SlideShare a Scribd company logo
1 of 222
HSC 312: Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring
Rubric
The following criteria will be used to grade your Complied Case
Analysis. Keep in mind that the score requirement described
under each score point on the scale defines the minimum
performance that must be demonstrated in order to achieve that
score.
Evaluation
Criteria
A
20 points
B
17 points
C
15 points
D
13 points
F
11 points
1.) Introduces
the case
analysis by
describing
the ethical
dilemma
requiring
resolution
Introduction is:
• Comprehensive
• Includes a
thorough, clear and
concise description
of the case and
ethical dilemma
proposed.
Introduction:
• Includes minor
omissions in
description of
either the case
or ethical
dilemma.
Introduction:
• Lacks detail in
part
• Includes minor
omissions in
both the
description of
the case and the
ethical dilemma.
Introduction:
• Lacks detail
• Includes major
omissions in
either
description of
the case or the
ethical
dilemma.
Description is either
missing or contains
major omissions
throughout.
2.) Identifies
the
primary
stakeholder
(s) and
provides a
description
of the
situation
from the
stakeholder
perspective
Description is:
• Comprehensive
• Includes
identification of
stakeholder
• Provides clear
stakeholder
Description:
• Has minor
omissions or
errors in
identification of
stakeholders or
in describing the
stakeholder
perspective.
Description:
• Lacks detail
• Omits some
significant
content or
contains several
minor errors.
Description:
• Lacks detail.
• Is superficial
and contains
multiple errors.
Description is:
• Missing or
incorrect
• Inconsistent
with selected
stakeholder
identify any
or identifies
irrelevant
stakeholders.
3.) Analyzes the
scenario
from the
perspective
of the
primary
stakeholder
and includes
a description
of at least
two ethical
theories that
relate to the
issue being
identified
Analysis and Description
are:
• Comprehensive
• Include responses
to all
subcomponents of
the question.
• Provides clear
description of two
or more ethical
theories and their
relation to the
issue.
Analysis and
Description:
• Include minor
omissions.
• Includes 1-2
minor errors in
regards to the
scenario of the
stakeholder or
the description
of the ethical
theories.
Analysis and
Description:
• Include a major
omission, OR
• Includes
several errors in
regards to the
scenario of the
stakeholder or
the description
of the ethical
theories.
Analysis and
Description:
• Includes a
major omission,
AND
• Includes
several errors in
regards to the
scenario of the
stakeholder or
the description
of the ethical
theories.
Analysis and
Description are:
• Missing
OR
• Response
contains
significant
errors or
omissions
throughout the
response.
4.) Provides a
reasonable
recommendat
ion based
upon the
analysis
presented
Recommendation is:
• Comprehensive.
• Clear and logical
• Summarizes key
points.
Recommendation
has:
• Minor
omissions or
errors
• Is clear and
logical
• Summarizes
most key points.
Recommendation:
• Omits some
significant
content and
contains several
minor errors
• Is clear or
logical but not
both
• Summarizes
minimal
points.
Recommendation:
• Is superficial
and contains
multiple errors
• Is not clear or
logical
• Summarizes 1-
2 points.
Recommendation is:
• Missing or
incorrect.
5.) Format Format is:
• Clear and
consistent.
• contains accurate
and proper
grammatical
conventions,
spelling,
formatting, and
referencing.
• Follows specific
instructions.
Format is:
• Clear and
mostly
consistent.
• Contains few
errors of
accuracy
• Follows
specific
instructions
with minor
omissions.
Format is:
• Clear but not
concise.
• Contains
multiple errors
of accuracy.
• Follows
specific
instructions
with multiple
omissions.
Format is:
• Not clear or
concise.
• Contains
serious errors.
• Specific
instructions are
barely followed.
Format:
• Is not clear.
• Does not
follow specific
instructions.
Final Project – Compiled Case Studies
Jane Doe
HSC312
May 2013
Professor X
HSC312 - Final Project: Compiled Case Studies May 2013
Jane Doe
Case Analysis: Sally & the DNR
Case Analysis Template for use with each of the four scenarios
in the final project:
1. Copy/paste the title of the question
2. Describe the most relevant ethical dilemma(s) presented (no
more than two).
3. Briefly describe the primary issue or issues that are relevant
in the scenario w/respect to
the dilemma.
4. Identify the most relevant stakeholder(s) (no more than 3)
and briefly describe the
situation from their perspective.
5. Analyze the dilemma, using scholarly discussion, from the
perspective of the primary
stakeholder (typically the patient). Include a discussion of at
least two ethical theories
or bioethics principles studied in the course that relate to the
dilemma and issues you
identified. Include any relevant legal concerns or requirements
outlined in the readings.
6. Present your assessment, resolution or potential solutions for
resolving the issue.
Remember that there are no right answers, per se, so reflective
questions can be as
appropriate as a firm conclusion.
7. Title page + APA formatted reference(s)
The following example provides further insight into what is
required for each element of the
template. Although the response is intentionally somewhat
longer than what is expected, it
should help clarify the specific requirements.
1. Ethical Dilemma
Prompt objective: Identify the ethical dilemma and state the
dilemma as a “should” question.
Note: there may be several relevant dilemmas that could be
addressed; use the prompt question
as a guide to an issue to analyze. The objective is to present a
cogent analysis of a relevant issue.
ISSUE: Should the attending physician sign a DNR without
Sally’s consent?
2. Primary issues related to the identified dilemma
Prompt objective: Identify the relevant issues related to your
dilemma. You should identify at
least two, but limit your selection of issues to a manageable
number within the scope of the
assignment.
Informed consent; Surrogate decision making & substituted
judgment; healthcare decision
making capacity; autonomy and the right to refuse treatment
3. Primary Stakeholders & Stakeholder positions:
Question objective: Identify 2-3 primary stakeholders including
the patient, and briefly describe
their position:
Sally: 62 yr old woman with Stage IV breast cancer that is
unresponsive to standard and
experimental treatment presents with shortness of breath
requiring a Thorentisis, a difficult
procedure given her condition. Sally wants to live and refuses
to discuss the terminal nature of
her condition.
HSC312 - Final Project: Compiled Case Studies May 2013
Jane Doe
Sally’s husband: Sally’s husband recognizes that Sally is dying
and wants everything done for
Sally to make her comfortable. He agrees with the attending
physician that CPR would make
Sally less, rather than more comfortable. He is Sally’s surrogate
decision maker.
The attending physician: Believes that further testing and
treatment for Sally is futile. He
questions whether Sally has the capacity to understand her
condition and consent to the DNR.
4. Potential
Solution
Analysis:
Prompt objective: Analyze the ethical dilemma from the
perspective of the primary stakeholder
(typically the patient), using the ethical theories and/or the
bioethics principles that relate to the
dilemma. Keep your analysis focused on at least two or three
moral theories or bioethics
principles, but do not attempt to address them all. There will
generally be more issues and
principles/theories that would apply than you can cover in a
short analysis. Include in your
discussion any known legal issues presented by the readings
that may influence a decision. Apply
the facts to the theories discussed. Keep in mind that there may
be several issues and theories to
discuss, but you are not required to find or address them all.
The essay below is purposefully
more involved than the assignment requires providing a few
examples of an ethical analysis.
Under the ethical and legal doctrine of informed consent
provided by the Patient Self-
Determination Act, an adult patient with healthcare decision-
making capacity has the right to
make an informed, autonomous choice to accept or reject
medical treatment. (Munson, 2012).
The right to self-determination is defined by the bioethics
principle of
Autonomy and refers to the patient’s right to make a voluntary
choice that is meaningful to them
and free from external or personal influences. (Tong, 2007).
Such influences may include fear,
denial, medication side effects, pain and guilt, among others.
Healthcare decision-making
capacity requires that the patient can articulate and understand
the nature of their condition and
the risks, benefits and consequences of accepting or rejecting
treatment. Assessing decision-
making capacity requires an evaluation of the patient’s
decision-making process, rather than an
evaluation of the choice itself. “…[T]he mere fact that a patient
does not accept a health care
professional’s recommendation does not necessarily mean that
the patient is incompetent" (Tong,
2007, p 53).
In order for a patient to evaluate the risks and benefits of an
available option is the understanding
that a physician will provide complete and honest disclosure of
all the associated medical facts
that may be pertinent to the patient (Canterbury vs. Spence,
1979). The need for such veracity in
caring for a patient is also a primary component of a physician’s
ethical responsibility, according
to the American Medical Association (AMA, 2012). Performing
a procedure without consent, or
withholding a viable treatment without disclosure, is a direct
violation of the AMA mandate,
Informed Consent doctrine and a patient’s trust.
A patient’s right to self-determination is foundational in
bioethics. If the patient loses decision-
making capacity, laws and policies are in place to ensure that
the patients’ expressed or implied
wishes are respected. Prior to losing capacity, a patient can
appoint a healthcare proxy agent who
will make decisions for the patient, based upon the patient’s
wishes and instructions. Critical to
the concept of a Health Care agent is the agent’s requirement
that any decisions reflect the
patients’ known and implied wishes, rather than the agent’s own
wishes for the patient. If no
HSC312 - Final Project: Compiled Case Studies May 2013
Jane Doe
such agent is named, a surrogate decision maker is appointed by
state statute or facility policy to
make decisions for the patient, using their knowledge of the
patient and the patient’s wishes,
values and spiritual beliefs.
Sally appears to be in denial about her condition and terribly
afraid of death, as evidenced by her
general state of “panic” and her refusal to talk to the Resident
about her condition. Most
importantly, Sally has stated that she wants to live, which may
reflect any number of thoughts
and emotions from a sense of grief at her circumstances to
denial of her terminal condition.
Because the physicians seem more focused on discussing their
inability to help Sally, rather than
being ‘competent’ in her mind to perform the thorientsis, Sally
may not see a value in discussing
her condition with them. Far from an irrational thought process,
Sally’s refusal to talk may
actually be a heartbreaking testament to her ability to assess a
situation and reach a rational
conclusion based on the facts. Further proof may be Sally’s
insistence that she “…wanted the
emergency squad called to attempt resuscitation if she arrested
at home” (Crigger, 1998). Given
her desire to live as long as possible, it would make sense that
she would want every chance
available to live.
Presuming Sally does have capacity, she is entitled to receive
full disclosure regarding anything
to do with her medical care—a right that extends to her
rejection of a proposal that is in conflict
with her own goals. Consequently, if the attending physician
institutes a DNR order without
Sally’s consent would constitute a violation of Sally’s right to
self-determination. Important in
the discussion of full disclosure in Sally’s case is the fact that it
no one has explained the
potential adverse consequences of performing CPR (Cardio-
pulmonary resuscitation) on
someone in her current medical condition. From the facts
presented, it is unclear how Sally
would respond if she knew there was a significant chance that if
she survived CPR, she could
end up in a Permanent Vegetative State, permanently
unconscious and kept alive by artificial life
support as a result.
The physician’s position that CPR is futile given the potential
for harm and what he perceives as
negligible benefit, does not override Sally’s right to define what
is and is not beneficial for her.
Acting on his own subjective values and interpretations, and
ignoring Sally’s values and desires
would constitute an act of Paternalism, a direct violation of
autonomy (Tong, 2007). While it is
true that a patient cannot demand an inappropriate treatment—
one that would produce more
harm than benefit— it could be argued that CPR as a standard
emergency procedure to ward off
imminent death does not pass the “inappropriateness” test. If a
patient with capacity is provided
with full disclosure of the potential harms, it is the patient’s
right to weigh the risks and benefits,
and make an informed choice. (Munson, 2012).
Similarly, if it is determined, that Sally lacks capacity; the
doctor would still be potentially
outside his authority to institute the DNR without informing
Sally’s surrogate decision maker.
While it is unclear whether Sally’s husband is her Healthcare
proxy agent, as a person who
knows her best and her spouse, he would still have the
presumptive right to use substituted
judgment and make the decision he believes Sally would make,
if she could. Knowing Sally’s
express position on the issue of aggressive treatment, he has an
obligation as the healthcare agent
to reject the DNR, regardless of his personal opinion and desire
that Sally just receive comfort
care.
HSC312 - Final Project: Compiled Case Studies May 2013
Jane Doe
In addition to the ethical principle of Autonomy and the
doctrine of informed consent, Care-
based Ethics also supports Sally’s right to reject the DNR. Care-
based Ethics emphasizes values
and virtues such as compassion, empathy, kindness and most
important, sensitivity to each
patient’s unique perspective and circumstances (Tong, 2007).
Because Sally is adamant she
wants everything done right now to help keep her alive as long
as possible, a physician
empathetic to Sally’s concerns and circumstances would not
sign the DNR without at least
informing her and addressing her fears about death and her
desire to preserve her life.
5. Recommedation:
Prompt objective: Present your assessment, resolution or
potential solutions for resolving the
issue. Remember that there are no right answers, per se, so
reflective questions can be as
appropriate as a firm conclusion.
Based on my analysis, the attending physician should not
institute the DNR against Sally’s
express wishes and without her knowledge. Doing so would
violate the ethical and legal
principles of autonomy and informed consent. I also recommend
that Sally be seen by a
Palliative Care specialist or a medical professional trained in
end-of-life care to help determine
whether Sally’s statements and behaviors demonstrate a lack of
capacity, or are understandably
motivated by denial and fear. Minimally, the consult should
help promote Sally’s overall well-
being by addressing her concerns in a compassionate and caring
way. Lastly, only if Sally lacks
capacity should Sally’s husband, as her healthcare agent, be
allowed to speak for Sally and
refuse the DNR. Because we do not know how Sally feels about
remaining on life support should
CPR fail, Sally’s husband must adhere to the doctrine of
substituted judgement and base a
decision upon his knowledge of Sally’s values and wishes,
including her known spiritual beliefs.
Bibliography
4 H A S T I N G S C E N T E R R E P O R T January-
February 2012
To the Editor:The traditional “in-
formed consent” process for medical
treatment is badly broken. As patients
face fateful medical decisions, they of-
tendonotknowthebasic“gist”oftheir
optionsorthelikelihoodofthepossible
outcomes, good and bad. The shared
decision-makingmovementaimstoim-
provethatsorrysituationbyhavingpa-
tients and clinicians work more closely
together when there is more than one
reasonablemedicaloption,asisthecase
formanyifnotmostsituations.Byen-
suring both that patients are informed
about their choices and that clinicians
areinformedaboutpatientpreferences,
thequalityofmedicaldecisionsshould
be improved. Patient decision aids are
notthemselvesshareddecision-making;
instead, they are tools to help make
shareddecision-makingpracticalinthe
busyworldofclinicalmedicine.
Inhisprovocativearticle(“Question-
ing the Quantitative Imperative: Deci-
sionAids,Prevention,andtheEthicsof
Disclosure,” March-April 2011), Peter
Schwartz seems to acknowledge the
need to improve the current informed
consent process but worries that pro-
viding quantitative information about
possible outcomes as part of a shared
decision-makingprocessmightbemis-
leadingtoorunwantedbypatients.He
proposesthe“default”optionshouldbe
to withhold this quantitative informa-
tion unless and until a patient asks for
it.Hisprimaryargumentsarethatmany
patientshavepoornumeracyskillsand
might not understand—or might even
be misled by—the quantitative facts,
andthatoutcomeshavenotbeenshown
tobebetterasaresultofprovidingpa-
tientswithquantitativeinformation.
Problemswithstatisticalnumeracy—
which have been shown to be an issue
for clinicians, too—do make it more
challenging to communicate risks and
benefits. However, just because a task
is difficult doesn’t mean it shouldn’t be
done.MostpeopleintheUnitedStates
don’twanttoplayapassiveroleintheir
health care, and the proportion isn’t
conditioned by assessed numeracy (M.
Galesic and R. Garcia-Retamero, “Do
Low-Numeracy People Avoid Shared
DecisionMaking?”Health Psychology30
[2011]:336-41).Moreover,asnotedin
PeterUbel’scompanioneditorial(“The
Experimental Imperative”), research
on the communication of quantitative
healthinformationisrevealingthatnew
strategies and technologies can help
overcome these barriers. For example,
visualaids,commonlyusedindecision
aids,canhelpevenpeoplewithfewnu-
meracy skills better understand health
statistics (R. Garcia-Retamero and M.
Galesic,“WhoProfitsfromVisualAids?
Overcoming Challenges in People’s
UnderstandingofRisks,”Social Science
Medicine 70 [2010]: 1019-25). Many
oftheinterventionsforwhichinformed
consentisnecessaryinhealthcare,such
as open-heart surgery and organ trans-
plantation, had to overcome numerous
barrierstoenterthemedicalarmamen-
tarium. It’s time to bring a similar in-
tensityofefforttoovercomethebarriers
of literacy and numeracy in communi-
catingimportanthealthinformationto
thepeoplewhomustlivewiththecon-
sequencesoftheirhealthdecisions.
Holding informed consent to an
outcome standard is an interesting ar-
gument. Schwartz acknowledges that
decision aids that present quantitative
outcomeprobabilitieshavebeenshown
to give patients more accurate percep-
tionsoftheirhealthrisks.Isputtingthe
“informed” in informed consent not
an important goal in itself? Would the
ethicalandlegalimperativeofinformed
consent hold up under scrutiny in a
trialwherepatientsfacingsurgerywere
randomized to an informed consent
process versus none? Would the whole
notionofinformedconsentbescrapped
iffunctionalstatusscoreswerenodiffer-
entinasecondtrial?Ithinknot.
Thekeyissuehereiswhetherthede-
faultoptionininformedconsentshould
be withholding quantitative informa-
tionunlesspatientsaskforitorprovid-
ingitunlesstheysaytheydon’twantit.
For too long, the medical system has
kept patients largely in the dark about
whatclinicianshaveplannedforthem.
Given this history, perhaps it’s time to
make giving more information—in-
cluding quantitative information—the
default position, and to work much
harderatdoingitwell.
Michael J. Barry
TheFoundationforInformed
MedicalDecisionMaking
To the Editor: Every day people
tell me about the challenges they face
in finding safe, decent health care and
making the most of it. Facing tough
letters
TooMuchInformation?
It’s time to overcome the barriers of literacy and
numeracy in communicating important health
information to the people who must live with
the consequences of their health decisions.
DOI:10.1002/HAST.4
January-February 2012 H A S T I N G S C E N T E R R E P O
R T 5
oN tHe WeB
nBioethicsforum
http://www.bioethicsforum.org
AdministrationRevealsLackofCLASS
By Peter S. Arno, Michael K.
Gusmano, and Deborah Viola
Just as the baby boomers are entering
retirement, the first real step toward a
national long-term care policy in forty-five
years has been cast asunder.
WhatisHumane?APleaforPlain
LanguageintheDebatesonAnimal
Experimentation
By Joel Marks
“Humane” is implicitly defined as
meeting accepted standards of care and
use according to legal and institutional
guidelines. What this means in practice is
that anything can be done to a laboratory
animal, provided it is necessary to carry
out an experiment or other procedure that a
committee has deemed worthy on scientific
and perhaps humanitarian grounds. I
submit that this is an illegitimate use of the
term “humane.”
Also:michaelK.Gusmanopointsout
misinformationaboutU.S.poverty;
CarolLevinesuggeststhatwe’dallbetter
startsavingnowforourbabies’future
long-termcare;franklinG.millerand
robertd.truogexploreuncertain-
tiespromptedbythelatestresearch
onpatientsinthevegetativestate;and
CameronWaldmanvisitsZuccottiPark
totalkwithcliniciansoccupyingWall
Street.
nthehealthCareCostmonitor
http://healthcarecostmonitor.
thehastingscenter.org
GlobalCompetitiveness:HowOther
CountriesWin
By Daniel Callahan and Elizabeth
H. Bradley
Nearly every country that leads the world
in international economic competitive-
ness also has a strong government-run or
regulated universal health care system and
a comprehensive welfare policy. The one
exception is the United States.
decisions about treatments and tests
withlittleornoobjectiveinformation
toguidethemoftentopstheirlistofdif-
ficulties.Ihavefrequentlyexperienced
thismyselfasIrecoverfromtreatment
ofmyfourthcancerdiagnosis.
I appreciate Peter Schwartz’s recog-
nitionoftheburdenplacedonpatients
andlovedonestoincorporatecomplex
risk information into decisions about
our care. And I welcome any con-
cern—however tangential—about the
shiftofresponsibilitiesfromclinicians
to patients, who are often ill-prepared
tofulfillthem.However,Ifindhisar-
gumentoverlyprotectiveinlightofthe
rushed, confusing demands of health
care today, increased public access to
health information, and the shared
decision-making policies imbedded in
theAffordableCareAct.
Schwartzdescribesthegeneralinnu-
meracyoftheAmericanpublicwitha
particularemphasisonourinabilityto
understandthedifferencebetweenrel-
ativeandabsoluterisk.Yetheneglects
to mention that we share this deficit
with many of our clinicians. He also
summarizestheliteratureoncognitive
heuristicsbutagainexemptsclinicians
from discussion. Does he believe that
cliniciansareimmunefromthesesame
biases? My doctor might withhold a
decision aid because she doesn’t have
timeforthiscumbersomeshareddeci-
sion-making nonsense or she believes
sheknowswhatIshoulddotorealize
thebestoutcome.Shewouldvieweach
oftheseasrationalchoices.
More puzzling is the importance
Schwartz assigns to risk information
indecisionswemakeaboutourhealth
care, preference-sensitive or not. Em-
piricalinformationisalways only oneof
manyfactorsthatinfluenceourchoic-
es. Scant relevant risk information is
available for most of the health care
decisionswemakenow.Wejustwing
it, based on anxiety, our neighbor’s
experience, and our sense of what the
rightchoiceistoday,whichcanbein-
fluencedbyourdoctor’smoodaseasily
asitcanbyfamilyandworkevents.
It is thus oddly shortsighted for
Schwartz to recommend withholding
decision aids for some patients (based
on the clinician’s assessment of our
competence) in the relatively few in-
stances where these aids are available
forpreference-sensitivecare,astheyare
for decisions about early-stage breast
cancertreatmentorgettingaprostate-
specific antigen test. Even if we don’t
fully understand what’s at stake, well-
presented risk information powerfully
communicates that we have choices:
that multiple treatment options are
possible,thattherearetrade-offstobe
considered,andthatnoguaranteesex-
ist,regardlessofourchoice.Theseare
sobering but important messages for
ustograspaswe,regardlessofournu-
meracy skills and cognitive biases, are
routinely forced to make critical deci-
sionsaboutourhealthcare.
It’s too late to argue that our clini-
cians should selectively provide de-
cision aids: the ACA provisions for
shared decision-making will likely
eventuallytieclinicianreimbursement
toprovidingthem.Andtheimpetusfor
thatargument—thatprovidingthisin-
formationimposesmandatoryautono-
my—isakintodiscussingthebenefits
ofclosingthebarndoorafterthecows
havewanderedaway:Ourautonomyis
alreadymandatedbydefault.
Jessie Gruman
CenterforAdvancingHealth
To the Editor: In his article, Peter
Schwartzeloquentlydiscussestheben-
efits and potential harms of providing
patients with numeric risk informa-
tion. He describes how—despite our
best efforts to inform patients about
therisksandbenefitsofscreeningtests
and preventive treatments and to im-
prove understanding of probability—
people “have persistently irrational
responses to quantitative information
aboutrisksandbenefits,”regardlessof
their level of numeracy. For decades,
6 H A S T I N G S C E N T E R R E P O R T January-
February 2012
decision scientists, economists, and
psychologists have struggled to under-
standwhyeventhemostknowledgeable
andnumeratepeoplemakesuboptimal
healthdecisions.
It seems that in our attempts to
educate patients about probability, we
sometimes fail to appreciate that un-
derstanding numeric facts and figures
is not an exclusively cognitive effort;
rather, it is often heavily influenced by
affect, which in turn influences one’s
abilitytoreason.Awell-knownexperi-
ment conducted in 1994 by Veronika
Denes-Raj and Seymour Epstein illus-
trates how affect can trump rational-
ity, even for well-educated people. In
it,subjectswoniftheydrewaredjelly
beanfromoneoftwobowls.Thesmall
bowlcontainedoneredandninewhite
beans,andthelargebowlcontainedfive
totenredbeansandatotalofonehun-
dred beans in all. Despite the fact that
eachbowlwaslabeledwiththepercent
of red beans it contained, the majority
of subjects drew a bean from the large
bowl, which was clearly the inferior
choice.Subjectsreportedthatthey“felt”
theyhadabetterchanceofwinningby
selectingthebowlwiththegreaterabso-
lutenumberof“winning”beans.
Theinteractionofaffectandnumer-
acy in health decisions has been dem-
onstrated in several studies examining
choices of medical treatments that in-
cludepotentialsideeffects.Inone2006
studyconductedbyJenniferAmsterlaw
and colleagues, people were presented
with two surgical scenarios: one had a
20percentmortalityrate,andtheother
had a 16 percent mortality rate along
witha1percentchanceoffourunpleas-
ant side effects (colostomy, chronic di-
arrhea, intermittent bowel obstruction,
orwoundinfection).Mostpeoplechose
thesurgicaloptionwiththehighermor-
tality,presumablybecauseoftheiraffec-
tiveresponsetothesideeffectsandtheir
tendencytooverweightlowprobability
events. Indeed, the mere presence of a
small side effect may decrease willing-
ness to undergo treatment, even if the
treatment offers substantial benefit.
Erika Waters and colleagues found in
2007 that side-effect aversion occurred
regardless of how probability was pre-
sentedorwhethergraphicformatswere
used to convey risk information, sug-
gestingthatdecisionswereguidedbyan
affective response to the possibility of
sideeffects,ratherthanbynumericrisk.
There are, of course, potential dan-
gers associated with providing patients
with too much quantitative informa-
tion.Inthiseraofshareddecision-mak-
ingandunprecedentedaccesstohealth
information, it is easy to experience
dataoverload.Providingpeoplewithall
available information can actually hin-
derdecision-making,andoften,lessnu-
mericinformationismorewhenhelping
people make quality health decisions.
Amongthepotentialdangersofprovid-
ing too much information is that pa-
tientsmaynotbeabletodiscernuseful
informationfromthemerelyrelevantor
altogetherirrelevant.However,thereare
also potential dangers associated with
providingtoolittleinformation.AsAn-
thonyBastardiandEldarShafirdemon-
stratedin1998,whenpeoplearefaced
with a preference-sensitive decision,
they often seek additional information
regardless of whether that information
iscriticaltotheirdecision.Inaseriesof
experiments,theyobservedthatpeople
whopursuedmissinginformationtend-
ed to endow it with greater value than
theywouldhaveifithadbeenavailable
initially. Somehow the act of pursuing
a missing but nonessential piece of in-
formation lent greater psychological
weight and salience to it. In a health
context, such misguided information-
seekingmightleadpatientstobaseim-
portanthealthdecisionsonfactorsthat
may be relevant but nonessential to an
effective decision. Clearly, more work
is needed to understand the possible
unintended consequences of providing
toomuchortoolittleriskinformation.
Attheveryleast,providersshouldkeep
in mind how affect can be attached to
numbersandrisksareperceived.
Wendy Nelson
NationalCancerInstitute
To the Editor:Thereisagreatdeal
of merit in Peter Schwartz’s important
andusefularticle,anditwilldoubtless
prompt considerable debate. I would
liketoaddtwobriefcomments.
First, Schwartz’s target—the quan-
titative imperative—can be viewed as
a specific instance of a broader target.
In Rethinking Informed Consent (Cam-
bridge University Press, 2007), Onora
O’Neill and I, like Schwartz, were
struckbytheconsiderableevidencethat
patients and research subjects often do
not comprehend what is disclosed. As
a result, “informed consent” is often
considered obtained even when, rela-
tive to contemporary standards, it is
substandardorinvalid.Toimprovethis
situation, we argued—amongst other
things—thatweneedtobeclearabout
the distinction between consent and
informed consent. The former is a fa-
miliar form of action that involves the
settingasideofrightsortheremovalof
certain kinds of prohibitions. Consent
isofconsiderable,butnotfoundational,
ethical importance for clinical actions.
Whilethosewhoconsentneedtoknow
something of the action to which they
consent,itdoesnotrequire“disclosure”
of large amounts of information about
proposed actions or risks. Informed
consent, in contrast, has its roots in
negligence law in the clinical context
andsharesbiomedicalethics’particular
The quantitative imperative is simply part of an
unjustified informative imperative that places
unfeasible demands upon those consenting.
January-February 2012 H A S T I N G S C E N T E R R E P O
R T 7
focus on the importance of individual
decision-making. We argued that bio-
medical ethics has, without sufficient
justification,takeninformedconsentto
be of key ethical importance. Matters
are made worse by the prevalence of a
widerangeofmetaphorsthatshapeour
thinkingaboutknowledgeandcommu-
nication,suchthatinformationisread-
ilycastasatypeof“stuff ”tobepassed
on,stored,disclosed,orpickedup.
Putting these elements together and
aligning with Schwartz’s terminology,
there is a ubiquitous informative im-
perative that pervades biomedical eth-
ics. This informative imperative rests
uponarangeofdistortionsandconfu-
sions. Once the ethical arguments are
clarified, the informative imperative
canbeseenasmuchlessdemandingin
its scope than is typically assumed.We
would thus agree with Schwartz’s con-
clusion—that quantitative information
ofcertainkindsneednotbedisclosed—
but for a different set of reasons. The
quantitativeimperative,onourview,is
simplyapartofawidespreadbutunjus-
tifiedinformativeimperativethatistoo
broadinitsscopeandplacesunfeasible
demandsuponthoseconsenting.
Second, it is important to note that
there may be reasons other than en-
suring validity of consent for disclos-
ing quantitative information. Given
the legal context of informed consent,
Schwartz’s proposals might raise wor-
riesforclinicians.Supposeinformation
aboutcertainrisksismerelymadeavail-
able, rather than being communicated
(andacknowledgedassuchby,say,sign-
ingaconsentform).Supposethatoneof
therisksnotcommunicated,butmade
available,happens.Thepatientsueson
thebasisthathadshebeeninformedof
therisk,shewouldnothaveconsented.
Thequantitativeimperativecanthusbe
seenasaprecautionarystrategyforcli-
niciansandtheirinstitutions.
Schwartzfocusesontherolethatin-
formationplays,orispurportedtoplay,
inenablingpatientdecision-making.In
arecentpaperintheJournal of Medical
Ethics (“Why Do Patients Want Infor-
mation If Not to Take Part in Deci-
sion Making?”), I focus on the (good)
reasons that patients have for wanting
information other than for decision-
making purposes. Patients want infor-
mation because they expect it, because
it allows them to establish trustworthi-
ness and credibility with their doctor,
and because the very process of com-
municatinginformationcanbeasignal
of respect and faith in a patient’s com-
petence. So even if we agree that the
quantitative imperative lacks firm ethi-
cal support, we might still believe that
suchinformationshouldbedisclosed.
Neil C. Manson
LancasterUniversity
Peter Schwartz replies:
I must correct Jessie Gruman’s sug-
gestion that my article supports with-
holdingdecisionaidsorquestionstheir
importance. Like Michael Barry and
Gruman, I agree that patients often
want or need more information than
theyreceive,andIbelievethatdecision
aidscanhelpaddressthisproblemand
will most likely play a growing role in
medicine. But the question is whether
decision aids can best help patients by
always providing quantitative infor-
mation—in particular, complex data
framedinmultipleways,astheInterna-
tional Patient Decision Aids Standards
andmanyexpertsrecommend.
Research has not established that
such disclosure improves patients’ un-
derstanding or decision-making in the
range of situations where decision aids
mightbeused.Therearemanypossible
negative impacts, mostly stemming
frominnumeracyandheuristicsandbi-
asesinhumanthought,asdescribedin
myarticleandintheexcellentaddition-
alexamplesprovidedbyWendyNelson
inherletter.Givenallthis,Iarguethat
the quantitative imperative must be
subjectedtomorecarefultesting,inthe
spiritofevidence-basedmedicine.
Barry’sletterandPeterUbel’seditori-
althataccompaniedthearticlesupport
research to investigate innovative ways
to provide quantitative information to
inform patients, including innumer-
ateones,withoutcreatingconfusionor
engendering irrational responses. Such
researchiscertainlyimportant,butmy
article emphasizes that the question is
not just how to present certain types
of data, but whether to present data at
all, and in what situations. Researchers
shouldnotassumethatallrelevantdata
shouldbegivenallthetime:itmayturn
out that in at least some cases, less is
more (for example, see B.J. Zikmund-
Fisher, A. Fagerlin, and P.A. Ubel, “A
Demonstration of ‘Less Can Be More’
in Risk Graphics,” Medical Decision
Making30[2010]:661-71).
My article is thus a call to keep an
open mind as research goes forward. It
aimstoplayarolethattheoreticalethi-
cal and philosophical analysis should
play:identifyingandcritiquingassump-
tions that guide behavior or research
in unrecognized or unexamined ways.
The assumption that all quantitative
information should be provided all the
timeisexactlythatsortofphilosophical
commitment.
I agree with Gruman that patients
too often cannot get information they
want, but I believe that decisions aids
maybestaddressthatproblembymak-
ing the information available to those
who want it, rather than presenting
it to everybody. She raises the excel-
lent question of how to choose who
will receive additional data, and she is
right, of course, to reject the idea that
thedecisionshouldbebasedsimplyon
a clinician’s impression of the patient’s
competence.
But what about a system where pa-
tientsareofferedadditionalinformation
Letterstotheeditormaybesentbye-mail
to [email protected], or to
Managing Editor, Hastings Center Report,
21MalcolmGordonRoad,Garrison,NY
10524; (845) 424-4931 fax. Letters ap-
pearing in the Report may be edited for
lengthandstylisticconsistency.
8 H A S T I N G S C E N T E R R E P O R T January-
February 2012
of various sorts? This idea is far from
radical: recommendations for discus-
sionsbetweenhealthcareprovidersand
patients suggest that some information
shouldbegiveninitially,andadditional
informationshouldbeofferedasanop-
tiontothosewhowantit(see,forexam-
ple,R.M.Epstein,B.S.Alper,andT.E.
Quill, “Communicating Evidence for
Participatory Decision Making,” Jour-
nal of the American Medical Association
291 [2004]: 2359-66). The amazing
capabilitiesofcomputer-baseddecision
aidsmaytemptdesignerstoprovidetoo
muchinformationupfront,andtofor-
getthewisdomoftailoringdisclosureto
thepatient’sinterestandunderstanding.
I agree with Neil Manson that
the quantitative imperative is part of
a larger “informative imperative” in
medicine that should be questioned
and challenged as Manson, O’Neill,
Carl Schneider, and others have done.
Considering how to provide the right
information,totherightpatients,atthe
right time, by way of a decision aid or
personal interaction, raises important
ethical and empirical questions, as the
articleemphasizes.
Doctors and Torture
To the Editor:In“TheTorturedPa-
tient: A Medical Dilemma” (May-June
2011), Chiara Lepora and Joseph Mil-
lum raise the issue of whether a physi-
cian may be justifiably complicit in
torture and answer in the affirmative.
Their argument is predicated on there
being a litany of moral considerations,
of which the wrongness of complicity
in torture is merely one; this wrong-
ness competes against other values
and sometimes is outweighed. While I
disagree with some of the authors’ as-
sumptions—for instance, that torture
is always unethical in the cases that
physicians are forced to countenance,
orthatcomplicityinanimmoralactis
primafacieimmoral—Iagreewiththeir
conclusion. Surely those who trumpet
deontological constraints would think
otherwise,butthisconclusionnaturally
follows from a pluralistic set of moral
values.
Whiletheyciteawiderangeofdec-
lamations against physicians’ involve-
mentintorture,onethattheyleaveout
comesfromsection2.067oftheAmeri-
canMedicalAssociation’sCode of Medi-
cal Ethics. What makes section 2.067
interesting is not just what it says, but
alsothefactthatitcomeshierarchically
nestedundersection2.06,whichspeaks
tophysicianinvolvementincapitalpun-
ishment. From the Code’s perspective,
the issues pertaining to capital punish-
mentandtortureareisomorphic:what
mattersismerelythatphysicianinvolve-
mentcouldmakethepatientworseoff.
In the case of capital punishment, the
upshotisobviousand,inthecaseoftor-
ture, resuscitation in order to facilitate
moretortureissimilarlydepraved.
This argument fails in both cases,
andthereasonhelpselucidatewhyLe-
poraandMillumareontherighttrack.
Thequestiontoaskislesswhatwould
happen if physicians were present,
but rather what would happen if they
were not. For example, imagine that
physicians were disallowed from these
settingsandaprospectivepatientexpe-
rienced complications: the abolitionist
would just settle for this person being
worseoff.Aphysician’spresenceensures
thateasilyremediablesituationsberem-
edied, which is precisely what I would
advocate.Thisisnottosaythatthereare
nocapacitiesinwhichphysicianscould
make people worse off, just that there
are some in which those people could
be made better off; therefore, a whole-
saleabolitiononphysicianparticipation
misses the mark. (There’s also an open
question about whether such agents
should be conceived of as “physicians”
atall—asopposedtomedicallytrained
militarypersonnel—butIshallnotpur-
suethatdiscussionhere.)
Tobesure,thoseopposingphysician
involvement in either capital punish-
mentortortureare,almostalways,not
just opposing physician involvement,
but rather those practices themselves.
When the Code says that physicians
must “oppose . . . torture for any rea-
son,” it is clearly making a political
claim and not one narrowly tied to
medicalethics;itisforpreciselythisrea-
son that I find such statements by the
Codetobeinappropriate.AsLeporaand
Millum acknowledge, some debate the
appropriateness of torture in “narrowly
specified, extreme cases.” It is a credit
to their essay that such a debate is left
open,ratherthanforeclosedbyfiat.
Fromtheperspectiveofmedicaleth-
ics,thecentralquestioniswhetherphy-
sicianinvolvementintorturemakesthe
patientbetterorworseoff.Fromamore
thoroughgoingconsequentialismofthe
sort that I would advocate, this ques-
tion bears no privileged status. While
Lepora and Millum would surely not
agreewithallofmyarguments,theyare
tobecommendedforeschewingdogma
andreachingacontroversialconclusion.
More generally, one would also hope
that their paper portends increased at-
tention to military medical ethics; this
is an important area within medical
ethics,andonethathasreceivedinsuf-
ficientattention.
Fritz Allhoff
WesternMichiganUniversity
The question to ask is less what would happen if
physicians were present, but rather what would
happen if they were not.
Copyright of Hastings Center Report is the property of Wiley-
Blackwell and its content may not be copied or
emailed to multiple sites or posted to a listserv without the
copyright holder's express written permission.
However, users may print, download, or email articles for
individual use.
10/27/2016
Final Case Analysis: The Emilly Dilemma - Abortion
https://mycourses.excelsior.edu/bbcswebdav/pid-3200850-dt-co
ntent-rid-31405097_1/courses/BHS.HSC312.Online.201610.201
612.s30047605/course%20wide… 1/3
Final Case Analysis: The Emily Dilemma - Abortion
Introduction to the Activity
Recall, that an ethical dilemma can be defined as two morally a
cceptable choices, both of
which will result in morally disturbing and unwelcome conseque
nces. Often when we
considering our position regarding an ethical dilemma, it is help
ful to consider not only the
issue presented, but whether we can justify our position based o
n an extreme, yet realistic
set of conditions. Abortion is perhaps one of the most disturbing
and confounding of issues
for engaging in such an exercise, as it is sometimes difficult to j
ustify the inconsistencies in
our moral intuitions when confronted with situations that define
an ethical dilemma.
Related Reading from Module 7:
Module notes and assigned textbook pages
Videos:
Ankele, J. (Producer), & Macsoud, A. (Producer) (2010). Beyon
d the politics of
life and choice: A new conversation about abortion (link availab
le in Mod 7)
Tsiaras, A. (Director) (2011, November 14). Alexander Tsiaras:
Conception to
birth -- visualized TedTalks. [Video file][9 min 37 sec]. Retriev
ed from
http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=fKyljukBE70 (apprx. 10min)
Iadarola , J. (Performer) (2012, November 25). Study: What hap
pens to women
denied abortions? [Video file][5 min 17 sec] The Young Turks.
Retrieved from
http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=dWBjQ7P9SSs (apprx. 5 min
)
Instructions to Learners
Please read the case scenario:
Twenty year old Emily who suffers from Bi-polar disorder and
Schizophrenia lives at home
with her parents, but is fairly independent. Last year, Emily had
a breakdown while living
away at school and required hospitalization. Due to a complex
mix of anti-psychotics,
antidepressants and other medications to control her condition,
Emily is now working part-
time at a local bookstore and taking two classes at the communit
y college. Emily loves
children and hopes eventually to become a kindergarten teacher.
Although Emily is on
birth control pills, she had missed some days over the past few
months during a brief
‘lapse’ in her mood, but insisted throughout that time that her b
oyfriend wear a condom.
The condom failed at some point and Emily is now eight weeks'
pregnant.
http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=fKyljukBE70
http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=dWBjQ7P9SSs
10/27/2016
Final Case Analysis: The Emilly Dilemma - Abortion
https://mycourses.excelsior.edu/bbcswebdav/pid-3200850-dt-co
ntent-rid-31405097_1/courses/BHS.HSC312.Online.201610.201
612.s30047605/course%20wide… 2/3
Emily’s doctors insist that the baby is at an exceptionally high r
isk for severe physical and
mental impairments, including incomplete limb and/or brain dev
elopment. At best, there is
no solid data detailing teratogenicity risk for all of her medicati
ons, but the combinations
and inability to incorporate less harmful substitutes raise signifi
cant concern. Because she
is within the first trimester, there are no legal concerns based on
the Roe v. Wade decision
so the doctors, her parents and her boyfriend are insisting that E
mily have an abortion to
spare the burden on the child. Emily, a devote Catholic, insists
on carrying the baby and
raising it once it is born. She has also personalized the argumen
ts, finding that by
devaluing the life of her baby, her family and others devalue her
as well.
Emily’s parents have threatened to file for guardianship over he
r so that they can force the
abortion, under their belief that she lacks decision-making capa
city and the abortion is in
her best interests. Although the doctors have no standing to join
the suit, they have agreed
to serve as expert witnesses for the parents. Emily’s boyfriend i
s considering petitioning
the court--after the baby is born--for the right to be released fro
m any parental
responsibilities, given his lack of a position in the decision to a
bort.
Emily’s Psychiatrist, Dr. Heady is very troubled by the case bot
h for Emily and for the
developing fetus. Knowing that you are a famous ethicist, he co
ntacts you informally and
presents the case as a hypothetical, maintaining Emily’s confide
ntiality. Dr. Heady is
unsure whether the parents can legally force the abortion, but he
is troubled on a much
more fundamental level, which is why he is seeking your counse
l.
Please respond to the following questions (approx. 500-700 wor
ds) using the
template format provided for the assignment:
Presuming that Emily has decision-making capacity, Dr. Heady
would like to hear your
thoughts on the following:
Ethically, should Emily be able to reject the abortion in the first
trimester, knowing
that it is highly probable that continuing to take her necessary
medications will
severely and permanently impair the baby?
In reflecting upon the question, recall the court’s arguments in
Roe v. Wade, and any
counter arguments provided in your materials. Also, consider th
e question of the
fetus (encompassing all stages from conception through prebirth
development) and
the concept of moral standing.
Use the following template for your assignment:
1. Use Microsoft Word to create a document.
2. Copy/paste the title of the question.
3. Describe the most relevant ethical dilemma(s) presented (no
more than two).
10/27/2016
Final Case Analysis: The Emilly Dilemma - Abortion
https://mycourses.excelsior.edu/bbcswebdav/pid-3200850-dt-co
ntent-rid-31405097_1/courses/BHS.HSC312.Online.201610.201
612.s30047605/course%20wide… 3/3
4. Briefly describe the primary issue or issues that are relevant i
n the scenario with
respect to the dilemma.
5. Identify the most relevant stakeholder(s) (no more than 3) an
d briefly describe the
situation from their perspective.
6. Analyze the dilemma, using scholarly discussion, from the pe
rspective of the primary
stakeholder (typically the patient). Include a discussion of at lea
st two ethical theories
or bioethics principles studied in the course that relate to the dil
emma and issues you
identified. Include any relevant legal concerns or requirements
outlined in the
readings.
7. Present your assessment, resolution or potential solutions for
resolving the issue.
Remember that there are no right answers, per se, so reflective q
uestions can be as
appropriate as a firm conclusion.
8. Title page + APA formatted reference(s).
10/27/2016 Final Case Analysis: Paternalism vs Autonomy
https://mycourses.excelsior.edu/bbcswebdav/pid-3200850-dt-co
ntent-rid-31405097_1/courses/BHS.HSC312.Online.201610.201
612.s30047605/course%20wide… 1/2
Final Case Analysis: Paternalism v.s. Autonomy – Dax Cowart
Introduction to the Activity
I would like to introduce you to the story of Dax Cowart. Attach
ed is an excerpt from a
speech that Dax Cowart made several years ago, a speech that re
mains poignant for
contemporary reflection. The story is heart breaking and challen
ges all the bounds of
ethics and health care. As you listen to Dax, or read the transcri
pt of his talk, think about
the issues Dax discusses, especially in connection with capacity
and the right to decline
medical treatment (which we will discuss in greater detail later
on in the course). These are
the stories and circumstances where ethics and health care colli
de and individuals are
forced to make tough decisions. In thinking over your responses
to the Discussion Board
questions, consider the concepts we have talked about in this M
odule and in Module I,
such as personal moral values; bioethical principles; the need to
weigh and prioritize
competing moral interests; a physician’s charge to provide ethic
al care and a patient’s right
to self-determination.
Related Reading from Module 2:
Munson text: pp. 3­6; 38-40 (end at State Paternalism); 41-42 (e
nd at Informed
Consent); 891­904;
UVA News Makers - Dax Cowart
(Note: you may either watch the video part 1 [Video file] [09 mi
n 30 sec], and
video part 2 [Video file] [07 min 53 sec] or read the transcript a
nd Hastings
Center Report: Confronting Death: who chooses, who controls?)
Instructions to Learners
Please respond to the following questions (approx. 500-700 wor
ds) using the
template format provided for the assignment:
You are Dax’s physician. How would you respond to Dax’s requ
ests that you “let him die”?
Would you continue to treat him against his wishes? Why or Wh
y Not?
Use the following template for your assignment:
1. Use Microsoft Word to create a document.
2. Copy/paste the title of the question.
3. Describe the most relevant ethical dilemma(s) presented (no
more than two).
4. Briefly describe the primary issue or issues that are relevant i
n the scenario with
respect to the dilemma.
http://www.virginia.edu/uvanewsmakers/newsmakers/cowart.ht
ml
https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=lSsu6HkguV8&list=PLD93B
CDA6AFE8C393
https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=oGISGeKqCEM
http://www.virginia.edu/uvanewsmakers/newsmakers/cowart.ht
ml
http://vlib.excelsior.edu/login?url=http://search.ebscohost.com/l
ogin.aspx?direct=true&db=rzh&AN=1998034028&site=ehost-
live&scope=site
10/27/2016 Final Case Analysis: Paternalism vs Autonomy
https://mycourses.excelsior.edu/bbcswebdav/pid-3200850-dt-co
ntent-rid-31405097_1/courses/BHS.HSC312.Online.201610.201
612.s30047605/course%20wide… 2/2
5. Identify the most relevant stakeholder(s) (no more than 3) an
d briefly describe the
situation from their perspective.
6. Analyze the dilemma, using scholarly discussion, from the pe
rspective of the primary
stakeholder (typically the patient). Include a discussion of at lea
st two ethical theories
or bioethics principles studied in the course that relate to the dil
emma and issues you
identified. Include any relevant legal concerns or requirements
outlined in the
readings.
7. Present your assessment, resolution or potential solutions for
resolving the issue.
Remember that there are no right answers, per se, so reflective q
uestions can be as
appropriate as a firm conclusion.
8. Title page + APA formatted reference(s).
10/27/2016
Final Case Analysis: Morally Wrong or Ethically Challenging?
https://mycourses.excelsior.edu/bbcswebdav/pid-3200850-dt-co
ntent-rid-31405097_1/courses/BHS.HSC312.Online.201610.201
612.s30047605/course%20wide… 1/2
Final Case Analysis: Morally Wrong or Ethically Challenging?
Introduction to the Activity
Many states have considered enacting PAS legislation since Ore
gon first legalized the practice in 1994, but as of yet, only
Oregon and Washington have laws allowing for Physician Assist
ed Suicide (PAS) 127.800; RCW 70.245). In Montana,
although there is no current legislation regarding PAS, the Mont
ana Supreme Court provided protection for doctor’s
providing lethal medication to terminally ill patient’s upon requ
est (Baxter v. Montana, 2009 MT 449). Currently, forty-three
states have specific laws (either statutory or common law (case
law) prohibiting assisted suicides, but four states (Hawaii,
Nevada, Utah, Wyoming) and the District of Columbia have no l
aw regarding the subject. Just recently, Massachusetts
voters defeated a ballet initiative based upon the Oregon statute
by a marginal 51% majority.
Related Reading from Module 5:
Module notes and assigned textbook pages
Arras, J. (1997). Physician-assisted suicide: a tragic view. The J
ournal Of Contemporary Health Law And Policy,
13(2), 361-389. (28)
*The New York State Task Force on Life and the Law, (1997).
When death is sought assisted suicide and
euthanasia in the medical context supplement to report. Retrieve
d from website:
http://wings.buffalo.edu/bioethics/suppl.html.
*Scroll down and read until the end of the passage “IV The Dist
inction Between Administering High Doses of
Opioids to Relieve Pain and “Physician­assisted Death.”
Public Health, (1997). Oregon revised statute: Death with dignit
y act (Chapter 127). Retrieved from Oregon Health
Authority website:
http://public.health.oregon.gov/ProviderPartnerResources/Evalu
ationResearch/DeathwithDignityAct/Pages/ors.
rules: 127.800 s.1.01. Definitions - 127.875 s.3.13. Insurance or
annuity policies.
Dep’t of Public Health, Annual Report on Oregon’s Death with
Dignity Act (2012) [PDF file size 197 KB]
http://public.health.oregon.gov/ProviderPartnerResources/Evalu
ationResearch/DeathwithDignityAct/Documents/year15.pdf
*Scan through the report to get an idea on how the statistics are
compiled and trends recorded
Instructions to Learners
Please read the case scenario:
You are a physician-ethicist at Hope hospital in Nirvana, USA.
Your state is voting this month whether to allow PAS, under
the exact guidelines and safeguards instituted in Oregon. The lo
cal news station has asked you to join a televised multi-
disciplinary panel and discuss the following questions:
Reviewing the safeguards included in the Oregon Statute, which
one(s ) potentially raise the most concerns in terms of
their ability to protect patients in Nirvana, USA? In developing
your response, consider whether the concerns are morally
founded or policy oriented. Also keep in mind the rules of profe
ssional responsibility, patient rights and the principles of
bioethics we have studied throughout the course.
NOTE: Please use the modified template below when considerin
g your response with respect to completing the template,
remember that a stakeholder can be described as many entities,
such as but not limited to an individual, a professional
society, the public at large or a subset of the population.
Modified Template:
1. Use Microsoft Word to create a document
2. Copy/paste the title of the question
3. State the safeguards that you find most concerning.
4. Identify the most relevant stakeholder(s) (no more than 3) pot
entially affected by the safeguards you listed.
http://www.lexisnexis.com.vlib.excelsior.edu/lnacui2api/api/ver
sion1/getDocCui?lni=3S3T-V110-00CV-
P0S8&csi=138724&hl=t&hv=t&hnsd=f&hns=t&hgn=t&oc=0024
0&perma=true
http://wings.buffalo.edu/bioethics/suppl.html
http://public.health.oregon.gov/ProviderPartnerResources/Evalu
ationResearch/DeathwithDignityAct/Pages/ors.aspx
http://public.health.oregon.gov/ProviderPartnerResources/Evalu
ationResearch/DeathwithDignityAct/Documents/year15.pdf
10/27/2016
Final Case Analysis: Morally Wrong or Ethically Challenging?
https://mycourses.excelsior.edu/bbcswebdav/pid-3200850-dt-co
ntent-rid-31405097_1/courses/BHS.HSC312.Online.201610.201
612.s30047605/course%20wide… 2/2
5. Analyze the concerns, using scholarly discussion from the per
spective of the primary stakeholder. Include a
discussion of at least two ethical theories or bioethics principles
studied in the course that relate to the dilemma and
issues you identified. Include any relevant legal concerns or req
uirements outlined in the readings.
6. Present your assessment, resolution or potential solutions for
resolving the concern. Remember that there are no
right answers, per se, so reflective questions can be as appropria
te as a firm conclusion.
7. Title page + APA formatted reference(s)
10/27/2016
Final Case Analysis: Confidentiality, Disclosure and Livid Love
birds
https://mycourses.excelsior.edu/bbcswebdav/pid-3200850-dt-co
ntent-rid-31405097_1/courses/BHS.HSC312.Online.201610.201
612.s30047605/course%20wide… 1/3
Final Case Analysis: Confidentiality, Disclosure and Livid Love
birds
Informed consent requires not only that a patient receive all of t
he information necessary to
make a reasoned decision, but also that they are able to process
and understand the
information provided. Language or cultural differences may imp
ede understanding, and a
blanket reliance on a doctor’s judgment may subvert the intent o
f the disclosure. Other
barriers to informed consent, such as denial, fear and even famil
y dynamics are often
more difficult to spot, but equally if not more detrimental. Relat
ionships between patients,
family members and healthcare providers often morph over time
into roles and role
reversals that present special challenges in healthcare ethics and
the doctor-patient
relationship. In this activity, you will consider the standards of
professional responsibility,
medical ethics and the doctor-patient relationship as they apply
when the boundaries
between the roles become blurred.
Related Reading from Module 3:
Module Notes
Munson text: (end at Parents & Children).
AMA Opinion 10.01 - Fundamental Elements of the Patient-Phy
sician Relationship
Mitnick, S., Leffler, C., & Hood, V. (2010). Family caregivers,
patients and physicians:
ethical guidance to optimize relationships. Journal Of General I
nternal Medicine,
25(3), 255-260.
Principles of Medical Ethics. (2001).
Schwartz, P. H. (2011). Questioning the Quantitative Imperative
: Decision Aids,
Prevention, and the Ethics of Disclosure. The Hastings Center R
eport, (2), 30.
doi:10.2307/41059016
Instructions to Learners
Please read the case scenario:
Mr. and Mrs. Lovebird were approaching their 65th wedding an
niversary when it was
discovered that Mr. Lovebird was battling Stage IV lung cancer,
with metastasis to his
colon. Vowing to “Fight this thing!” the Lovebirds sought out th
e best specialists and Mr.
Lovebird underwent two surgeries, chemotherapy and several ro
unds of radiation. Mr.
Lovebird did quite well for a while, but lately he has experience
d severe fatigue and
discomfort. He has also lost his appetite, resulting in a 15lb wei
ght loss in just two months.
Concerned, the Lovebirds went to see Dr. Friendly, their primar
y care physician for over 30
years, whom they trust implicitly. Knowing that the Lovebirds a
re in denial to some extent,
but also believing that medicine is an inexact science, Dr. Frien
dly told them both about an
http://www.ama-assn.org/ama/pub/physician-resources/medical-
ethics/code-medical-ethics/opinion1001.page
http://www.ama-assn.org/ama/pub/physician-resources/medical-
ethics/code-medical-ethics/principles-medical-ethics.page
http://eds.a.ebscohost.com.vlib.excelsior.edu/eds/detail?vid=2&
sid=3a5595c1-f673-4a7c-9b34-
ff2409ff1a33%40sessionmgr4001&hid=4105&bdata=JnNpdGU9
ZWRzLWxpdmUmc2NvcGU9c2l0ZQ%3d%3d#db=rzh&AN=201
1703087
10/27/2016
Final Case Analysis: Confidentiality, Disclosure and Livid Love
birds
https://mycourses.excelsior.edu/bbcswebdav/pid-3200850-dt-co
ntent-rid-31405097_1/courses/BHS.HSC312.Online.201610.201
612.s30047605/course%20wide… 2/3
experimental treatment option that might be worth “checking int
o,” even though the
chances were slim that it would provide much benefit.
At a dinner party for a mutual acquaintance, Dr. Friendly is app
roached by Lancelot, the
Lovebird’s only child. Dr. Friendly is aware of the close relatio
nship between Lancelot and
the Lovebirds, so he is concerned for their welfare when Lancel
ot approaches him. Once
alone, Lancelot appears upset and tells Dr. Friendly that he is co
ncerned about the
experimental treatment option Dr. Friendly mentioned to the Lo
vebirds, given Mr.
Lovebird’s fatigue and weight loss. From Lancelot’s perspective
, it is obvious that even if
successful, it would only buy Mr. Lovebird a few months and th
ose months may not be
very good ones. He is also concerned that Mr. Lovebird is tired
of treatments, but goes
along to please Mrs. Lovebird. Dr. Friendly smiles and shakes h
is head “Your mother has
always been a force to be reckoned with,” he says “But, in realit
y, a few months is better
than no months!” He also assures Lancelot that if the Oncologis
t does not think Mr.
Lovebird is a good candidate for the procedure, the Oncologist
will tell them so.
When Lancelot suggests that Dr. Friendly’s professional judgme
nt may be colored by the
Lovebird’s denial, Dr. Friendly becomes defensive, stating that
as their doctor all he can do
is provide them with information and statistics on the disease pr
ognosis and the benefits
and risks of any potential options. He admonishes Lancelot, stat
ing “if your parents want to
believe in miracles, I am not going to take that away from them,
and you shouldn’t either!”
Visibly upset, Lancelot insists that Dr. Friendly discuss the Hos
pice option with the
Lovebirds, preferably with Mr. Lovebird, first. Although Dr. Fri
endly is concerned that the
idea of Hospice could be more lethal to the Lovebirds than any
experimental treatment, he
agrees, on the condition that Lancelot raise it with the Lovebird
s first. “If your parents seem
open to the conversation, give me a call or have them call me, a
nd I will sit down with them
to discuss the options.”
The next day, Lancelot goes to see Mr. and Mrs. Lovebird, and s
hares his conversation
with Dr. Friendly, telling them that both he and Dr. Friendly agr
ee that it may be time for
Hospice services. Both the Lovebirds become very angry that he
was discussing them with
Dr. Friendly without them knowing it. They are also devastated
that Dr. Friendly would
conspire with Lancelot to force a decision on them that is clearl
y premature. When he
leaves, Mrs. Lovebird calls Dr. Friendly and tells him that she i
s furious with his breach of
confidentiality and that he should stick to family practice, as he
is not an oncology expert.
Please respond to the following questions (approx. 500-700 wor
ds) using the
template format provided for the assignment:
Given Dr. Friendly’s longstanding relationship with the Lovebir
ds, his insight into their
processing and coping mechanisms, and the close family relatio
nship he has witnessed
between the Lovebirds and their son, did Dr. Friendly’s breach
his professional
10/27/2016
Final Case Analysis: Confidentiality, Disclosure and Livid Love
birds
https://mycourses.excelsior.edu/bbcswebdav/pid-3200850-dt-co
ntent-rid-31405097_1/courses/BHS.HSC312.Online.201610.201
612.s30047605/course%20wide… 3/3
responsibility to Mr. and Mrs. Lovebird by suggesting that Lanc
elot discuss the Hospice
option with the Lovebirds first?
Use the following template for your assignment:
1. Use Microsoft Word to create a document.
2. Copy/paste the title of the question.
3. Describe the most relevant ethical dilemma(s) presented (no
more than two).
4. Briefly describe the primary issue or issues that are relevant i
n the scenario with
respect to the dilemma.
5. Identify the most relevant stakeholder(s) (no more than 3) an
d briefly describe the
situation from their perspective.
6. Analyze the dilemma, using scholarly discussion, from the pe
rspective of the primary
stakeholder (typically the patient). Include a discussion of at lea
st two ethical theories
or bioethics principles studied in the course that relate to the dil
emma and issues you
identified. Include any relevant legal concerns or requirements
outlined in the
readings.
7. Present your assessment, resolution or potential solutions for
resolving the issue.
Remember that there are no right answers, per se, so reflective q
uestions can be as
appropriate as a firm conclusion.
8. Title page + APA formatted reference(s).
A MEDICAL ETHICS ASSESSMENT OF THE CASE
OF TERRI SCHIAVO
TOM PRESTON
University of Washington, Seattle, Washington, USA
MICHAEL KELLY
Swedish Medical Center and University of Washington,
Seattle, Washington, USA
The social, legal, and political discussion about the decision to
stop feeding and
hydration for Terri Schiavo lacked a medical ethics assessment.
The authors used
the principles of medical indications, quality of life, patient
preference, and
contextual features as a guide to medical decision-making in
this case. Their
conclusions include the following: (a) the use of a feeding tube
inserted directly
in to the stomach constituted artificial treatment; (b) the
treatment prolonged
biological life but did not lead to a cure and did not restore
health; (c) quality
of life was absent for the patient, with no sensation and no
motor or cognitive
functioning; and (d) by preponderance of medical opinion, she
would have chosen
not to live in a persistent vegetative state. The authors find the
withdrawal of
treatment was permissible and correct. It was not a choice
between living and
dying, but a decision of when to allow dying consistent with the
patient’s choice.
The case of Terri Schiavo, vexing as it was, holds lessons for us
all.
The forceful public reactions to the medical and legal
proceedings
leading to her demise showed a deep schism over the moral=
religious issues inherent in how we die in the modern age of
medi-
cine. In our opinion, the political and legal wrangling detracted
from the public understanding of the medical and bioethical
issues
involved in the case.
Some might further argue that the case exposed a severe fault
line in the bioethics approach to issues of this sort, or at least a
limi-
tation of the usefulness of bioethics. After all, the case never
went
under the scrutiny of a bioethics committee and there was no
This article was written prior to release of the autopsy report on
Terri Schiavo.
Address correspondence to Tom Preston, 1128 22nd Ave. E.,
Seattle, WA 98112.
E-mail: [email protected]
121
Death Studies, 30: 121–133, 2006
Copyright # Taylor & Francis Group, LLC
ISSN: 0748-1187 print/1091-7683 online
DOI: 10.1080/07481180500455608
formal statement of medical ethics conveyed to the public in
support of letting Terri die. The public media presentation of
the
case was in social, political, and legal terms, with sparse, if
any,
discussion of how bioethical principles might apply to the
difficult
issues involved. The absence of a classic medical ethics
assessment
was a lost opportunity to educate the public.
In this article we apply the basic tenets of medical ethics to the
medical decision-making process in the Schiavo case. Medical
ethics, or bioethics, began as a means of giving physicians and
other health care providers guidelines for handling ethical pro-
blems that occur in the practice of medicine. It then developed
as a method for dealing with new ethical issues, particularly
those
arising from procedures such as artificial kidney treatment
(dialy-
sis), resuscitation, and withdrawal of life-sustaining treatment
( Jonsen, Siegler, & Winslade, 1992). We use the technique of
Jonsen, Siegler, and Winslade (2002), which focuses on four
topics
clinicians should take into account in assessing the ethical
aspects
of a medical decision: medical indications, patient preference,
quality of life, and contextual features.
Medical Indications
Medical ethics begins by asking whether the proposed treatment
or procedure is medically indicated—does it fulfill the goals of
medicine? Using the principle of beneficence, we ask does this
treatment maintain life, restore health, and prevent symptoms?
Do the benefits outweigh the potential harm of the treatment?
What were the medical ‘‘facts’’ of the Terri Schiavo case, and
what can bioethics teach us about how to proceed when a next
similar case occurs? Removing Terri Schiavo’s feeding tube was
not a treatment per se, but rather the discontinuation of
treatment
with hydration and nutrition. Terri did not sense food in her
mouth
and did not have a swallowing reflex. Because she was unable
to
swallow, she could not be fed through her mouth without a
strong
likelihood of choking to death, so the feeding tube was the only
means of keeping her alive. The treatment under analysis is
there-
fore the continuation of fluids and nutrients through Terri’s
feeding
tube. The central question was whether continued treatment
with
the feeding tube was medically indicated. Was this treatment of
122 T. Preston and M. Kelly
benefit to Terri, or was the treatment disproportionately burden-
some and harmful to her?
One of the goals of medicine is to maintain life or to prevent
death. The goal, however, is not to prevent all death but to
prevent
untimely or inappropriate death. In this case, continued feeding
certainly would have kept Terri alive, as it had done for 15
years.
Although in many cases the goal of maintaining life is pre-
eminent,
when the ethical issue is whether life should continue or be
allowed
to end, this goal is subsumed under other considerations.
Whether
death from stopping the treatment would have been considered
timely or untimely depends on factors such as perceived patient
preference, judgment of what would be best for her, and
opinions
about the quality of her life.
Would continued treatment have relieved symptoms of pain
and suffering? No. Terri had only involuntary reflexes, with no
function above the brain stem. She had no cognitive function or
awareness of her surroundings, and no physical or mental
sensation
of pain or suffering. Therefore treatment was not relieving
suffering.
Would continued treatment have restored health? Would it
have cured the disease or improved functional status? Two
neurol-
ogists selected by Terri’s parents (who opposed ending
treatment)
suggested that Terri’s smiles and movements represented
cognition
and sensation, whereas two neurologists selected by Terri’s
husband and one selected independently by the court testified
that
Terri’s reflexes were involuntary and she was in a persistent
veg-
etative state from which she would never recover (see
Cerminara’s
introductory article for a detailed review of the related history).
All five neurologists agreed that Terri had suffered enormous
damage to her brain, such that most of her cerebral cortex,
which
controls conscious thought, was gone, replaced by spinal fluid.
The
biological probability for a cure of her condition was so
minimal as
to be effectively zero.
In the second trial, the court heard conflicting evidence as to
whether new therapy might succeed in restoring Terri’s brain
func-
tion and found no credible evidence that Terri would ever
recover
significant function. This finding was unanimously upheld on
appeal. Undeniably, the prognosis in this case was crucial to a
sound ethical judgment, and any disagreement makes the
decision
difficult. We agree with the trial courts that claims of potential
improvement with new therapies were without merit. The
treatment
Medical Ethics Assessment 123
offered no chance for restoring health. Because treatment was
not
relieving symptoms, and it held no reasonable chance for a cure
or
clinical improvement, there was no medical indication for
contin-
ued treatment with the feeding tube.
Germane to the discussion is a related question: Was Terri
Schiavo on life support, or was she merely being fed through a
tube? Some argued that treatment with food and fluids should
never be withdrawn from dying or permanently unconscious
patients (e.g., Pope John Paul II, 2004). Feeding is natural, they
said, and ‘‘merely being fed through a tube’’ is not life
support—it
is different from stopping treatments such as artificial breathing
with a mechanical ventilator.
We all understand the emotion behind this argument when
it is made to keep a loved one alive, but from a medical ethics
perspective it is not correct. Medically, stopping feeding is no
different from stopping a breathing machine that is keeping
some-
one alive. Air is also natural, and breathing is a natural
function.
Food and air are equally natural and essential to life. If a person
is permanently unable to breathe, we can delay death with
artificial
breathing. If a person is permanently unable to swallow we can
delay death by placing a feeding tube into the stomach and
bypass-
ing the need to swallow.
It is as unnatural to pierce through the abdomen and place a
tube into a patient’s stomach, and then pour food through the
tube
or pump it into the stomach with a machine, as it is to use a
machine to blow air into a patient’s lungs. With artificial
breathing,
the air at least goes in and out through the natural wind-pipe,
while
artificial feeding bypasses the natural process of swallowing
food
through the esophagus to the stomach. The mechanisms of arti-
ficial feeding and breathing are different, but one is not more or
less natural than the other.
But, some argued, food and fluids are ordinary and natural
and stopping them is ‘‘killing,’’ it is ‘‘starving’’ a person to
death
(e.g., Pope John Paul II, 2004). On the other hand, they said, it
is
allowable to disconnect a patient from a breathing machine
because
it is an extraordinary medical measure (see also, President’s
Commission for the Study of Ethical Problems in Medicine and
Biomedical and Behavioral Research, 1983). But one is not
extra-
ordinary, whereas the other is ordinary. In its landmark report,
the President’s Commission for the Study of Ethical Problems
in
124 T. Preston and M. Kelly
Medicine concluded: ‘‘There is no basis for holding that
whether
a treatment is common or unusual, or whether it is simple or
com-
plex, is in itself significant to a moral analysis of whether a
treatment
is warranted or obligatory’’ (p. 87). Also, according to Florida
stat-
ute, a ‘‘Life-prolonging procedure means any medical
procedure,
treatment, or intervention, including artificially provided
sustenance
and hydration, which sustains, restores, or supplants a
spontaneous
vital function’’ (Health Care Advance Directives, Definitions,
x765.101, 2004, emphasis added; see also xx765.301-309). This
is
consistent with medical understanding and the tenets of medical
ethics. Terri Schiavo was on life-support because she could not
survive without the fluid and nutrition treatment she was
receiving.
Nonmaleficence
Application of the principle of nonmaleficence (do no harm)
leads
us to ask, would continued feeding have been good treatment
for
Terri, or would it have harmed her? Would either maintaining
or discontinuing the treatment cause harm out of proportion to
benefit for her?
Would removing Terri’s feeding tube be inhumane by causing
‘‘starvation’’ and pain? In comparison to withdrawing artificial
breathing with a ventilator, stopping tube-feeding appears to be
a
long, drawn-out procedure during which the patient may suffer.
But Terri had no sensation of thirst or hunger. She did not
suffer
when the feeding tube was withdrawn, and the absence of food
and fluids did not cause suffering (Multi-Society Task Force on
PVS, 1994).
There is an important emotional difference between slow
dying after withdrawal of food and water and the rapid death
following disconnecting a patient from a respirator. One
watches
the patient dying slowly from absence of food and water and
might
conclude, ‘‘They are starving her to death.’’ But families do not
usually watch their loved one being disconnected from a
breathing
machine. If they did, they would say, ‘‘They are suffocating
him to
death.’’ Discomfort or pain is possible in the latter procedure
only
if the patient is not given sufficient sedative or pain medicine to
obliterate symptoms. On the other hand, there is no discomfort
associated with dehydration after withdrawal of a feeding tube
in
a patient with persistent vegetative state.
Medical Ethics Assessment 125
Would continued treatment have harmed Terri? Unfortunately,
many relatives or loved ones of patients on life-supporting
therapy
do not understand the consequences of continued treatment.
Although Terri would not have perceived suffering had she
remained alive, over the years or decades to come she inevitably
would have acquired illnesses associated with aging and being
bed-ridden, which would have increased the psychological
burden
on her family.
The larger question was whether Terri benefited or was
harmed by dying. The answer to this rests in part on her quality
of life if feeding had been continued. Certainty on this point is
impossible and must take into account the complexity of the
judg-
ment of the value of living indefinitely in a persistent
vegetative
state. Whether Terri benefited or was harmed by dying also
depends on determination of her personal preference, or her
valuation of continued living in that condition.
Autonomy, or Patient Preferences
In our opinion, this is probably the most important ethical
determi-
nant of the case. There is little question that had Terri had an
advance directive with a clear statement on whether she would
want to continue living in a persistent vegetative state, the
medical
decision would have been according to her stated desire and
there
would have been little or no controversy. Perhaps the most
daunt-
ing problem in medical ethics is a life or death decision when
the
patient cannot state her choice, and the patient’s loved ones
have
conflicting wishes of what to do. This brings us to the concept
of
substituted judgment wherein the individual(s) who speaks for
the patient must make decisions according to the beliefs and life
style of the patient. The judgment should reflect not what the
loved
ones would want for the patient, but what the patient would
want.
Should we consider a patient’s known religious or social
beliefs? Indeed, we give much weight to any known such beliefs
or affirmations as indicative of a person’s fundamental values
and wishes. To this end, an explicit understanding of Terri’s
religious or social beliefs, such as from recorded statements,
would
have helped in determining whether she would have wanted
treatment to be continued or stopped. There was nothing
conclusive
on this point.
126 T. Preston and M. Kelly
We believe no one can be absolutely certain what Terri would
have wanted, or how much thought she gave before her injury to
what would have been for her a remote and hypothetical matter.
Lacking explicit evidence, we cannot gainsay the findings of the
courts. By the best evidence we have, Terri Schiavo would not
have wished to continue living in the condition of persistent
vegetative state (see Cerminara’s introduction).
Autonomy is exceedingly important in medical ethics, and
ordinarily trumps the wishes of others. The person involved in
the proposed procedure or treatment should in most cases be
able
to make medical decisions for herself, or, as in this case,
through a
surrogate or guardian.
But autonomy cannot be absolute if a medical decision hurts
others disproportionately to the gain of the person making the
autonomous decision. In this case, the decision should take into
account the preferences of others, notably Terri’s closest
relatives
or loved ones. However, the disagreement between Terri’s
parents
and her husband meant that the wishes of the two sides of the
dispute were diametrically opposed. If we give equal weight to
the opposing parties, this consideration is a net sum zero,
leaving
the patient’s desire as the sole determinant. Although some
disagree with the determination of what Terri would have
wanted,
it is based on the best evidence possible, and to go against the
best
evidence would be unwise.
Quality of Life
Future quality of life assessment is contingent on accurate
prognosis.
The finding that with continued treatment Terri would have
remained indefinitely in a persistent vegetative state means
there
was no reasonable hope for a cure, awareness of sensation, the
ability to move voluntarily, or to have cognitive function. With
no
awareness, she had no quality of life. Therefore, continued
treatment
would not have changed her quality of life status—it would not
have
made it better or worse.
Whether continuing with no quality of life would be seen as
favorable or unfavorable devolves upon assessment of whether
Terri would have wanted to continue existing in a persistent
vegetative state. This in turn hinges on medical prognosis.
Although
we acknowledge some difference of opinion regarding Terri’s
Medical Ethics Assessment 127
prognosis, by the preponderance of expert opinion, further
treatment would have been futile, and she would have had no
qual-
ity of life. By the quality of life criterion, therefore, it was
ethically
permissible to allow her to die.
Contextual Features—Socio-Economic, Personal,
and Institutional
Vital medical decisions are never made in a social vacuum, but
within the context of an individual’s upbringing, her family and
friends, social and cultural institutions, the law, and economic
influ-
ences. It is important to consider all contextual elements in
reaching
an important medical decision, as the decision can have a
lasting
effect on other persons and institutions, as well as on the
patient.
Should a medical decision take into account the considera-
tions of others? Yes, it should, and in particular it should
account
for close family members. However, here we come to the most
wrenching aspect of the case: the conflict and antagonism
between
Terri’s parents and her husband. Terri’s parents said they
desper-
ately wanted to keep her alive, so stopping treatment and
allowing
her to die would have hurt them deeply. On the other hand, if
Terri’s husband believed strongly that she should not be kept
alive,
a decision contrary to that wish would have hurt him. Can we
say
the parents’ emotional pain at seeing her die was greater than
the
husband’s pain would have been had she been kept alive? From
reports in the public media, and from the lengths to which her
par-
ents went to keep Terri alive, we can say ‘‘perhaps so.’’ Did
years
of continued treatment after Terri’s husband first asked to have
the
tube removed cause him pain? Perhaps so. What matters is
whether a decision one way or the other would cause undue
emotional harm to either of the parties.
The perception, by outsiders like us looking at the case, of
harm to either Terri’s parents or to her husband, is undoubtedly
influenced by characteristics, beliefs and values, and economic
or social gain or loss of the opposing personalities in the case.
For example, the personal religious convictions of Terri’s
parents
may have played a large role in wanting to keep her alive. Also,
the relationships of the loved ones to Terri, and observers’
ability
to identify with either the parents or the husband, may influence
outside observers’ views of right and wrong.
128 T. Preston and M. Kelly
Our perception of emotional harm is also influenced by our
own personal values and beliefs. Assessing harm to others
intimately
involved in the case also would involve value judgments based
on
information gleaned from the public media. It would be wrong,
we
believe, to judge the degree of harm to the parents or husband
based on our opinion of the reasons or underpinnings of their
wishes, or perceived personal characteristics of the disputants.
Further, this concern for others is disproportionately small com-
pared with what was best for Terri.
We must also consider the impact of our ethics decision on
institutions and religious or cultural groups that may believe
they
will be impacted by the decision. In July 2004, based on a
speech
in which Pope John Paul II said it is obligatory for physicians to
tube-feed patients in persistent vegetative states, Terri’s parents
filed a motion aimed at stopping withdrawal of the feeding tube
(see Cerminara’s article). This statement was contrary to what
was then a near consensus in the medical ethics community in
the United States—namely, it is ethically permissible to
withdraw
food and hydration in a patient in a persistent vegetative state if
the patient or the patient’s surrogate so desires. This finding
was
also affirmed by the U.S. Supreme Court (Cruzan v. Director,
Missouri Department of Health, 1990). Would a decision to stop
treat-
ment through a feeding tube cause harm to the Church? Many
‘‘right to life’’ advocates objected strenuously to removal of the
feeding tube, often on ideological grounds. Would removing the
feeding tube harm these groups and individuals?
These are contextual ‘‘macro-issues’’ of how individual medical
decisions can influence or alter institutions and policies that
affect
large groups of people or entire populations. Although macro-
issues
introduce important considerations, we cannot give them great
weight in this case. Unless there is a clear and overwhelming
public
consensus, there are usually multiple opposing forces
concerning a
contentious social issue. For example, although ‘‘right to life’’
indivi-
duals may feel harmed by a policy permitting cessation of
feeding
for a patient in a persistent vegetative state, ‘‘right to die’’
individuals
may perceive harm from a converse policy. One of the primary
goals of medical ethics is to protect the individual patient from
pub-
lic policies and institutions potentially harmful to the
individual’s
values or goals. The prime consideration must be the welfare
and
desires of the patient, not of social policy or institutions.
Medical Ethics Assessment 129
Another macro-issue is the allocation of scarce resources.
Using a ‘‘utilitarian’’ approach, we would make medical
decisions
to create the most good for the most people. Thus, one might
argue
that the resources necessary to keep someone alive for 15 years
in a
persistent vegetative state would be better allocated to provide
basic health care for others who have no health insurance or
can-
not get adequate health care. The expenditure of resources of
this
order and magnitude is not trivial. However, although
individual
cases may bring national attention to social inadequacies,
broader
societal issues such as allocation of scarce resources are better
handled on a macro scale of policy-making. The preponderance
of weight in individual medical ethical decisions must be
directed
to considerations of what is best for the individual patient.
If contextual factors (perceived harm to the relatives of one
side or the other; religious beliefs; political, economic, and
legal
desires) were overwhelming, they might tilt our judgment. Such
not being the case, however, the ethical decision must rest
firmly
on assessment of what was best for the patient. In the end, in
Terri’s case all these contextual factors are minimal or are sub-
sumed under the ethical considerations of beneficence and the
patient’s preference.
Comment and Conclusions
By applying the classic elements of medical ethics, we find that
it
was ethically permissible and appropriate to stop Terri
Schiavo’s
treatment by use of a feeding tube. After 15 years with no sign
of
improvement, it is unreasonable to conclude that continued tube
feeding would have led to clinical improvement. When the out-
come is uncertain we should err on the side of maintaining life.
But a helpful ethical maxim is that it is better to stop a
treatment that
was tried and did not work than to not start a treatment that has
an
uncertain outcome. This maxim was definitely followed in this
case!
The ramifications of the case are numerous if not legion by
now and deserve the attention of all Americans. We believe the
case’s most important lesson is the need for advance directives.
The immense hostility and divisiveness engendered,
individually
and nationally, may be even more likely to recur in a future case
of a patient in similar circumstances. The case has caused an
unnecessary social divide.
130 T. Preston and M. Kelly
In future cases involving care of patients in persistent
vegetative
states, violent disagreements as in the Schiavo case may be
avoided
by a full and early application of the principles of medical
ethics.
Just as importantly, the public needs to be informed of this
approach to ethically difficult medical decisions, and the media
should make use of it in their reporting. In our opinion, the
inor-
dinate and sensationalist media attention to the Schiavo case,
with
the marked emotional reactions of so many individuals and
groups, detracted greatly from an understanding of the ethical
principles that should have been applied to a determination of
what was best for Terri.
The medical ethics approach is not intended as an all-encom-
passing set of rules for clinical decision-making. In a rare
public
reference to bioethics, a syndicated columnist said the
discipline
had become a secular tool and blamed ‘‘left-leaning bioethics’’
for justifying the ‘‘killing’’ of people such as Terri Schiavo
(Leo,
2005). We acknowledge the secular basis of medical ethics as
necessary to establish guidelines for all physicians without
imposing specific religious or spiritual beliefs on those who do
not share them. How physicians and others superimpose their
religious or spiritual beliefs on medical ethics is a matter of
indi-
vidual values and goals. One may supplement medical ethics
with personal principled beliefs, but we urge all to understand
that in medical ethics ‘‘one size does not fit all.’’ There must be
room to apply the principles of medical ethics within diverse
sub-cultures.
Part of the problem, we believe, has been a misplaced focus
on ‘‘pulling the feeding tube,’’ rather than on the basic ethical
question of the treatment Terri was receiving. By focusing only
on the final act of withdrawing food and fluids, with its
attendant
symbolism to some of ‘‘killing,’’ one cannot understand the
patient’s medical condition, the role of prior medical decisions,
and the need for medical ethics in reaching a decision.
Fundamental to an understanding of dying patients is the
nature of earlier decisions, particularly treatments. Any life-
extend-
ing treatment decision is a choice to defer dying to a later date
and,
most likely, under different conditions. Continued provision of
artificial nutrition and hydration to Terri would not have
fulfilled
the ethical goals of medical treatment—it could have only
postponed,
not prevented death.
Medical Ethics Assessment 131
Dyinghasbeenpostponedbyhumanchoicewhenweartificially
feed or breathe for a patient. The treatment is the key ethical
issue,
as without it the patient dies; however, with continuous
treatment
there is a continuous deferral of dying to a later date. The
problem
with continuing treatment after the prognosis is clear is exactly
what happened to Terri. Once natural death is overcome medi-
cally, and there is no medical reason to expect recovery,
someone
must make the decision about how and when to allow death to
pro-
ceed.
The issue is not ‘‘killing,’’ or depriving a disabled person of
life,
but when to stop an unsuccessful treatment in order to allow
death
that has been unnaturally postponed. Medically, it seems
reasonable
to continue treatment for up to a year after a patient is
diagnosed as
being in a persistent vegetative state, although many
neurologists
might argue it is futile to treat after six months, or even less.
But after
the long-term outlook is clear, the choice is whether to allow a
patient to die, as would have been Terri’s choice based on the
best
evidence, or to wait and let her die years later, as her parents
wished.
Either way it is a human decision someone had to make.
Most Americans still die in institutions such as hospitals and
nursing homes where decisions are made whether to resuscitate,
to treat life-threatening complications, to try more curative
ther-
apy, or to withdraw life-sustaining treatments (Faber-
Langendoen
& Lanken, 2000; Field & Cassel, 1997). When patients are at
the
end of life and not capable of making medical decisions, loved
ones often make decisions to stop treatments and let them die
instead of extending ‘‘life’’ to the limits of modern technology.
This
is not killing, it is allowing death to proceed rather than
extending
the dying process. After life is first prolonged by medical
manage-
ment, it is allowed to end sometime later. It was the same for
Terri
Schiavo, and it is ethically correct.
References
Cruzan v. Director. Missouri Department of Health, 476 U.S.
261 (1990).
Faber-Langendoen, K. & Lanken, P. N. (2000). Dying patients
in the intensive
care unit: Forgoing treatment, maintaining care. Annals of
Internal Medicine,
133, 886–893.
Field, M. J. & Cassel, C. K. (Eds.). (1997). Approaching death:
Improving care at the
end of life. Washington, DC: National Academy Press.
132 T. Preston and M. Kelly
Health Care Advance Directives, Definitions. (2004). Fla. Stat.
Title XLIV, Chap-
ter 765.101.
Jonsen, A. R., Siegler, M., & Winslade, W. J. (1992). Clinical
ethics (3rd ed.).
New York: McGraw Hill.
Jonsen, A. R., Siegler, M., & Winslade, W. J. (2002). Clinical
ethics (5th ed.).
New York: McGraw Hill.
Leo, J. (March 29, 2005). Left-leaning bioethics at core of the
Schiavo debate.
Seattle Times, p. B7.
Multi-Society Task Force on PVS. (1994). Medical aspects of
the persistent
vegetative state—second of two parts. New England Journal of
Medicine, 330,
1572–1579.
Pope John Paul II. (2004, March 20). Address of John Paul II to
the participants in
the International Congress on ‘‘Life-Sustaining Treatments and
Vegetation State:
Scientific Advances and Ethical Dilemmas.’’ Retrieved
September 9, 2005 from
http://www.vatican.va/holy_father/john/paul_ii/speeches/2004/
march/
documents/hf_jp-ii_spe_20040320_congress-fiamc_en.html.
President’s Commission for the Study of Ethical Problems in
Medicine and
Biomedical and Behavioral Research. (1983). Deciding to forgo
life-sustaining
treatment: A report on the ethical, medical, and legal issues in
treatment decisions.
Washington, DC: GPO (Government Printing Office).
Medical Ethics Assessment 133
WHAT WOULD TERRI WANT?
ON THE PSYCHOLOGICAL CHALLENGES
OF SURROGATE DECISION MAKING
PETER H. DITTO
University of California, Irvine, California, USA
The Terri Schiavo case was unique in the media attention it
garnered, but the
decision making challenges faced by Terri’s family are common
ones encountered
by all families who must make choices about the use of life-
sustaining medical
treatment for an incapacitated loved one. This article highlights
three key issues
that were particularly problematic in the Schiavo case, but that
represent general
psychological challenges inherent to the task of surrogate
decision making. The 3
central points of uncertainty, and therefore conflict, in the
Schiavo case concerned:
(a) the appropriate standard by which medical decisions for
Terri should be
made, (b) the specific nature of Terri’s wishes about the use of
life-sustaining
medical technology, and (c) the true extent of disability and
prognosis for recovery
represented by Terri’s medical condition. No simple remedy is
possible that will
resolve all of the uncertainties inherent to surrogate decision
making, but some
general strategies for improving the quality of end-of-life
medical decisions are
discussed.
The tragic final chapter of Terri Schiavo’s life story was unique
in
many ways. Even in an era saturated with celebrity trials and
confessional television talk shows, seldom has such an
exquisitely
personal decision been elevated to the level of full-blown, 21st-
century style public spectacle. Discussions normally held in
rever-
ent tones within the dimly lit corridors of hospitals and hospices
were magnified by a 24-hour news cycle and an ongoing culture
war into a national conversation. The situation seemed uniquely
cursed with every difficulty that might befall a family striving
to
make the right decisions for an incapacitated loved one.
Irreconcil-
able differences between family members about the appropriate
course of action, the lack of any written documentation of
Terri’s
Address correspondence to Peter H. Ditto, Department of
Psychology and Social
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx
 HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx

More Related Content

Similar to HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx

Homework 4.docx
Homework 4.docxHomework 4.docx
Homework 4.docx4934bk
 
The purpose of this paper is to apply information gathered from th.docx
The purpose of this paper is to apply information gathered from th.docxThe purpose of this paper is to apply information gathered from th.docx
The purpose of this paper is to apply information gathered from th.docxoreo10
 
Client Background Information· Marge C.· 41 year old female·
Client Background Information· Marge C.· 41 year old female·Client Background Information· Marge C.· 41 year old female·
Client Background Information· Marge C.· 41 year old female·WilheminaRossi174
 
Strategic Decision MakingComprehensive Capstone Case Study Instr.docx
Strategic Decision MakingComprehensive Capstone Case Study Instr.docxStrategic Decision MakingComprehensive Capstone Case Study Instr.docx
Strategic Decision MakingComprehensive Capstone Case Study Instr.docxsusanschei
 
Week 3 Assignment Addressing BiasGuidelines with Scoring Rubric.docx
Week 3 Assignment Addressing BiasGuidelines with Scoring Rubric.docxWeek 3 Assignment Addressing BiasGuidelines with Scoring Rubric.docx
Week 3 Assignment Addressing BiasGuidelines with Scoring Rubric.docxcockekeshia
 
Bioethics Case Study1.1.Bioethics Case Study This assignment .docx
Bioethics Case Study1.1.Bioethics Case Study This assignment .docxBioethics Case Study1.1.Bioethics Case Study This assignment .docx
Bioethics Case Study1.1.Bioethics Case Study This assignment .docxmoirarandell
 
Selection and formulation of a research problem.pptx
Selection and formulation of a research problem.pptxSelection and formulation of a research problem.pptx
Selection and formulation of a research problem.pptxGeorgeKabongah2
 
Grading criteria criteriamarks awarded leaflet – 20i
Grading criteria criteriamarks awarded leaflet – 20iGrading criteria criteriamarks awarded leaflet – 20i
Grading criteria criteriamarks awarded leaflet – 20ioreo10
 
Discussion QuestionWilliam Ford Jr., Chairman of Ford Motor C.docx
Discussion QuestionWilliam Ford Jr., Chairman of Ford Motor C.docxDiscussion QuestionWilliam Ford Jr., Chairman of Ford Motor C.docx
Discussion QuestionWilliam Ford Jr., Chairman of Ford Motor C.docxedgar6wallace88877
 
Complete and submit your Comprehensive Psychiatric including your differentia...
Complete and submit your Comprehensive Psychiatric including your differentia...Complete and submit your Comprehensive Psychiatric including your differentia...
Complete and submit your Comprehensive Psychiatric including your differentia...stirlingvwriters
 
Critical thinking and decision making
Critical thinking and decision makingCritical thinking and decision making
Critical thinking and decision makingMahmoud Shaqria
 
Complete and submit your Comprehensive Psychiatric Evaluation, i.docx
Complete and submit your Comprehensive Psychiatric Evaluation, i.docxComplete and submit your Comprehensive Psychiatric Evaluation, i.docx
Complete and submit your Comprehensive Psychiatric Evaluation, i.docxzollyjenkins
 
Top of FormViewG View Grading RubricsCounselor Ethics and Re.docx
Top of FormViewG View Grading RubricsCounselor Ethics and Re.docxTop of FormViewG View Grading RubricsCounselor Ethics and Re.docx
Top of FormViewG View Grading RubricsCounselor Ethics and Re.docxturveycharlyn
 
Discovery & data gathering 102310
Discovery & data gathering 102310Discovery & data gathering 102310
Discovery & data gathering 102310tjcarter
 
Assignment #2- Policy Implementation (17.5 points)Build on Assig.docx
Assignment #2- Policy Implementation (17.5 points)Build on Assig.docxAssignment #2- Policy Implementation (17.5 points)Build on Assig.docx
Assignment #2- Policy Implementation (17.5 points)Build on Assig.docxdavezstarr61655
 
Keller hsm 541 week 7 course project due
Keller hsm 541 week 7 course project dueKeller hsm 541 week 7 course project due
Keller hsm 541 week 7 course project duenoahjamessss
 
Keller hsm 541 week 7 course project due
Keller hsm 541 week 7 course project dueKeller hsm 541 week 7 course project due
Keller hsm 541 week 7 course project duedavid milton
 

Similar to HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx (20)

Homework 4.docx
Homework 4.docxHomework 4.docx
Homework 4.docx
 
The purpose of this paper is to apply information gathered from th.docx
The purpose of this paper is to apply information gathered from th.docxThe purpose of this paper is to apply information gathered from th.docx
The purpose of this paper is to apply information gathered from th.docx
 
Client Background Information· Marge C.· 41 year old female·
Client Background Information· Marge C.· 41 year old female·Client Background Information· Marge C.· 41 year old female·
Client Background Information· Marge C.· 41 year old female·
 
Strategic Decision MakingComprehensive Capstone Case Study Instr.docx
Strategic Decision MakingComprehensive Capstone Case Study Instr.docxStrategic Decision MakingComprehensive Capstone Case Study Instr.docx
Strategic Decision MakingComprehensive Capstone Case Study Instr.docx
 
Week 3 Assignment Addressing BiasGuidelines with Scoring Rubric.docx
Week 3 Assignment Addressing BiasGuidelines with Scoring Rubric.docxWeek 3 Assignment Addressing BiasGuidelines with Scoring Rubric.docx
Week 3 Assignment Addressing BiasGuidelines with Scoring Rubric.docx
 
Bioethics Case Study1.1.Bioethics Case Study This assignment .docx
Bioethics Case Study1.1.Bioethics Case Study This assignment .docxBioethics Case Study1.1.Bioethics Case Study This assignment .docx
Bioethics Case Study1.1.Bioethics Case Study This assignment .docx
 
Case Study Method
Case Study MethodCase Study Method
Case Study Method
 
Selection and formulation of a research problem.pptx
Selection and formulation of a research problem.pptxSelection and formulation of a research problem.pptx
Selection and formulation of a research problem.pptx
 
8-11 (2).pptx
8-11 (2).pptx8-11 (2).pptx
8-11 (2).pptx
 
Grading criteria criteriamarks awarded leaflet – 20i
Grading criteria criteriamarks awarded leaflet – 20iGrading criteria criteriamarks awarded leaflet – 20i
Grading criteria criteriamarks awarded leaflet – 20i
 
Writingacaseanalysis
WritingacaseanalysisWritingacaseanalysis
Writingacaseanalysis
 
Discussion QuestionWilliam Ford Jr., Chairman of Ford Motor C.docx
Discussion QuestionWilliam Ford Jr., Chairman of Ford Motor C.docxDiscussion QuestionWilliam Ford Jr., Chairman of Ford Motor C.docx
Discussion QuestionWilliam Ford Jr., Chairman of Ford Motor C.docx
 
Complete and submit your Comprehensive Psychiatric including your differentia...
Complete and submit your Comprehensive Psychiatric including your differentia...Complete and submit your Comprehensive Psychiatric including your differentia...
Complete and submit your Comprehensive Psychiatric including your differentia...
 
Critical thinking and decision making
Critical thinking and decision makingCritical thinking and decision making
Critical thinking and decision making
 
Complete and submit your Comprehensive Psychiatric Evaluation, i.docx
Complete and submit your Comprehensive Psychiatric Evaluation, i.docxComplete and submit your Comprehensive Psychiatric Evaluation, i.docx
Complete and submit your Comprehensive Psychiatric Evaluation, i.docx
 
Top of FormViewG View Grading RubricsCounselor Ethics and Re.docx
Top of FormViewG View Grading RubricsCounselor Ethics and Re.docxTop of FormViewG View Grading RubricsCounselor Ethics and Re.docx
Top of FormViewG View Grading RubricsCounselor Ethics and Re.docx
 
Discovery & data gathering 102310
Discovery & data gathering 102310Discovery & data gathering 102310
Discovery & data gathering 102310
 
Assignment #2- Policy Implementation (17.5 points)Build on Assig.docx
Assignment #2- Policy Implementation (17.5 points)Build on Assig.docxAssignment #2- Policy Implementation (17.5 points)Build on Assig.docx
Assignment #2- Policy Implementation (17.5 points)Build on Assig.docx
 
Keller hsm 541 week 7 course project due
Keller hsm 541 week 7 course project dueKeller hsm 541 week 7 course project due
Keller hsm 541 week 7 course project due
 
Keller hsm 541 week 7 course project due
Keller hsm 541 week 7 course project dueKeller hsm 541 week 7 course project due
Keller hsm 541 week 7 course project due
 

More from aryan532920

According to the NASW Code of Ethics section 6.04 (NASW, 2008), .docx
According to the NASW Code of Ethics section 6.04 (NASW, 2008), .docxAccording to the NASW Code of Ethics section 6.04 (NASW, 2008), .docx
According to the NASW Code of Ethics section 6.04 (NASW, 2008), .docxaryan532920
 
According to the text, crime has been part of the human condition si.docx
According to the text, crime has been part of the human condition si.docxAccording to the text, crime has been part of the human condition si.docx
According to the text, crime has been part of the human condition si.docxaryan532920
 
According to Ronald Story and Bruce Laurie, The dozen years between.docx
According to Ronald Story and Bruce Laurie, The dozen years between.docxAccording to Ronald Story and Bruce Laurie, The dozen years between.docx
According to Ronald Story and Bruce Laurie, The dozen years between.docxaryan532920
 
According to Kirk (2016), most of your time will be spent work with .docx
According to Kirk (2016), most of your time will be spent work with .docxAccording to Kirk (2016), most of your time will be spent work with .docx
According to Kirk (2016), most of your time will be spent work with .docxaryan532920
 
According to the Council on Social Work Education, Competency 5 Eng.docx
According to the Council on Social Work Education, Competency 5 Eng.docxAccording to the Council on Social Work Education, Competency 5 Eng.docx
According to the Council on Social Work Education, Competency 5 Eng.docxaryan532920
 
According to Kirk (2016), most of our time will be spent working.docx
According to Kirk (2016), most of our time will be spent working.docxAccording to Kirk (2016), most of our time will be spent working.docx
According to Kirk (2016), most of our time will be spent working.docxaryan532920
 
According to Kirk (2016), most of your time will be spent working wi.docx
According to Kirk (2016), most of your time will be spent working wi.docxAccording to Kirk (2016), most of your time will be spent working wi.docx
According to Kirk (2016), most of your time will be spent working wi.docxaryan532920
 
According to Davenport (2014) the organizational value of healthcare.docx
According to Davenport (2014) the organizational value of healthcare.docxAccording to Davenport (2014) the organizational value of healthcare.docx
According to Davenport (2014) the organizational value of healthcare.docxaryan532920
 
According to the authors, privacy and security go hand in hand; .docx
According to the authors, privacy and security go hand in hand; .docxAccording to the authors, privacy and security go hand in hand; .docx
According to the authors, privacy and security go hand in hand; .docxaryan532920
 
According to Gilbert and Troitzsch (2005), Foundations of Simula.docx
According to Gilbert and Troitzsch (2005), Foundations of Simula.docxAccording to Gilbert and Troitzsch (2005), Foundations of Simula.docx
According to Gilbert and Troitzsch (2005), Foundations of Simula.docxaryan532920
 
According to Klein (2016), using ethical absolutism and ethical .docx
According to Klein (2016), using ethical absolutism and ethical .docxAccording to Klein (2016), using ethical absolutism and ethical .docx
According to Klein (2016), using ethical absolutism and ethical .docxaryan532920
 
According to Franks and Smallwood (2013), information has become.docx
According to Franks and Smallwood (2013), information has become.docxAccording to Franks and Smallwood (2013), information has become.docx
According to Franks and Smallwood (2013), information has become.docxaryan532920
 
According to the Council on Social Work Education, Competency 5.docx
According to the Council on Social Work Education, Competency 5.docxAccording to the Council on Social Work Education, Competency 5.docx
According to the Council on Social Work Education, Competency 5.docxaryan532920
 
According to the authors, privacy and security go hand in hand; and .docx
According to the authors, privacy and security go hand in hand; and .docxAccording to the authors, privacy and security go hand in hand; and .docx
According to the authors, privacy and security go hand in hand; and .docxaryan532920
 
According to recent surveys, China, India, and the Philippines are t.docx
According to recent surveys, China, India, and the Philippines are t.docxAccording to recent surveys, China, India, and the Philippines are t.docx
According to recent surveys, China, India, and the Philippines are t.docxaryan532920
 
According to the authors, countries that lag behind the rest of the .docx
According to the authors, countries that lag behind the rest of the .docxAccording to the authors, countries that lag behind the rest of the .docx
According to the authors, countries that lag behind the rest of the .docxaryan532920
 
According to Peskin et al. (2013) in our course reader, Studies on .docx
According to Peskin et al. (2013) in our course reader, Studies on .docxAccording to Peskin et al. (2013) in our course reader, Studies on .docx
According to Peskin et al. (2013) in our course reader, Studies on .docxaryan532920
 
According to Franks and Smallwood (2013), information has become the.docx
According to Franks and Smallwood (2013), information has become the.docxAccording to Franks and Smallwood (2013), information has become the.docx
According to Franks and Smallwood (2013), information has become the.docxaryan532920
 
According to Ang (2011), how is Social Media management differen.docx
According to Ang (2011), how is Social Media management differen.docxAccording to Ang (2011), how is Social Media management differen.docx
According to Ang (2011), how is Social Media management differen.docxaryan532920
 
According to (Alsaidi & Kausar (2018), It is expected that by 2020,.docx
According to (Alsaidi & Kausar (2018), It is expected that by 2020,.docxAccording to (Alsaidi & Kausar (2018), It is expected that by 2020,.docx
According to (Alsaidi & Kausar (2018), It is expected that by 2020,.docxaryan532920
 

More from aryan532920 (20)

According to the NASW Code of Ethics section 6.04 (NASW, 2008), .docx
According to the NASW Code of Ethics section 6.04 (NASW, 2008), .docxAccording to the NASW Code of Ethics section 6.04 (NASW, 2008), .docx
According to the NASW Code of Ethics section 6.04 (NASW, 2008), .docx
 
According to the text, crime has been part of the human condition si.docx
According to the text, crime has been part of the human condition si.docxAccording to the text, crime has been part of the human condition si.docx
According to the text, crime has been part of the human condition si.docx
 
According to Ronald Story and Bruce Laurie, The dozen years between.docx
According to Ronald Story and Bruce Laurie, The dozen years between.docxAccording to Ronald Story and Bruce Laurie, The dozen years between.docx
According to Ronald Story and Bruce Laurie, The dozen years between.docx
 
According to Kirk (2016), most of your time will be spent work with .docx
According to Kirk (2016), most of your time will be spent work with .docxAccording to Kirk (2016), most of your time will be spent work with .docx
According to Kirk (2016), most of your time will be spent work with .docx
 
According to the Council on Social Work Education, Competency 5 Eng.docx
According to the Council on Social Work Education, Competency 5 Eng.docxAccording to the Council on Social Work Education, Competency 5 Eng.docx
According to the Council on Social Work Education, Competency 5 Eng.docx
 
According to Kirk (2016), most of our time will be spent working.docx
According to Kirk (2016), most of our time will be spent working.docxAccording to Kirk (2016), most of our time will be spent working.docx
According to Kirk (2016), most of our time will be spent working.docx
 
According to Kirk (2016), most of your time will be spent working wi.docx
According to Kirk (2016), most of your time will be spent working wi.docxAccording to Kirk (2016), most of your time will be spent working wi.docx
According to Kirk (2016), most of your time will be spent working wi.docx
 
According to Davenport (2014) the organizational value of healthcare.docx
According to Davenport (2014) the organizational value of healthcare.docxAccording to Davenport (2014) the organizational value of healthcare.docx
According to Davenport (2014) the organizational value of healthcare.docx
 
According to the authors, privacy and security go hand in hand; .docx
According to the authors, privacy and security go hand in hand; .docxAccording to the authors, privacy and security go hand in hand; .docx
According to the authors, privacy and security go hand in hand; .docx
 
According to Gilbert and Troitzsch (2005), Foundations of Simula.docx
According to Gilbert and Troitzsch (2005), Foundations of Simula.docxAccording to Gilbert and Troitzsch (2005), Foundations of Simula.docx
According to Gilbert and Troitzsch (2005), Foundations of Simula.docx
 
According to Klein (2016), using ethical absolutism and ethical .docx
According to Klein (2016), using ethical absolutism and ethical .docxAccording to Klein (2016), using ethical absolutism and ethical .docx
According to Klein (2016), using ethical absolutism and ethical .docx
 
According to Franks and Smallwood (2013), information has become.docx
According to Franks and Smallwood (2013), information has become.docxAccording to Franks and Smallwood (2013), information has become.docx
According to Franks and Smallwood (2013), information has become.docx
 
According to the Council on Social Work Education, Competency 5.docx
According to the Council on Social Work Education, Competency 5.docxAccording to the Council on Social Work Education, Competency 5.docx
According to the Council on Social Work Education, Competency 5.docx
 
According to the authors, privacy and security go hand in hand; and .docx
According to the authors, privacy and security go hand in hand; and .docxAccording to the authors, privacy and security go hand in hand; and .docx
According to the authors, privacy and security go hand in hand; and .docx
 
According to recent surveys, China, India, and the Philippines are t.docx
According to recent surveys, China, India, and the Philippines are t.docxAccording to recent surveys, China, India, and the Philippines are t.docx
According to recent surveys, China, India, and the Philippines are t.docx
 
According to the authors, countries that lag behind the rest of the .docx
According to the authors, countries that lag behind the rest of the .docxAccording to the authors, countries that lag behind the rest of the .docx
According to the authors, countries that lag behind the rest of the .docx
 
According to Peskin et al. (2013) in our course reader, Studies on .docx
According to Peskin et al. (2013) in our course reader, Studies on .docxAccording to Peskin et al. (2013) in our course reader, Studies on .docx
According to Peskin et al. (2013) in our course reader, Studies on .docx
 
According to Franks and Smallwood (2013), information has become the.docx
According to Franks and Smallwood (2013), information has become the.docxAccording to Franks and Smallwood (2013), information has become the.docx
According to Franks and Smallwood (2013), information has become the.docx
 
According to Ang (2011), how is Social Media management differen.docx
According to Ang (2011), how is Social Media management differen.docxAccording to Ang (2011), how is Social Media management differen.docx
According to Ang (2011), how is Social Media management differen.docx
 
According to (Alsaidi & Kausar (2018), It is expected that by 2020,.docx
According to (Alsaidi & Kausar (2018), It is expected that by 2020,.docxAccording to (Alsaidi & Kausar (2018), It is expected that by 2020,.docx
According to (Alsaidi & Kausar (2018), It is expected that by 2020,.docx
 

Recently uploaded

URLs and Routing in the Odoo 17 Website App
URLs and Routing in the Odoo 17 Website AppURLs and Routing in the Odoo 17 Website App
URLs and Routing in the Odoo 17 Website AppCeline George
 
KSHARA STURA .pptx---KSHARA KARMA THERAPY (CAUSTIC THERAPY)————IMP.OF KSHARA ...
KSHARA STURA .pptx---KSHARA KARMA THERAPY (CAUSTIC THERAPY)————IMP.OF KSHARA ...KSHARA STURA .pptx---KSHARA KARMA THERAPY (CAUSTIC THERAPY)————IMP.OF KSHARA ...
KSHARA STURA .pptx---KSHARA KARMA THERAPY (CAUSTIC THERAPY)————IMP.OF KSHARA ...M56BOOKSTORE PRODUCT/SERVICE
 
Sanyam Choudhary Chemistry practical.pdf
Sanyam Choudhary Chemistry practical.pdfSanyam Choudhary Chemistry practical.pdf
Sanyam Choudhary Chemistry practical.pdfsanyamsingh5019
 
SOCIAL AND HISTORICAL CONTEXT - LFTVD.pptx
SOCIAL AND HISTORICAL CONTEXT - LFTVD.pptxSOCIAL AND HISTORICAL CONTEXT - LFTVD.pptx
SOCIAL AND HISTORICAL CONTEXT - LFTVD.pptxiammrhaywood
 
Presentation by Andreas Schleicher Tackling the School Absenteeism Crisis 30 ...
Presentation by Andreas Schleicher Tackling the School Absenteeism Crisis 30 ...Presentation by Andreas Schleicher Tackling the School Absenteeism Crisis 30 ...
Presentation by Andreas Schleicher Tackling the School Absenteeism Crisis 30 ...EduSkills OECD
 
POINT- BIOCHEMISTRY SEM 2 ENZYMES UNIT 5.pptx
POINT- BIOCHEMISTRY SEM 2 ENZYMES UNIT 5.pptxPOINT- BIOCHEMISTRY SEM 2 ENZYMES UNIT 5.pptx
POINT- BIOCHEMISTRY SEM 2 ENZYMES UNIT 5.pptxSayali Powar
 
Employee wellbeing at the workplace.pptx
Employee wellbeing at the workplace.pptxEmployee wellbeing at the workplace.pptx
Employee wellbeing at the workplace.pptxNirmalaLoungPoorunde1
 
The basics of sentences session 2pptx copy.pptx
The basics of sentences session 2pptx copy.pptxThe basics of sentences session 2pptx copy.pptx
The basics of sentences session 2pptx copy.pptxheathfieldcps1
 
_Math 4-Q4 Week 5.pptx Steps in Collecting Data
_Math 4-Q4 Week 5.pptx Steps in Collecting Data_Math 4-Q4 Week 5.pptx Steps in Collecting Data
_Math 4-Q4 Week 5.pptx Steps in Collecting DataJhengPantaleon
 
Accessible design: Minimum effort, maximum impact
Accessible design: Minimum effort, maximum impactAccessible design: Minimum effort, maximum impact
Accessible design: Minimum effort, maximum impactdawncurless
 
Incoming and Outgoing Shipments in 1 STEP Using Odoo 17
Incoming and Outgoing Shipments in 1 STEP Using Odoo 17Incoming and Outgoing Shipments in 1 STEP Using Odoo 17
Incoming and Outgoing Shipments in 1 STEP Using Odoo 17Celine George
 
Organic Name Reactions for the students and aspirants of Chemistry12th.pptx
Organic Name Reactions  for the students and aspirants of Chemistry12th.pptxOrganic Name Reactions  for the students and aspirants of Chemistry12th.pptx
Organic Name Reactions for the students and aspirants of Chemistry12th.pptxVS Mahajan Coaching Centre
 
18-04-UA_REPORT_MEDIALITERAСY_INDEX-DM_23-1-final-eng.pdf
18-04-UA_REPORT_MEDIALITERAСY_INDEX-DM_23-1-final-eng.pdf18-04-UA_REPORT_MEDIALITERAСY_INDEX-DM_23-1-final-eng.pdf
18-04-UA_REPORT_MEDIALITERAСY_INDEX-DM_23-1-final-eng.pdfssuser54595a
 
How to Configure Email Server in Odoo 17
How to Configure Email Server in Odoo 17How to Configure Email Server in Odoo 17
How to Configure Email Server in Odoo 17Celine George
 
Hybridoma Technology ( Production , Purification , and Application )
Hybridoma Technology  ( Production , Purification , and Application  ) Hybridoma Technology  ( Production , Purification , and Application  )
Hybridoma Technology ( Production , Purification , and Application ) Sakshi Ghasle
 
mini mental status format.docx
mini    mental       status     format.docxmini    mental       status     format.docx
mini mental status format.docxPoojaSen20
 

Recently uploaded (20)

URLs and Routing in the Odoo 17 Website App
URLs and Routing in the Odoo 17 Website AppURLs and Routing in the Odoo 17 Website App
URLs and Routing in the Odoo 17 Website App
 
KSHARA STURA .pptx---KSHARA KARMA THERAPY (CAUSTIC THERAPY)————IMP.OF KSHARA ...
KSHARA STURA .pptx---KSHARA KARMA THERAPY (CAUSTIC THERAPY)————IMP.OF KSHARA ...KSHARA STURA .pptx---KSHARA KARMA THERAPY (CAUSTIC THERAPY)————IMP.OF KSHARA ...
KSHARA STURA .pptx---KSHARA KARMA THERAPY (CAUSTIC THERAPY)————IMP.OF KSHARA ...
 
Sanyam Choudhary Chemistry practical.pdf
Sanyam Choudhary Chemistry practical.pdfSanyam Choudhary Chemistry practical.pdf
Sanyam Choudhary Chemistry practical.pdf
 
SOCIAL AND HISTORICAL CONTEXT - LFTVD.pptx
SOCIAL AND HISTORICAL CONTEXT - LFTVD.pptxSOCIAL AND HISTORICAL CONTEXT - LFTVD.pptx
SOCIAL AND HISTORICAL CONTEXT - LFTVD.pptx
 
Model Call Girl in Tilak Nagar Delhi reach out to us at 🔝9953056974🔝
Model Call Girl in Tilak Nagar Delhi reach out to us at 🔝9953056974🔝Model Call Girl in Tilak Nagar Delhi reach out to us at 🔝9953056974🔝
Model Call Girl in Tilak Nagar Delhi reach out to us at 🔝9953056974🔝
 
Presentation by Andreas Schleicher Tackling the School Absenteeism Crisis 30 ...
Presentation by Andreas Schleicher Tackling the School Absenteeism Crisis 30 ...Presentation by Andreas Schleicher Tackling the School Absenteeism Crisis 30 ...
Presentation by Andreas Schleicher Tackling the School Absenteeism Crisis 30 ...
 
POINT- BIOCHEMISTRY SEM 2 ENZYMES UNIT 5.pptx
POINT- BIOCHEMISTRY SEM 2 ENZYMES UNIT 5.pptxPOINT- BIOCHEMISTRY SEM 2 ENZYMES UNIT 5.pptx
POINT- BIOCHEMISTRY SEM 2 ENZYMES UNIT 5.pptx
 
Staff of Color (SOC) Retention Efforts DDSD
Staff of Color (SOC) Retention Efforts DDSDStaff of Color (SOC) Retention Efforts DDSD
Staff of Color (SOC) Retention Efforts DDSD
 
Employee wellbeing at the workplace.pptx
Employee wellbeing at the workplace.pptxEmployee wellbeing at the workplace.pptx
Employee wellbeing at the workplace.pptx
 
The basics of sentences session 2pptx copy.pptx
The basics of sentences session 2pptx copy.pptxThe basics of sentences session 2pptx copy.pptx
The basics of sentences session 2pptx copy.pptx
 
TataKelola dan KamSiber Kecerdasan Buatan v022.pdf
TataKelola dan KamSiber Kecerdasan Buatan v022.pdfTataKelola dan KamSiber Kecerdasan Buatan v022.pdf
TataKelola dan KamSiber Kecerdasan Buatan v022.pdf
 
_Math 4-Q4 Week 5.pptx Steps in Collecting Data
_Math 4-Q4 Week 5.pptx Steps in Collecting Data_Math 4-Q4 Week 5.pptx Steps in Collecting Data
_Math 4-Q4 Week 5.pptx Steps in Collecting Data
 
Accessible design: Minimum effort, maximum impact
Accessible design: Minimum effort, maximum impactAccessible design: Minimum effort, maximum impact
Accessible design: Minimum effort, maximum impact
 
Código Creativo y Arte de Software | Unidad 1
Código Creativo y Arte de Software | Unidad 1Código Creativo y Arte de Software | Unidad 1
Código Creativo y Arte de Software | Unidad 1
 
Incoming and Outgoing Shipments in 1 STEP Using Odoo 17
Incoming and Outgoing Shipments in 1 STEP Using Odoo 17Incoming and Outgoing Shipments in 1 STEP Using Odoo 17
Incoming and Outgoing Shipments in 1 STEP Using Odoo 17
 
Organic Name Reactions for the students and aspirants of Chemistry12th.pptx
Organic Name Reactions  for the students and aspirants of Chemistry12th.pptxOrganic Name Reactions  for the students and aspirants of Chemistry12th.pptx
Organic Name Reactions for the students and aspirants of Chemistry12th.pptx
 
18-04-UA_REPORT_MEDIALITERAСY_INDEX-DM_23-1-final-eng.pdf
18-04-UA_REPORT_MEDIALITERAСY_INDEX-DM_23-1-final-eng.pdf18-04-UA_REPORT_MEDIALITERAСY_INDEX-DM_23-1-final-eng.pdf
18-04-UA_REPORT_MEDIALITERAСY_INDEX-DM_23-1-final-eng.pdf
 
How to Configure Email Server in Odoo 17
How to Configure Email Server in Odoo 17How to Configure Email Server in Odoo 17
How to Configure Email Server in Odoo 17
 
Hybridoma Technology ( Production , Purification , and Application )
Hybridoma Technology  ( Production , Purification , and Application  ) Hybridoma Technology  ( Production , Purification , and Application  )
Hybridoma Technology ( Production , Purification , and Application )
 
mini mental status format.docx
mini    mental       status     format.docxmini    mental       status     format.docx
mini mental status format.docx
 

HSC 312 Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubr.docx

  • 1. HSC 312: Final Project –Complied Case Analysis Scoring Rubric The following criteria will be used to grade your Complied Case Analysis. Keep in mind that the score requirement described under each score point on the scale defines the minimum performance that must be demonstrated in order to achieve that score. Evaluation Criteria A 20 points B 17 points C
  • 2. 15 points D 13 points F 11 points 1.) Introduces the case analysis by describing the ethical dilemma requiring resolution Introduction is: • Comprehensive • Includes a thorough, clear and
  • 3. concise description of the case and ethical dilemma proposed. Introduction: • Includes minor omissions in description of either the case or ethical dilemma. Introduction: • Lacks detail in part • Includes minor omissions in both the
  • 4. description of the case and the ethical dilemma. Introduction: • Lacks detail • Includes major omissions in either description of the case or the ethical dilemma. Description is either missing or contains major omissions throughout. 2.) Identifies the
  • 5. primary stakeholder (s) and provides a description of the situation from the stakeholder perspective Description is: • Comprehensive • Includes identification of stakeholder • Provides clear stakeholder Description:
  • 6. • Has minor omissions or errors in identification of stakeholders or in describing the stakeholder perspective. Description: • Lacks detail • Omits some significant content or contains several minor errors. Description:
  • 7. • Lacks detail. • Is superficial and contains multiple errors. Description is: • Missing or incorrect • Inconsistent with selected stakeholder identify any or identifies irrelevant stakeholders. 3.) Analyzes the scenario
  • 8. from the perspective of the primary stakeholder and includes a description of at least two ethical theories that relate to the issue being identified Analysis and Description are: • Comprehensive • Include responses to all
  • 9. subcomponents of the question. • Provides clear description of two or more ethical theories and their relation to the issue. Analysis and Description: • Include minor omissions. • Includes 1-2 minor errors in regards to the scenario of the stakeholder or the description
  • 10. of the ethical theories. Analysis and Description: • Include a major omission, OR • Includes several errors in regards to the scenario of the stakeholder or the description of the ethical theories. Analysis and Description: • Includes a major omission,
  • 11. AND • Includes several errors in regards to the scenario of the stakeholder or the description of the ethical theories. Analysis and Description are: • Missing OR • Response contains significant errors or omissions
  • 12. throughout the response. 4.) Provides a reasonable recommendat ion based upon the analysis presented Recommendation is: • Comprehensive. • Clear and logical • Summarizes key points. Recommendation has: • Minor omissions or
  • 13. errors • Is clear and logical • Summarizes most key points. Recommendation: • Omits some significant content and contains several minor errors • Is clear or logical but not both • Summarizes minimal points. Recommendation:
  • 14. • Is superficial and contains multiple errors • Is not clear or logical • Summarizes 1- 2 points. Recommendation is: • Missing or incorrect. 5.) Format Format is: • Clear and consistent. • contains accurate and proper
  • 15. grammatical conventions, spelling, formatting, and referencing. • Follows specific instructions. Format is: • Clear and mostly consistent. • Contains few errors of accuracy • Follows specific instructions with minor
  • 16. omissions. Format is: • Clear but not concise. • Contains multiple errors of accuracy. • Follows specific instructions with multiple omissions. Format is: • Not clear or concise. • Contains serious errors. • Specific
  • 17. instructions are barely followed. Format: • Is not clear. • Does not follow specific instructions. Final Project – Compiled Case Studies Jane Doe HSC312 May 2013 Professor X
  • 18. HSC312 - Final Project: Compiled Case Studies May 2013 Jane Doe Case Analysis: Sally & the DNR Case Analysis Template for use with each of the four scenarios in the final project: 1. Copy/paste the title of the question 2. Describe the most relevant ethical dilemma(s) presented (no more than two). 3. Briefly describe the primary issue or issues that are relevant in the scenario w/respect to the dilemma. 4. Identify the most relevant stakeholder(s) (no more than 3) and briefly describe the situation from their perspective. 5. Analyze the dilemma, using scholarly discussion, from the perspective of the primary stakeholder (typically the patient). Include a discussion of at least two ethical theories or bioethics principles studied in the course that relate to the
  • 19. dilemma and issues you identified. Include any relevant legal concerns or requirements outlined in the readings. 6. Present your assessment, resolution or potential solutions for resolving the issue. Remember that there are no right answers, per se, so reflective questions can be as appropriate as a firm conclusion. 7. Title page + APA formatted reference(s) The following example provides further insight into what is required for each element of the template. Although the response is intentionally somewhat longer than what is expected, it should help clarify the specific requirements. 1. Ethical Dilemma Prompt objective: Identify the ethical dilemma and state the dilemma as a “should” question. Note: there may be several relevant dilemmas that could be addressed; use the prompt question as a guide to an issue to analyze. The objective is to present a cogent analysis of a relevant issue. ISSUE: Should the attending physician sign a DNR without
  • 20. Sally’s consent? 2. Primary issues related to the identified dilemma Prompt objective: Identify the relevant issues related to your dilemma. You should identify at least two, but limit your selection of issues to a manageable number within the scope of the assignment. Informed consent; Surrogate decision making & substituted judgment; healthcare decision making capacity; autonomy and the right to refuse treatment 3. Primary Stakeholders & Stakeholder positions: Question objective: Identify 2-3 primary stakeholders including the patient, and briefly describe their position: Sally: 62 yr old woman with Stage IV breast cancer that is unresponsive to standard and experimental treatment presents with shortness of breath requiring a Thorentisis, a difficult procedure given her condition. Sally wants to live and refuses
  • 21. to discuss the terminal nature of her condition. HSC312 - Final Project: Compiled Case Studies May 2013 Jane Doe Sally’s husband: Sally’s husband recognizes that Sally is dying and wants everything done for Sally to make her comfortable. He agrees with the attending physician that CPR would make Sally less, rather than more comfortable. He is Sally’s surrogate decision maker. The attending physician: Believes that further testing and treatment for Sally is futile. He questions whether Sally has the capacity to understand her condition and consent to the DNR. 4. Potential Solution Analysis:
  • 22. Prompt objective: Analyze the ethical dilemma from the perspective of the primary stakeholder (typically the patient), using the ethical theories and/or the bioethics principles that relate to the dilemma. Keep your analysis focused on at least two or three moral theories or bioethics principles, but do not attempt to address them all. There will generally be more issues and principles/theories that would apply than you can cover in a short analysis. Include in your discussion any known legal issues presented by the readings that may influence a decision. Apply the facts to the theories discussed. Keep in mind that there may be several issues and theories to discuss, but you are not required to find or address them all. The essay below is purposefully more involved than the assignment requires providing a few
  • 23. examples of an ethical analysis. Under the ethical and legal doctrine of informed consent provided by the Patient Self- Determination Act, an adult patient with healthcare decision- making capacity has the right to make an informed, autonomous choice to accept or reject medical treatment. (Munson, 2012). The right to self-determination is defined by the bioethics principle of Autonomy and refers to the patient’s right to make a voluntary choice that is meaningful to them and free from external or personal influences. (Tong, 2007). Such influences may include fear, denial, medication side effects, pain and guilt, among others. Healthcare decision-making capacity requires that the patient can articulate and understand
  • 24. the nature of their condition and the risks, benefits and consequences of accepting or rejecting treatment. Assessing decision- making capacity requires an evaluation of the patient’s decision-making process, rather than an evaluation of the choice itself. “…[T]he mere fact that a patient does not accept a health care professional’s recommendation does not necessarily mean that the patient is incompetent" (Tong, 2007, p 53). In order for a patient to evaluate the risks and benefits of an available option is the understanding that a physician will provide complete and honest disclosure of all the associated medical facts that may be pertinent to the patient (Canterbury vs. Spence, 1979). The need for such veracity in
  • 25. caring for a patient is also a primary component of a physician’s ethical responsibility, according to the American Medical Association (AMA, 2012). Performing a procedure without consent, or withholding a viable treatment without disclosure, is a direct violation of the AMA mandate, Informed Consent doctrine and a patient’s trust. A patient’s right to self-determination is foundational in bioethics. If the patient loses decision- making capacity, laws and policies are in place to ensure that the patients’ expressed or implied wishes are respected. Prior to losing capacity, a patient can appoint a healthcare proxy agent who will make decisions for the patient, based upon the patient’s wishes and instructions. Critical to
  • 26. the concept of a Health Care agent is the agent’s requirement that any decisions reflect the patients’ known and implied wishes, rather than the agent’s own wishes for the patient. If no HSC312 - Final Project: Compiled Case Studies May 2013 Jane Doe such agent is named, a surrogate decision maker is appointed by state statute or facility policy to make decisions for the patient, using their knowledge of the patient and the patient’s wishes, values and spiritual beliefs. Sally appears to be in denial about her condition and terribly afraid of death, as evidenced by her general state of “panic” and her refusal to talk to the Resident
  • 27. about her condition. Most importantly, Sally has stated that she wants to live, which may reflect any number of thoughts and emotions from a sense of grief at her circumstances to denial of her terminal condition. Because the physicians seem more focused on discussing their inability to help Sally, rather than being ‘competent’ in her mind to perform the thorientsis, Sally may not see a value in discussing her condition with them. Far from an irrational thought process, Sally’s refusal to talk may actually be a heartbreaking testament to her ability to assess a situation and reach a rational conclusion based on the facts. Further proof may be Sally’s insistence that she “…wanted the emergency squad called to attempt resuscitation if she arrested at home” (Crigger, 1998). Given
  • 28. her desire to live as long as possible, it would make sense that she would want every chance available to live. Presuming Sally does have capacity, she is entitled to receive full disclosure regarding anything to do with her medical care—a right that extends to her rejection of a proposal that is in conflict with her own goals. Consequently, if the attending physician institutes a DNR order without Sally’s consent would constitute a violation of Sally’s right to self-determination. Important in the discussion of full disclosure in Sally’s case is the fact that it no one has explained the potential adverse consequences of performing CPR (Cardio- pulmonary resuscitation) on
  • 29. someone in her current medical condition. From the facts presented, it is unclear how Sally would respond if she knew there was a significant chance that if she survived CPR, she could end up in a Permanent Vegetative State, permanently unconscious and kept alive by artificial life support as a result. The physician’s position that CPR is futile given the potential for harm and what he perceives as negligible benefit, does not override Sally’s right to define what is and is not beneficial for her. Acting on his own subjective values and interpretations, and ignoring Sally’s values and desires would constitute an act of Paternalism, a direct violation of autonomy (Tong, 2007). While it is true that a patient cannot demand an inappropriate treatment—
  • 30. one that would produce more harm than benefit— it could be argued that CPR as a standard emergency procedure to ward off imminent death does not pass the “inappropriateness” test. If a patient with capacity is provided with full disclosure of the potential harms, it is the patient’s right to weigh the risks and benefits, and make an informed choice. (Munson, 2012). Similarly, if it is determined, that Sally lacks capacity; the doctor would still be potentially outside his authority to institute the DNR without informing Sally’s surrogate decision maker. While it is unclear whether Sally’s husband is her Healthcare proxy agent, as a person who knows her best and her spouse, he would still have the presumptive right to use substituted
  • 31. judgment and make the decision he believes Sally would make, if she could. Knowing Sally’s express position on the issue of aggressive treatment, he has an obligation as the healthcare agent to reject the DNR, regardless of his personal opinion and desire that Sally just receive comfort care. HSC312 - Final Project: Compiled Case Studies May 2013 Jane Doe In addition to the ethical principle of Autonomy and the doctrine of informed consent, Care- based Ethics also supports Sally’s right to reject the DNR. Care- based Ethics emphasizes values and virtues such as compassion, empathy, kindness and most
  • 32. important, sensitivity to each patient’s unique perspective and circumstances (Tong, 2007). Because Sally is adamant she wants everything done right now to help keep her alive as long as possible, a physician empathetic to Sally’s concerns and circumstances would not sign the DNR without at least informing her and addressing her fears about death and her desire to preserve her life. 5. Recommedation: Prompt objective: Present your assessment, resolution or potential solutions for resolving the issue. Remember that there are no right answers, per se, so reflective questions can be as appropriate as a firm conclusion.
  • 33. Based on my analysis, the attending physician should not institute the DNR against Sally’s express wishes and without her knowledge. Doing so would violate the ethical and legal principles of autonomy and informed consent. I also recommend that Sally be seen by a Palliative Care specialist or a medical professional trained in end-of-life care to help determine whether Sally’s statements and behaviors demonstrate a lack of capacity, or are understandably motivated by denial and fear. Minimally, the consult should help promote Sally’s overall well- being by addressing her concerns in a compassionate and caring way. Lastly, only if Sally lacks capacity should Sally’s husband, as her healthcare agent, be allowed to speak for Sally and
  • 34. refuse the DNR. Because we do not know how Sally feels about remaining on life support should CPR fail, Sally’s husband must adhere to the doctrine of substituted judgement and base a decision upon his knowledge of Sally’s values and wishes, including her known spiritual beliefs. Bibliography 4 H A S T I N G S C E N T E R R E P O R T January- February 2012 To the Editor:The traditional “in- formed consent” process for medical treatment is badly broken. As patients face fateful medical decisions, they of- tendonotknowthebasic“gist”oftheir optionsorthelikelihoodofthepossible
  • 35. outcomes, good and bad. The shared decision-makingmovementaimstoim- provethatsorrysituationbyhavingpa- tients and clinicians work more closely together when there is more than one reasonablemedicaloption,asisthecase formanyifnotmostsituations.Byen- suring both that patients are informed about their choices and that clinicians areinformedaboutpatientpreferences, thequalityofmedicaldecisionsshould be improved. Patient decision aids are notthemselvesshareddecision-making; instead, they are tools to help make shareddecision-makingpracticalinthe busyworldofclinicalmedicine. Inhisprovocativearticle(“Question- ing the Quantitative Imperative: Deci- sionAids,Prevention,andtheEthicsof Disclosure,” March-April 2011), Peter Schwartz seems to acknowledge the need to improve the current informed consent process but worries that pro- viding quantitative information about
  • 36. possible outcomes as part of a shared decision-makingprocessmightbemis- leadingtoorunwantedbypatients.He proposesthe“default”optionshouldbe to withhold this quantitative informa- tion unless and until a patient asks for it.Hisprimaryargumentsarethatmany patientshavepoornumeracyskillsand might not understand—or might even be misled by—the quantitative facts, andthatoutcomeshavenotbeenshown tobebetterasaresultofprovidingpa- tientswithquantitativeinformation. Problemswithstatisticalnumeracy— which have been shown to be an issue for clinicians, too—do make it more challenging to communicate risks and benefits. However, just because a task is difficult doesn’t mean it shouldn’t be done.MostpeopleintheUnitedStates don’twanttoplayapassiveroleintheir health care, and the proportion isn’t conditioned by assessed numeracy (M.
  • 37. Galesic and R. Garcia-Retamero, “Do Low-Numeracy People Avoid Shared DecisionMaking?”Health Psychology30 [2011]:336-41).Moreover,asnotedin PeterUbel’scompanioneditorial(“The Experimental Imperative”), research on the communication of quantitative healthinformationisrevealingthatnew strategies and technologies can help overcome these barriers. For example, visualaids,commonlyusedindecision aids,canhelpevenpeoplewithfewnu- meracy skills better understand health statistics (R. Garcia-Retamero and M. Galesic,“WhoProfitsfromVisualAids? Overcoming Challenges in People’s UnderstandingofRisks,”Social Science Medicine 70 [2010]: 1019-25). Many oftheinterventionsforwhichinformed consentisnecessaryinhealthcare,such as open-heart surgery and organ trans- plantation, had to overcome numerous barrierstoenterthemedicalarmamen- tarium. It’s time to bring a similar in-
  • 38. tensityofefforttoovercomethebarriers of literacy and numeracy in communi- catingimportanthealthinformationto thepeoplewhomustlivewiththecon- sequencesoftheirhealthdecisions. Holding informed consent to an outcome standard is an interesting ar- gument. Schwartz acknowledges that decision aids that present quantitative outcomeprobabilitieshavebeenshown to give patients more accurate percep- tionsoftheirhealthrisks.Isputtingthe “informed” in informed consent not an important goal in itself? Would the ethicalandlegalimperativeofinformed consent hold up under scrutiny in a trialwherepatientsfacingsurgerywere randomized to an informed consent process versus none? Would the whole notionofinformedconsentbescrapped iffunctionalstatusscoreswerenodiffer- entinasecondtrial?Ithinknot. Thekeyissuehereiswhetherthede-
  • 39. faultoptionininformedconsentshould be withholding quantitative informa- tionunlesspatientsaskforitorprovid- ingitunlesstheysaytheydon’twantit. For too long, the medical system has kept patients largely in the dark about whatclinicianshaveplannedforthem. Given this history, perhaps it’s time to make giving more information—in- cluding quantitative information—the default position, and to work much harderatdoingitwell. Michael J. Barry TheFoundationforInformed MedicalDecisionMaking To the Editor: Every day people tell me about the challenges they face in finding safe, decent health care and making the most of it. Facing tough letters
  • 40. TooMuchInformation? It’s time to overcome the barriers of literacy and numeracy in communicating important health information to the people who must live with the consequences of their health decisions. DOI:10.1002/HAST.4 January-February 2012 H A S T I N G S C E N T E R R E P O R T 5 oN tHe WeB nBioethicsforum http://www.bioethicsforum.org AdministrationRevealsLackofCLASS By Peter S. Arno, Michael K. Gusmano, and Deborah Viola
  • 41. Just as the baby boomers are entering retirement, the first real step toward a national long-term care policy in forty-five years has been cast asunder. WhatisHumane?APleaforPlain LanguageintheDebatesonAnimal Experimentation By Joel Marks “Humane” is implicitly defined as meeting accepted standards of care and use according to legal and institutional guidelines. What this means in practice is that anything can be done to a laboratory animal, provided it is necessary to carry out an experiment or other procedure that a committee has deemed worthy on scientific and perhaps humanitarian grounds. I submit that this is an illegitimate use of the term “humane.” Also:michaelK.Gusmanopointsout misinformationaboutU.S.poverty; CarolLevinesuggeststhatwe’dallbetter startsavingnowforourbabies’future
  • 42. long-termcare;franklinG.millerand robertd.truogexploreuncertain- tiespromptedbythelatestresearch onpatientsinthevegetativestate;and CameronWaldmanvisitsZuccottiPark totalkwithcliniciansoccupyingWall Street. nthehealthCareCostmonitor http://healthcarecostmonitor. thehastingscenter.org GlobalCompetitiveness:HowOther CountriesWin By Daniel Callahan and Elizabeth H. Bradley Nearly every country that leads the world in international economic competitive- ness also has a strong government-run or regulated universal health care system and a comprehensive welfare policy. The one exception is the United States. decisions about treatments and tests withlittleornoobjectiveinformation
  • 43. toguidethemoftentopstheirlistofdif- ficulties.Ihavefrequentlyexperienced thismyselfasIrecoverfromtreatment ofmyfourthcancerdiagnosis. I appreciate Peter Schwartz’s recog- nitionoftheburdenplacedonpatients andlovedonestoincorporatecomplex risk information into decisions about our care. And I welcome any con- cern—however tangential—about the shiftofresponsibilitiesfromclinicians to patients, who are often ill-prepared tofulfillthem.However,Ifindhisar- gumentoverlyprotectiveinlightofthe rushed, confusing demands of health care today, increased public access to health information, and the shared decision-making policies imbedded in theAffordableCareAct. Schwartzdescribesthegeneralinnu- meracyoftheAmericanpublicwitha particularemphasisonourinabilityto understandthedifferencebetweenrel-
  • 44. ativeandabsoluterisk.Yetheneglects to mention that we share this deficit with many of our clinicians. He also summarizestheliteratureoncognitive heuristicsbutagainexemptsclinicians from discussion. Does he believe that cliniciansareimmunefromthesesame biases? My doctor might withhold a decision aid because she doesn’t have timeforthiscumbersomeshareddeci- sion-making nonsense or she believes sheknowswhatIshoulddotorealize thebestoutcome.Shewouldvieweach oftheseasrationalchoices. More puzzling is the importance Schwartz assigns to risk information indecisionswemakeaboutourhealth care, preference-sensitive or not. Em- piricalinformationisalways only oneof manyfactorsthatinfluenceourchoic- es. Scant relevant risk information is available for most of the health care decisionswemakenow.Wejustwing it, based on anxiety, our neighbor’s
  • 45. experience, and our sense of what the rightchoiceistoday,whichcanbein- fluencedbyourdoctor’smoodaseasily asitcanbyfamilyandworkevents. It is thus oddly shortsighted for Schwartz to recommend withholding decision aids for some patients (based on the clinician’s assessment of our competence) in the relatively few in- stances where these aids are available forpreference-sensitivecare,astheyare for decisions about early-stage breast cancertreatmentorgettingaprostate- specific antigen test. Even if we don’t fully understand what’s at stake, well- presented risk information powerfully communicates that we have choices: that multiple treatment options are possible,thattherearetrade-offstobe considered,andthatnoguaranteesex- ist,regardlessofourchoice.Theseare sobering but important messages for ustograspaswe,regardlessofournu-
  • 46. meracy skills and cognitive biases, are routinely forced to make critical deci- sionsaboutourhealthcare. It’s too late to argue that our clini- cians should selectively provide de- cision aids: the ACA provisions for shared decision-making will likely eventuallytieclinicianreimbursement toprovidingthem.Andtheimpetusfor thatargument—thatprovidingthisin- formationimposesmandatoryautono- my—isakintodiscussingthebenefits ofclosingthebarndoorafterthecows havewanderedaway:Ourautonomyis alreadymandatedbydefault. Jessie Gruman CenterforAdvancingHealth To the Editor: In his article, Peter Schwartzeloquentlydiscussestheben- efits and potential harms of providing patients with numeric risk informa- tion. He describes how—despite our
  • 47. best efforts to inform patients about therisksandbenefitsofscreeningtests and preventive treatments and to im- prove understanding of probability— people “have persistently irrational responses to quantitative information aboutrisksandbenefits,”regardlessof their level of numeracy. For decades, 6 H A S T I N G S C E N T E R R E P O R T January- February 2012 decision scientists, economists, and psychologists have struggled to under- standwhyeventhemostknowledgeable andnumeratepeoplemakesuboptimal healthdecisions. It seems that in our attempts to educate patients about probability, we sometimes fail to appreciate that un- derstanding numeric facts and figures is not an exclusively cognitive effort;
  • 48. rather, it is often heavily influenced by affect, which in turn influences one’s abilitytoreason.Awell-knownexperi- ment conducted in 1994 by Veronika Denes-Raj and Seymour Epstein illus- trates how affect can trump rational- ity, even for well-educated people. In it,subjectswoniftheydrewaredjelly beanfromoneoftwobowls.Thesmall bowlcontainedoneredandninewhite beans,andthelargebowlcontainedfive totenredbeansandatotalofonehun- dred beans in all. Despite the fact that eachbowlwaslabeledwiththepercent of red beans it contained, the majority of subjects drew a bean from the large bowl, which was clearly the inferior choice.Subjectsreportedthatthey“felt” theyhadabetterchanceofwinningby selectingthebowlwiththegreaterabso- lutenumberof“winning”beans. Theinteractionofaffectandnumer- acy in health decisions has been dem- onstrated in several studies examining
  • 49. choices of medical treatments that in- cludepotentialsideeffects.Inone2006 studyconductedbyJenniferAmsterlaw and colleagues, people were presented with two surgical scenarios: one had a 20percentmortalityrate,andtheother had a 16 percent mortality rate along witha1percentchanceoffourunpleas- ant side effects (colostomy, chronic di- arrhea, intermittent bowel obstruction, orwoundinfection).Mostpeoplechose thesurgicaloptionwiththehighermor- tality,presumablybecauseoftheiraffec- tiveresponsetothesideeffectsandtheir tendencytooverweightlowprobability events. Indeed, the mere presence of a small side effect may decrease willing- ness to undergo treatment, even if the treatment offers substantial benefit. Erika Waters and colleagues found in 2007 that side-effect aversion occurred regardless of how probability was pre- sentedorwhethergraphicformatswere used to convey risk information, sug-
  • 50. gestingthatdecisionswereguidedbyan affective response to the possibility of sideeffects,ratherthanbynumericrisk. There are, of course, potential dan- gers associated with providing patients with too much quantitative informa- tion.Inthiseraofshareddecision-mak- ingandunprecedentedaccesstohealth information, it is easy to experience dataoverload.Providingpeoplewithall available information can actually hin- derdecision-making,andoften,lessnu- mericinformationismorewhenhelping people make quality health decisions. Amongthepotentialdangersofprovid- ing too much information is that pa- tientsmaynotbeabletodiscernuseful informationfromthemerelyrelevantor altogetherirrelevant.However,thereare also potential dangers associated with providingtoolittleinformation.AsAn- thonyBastardiandEldarShafirdemon- stratedin1998,whenpeoplearefaced
  • 51. with a preference-sensitive decision, they often seek additional information regardless of whether that information iscriticaltotheirdecision.Inaseriesof experiments,theyobservedthatpeople whopursuedmissinginformationtend- ed to endow it with greater value than theywouldhaveifithadbeenavailable initially. Somehow the act of pursuing a missing but nonessential piece of in- formation lent greater psychological weight and salience to it. In a health context, such misguided information- seekingmightleadpatientstobaseim- portanthealthdecisionsonfactorsthat may be relevant but nonessential to an effective decision. Clearly, more work is needed to understand the possible unintended consequences of providing toomuchortoolittleriskinformation. Attheveryleast,providersshouldkeep in mind how affect can be attached to numbersandrisksareperceived.
  • 52. Wendy Nelson NationalCancerInstitute To the Editor:Thereisagreatdeal of merit in Peter Schwartz’s important andusefularticle,anditwilldoubtless prompt considerable debate. I would liketoaddtwobriefcomments. First, Schwartz’s target—the quan- titative imperative—can be viewed as a specific instance of a broader target. In Rethinking Informed Consent (Cam- bridge University Press, 2007), Onora O’Neill and I, like Schwartz, were struckbytheconsiderableevidencethat patients and research subjects often do not comprehend what is disclosed. As a result, “informed consent” is often considered obtained even when, rela- tive to contemporary standards, it is substandardorinvalid.Toimprovethis situation, we argued—amongst other things—thatweneedtobeclearabout
  • 53. the distinction between consent and informed consent. The former is a fa- miliar form of action that involves the settingasideofrightsortheremovalof certain kinds of prohibitions. Consent isofconsiderable,butnotfoundational, ethical importance for clinical actions. Whilethosewhoconsentneedtoknow something of the action to which they consent,itdoesnotrequire“disclosure” of large amounts of information about proposed actions or risks. Informed consent, in contrast, has its roots in negligence law in the clinical context andsharesbiomedicalethics’particular The quantitative imperative is simply part of an unjustified informative imperative that places unfeasible demands upon those consenting. January-February 2012 H A S T I N G S C E N T E R R E P O
  • 54. R T 7 focus on the importance of individual decision-making. We argued that bio- medical ethics has, without sufficient justification,takeninformedconsentto be of key ethical importance. Matters are made worse by the prevalence of a widerangeofmetaphorsthatshapeour thinkingaboutknowledgeandcommu- nication,suchthatinformationisread- ilycastasatypeof“stuff ”tobepassed on,stored,disclosed,orpickedup. Putting these elements together and aligning with Schwartz’s terminology, there is a ubiquitous informative im- perative that pervades biomedical eth- ics. This informative imperative rests uponarangeofdistortionsandconfu- sions. Once the ethical arguments are clarified, the informative imperative canbeseenasmuchlessdemandingin its scope than is typically assumed.We would thus agree with Schwartz’s con-
  • 55. clusion—that quantitative information ofcertainkindsneednotbedisclosed— but for a different set of reasons. The quantitativeimperative,onourview,is simplyapartofawidespreadbutunjus- tifiedinformativeimperativethatistoo broadinitsscopeandplacesunfeasible demandsuponthoseconsenting. Second, it is important to note that there may be reasons other than en- suring validity of consent for disclos- ing quantitative information. Given the legal context of informed consent, Schwartz’s proposals might raise wor- riesforclinicians.Supposeinformation aboutcertainrisksismerelymadeavail- able, rather than being communicated (andacknowledgedassuchby,say,sign- ingaconsentform).Supposethatoneof therisksnotcommunicated,butmade available,happens.Thepatientsueson thebasisthathadshebeeninformedof therisk,shewouldnothaveconsented. Thequantitativeimperativecanthusbe
  • 56. seenasaprecautionarystrategyforcli- niciansandtheirinstitutions. Schwartzfocusesontherolethatin- formationplays,orispurportedtoplay, inenablingpatientdecision-making.In arecentpaperintheJournal of Medical Ethics (“Why Do Patients Want Infor- mation If Not to Take Part in Deci- sion Making?”), I focus on the (good) reasons that patients have for wanting information other than for decision- making purposes. Patients want infor- mation because they expect it, because it allows them to establish trustworthi- ness and credibility with their doctor, and because the very process of com- municatinginformationcanbeasignal of respect and faith in a patient’s com- petence. So even if we agree that the quantitative imperative lacks firm ethi- cal support, we might still believe that suchinformationshouldbedisclosed.
  • 57. Neil C. Manson LancasterUniversity Peter Schwartz replies: I must correct Jessie Gruman’s sug- gestion that my article supports with- holdingdecisionaidsorquestionstheir importance. Like Michael Barry and Gruman, I agree that patients often want or need more information than theyreceive,andIbelievethatdecision aidscanhelpaddressthisproblemand will most likely play a growing role in medicine. But the question is whether decision aids can best help patients by always providing quantitative infor- mation—in particular, complex data framedinmultipleways,astheInterna- tional Patient Decision Aids Standards andmanyexpertsrecommend. Research has not established that such disclosure improves patients’ un- derstanding or decision-making in the
  • 58. range of situations where decision aids mightbeused.Therearemanypossible negative impacts, mostly stemming frominnumeracyandheuristicsandbi- asesinhumanthought,asdescribedin myarticleandintheexcellentaddition- alexamplesprovidedbyWendyNelson inherletter.Givenallthis,Iarguethat the quantitative imperative must be subjectedtomorecarefultesting,inthe spiritofevidence-basedmedicine. Barry’sletterandPeterUbel’seditori- althataccompaniedthearticlesupport research to investigate innovative ways to provide quantitative information to inform patients, including innumer- ateones,withoutcreatingconfusionor engendering irrational responses. Such researchiscertainlyimportant,butmy article emphasizes that the question is not just how to present certain types of data, but whether to present data at all, and in what situations. Researchers
  • 59. shouldnotassumethatallrelevantdata shouldbegivenallthetime:itmayturn out that in at least some cases, less is more (for example, see B.J. Zikmund- Fisher, A. Fagerlin, and P.A. Ubel, “A Demonstration of ‘Less Can Be More’ in Risk Graphics,” Medical Decision Making30[2010]:661-71). My article is thus a call to keep an open mind as research goes forward. It aimstoplayarolethattheoreticalethi- cal and philosophical analysis should play:identifyingandcritiquingassump- tions that guide behavior or research in unrecognized or unexamined ways. The assumption that all quantitative information should be provided all the timeisexactlythatsortofphilosophical commitment. I agree with Gruman that patients too often cannot get information they want, but I believe that decisions aids maybestaddressthatproblembymak-
  • 60. ing the information available to those who want it, rather than presenting it to everybody. She raises the excel- lent question of how to choose who will receive additional data, and she is right, of course, to reject the idea that thedecisionshouldbebasedsimplyon a clinician’s impression of the patient’s competence. But what about a system where pa- tientsareofferedadditionalinformation Letterstotheeditormaybesentbye-mail to [email protected], or to Managing Editor, Hastings Center Report, 21MalcolmGordonRoad,Garrison,NY 10524; (845) 424-4931 fax. Letters ap- pearing in the Report may be edited for lengthandstylisticconsistency. 8 H A S T I N G S C E N T E R R E P O R T January- February 2012
  • 61. of various sorts? This idea is far from radical: recommendations for discus- sionsbetweenhealthcareprovidersand patients suggest that some information shouldbegiveninitially,andadditional informationshouldbeofferedasanop- tiontothosewhowantit(see,forexam- ple,R.M.Epstein,B.S.Alper,andT.E. Quill, “Communicating Evidence for Participatory Decision Making,” Jour- nal of the American Medical Association 291 [2004]: 2359-66). The amazing capabilitiesofcomputer-baseddecision aidsmaytemptdesignerstoprovidetoo muchinformationupfront,andtofor- getthewisdomoftailoringdisclosureto thepatient’sinterestandunderstanding. I agree with Neil Manson that the quantitative imperative is part of a larger “informative imperative” in medicine that should be questioned and challenged as Manson, O’Neill, Carl Schneider, and others have done.
  • 62. Considering how to provide the right information,totherightpatients,atthe right time, by way of a decision aid or personal interaction, raises important ethical and empirical questions, as the articleemphasizes. Doctors and Torture To the Editor:In“TheTorturedPa- tient: A Medical Dilemma” (May-June 2011), Chiara Lepora and Joseph Mil- lum raise the issue of whether a physi- cian may be justifiably complicit in torture and answer in the affirmative. Their argument is predicated on there being a litany of moral considerations, of which the wrongness of complicity in torture is merely one; this wrong- ness competes against other values and sometimes is outweighed. While I disagree with some of the authors’ as- sumptions—for instance, that torture is always unethical in the cases that physicians are forced to countenance,
  • 63. orthatcomplicityinanimmoralactis primafacieimmoral—Iagreewiththeir conclusion. Surely those who trumpet deontological constraints would think otherwise,butthisconclusionnaturally follows from a pluralistic set of moral values. Whiletheyciteawiderangeofdec- lamations against physicians’ involve- mentintorture,onethattheyleaveout comesfromsection2.067oftheAmeri- canMedicalAssociation’sCode of Medi- cal Ethics. What makes section 2.067 interesting is not just what it says, but alsothefactthatitcomeshierarchically nestedundersection2.06,whichspeaks tophysicianinvolvementincapitalpun- ishment. From the Code’s perspective, the issues pertaining to capital punish- mentandtortureareisomorphic:what mattersismerelythatphysicianinvolve- mentcouldmakethepatientworseoff. In the case of capital punishment, the
  • 64. upshotisobviousand,inthecaseoftor- ture, resuscitation in order to facilitate moretortureissimilarlydepraved. This argument fails in both cases, andthereasonhelpselucidatewhyLe- poraandMillumareontherighttrack. Thequestiontoaskislesswhatwould happen if physicians were present, but rather what would happen if they were not. For example, imagine that physicians were disallowed from these settingsandaprospectivepatientexpe- rienced complications: the abolitionist would just settle for this person being worseoff.Aphysician’spresenceensures thateasilyremediablesituationsberem- edied, which is precisely what I would advocate.Thisisnottosaythatthereare nocapacitiesinwhichphysicianscould make people worse off, just that there are some in which those people could be made better off; therefore, a whole- saleabolitiononphysicianparticipation misses the mark. (There’s also an open
  • 65. question about whether such agents should be conceived of as “physicians” atall—asopposedtomedicallytrained militarypersonnel—butIshallnotpur- suethatdiscussionhere.) Tobesure,thoseopposingphysician involvement in either capital punish- mentortortureare,almostalways,not just opposing physician involvement, but rather those practices themselves. When the Code says that physicians must “oppose . . . torture for any rea- son,” it is clearly making a political claim and not one narrowly tied to medicalethics;itisforpreciselythisrea- son that I find such statements by the Codetobeinappropriate.AsLeporaand Millum acknowledge, some debate the appropriateness of torture in “narrowly specified, extreme cases.” It is a credit to their essay that such a debate is left open,ratherthanforeclosedbyfiat.
  • 66. Fromtheperspectiveofmedicaleth- ics,thecentralquestioniswhetherphy- sicianinvolvementintorturemakesthe patientbetterorworseoff.Fromamore thoroughgoingconsequentialismofthe sort that I would advocate, this ques- tion bears no privileged status. While Lepora and Millum would surely not agreewithallofmyarguments,theyare tobecommendedforeschewingdogma andreachingacontroversialconclusion. More generally, one would also hope that their paper portends increased at- tention to military medical ethics; this is an important area within medical ethics,andonethathasreceivedinsuf- ficientattention. Fritz Allhoff WesternMichiganUniversity The question to ask is less what would happen if physicians were present, but rather what would
  • 67. happen if they were not. Copyright of Hastings Center Report is the property of Wiley- Blackwell and its content may not be copied or emailed to multiple sites or posted to a listserv without the copyright holder's express written permission. However, users may print, download, or email articles for individual use. 10/27/2016 Final Case Analysis: The Emilly Dilemma - Abortion https://mycourses.excelsior.edu/bbcswebdav/pid-3200850-dt-co ntent-rid-31405097_1/courses/BHS.HSC312.Online.201610.201 612.s30047605/course%20wide… 1/3
  • 68. Final Case Analysis: The Emily Dilemma - Abortion Introduction to the Activity Recall, that an ethical dilemma can be defined as two morally a cceptable choices, both of which will result in morally disturbing and unwelcome conseque nces. Often when we considering our position regarding an ethical dilemma, it is help ful to consider not only the issue presented, but whether we can justify our position based o n an extreme, yet realistic set of conditions. Abortion is perhaps one of the most disturbing and confounding of issues for engaging in such an exercise, as it is sometimes difficult to j ustify the inconsistencies in our moral intuitions when confronted with situations that define an ethical dilemma. Related Reading from Module 7: Module notes and assigned textbook pages Videos: Ankele, J. (Producer), & Macsoud, A. (Producer) (2010). Beyon
  • 69. d the politics of life and choice: A new conversation about abortion (link availab le in Mod 7) Tsiaras, A. (Director) (2011, November 14). Alexander Tsiaras: Conception to birth -- visualized TedTalks. [Video file][9 min 37 sec]. Retriev ed from http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=fKyljukBE70 (apprx. 10min) Iadarola , J. (Performer) (2012, November 25). Study: What hap pens to women denied abortions? [Video file][5 min 17 sec] The Young Turks. Retrieved from http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=dWBjQ7P9SSs (apprx. 5 min ) Instructions to Learners Please read the case scenario: Twenty year old Emily who suffers from Bi-polar disorder and Schizophrenia lives at home with her parents, but is fairly independent. Last year, Emily had a breakdown while living away at school and required hospitalization. Due to a complex mix of anti-psychotics,
  • 70. antidepressants and other medications to control her condition, Emily is now working part- time at a local bookstore and taking two classes at the communit y college. Emily loves children and hopes eventually to become a kindergarten teacher. Although Emily is on birth control pills, she had missed some days over the past few months during a brief ‘lapse’ in her mood, but insisted throughout that time that her b oyfriend wear a condom. The condom failed at some point and Emily is now eight weeks' pregnant. http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=fKyljukBE70 http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=dWBjQ7P9SSs 10/27/2016 Final Case Analysis: The Emilly Dilemma - Abortion https://mycourses.excelsior.edu/bbcswebdav/pid-3200850-dt-co ntent-rid-31405097_1/courses/BHS.HSC312.Online.201610.201 612.s30047605/course%20wide… 2/3 Emily’s doctors insist that the baby is at an exceptionally high r
  • 71. isk for severe physical and mental impairments, including incomplete limb and/or brain dev elopment. At best, there is no solid data detailing teratogenicity risk for all of her medicati ons, but the combinations and inability to incorporate less harmful substitutes raise signifi cant concern. Because she is within the first trimester, there are no legal concerns based on the Roe v. Wade decision so the doctors, her parents and her boyfriend are insisting that E mily have an abortion to spare the burden on the child. Emily, a devote Catholic, insists on carrying the baby and raising it once it is born. She has also personalized the argumen ts, finding that by devaluing the life of her baby, her family and others devalue her as well. Emily’s parents have threatened to file for guardianship over he r so that they can force the abortion, under their belief that she lacks decision-making capa city and the abortion is in her best interests. Although the doctors have no standing to join the suit, they have agreed to serve as expert witnesses for the parents. Emily’s boyfriend i s considering petitioning
  • 72. the court--after the baby is born--for the right to be released fro m any parental responsibilities, given his lack of a position in the decision to a bort. Emily’s Psychiatrist, Dr. Heady is very troubled by the case bot h for Emily and for the developing fetus. Knowing that you are a famous ethicist, he co ntacts you informally and presents the case as a hypothetical, maintaining Emily’s confide ntiality. Dr. Heady is unsure whether the parents can legally force the abortion, but he is troubled on a much more fundamental level, which is why he is seeking your counse l. Please respond to the following questions (approx. 500-700 wor ds) using the template format provided for the assignment: Presuming that Emily has decision-making capacity, Dr. Heady would like to hear your thoughts on the following: Ethically, should Emily be able to reject the abortion in the first
  • 73. trimester, knowing that it is highly probable that continuing to take her necessary medications will severely and permanently impair the baby? In reflecting upon the question, recall the court’s arguments in Roe v. Wade, and any counter arguments provided in your materials. Also, consider th e question of the fetus (encompassing all stages from conception through prebirth development) and the concept of moral standing. Use the following template for your assignment: 1. Use Microsoft Word to create a document. 2. Copy/paste the title of the question. 3. Describe the most relevant ethical dilemma(s) presented (no more than two). 10/27/2016 Final Case Analysis: The Emilly Dilemma - Abortion https://mycourses.excelsior.edu/bbcswebdav/pid-3200850-dt-co
  • 74. ntent-rid-31405097_1/courses/BHS.HSC312.Online.201610.201 612.s30047605/course%20wide… 3/3 4. Briefly describe the primary issue or issues that are relevant i n the scenario with respect to the dilemma. 5. Identify the most relevant stakeholder(s) (no more than 3) an d briefly describe the situation from their perspective. 6. Analyze the dilemma, using scholarly discussion, from the pe rspective of the primary stakeholder (typically the patient). Include a discussion of at lea st two ethical theories or bioethics principles studied in the course that relate to the dil emma and issues you identified. Include any relevant legal concerns or requirements outlined in the readings. 7. Present your assessment, resolution or potential solutions for resolving the issue. Remember that there are no right answers, per se, so reflective q uestions can be as
  • 75. appropriate as a firm conclusion. 8. Title page + APA formatted reference(s). 10/27/2016 Final Case Analysis: Paternalism vs Autonomy https://mycourses.excelsior.edu/bbcswebdav/pid-3200850-dt-co ntent-rid-31405097_1/courses/BHS.HSC312.Online.201610.201 612.s30047605/course%20wide… 1/2 Final Case Analysis: Paternalism v.s. Autonomy – Dax Cowart Introduction to the Activity I would like to introduce you to the story of Dax Cowart. Attach ed is an excerpt from a speech that Dax Cowart made several years ago, a speech that re mains poignant for contemporary reflection. The story is heart breaking and challen ges all the bounds of ethics and health care. As you listen to Dax, or read the transcri pt of his talk, think about
  • 76. the issues Dax discusses, especially in connection with capacity and the right to decline medical treatment (which we will discuss in greater detail later on in the course). These are the stories and circumstances where ethics and health care colli de and individuals are forced to make tough decisions. In thinking over your responses to the Discussion Board questions, consider the concepts we have talked about in this M odule and in Module I, such as personal moral values; bioethical principles; the need to weigh and prioritize competing moral interests; a physician’s charge to provide ethic al care and a patient’s right to self-determination. Related Reading from Module 2: Munson text: pp. 3­6; 38-40 (end at State Paternalism); 41-42 (e nd at Informed Consent); 891­904; UVA News Makers - Dax Cowart (Note: you may either watch the video part 1 [Video file] [09 mi n 30 sec], and
  • 77. video part 2 [Video file] [07 min 53 sec] or read the transcript a nd Hastings Center Report: Confronting Death: who chooses, who controls?) Instructions to Learners Please respond to the following questions (approx. 500-700 wor ds) using the template format provided for the assignment: You are Dax’s physician. How would you respond to Dax’s requ ests that you “let him die”? Would you continue to treat him against his wishes? Why or Wh y Not? Use the following template for your assignment: 1. Use Microsoft Word to create a document. 2. Copy/paste the title of the question. 3. Describe the most relevant ethical dilemma(s) presented (no more than two). 4. Briefly describe the primary issue or issues that are relevant i n the scenario with respect to the dilemma.
  • 78. http://www.virginia.edu/uvanewsmakers/newsmakers/cowart.ht ml https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=lSsu6HkguV8&list=PLD93B CDA6AFE8C393 https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=oGISGeKqCEM http://www.virginia.edu/uvanewsmakers/newsmakers/cowart.ht ml http://vlib.excelsior.edu/login?url=http://search.ebscohost.com/l ogin.aspx?direct=true&db=rzh&AN=1998034028&site=ehost- live&scope=site 10/27/2016 Final Case Analysis: Paternalism vs Autonomy https://mycourses.excelsior.edu/bbcswebdav/pid-3200850-dt-co ntent-rid-31405097_1/courses/BHS.HSC312.Online.201610.201 612.s30047605/course%20wide… 2/2 5. Identify the most relevant stakeholder(s) (no more than 3) an d briefly describe the situation from their perspective. 6. Analyze the dilemma, using scholarly discussion, from the pe rspective of the primary stakeholder (typically the patient). Include a discussion of at lea
  • 79. st two ethical theories or bioethics principles studied in the course that relate to the dil emma and issues you identified. Include any relevant legal concerns or requirements outlined in the readings. 7. Present your assessment, resolution or potential solutions for resolving the issue. Remember that there are no right answers, per se, so reflective q uestions can be as appropriate as a firm conclusion. 8. Title page + APA formatted reference(s). 10/27/2016 Final Case Analysis: Morally Wrong or Ethically Challenging? https://mycourses.excelsior.edu/bbcswebdav/pid-3200850-dt-co ntent-rid-31405097_1/courses/BHS.HSC312.Online.201610.201 612.s30047605/course%20wide… 1/2
  • 80. Final Case Analysis: Morally Wrong or Ethically Challenging? Introduction to the Activity Many states have considered enacting PAS legislation since Ore gon first legalized the practice in 1994, but as of yet, only Oregon and Washington have laws allowing for Physician Assist ed Suicide (PAS) 127.800; RCW 70.245). In Montana, although there is no current legislation regarding PAS, the Mont ana Supreme Court provided protection for doctor’s providing lethal medication to terminally ill patient’s upon requ est (Baxter v. Montana, 2009 MT 449). Currently, forty-three states have specific laws (either statutory or common law (case law) prohibiting assisted suicides, but four states (Hawaii, Nevada, Utah, Wyoming) and the District of Columbia have no l aw regarding the subject. Just recently, Massachusetts voters defeated a ballet initiative based upon the Oregon statute by a marginal 51% majority. Related Reading from Module 5: Module notes and assigned textbook pages Arras, J. (1997). Physician-assisted suicide: a tragic view. The J ournal Of Contemporary Health Law And Policy, 13(2), 361-389. (28)
  • 81. *The New York State Task Force on Life and the Law, (1997). When death is sought assisted suicide and euthanasia in the medical context supplement to report. Retrieve d from website: http://wings.buffalo.edu/bioethics/suppl.html. *Scroll down and read until the end of the passage “IV The Dist inction Between Administering High Doses of Opioids to Relieve Pain and “Physician­assisted Death.” Public Health, (1997). Oregon revised statute: Death with dignit y act (Chapter 127). Retrieved from Oregon Health Authority website: http://public.health.oregon.gov/ProviderPartnerResources/Evalu ationResearch/DeathwithDignityAct/Pages/ors. rules: 127.800 s.1.01. Definitions - 127.875 s.3.13. Insurance or annuity policies. Dep’t of Public Health, Annual Report on Oregon’s Death with Dignity Act (2012) [PDF file size 197 KB] http://public.health.oregon.gov/ProviderPartnerResources/Evalu ationResearch/DeathwithDignityAct/Documents/year15.pdf *Scan through the report to get an idea on how the statistics are compiled and trends recorded Instructions to Learners
  • 82. Please read the case scenario: You are a physician-ethicist at Hope hospital in Nirvana, USA. Your state is voting this month whether to allow PAS, under the exact guidelines and safeguards instituted in Oregon. The lo cal news station has asked you to join a televised multi- disciplinary panel and discuss the following questions: Reviewing the safeguards included in the Oregon Statute, which one(s ) potentially raise the most concerns in terms of their ability to protect patients in Nirvana, USA? In developing your response, consider whether the concerns are morally founded or policy oriented. Also keep in mind the rules of profe ssional responsibility, patient rights and the principles of bioethics we have studied throughout the course. NOTE: Please use the modified template below when considerin g your response with respect to completing the template, remember that a stakeholder can be described as many entities, such as but not limited to an individual, a professional society, the public at large or a subset of the population. Modified Template: 1. Use Microsoft Word to create a document
  • 83. 2. Copy/paste the title of the question 3. State the safeguards that you find most concerning. 4. Identify the most relevant stakeholder(s) (no more than 3) pot entially affected by the safeguards you listed. http://www.lexisnexis.com.vlib.excelsior.edu/lnacui2api/api/ver sion1/getDocCui?lni=3S3T-V110-00CV- P0S8&csi=138724&hl=t&hv=t&hnsd=f&hns=t&hgn=t&oc=0024 0&perma=true http://wings.buffalo.edu/bioethics/suppl.html http://public.health.oregon.gov/ProviderPartnerResources/Evalu ationResearch/DeathwithDignityAct/Pages/ors.aspx http://public.health.oregon.gov/ProviderPartnerResources/Evalu ationResearch/DeathwithDignityAct/Documents/year15.pdf 10/27/2016 Final Case Analysis: Morally Wrong or Ethically Challenging? https://mycourses.excelsior.edu/bbcswebdav/pid-3200850-dt-co ntent-rid-31405097_1/courses/BHS.HSC312.Online.201610.201 612.s30047605/course%20wide… 2/2 5. Analyze the concerns, using scholarly discussion from the per spective of the primary stakeholder. Include a
  • 84. discussion of at least two ethical theories or bioethics principles studied in the course that relate to the dilemma and issues you identified. Include any relevant legal concerns or req uirements outlined in the readings. 6. Present your assessment, resolution or potential solutions for resolving the concern. Remember that there are no right answers, per se, so reflective questions can be as appropria te as a firm conclusion. 7. Title page + APA formatted reference(s) 10/27/2016 Final Case Analysis: Confidentiality, Disclosure and Livid Love birds https://mycourses.excelsior.edu/bbcswebdav/pid-3200850-dt-co ntent-rid-31405097_1/courses/BHS.HSC312.Online.201610.201 612.s30047605/course%20wide… 1/3 Final Case Analysis: Confidentiality, Disclosure and Livid Love birds
  • 85. Informed consent requires not only that a patient receive all of t he information necessary to make a reasoned decision, but also that they are able to process and understand the information provided. Language or cultural differences may imp ede understanding, and a blanket reliance on a doctor’s judgment may subvert the intent o f the disclosure. Other barriers to informed consent, such as denial, fear and even famil y dynamics are often more difficult to spot, but equally if not more detrimental. Relat ionships between patients, family members and healthcare providers often morph over time into roles and role reversals that present special challenges in healthcare ethics and the doctor-patient relationship. In this activity, you will consider the standards of professional responsibility, medical ethics and the doctor-patient relationship as they apply when the boundaries between the roles become blurred. Related Reading from Module 3:
  • 86. Module Notes Munson text: (end at Parents & Children). AMA Opinion 10.01 - Fundamental Elements of the Patient-Phy sician Relationship Mitnick, S., Leffler, C., & Hood, V. (2010). Family caregivers, patients and physicians: ethical guidance to optimize relationships. Journal Of General I nternal Medicine, 25(3), 255-260. Principles of Medical Ethics. (2001). Schwartz, P. H. (2011). Questioning the Quantitative Imperative : Decision Aids, Prevention, and the Ethics of Disclosure. The Hastings Center R eport, (2), 30. doi:10.2307/41059016 Instructions to Learners Please read the case scenario: Mr. and Mrs. Lovebird were approaching their 65th wedding an niversary when it was discovered that Mr. Lovebird was battling Stage IV lung cancer, with metastasis to his colon. Vowing to “Fight this thing!” the Lovebirds sought out th
  • 87. e best specialists and Mr. Lovebird underwent two surgeries, chemotherapy and several ro unds of radiation. Mr. Lovebird did quite well for a while, but lately he has experience d severe fatigue and discomfort. He has also lost his appetite, resulting in a 15lb wei ght loss in just two months. Concerned, the Lovebirds went to see Dr. Friendly, their primar y care physician for over 30 years, whom they trust implicitly. Knowing that the Lovebirds a re in denial to some extent, but also believing that medicine is an inexact science, Dr. Frien dly told them both about an http://www.ama-assn.org/ama/pub/physician-resources/medical- ethics/code-medical-ethics/opinion1001.page http://www.ama-assn.org/ama/pub/physician-resources/medical- ethics/code-medical-ethics/principles-medical-ethics.page http://eds.a.ebscohost.com.vlib.excelsior.edu/eds/detail?vid=2& sid=3a5595c1-f673-4a7c-9b34- ff2409ff1a33%40sessionmgr4001&hid=4105&bdata=JnNpdGU9 ZWRzLWxpdmUmc2NvcGU9c2l0ZQ%3d%3d#db=rzh&AN=201 1703087
  • 88. 10/27/2016 Final Case Analysis: Confidentiality, Disclosure and Livid Love birds https://mycourses.excelsior.edu/bbcswebdav/pid-3200850-dt-co ntent-rid-31405097_1/courses/BHS.HSC312.Online.201610.201 612.s30047605/course%20wide… 2/3 experimental treatment option that might be worth “checking int o,” even though the chances were slim that it would provide much benefit. At a dinner party for a mutual acquaintance, Dr. Friendly is app roached by Lancelot, the Lovebird’s only child. Dr. Friendly is aware of the close relatio nship between Lancelot and the Lovebirds, so he is concerned for their welfare when Lancel ot approaches him. Once alone, Lancelot appears upset and tells Dr. Friendly that he is co ncerned about the experimental treatment option Dr. Friendly mentioned to the Lo vebirds, given Mr. Lovebird’s fatigue and weight loss. From Lancelot’s perspective , it is obvious that even if successful, it would only buy Mr. Lovebird a few months and th
  • 89. ose months may not be very good ones. He is also concerned that Mr. Lovebird is tired of treatments, but goes along to please Mrs. Lovebird. Dr. Friendly smiles and shakes h is head “Your mother has always been a force to be reckoned with,” he says “But, in realit y, a few months is better than no months!” He also assures Lancelot that if the Oncologis t does not think Mr. Lovebird is a good candidate for the procedure, the Oncologist will tell them so. When Lancelot suggests that Dr. Friendly’s professional judgme nt may be colored by the Lovebird’s denial, Dr. Friendly becomes defensive, stating that as their doctor all he can do is provide them with information and statistics on the disease pr ognosis and the benefits and risks of any potential options. He admonishes Lancelot, stat ing “if your parents want to believe in miracles, I am not going to take that away from them, and you shouldn’t either!” Visibly upset, Lancelot insists that Dr. Friendly discuss the Hos pice option with the Lovebirds, preferably with Mr. Lovebird, first. Although Dr. Fri
  • 90. endly is concerned that the idea of Hospice could be more lethal to the Lovebirds than any experimental treatment, he agrees, on the condition that Lancelot raise it with the Lovebird s first. “If your parents seem open to the conversation, give me a call or have them call me, a nd I will sit down with them to discuss the options.” The next day, Lancelot goes to see Mr. and Mrs. Lovebird, and s hares his conversation with Dr. Friendly, telling them that both he and Dr. Friendly agr ee that it may be time for Hospice services. Both the Lovebirds become very angry that he was discussing them with Dr. Friendly without them knowing it. They are also devastated that Dr. Friendly would conspire with Lancelot to force a decision on them that is clearl y premature. When he leaves, Mrs. Lovebird calls Dr. Friendly and tells him that she i s furious with his breach of confidentiality and that he should stick to family practice, as he is not an oncology expert. Please respond to the following questions (approx. 500-700 wor
  • 91. ds) using the template format provided for the assignment: Given Dr. Friendly’s longstanding relationship with the Lovebir ds, his insight into their processing and coping mechanisms, and the close family relatio nship he has witnessed between the Lovebirds and their son, did Dr. Friendly’s breach his professional 10/27/2016 Final Case Analysis: Confidentiality, Disclosure and Livid Love birds https://mycourses.excelsior.edu/bbcswebdav/pid-3200850-dt-co ntent-rid-31405097_1/courses/BHS.HSC312.Online.201610.201 612.s30047605/course%20wide… 3/3 responsibility to Mr. and Mrs. Lovebird by suggesting that Lanc elot discuss the Hospice option with the Lovebirds first? Use the following template for your assignment:
  • 92. 1. Use Microsoft Word to create a document. 2. Copy/paste the title of the question. 3. Describe the most relevant ethical dilemma(s) presented (no more than two). 4. Briefly describe the primary issue or issues that are relevant i n the scenario with respect to the dilemma. 5. Identify the most relevant stakeholder(s) (no more than 3) an d briefly describe the situation from their perspective. 6. Analyze the dilemma, using scholarly discussion, from the pe rspective of the primary stakeholder (typically the patient). Include a discussion of at lea st two ethical theories or bioethics principles studied in the course that relate to the dil emma and issues you identified. Include any relevant legal concerns or requirements outlined in the readings. 7. Present your assessment, resolution or potential solutions for resolving the issue.
  • 93. Remember that there are no right answers, per se, so reflective q uestions can be as appropriate as a firm conclusion. 8. Title page + APA formatted reference(s). A MEDICAL ETHICS ASSESSMENT OF THE CASE OF TERRI SCHIAVO TOM PRESTON University of Washington, Seattle, Washington, USA MICHAEL KELLY Swedish Medical Center and University of Washington, Seattle, Washington, USA The social, legal, and political discussion about the decision to stop feeding and hydration for Terri Schiavo lacked a medical ethics assessment. The authors used
  • 94. the principles of medical indications, quality of life, patient preference, and contextual features as a guide to medical decision-making in this case. Their conclusions include the following: (a) the use of a feeding tube inserted directly in to the stomach constituted artificial treatment; (b) the treatment prolonged biological life but did not lead to a cure and did not restore health; (c) quality of life was absent for the patient, with no sensation and no motor or cognitive functioning; and (d) by preponderance of medical opinion, she would have chosen not to live in a persistent vegetative state. The authors find the withdrawal of treatment was permissible and correct. It was not a choice between living and dying, but a decision of when to allow dying consistent with the patient’s choice. The case of Terri Schiavo, vexing as it was, holds lessons for us all. The forceful public reactions to the medical and legal proceedings
  • 95. leading to her demise showed a deep schism over the moral= religious issues inherent in how we die in the modern age of medi- cine. In our opinion, the political and legal wrangling detracted from the public understanding of the medical and bioethical issues involved in the case. Some might further argue that the case exposed a severe fault line in the bioethics approach to issues of this sort, or at least a limi- tation of the usefulness of bioethics. After all, the case never went under the scrutiny of a bioethics committee and there was no This article was written prior to release of the autopsy report on Terri Schiavo. Address correspondence to Tom Preston, 1128 22nd Ave. E., Seattle, WA 98112. E-mail: [email protected] 121 Death Studies, 30: 121–133, 2006 Copyright # Taylor & Francis Group, LLC
  • 96. ISSN: 0748-1187 print/1091-7683 online DOI: 10.1080/07481180500455608 formal statement of medical ethics conveyed to the public in support of letting Terri die. The public media presentation of the case was in social, political, and legal terms, with sparse, if any, discussion of how bioethical principles might apply to the difficult issues involved. The absence of a classic medical ethics assessment was a lost opportunity to educate the public. In this article we apply the basic tenets of medical ethics to the medical decision-making process in the Schiavo case. Medical ethics, or bioethics, began as a means of giving physicians and other health care providers guidelines for handling ethical pro- blems that occur in the practice of medicine. It then developed as a method for dealing with new ethical issues, particularly those arising from procedures such as artificial kidney treatment (dialy-
  • 97. sis), resuscitation, and withdrawal of life-sustaining treatment ( Jonsen, Siegler, & Winslade, 1992). We use the technique of Jonsen, Siegler, and Winslade (2002), which focuses on four topics clinicians should take into account in assessing the ethical aspects of a medical decision: medical indications, patient preference, quality of life, and contextual features. Medical Indications Medical ethics begins by asking whether the proposed treatment or procedure is medically indicated—does it fulfill the goals of medicine? Using the principle of beneficence, we ask does this treatment maintain life, restore health, and prevent symptoms? Do the benefits outweigh the potential harm of the treatment? What were the medical ‘‘facts’’ of the Terri Schiavo case, and what can bioethics teach us about how to proceed when a next similar case occurs? Removing Terri Schiavo’s feeding tube was not a treatment per se, but rather the discontinuation of treatment with hydration and nutrition. Terri did not sense food in her mouth and did not have a swallowing reflex. Because she was unable
  • 98. to swallow, she could not be fed through her mouth without a strong likelihood of choking to death, so the feeding tube was the only means of keeping her alive. The treatment under analysis is there- fore the continuation of fluids and nutrients through Terri’s feeding tube. The central question was whether continued treatment with the feeding tube was medically indicated. Was this treatment of 122 T. Preston and M. Kelly benefit to Terri, or was the treatment disproportionately burden- some and harmful to her? One of the goals of medicine is to maintain life or to prevent death. The goal, however, is not to prevent all death but to prevent untimely or inappropriate death. In this case, continued feeding certainly would have kept Terri alive, as it had done for 15 years.
  • 99. Although in many cases the goal of maintaining life is pre- eminent, when the ethical issue is whether life should continue or be allowed to end, this goal is subsumed under other considerations. Whether death from stopping the treatment would have been considered timely or untimely depends on factors such as perceived patient preference, judgment of what would be best for her, and opinions about the quality of her life. Would continued treatment have relieved symptoms of pain and suffering? No. Terri had only involuntary reflexes, with no function above the brain stem. She had no cognitive function or awareness of her surroundings, and no physical or mental sensation of pain or suffering. Therefore treatment was not relieving suffering. Would continued treatment have restored health? Would it have cured the disease or improved functional status? Two neurol- ogists selected by Terri’s parents (who opposed ending treatment)
  • 100. suggested that Terri’s smiles and movements represented cognition and sensation, whereas two neurologists selected by Terri’s husband and one selected independently by the court testified that Terri’s reflexes were involuntary and she was in a persistent veg- etative state from which she would never recover (see Cerminara’s introductory article for a detailed review of the related history). All five neurologists agreed that Terri had suffered enormous damage to her brain, such that most of her cerebral cortex, which controls conscious thought, was gone, replaced by spinal fluid. The biological probability for a cure of her condition was so minimal as to be effectively zero. In the second trial, the court heard conflicting evidence as to whether new therapy might succeed in restoring Terri’s brain func- tion and found no credible evidence that Terri would ever recover significant function. This finding was unanimously upheld on
  • 101. appeal. Undeniably, the prognosis in this case was crucial to a sound ethical judgment, and any disagreement makes the decision difficult. We agree with the trial courts that claims of potential improvement with new therapies were without merit. The treatment Medical Ethics Assessment 123 offered no chance for restoring health. Because treatment was not relieving symptoms, and it held no reasonable chance for a cure or clinical improvement, there was no medical indication for contin- ued treatment with the feeding tube. Germane to the discussion is a related question: Was Terri Schiavo on life support, or was she merely being fed through a tube? Some argued that treatment with food and fluids should never be withdrawn from dying or permanently unconscious patients (e.g., Pope John Paul II, 2004). Feeding is natural, they said, and ‘‘merely being fed through a tube’’ is not life
  • 102. support—it is different from stopping treatments such as artificial breathing with a mechanical ventilator. We all understand the emotion behind this argument when it is made to keep a loved one alive, but from a medical ethics perspective it is not correct. Medically, stopping feeding is no different from stopping a breathing machine that is keeping some- one alive. Air is also natural, and breathing is a natural function. Food and air are equally natural and essential to life. If a person is permanently unable to breathe, we can delay death with artificial breathing. If a person is permanently unable to swallow we can delay death by placing a feeding tube into the stomach and bypass- ing the need to swallow. It is as unnatural to pierce through the abdomen and place a tube into a patient’s stomach, and then pour food through the tube or pump it into the stomach with a machine, as it is to use a machine to blow air into a patient’s lungs. With artificial breathing,
  • 103. the air at least goes in and out through the natural wind-pipe, while artificial feeding bypasses the natural process of swallowing food through the esophagus to the stomach. The mechanisms of arti- ficial feeding and breathing are different, but one is not more or less natural than the other. But, some argued, food and fluids are ordinary and natural and stopping them is ‘‘killing,’’ it is ‘‘starving’’ a person to death (e.g., Pope John Paul II, 2004). On the other hand, they said, it is allowable to disconnect a patient from a breathing machine because it is an extraordinary medical measure (see also, President’s Commission for the Study of Ethical Problems in Medicine and Biomedical and Behavioral Research, 1983). But one is not extra- ordinary, whereas the other is ordinary. In its landmark report, the President’s Commission for the Study of Ethical Problems in 124 T. Preston and M. Kelly
  • 104. Medicine concluded: ‘‘There is no basis for holding that whether a treatment is common or unusual, or whether it is simple or com- plex, is in itself significant to a moral analysis of whether a treatment is warranted or obligatory’’ (p. 87). Also, according to Florida stat- ute, a ‘‘Life-prolonging procedure means any medical procedure, treatment, or intervention, including artificially provided sustenance and hydration, which sustains, restores, or supplants a spontaneous vital function’’ (Health Care Advance Directives, Definitions, x765.101, 2004, emphasis added; see also xx765.301-309). This is consistent with medical understanding and the tenets of medical ethics. Terri Schiavo was on life-support because she could not survive without the fluid and nutrition treatment she was receiving. Nonmaleficence
  • 105. Application of the principle of nonmaleficence (do no harm) leads us to ask, would continued feeding have been good treatment for Terri, or would it have harmed her? Would either maintaining or discontinuing the treatment cause harm out of proportion to benefit for her? Would removing Terri’s feeding tube be inhumane by causing ‘‘starvation’’ and pain? In comparison to withdrawing artificial breathing with a ventilator, stopping tube-feeding appears to be a long, drawn-out procedure during which the patient may suffer. But Terri had no sensation of thirst or hunger. She did not suffer when the feeding tube was withdrawn, and the absence of food and fluids did not cause suffering (Multi-Society Task Force on PVS, 1994). There is an important emotional difference between slow dying after withdrawal of food and water and the rapid death following disconnecting a patient from a respirator. One watches the patient dying slowly from absence of food and water and
  • 106. might conclude, ‘‘They are starving her to death.’’ But families do not usually watch their loved one being disconnected from a breathing machine. If they did, they would say, ‘‘They are suffocating him to death.’’ Discomfort or pain is possible in the latter procedure only if the patient is not given sufficient sedative or pain medicine to obliterate symptoms. On the other hand, there is no discomfort associated with dehydration after withdrawal of a feeding tube in a patient with persistent vegetative state. Medical Ethics Assessment 125 Would continued treatment have harmed Terri? Unfortunately, many relatives or loved ones of patients on life-supporting therapy do not understand the consequences of continued treatment. Although Terri would not have perceived suffering had she remained alive, over the years or decades to come she inevitably would have acquired illnesses associated with aging and being
  • 107. bed-ridden, which would have increased the psychological burden on her family. The larger question was whether Terri benefited or was harmed by dying. The answer to this rests in part on her quality of life if feeding had been continued. Certainty on this point is impossible and must take into account the complexity of the judg- ment of the value of living indefinitely in a persistent vegetative state. Whether Terri benefited or was harmed by dying also depends on determination of her personal preference, or her valuation of continued living in that condition. Autonomy, or Patient Preferences In our opinion, this is probably the most important ethical determi- nant of the case. There is little question that had Terri had an advance directive with a clear statement on whether she would want to continue living in a persistent vegetative state, the medical decision would have been according to her stated desire and there
  • 108. would have been little or no controversy. Perhaps the most daunt- ing problem in medical ethics is a life or death decision when the patient cannot state her choice, and the patient’s loved ones have conflicting wishes of what to do. This brings us to the concept of substituted judgment wherein the individual(s) who speaks for the patient must make decisions according to the beliefs and life style of the patient. The judgment should reflect not what the loved ones would want for the patient, but what the patient would want. Should we consider a patient’s known religious or social beliefs? Indeed, we give much weight to any known such beliefs or affirmations as indicative of a person’s fundamental values and wishes. To this end, an explicit understanding of Terri’s religious or social beliefs, such as from recorded statements, would have helped in determining whether she would have wanted treatment to be continued or stopped. There was nothing conclusive on this point.
  • 109. 126 T. Preston and M. Kelly We believe no one can be absolutely certain what Terri would have wanted, or how much thought she gave before her injury to what would have been for her a remote and hypothetical matter. Lacking explicit evidence, we cannot gainsay the findings of the courts. By the best evidence we have, Terri Schiavo would not have wished to continue living in the condition of persistent vegetative state (see Cerminara’s introduction). Autonomy is exceedingly important in medical ethics, and ordinarily trumps the wishes of others. The person involved in the proposed procedure or treatment should in most cases be able to make medical decisions for herself, or, as in this case, through a surrogate or guardian. But autonomy cannot be absolute if a medical decision hurts others disproportionately to the gain of the person making the autonomous decision. In this case, the decision should take into account the preferences of others, notably Terri’s closest
  • 110. relatives or loved ones. However, the disagreement between Terri’s parents and her husband meant that the wishes of the two sides of the dispute were diametrically opposed. If we give equal weight to the opposing parties, this consideration is a net sum zero, leaving the patient’s desire as the sole determinant. Although some disagree with the determination of what Terri would have wanted, it is based on the best evidence possible, and to go against the best evidence would be unwise. Quality of Life Future quality of life assessment is contingent on accurate prognosis. The finding that with continued treatment Terri would have remained indefinitely in a persistent vegetative state means there was no reasonable hope for a cure, awareness of sensation, the ability to move voluntarily, or to have cognitive function. With no awareness, she had no quality of life. Therefore, continued
  • 111. treatment would not have changed her quality of life status—it would not have made it better or worse. Whether continuing with no quality of life would be seen as favorable or unfavorable devolves upon assessment of whether Terri would have wanted to continue existing in a persistent vegetative state. This in turn hinges on medical prognosis. Although we acknowledge some difference of opinion regarding Terri’s Medical Ethics Assessment 127 prognosis, by the preponderance of expert opinion, further treatment would have been futile, and she would have had no qual- ity of life. By the quality of life criterion, therefore, it was ethically permissible to allow her to die. Contextual Features—Socio-Economic, Personal, and Institutional
  • 112. Vital medical decisions are never made in a social vacuum, but within the context of an individual’s upbringing, her family and friends, social and cultural institutions, the law, and economic influ- ences. It is important to consider all contextual elements in reaching an important medical decision, as the decision can have a lasting effect on other persons and institutions, as well as on the patient. Should a medical decision take into account the considera- tions of others? Yes, it should, and in particular it should account for close family members. However, here we come to the most wrenching aspect of the case: the conflict and antagonism between Terri’s parents and her husband. Terri’s parents said they desper- ately wanted to keep her alive, so stopping treatment and allowing her to die would have hurt them deeply. On the other hand, if Terri’s husband believed strongly that she should not be kept alive,
  • 113. a decision contrary to that wish would have hurt him. Can we say the parents’ emotional pain at seeing her die was greater than the husband’s pain would have been had she been kept alive? From reports in the public media, and from the lengths to which her par- ents went to keep Terri alive, we can say ‘‘perhaps so.’’ Did years of continued treatment after Terri’s husband first asked to have the tube removed cause him pain? Perhaps so. What matters is whether a decision one way or the other would cause undue emotional harm to either of the parties. The perception, by outsiders like us looking at the case, of harm to either Terri’s parents or to her husband, is undoubtedly influenced by characteristics, beliefs and values, and economic or social gain or loss of the opposing personalities in the case. For example, the personal religious convictions of Terri’s parents may have played a large role in wanting to keep her alive. Also, the relationships of the loved ones to Terri, and observers’ ability to identify with either the parents or the husband, may influence
  • 114. outside observers’ views of right and wrong. 128 T. Preston and M. Kelly Our perception of emotional harm is also influenced by our own personal values and beliefs. Assessing harm to others intimately involved in the case also would involve value judgments based on information gleaned from the public media. It would be wrong, we believe, to judge the degree of harm to the parents or husband based on our opinion of the reasons or underpinnings of their wishes, or perceived personal characteristics of the disputants. Further, this concern for others is disproportionately small com- pared with what was best for Terri. We must also consider the impact of our ethics decision on institutions and religious or cultural groups that may believe they will be impacted by the decision. In July 2004, based on a speech in which Pope John Paul II said it is obligatory for physicians to
  • 115. tube-feed patients in persistent vegetative states, Terri’s parents filed a motion aimed at stopping withdrawal of the feeding tube (see Cerminara’s article). This statement was contrary to what was then a near consensus in the medical ethics community in the United States—namely, it is ethically permissible to withdraw food and hydration in a patient in a persistent vegetative state if the patient or the patient’s surrogate so desires. This finding was also affirmed by the U.S. Supreme Court (Cruzan v. Director, Missouri Department of Health, 1990). Would a decision to stop treat- ment through a feeding tube cause harm to the Church? Many ‘‘right to life’’ advocates objected strenuously to removal of the feeding tube, often on ideological grounds. Would removing the feeding tube harm these groups and individuals? These are contextual ‘‘macro-issues’’ of how individual medical decisions can influence or alter institutions and policies that affect large groups of people or entire populations. Although macro- issues introduce important considerations, we cannot give them great weight in this case. Unless there is a clear and overwhelming public
  • 116. consensus, there are usually multiple opposing forces concerning a contentious social issue. For example, although ‘‘right to life’’ indivi- duals may feel harmed by a policy permitting cessation of feeding for a patient in a persistent vegetative state, ‘‘right to die’’ individuals may perceive harm from a converse policy. One of the primary goals of medical ethics is to protect the individual patient from pub- lic policies and institutions potentially harmful to the individual’s values or goals. The prime consideration must be the welfare and desires of the patient, not of social policy or institutions. Medical Ethics Assessment 129 Another macro-issue is the allocation of scarce resources. Using a ‘‘utilitarian’’ approach, we would make medical decisions to create the most good for the most people. Thus, one might
  • 117. argue that the resources necessary to keep someone alive for 15 years in a persistent vegetative state would be better allocated to provide basic health care for others who have no health insurance or can- not get adequate health care. The expenditure of resources of this order and magnitude is not trivial. However, although individual cases may bring national attention to social inadequacies, broader societal issues such as allocation of scarce resources are better handled on a macro scale of policy-making. The preponderance of weight in individual medical ethical decisions must be directed to considerations of what is best for the individual patient. If contextual factors (perceived harm to the relatives of one side or the other; religious beliefs; political, economic, and legal desires) were overwhelming, they might tilt our judgment. Such not being the case, however, the ethical decision must rest firmly on assessment of what was best for the patient. In the end, in
  • 118. Terri’s case all these contextual factors are minimal or are sub- sumed under the ethical considerations of beneficence and the patient’s preference. Comment and Conclusions By applying the classic elements of medical ethics, we find that it was ethically permissible and appropriate to stop Terri Schiavo’s treatment by use of a feeding tube. After 15 years with no sign of improvement, it is unreasonable to conclude that continued tube feeding would have led to clinical improvement. When the out- come is uncertain we should err on the side of maintaining life. But a helpful ethical maxim is that it is better to stop a treatment that was tried and did not work than to not start a treatment that has an uncertain outcome. This maxim was definitely followed in this case! The ramifications of the case are numerous if not legion by now and deserve the attention of all Americans. We believe the case’s most important lesson is the need for advance directives.
  • 119. The immense hostility and divisiveness engendered, individually and nationally, may be even more likely to recur in a future case of a patient in similar circumstances. The case has caused an unnecessary social divide. 130 T. Preston and M. Kelly In future cases involving care of patients in persistent vegetative states, violent disagreements as in the Schiavo case may be avoided by a full and early application of the principles of medical ethics. Just as importantly, the public needs to be informed of this approach to ethically difficult medical decisions, and the media should make use of it in their reporting. In our opinion, the inor- dinate and sensationalist media attention to the Schiavo case, with the marked emotional reactions of so many individuals and groups, detracted greatly from an understanding of the ethical principles that should have been applied to a determination of
  • 120. what was best for Terri. The medical ethics approach is not intended as an all-encom- passing set of rules for clinical decision-making. In a rare public reference to bioethics, a syndicated columnist said the discipline had become a secular tool and blamed ‘‘left-leaning bioethics’’ for justifying the ‘‘killing’’ of people such as Terri Schiavo (Leo, 2005). We acknowledge the secular basis of medical ethics as necessary to establish guidelines for all physicians without imposing specific religious or spiritual beliefs on those who do not share them. How physicians and others superimpose their religious or spiritual beliefs on medical ethics is a matter of indi- vidual values and goals. One may supplement medical ethics with personal principled beliefs, but we urge all to understand that in medical ethics ‘‘one size does not fit all.’’ There must be room to apply the principles of medical ethics within diverse sub-cultures. Part of the problem, we believe, has been a misplaced focus on ‘‘pulling the feeding tube,’’ rather than on the basic ethical question of the treatment Terri was receiving. By focusing only
  • 121. on the final act of withdrawing food and fluids, with its attendant symbolism to some of ‘‘killing,’’ one cannot understand the patient’s medical condition, the role of prior medical decisions, and the need for medical ethics in reaching a decision. Fundamental to an understanding of dying patients is the nature of earlier decisions, particularly treatments. Any life- extend- ing treatment decision is a choice to defer dying to a later date and, most likely, under different conditions. Continued provision of artificial nutrition and hydration to Terri would not have fulfilled the ethical goals of medical treatment—it could have only postponed, not prevented death. Medical Ethics Assessment 131 Dyinghasbeenpostponedbyhumanchoicewhenweartificially feed or breathe for a patient. The treatment is the key ethical issue,
  • 122. as without it the patient dies; however, with continuous treatment there is a continuous deferral of dying to a later date. The problem with continuing treatment after the prognosis is clear is exactly what happened to Terri. Once natural death is overcome medi- cally, and there is no medical reason to expect recovery, someone must make the decision about how and when to allow death to pro- ceed. The issue is not ‘‘killing,’’ or depriving a disabled person of life, but when to stop an unsuccessful treatment in order to allow death that has been unnaturally postponed. Medically, it seems reasonable to continue treatment for up to a year after a patient is diagnosed as being in a persistent vegetative state, although many neurologists might argue it is futile to treat after six months, or even less. But after the long-term outlook is clear, the choice is whether to allow a
  • 123. patient to die, as would have been Terri’s choice based on the best evidence, or to wait and let her die years later, as her parents wished. Either way it is a human decision someone had to make. Most Americans still die in institutions such as hospitals and nursing homes where decisions are made whether to resuscitate, to treat life-threatening complications, to try more curative ther- apy, or to withdraw life-sustaining treatments (Faber- Langendoen & Lanken, 2000; Field & Cassel, 1997). When patients are at the end of life and not capable of making medical decisions, loved ones often make decisions to stop treatments and let them die instead of extending ‘‘life’’ to the limits of modern technology. This is not killing, it is allowing death to proceed rather than extending the dying process. After life is first prolonged by medical manage- ment, it is allowed to end sometime later. It was the same for Terri Schiavo, and it is ethically correct.
  • 124. References Cruzan v. Director. Missouri Department of Health, 476 U.S. 261 (1990). Faber-Langendoen, K. & Lanken, P. N. (2000). Dying patients in the intensive care unit: Forgoing treatment, maintaining care. Annals of Internal Medicine, 133, 886–893. Field, M. J. & Cassel, C. K. (Eds.). (1997). Approaching death: Improving care at the end of life. Washington, DC: National Academy Press. 132 T. Preston and M. Kelly Health Care Advance Directives, Definitions. (2004). Fla. Stat. Title XLIV, Chap- ter 765.101. Jonsen, A. R., Siegler, M., & Winslade, W. J. (1992). Clinical
  • 125. ethics (3rd ed.). New York: McGraw Hill. Jonsen, A. R., Siegler, M., & Winslade, W. J. (2002). Clinical ethics (5th ed.). New York: McGraw Hill. Leo, J. (March 29, 2005). Left-leaning bioethics at core of the Schiavo debate. Seattle Times, p. B7. Multi-Society Task Force on PVS. (1994). Medical aspects of the persistent vegetative state—second of two parts. New England Journal of Medicine, 330, 1572–1579. Pope John Paul II. (2004, March 20). Address of John Paul II to the participants in the International Congress on ‘‘Life-Sustaining Treatments and Vegetation State: Scientific Advances and Ethical Dilemmas.’’ Retrieved September 9, 2005 from http://www.vatican.va/holy_father/john/paul_ii/speeches/2004/ march/
  • 126. documents/hf_jp-ii_spe_20040320_congress-fiamc_en.html. President’s Commission for the Study of Ethical Problems in Medicine and Biomedical and Behavioral Research. (1983). Deciding to forgo life-sustaining treatment: A report on the ethical, medical, and legal issues in treatment decisions. Washington, DC: GPO (Government Printing Office). Medical Ethics Assessment 133 WHAT WOULD TERRI WANT? ON THE PSYCHOLOGICAL CHALLENGES OF SURROGATE DECISION MAKING PETER H. DITTO University of California, Irvine, California, USA
  • 127. The Terri Schiavo case was unique in the media attention it garnered, but the decision making challenges faced by Terri’s family are common ones encountered by all families who must make choices about the use of life- sustaining medical treatment for an incapacitated loved one. This article highlights three key issues that were particularly problematic in the Schiavo case, but that represent general psychological challenges inherent to the task of surrogate decision making. The 3 central points of uncertainty, and therefore conflict, in the Schiavo case concerned: (a) the appropriate standard by which medical decisions for Terri should be made, (b) the specific nature of Terri’s wishes about the use of life-sustaining medical technology, and (c) the true extent of disability and prognosis for recovery represented by Terri’s medical condition. No simple remedy is possible that will resolve all of the uncertainties inherent to surrogate decision making, but some
  • 128. general strategies for improving the quality of end-of-life medical decisions are discussed. The tragic final chapter of Terri Schiavo’s life story was unique in many ways. Even in an era saturated with celebrity trials and confessional television talk shows, seldom has such an exquisitely personal decision been elevated to the level of full-blown, 21st- century style public spectacle. Discussions normally held in rever- ent tones within the dimly lit corridors of hospitals and hospices were magnified by a 24-hour news cycle and an ongoing culture war into a national conversation. The situation seemed uniquely cursed with every difficulty that might befall a family striving to make the right decisions for an incapacitated loved one. Irreconcil- able differences between family members about the appropriate course of action, the lack of any written documentation of Terri’s Address correspondence to Peter H. Ditto, Department of Psychology and Social