesn’t show that hard determinism is false; all it shows
is that one cannot actively live and at the same time
consistently profess hard determinism. I’d rather be a walking
self-contradiction than believe in free will.”
However, it is very hard to believe that a philosophical theory
that cannot be consistently believed—a theory the acceptance of
which is logically inconsistent with actively living—is true.
How can such a theory be true?
The Moral Responsibility Argument
Van Inwagen believes that the following argument is an even
stronger reason to reject hard determinism and admit the
existence of free will.
Without free will, we would never be morally responsible for
anything, and we are sometimes morally responsible.
More formally and with some missing premises filled in:
1. Free will is a necessary condition of moral responsibility.
2. It is rationally undeniable that we are at least sometimes
morally responsible for our actions.
3. Therefore, human beings at least sometimes …
It's the flaw of circularity. An argument is circular when it uses
its conclusion as a premise. Put differently, circular arguments
assume what needs to be shown. In terms of the arguments
against hard determinism, the argument looks like this: "That
we have free will is evidenced by the fact that I made a freely
willed choice."
Check out this document for examples of this error from our
discussion. The document is also in the module for this week, in
case you can't open it from this attachment.
Also, I include this article as an FYI: It explains a benefit of
learning to step back and evaluate our arguments: Cognitive
Ability & Vulnerability to Fake News.docx
This week's quiz covers the material in the "Free Will" reading
from section 5 to the end. It will also cover my comments on
circular reasoning. I have highlighted this logical flaw in prior
documents and on prior quiz questions. Most recently, I posted
a document called Comments on Circularity and Week 7
Discussion. I suggest that you review this and have it open as
you take the quiz.
Part One. Pick any idea in this week's material that interests you
and post your philosophical thoughts on it. Please consider one
of the discussion questions listed at the end of sections (on
pages, 13, 16, and 28).
Part Two. Respond critically when you comment on the post of
one (or more) members of the class. This means: give an
argument to support your view.
QI
This week I would like to discuss soft determinism. Soft
determinism claims that freedom and determinism are
compatible because it changes the definition of freedom from
“could have done otherwise” to “doing what an individual wants
to do”. However, I think no matter how soft determinism revises
its argument, it is not acceptable because freedom and
determinism are two incompatible concepts, while soft
determinism tries to make these two incompatible concepts
compatible. Soft determinism is a dead end because the core of
freedom is basically against the core of determinism, and it
cannot change the definition of freedom to fit determinism
because the changed definition of freedom is not the real
definition of freedom. Therefore, even though I do not believe
in determinism, I think hard determinism makes more sense than
soft determinism, for at least hard determinism is not as self-
contradictory as soft determinism.
A Few Comments on Discussion for Week 7:
Introduction: The idea that we do not have free will is
disturbing to me. If it’s true, it’s likely a belief that I’m unable
– psychologically to experience: as much as I’ve tried (just to
see if I could), I am unable to shake the feeling that I am the
thinker of my thoughts and the chooser of my choices.
However, the fact that I can’t shake this feeling, doesn’t mean
the feeling is accurate. My sense of free will may be an illusion
just like other optical illusions (some which are equally
unshakeable) are illusions. Once I pause to consider whether my
sense of free will is an illusion, I must next ask, “what would
count as evidence for or against it being an illusion?”
As explained in my comments on the Week 7 home page, we
need to avoid circular reasoning, when searching for evidence.
We may not know, for sure, what would count as sufficient
evidence, but we can be confident that certain types of
reasoning are unreliable and weak. Let me briefly review two
flawed patterns of reasoning:
Circular Arguments: These arguments follow the pattern: I
know X is true, because X is true. Applied to free will, an
example would be, “I know my experience of free will is not an
illusion because I have experienced making free choices.”
Belief Bias: This occurs when we judge an argument based on
whether we agree with the conclusion. This is a flawed strategy
of evaluation because it’s possible to give terrible arguments for
true conclusions. (Try it: write down a statement you know to
be true as your conclusion. Then write down some random
statement as a premise. Is the argument a good one? Unless
you got really lucky with your random statement, it’s not.)
Why it matters: Avoiding circularity and belief bias matter for
many reasons. I’ll highlight one. If you settle for circular
arguments, or don’t worry about belief bias, then you deprive
yourself of the chance to discover really good arguments. You
may shield yourself psychologically from having to confront
uncomfortable challenges to your beliefs, but you also shield
yourself from finding really good arguments (foundations) for
your beliefs. So, if you’re interested in building your belief
structure on solid ground, rather than on sand, then you have a
reason to avoid circularity and belief bias. If you care about
truth, then you have another reason.
Some Examples from the discussions: I would say that about
95% of people who gave an argument against hard determinism
gave a circular argument. Here are some examples.
1. If this is true, why do we have a brain capable of making
decisions. [PG. This assumes we have a brain capable of making
decisions: i.e., a brain with free will. So the argument becomes,
hard determinism can’t be true, because it’s false.]
2. Hard determinism is false because “I believe that each person
has a free will, and ….I believe that one's own free will can
affect others through positive and negative interaction.” [PG:
This looks like belief bias. HD is rejected because the author of
the post doesn’t believe the view. The argument itself was not
directly addressed in this post.]
3. All of us have probably experienced something where it
seemed like we were meant to do something specific, based on
what we had learned and been through, but chose to do
something totally different. [PG: What we are debating is
whether the experience of choosing is an illusion. So the
question is how you know you are the chooser of your choice,
or whether it just seems like you are.]
4. HD is probably not true because, “However, in fact, I think
we do have choices and alternatives in a lot of daily situations.
For instance, when I plan to buy a drink, I can choose to buy
Pepsi, Cola, or orange juice, or perhaps I can buy them all.”
[PG: Notice first that this doesn’t exhibit belief bias because
the author supports the claim with reasons. However, the
reasons are circular: it assumes what needs to be shown,
namely, that the choice to buy Pepsi wasn’t determined by prior
material causes.]
I’ll just display other examples, I won’t comment. I hope that
by now – if you’re still reading – you will be able to see the
circularity. In each case below, the example simply assumes
what needs to be shown: i.e., the example avoids the question
that is being debated.
5. We have free will as shown by a case where a person chooses
how they will clean a house.
6. We have free will as shown by a case where a person chooses
to ignore a doctor’s orders.
7. We have free will as shown by our ability to freely choose
whether or not to follow God.
8. We have free will as shown by our ability to decide what
coffee we drink or what routes we take.
9. We have free will as shown by our decision to work hard (or
not) to succeed, or our decision about whether or not to rob a
bank.
10. We have free will as shown by cases where people grow up
in the same environments but make different choices. [PG: If it
could be shown that the people were identical, atom for atom, as
S.Harris says, and that they were exposed to exactly the same
set of causal inputs, yet still differed in their behavior, then this
would cast doubt on HD.]
11. We have free will as shown by cases where people are
indecisive, but then change their minds. [PG: What is at issue
is whether they changed their mind. How did that change
occur? A hard determinist will point to prior material causes.
A free will advocate might point so some other sort of cause.
My point here is that the act of changing a decision raises the
question, it doesn’t answer it.]
Summary: As you can see, the pull towards circularity is very
strong. But it should be resisted (I’m assuming HD is false and
we have a choice to resist) if we care about gaining a better
understanding of ourselves and how we are designed (I’ll leave
it open as to whether we were designed by a conscious being.)
The arguments we look at this week are non-circular (or at least
not as obviously circular) attempts to respond to the arguments
of hard determinism.
Finally: There will be a question or two about belief bias and
circular arguments on the next quiz! If you can point out the
circularity in the examples above, you will ace them. I hope
you do.

More Related Content

Similar to Cognitive Ability and Vulnerability to Fake Newshttpsgetpocke.docx

THE TRUTH ABOUT LYINGBy Allison KornetHas Lying Gotten.docx
THE TRUTH ABOUT LYINGBy Allison KornetHas Lying Gotten.docxTHE TRUTH ABOUT LYINGBy Allison KornetHas Lying Gotten.docx
THE TRUTH ABOUT LYINGBy Allison KornetHas Lying Gotten.docx
christalgrieg
 
Literature ReviewIn an article written by Eakin et al. in 2003 f.docx
Literature ReviewIn an article written by Eakin et al. in 2003 f.docxLiterature ReviewIn an article written by Eakin et al. in 2003 f.docx
Literature ReviewIn an article written by Eakin et al. in 2003 f.docx
SHIVA101531
 
ToK Essay May 2013 - The Possesssion of Knowledge carries an Ethical Responsi...
ToK Essay May 2013 - The Possesssion of Knowledge carries an Ethical Responsi...ToK Essay May 2013 - The Possesssion of Knowledge carries an Ethical Responsi...
ToK Essay May 2013 - The Possesssion of Knowledge carries an Ethical Responsi...
Raevenn Breen
 
10 things wrong with the effects model
10 things wrong with the effects model10 things wrong with the effects model
10 things wrong with the effects model
nctcmedia12
 
Birth order may not shape personality after all Guarino, .docx
Birth order may not shape personality after all  Guarino, .docxBirth order may not shape personality after all  Guarino, .docx
Birth order may not shape personality after all Guarino, .docx
moirarandell
 
discussion 1 - BRADYData is something that every researcher need.docx
discussion 1 - BRADYData is something that every researcher need.docxdiscussion 1 - BRADYData is something that every researcher need.docx
discussion 1 - BRADYData is something that every researcher need.docx
owenhall46084
 
Choose initial posts made by 2 separate people; comment on them;.docx
Choose initial posts made by 2 separate people; comment on them;.docxChoose initial posts made by 2 separate people; comment on them;.docx
Choose initial posts made by 2 separate people; comment on them;.docx
gordienaysmythe
 

Similar to Cognitive Ability and Vulnerability to Fake Newshttpsgetpocke.docx (15)

David gauntlett’s ’10 things wrong with the media 'effects' model
David gauntlett’s ’10 things wrong with the media 'effects' modelDavid gauntlett’s ’10 things wrong with the media 'effects' model
David gauntlett’s ’10 things wrong with the media 'effects' model
 
THE TRUTH ABOUT LYINGBy Allison KornetHas Lying Gotten.docx
THE TRUTH ABOUT LYINGBy Allison KornetHas Lying Gotten.docxTHE TRUTH ABOUT LYINGBy Allison KornetHas Lying Gotten.docx
THE TRUTH ABOUT LYINGBy Allison KornetHas Lying Gotten.docx
 
Teaching the Conspiracies - Mainz
Teaching the Conspiracies - MainzTeaching the Conspiracies - Mainz
Teaching the Conspiracies - Mainz
 
Psychics
PsychicsPsychics
Psychics
 
Literature ReviewIn an article written by Eakin et al. in 2003 f.docx
Literature ReviewIn an article written by Eakin et al. in 2003 f.docxLiterature ReviewIn an article written by Eakin et al. in 2003 f.docx
Literature ReviewIn an article written by Eakin et al. in 2003 f.docx
 
ToK Essay May 2013 - The Possesssion of Knowledge carries an Ethical Responsi...
ToK Essay May 2013 - The Possesssion of Knowledge carries an Ethical Responsi...ToK Essay May 2013 - The Possesssion of Knowledge carries an Ethical Responsi...
ToK Essay May 2013 - The Possesssion of Knowledge carries an Ethical Responsi...
 
10 things wrong with the effects model
10 things wrong with the effects model10 things wrong with the effects model
10 things wrong with the effects model
 
Birth order may not shape personality after all Guarino, .docx
Birth order may not shape personality after all  Guarino, .docxBirth order may not shape personality after all  Guarino, .docx
Birth order may not shape personality after all Guarino, .docx
 
Weinberger07
Weinberger07Weinberger07
Weinberger07
 
discussion 1 - BRADYData is something that every researcher need.docx
discussion 1 - BRADYData is something that every researcher need.docxdiscussion 1 - BRADYData is something that every researcher need.docx
discussion 1 - BRADYData is something that every researcher need.docx
 
Choose initial posts made by 2 separate people; comment on them;.docx
Choose initial posts made by 2 separate people; comment on them;.docxChoose initial posts made by 2 separate people; comment on them;.docx
Choose initial posts made by 2 separate people; comment on them;.docx
 
Trance Formation of America
Trance Formation of America Trance Formation of America
Trance Formation of America
 
Final Paper-FINAL PRODUCT
Final Paper-FINAL PRODUCTFinal Paper-FINAL PRODUCT
Final Paper-FINAL PRODUCT
 
Cathy o'brien &amp; mark phillips trance formation of america (mk-ultra, m...
Cathy o'brien  &amp; mark phillips   trance formation of america (mk-ultra, m...Cathy o'brien  &amp; mark phillips   trance formation of america (mk-ultra, m...
Cathy o'brien &amp; mark phillips trance formation of america (mk-ultra, m...
 
Brain Power
Brain PowerBrain Power
Brain Power
 

More from pickersgillkayne

CompetencyIn this project, you will demonstrate your mastery of .docx
CompetencyIn this project, you will demonstrate your mastery of .docxCompetencyIn this project, you will demonstrate your mastery of .docx
CompetencyIn this project, you will demonstrate your mastery of .docx
pickersgillkayne
 
CompetencyExplore advocacy opportunities in the community..docx
CompetencyExplore advocacy opportunities in the community..docxCompetencyExplore advocacy opportunities in the community..docx
CompetencyExplore advocacy opportunities in the community..docx
pickersgillkayne
 
CompetencyExamine leaderships role in executing successful change.docx
CompetencyExamine leaderships role in executing successful change.docxCompetencyExamine leaderships role in executing successful change.docx
CompetencyExamine leaderships role in executing successful change.docx
pickersgillkayne
 
CompetencyDescribe the atmosphere, biosphere, hydrosphere, g.docx
CompetencyDescribe the atmosphere, biosphere, hydrosphere, g.docxCompetencyDescribe the atmosphere, biosphere, hydrosphere, g.docx
CompetencyDescribe the atmosphere, biosphere, hydrosphere, g.docx
pickersgillkayne
 
CompetencyDevelop examples of ethical and privacy concerns a.docx
CompetencyDevelop examples of ethical and privacy concerns a.docxCompetencyDevelop examples of ethical and privacy concerns a.docx
CompetencyDevelop examples of ethical and privacy concerns a.docx
pickersgillkayne
 
CompetencyAssess the causes and consequences of historical e.docx
CompetencyAssess the causes and consequences of historical e.docxCompetencyAssess the causes and consequences of historical e.docx
CompetencyAssess the causes and consequences of historical e.docx
pickersgillkayne
 
CompetencyApply data analytic methodologies to diverse popul.docx
CompetencyApply data analytic methodologies to diverse popul.docxCompetencyApply data analytic methodologies to diverse popul.docx
CompetencyApply data analytic methodologies to diverse popul.docx
pickersgillkayne
 
CompetencyAssess the development of societal standards in re.docx
CompetencyAssess the development of societal standards in re.docxCompetencyAssess the development of societal standards in re.docx
CompetencyAssess the development of societal standards in re.docx
pickersgillkayne
 
CompetencyAnalyze the evolution of social media standards an.docx
CompetencyAnalyze the evolution of social media standards an.docxCompetencyAnalyze the evolution of social media standards an.docx
CompetencyAnalyze the evolution of social media standards an.docx
pickersgillkayne
 
CompetencyAnalyze the evolution of social media standards and .docx
CompetencyAnalyze the evolution of social media standards and .docxCompetencyAnalyze the evolution of social media standards and .docx
CompetencyAnalyze the evolution of social media standards and .docx
pickersgillkayne
 
CompetencyAnalyze leadership and management roles in change ma.docx
CompetencyAnalyze leadership and management roles in change ma.docxCompetencyAnalyze leadership and management roles in change ma.docx
CompetencyAnalyze leadership and management roles in change ma.docx
pickersgillkayne
 
Competency Checklist and Professional Development Resources .docx
Competency Checklist and Professional Development Resources .docxCompetency Checklist and Professional Development Resources .docx
Competency Checklist and Professional Development Resources .docx
pickersgillkayne
 
CompetenciesDetermine the historical impact of art on mode.docx
CompetenciesDetermine the historical impact of art on mode.docxCompetenciesDetermine the historical impact of art on mode.docx
CompetenciesDetermine the historical impact of art on mode.docx
pickersgillkayne
 

More from pickersgillkayne (20)

CompetencyIn this project, you will demonstrate your mastery of .docx
CompetencyIn this project, you will demonstrate your mastery of .docxCompetencyIn this project, you will demonstrate your mastery of .docx
CompetencyIn this project, you will demonstrate your mastery of .docx
 
CompetencyExplore advocacy opportunities in the community..docx
CompetencyExplore advocacy opportunities in the community..docxCompetencyExplore advocacy opportunities in the community..docx
CompetencyExplore advocacy opportunities in the community..docx
 
CompetencyEvaluate the role and impact of financial principl.docx
CompetencyEvaluate the role and impact of financial principl.docxCompetencyEvaluate the role and impact of financial principl.docx
CompetencyEvaluate the role and impact of financial principl.docx
 
CompetencyEvaluate the impact of innovation on team success..docx
CompetencyEvaluate the impact of innovation on team success..docxCompetencyEvaluate the impact of innovation on team success..docx
CompetencyEvaluate the impact of innovation on team success..docx
 
CompetencyEvaluate the role of identity, diverse segments, a.docx
CompetencyEvaluate the role of identity, diverse segments, a.docxCompetencyEvaluate the role of identity, diverse segments, a.docx
CompetencyEvaluate the role of identity, diverse segments, a.docx
 
CompetencyExamine leaderships role in executing successful change.docx
CompetencyExamine leaderships role in executing successful change.docxCompetencyExamine leaderships role in executing successful change.docx
CompetencyExamine leaderships role in executing successful change.docx
 
CompetencyEvaluate psychological theories and their insights.docx
CompetencyEvaluate psychological theories and their insights.docxCompetencyEvaluate psychological theories and their insights.docx
CompetencyEvaluate psychological theories and their insights.docx
 
CompetencyEmploy contemporary economic principles that guide.docx
CompetencyEmploy contemporary economic principles that guide.docxCompetencyEmploy contemporary economic principles that guide.docx
CompetencyEmploy contemporary economic principles that guide.docx
 
CompetencyDetermine how the environment and economies are in.docx
CompetencyDetermine how the environment and economies are in.docxCompetencyDetermine how the environment and economies are in.docx
CompetencyDetermine how the environment and economies are in.docx
 
CompetencyDescribe the atmosphere, biosphere, hydrosphere, g.docx
CompetencyDescribe the atmosphere, biosphere, hydrosphere, g.docxCompetencyDescribe the atmosphere, biosphere, hydrosphere, g.docx
CompetencyDescribe the atmosphere, biosphere, hydrosphere, g.docx
 
CompetencyDevelop examples of ethical and privacy concerns a.docx
CompetencyDevelop examples of ethical and privacy concerns a.docxCompetencyDevelop examples of ethical and privacy concerns a.docx
CompetencyDevelop examples of ethical and privacy concerns a.docx
 
CompetencyAssess the causes and consequences of historical e.docx
CompetencyAssess the causes and consequences of historical e.docxCompetencyAssess the causes and consequences of historical e.docx
CompetencyAssess the causes and consequences of historical e.docx
 
CompetencyApply data analytic methodologies to diverse popul.docx
CompetencyApply data analytic methodologies to diverse popul.docxCompetencyApply data analytic methodologies to diverse popul.docx
CompetencyApply data analytic methodologies to diverse popul.docx
 
CompetencyAssess the development of societal standards in re.docx
CompetencyAssess the development of societal standards in re.docxCompetencyAssess the development of societal standards in re.docx
CompetencyAssess the development of societal standards in re.docx
 
CompetencyAnalyze the evolution of social media standards an.docx
CompetencyAnalyze the evolution of social media standards an.docxCompetencyAnalyze the evolution of social media standards an.docx
CompetencyAnalyze the evolution of social media standards an.docx
 
CompetencyAnalyze the evolution of social media standards and .docx
CompetencyAnalyze the evolution of social media standards and .docxCompetencyAnalyze the evolution of social media standards and .docx
CompetencyAnalyze the evolution of social media standards and .docx
 
CompetencyAnalyze leadership and management roles in change ma.docx
CompetencyAnalyze leadership and management roles in change ma.docxCompetencyAnalyze leadership and management roles in change ma.docx
CompetencyAnalyze leadership and management roles in change ma.docx
 
CompetencyAnalyze financial statements to assess performance a.docx
CompetencyAnalyze financial statements to assess performance a.docxCompetencyAnalyze financial statements to assess performance a.docx
CompetencyAnalyze financial statements to assess performance a.docx
 
Competency Checklist and Professional Development Resources .docx
Competency Checklist and Professional Development Resources .docxCompetency Checklist and Professional Development Resources .docx
Competency Checklist and Professional Development Resources .docx
 
CompetenciesDetermine the historical impact of art on mode.docx
CompetenciesDetermine the historical impact of art on mode.docxCompetenciesDetermine the historical impact of art on mode.docx
CompetenciesDetermine the historical impact of art on mode.docx
 

Recently uploaded

Recently uploaded (20)

On_Translating_a_Tamil_Poem_by_A_K_Ramanujan.pptx
On_Translating_a_Tamil_Poem_by_A_K_Ramanujan.pptxOn_Translating_a_Tamil_Poem_by_A_K_Ramanujan.pptx
On_Translating_a_Tamil_Poem_by_A_K_Ramanujan.pptx
 
UGC NET Paper 1 Mathematical Reasoning & Aptitude.pdf
UGC NET Paper 1 Mathematical Reasoning & Aptitude.pdfUGC NET Paper 1 Mathematical Reasoning & Aptitude.pdf
UGC NET Paper 1 Mathematical Reasoning & Aptitude.pdf
 
Understanding Accommodations and Modifications
Understanding  Accommodations and ModificationsUnderstanding  Accommodations and Modifications
Understanding Accommodations and Modifications
 
Fostering Friendships - Enhancing Social Bonds in the Classroom
Fostering Friendships - Enhancing Social Bonds  in the ClassroomFostering Friendships - Enhancing Social Bonds  in the Classroom
Fostering Friendships - Enhancing Social Bonds in the Classroom
 
Basic Intentional Injuries Health Education
Basic Intentional Injuries Health EducationBasic Intentional Injuries Health Education
Basic Intentional Injuries Health Education
 
latest AZ-104 Exam Questions and Answers
latest AZ-104 Exam Questions and Answerslatest AZ-104 Exam Questions and Answers
latest AZ-104 Exam Questions and Answers
 
This PowerPoint helps students to consider the concept of infinity.
This PowerPoint helps students to consider the concept of infinity.This PowerPoint helps students to consider the concept of infinity.
This PowerPoint helps students to consider the concept of infinity.
 
General Principles of Intellectual Property: Concepts of Intellectual Proper...
General Principles of Intellectual Property: Concepts of Intellectual  Proper...General Principles of Intellectual Property: Concepts of Intellectual  Proper...
General Principles of Intellectual Property: Concepts of Intellectual Proper...
 
Sociology 101 Demonstration of Learning Exhibit
Sociology 101 Demonstration of Learning ExhibitSociology 101 Demonstration of Learning Exhibit
Sociology 101 Demonstration of Learning Exhibit
 
Wellbeing inclusion and digital dystopias.pptx
Wellbeing inclusion and digital dystopias.pptxWellbeing inclusion and digital dystopias.pptx
Wellbeing inclusion and digital dystopias.pptx
 
Jamworks pilot and AI at Jisc (20/03/2024)
Jamworks pilot and AI at Jisc (20/03/2024)Jamworks pilot and AI at Jisc (20/03/2024)
Jamworks pilot and AI at Jisc (20/03/2024)
 
Basic Civil Engineering first year Notes- Chapter 4 Building.pptx
Basic Civil Engineering first year Notes- Chapter 4 Building.pptxBasic Civil Engineering first year Notes- Chapter 4 Building.pptx
Basic Civil Engineering first year Notes- Chapter 4 Building.pptx
 
HMCS Vancouver Pre-Deployment Brief - May 2024 (Web Version).pptx
HMCS Vancouver Pre-Deployment Brief - May 2024 (Web Version).pptxHMCS Vancouver Pre-Deployment Brief - May 2024 (Web Version).pptx
HMCS Vancouver Pre-Deployment Brief - May 2024 (Web Version).pptx
 
TỔNG ÔN TẬP THI VÀO LỚP 10 MÔN TIẾNG ANH NĂM HỌC 2023 - 2024 CÓ ĐÁP ÁN (NGỮ Â...
TỔNG ÔN TẬP THI VÀO LỚP 10 MÔN TIẾNG ANH NĂM HỌC 2023 - 2024 CÓ ĐÁP ÁN (NGỮ Â...TỔNG ÔN TẬP THI VÀO LỚP 10 MÔN TIẾNG ANH NĂM HỌC 2023 - 2024 CÓ ĐÁP ÁN (NGỮ Â...
TỔNG ÔN TẬP THI VÀO LỚP 10 MÔN TIẾNG ANH NĂM HỌC 2023 - 2024 CÓ ĐÁP ÁN (NGỮ Â...
 
Single or Multiple melodic lines structure
Single or Multiple melodic lines structureSingle or Multiple melodic lines structure
Single or Multiple melodic lines structure
 
How to Create and Manage Wizard in Odoo 17
How to Create and Manage Wizard in Odoo 17How to Create and Manage Wizard in Odoo 17
How to Create and Manage Wizard in Odoo 17
 
Exploring_the_Narrative_Style_of_Amitav_Ghoshs_Gun_Island.pptx
Exploring_the_Narrative_Style_of_Amitav_Ghoshs_Gun_Island.pptxExploring_the_Narrative_Style_of_Amitav_Ghoshs_Gun_Island.pptx
Exploring_the_Narrative_Style_of_Amitav_Ghoshs_Gun_Island.pptx
 
SOC 101 Demonstration of Learning Presentation
SOC 101 Demonstration of Learning PresentationSOC 101 Demonstration of Learning Presentation
SOC 101 Demonstration of Learning Presentation
 
21st_Century_Skills_Framework_Final_Presentation_2.pptx
21st_Century_Skills_Framework_Final_Presentation_2.pptx21st_Century_Skills_Framework_Final_Presentation_2.pptx
21st_Century_Skills_Framework_Final_Presentation_2.pptx
 
Accessible Digital Futures project (20/03/2024)
Accessible Digital Futures project (20/03/2024)Accessible Digital Futures project (20/03/2024)
Accessible Digital Futures project (20/03/2024)
 

Cognitive Ability and Vulnerability to Fake Newshttpsgetpocke.docx

  • 1. Cognitive Ability and Vulnerability to Fake News https://getpocket.com/explore/item/cognitive-ability-and- vulnerability-to-fake-news?utm_source=pocket-newtab Researchers identify a major risk factor for pernicious effects of misinformation. Scientific American · David Z. Hambrick · Madeline Marquardt Photo by gguy44 / Getty Images. “Fake news” is Donald Trump’s favorite catchphrase. Since the 2016 election, it has appeared in hundreds of tweets by the President, decrying everything from accusations of sexual assault against him to the Russian collusion investigation to reports that he watches up to eight hours of television a day. Trump may just use “fake news” as a rhetorical device to discredit stories he doesn’t like, but there is evidence that real fake news is a serious problem. As one alarming example, an analysis by the internet media company Buzzfeed revealed that during the final three months of the 2016 U.S. presidential campaign, the 20 most popular false election stories generated around 1.3 million more Facebook engagements—shares, reactions, and comments—than did the 20 most popular legitimate stories. The most popular fake story was “Pope Francis Shocks World, Endorses Donald Trump for President.” Fake news can distort people’s beliefs even after being debunked. For example, repeated over and over, a story such as the one about the Pope endorsing Trump can create a glow around a political candidate that persists long after the story is exposed as fake. A 2017 study published in the journal Intelligence suggests that some people may have an especially difficult time rejecting misinformation. Asked to rate a fictitious person on a range of character traits, people who scored low on a test of cognitive ability continued to be
  • 2. influenced by damaging information about the person even after they were explicitly told the information was false. The study is significant because it identifies what may be a major risk factor for vulnerability to fake news. Ghent University researchers Jonas De keersmaecker and Arne Roets first had over 400 subjects take a personality test. They then randomly assigned each subject to one of two conditions. In the experimental condition, the subjects read a biographical description of a young woman named Nathalie. The bio explained that Nathalie, a nurse at a local hospital, “was arrested for stealing drugs from the hospital; she has been stealing drugs for 2 years and selling them on the street in order to buy designer clothes.” The subjects then rated Nathalie on traits such as trustworthiness and sincerity, after which they took a test of cognitive ability. Finally, the subjects saw a message on their computer screen explicitly stating that the information about Nathalie stealing drugs and getting arrested was not true, and then rated her again on the same traits. The control condition was identical, except that subjects were not given the paragraph with the false information and rated Nathalie only once. The subjects in the experimental condition initially rated Nathalie much more negatively than did the subjects in the control condition. This was not surprising, considering that they had just learned she was a thief and a drug dealer. The interesting question was whether cognitive ability would predict attitude adjustment—that is, the degree to which the subjects in the experimental condition would rate Nathalie more favorably after being told that this information was false. It did: subjects high in cognitive ability adjusted their ratings more than did those lower in cognitive ability. The subjects with lower cognitive ability had more trouble shaking their negative first impression of Nathalie. This was true even after the researchers statistically controlled for the subjects’ level of open- mindedness (their willingness to change their mind when wrong) and right-wing authoritarianism (their intolerance
  • 3. toward others), as assessed by the personality test. Thus, even if a person was open-minded and tolerant, a low level of cognitive ability put them at risk for being unjustifiably harsh in their second evaluation of Nathalie. One possible explanation for this finding is based on the theory that a person’s cognitive ability reflects how well they can regulate the contents of working memory—their “mental workspace” for processing information. First proposed by the cognitive psychologists Lynn Hasher and Rose Zacks, this theory holds that some people are more prone to “mental clutter” than other people. In other words, some people are less able to discard (or “inhibit”) information from their working memory that is no longer relevant to the task at hand—or, as in the case of Nathalie, information that has been discredited. Research on cognitive aging indicates that, in adulthood, this ability declines considerably with advancing age, suggesting that older adults may also be especially vulnerable to fake news. Another reason why cognitive ability may predict vulnerability to fake news is that it correlates highly with education. Through education, people may develop meta-cognitive skills—strategies for monitoring and regulating one’s own thinking—that can be used to combat the effects of misinformation. Meanwhile, other research is shedding light on the mechanisms underlying the effects of misinformation. Repeating a false claim increases its believability, giving it an air of what Stephen Colbert famously called “truthiness.” Known as the illusion of truth effect, this phenomenon was first demonstrated in the laboratory by Hasher and her colleagues. On each of three days, subjects listened to plausible-sounding statements and rated each on whether they thought it was true. Half of the statements were in fact true, such as Australia is approximately equal in area to the continental United States, whereas the other half were false, such as Zachary Taylor was the first president to die in office (it was William Henry Harrison). Some of the statements were repeated across days, whereas others were presented only once. The results showed that the average truth
  • 4. rating increased from day to day for the repeated statements, but remained constant for the non-repeated statements, indicating that subjects mistook familiarity for verity. More recent research reveals that even knowledge of the truth doesn’t necessarily protect against the illusion of truth. In a 2015 study published in the Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, Lisa Fazio and her colleagues asked subjects to rate a set of statements on how interesting they found them. Following Hasher and colleagues’ procedure, some of the statements were true, whereas others were false. The subjects then rated a second set of statements for truthfulness on a six-point scale, from definitely false to definitely true. Some of the statements were repeated from the first set, whereas others were new. Finally, the subjects took a knowledge test that included questions based on the statements. The results revealed that repetition increased the subjects’ perception of the truthfulness of false statements, even for statements they knew to be false. For example, even if a subject correctly answered Pacific Ocean to the question What is the largest ocean on Earth? on the knowledge test, they still tended to give the false statement The Atlantic Ocean is the largest ocean on Earth a higher truth rating if it was repeated. When a claim was made to feel familiar through repetition, subjects neglected to consult their own knowledge base in rating the claim’s truthfulness. These studies add to scientific understanding of the fake news problem, which is providing a foundation for an evidenced- based approach to addressing the problem. A recommendation that follows from research on the illusion of truth effect is to serve as your own fact checker. If you are convinced that some claim is true, ask yourself why. Is it because you have credible evidence that the claim is true, or is it just because you’ve encountered the claim over and over? Also ask yourself if you know of any evidence that refutes the claim. (You just might be surprised to find that you do.) This type of recommendation could be promoted through public service announcements, which have been shown to be effective for things like getting
  • 5. people to litter less and recycle more. For its part, research on individual differences in susceptibility to fake news, such as the study by De keersmaecker and Roets, can help to identify people who are particularly important to reach through this type of informational campaign. At a more general level, this research underscores the threat that fake news poses to democratic society. The aim of using fake news as propaganda is to make people think and behave in ways they wouldn’t otherwise—for example, hold a view that is contradicted by overwhelming scientific consensus. When this nefarious aim is achieved, citizens no longer have the ability to act in their own self-interest. In the logic of democracy, this isn’t just bad for that citizen—it’s bad for society. David Z. Hambrick is a professor in the department of psychology at Michigan State University. His research focuses on individual differences in cognitive ability and complex skill. Madeline Marquardt graduated Michigan State University in 2018 with a degree in Neuroscience and additional degree in Professional Writing and is now a TEFL Peace Corps Volunteer in Armenia. Advertisement More from Scientific American This post originally appeared on Scientific American and was published February 5, 2018. This article is republished here with permission. Chapter 8. Do We Have Free Will? 20 Chapter 8 Do We Have Free Will?
  • 6. Read the section after page ten Copyright by Paul Herrick, 2020. For class use only. Not for distribution. This chapter: 26 pages of reading. 1. A Sign of the Times More and more people are giving up the traditional belief in free will. Public intellectuals with large followings such as Sam Harris are a sign of the times. After describing the horrific home invasion murder spree in 2007 that earned two criminals named Hayes and Komisarjevsky six consecutive life sentences without parole for their cold-blooded murders of a defenseless family, Harris, a prominent New Atheist writes the following about the killers in his best-selling book Free Will: Whatever their conscious motives, those men cannot know why they are as they are. Nor can we account for why we are not like them. As sickening as I find their behavior, I have to admit that if I were to trade places with one of them, atom for atom, I would be him: There is no extra part of me [such as an immaterial soul] that could decide to see the world differently or to resist the impulse to victimize other people. . . . If I had truly been in Komisarjevsky’s shoes on July 23, 2007—that is, if I had his genes and life experience and an identical brain. . . . in an identical state—I would have acted exactly as he did. . . . The role of luck, therefore, appears to be decisive. Harris concludes from this: Free will is an illusion. Our wills are simply not of our own making. Thoughts and intentions emerge from background causes of which we are unaware and over which we exert no conscious control. We must also give up our belief in moral responsibility:
  • 7. The men and women on death row have some combination of bad genes, bad parents, bad environment, and bad ideas (and the innocent, of course, have supremely bad luck). Which of these quantities, exactly, were they responsible for? No human being is responsible for his genes or his upbringing, yet we have every reason to believe these factors determine his character. (emphasis added) In short, lacking free will, no one deserves either credit or blame for anything they’ve done. How much credit does a person deserve for not being lazy? None at all. Laziness, like diligence, is a neurological condition . . . [Again] free will is an illusion. If Harris is correct, no one has free will, no one is morally responsible for his choices or his character, no matter what he does, and no one deserves praise, blame, reward or punishment for anything he has done. Luck, rather than choice, is “decisive” in life. If a young student from a difficult background works hard, sacrifices, and graduates from college with honors, he or she deserves no credit or praise—his accomplishment is due to luck not his own free will. If someone robs a bank and shoots three tellers as they plead for their lives, he deserves neither blame nor punishment. His action is due to unfortunate circumstances, for (again) luck, rather than character, choice, or effort, “appears to be decisive.” Each of us would have done the same thing—robbed the bank and shot all three tellers—if we had the same genes and had grown up in the same background. The unspoken implication, I believe, is that no one can justifiably say that he or she is a better person than a serial killer, a carjacker, or a bank robber. Are free will and moral responsibility illusions, as Sam Harris and others in the New Atheist movement claim? Are they outdated myths held over from ignorant times? Is it time to give up the traditional beliefs in free will and personal accountability? These are the big questions of this chapter—
  • 8. questions that go to the heart of what kind of beings we really are. We’ll approach the issue in stages, beginning with a thought experiment that will help make even more vivid the fundamental concepts at stake. 2. The Psychology Student In his thought-provoking book, The Strangeness of the Ordinary: Problems and Issues in Contemporary Metaphysics, the philosopher Robert Coburn (1931–2018) asks us to imagine the following scenario: A group of scientists have discovered a way to send radio signals to an experimental subject’s brain and activate individual brain cells. They also know which kinds of actions are caused by which groups of brain cells. So they know that if they send signal X into a certain region in the brain, the subject will automatically stand up, if they send signal Y, he will eat a hamburger, and so forth. By targeting specific brain cells, they can manipulate a test subject as if he is a puppet on a string. Coburn next asks us to imagine that an undergrad in psychology volunteers to be an experimental guinea pig. Everything the volunteer will do during the next month will be caused remotely by these scientists from their laboratory. So, with the consent forms signed and the electrodes in place, the experiment begins. On the first day, the scientists send signals into the student’s brain that cause him to watch reruns of the 1950s TV series Gunsmoke. On the second day, they cause him to order takeout online, and so forth. At any moment, there is only one thing the test subject can do—that which the scientists at that moment cause him to do. The subject cannot do anything but exactly what he is caused to do by the radio signals sent by the scientists. Was the student acting of his own free will during the experiment? Would we hold him morally responsible for his actions during the test month? Would we blame him if the scientists caused him to rob a bank? Would we give him credit
  • 9. if they made him rescue someone drowning in a lake? These questions are asked within the context of our ordinary, everyday moral thinking. Surely we would not hold the student accountable if the scientists caused him to rob a bank or steal a car. Nor would we give him praise or credit if the scientists caused him to do a good deed such as saving a life. And the reason we would not is that at each moment during the experiment, the student couldn’t do anything other than exactly what he was caused to do. The general principle we apply here is this: If a person does something and the person could not possibly have done anything else at the moment, given the causes at work just prior to the moment of action, then the person is not acting of his or her own free will, the person is not morally responsible, and the person deserves neither praise nor blame. Next, Coburn brings in our ordinary concept of causation. In everyday life, we assume that every event has a cause. If your car’s engine dies, you naturally suppose that something caused it to die. If you get sick, you assume that something caused your illness. But we also assume that human actions have causes. If someone does something odd, we say, “I wonder what caused him do that?” Sometimes we say to ourselves, “What made me to do such a thing?” or “What got into me?” Coburn now asks a great question: Does it make any difference, with respect to free will, praise, blame, and moral responsibility, whether (a) our actions are caused by scientists in a remote lab sending signals into our brains, or (b) our actions are caused by our social environment, our genes, the wiring in our brains, and the sum total of all previous causes at work in the universe? Aren’t we unfree in either case? But doesn’t everything have a cause? If so, how is it even possible we have free will or moral responsibility? 3. Definitions Before We Proceed Our discussion so far has brought to the surface several key concepts. Each needs to be sharpened before we proceed, or
  • 10. things will get murky and lines of reasoning will fray. Moral Responsibility Suppose that Pat is admiring a painting at an art museum when someone rushes up behind her and without warning violently pushes her into the painting. Would we blame her for the damage? Would we hold her morally responsible? Or would we blame the person who pushed her? Surely we would not blame the victim here. And the reason we would not is obvious: once she was violently pushed from behind without warning, she could not have done otherwise (than fall into the painting). Two principles are at work in this case: the first is known in philosophy as the “principle of alternate possibilities”; the second we’ll call the “praise and blame principle.” Both reflect our moral common sense. The Principle of Alternate Possibilities: If a person on a particular occasion performs an action and the person at the moment could not have done otherwise, then the person is not morally responsible for performing the action. This is logically equivalent to the following: If a person on a particular occasion is morally responsible for performing an action, then the person could have done otherwise at the time. Next: The Praise and Blame Principle: If a person is not morally responsible for performing an action, then that person deserves neither praise nor blame for the action. These ideas lead us to think about the meaning of free will. This is a very difficult concept.
  • 11. Toward an Account of Free Will Suppose that a person who suffers from epilepsy has a seizure and uncontrollably falls to the ground. We would not ordinarily say the person fell of his or her own free will. And the reason we would not is surely that once the seizure occurred, that person could not have done anything else but fall. This suggests the following principle: If a person at a particular moment does something and the person could not possibly have done otherwise at that moment, given all the prior conditions that led up to the moment, then the individual was not acting of his or her own free will. This is logically equivalent to the following statement: If a person at a particular moment does something of his or her own free will, then that individual could have done otherwise, given the very same antecedent conditions leading up to the moment. An important consequence follows. If a person performs an action at a time t and that person could have done otherwise at t, given the very same antecedent causes and conditions, then at time t the person had the power to do what he did, call it “action A,” and at the same time and with the same antecedent conditions, the person also had the power to do something else instead, call it “action B.” These thoughts suggest a tentative account of free will: A person P has free will at a moment in time t if, and only if, at time t, P has it within his or her power to do one thing, action A, and at the same time and under the same conditions, and given the same antecedent causes and conditions, P also has it within his or her power to do something else instead, action B. For example, suppose someone orders a salad in a restaurant.
  • 12. We would say the person “freely” ordered the salad if we believe that (a) at the moment the person placed his order he had it within his power to order the salad, and (b) at the same time the person also had the power to order something else instead, or nothing at all. This is a “two-power” account of free will. On the basis of a similar idea, the philosopher Robert Kane describes free will as the possession of “dual power.” Some philosophers express the same idea when they define free will concisely as “the ability to have done otherwise.” Let’s incorporate these thoughts into our account by saying that a person has free will if, on at least some occasions, the person possesses two powers at the same time: the power or ability to perform one action A and the power or ability to perform an alternative action B under the same conditions and given the same past causes and conditions. If you have dual power, then on some occasions, you do one thing, but at the same time, with the past exactly as it was and present conditions exactly as they are, you could have done something else instead. Put differently, you act of your own free will if you do something while at the same time possessing the (unactualized) power to have done something else instead, given the same antecedent circumstances and past events. This is an analysis of the common account of free will. We are often urged to take ownership of our actions, and we often say things like, “That was my bad,” “It’s up to you” and “You own that one.” The common account of free will just outlined helps explain the sense in which our free actions are truly our own, the sense in which our actions are up to us in the final analysis. For on this account, we are the causes of our free actions. Whether we have free will or not, this would seem to be the kind of freedom required by our ordinary notions of free will, praise, blame, and moral responsibility. Cause and Effect What do we ordinarily mean when we say that A “caused” B? We normally mean that the occurrence of A was a sufficient
  • 13. condition for the occurrence of B. If A is a sufficient condition for some event B, then once A happens, or obtains, B must happen, in the same sense that a normal cube of sugar must melt once it is dropped into a cup of boiling water, or an ordinary wine glass must shatter if it is dropped from twenty feet above onto a concrete surface. If B must occur once A has occurred, then nothing else but B can occur (once A has occurred). Put still another way, if A is sufficient for B, then once A exists, B is inevitable. The point is so important it must be reinforced with a visual image. Imagine a row of dominoes lined up so that when the first one falls, it will knock over the second one, and so on down the line. Once the first domino is pushed, it is only a matter of time before the last domino inevitably falls. Similarly, if A causes B and B causes C and so on to Z, then once A happens, Z must eventually occur; Z is inevitable. Determinism One final building block idea remains to be explained. Determinism is the view that every event, including the occurrence of every human action, has a sufficient cause (hereinafter “cause” for short), which in turn has a cause, and so forth back and back as far as cause and effect go. If determinism is true, then we live in a “deterministic universe.” As we’ve seen, cosmologists have already traced an unbroken chain of physical causes and effects back fourteen billion years to the Big Bang. Thus, according to determinism informed by science, every event that occurs today—including every human action--can be traced back, through a chain of deterministic causes and effects, fourteen billion years to the Big Bang. If we live in a deterministic universe, then the event consisting of you reading this sentence this moment was already set to occur fourteen billion years ago. Indeed, if determinism is true, every event in your life was already set to occur before you were
  • 14. born. Now, with these fundamental concepts sharpened, we are ready for the big arguments. In modern philosophy, there are four major positions on the question of free will, standardly named “hard determinism,” “soft determinism” (also called “compatibilism”), “simple indeterminism,” and “agent causation.” Just about every theory of free will under discussion today is a variation on, or is derived from, one of these four major viewpoints. Questions for Reflection and Discussion 8.1 1. In the thought experiment at the beginning of this chapter, is the student acting of his own free will during the experiment? Discuss. 2. Is the student responsible for his actions during the experiment? Discuss. 3. Does the student ever deserve praise or blame during the experiment? Discuss. 4. According to the common account, when are we morally responsible for our actions? 5. On the common account, when do we deserve praise or blame for our actions? 6. According to the common notion, what is a free action? What is free will? 7. What is dual power alleged to be? 8. Does it matter whether we have free will? “What difference does it make?” 9. At this point in the discussion, do you believe we have free
  • 15. will? Why or why not? 10. This may require some research. At this point in the discussion, were Hayes and Komisarjevsky morally responsible for their crime? Did they deserve to be punished? Were they acting of their own free will? What is your opinion? Discuss. 4. Hard Determinism Consider the following argument: 1. Determinism is true, that is to say, every event, including the occurrence of every human action, has a determining or sufficient cause, which has a cause, and so forth back and back billions of years, as far back as cause and effect go. 2. If A caused B, then once A happened, B had to happen in the sense that nothing but B could happen next. Put another way, once A happened, B became inevitable. 3. It follows that at any moment in time, when a person performs an action, that person could not have done otherwise at the moment. 4. If at a moment in time a person could not have done otherwise, then at that moment the person was not acting of his or her own free will. (This is the common account of free will.) 5. If a person could not have done otherwise in a situation, then that person is not morally responsible for what he or she has done. (This is the principle of alternate possibilities.) 6. If a person is not morally responsible for his action, then he deserves neither praise nor blame. (This is the praise and blame principle.) 7. Therefore, it follows necessarily that no one has free will, no one is morally responsible for his or her actions, and no one ever deserves praise or blame, reward or punishment. If you accept the premises and conclusion of this deductive argument, your philosophical position is called “hard determinism” and you are a “hard determinist.” Notice that hard
  • 16. determinists accept the common definitions of free will and moral responsibility—they just believe these definitions apply to no one. In other words, like Sam Harris, they believe that free will and moral responsibility, although they can be defined, are illusions. The seven-step argument for hard determinism just stated is deductively valid (if its premises are true, its conclusion must be true). The only question is therefore, Is it sound? (In addition to being valid, are its premises true?) Incompatibilism If you read books on hard determinism, you’ll notice that hard determinists are sometimes called “incompatibilists.” Incompatibilism in this context is the view that freedom and determinism are logically incompatible. What does this mean? Two statements P and Q are logically incompatible if it is impossible that both are true. Incompatibilism with respect to free will and determinism is therefore the claim that it is impossible that determinism is true and at the same time we have free will. So, when hard determinism is under discussion, incompatibilism is the claim that if we are free, then we are not determined, and if we are determined, then we are not free. Here is an argument for incompatibilism: 1. If at a moment in time a person performs an action and at that moment the person could not have done otherwise, then the person was not acting of his or her own free will. 2. If at a moment in time a person performs an action and at that moment the person could have done otherwise, then the person was acting of his or her own free will. 3. If determinism is true, then at each moment in time, no one could have done otherwise. 4. Thus, if determinism is true, no one has free will, and if we
  • 17. sometimes act of our own free will, then determinism is false. 5. Therefore, freedom and determinism are logically incompatible—they cannot both be true. The hard determinist endorses incompatibilism, for he believes that we cannot be both free and determined. With incompatibilisim defined, a shorter argument for hard determinism can be given. 1. Determinism is true. 2. Incompatibilism is true. 3. Therefore, necessarily no one has free will. This argument, like the longer argument for hard determinism, is valid. But is it sound? <Box> Hard Determinism’s Early Boosters Baron Paul Henri d’Holbach (1723–1789), a famous eighteenth- century German intellectual, gave hard determinism one of its first modern expressions. On the assumption that the principle of universal determinism is true, Holbach argued: In whatever manner man is considered, he is connected to universal nature, and submitted to the necessary and immutable laws that she imposes on all the beings she contains . . . Man’s life is a line that nature commands him to outline upon the surface of the earth, without his ever being able to swerve from it, even for an instant. He is born without his own consent; his organization does in nowise depend upon himself; his ideas come to him involuntarily; his habits are in the power of those who cause him to contract them; he is unceasingly modified by causes, whether visible or concealed, over which he has no control, which necessarily regulate his mode of existence, give the hue to his way of thinking, and determine his manner of
  • 18. acting. He is good or bad . . . without his will counting for anything in these various states. From this he concluded that free will and moral responsibility do not exist. At about the same time, the French mathematical physicist P. S. Laplace (1749–1827) illustrated the idea of hard determinism with a colorful example. In The System of the World, Laplace used calculus and Newton’s mathematical laws of motion to calculate the future paths of the planets with precision. After this accomplishment, he assumed that his calculations apply to the entire universe, including each human action. Human actions, he concluded, are as predictable as the motions of the planets. Thus, if a superintelligence were to know all the laws of physics and the position and momentum of every particle of matter in the universe, including every particle of matter composing every human body, it could predict every future event, including every future human action. Laplace wrote: Given for one instant an intelligence which could comprehend all the forces by which nature is animated and the respective situations of the beings who compose it—an intelligence sufficiently vast to submit these data to analysis—it would embrace in the same formula the movements of the greatest bodies of the universe and those of the lightest atom; for it, nothing would be uncertain and the future, as the past, would be present to its eyes. Claims like these, coming from respected scholars and scientists, convinced many people during the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries that hard determinism is true and thus that free will and moral responsibility are illusions. There was just one problem. Holbach never gave an argument for his key claim, namely, that literally everything, including each human action, is determined. His key claim was simply an
  • 19. unsubstantiated assumption—it was backed by no argument at all. Likewise, Laplace gave no argument for his key claim, that everything in the universe is determined including every human action. He simply assumed it without any scientific proof or evidence at all. The principle of universal determinism had not been proved by the science of the day, and it has not to this day been proved. Indeed, we now know that it cannot be proved by science alone, for it is a metaphysical, rather than a scientific, claim. Both men also assumed without argument that human actions are natural events caused in the same way everything else is caused—by physical sequences of cause and effect. This, too, had not been proved by science and has not been proved by science to this day, as we saw in the previous chapter. Despite their scientific pretensions, neither Holbach nor Laplace offered a scientific proof for their deterministic and materialist assumptions. There is a word for this kind of thinking: it is called “dogmatism.” It can also be called “sophistry.” <End Box> 5. Two Philosophical Arguments against Hard Determinism Van Inwagen’s Deliberation Argument Although science has not proved that hard determinism is true, there are philosophical arguments that claim to show that it is false. Peter van Inwagen offers one in the form of a thought experiment. Imagine you are seated in a windowless room with no exits other than two solid steel doors in front of you. You are told that one of the two doors is welded shut, but you do not know which of the two this is. Given these details, try to imagine deliberating over which door to exit by. Van Inwagen argues that, although it would make sense to deliberate about which of the two doors to try to exit by, that is, which door handle to try to turn, it would not make sense to
  • 20. deliberate about which door to exit by. Why? I am paraphrasing his answer: You cannot rationally deliberate over whether to take one course of action (call it “A”) or an alternative, incompatible course of action B unless you believe at some level that at the moment of choice you have it within your power to do A, and at the same time you also have it within your power to do B. If you know that of two incompatible courses of action A and B, one of the two is impossible, then it makes no sense to deliberate over which of the two courses of action to actually take. You might deliberate over which course of action to attempt, but not over which course of action to take. Now imagine a different setup. This time you know that both doors are unlocked. If you turn the knob on the first door, it will open. If you turn the knob on the second door, it will open. In this case, it makes sense to imagine deliberating over which door to exit by. This thought experiment, argues van Inwagen, uncovers an important logical truth about human action, namely, that you cannot rationally deliberate about whether to do A or to do B unless you believe at some level that both courses of action are open to you, that is, are possible at the moment. In other words, unless you believe that you can do A and you can do B. Assuming the common sense “two powers” account of free will, van Inwagen’s claim implies that you cannot rationally deliberate unless you at least believe you have free will. Next, van Inwagen observes, human behavior can manifest an unstated and even an unacknowledged belief. If Joe acts frightened and runs away every time a dog approaches, his behavior expresses a belief that dogs are dangerous, even if he has never stated or admitted it. Likewise, when a person sincerely deliberates over whether to do A or B, that person’s
  • 21. behavior manifests a belief in free will, even if the person says that he does not believe in free will and even if that person has never thought about the issue. But each of us deliberates. We deliberate hundreds of times each day. Two things follow. First, at some level, everyone believes in free will. Second, every time the hard determinist deliberates, his own behavior expresses a belief in free will that contradicts his professed belief in hard determinism. Thus, if you endorse hard determinism, you contradict yourself every time you make a deliberate choice. Hard determinism is thus a philosophical doctrine that cannot consistently be lived. It is also a doctrine that cannot consistently be professed. To a hard determinist, then, we might argue, “Since deliberation is a necessary part of life and since deliberation presupposes a belief in free will, you cannot live and be logically consistent and at the same time assert hard determinism. But you can give up hard determinism and assert free will without any inconsistency. You should therefore give up hard determinism, since that is the only one of the two options that can consistently be dropped.” If this argument is cogent, the hard determinist’s life is absurd in the sense that it contains a logical conflict between belief and action, pretension and reality. To accept hard determinism and deny free will, van Inwagen concludes, is to condemn yourself to a life of constant self-contradiction. Of course, a hard determinist can bite the bullet and reply, “This doesn’t show that hard determinism is false; all it shows is that one cannot actively live and at the same time consistently profess hard determinism. I’d rather be a walking self-contradiction than believe in free will.” However, it is very hard to believe that a philosophical theory that cannot be consistently believed—a theory the acceptance of
  • 22. which is logically inconsistent with actively living—is true. How can such a theory be true? The Moral Responsibility Argument Van Inwagen believes that the following argument is an even stronger reason to reject hard determinism and admit the existence of free will. Without free will, we would never be morally responsible for anything, and we are sometimes morally responsible. More formally and with some missing premises filled in: 1. Free will is a necessary condition of moral responsibility. 2. It is rationally undeniable that we are at least sometimes morally responsible for our actions. 3. Therefore, human beings at least sometimes … It's the flaw of circularity. An argument is circular when it uses its conclusion as a premise. Put differently, circular arguments assume what needs to be shown. In terms of the arguments against hard determinism, the argument looks like this: "That we have free will is evidenced by the fact that I made a freely willed choice." Check out this document for examples of this error from our discussion. The document is also in the module for this week, in case you can't open it from this attachment. Also, I include this article as an FYI: It explains a benefit of learning to step back and evaluate our arguments: Cognitive Ability & Vulnerability to Fake News.docx
  • 23. This week's quiz covers the material in the "Free Will" reading from section 5 to the end. It will also cover my comments on circular reasoning. I have highlighted this logical flaw in prior documents and on prior quiz questions. Most recently, I posted a document called Comments on Circularity and Week 7 Discussion. I suggest that you review this and have it open as you take the quiz. Part One. Pick any idea in this week's material that interests you and post your philosophical thoughts on it. Please consider one of the discussion questions listed at the end of sections (on pages, 13, 16, and 28). Part Two. Respond critically when you comment on the post of one (or more) members of the class. This means: give an argument to support your view. QI This week I would like to discuss soft determinism. Soft determinism claims that freedom and determinism are compatible because it changes the definition of freedom from “could have done otherwise” to “doing what an individual wants to do”. However, I think no matter how soft determinism revises its argument, it is not acceptable because freedom and determinism are two incompatible concepts, while soft determinism tries to make these two incompatible concepts compatible. Soft determinism is a dead end because the core of freedom is basically against the core of determinism, and it cannot change the definition of freedom to fit determinism because the changed definition of freedom is not the real
  • 24. definition of freedom. Therefore, even though I do not believe in determinism, I think hard determinism makes more sense than soft determinism, for at least hard determinism is not as self- contradictory as soft determinism. A Few Comments on Discussion for Week 7: Introduction: The idea that we do not have free will is disturbing to me. If it’s true, it’s likely a belief that I’m unable – psychologically to experience: as much as I’ve tried (just to see if I could), I am unable to shake the feeling that I am the thinker of my thoughts and the chooser of my choices. However, the fact that I can’t shake this feeling, doesn’t mean the feeling is accurate. My sense of free will may be an illusion just like other optical illusions (some which are equally unshakeable) are illusions. Once I pause to consider whether my sense of free will is an illusion, I must next ask, “what would count as evidence for or against it being an illusion?” As explained in my comments on the Week 7 home page, we need to avoid circular reasoning, when searching for evidence. We may not know, for sure, what would count as sufficient evidence, but we can be confident that certain types of reasoning are unreliable and weak. Let me briefly review two flawed patterns of reasoning: Circular Arguments: These arguments follow the pattern: I know X is true, because X is true. Applied to free will, an example would be, “I know my experience of free will is not an illusion because I have experienced making free choices.” Belief Bias: This occurs when we judge an argument based on whether we agree with the conclusion. This is a flawed strategy of evaluation because it’s possible to give terrible arguments for true conclusions. (Try it: write down a statement you know to be true as your conclusion. Then write down some random statement as a premise. Is the argument a good one? Unless you got really lucky with your random statement, it’s not.) Why it matters: Avoiding circularity and belief bias matter for many reasons. I’ll highlight one. If you settle for circular
  • 25. arguments, or don’t worry about belief bias, then you deprive yourself of the chance to discover really good arguments. You may shield yourself psychologically from having to confront uncomfortable challenges to your beliefs, but you also shield yourself from finding really good arguments (foundations) for your beliefs. So, if you’re interested in building your belief structure on solid ground, rather than on sand, then you have a reason to avoid circularity and belief bias. If you care about truth, then you have another reason. Some Examples from the discussions: I would say that about 95% of people who gave an argument against hard determinism gave a circular argument. Here are some examples. 1. If this is true, why do we have a brain capable of making decisions. [PG. This assumes we have a brain capable of making decisions: i.e., a brain with free will. So the argument becomes, hard determinism can’t be true, because it’s false.] 2. Hard determinism is false because “I believe that each person has a free will, and ….I believe that one's own free will can affect others through positive and negative interaction.” [PG: This looks like belief bias. HD is rejected because the author of the post doesn’t believe the view. The argument itself was not directly addressed in this post.] 3. All of us have probably experienced something where it seemed like we were meant to do something specific, based on what we had learned and been through, but chose to do something totally different. [PG: What we are debating is whether the experience of choosing is an illusion. So the question is how you know you are the chooser of your choice, or whether it just seems like you are.] 4. HD is probably not true because, “However, in fact, I think we do have choices and alternatives in a lot of daily situations. For instance, when I plan to buy a drink, I can choose to buy Pepsi, Cola, or orange juice, or perhaps I can buy them all.” [PG: Notice first that this doesn’t exhibit belief bias because the author supports the claim with reasons. However, the reasons are circular: it assumes what needs to be shown,
  • 26. namely, that the choice to buy Pepsi wasn’t determined by prior material causes.] I’ll just display other examples, I won’t comment. I hope that by now – if you’re still reading – you will be able to see the circularity. In each case below, the example simply assumes what needs to be shown: i.e., the example avoids the question that is being debated. 5. We have free will as shown by a case where a person chooses how they will clean a house. 6. We have free will as shown by a case where a person chooses to ignore a doctor’s orders. 7. We have free will as shown by our ability to freely choose whether or not to follow God. 8. We have free will as shown by our ability to decide what coffee we drink or what routes we take. 9. We have free will as shown by our decision to work hard (or not) to succeed, or our decision about whether or not to rob a bank. 10. We have free will as shown by cases where people grow up in the same environments but make different choices. [PG: If it could be shown that the people were identical, atom for atom, as S.Harris says, and that they were exposed to exactly the same set of causal inputs, yet still differed in their behavior, then this would cast doubt on HD.] 11. We have free will as shown by cases where people are indecisive, but then change their minds. [PG: What is at issue is whether they changed their mind. How did that change occur? A hard determinist will point to prior material causes. A free will advocate might point so some other sort of cause. My point here is that the act of changing a decision raises the question, it doesn’t answer it.] Summary: As you can see, the pull towards circularity is very strong. But it should be resisted (I’m assuming HD is false and we have a choice to resist) if we care about gaining a better understanding of ourselves and how we are designed (I’ll leave it open as to whether we were designed by a conscious being.)
  • 27. The arguments we look at this week are non-circular (or at least not as obviously circular) attempts to respond to the arguments of hard determinism. Finally: There will be a question or two about belief bias and circular arguments on the next quiz! If you can point out the circularity in the examples above, you will ace them. I hope you do.