SlideShare a Scribd company logo
1 of 145
MATTHIAS KAISER, KATE MILLAR, ERIK THORSTENSEN,
and SANDY
TOMKINS
DEVELOPING THE ETHICAL MATRIX AS A DECISION
SUPPORT
FRAMEWORK: GM FISH AS A CASE STUDY
(Accepted in revised form October 25, 2006)
ABSTRACT. The Ethical Matrix was developed to help
decision-makers explore the
ethical issues raised by agri-food biotechnologies. Over the
decade since its inception
the Ethical Matrix has been used by a number of organizations
and the philosophical
basis of the framework has been discussed and analyzed
extensively. The role of tools
such as the Ethical Matrix in public policy decision-making has
received increasing
attention. In order to further develop the methodological aspects
of the Ethical
Matrix method, work was carried out to study the potential role
of the Ethical
Matrix as a decision support framework. When considering
which frameworks to
apply when analyzing the ethical dimensions of the application
of agri-food bio-
technologies, it is important to clarify the substantive nature of
any prospective
framework. In order to further investigate this issue, reflections
on the neologism
‘‘ethical soundness’’ of an ethical framework are presented
here. This concept is
introduced in order to provide more structured evaluations of a
range of ethical
tools, including ethical frameworks such as the Ethical Matrix.
As well as examining
the philosophical dimensions of the method, theoretical analysis
and literature
studies were combined with stakeholder engagement exercises
and consultations in
order to review the Ethical Matrix from a user perspective. This
work resulted in the
development of an Ethical Matrix Manual, which is intended to
act as a guide for
potential user groups.
KEY WORDS: biotechnology, decision support, Ethical
frameworks, Ethical
Matrix, GM fish
1. INTRODUCTION
One of the first decision-support frameworks to be developed to
explore the
ethical issues raised by agri-food biotechnologies was the
Ethical Matrix,
proposed by Mepham of the University of Nottingham in the
mid 1990s.
Since then, the Matrix has been applied to a number of case
studies, such as
bST, xenotransplantation and bioremediation, by Mepham and
his col-
leagues at the University of Nottingham (e.g., Mepham, 1996,
2000, 2001;
Mepham and Tomkins, 2003; Moore, 1996; Millar, 2002) and in
the Food
Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics (2007) 20:65–
80
DOI 10.1007/s10806-006-9023-8 � Springer 2007
Ethics Council, and by others working at several different
institutions (e.g.,
Kaiser and Forsberg, 2001; Kaiser, 2004; Schroeder and Palmer,
2003;
FAO/WHO, 2003; Chadwick et al., 2003). Over the decade since
its incep-
tion, the Ethical Matrix has attracted considerable attention
from specialists
in the field of bioethics, and the philosophical and
methodological basis of
the framework has been discussed and analyzed extensively.
Therefore, we
shall not attempt to survey and present all pertinent aspects and
justifica-
tions of the Ethical Matrix in this paper (refer to Mepham et al.,
2006 and
cf. also Forsberg, 2007).
The role of tools such as the Ethical Matrix in public policy
decision-
making has received increasing attention over the last few
years, with a
number of practitioners exploring the use of new and novel
frameworks and
tools, in particular in regard to applied ethics. In order to
further develop the
methodological aspects of the Ethical Matrix method, the
authors have
studied the potential role of the Ethical Matrix as a decision
support frame-
work in the field of biotechnology and food regulation.
Theoretical analysis
and literature studies were combined with stakeholder
engagement exercises
and consultations in order to study various aspects of the
Ethical Matrix
from a user perspective. This work resulted in the development
of an Ethical
Matrix Manual (Mepham et al., 2006). The aim of the paper is
to clarify some
general evaluation criteria for the uses of the Ethical Matrix as
a decision
support framework, and to exemplify briefly two participatory
approaches.
2. ETHICAL SOUNDNESS OF THE FRAMEWORKS
When considering which frameworks are appropriate for use
when ana-
lyzing the ethical dimensions of agri-food biotechnologies, it is
important to
clarify the substantive nature of any prospective framework. In
order to
investigate this, we have attempted to present some reflections
on the
neologism ‘‘ethical soundness’’ of an ethical framework. This
concept is
introduced in order to provide more structured evaluations of a
wider range
of ethical frameworks.
1
The term ‘‘soundness’’ in this context is adapted from the
philosophical
work on logic. An inference is normally termed ‘‘sound’’ if,
and only if, the
logical form of the argument is valid (i.e., truth preserving) and
all its
premises are true. An axiom system is sound if, and only if, all
the axioms
and theorems are true under all interpretations. Accordingly,
one would say
that an ethical argument is sound if, and only if, the logical
form of the
normative argument is valid (e.g., in a version of deontic logic,
namely, a
1
For a list of several such frameworks see the website of the
project Ethical Bio TA Tools:
http://www.ethicaltools.info/.
MATTHIAS KAISER ET AL.66
logic of normative concepts) and all its premises are either true
or valid (here
in the sense of the German term ‘‘gültig’’; ‘‘normative
rightness’’). It could
then be said that a normative system (theory) is sound if, and
only if, all its
axioms and derived theorems are valid under all normative
interpretations.
However, an ethical framework is not to be confused with a
particular
ethical theory. An ethical theory would, ideally, distinguish all
morally right
from all morally wrong or morally neutral actions. A framework
on the
other hand only assists us in reaching a reflected ethical insight
or normative
conclusion. A framework is not composed of statements that
together make
up a normative theory; rather it is a tool on a meta-level, since
it makes use
of a variety of ethical theories and normative arguments. Given
this variety,
the above description of ethical soundness cannot apply to such
a frame-
work, since viewpoints might be included that arise from very
different
theoretical conceptions and that may collide with each other.
Thus, ethical
soundness of a framework cannot mean normative validity under
all
interpretations. But a framework is also a practical and
pragmatic tool,
since it should allow us to extract all relevant information for
decision-
making involving ethical issues, without necessarily implying a
unique an-
swer to all issues. Ethical frameworks are not material objects,
or even sets
of statements; rather, they are conceptual or procedural devices,
which are
designed to facilitate explicit ethical decision-making, typically
by a body
consisting of several individuals with varying viewpoints. They
are tools that
are dependent on the competency of users, i.e., as moral
individuals. Given
this definition of an ethical framework, the use of ethical
soundness in this
context is therefore conjectural and non-traditional, and
requires further
analysis. This analysis should take account of the essential
function of
ethical frameworks to assist public bodies in making ethically
justified
decisions.
The question then arises, what should be preserved and
accentuated if
one transposes ethical soundness from normative ethical theory
to ethical
frameworks that are developed to aid decision-making. The
intuitive notion
is that a decision support framework works well, i.e., is
ethically sound, if it
allows competent access to all relevant normative
considerations and facts
of an issue, and leaves the users free to draw conclusions based
upon their
own priorities, but informed by insights into alternative
viewpoints.
Frameworks that have an inbuilt bias towards a particular
ethical position
should not be regarded as ‘‘ethically sound.’’ Similarly,
frameworks used
within a given knowledge base that systematically neglect
information that
is crucial for certain normative viewpoints, are also not
ethically sound. All
frameworks should ensure that the normative reasoning put
forward by
potential users is transparent to all external reviewers and
evaluators.
GM FISH AS A CASE STUDY 67
Therefore it is proposed that an ethical framework is ethically
sound, if
and only if, its application produces understanding of ethically
relevant con-
siderations in such a way that within a given body of knowledge
and on con-
dition of its competent use no further considerations would
decisively alter the
normative conclusions drawn from the framework by the users.
Such a definition of soundness of an ethical framework in some
way
parallels proposed definitions of, e.g., scientific objectivity (cf.
Føllesdal
et al., 1986, pp. 354–360).
2
It is clear that a definition of this kind with an
inbuilt counterfactual clause cannot be checked in any direct
manner as to
whether it applies or not. However, a test of ethical soundness
is to ask
whether certain ideal criteria are sufficiently respected in a
competent use of
a framework, such as the Ethical Matrix. These criteria could
then be seen as
indicators of ethical soundness, in much the same way as one
talks of
indicators of sustainability etc. The indicators would be such
that neglecting
them would weaken the value of the framework as a decision
support tool
and typically lead to different normative conclusions or
different reasons for
given conclusions. It should also be recognized that these
indicators could
be used to evaluate the performance of several alternative
ethical frame-
works (of which the Ethical Matrix is just one).
Thus, in the decision-making context addressed here, i.e., a
context
where a decision-maker is faced with competing value claims in
society and
a plurality of ethical theories appealed to by various groups,
several con-
siderations enter the picture that may indicate the ethical
soundness of
frameworks. The main properties of ethically sound
frameworks, as we
tentatively see them, are the following:
(1) Inclusion of values at stake
(2) Transparency
(3) Multiplicity of viewpoints
(4) Exposition of case-relevant ethically-relevant aspects
(5) Inclusion of ethical arguments
2.1. Inclusion of Values at Stake
Moral decisions represent choices between different moral
impacts or
assessments. Therefore, an explicit listing of all the values that
are at stake in
a decision is instrumental for the ethical soundness of the
framework. If a
relevant value is overlooked, the outcome of the moral
evaluation will
typically be different.
2
Føllesdal et al. (1986) characterizes scientific objectivity as the
ideal that is reached when a
given scientific claim would not be evaluated differently by
adding more pertinent facts in its
justification.
MATTHIAS KAISER ET AL.68
2.2. Transparency
One of the main challenges of ethical frameworks is to
overcome the
opaqueness of moral decision-making. The challenge is thus
that the process
of decision-making becomes transparent. Transparency is a
precondition for
(a) allowing a wide and inclusive social debate on the issue, and
(b) making
decisions that are socially robust and not immediately
challenged by public
voices on the basis of information gaps. All too often political
actors and
decision-makers seem to assume that ethical positions are
simply taken,
without clarification of why and how they are reached and how
they could
be challenged. This opacity leads to instability in moral
evaluation.
3
2.3. Multiplicity of Viewpoints
Democratic societies are by definition pluralist societies, and
this extends
naturally to the sphere of ethics. Any given or automatic
dominance of a
particular ethical viewpoint, be it a utilitarian viewpoint or
Kantian ethics,
etc., would infringe on the rights of those who adhere to
alternative ethical
viewpoints. Not seriously considering other ethical viewpoints
would also be
deeply unjust and run counter to ideals of equity. An ethical
framework
should, therefore, take account of this multiplicity of known
ethical view-
points. To the extent that this is not guaranteed by the
competent use of a
framework, the ethical soundness of the framework is
threatened, since
consideration of alternative conceptions may alter the outcome.
2.4. Exposition of Case-specific Ethically Relevant Aspects
Ethical decision-making presupposes that all ethically relevant
aspects of
the issue are adequately accounted for. As well as appropriately
specified
ethical principles, ethically relevant aspects include factual
information, the
inclusion of which potentially contributes to strengthening or
weakening a
particular moral outcome or judgment.
2.5. Inclusion of Ethical Arguments
Frameworks seem to differ in regard to the extent to which they
aspire to
represent ethical argumentation. In ethical theory, the ideal is
that an ethical
position is reached through a reflective argument, based on the
available
3
Even transparent decisions may of course be challenged, but
then disagreements may either
point to a lack of specific information that was not duly
considered, or to a simple disagreement
on the weighing of values. Currently we see that a number of
decisions are challenged simply on
the basis of being ‘‘unethical’’ or for presenting the wrong
ethical position. Ethical frameworks
aspire to extend beyond this rhetoric by ensuring the
transparency of the ethical reasoning
behind any given decision.
GM FISH AS A CASE STUDY 69
information and the ethical principles of the theory. This
applies in par-
ticular to situations where different principles run into conflict
and one has
to weigh and balance them. Knowledge of the arguments behind
particular
decisions enables rational critique and debate. Thus, we might
see this
aspect as instrumental for the ethical soundness of a framework.
The concept of ethical soundness was applied to evaluate the
suitability
of different candidates to operate as ethical tools in democratic
decision-
making processes. For instance, a committee approach (that
might be
ranked as a procedural decision support framework) might not
easily, or
necessarily, satisfy all requirements for transparency, e.g., in
terms of how
the final recommendation was reached and who discussed what.
However, it
is clearly very difficult to provide a definite characterization of
all possible
frameworks.
Examining the Ethical Matrix, and the process for translating
the prin-
ciples for such a matrix, reveals that the criterion of
transparency seems
optimally to be realized. A judgment formed on the basis of a
Matrix shows
clearly what information was available and which
considerations were
judged to be dominant and how they were weighed. Similarly,
one can say
that the multiplicity of viewpoints is optimally accounted for by
the explicit
listing of stakeholder viewpoints. In principle, there is also a
good chance
that an Ethical Matrix will account for all ethically relevant
information and
all ethical arguments. Yet, there are some caveats: these
features are
dependent on the information that is available and included in
the analysis.
Typically, this will depend on the scientific training and ethical
competence
of the users of the framework, such as organizers of a workshop
and the
participants or a committee secretariat. To the extent that all
users are
challenged by information overload, it may be difficult to be at
the cutting
edge of all issues. This may be reflected, for example, in the
quality of the
information included in the Matrix. In spite of this caveat, it
seems that the
probability of including all relevant values at stake would be
high, since this
is a criterion for compiling a list of interest groups. In
summary, the Ethical
Matrix would appear to score relatively highly on the indicators
of ethical
soundness.
One of the purposes of conducting an exercise to determine
ethical
soundness is to recognize that not all frameworks score alike
under the five
specified criteria. It appears that no framework could easily
fulfill all the
ethical soundness criteria. This may be due to the following
factors: (i) the
list of conditions may not really be comprehensive for this
purpose; (ii) some
frameworks may consciously be built upon leaving out certain
aspects in
order to optimize other aspects, e.g., playing down ethical
argument in favor
of transparency and multiplicity of viewpoints; (iii) the nature
of ethical
decision-making may be such that one in effect has to choose
between a
MATTHIAS KAISER ET AL.70
broad and inclusive framework and an in-depth framework with
detailed
expert arguments; and (iv) different frameworks may be
intended for dif-
ferent stages of the decision making process. In view of such
limitations, one
should be careful to consider the five properties as tentative
indicators for
reviewing the ethical soundness of a framework, and not as
conditions that
together define ethical soundness.
The aim of the above characterization was to clarify further the
needs of
decision-makers with regards to ethical frameworks. While one
may easily
agree that an ethical framework should facilitate the decision-
making pro-
cess, one also needs to pay closer attention to the variety of
possible uses to
which these frameworks can be put.
3. DEVELOPING A USER MANUAL FOR THE ETHICAL
MATRIX
When considering the conceptual basis of the Ethical Matrix, as
articulated
by Mepham et al. (2006), it is at its simplest level a checklist of
concerns,
structured around established ethical theory. However, it can
also be used as
a means of promoting structured discussion. The interest
groups, the
weighting of each cell, and even the appropriateness of the
principles may all
be challenged or modified by those using it. At best, it helps
those involved
in making a decision to put themselves in the shoes of others.
At the very
least, it ensures that more than the usual narrow range of
concerns are
raised and considered.
In order to review the needs of potential users of the Ethical
Matrix and
to develop a user manual for the Ethical Matrix, two workshops
were
convened, in each of which the potential use of GM fish was
chosen as the
case study. This case was chosen in order that the exercises
could relate
directly to the decision-making process involving the
Norwegian Ethical
Board on the Ethics of Patents. However, it is not the intention
of this
article to present a detailed ethical discussion of the chosen
case study. The
main focus of this article is to discuss a number of structural
features of the
Ethical Matrix approach that are of interest when evaluating it
as a decision
support framework. One workshop was conducted in Edinburgh
with a
group of experts, while a second workshop was conducted in
Oslo with
‘‘lay’’ participants. One of the previously reported strengths of
the Ethical
Matrix is that it can be used by numerous groups and does not
presuppose
that participants should all be knowledgeable stakeholders.
The research team reviewed aspects of the operation of an
expert group
with a group of lay people when using the Ethical Matrix.
However, within
a European context there are notable differences in scientific
and political
culture. While some countries seek ethical advice from broadly
composed
GM FISH AS A CASE STUDY 71
and highly qualified expert groups (which can include lay
members), other
countries, notably in Northern Europe, seek to further include
members of
the lay public, in the processes that lead to such advice. The
research team
worked on the assumption that there may not be any general or a
priori
arguments for or against either of these approaches, but that
both require
transparent justification of their ethical assessments.
Building on published material on the Ethical Matrix and the
practical
experiences of the research team, a provisional protocol was
devised as a
basis for the development of a Manual for the framework (see
the diagram
in Figure 1 for a summary). This protocol set out a clear
methodology for
potential users. The protocol gave guidance on the application
of the
method and both Research Groups used this protocol in two
workshop
trials. The protocol was then evaluated to determine its
applicability and
was further developed. In order to explore the two
methodological ap-
proaches to the Ethical Matrix that have emerged, the two
research groups
independently applied a top-down approach (TDA), or the
classical form of
the method, and a bottom up approach (BUA) that are described
below.
The Ethical Matrix may be used in several ways and by
different groups of
people, or even by individuals. So organizational requirements
are likely to
be quite different in different circumstances, and to be critically
influenced by
factors that are not directly related to the nature of the Ethical
Matrix as an
ethical tool. Such factors not only include financial and time
limitations but
also the degree to which participants in a group exercise are
encouraged to set
the agenda themselves rather than follow a prescribed step-by-
step proce-
dure. With reference to the latter point, the different ways in
which the
Ethical Matrix may be used will be greatly influenced by
whether its use
conforms more to a ‘‘top-down’’ approach than to a ‘‘bottom-
up’’ approach.
4. ETHICAL MATRIX TOP DOWN APPROACH (TDA)
In a TDA, the specifications of the Ethical Matrix principles are
largely set
by the organizers of the workshop, who have acknowledged
expertise in
facilitating bioethical deliberation, and play a prominent role in
structuring
the exercise.
In order to examine whether expert participants found the TDA
Ethical
Matrix approach useful when applied in a participatory setting,
a workshop
was organized in September 2005 in the UK. Using the potential
use of GM
salmon in aquaculture as a case study, nine ‘‘expert’’
participants applied the
Ethical Matrix to discuss key issues raised by the use of the GM
technology.
The notion of ‘‘expert status’’ was designated to the
participants on the basis
that they are actively involved with the aquaculture industry, or
biotech-
MATTHIAS KAISER ET AL.72
nology research and development. The group�s expertise
covered areas such
as marine biology; aquaculture industry; fish welfare;
regulation; and
molecular biology, etc. The final selection of participating
experts was done
by the workshop organizers. The final list of participants was
determined by
a combination of considerations, such as interest and
willingness to partic-
ipate, area of expertise, recognized standing in the profession,
etc.
DEFINE SUBJECT AREA
* Consideration of the technological claims
* Consideration of key ethical issues associated with
implementing the technology
DEFINE THE ETHICAL MATRIX
* Define the relevant interest groups
* Define the specifications of principles for each of the cells
WORKSHOP OBJECTIVES
* Define the aim of the workshop
* Define the scope of the discussion
* Define the outcomes expected from the workshop
WORKSHOP MATERIALS
* Prepare an introductory presentation
* Define the meeting sessions
* Define the role of the facilitator
* Prepare a briefing paper on the key ethical issues
FEEDBACK FORMS
* Prepare meeting feedback forms to review process and
the methodology
* Prepare SWOT analysis forms for assessing the
methodology
SELECT WORKSHOP PARTICIPANTS
* Define the relevant stakeholders
* Determine the relevant areas of expertise
* Ensure that there is a diversity of opinion and interests
represented
PARTICIPANT INVITATION
* Clarify the terms of reference for the workshop
* Clarify the reporting procedure and the role of each
participant
* Send out participant documents including a description of
the method and topic briefing paper
WORKSHOP
* Opening session that defines the methodology, sets out the
aims of the meeting, clarifies the
context of the discussions and clarifies the reporting process for
presenting the results of the
meeting.
* Balanced presentation of experts’ views
* Work through the cells of the matrix in a series of discussion
sessions
* Conclude with an overview session that draws out
participants’ overview of the issues
* Completion of the feedback forms
ANALYSIS OF THE DATA BY FACILITATOR
* Qualitative analysis of the discussion
* Quantitative analysis of data
* Qualitative analysis of the feedback forms
* Report on findings
FEEDBACK TO PARTICIPANTS
* Send draft of the workshop data analysis back to participants
to allow
them to check and review the representation of their input
FINAL ANALYSIS AND REPORT
Figure 1. Summary of a generic protocol of the Ethical Matrix.
GM FISH AS A CASE STUDY 73
Participants were sent briefing documents prior to the meeting,
including a
copy of the Ethical Matrix methodology. The workshop was
held over one day
andatthestartof
theevent,participantsweregivenanintroductiontotheEthical
Matrix and the potential issues raised by the case study. During
this process, the
classic TDA Ethical Matrix was used, where the principles are
pre-specified for
each of the interest groups (cf. Table 1). One justification for
using the ‘‘classic’’
Ethical Matrix approach was that it had proven useful in many
earlier settings,
and that its form and content are well documented (cf. Mepham,
2005).
The participants used the Ethical Matrix to map out the key
issued
raised. As part of their assessment, they were asked to comment
on the use
of the Ethical Matrix and its potential value. When examining
participants�
views of the Ethical Matrix in relation to the notion of ethical
soundness,
many felt that the strengths of the framework were its inclusion
of a mul-
tiplicity of viewpoints and the discussion of the key (ethical)
arguments.
Participants commented on the value of working through the
pre-defined
Ethical Matrix as it facilitated a structured debate amongst the
group.
When asked to complete a SWOT-analysis (setting out
strengths, weak-
nesses, opportunities, and threats) of the method, common
weaknesses were
described as: the lack of time to discuss each issue and the
potential limita-
tions of the knowledge of the participants. Participants noted
the need to
ensure that a broader range of stakeholders are involved in the
discussion,
therefore, the involvement of additional participants with
complementary
backgrounds would have been welcomed by the group. These
potential
limitations should be further explored within the context of
other partici-
patory methods, since many of the limitations identified can
relate to these
methods per se. As part of the written feedback, all participants
believed the
use of the Ethical Matrix helped the process. Although this was
a limited
exercise conducted in a UK setting, the findings from this
workshop appeared
to reinforce the perception that expert groups prefer to work
with a TDA.
5. ETHICAL MATRIX BOTTOM UP APPROACH (BUA)
In a bottom-up approach, the organizers provide less explicit
guidance, and
defer to the majority views of the (usually) lay participants in
specifying the
principles and conducting ethical deliberation.
In order to further analyze and develop the BUA Ethical Matrix
method,
a workshop was organized in Oslo (November 2004). The use of
GM
salmon in aquaculture was again chosen as the case for study.
Ten lay
participants were chosen from a sample of 70 (standardized
demographic
balancing was applied) self selecting citizens who had
responded to an
advertisement placed in a public newspaper. The ten
participants were
MATTHIAS KAISER ET AL.74
T
a
b
le
1
.
S
p
ec
ifi
ca
ti
o
n
o
f
th
e
E
th
ic
a
l
M
a
tr
ix
u
se
d
b
y
th
e
E
d
in
b
u
rg
h
w
o
rk
sh
o
p
p
a
rt
ic
ip
a
n
ts
.
E
th
ic
a
l
M
a
tr
ix
fo
r
G
M
sa
lm
o
n
(G
en
er
ic
d
efi
n
it
io
n
s
o
f
p
ri
n
ci
p
le
s
fo
r
th
e
co
rr
es
p
o
n
d
in
g
in
te
re
st
g
ro
u
p
s)
W
el
lb
ei
n
g
A
u
to
n
o
m
y
Ju
st
ic
e
T
re
a
te
d
sa
lm
o
n
W
el
fa
re
o
f
th
e
o
rg
a
n
is
m
B
eh
a
v
io
ra
l
fr
ee
d
o
m
In
tr
in
si
c
v
a
lu
e
F
is
h
p
ro
d
u
ce
rs
E
ffi
ca
cy
,
sa
fe
ty
a
n
d
re
m
u
n
er
a
ti
o
n
F
re
ed
o
m
to
a
d
o
p
t
o
r
n
o
t
a
d
o
p
t
F
a
ir
tr
ea
tm
en
t
in
tr
a
d
e
a
n
d
la
w
A
ff
ec
te
d
ci
ti
ze
n
s
(i
n
cl
u
d
in
g
co
n
su
m
er
s)
S
a
fe
ty
a
n
d
q
u
a
li
ty
o
f
li
fe
D
em
o
cr
a
ti
c
d
ec
is
io
n
-m
a
k
in
g
In
d
iv
id
u
a
l
a
n
d
re
g
io
n
a
l
ju
st
ic
e
T
ec
h
n
o
lo
g
is
t
a
n
d
fi
sh
b
re
ed
er
s
C
o
m
m
er
ci
a
l
v
ia
b
il
it
y
a
n
d
w
o
rk
in
g
co
n
d
it
io
n
s
A
b
il
it
y
to
in
n
o
v
a
te
E
q
u
it
a
b
le
tr
a
d
in
g
(m
a
rk
et
)
sy
st
em
E
n
v
ir
o
n
m
en
t
P
ro
te
ct
io
n
o
f
th
e
en
v
ir
o
n
m
en
t
B
io
d
iv
er
si
ty
o
f
b
io
ti
c
p
o
p
u
la
ti
o
n
s
S
u
st
a
in
a
b
il
it
y
o
f
th
e
en
v
ir
o
n
m
en
t
GM FISH AS A CASE STUDY 75
chosen on the basis of criteria such as gender, age, variety in
educational
background, and apparent motivation in application.
Participants were sent
briefing documents on the potential use of GM salmon and the
workshop
was conducted in two sessions on two separate days. On the
first day, the
participants were introduced to the case study and during the
second day the
group worked through the issues using the Ethical Matrix.
For this BUA approach, the research group applied a BUA
Ethical
Matrix based on the four principles – with well-being specified
separately as
increased benefits and reduced harm, autonomy, and fairness.
The partici-
pants translated these ethical principles into specifications for
the interest
groups and as a result of discussions the principle Autonomy
was modified
and the term Dignity was subsequently used in the Matrix. The
participants
also added additional stakeholders to the original list. Some
participants
argued for the inclusion of ‘‘future generations’’ as a
stakeholder group, but
it was agreed that these considerations could be included under
the Con-
sumer group. Others perceived ‘‘Research and Knowledge
Production’’ to
be an important issue. As a result of this discussion, an
additional stake-
holder group, ‘‘Research Community,’’ was added to the
Matrix. Five
interest groups were, therefore, used in this BUA Matrix. The
Ethical Matrix
articulated and agreed to by workshop participants is set out in
Table 2.
It should be noted that the Ethical Matrix method was
introduced to the
participants at the beginning of the discussion. Although,
participants
appreciated the organizers initial presentation of an Ethical
Matrix as a
starting point for their discussions, they claimed that if given
more time,
they might have proposed further changes, both in the list of
ethical prin-
ciples and in the list of stakeholders. Participants stated that the
Matrix
applied during the workshop should be seen as a first
approximation to the
problem, but they also highlighted that it would not necessarily
rank as a
‘‘natural’’ classification scheme. The organizers interpreted this
view as
indicating a level of abstraction in the Ethical Matrix method
that requires
some familiarity with, and knowledge of, ethical assessment
procedures.
In terms of outcomes from the workshop, much discussion
centered on
what the principles ‘‘Increased benefits’’ and ‘‘Reduced harm’’
actually re-
ferred to. It was, for instance, not obvious to the participants
that ‘‘Food
safety’’ was a correct specification of reduced harm for
consumers.
On the second day, the participants discussed the potential
ethical
impacts for the defined stakeholders (interest groups). This was
referred to
as specifying the consequence matrix. The organizers proposed
a completed
consequence matrix, but the participants wished to propose their
own
analysis of the issues without assistance.
In terms of feedback from the participants and in view of the
notion of
ethical soundness, some individuals were of the opinion that the
ethical
MATTHIAS KAISER ET AL.76
T
a
b
le
2
.
S
p
ec
ifi
ca
ti
o
n
o
f
th
e
E
th
ic
a
l
P
ri
n
ci
p
le
s
b
y
th
e
O
sl
o
w
o
rk
sh
o
p
p
a
rt
ic
ip
a
n
ts
.
G
M
sa
lm
o
n
(f
a
st
g
ro
w
th
+
st
er
il
it
y
)
In
cr
ea
se
d
b
en
efi
ts
R
ed
u
ce
d
h
a
rm
D
ig
n
it
y
F
a
ir
n
es
s
F
is
h
p
ro
d
u
ce
rs
In
co
m
e
a
n
d
w
o
rk
in
g
co
n
d
it
io
n
s
D
ep
en
d
en
ce
o
n
n
a
tu
ra
l
re
so
u
rc
es
,
p
la
ce
a
n
d
su
p
p
li
es
F
re
ed
o
m
to
ch
o
se
F
a
ir
tr
a
d
e
co
n
d
it
io
n
s
C
o
n
su
m
er
s
(p
re
se
n
t
a
n
d
fu
tu
re
)
N
u
tr
it
io
n
a
l
q
u
a
li
ty
F
o
o
d
sa
fe
ty
R
es
p
ec
t
fo
r
th
e
co
n
su
m
er
(f
o
o
d
la
b
el
in
g
)
A
ff
o
rd
a
b
le
p
ro
d
u
ct
s
a
n
d
g
en
er
a
l
a
v
a
il
a
b
il
it
y
T
re
a
te
d
fi
sh
R
es
is
ta
n
ce
to
d
is
ea
se
s
A
n
im
a
l
w
el
fa
re
F
re
ed
o
m
to
m
o
v
e
R
es
p
ec
t
fo
r
n
a
tu
ra
l
p
ro
p
er
ti
es
E
n
v
ir
o
n
m
en
t
P
ro
te
ct
io
n
P
o
ll
u
ti
o
n
S
u
st
a
in
a
b
il
it
y
o
f
b
io
lo
g
ic
a
l
d
iv
er
si
ty
R
eg
io
n
a
l
su
st
a
in
a
b
il
it
y
R
es
ea
rc
h
co
m
m
u
n
it
y
N
ew
th
em
es
a
n
d
fu
n
d
s
D
ep
en
d
en
ce
o
f
in
d
u
st
ri
a
l
fu
n
d
in
g
C
h
o
o
si
n
g
o
n
e�
s
o
w
n
re
se
a
rc
h
‘‘
U
n
d
efi
n
ed
’’
GM FISH AS A CASE STUDY 77
arguments were not fully clarified. This may be a limitation of
the BUA,
where principles are not predefined. Since this workshop was
conducted
with lay participants, it was felt that there should be sufficient
time for a
learning process to occur, in terms of the process and the
subject. Giving
more time for participants to reflect upon their own judgments
could im-
prove the process. The evolution of specification of the
different cells and
their contents are dependent upon interpretation, and this
interpretation
depends on the participants� background and preparation. This
may be seen
as a limitation for the use of the BUA approach with lay
participants.
However, the completed cells create compartmentalized data on
the par-
ticipants� views of the issues. The completion of the cells
demanded a fo-
cused debate over how one perceives a decision to affect the
interested
parties. This leads to a debate over values and potential ethical
impacts.
In addition to the comments on the methodology, several
participants
reported that some of their views changed as a result of
conducting the process.
For instance, while they raised ethical concerns with regards to
commercial use
of growth enhanced GM salmon, they also felt that the
development of sterile
GM salmon might reduce the significance of some of the major
concerns, since
it might address current concerns relating to wild stock levels.
Thus they found
that they did not fundamentally object to the use of GM
technology in animal
production, but options were dependent on the distribution of
implied benefits.
According to the participants, many of the advantages
demonstrated in
this study were procedural. There is room for further
development of the
methodology as a tool relevant for engaging with lay
participants. Some of
these developments are interrelated, e.g., time and clarity. It is
conceivable
that some more time – or stretching the exercise over a longer
period – could
lead to more reflection on ethical arguments.
CONCLUSIONS
Applying both the TDA and BUA approaches to the case of GM
salmon pro-
vided valuable insights that allowed further development of the
Ethical Manual.
The workshops highlighted the fact that, although the Ethical
Matrix does not
emerge as a very simple tool to use as a participatory ethical
framework, it does
show its potential to structure ethical concerns under varying
conditions.
It is not possible to conduct a direct comparison of the
outcomes from the
two workshops, since the participant sample is too small and the
method-
ological approach differed, in terms of preconditions and type
of participant.
However, even with these varying conditions, the two
applications of the
method, TDA and BUA, have allowed the analysis of some
crucial indica-
tors relating to the ethical soundness of decision support
frameworks.
MATTHIAS KAISER ET AL.78
Examining the discourse from the workshops, the participants
were able
to present their ethical reasoning in relation to the technology
that allowed
their evaluations to be more transparent, the reference to ethical
values and
argument was made explicit. The use of both methodologies,
TDA and BUA,
allowed individuals to present varying ethical viewpoints, even
to the extent
that they may not have coincided with participants original
viewpoints.
Conducting further participatory events would establish how
comprehensive
the recorded considered ethical viewpoints were in this study.
With regards to
ethically relevant factual information, both groups seemed to
endorse the
view that a broad range of expertise should be involved in the
preparation of
technology evaluation of this nature. This represents a
significant challenge
and responsibility for the organizers of this type of consultation
process.
These trial workshops highlighted that there are further
opportunities to
explore and develop the Ethical Matrix for use as a
participatory tool.
However, some interesting outcomes were observed from these
exercises. The
expert group felt that the use of the Ethical Matrix provided a
needed
structure for the discussion, allowing all participants to
contribute and
participate. It was interesting to note that the lay panel, which
at the start of
the process had voiced some skepticism towards biotechnology,
ended up
with a more positive evaluation of the potential use of GM
salmon by the end
of the process. No inherent technophobia seemed dominant in
their evalu-
ation and it seemed as if the close examination of this case
study on the basis
of an Ethical Matrix approach provided an overview that
allowed partici-
pants to distance themselves from preconceived ideas and judge
on the basis
of information and principles that are designed to serve the
common good.
Thus, it is hoped that for both applications, lay and expert, that
the Ethical
Matrix may actively contribute to what one may call ethical
discourses.
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
This work was conducted as part of the EC funded project under
DG Re-
search, FP5, Quality of Life program, ‘‘Ethical Bio TA tools,’’
(QLG6-
CT-2002-02594). The funding and the inspiring collaboration of
all other
consortium members are gratefully acknowledged.
REFERENCES
Beauchamp, T. L. and J. F. Childress (2002), Principles of
Biomedical Ethics, 5th ed.
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Chadwick, R. S., B. Henson, G. Moseley, M. Koenen, C.
Liakopoulos, A. Midden,
G. Palou, D. Rechkemmer, D. Schroeder, and A. Wright (2003),
Functional Foods,
Berlin: Springer Verlag.
GM FISH AS A CASE STUDY 79
FAO/WHO (2003), FAO/WHO expert consultation on the safety
assessment of foods
derived from genetically modified animals including fish,
November 2003, Rome:
FAO/WHO, pp. 17–21.
Føllesdal, D., L. Walløe, and J. Elster (1986), Rationale
Argumentation, Berlin, New
York: W. de Gruyter.
Forsberg, E. M. (2007), ‘‘Value Pluralism and Coherentist
Justification of Ethical
Advice.’’ Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics, 20.
Doi: 10.1007/
S10806-006-9017-16.
Kaiser, M. (2004), ‘‘Xenotransplantation – Ethical
Considerations Based on Human
and Societal Perspectives,’’ in W. Farstad, Ø. Andresen, O.
Nyberg, and B.
Christensen (eds.), Acta Veterinaria Scandinavica, Proceedings
of the 16th Inter-
nordic Symposium of the Nordic Committee for Veterinary
Scientific Cooperation on
Animal Organs to Save Human Lives, Suppl. 99, pp. 65–73.
Kaiser, M. and E. M. Forsberg (2001), ‘‘Assessing Fisheries –
Using an Ethical
Matrix in a Participatory Process.’’ Journal of Agricultural and
Environmental
Ethics, 14, pp. 192–200.
Mepham, B. (1996). ‘‘Ethical Analysis of Food
Biotechnologies: An Evaluative
Framework,’’ in B. Mepham (ed.), Food Ethics, London:
Routledge, pp. 101–119.
Mepham, B. (2000), ‘‘A Framework for the Ethical Analysis of
Novel Foods: The
Ethical Matrix.’’ Journal of Agricultural and Environmental
Ethics, 12, pp. 165–176.
Mepham, B. (2001), ‘‘Novel Foods,’’ in R. Chadwick (ed.),
Concise Encyclopaedia of
Ethics and New Technologies, San Diego: Academic Press, pp.
300–313.
Mepham, B. (2005), Bioethics: An Introduction for the
Biosciences, Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Mepham, B. and S. Tomkins (2003), Ethics and Animal
Farming: An Interactive Web
Program. www.ethicalmatrix.net.
Mepham, B., M. Kaiser, E. Thorstensen, S. Tomkins, and K.
Millar (2006), Ethical
Matrix User Manual, The Netherlands: Agricultural Economics
Research Institute.
Millar, K. (2002), ‘‘Thinking about Cleaning Up: The Ethics of
Bioremediation.’’
Science and Public Affairs, 3, pp. 20–21.
Moore, C. J. (1996), A Bioethical Analysis of Transgenesis in
Animals. PhD thesis,
University of Nottingham.
Schroeder, D. and C. Palmer (2003), ‘‘Technology Assessment
and the Ethical
Matrix.’’ Poiesis Praxis, 1, pp. 295–307.
MATTHIAS KAISER and ERIK THORSTENSEN
National Committee for Research Ethics in Science and
Technology (NENT)
P.O. Box 522 Sentrum,
Prinsensgate 18
0105, Oslo, Norway
E-mail: [email protected]
KATE MILLAR and SANDY TOMKINS
Centre for Applied Bioethics, School of Biosciences,
University of Nottingham, Sutton Bonington Campus
Loughborough, Leics, LE12 5RD, UK
E-mails: [email protected]; [email protected]
MATTHIAS KAISER ET AL.80
Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further
reproduction prohibited without permission.
<<
/ASCII85EncodePages false
/AllowTransparency false
/AutoPositionEPSFiles true
/AutoRotatePages /None
/Binding /Left
/CalGrayProfile (None)
/CalRGBProfile (sRGB IEC61966-2.1)
/CalCMYKProfile (ISO Coated)
/sRGBProfile (sRGB IEC61966-2.1)
/CannotEmbedFontPolicy /Error
/CompatibilityLevel 1.3
/CompressObjects /Off
/CompressPages true
/ConvertImagesToIndexed true
/PassThroughJPEGImages true
/CreateJDFFile false
/CreateJobTicket false
/DefaultRenderingIntent /Perceptual
/DetectBlends true
/ColorConversionStrategy /sRGB
/DoThumbnails true
/EmbedAllFonts true
/EmbedJobOptions true
/DSCReportingLevel 0
/SyntheticBoldness 1.00
/EmitDSCWarnings false
/EndPage -1
/ImageMemory 524288
/LockDistillerParams true
/MaxSubsetPct 100
/Optimize true
/OPM 1
/ParseDSCComments true
/ParseDSCCommentsForDocInfo true
/PreserveCopyPage true
/PreserveEPSInfo true
/PreserveHalftoneInfo false
/PreserveOPIComments false
/PreserveOverprintSettings true
/StartPage 1
/SubsetFonts false
/TransferFunctionInfo /Apply
/UCRandBGInfo /Preserve
/UsePrologue false
/ColorSettingsFile ()
/AlwaysEmbed [ true
]
/NeverEmbed [ true
]
/AntiAliasColorImages false
/DownsampleColorImages true
/ColorImageDownsampleType /Bicubic
/ColorImageResolution 150
/ColorImageDepth -1
/ColorImageDownsampleThreshold 1.50000
/EncodeColorImages true
/ColorImageFilter /DCTEncode
/AutoFilterColorImages false
/ColorImageAutoFilterStrategy /JPEG
/ColorACSImageDict <<
/QFactor 0.76
/HSamples [2 1 1 2] /VSamples [2 1 1 2]
>>
/ColorImageDict <<
/QFactor 0.76
/HSamples [2 1 1 2] /VSamples [2 1 1 2]
>>
/JPEG2000ColorACSImageDict <<
/TileWidth 256
/TileHeight 256
/Quality 30
>>
/JPEG2000ColorImageDict <<
/TileWidth 256
/TileHeight 256
/Quality 30
>>
/AntiAliasGrayImages false
/DownsampleGrayImages true
/GrayImageDownsampleType /Bicubic
/GrayImageResolution 150
/GrayImageDepth -1
/GrayImageDownsampleThreshold 1.50000
/EncodeGrayImages true
/GrayImageFilter /DCTEncode
/AutoFilterGrayImages true
/GrayImageAutoFilterStrategy /JPEG
/GrayACSImageDict <<
/QFactor 0.76
/HSamples [2 1 1 2] /VSamples [2 1 1 2]
>>
/GrayImageDict <<
/QFactor 0.15
/HSamples [1 1 1 1] /VSamples [1 1 1 1]
>>
/JPEG2000GrayACSImageDict <<
/TileWidth 256
/TileHeight 256
/Quality 30
>>
/JPEG2000GrayImageDict <<
/TileWidth 256
/TileHeight 256
/Quality 30
>>
/AntiAliasMonoImages false
/DownsampleMonoImages true
/MonoImageDownsampleType /Bicubic
/MonoImageResolution 600
/MonoImageDepth -1
/MonoImageDownsampleThreshold 1.50000
/EncodeMonoImages true
/MonoImageFilter /CCITTFaxEncode
/MonoImageDict <<
/K -1
>>
/AllowPSXObjects false
/PDFX1aCheck false
/PDFX3Check false
/PDFXCompliantPDFOnly false
/PDFXNoTrimBoxError true
/PDFXTrimBoxToMediaBoxOffset [
0.00000
0.00000
0.00000
0.00000
]
/PDFXSetBleedBoxToMediaBox true
/PDFXBleedBoxToTrimBoxOffset [
0.00000
0.00000
0.00000
0.00000
]
/PDFXOutputIntentProfile (None)
/PDFXOutputCondition ()
/PDFXRegistryName (http://www.color.org?)
/PDFXTrapped /False
/Description <<
/DEU
<FEFF004a006f0062006f007000740069006f006e007300200066
006f00720020004100630072006f0062006100740020004400690
07300740069006c006c0065007200200036002e000d0050007200
6f006400750063006500730020005000440046002000660069006
c0065007300200077006800690063006800200061007200650020
007500730065006400200066006f0072002000640069006700690
0740061006c0020007000720069006e00740069006e0067002000
61006e00640020006f006e006c0069006e0065002000750073006
100670065002e000d002800630029002000320030003000340020
0053007000720069006e006700650072002d005600650072006c0
061006700200047006d0062004800200061006e00640020004900
6d007000720065007300730065006400200047006d00620048000
d000d0054006800650020006c0061007400650073007400200076
0065007200730069006f006e002000630061006e0020006200650
0200064006f0077006e006c006f00610064006500640020006100
7400200068007400740070003a002f002f00700072006f00640075
006300740069006f006e002e0073007000720069006e006700650
072002e00640065002f007000640066002f000d00540068006500
72006500200079006f0075002000630061006e00200061006c007
3006f002000660069006e00640020006100200073007500690074
00610062006c006500200045006e0066006f00630075007300200
05000440046002000500072006f00660069006c00650020006600
6f0072002000500069007400530074006f0070002000500072006
f00660065007300730069006f006e0061006c0020003600200061
006e0064002000500069007400530074006f00700020005300650
0720076006500720020003300200066006f007200200070007200
650066006c00690067006800740069006e006700200079006f007
500720020005000440046002000660069006c0065007300200062
00650066006f007200650020006a006f006200200073007500620
06d0069007300730069006f006e002e>
/ENU
<FEFF004a006f0062006f007000740069006f006e007300200066
006f00720020004100630072006f0062006100740020004400690
07300740069006c006c0065007200200036002e000d0050007200
6f006400750063006500730020005000440046002000660069006
c0065007300200077006800690063006800200061007200650020
007500730065006400200066006f0072002000640069006700690
0740061006c0020007000720069006e00740069006e0067002000
61006e00640020006f006e006c0069006e0065002000750073006
100670065002e000d002800630029002000320030003000340020
0053007000720069006e00670065007200200061006e006400200
049006d007000720065007300730065006400200047006d006200
48>
>>
>> setdistillerparams
<<
/HWResolution [2400 2400]
/PageSize [2834.646 2834.646]
>> setpagedevice
Brion J. Fox, JD, University of Wisconsin Comprehensive
Cancer
Center, Madison, Wisconsin; Joanna E. Cohen, PhD, Ontario
Tobacco
Research Unit, University of Toronto, Toronto, Ontario,
Canada, and
Department of Public Health Sciences, University of Toronto,
Toronto,
Ontario, Canada. This work was carried out at the Center for
Tobacco
Research and Intervention, University of Wisconsin Medical
School,
and at the Ontario Tobacco Research Unit.
Corespondence: Brion J. Fox, J.D., University of Wisconsin
Comprehensive Cancer Center, Room 385 WARF Bldg., 610
Walnut
St., Madison, WI 53726, USA. Tel.: + 1 (608) 262-3894; fax: +
1 (608)
262-2425; E-mail: [email protected] u
Review
Tobacco harm reduction: A call to address the
ethical dilemmas
Brion J. Fox, Joanna E. Cohen
[Received 31 July 31, 2001; accepted 18 February 2002]
The 2001 Institute of Medicine report Clearing the Smoke:
Assessing the Science Base for Tobacco Harm
Reduction has helped to focus attention on the scientific basis
for assessing tobacco harm reduction products.
As the tobacco research and policy communities tackle the
challenges of evaluating harm reduction, there are
ethical issues that must also be addressed. There has, however,
been very little writing on the ethics of this field.
In an effort to spur research into answering these ethical
questions, we present two complementary approaches.
First we outline three overarching topics in tobacco harm
reduction that would particularly lend themselves to
study: (a) Is the pursuit of tobacco harm reduction an ethical
goal? (b) What are the ethical considerations of
tobacco harm reduction vis-à-vis pharmaceutical companies?
and (c) What are the ethical considerations for
harm reduction vis-à-vis tobacco companies? We then present
one possible framework for analyzing the ethical
issues that accompany particular tobacco harm reduction
strategies. By considering the ethical dilemmas
attendant to tobacco harm reduction in a prospective and
thoughtful manner, we will be better prepared to
handle the challenges that face us individually as researchers
and collectively as a tobacco control
community.
Introduction
In 2001, the Institute of Medicine published a report
assessing the science base for tobacco harm reduction
(Stratton, Shetty, Wallace, & Bondurant, 2001). In that
report, the term harm reduction referred to strategies
that lower tobacco-related mortality and morbidity even
though there continues to be exposure to one or more
tobacco-related toxicants. There are a wide variety of
harm reduction strategies. Some of these strategies
include using nicotine replacement therapies to reduce
smoking, the development of ‘safer’ cigarettes, and the
implementation of behavioral strategies to reduce the
total number of cigarettes a person smokes. The
Institute of Medicine report has helped spur the tobacco
research and policy community to examine more
closely the prospect of developing products and strate-
gies for tobacco harm reduction. This effort comes
bearing a myriad of challenges, including the scientific
difficulties in developing and evaluating new products,
the prospect that individual benefits may be outweighed
by population harms, and the reality that many ideas
may arise, and indeed may be encouraged to arise
(Stratton et al., 2001), from the tobacco and pharma-
ceutical industries.
Some have argued that tobacco harm reduction
strategies are inevitable because the tobacco and pharma-
ceutical industries are pursuing reduced risk products
independently. This, however, merely abdicates responsi-
bility for exploring whether a harm reduction approach is
desirable. We in the tobacco control community have an
obligation to make choices about our own behavior and
to act as advisors to clinicians, consumers, policymakers,
and other researchers. These roles are especially impor-
tant when examining tobacco harm reduction because of
the uncertain nature of the information and the possible
unintended consequences of harm reduction strategies.
As tobacco scientists and policymakers address these
ISSN 1462-2203 print/ISSN 1469-994X online/02/0600S81-07
© 2002 Society for Research on Nicotine and Tobacco
DOI: 10.1080/1462220021000032861
Nicotine & Tobacco Research (2002), S81– S87
challenges, it is imperative to confront head-on the
ethical questions that they present. If we fail to examine
these issues proactively, we may find ourselves reacting
to potential dilemmas as individual moral actors, rather
than defining as a community the standards to which we
should hold research and researchers. By engaging in this
dialogue early, we will be able to respond thoughtfully to
many of the ethical challenges posed.
In the hope of provoking these discussions, we suggest
below three topics that should be the focus of greater
study as the tobacco control community evaluates the
advantages and disadvantages of pursuing a harm
reduction strategy: (a) Is the pursuit of tobacco harm
reduction an ethical goal? (b) What are the ethical
considerations of tobacco harm reduction vis-à-vis
pharmaceutical companies? and (c) What are the ethical
considerations for harm reduction vis-à-vis tobacco
companies? Because of the overarching nature of these
questions, they will not be answered quickly, nor should
they be. These questions should be part of an ongoing
dialogue and series of analyses that encompass the wide
range of interests of the tobacco control community.
Given, however, that there is an immediate need to
understand some of the ethical implications of particular
harm reduction strategies, we also present and discuss an
ethical framework for analyzing proposed harm reduc-
tion strategies.
Should the tobacco control community pursue
tobacco harm reduction?
As the Institute of Medicine report discusses, harm
reduction strategies that have been adopted in fields
other than tobacco control can provide analogies to
possible tobacco harm reduction strategies. For example,
improving the safety of automobiles is analogous to
removing toxicants from tobacco smoke; providing clean
needles through needle exchange programs is analogous
to heating rather than burning tobacco products; and
providing methadone to heroin addicts is analogous to
providing long-term nicotine replacement therapy to
people who are addicted to nicotine. In many cases, these
harm reduction strategies were reported to be successful,
although recently there has been growing criticism of a
harm reduction approach (Erickson, 1999; Mangham,
2001; Mugford, 1992).
Part of the desire to pursue a tobacco harm reduction
strategy is based upon the belief that we will be unable to
achieve our health goals through current efforts to
prevent and treat tobacco use. For example, it is believed
that there remains a significant core of individuals who
are unable to quit, are increasingly recalcitrant or
otherwise impervious to the public health messages (e.g.,
Irvin & Brandon, 2000), and who would benefit from
harm reduction strategies. In addition, even the most
efficacious treatments or prevention programs will not
reach all smokers. In fact, there is a core of smokers,
often poorer, less educated, or suffering from a co-
morbidity such as mental illness, that would dispropor-
tionately benefit from safer products. The difficult
question, however, is whether efforts taken to reach hard
core smokers will overshadow efforts that could help a
larger number of smokers.
The recently published Public Health Service Clinical
Practice Guideline Treating Tobacco Use and Depend-
ence concluded, ‘There is insufficient evidence to
support a recommendation regarding harm reduction
strategies’ (Fiore et al., 2000). The Guideline describes
numerous strategies and approaches for the effective
treatment of tobacco dependence, and speaks of ‘opti-
mism’ for a ‘promising era in the treatment of tobacco
use and dependence’ (Fiore et al., 2000). The report
identifies the failure to systematically implement the
guideline recommendations as the key barrier to increas-
ing quit rates; that is, it may be too soon to give up hope
on treating the great majority of smokers. This is not
because our tools are insufficient, but because we have
been inadequate in adopting and applying the tools. This
view was supported by the publication of a prevention
priorities project that identified that adult tobacco
cessation treatment was among the most effective, cost-
effective, yet under-utilized prevention interventions
(Coffield et al., 2001).
Similarly, the Centers for Disease Control and Pre-
vention have identified Best Practices for states devel-
oping programs to reduce tobacco use (Centers for
Disease Control and Prevention, 1999). The neglect of
many states to fully fund programs to promote these
best practices shows another failure to live up to the
full promise of what we can accomplish in reducing
tobacco use. Indeed, the U.S. Surgeon General has
declared that a 50% reduction in youth and adult
smoking could be achieved by applying what we
already know (U.S. Department of Health and Human
Services, 2000).
The concern is that if clinicians and public health
professionals are encouraged to implement harm reduc-
tion strategies, it is possible that this would be done at
the expense of delivering the cessation messages and
developing the prevention programs that we know are
effective. We fail not because current strategies are
ineffective, but because of a lack of commitment to
strategies that we know work. The conundrum thus
posed is whether it is ethical to invest time, energy, and
resources in the development and testing of new harm
reduction strategies when strategies known to be effec-
tive have not been fully implemented. The challenge
remains even if a private company introduces the harm
reduction strategy– i.e., the tobacco control community
will need to decide if it endorses or uses the product.
It is not as simple as saying that we can pursue all
approaches simultaneously. One of the difficulties in
persuading clinicians to provide treatment is the con-
founding nature of the multiple messages they receive.
Similarly, it has been shown that with the advent of low
tar and nicotine cigarettes, smokers used the lower-risk
messages to continue their smoking behavior (National
Cancer Institute, 2001). In assessing the potential value
S82 ETHICAL DILEMMAS
of a harm reduction product, there must be some
recognition that there will be a tradeoff for other public
health efforts. On the other hand, there should also be a
recognition that there is nothing foreseeable that suggests
the current approaches will ‘solve’ the problem in the
near future, and eventually some form of harm reduction
product may be necessary.
What are the ethical considerations of harm
reduction with regard to pharmaceutical
companies?
Any consideration of pursuing or recognizing the
legitimacy of tobacco harm reduction raises the specter
of involvement with pharmaceutical companies. These
companies currently market nicotine replacement prod-
ucts and non-nicotine therapies, such as bupropion SR.
These agents have been approved for use as cessation
devices in a number of countries, and have established
the pharmaceutical companies as partners in the effort to
promote tobacco cessation. In the future, these com-
panies may seek to promote these or newly developed
products as harm reduction products, which could put
them at odds with the cessation community.
The participation of pharmaceutical companies in the
debate on harm reduction raises challenging ethical
issues. Despite the positive advances that have been
made by the drug industry, they are private corporations
driven by a profit motive. In the pursuit of harm
reduction, this business ethic may conflict with a public
health ethic. There are a number of ways that this conflict
could be realized. For example, the development of
competitive nicotine delivery devices that would replace
cigarette smoking with long-term nicotine maintenance
(Warner, Slade, & Sweanor, 1997) could subject the
pharmaceutical companies to the criticism that they are
simply replacing one addiction with another. Moreover,
if the pharmaceutical industry produces new products
that reduce harm but do not promote cessation, or market
existing products as a complement to smoking that will
reduce overall harm, the presumed beneficence of the
industry may be lost.
There may also be ethical issues with respect to having
researchers collaborate with pharmaceutical companies.
These companies have an economic interest in the
outcomes of studies they fund that may conflict with the
independence that researchers desire. There is an asso-
ciation between positions that are favorable to the
pharmaceutical industry and financial relationships of
the authors with this industry (Stelfox, Chua, O’Rourke,
& Detsky, 1998). There is evidence that proceedings
from pharmaceutical-sponsored symposia tend to have
misleading titles, to use brand names, and to not be peer
reviewed (Bero, Galbraith, & Rennie, 1992). Further,
many contracts between the pharmaceutical industry and
investigators have unacceptable publication clauses, and
a substantial number of articles that are published
include authorship lists that do not meet accepted criteria
for authorship (Bodenheimer, 2000). An uncomfortabl e
reality is that pharmaceutical companies and, potentially,
tobacco researchers who receive support from the
pharmaceutical industry, could have a vested interest in
the types of harm reduction strategies explored.
Recent efforts have addressed the publication of data
from sponsored clinical trials (e.g., Davidoff et al., 2001)
and have established guidelines for industry collabora-
tion (Centers for Disease Control and Prevention, 1997).
These efforts provide guidance as to how to conduct
collaborations but do not discuss whether to pursue the
collaboration in the first place. Moreover, because drug
companies are able to invest great resources in the
development of pharmaceutical products, they may be in
a position to control the tobacco harm reduction research
agenda. Drug-free harm reduction strategies, such as
banning smoking in workplaces (Chapman et al., 1999;
Evans, Farrelly, & Montgomery, 1999; Glasgow, Cum-
mings, & Hyland, 1997), may get left out of any serious
discussion of tobacco harm reduction.
A final difficulty is that, although it is possible to get
public money to study pharmaceutical products, the
majority of funds for clinical drug trials in the U.S. is
provided by pharmaceutical companies. Academic medi-
cal centers are now receiving a minority of those funds,
with for-profit contract-research and site-management
organizations the favored providers of clinical trial
services (Bodenheimer, 2000); thus, researchers who
choose to pursue harm reduction products may be
required to work with this industry.
What are the ethical considerations of harm
reduction with regard to tobacco companies?
With respect to harm reduction, the greatest incentive for
creating safer products may come from the tobacco
industry itself. Many of the private lawsuits have been
based upon a failure of the industry to create a safer
product, misleading the public into thinking that a
product is safe, or, in the case of public plaintiffs, to not
pursue research into safer products. The industry thus has
incentives, in the form of improved public relations and
the avoidance of future litigation, to create a safer
product. Any company that develops a safer product is
also likely to have a significant market advantage over its
competitors.
Furthermore, the tobacco companies may be best
situated to understand the subtleties of nicotine delivery
and the development of a safer cigarette. Indeed, there
are many industry products that are already being tested
or discussed. As a result of these factors, it is likely that
the tobacco control community will face the prospect of
having to assess a tobacco-industry-produced harm
reduction product. This assessment may include direct
collaboration in the development or testing of such a
product, or responding to the presence of such a produc t
in the market.
There are reasons that the tobacco control community
may be cautious of such a collaboration. It is well
established that the tobacco industry has perverted
NICOTINE & TOBACCO RESEARCH S83
science for its own purposes by creating artificial
controversy, attacking the reputation of tobacco control
researchers, and filtering science through lawyers (Bero,
Barnes, Hanauer, Slade, & Glantz, 1995; Saloojee &
Dagli, 2000). Efforts by the tobacco industry to sponsor
forums to discuss scientific issues or promote collabora-
tion have been met with scorn and have been boycotted
by many in tobacco control. Similarly, efforts to enlist
reputable scientists to review or support the work funded
by the industry have been met with derision (Gardiner,
2001).
Distrust of the industry runs so deep that many have
argued that relationships with the tobacco industry are
unacceptable (Shield, 2001), that universities should
refuse money from the tobacco industry (Chapman &
Shatenstein, 2001; Cohen, Ashley, Goldstein, Ferrence,
& Brewster, 1999) and that journal editors should refuse
to publish articles based on research sponsored by the
tobacco industry (King, Yamey, & Smith, 2000). Even
analyses of legal settlements with the industry have been
described as ‘dealing with the Devil’ (Annas, 1997). One
would be hard-pressed to find anything positive about
the past behavior of the tobacco industry that would
warrant faith in moving forward in collaboration with
this industry, and many organizations have specific
policies against collaboration with the tobacco industry
(Cohen, 2001). It is feared that collaboration, complicity,
or acquiescence of the public health community in
tobacco industry efforts could result in increased credi-
bility of the tobacco industry, making it harder to oppos e
industry efforts that are genuinely detrimental to the
public health.
Given the innate distrust of the tobacco industry,
researchers are likely to want to test independently any
products developed by this industry. In addition, there
will be an innate skepticism of industry motives; for
example, is the industry using harm reduction as a means
to increase the number of smokers, or to decrease the
number of smokers who quit? This skepticism will also
lead researchers to critically examine the broader
implications of the proposed product. This independent
testing may simply delay rather than answer certain
ethical questions, because independent testing could
result in confirming that the products meet the claims of
the industry.
There are risks to rejecting potential future relation-
ships with the tobacco industry. As the pharmaceutical
companies bear the cost of testing their products, there is
an argument that tobacco companies should bear the cost
of testing their products. In addition, if science is built
upon open discourse, censorship of the industry could
marginalize the tobacco control community. To reject all
future collaborations assumes that the industry is beyond
redemption, which may be a faulty and risky assumption.
For example, the industry’s reputation is extraordinarily
low in the eyes of the public. The result of this has been
a drive for regulation and litigation. If the industry
changes and the tobacco control community is not
prepared to deal with an industry that is not easily
demonized, the tobacco control community may lose its
own credibility.
Before initiating any collaboration with tobacco
companies on harm reduction strategies or tools,
thoughtful analyses will be needed to define the
appropriate scope and nature of the associations. Ethical
considerations will vary depending on the proximity of
the funds to the tobacco industry and the level of
restrictions on the use of the funds. For example, there
seems to be a spectrum of funding risks from clearly
inappropriate to acceptable that includes: the sponsorship
of a researcher or student, the direct funding of a research
project, the unrestricted funding to an institution, and the
use of litigation settlement funds for research. Similarly,
significant ethical consideration should be given to
determine how the public health community should react
to industry efforts even if there is no collaboration. Over
time, these reactions may prove to be what changes the
most, should the industry actually reform, even if, for the
immediate future, skepticism is warranted.
A framework for analyzing tobacco harm reduction
strategies
If the tobacco control community can answer the
questions laid out above in a way that supports pursuing
tobacco harm reduction, there will still be a need to
examine the ethics of individual tobacco harm reduction
strategies. We propose an ethical framework under which
such strategies could be analyzed similar to frameworks
produced in other contexts (see for example Kass, 2001).
An ethical framework will not predetermine answers to
all ethical questions, nor will it guarantee that any two
parties using the framework will arrive at the same
outcome. What it can assist with is a rigorous analysis of
the relevant questions that can then lead to an increased
understanding of the principles at stake. Such a frame-
work could also assist in the development of analyses
and standards for scientific conduct, and the develop-
ment of future research questions.
Ethicists have generally agreed upon a series of cross-
cutting principles that can serve as the basis for a
framework for analysis. Among these principles are:
beneficence – the principle of doing good; nonmalefi-
cence – the principle of not doing harm; self-determina-
tion – the principle of allowing individuals to make their
own decisions; and justice – the principle of fairness
(Beauchamp & Steinbock, 1999). These principles also
serve as the basis for many of the ethical theories,
including utilitarian, Kantian, and communitarian theo-
ries (Beauchamp & Steinbock, 1999). For our framework
we have chosen to use a utilitarian approach, which
evaluates and balances the likely benefits and burdens of
the proposed strategy. This balancing should be done in
such a manner that it takes into account the cross-cutting
ethical principles as they come to bear on the underlying
question. The framework that follows will account for
many of the ethical questions raised earlier in this
paper.
S84 ETHICAL DILEMMAS
What are the proposed benefits?
A proposed tobacco harm reduction strategy should be
analyzed for its probable real world benefits and should
be examined for efficacy and for effectiveness. Fur-
thermore, care should be taken to understand the true
penetration of the proposed strategy into the market. For
example, promoting nicotine replacement products as a
part of a harm reduction strategy could fail if the
products are not used or are used incorrectly. Similarly,
new products will have limited effect if they are not
purchased and used by consumers because of inadequate
taste or nicotine delivery. Where evidence is suggestive
of a strong potential benefit, one should not necessarily
withhold the strategy in favor of scientific certainty, but
it should be coupled with specific research questions to
be able to promote the long-term analysis of the
proposed strategy.
A primary difficulty in assessing effectiveness is that
the time for scientific discovery is lengthy, and the net
epidemiologic effects of new products cannot be known
for years. On the one hand, too cautious a stance may
discourage the development of new products that are
potentially effective in reducing at least some of the risks
of smoking. On the other hand, proposed tobacco harm
reduction strategies should result in more good than
harm, and not simply substitute harms. For example,
much has been written about the failure of low tar
cigarettes as a harm reduction approach. Initially these
products were seen as potentially beneficial for health
because they were supposed to deliver lower levels of tar.
In the end, however, these products were determined to
be no better than conventional products because of the
innate hazards of tobacco products and how smokers
actually used the product, which offset much of the
benefit that could have been realized. Although an ethical
analysis of low tar cigarettes may not have prevented the
mistakes which occurred, a thorough ethical discussion
could have identified the risks and tradeoffs that were
being made, and promoted research to assist in evaluat-
ing the potential risks versus the potential benefits.
What are the possible harms?
Even if a particular harm reduction strategy suggests
great promise, it must be scrutinized for the potential
burdens that accompany it. These burdens could be
inherent in the product or the result of replacing one risk
with another. An historical example of this kind of
burden would be the original Kent micronite filter, which
was found to have high levels of crocidolite asbestos
fibers (Longo, Rigler, & Slade, 1995).
Burdens could also arise from secondary conse-
quences accompanying the harm reduction product. For
example, by creating a safer product there could be a
reduced incentive to quit smoking or avoid initiation.
Therefore, a presumed-safer product could have the
perverse effect of creating a greater population-wide
harm if prevalence is increased. The overarching issues
related to opportunity costs discussed above are espe-
cially appropriate to this part of the framework. Sim-
ilarly, certain types of products may remove other
motivations to quit or maintain abstinence. For example,
a product that reduces or eliminates second-hand smoke
could remove the incentive for individuals to quit in
order to protect those around them. It could also serve to
remove incentives for employers, home-owners, or
policymakers to promote smoke-free environments.
Other burdens may be more regulatory in nature. If a
product is developed that escapes definition as a
cigarette, it may avoid taxation, advertising restrictions,
and so forth. Although the solution could be regulatory,
such an outcome should be considered in an ethical
analysis.
Just as the proposed benefits are to some degree
speculative, the proposed burdens will also be a matter of
some prognostication; nevertheless, efforts should be
made to understand the likely harms as well as the gaps
in research that need to be filled to explain the true nature
of the burden. For example, a better understanding of
how individuals process risk messages is important to
understanding the probable impact a reduced risk
product may have on prevalence rates. In addition,
research such as that published recently by Kozlowski
and colleagues (Kozlowski, Strasser, Giovino, Erickson,
& Terza, 2001), which provides a model for how one can
balance the reduction in risk of a harm-reducing produc t
against the increased use of that product, can assist in the
calculation of the scope of the burden.
Would the possible benefits and harms be
distributed across the population equitably?
Even if a product appears on balance to be beneficial,
with the probable risks outweighing the burdens, the
proposed product should be analyzed for its implications
for social justice. If there exists a truly beneficial produc t
that significantly reduces the risk of disease related to
smoking, but that product is expensive, there arises a
social justice question. What mechanisms are in place, or
need to be put in place, to make a safer produc t
accessible to all who might need it? This opens an
additional set of problems, however. If no mechanism
exists, should the product be abandoned even if such an
action would prohibit benefit to those who could afford
it? Conversely, it would be awkward at best for the
tobacco control community to argue for increased
availability of a tobacco product, albeit a reduced-risk
one.
There also could be cultural or other barriers to
products that may create a social disparity. For example,
smokeless tobacco, which may be considered a reduced-
harm product, is almost exclusively used by males. The
answers to these and comparable social justice questions
lie outside the scope of this paper; nevertheless, at a
minimum an examination of these questions should be
made prior to the endorsement of a particular tobacco
harm reduction strategy.
NICOTINE & TOBACCO RESEARCH S85
What additional benefits and risks accompany the
proposed strategy because of the involvement of
private industry?
A further level of scrutiny that a proposed harm
reduction product or strategy should undergo is whether
the development or promotion of the product involves
the pharmaceutical or tobacco industries. In addition to
the industry analyses proposed above, one must make
transparent any biases or conflicts of interest that could
arise due to industry involvement.
The mere existence of a bias may not be deleterious,
but the proposed analysis would require the disclosure of
all potential biases. Financial disclosures are clearly the
most apparent and have found their way into the
requirements for peer review publications and general
researcher behavior. However, biases can also be experi-
entially based. For example, as discussed above, the
inherent mistrust of the tobacco industry and its motives
runs deep, which itself may cause one to prejudge a
product from the industry. These biases should also be
disclosed when endorsing or criticizing a tobacco harm
reduction strategy.
An example of how industry involvement could create
an ethical dilemma can be seen in the following
hypothetical situation. How should the tobacco control
community react if essentially identical reduced-risk
products arise out of both the pharmaceutical and
tobacco industries? If the products otherwise pass ethical
muster, the tobacco control community may choose to
support the pharmaceutical company product because of
the historical burdens that are associated with the
tobacco industry. Alternatively, the tobacco control
community may shy away from endorsing the pharma-
ceutical company product because of an appearance of
impropriety if this company had funded tobacco control
programs or researchers. Silence could result in a
slowing of the dissemination of the proposed product.
Whichever solution individuals choose to follow, their
biases should be disclosed.
Discussion
One potential interpretation of this commentary is that
the tobacco control community should operate under a
single set of ethics. We are not advocating either for or
against this proposition, and we believe this idea should
be thoughtfully examined prior to any recommendation.
One of the strengths of tobacco-related research is that it
represents the coming together of a range of disciplines
and perspectives. It is possible that the forced homoge-
neity of a single set of ethics could eliminate some of the
diversity we currently enjoy.
If we examine the most basic sources of principle that
exist in our discipline, we can see how the issues conflict
as much as they overlap. Clinicians who operate under
the medical model, treating disease one patient at a time,
could value a harm reduction strategy that benefits an
individual much more than do public health profession-
als who are trying to address population-based problems.
Indeed, one could argue that a failure to prescribe a harm
reduction product to a particular patient who could
benefit from its use could be seen as a violation of a
biomedical ethic. Alternatively, one could see that public
health workers could consider it unethical to support a
harm reduction product that had a negative effect on the
overall population. Similarly, non-profit organizations
may be driven by a mission to improve health of all
people, whereas for profit corporations are, by definition,
responsible for maximizing profits for their shareholders.
If a commercially viable and individually-beneficial
harm reduction product was available but nevertheless
had a negative net population-based effect, one could not
expect private corporations to shy away from that
product, nor is it ethically clear that they should.
Our position is simply stated: Individuals should, prior
to adopting a stance on a particular harm reduction
strategy, conduct a rigorous ethical analysis such as that
presented in this paper. Moreover, to best protect the
interests of researchers and policymakers, we urge that
ethical studies be embraced as a necessary part of any
larger commitment to pursue harm reduction. These
studies should involve thoughtful analyses of the issues
from a variety of perspectives, including biomedical,
public health, corporate, legal, and policy. We have
presented but one approach for determining the appro-
priateness of harm reduction strategies. We hope that it
stimulates discussion and encourages others to improve
upon the framework.
Acknowledgments and disclosures
Preparation of this manuscript by the first author was supported,
in part,
by the Robert Wood Johnson Foundation program Developin g
Leadership in Reducing Substance Abuse. Dr. Cohen received
funding
from the Canadian Institute of Health Research. The authors
would like
to thank Stella Aguinaga Bialous, Mary Jane Ashley, Roberta
Ferrence,
Pam Kaufman, and Kenneth Warner for their helpful comments
on
earlier drafts of this manuscript .
References
Annas, G. J. ( 1997). Tobacco litigation as cancer prevention:
dealing
with the devil. New England Journal of Medicine, 336, 304–
308.
Beauchamp, D. E., Steinbock, B. (1999). New ethics for the
public’s
health. New York: Oxford University Press.
Bero, L., Barnes, D. E., Hanauer, P., Slade, J., Glantz, S. A.
(1995).
Lawyer control of the tobacco industry’s external research
program:
The Brown and Williamson documents. Journal of the American
Medical Association, 274, 241– 247.
Bero, L. A., Galbraith, A., Rennie, D. (1992). The publication
of
sponsored symposiums in medical journals. New England
Journal of
Medicine, 327, 1135 –1140.
Bodenheimer, T. (2000). Uneasy alliance: Clinical investigators
and the
pharmaceutical industry. New England Journal of Medicine,
342,
1539– 1544.
Centers for Disease Control and Prevention. (1997, February).
Guidance for collaboration with the private sector. Retrieved
February 10, 2002, from http://www.cdc.gov/od/foia/policies/
collabor.htm
Centers for Disease Control and Prevention. (1999). Best
practices for
comprehensive tobacco control program s. Atlanta, GA: Office
on
Smoking and Health.
Chapman, S., Borland, R., Scollo, M., Brownson, R. C.,
Dominello, A.,
Woodward, S. (1999). The impact of smoke-free workplaces on
declining cigarette consumption in Australia and the United
States.
American Journal of Public Health, 89, 1018–1023.
S86 ETHICAL DILEMMAS
Chapman, S., Shatenstein, S. (2001). The ethics of the cash
register:
Taking tobacco research dollars. Tobacco Control, 10, 1– 2.
Coffield, A. B., Maciosek, M. V., McGinnis, J. M., Harris, J.
R.,
Caldwell, M. B., Teutsch, S. M., Atkins, D., Richland, J. H.,
Haddix,
A. (2001). Priorities among recommended clinical preventive
services. American Journal of Preventive Medicine, 21, 1– 9.
Cohen, J. E., Ashley, M. J., Goldstein, A. O., Ferrence, R.,
Brewster, J.
M. (1999). Institutional addiction to tobacco. Tobacco Control,
8,
70– 74.
Cohen, J. E. (2001). Universities and tobacco money: some
universities
are accomplices in the tobacco epidemic. British Medical
Journal,
323, 1– 2.
Davidoff, F., DeAngelis, C. D., Drazen, J. M., Hoey, J.,
Højgaard, L.,
Horton, R., Kotzin, S., Nicholls, M. G., Nylenna, M., Overbeke,
A.
J., Sox, H. C., Van Der Weyden, M. B., Wilkes, M. S. (2001).
Sponsorship, authorship, and acountability. Journal of the
American
Medical Association, 286, 1232 –1234.
Erickson, P. G. (1999). Introduction: The three phases of harm
reduction. An examination of emerging concepts, methodologies
,
and critiques. Substance Use & Misuse, 34, 1–7.
Evans, W. N., Farrelly, M. C., Montgomery, E. (1999). Do
workplace
smoking bans reduce smoking? American Economic Review, 89,
728–747.
Fiore, M. C., Bailey, W. C., Cohen, S. J., et al. (2000). Treating
Tobacco
Use and Dependence. Clinical Practice Guideline. Rockville,
MD:
Public Health Service.
Gardiner, P. (2001). The Philip Morris external research
program; fig
leaf optional. Burning Issues: TRDRP Newsletter, 4, 7–10.
Glasgow, R. E., Cummings, K. M., Hyland, A. ( 1997).
Relationship of
worksite smoking policy to changes in employee tobacco use:
Findings from COMMIT. Tobacco Control, 6(Suppl 2), S44-
S48.
Irvin, J. E., Brandon, T. H. (2000). The increasing recalcitrance
of
smokers in clinical trials. Nicotine & Tobacco Research, 2, 79–
84.
Kass, N. E. (2001). An ethics framework for public health.
American
Journal of Public Health, 91, 1776–1782.
King, J., Yamey, G., Smith, R. (2000). For and against: Why
journals
should not publish articles funded by the tobacco industry.
British
Medical Journa l, 321, 1074.
Kozlowski, L. T., Strasser, A. A., Giovino, G. A., Erickson, P.
A., Terza,
J. V. (2001). Applying the risk/use equilibrium: use medicinal
nicotine now for harm reduction. Tobacco Control, 10, 201–
203.
Longo, W. E., Rigler, M. W., Slade, J. ( 1995). Crocidolite
asbestos
fibers in smoke from original Kent cigarettes. Cancer Research,
55,
2232– 2235.
Mangham, C. (2001). Harm reduction and illegal drugs: the real
debate.
Canadian Journal of Public Health, 92, 204– 205.
Mugford, S. (1992). Harm reduction: Does it lead where its
proponent s
imagine? In N. Heather, A. Wodak, E. Nadelmann, & P. O’Hare
(Eds.), Psychoactive drugs and harm reduction – from faith to
science. London: Whurr Publishers.
National Cancer Institute. (2001). Risks associated with
smoking
cigarettes with low machine-measured yields of tar and
nicotine.
Smoking and Tobacco Control Monograph No. 13. (NIH
Publication
No. 02– 5074). Retrieved July 10, 2002, from http://cancercon-
trol.cancer.gov/tcrb/monographs /13/
Saloojee, Y., & Dagli, E. (2000). Tobacco industry tactics for
resisting
public policy on health. Bulletin of the World Health
Organization,
78, 902– 910.
Shield, M. (2001). Policies and positions of other funding
organizations
on the funding controversy. Burning Issues: TRDRP Newsletter,
4,
2– 4.
Stelfox, H. T., Chua, G., O’Rourke, K., & Detsky, A. S. (1998).
Conflict of interest in the debate over calcium-channel
antagonists .
New England Journal of Medicine, 327, 101– 106.
Stratton, K., Shetty, P., Wallace, R., & Bondurant, S. (Eds.).
(2001).
Clearing the smoke: Assessing the science base for tobacco
harm
reduction . Washington, DC: National Academy Press.
U. S. Department of Health and Human Services. ( 2000).
Reducing
tobacco use. A report of the Surgeon General. Washington, DC:
U.
S. Government Printing Office. Retrieved July 10, 2002, from
http:/
/www.cdc.gov/tobacco/sgr/sgr_2000.htm
Warner, K. E., Slade, J., Sweanor, D. T. (1997). The emerging
market
for long-term nicotine maintenance. Journal of the American
Medical Association, 278, 1087–1092.
NICOTINE & TOBACCO RESEARCH S87
March/April 2009 229
he financial fiascos at Enron,
Tyco, WorldCom, Global Cross-
ing, Qwest, HealthSouth, and the vari-
ous hedge fund investments managed
by securities firms that were highly
questionable from an ethical perspec-
tive have received extensive coverage
in the media. As these unethical—if not
illegal events unfolded—the pressure
mounted for regulatory agencies such
as the Securities and Exchange Com-
mission to enforce tightened restrictions
and for legislative bodies, including the
U.S. Congress, to prohibit some of the
more deliberate misrepresentations. For
example, the Sarbanes-Oxley Act (2002),
with its Public Companies Accounting
Oversight Board, has made an attempt
to address aspects of this far-reaching
problem. Some of the business profes-
sionals involved in these incidents active-
ly participated in cover-ups, shredding
documentary evidence of their corporate
misconduct (e.g., Arthur Andersen) and
creating an elaborate web of intentional-
ly misleading corporate structures. Some
of these professionals merely looked the
other way as such deceptions occurred in
the workplace. However, when a course
of action has been undertaken, it is often
difficult for subsequent players to effec-
tively challenge the status quo (Demski,
2003). In a 2005–2006 survey devel-
oped by KPMG (an international public
accounting and consulting firm), nearly
75% of the respondents reported that
they had observed misconduct in their
current organization during the previous
12 months (Williams, 2006). During the
same time period, a study by Walker Infor-
mation, as reported in a meta-analysis
by Verschoor (2006), found that 42% of
respondents thought their organization’s
senior leaders were unethical. Walker
Information’s study also reported that
25% of the respondents had knowledge
of, or suspected, an ethics violation in the
previous 2 years (Verschoor).
The widespread nature of the recently
publicized scandals suggests that there
has been a deterioration of ethical stan-
dards in the corporate workplace and rais-
es the question of whether regulatory or
legislative actions alone are sufficient to
ensure that the next generation of workers
demonstrate ethical decision making.
Although professional ethics contin-
ues to be a growing concern for busi-
nesses and government in the United
States, interest has surfaced about the
ethics of college students who are
tomorrow’s business leaders. The pres-
ent study focuses on college students’
perceptions of professional ethics and
how these perceptions can be evaluated
using academic situations as surrogates
for business situations.
BACKGROUND
In our research, we used cheating by
students as an indicator of future ethical
Students’ Perceptions of Business Ethics:
Using Cheating as a Surrogate
for Business Situations
LYNNETTE S. SMYTH CHARLES O. KRONCKE
GORDON COLLEGE COLLEGE OF MOUNT SAINT JOSEPH
BARNESVILLE, GEORGIA CINCINNATI, OHIO
JAMES R. DAVIS
ANDERSON UNIVERSITY
ANDERSON, SOUTH CAROLINA
TABSTRACT. Today’s college students are entering the
workplace at a time when
ethical issues are under greater scrutiny.
Thus, the authors examined students’ per-
ceptions of varying ethical situations, sam-
pling 786 college students at 3 institutions
(1 public, 1 Baptist affiliated, 1 Catholic
affiliated). The authors used an anonymous
survey and statistically analyzed student
assessment of questionable academic and
business situations. The survey results indi-
cated that (a) nonbusiness majors, on aver-
age, are more ethical than business majors;
(b) female students are more ethical than
male students; and (c) when analyzing the
results by class, upper division students are
more ethical than lower division students.
Keywords: business ethics, cheating and
ethics, student cheating
Copyright © 2009 Heldref Publications
230 Journal of Education for Business
behavior, which was, in part, based on
research by Sims (1993), who found
that past cheating is a strong predictor of
future cheating. Although cheating, the
college student’s most common avenue
for unethical behavior, is an ongoing
concern, it has greater potential conse-
quences for those students who become
tomorrow’s business professionals. It
is troubling that a significant percent-
age of college students engage in some
form of cheating (Diekhoff et al., 1996;
Grimes, 2002). Academic cheating can
be as simple as using crib notes in class
or plagiarizing others’ written assign-
ments, or it can be as extreme as using
unauthorized sources for take-home
exams or even hiring professionals to
write papers and prepare case reports. It
is certain that the continued growth of
the Internet is making the more flagrant
forms of cheating widely accessible to a
growing number of students.
Much research has been conducted
to examine collegiate cheating by vari-
ous demographic variables other than
academic major. Crown and Spiller
(1998) examined 16 previous studies on
the relation between gender and cheat-
ing, and found mixed statistical results.
Studies that focused on cheating and
the student’s academic year in college
also yielded inconsistent results. Baird
(1980) reported that upperclassmen
cheat less often; Lipson and McGav-
ern (1993) determined that sophomores
cheat the most; and Haines, Diekhoff,
LeBeff, and Clark’s (1986) research
showed no significant difference in
cheating behavior on the basis of aca-
demic classes. Davis and Welton (1991)
found that lower division students have
lower ethical standards than do upper
division students, a difference not found
between upper division students and
graduate students. Similarly, younger
students cheat more than their older
peers (Diekhoff et al., 1996; Graham,
Monday, O’Brien, & Steffen, 1994;
Haines et al.).
It is undoubtable that current trends in
the global business environment (and in
pending legislation) ensure that business
professionals will come under closer
scrutiny in the future and will likely be
expected to hold a higher level of ethi-
cal standards than has been the case in
recent years. Rocha and Teixeira (2006)
conducted a large multinational study
on academic cheating and found that
the magnitude of academic fraud is not
constant across countries and that there
is a positive correlation between the
amount of academic fraud in a country
and its level of real-world business cor-
ruption. It is clear that higher education
must give student exposure to ethics a
greater priority, beginning with ethical
decision making in students’ lives in
their academic communities. Cheating
is a form of unethical behavior, and
students who cheat in college today may
soon become professionals engaging in
similar unethical behaviors in the work-
place of tomorrow (Sims, 1993; Smith,
Davy, Rosenberg, & Haight, 2002).
DATA AND METHODOLOGY
To examine the prevalence of unethical
attitudes and behavior in the college envi-
ronment, we examined the issue of cheat-
ing at three institutions: one 2-year public
college and two private 4-year colleges.
Data
During the spring semester of 2006,
we surveyed 786 students regarding
their attitudes toward, and experiences
with, cheating and their perceptions of
professional ethics in business. We con-
ducted the survey at three institutions
with enrollments of less than 3,500
students (residential and commuter):
Anderson University, a 4-year private
Baptist-affiliated college in Anderson,
South Carolina; Gordon College, a 2-
year public college of the University
System of Georgia, located in Barnes-
ville, Georgia; and the College of Mount
Saint Joseph, a 4-year Catholic college
in Cincinnati, Ohio. In this article, we
denote these three colleges as Baptist
college, public college, and Catholic
college, respectively.
In an effort to obtain a broad cross-
section of students, we gave surveys dur-
ing classroom time in selected courses
representing the various majors at each
institution to sample approximately
10% of the student body at each institu-
tion. We provided all respondents the
assurances of confidentiality and ano-
nymity, an especially important require-
ment in researching student experiences
with cheating and unethical behavior.
Because of participant requirements,
each student was given the choice of
not participating in the study, and fewer
than 1% declined.
Students were given a set of ques-
tions regarding various aspects of
cheating that included generalized
inquiries into how often they cheated
in college, how often they observed
collegiate cheating and its detection by
faculty members, their willingness to
participate in cheating, and their sense
of ethics and acceptability of cheating.
In addition, students were asked to rate
on a 7-point Likert-type scale ranging
from 1 (not dishonest at all) to 7 (very
severe dishonesty) their assessments
of the dishonesty level of a number of
business and academic situations. A
number of demographic variables were
also collected for each respondent to
assess how student attitudes regarding
cheating may differ by demographic
grouping.
Methodology
We analyzed the student responses
in a variety of ways. To investigate the
internal consistency of the surveyed eth-
ical statements, Cronbach’s alpha was
calculated for the 26 statements with a
resulting value of .97. In addition, the
deletion of each statement one at a time
did not significantly increase the value
of alpha. This suggests that the items
measure the same underlying unidimen-
sional construct: ethical perspective.
For much of the analysis, the data
were processed using the chi-square sta-
tistical test for independence and the
corresponding nonparametric Cramer’s
V statistic to correct for the possible
influence of sample size. Cramer’s V
tests for the strength of the degree of
association among the variables being
tested, and thus the null hypothesis has
no degree of association. For this analy-
sis and given the large sample size, there
was little difference, if any, between the
p values of the two methods; therefore,
the Cramer’s V statistics were the pri-
mary basis for the conclusions given
for this research project. In addition,
in an effort to assess if business majors
have significantly different perceptions
of unethical behavior compared with
their nonbusiness majors counterparts,
the mean responses of each group were
March/April 2009 231
compared for each statement using a
simple two-tailed independent t test,
with a null hypothesis of equal means
between the two groups. For each state-
ment, the equal variance assumption of
the t test was evaluated using Levene’s F
test statistic; for those cases in which the
equal variance assumption was rejected,
the separate variance formulation was
used to form the t statistic value.
The primary focus of this article is on
two sets of situations, each containing 13
statements for evaluation: ethical situa-
tions in the academic environment and
similar situations in a business setting.
The statements can be categorized as
pertaining to lying and deceiving, cheat-
ing, cheating others, stealing, assisting
others in wrongdoing, and contemplat-
ing unethical behavior. It is important to
note that, although these academic and
business situations were paired for this
analysis, they were not paired on the
survey instrument, and thus respondents
considered each situation separately.
RESULTS
General Cheating
From the demographics collected, we
were able to determine that student bod-
ies at the surveyed colleges predomi-
nately comprised full-time students (an
average of 86%). Approximately 40%
of students were business majors. The
gender split was estimated at 57% (56.8)
female students, and 43% (43.1) male
students because 10% (10.1) of respon-
dents did not report their gender. From
the set of questions regarding cheating
in general, we found that 55% of the
respondents reported having cheated in
college at least once, a value that is
in line with two studies: (a) Grimes
(2002), in which 49.8% reported hav-
ing cheated, and (b) Smyth and Davis
(2004), in which 46% of respondents
reported having cheated in college at
MATTHIAS KAISER, KATE MILLAR, ERIK THORSTENSEN, and SANDYTOM.docx
MATTHIAS KAISER, KATE MILLAR, ERIK THORSTENSEN, and SANDYTOM.docx
MATTHIAS KAISER, KATE MILLAR, ERIK THORSTENSEN, and SANDYTOM.docx
MATTHIAS KAISER, KATE MILLAR, ERIK THORSTENSEN, and SANDYTOM.docx
MATTHIAS KAISER, KATE MILLAR, ERIK THORSTENSEN, and SANDYTOM.docx
MATTHIAS KAISER, KATE MILLAR, ERIK THORSTENSEN, and SANDYTOM.docx
MATTHIAS KAISER, KATE MILLAR, ERIK THORSTENSEN, and SANDYTOM.docx
MATTHIAS KAISER, KATE MILLAR, ERIK THORSTENSEN, and SANDYTOM.docx
MATTHIAS KAISER, KATE MILLAR, ERIK THORSTENSEN, and SANDYTOM.docx
MATTHIAS KAISER, KATE MILLAR, ERIK THORSTENSEN, and SANDYTOM.docx
MATTHIAS KAISER, KATE MILLAR, ERIK THORSTENSEN, and SANDYTOM.docx
MATTHIAS KAISER, KATE MILLAR, ERIK THORSTENSEN, and SANDYTOM.docx
MATTHIAS KAISER, KATE MILLAR, ERIK THORSTENSEN, and SANDYTOM.docx
MATTHIAS KAISER, KATE MILLAR, ERIK THORSTENSEN, and SANDYTOM.docx
MATTHIAS KAISER, KATE MILLAR, ERIK THORSTENSEN, and SANDYTOM.docx
MATTHIAS KAISER, KATE MILLAR, ERIK THORSTENSEN, and SANDYTOM.docx
MATTHIAS KAISER, KATE MILLAR, ERIK THORSTENSEN, and SANDYTOM.docx
MATTHIAS KAISER, KATE MILLAR, ERIK THORSTENSEN, and SANDYTOM.docx
MATTHIAS KAISER, KATE MILLAR, ERIK THORSTENSEN, and SANDYTOM.docx
MATTHIAS KAISER, KATE MILLAR, ERIK THORSTENSEN, and SANDYTOM.docx
MATTHIAS KAISER, KATE MILLAR, ERIK THORSTENSEN, and SANDYTOM.docx
MATTHIAS KAISER, KATE MILLAR, ERIK THORSTENSEN, and SANDYTOM.docx
MATTHIAS KAISER, KATE MILLAR, ERIK THORSTENSEN, and SANDYTOM.docx
MATTHIAS KAISER, KATE MILLAR, ERIK THORSTENSEN, and SANDYTOM.docx
MATTHIAS KAISER, KATE MILLAR, ERIK THORSTENSEN, and SANDYTOM.docx
MATTHIAS KAISER, KATE MILLAR, ERIK THORSTENSEN, and SANDYTOM.docx
MATTHIAS KAISER, KATE MILLAR, ERIK THORSTENSEN, and SANDYTOM.docx
MATTHIAS KAISER, KATE MILLAR, ERIK THORSTENSEN, and SANDYTOM.docx
MATTHIAS KAISER, KATE MILLAR, ERIK THORSTENSEN, and SANDYTOM.docx
MATTHIAS KAISER, KATE MILLAR, ERIK THORSTENSEN, and SANDYTOM.docx

More Related Content

Similar to MATTHIAS KAISER, KATE MILLAR, ERIK THORSTENSEN, and SANDYTOM.docx

Healthcare Management EthicsNo one would deny clinical and
Healthcare Management EthicsNo one would deny clinical andHealthcare Management EthicsNo one would deny clinical and
Healthcare Management EthicsNo one would deny clinical and
SusanaFurman449
 
Planning, Negotiating & Implementation Assignment
Planning, Negotiating & Implementation Assignment                 Planning, Negotiating & Implementation Assignment
Planning, Negotiating & Implementation Assignment
dessiechisomjj4
 
Chapter 5 theory and methodology
Chapter 5 theory and methodology Chapter 5 theory and methodology
Chapter 5 theory and methodology
grainne
 
©2016 Business Ethics Quarterly 264 (October 2016). ISSN 1.docx
 ©2016  Business Ethics Quarterly  264 (October 2016). ISSN 1.docx ©2016  Business Ethics Quarterly  264 (October 2016). ISSN 1.docx
©2016 Business Ethics Quarterly 264 (October 2016). ISSN 1.docx
mayank272369
 
Chapter 4 Administration Responsibility The Key to Administrativ.docx
Chapter 4 Administration Responsibility The Key to Administrativ.docxChapter 4 Administration Responsibility The Key to Administrativ.docx
Chapter 4 Administration Responsibility The Key to Administrativ.docx
keturahhazelhurst
 
Here is a research tip We write the theory into a separate sectio
Here is a research tip We write the theory into a separate sectioHere is a research tip We write the theory into a separate sectio
Here is a research tip We write the theory into a separate sectio
SusanaFurman449
 
A big challenge is that these are two different building types.docx
A big challenge is that these are two different building types.docxA big challenge is that these are two different building types.docx
A big challenge is that these are two different building types.docx
robert345678
 
systematic review info.pdf
systematic review info.pdfsystematic review info.pdf
systematic review info.pdf
raazia gul
 
CHAPTER 10 MIXED METHODS PROCEDURESHow would you write a mixed m
CHAPTER 10 MIXED METHODS PROCEDURESHow would you write a mixed mCHAPTER 10 MIXED METHODS PROCEDURESHow would you write a mixed m
CHAPTER 10 MIXED METHODS PROCEDURESHow would you write a mixed m
EstelaJeffery653
 
For your approved topic submitted in 2.2 Research Paper Topic Sel
For your approved topic submitted in 2.2 Research Paper Topic SelFor your approved topic submitted in 2.2 Research Paper Topic Sel
For your approved topic submitted in 2.2 Research Paper Topic Sel
ShainaBoling829
 

Similar to MATTHIAS KAISER, KATE MILLAR, ERIK THORSTENSEN, and SANDYTOM.docx (20)

Ethical Issues in Research
Ethical Issues in ResearchEthical Issues in Research
Ethical Issues in Research
 
Healthcare Management EthicsNo one would deny clinical and
Healthcare Management EthicsNo one would deny clinical andHealthcare Management EthicsNo one would deny clinical and
Healthcare Management EthicsNo one would deny clinical and
 
Planning, Negotiating & Implementation Assignment
Planning, Negotiating & Implementation Assignment                 Planning, Negotiating & Implementation Assignment
Planning, Negotiating & Implementation Assignment
 
Ethics report
Ethics reportEthics report
Ethics report
 
Chapter 5 theory and methodology
Chapter 5 theory and methodology Chapter 5 theory and methodology
Chapter 5 theory and methodology
 
©2016 Business Ethics Quarterly 264 (October 2016). ISSN 1.docx
 ©2016  Business Ethics Quarterly  264 (October 2016). ISSN 1.docx ©2016  Business Ethics Quarterly  264 (October 2016). ISSN 1.docx
©2016 Business Ethics Quarterly 264 (October 2016). ISSN 1.docx
 
ebp-resourceguide-final copy
ebp-resourceguide-final copyebp-resourceguide-final copy
ebp-resourceguide-final copy
 
Chapter 4 Administration Responsibility The Key to Administrativ.docx
Chapter 4 Administration Responsibility The Key to Administrativ.docxChapter 4 Administration Responsibility The Key to Administrativ.docx
Chapter 4 Administration Responsibility The Key to Administrativ.docx
 
Here is a research tip We write the theory into a separate sectio
Here is a research tip We write the theory into a separate sectioHere is a research tip We write the theory into a separate sectio
Here is a research tip We write the theory into a separate sectio
 
Action Research - David Avison
Action Research  - David AvisonAction Research  - David Avison
Action Research - David Avison
 
A big challenge is that these are two different building types.docx
A big challenge is that these are two different building types.docxA big challenge is that these are two different building types.docx
A big challenge is that these are two different building types.docx
 
Identifying Structures in Social Conversations in NSCLC Patients through the ...
Identifying Structures in Social Conversations in NSCLC Patients through the ...Identifying Structures in Social Conversations in NSCLC Patients through the ...
Identifying Structures in Social Conversations in NSCLC Patients through the ...
 
Identifying Structures in Social Conversations in NSCLC Patients through the ...
Identifying Structures in Social Conversations in NSCLC Patients through the ...Identifying Structures in Social Conversations in NSCLC Patients through the ...
Identifying Structures in Social Conversations in NSCLC Patients through the ...
 
ihpsrppt1latestdec2014-150121003700-conversion-gate01 (1).pdf
ihpsrppt1latestdec2014-150121003700-conversion-gate01 (1).pdfihpsrppt1latestdec2014-150121003700-conversion-gate01 (1).pdf
ihpsrppt1latestdec2014-150121003700-conversion-gate01 (1).pdf
 
Why are we running this course?
Why are we running this course?Why are we running this course?
Why are we running this course?
 
Presentation 1 letr & ethics
Presentation 1   letr & ethicsPresentation 1   letr & ethics
Presentation 1 letr & ethics
 
systematic review info.pdf
systematic review info.pdfsystematic review info.pdf
systematic review info.pdf
 
decision.support
decision.supportdecision.support
decision.support
 
CHAPTER 10 MIXED METHODS PROCEDURESHow would you write a mixed m
CHAPTER 10 MIXED METHODS PROCEDURESHow would you write a mixed mCHAPTER 10 MIXED METHODS PROCEDURESHow would you write a mixed m
CHAPTER 10 MIXED METHODS PROCEDURESHow would you write a mixed m
 
For your approved topic submitted in 2.2 Research Paper Topic Sel
For your approved topic submitted in 2.2 Research Paper Topic SelFor your approved topic submitted in 2.2 Research Paper Topic Sel
For your approved topic submitted in 2.2 Research Paper Topic Sel
 

More from andreecapon

MGMT 511Location ProblemGeorge Heller was so successful in.docx
MGMT 511Location ProblemGeorge Heller was so successful in.docxMGMT 511Location ProblemGeorge Heller was so successful in.docx
MGMT 511Location ProblemGeorge Heller was so successful in.docx
andreecapon
 
MGMT 464From Snowboarders to Lawnmowers Case Study Case An.docx
MGMT 464From Snowboarders to Lawnmowers Case Study Case An.docxMGMT 464From Snowboarders to Lawnmowers Case Study Case An.docx
MGMT 464From Snowboarders to Lawnmowers Case Study Case An.docx
andreecapon
 
MG345_Lead from Middle.pptLeading from the Middle Exe.docx
MG345_Lead from Middle.pptLeading from the Middle Exe.docxMG345_Lead from Middle.pptLeading from the Middle Exe.docx
MG345_Lead from Middle.pptLeading from the Middle Exe.docx
andreecapon
 
MGMT 345Phase 2 IPBusiness MemoToWarehouse ManagerFrom[You.docx
MGMT 345Phase 2 IPBusiness MemoToWarehouse ManagerFrom[You.docxMGMT 345Phase 2 IPBusiness MemoToWarehouse ManagerFrom[You.docx
MGMT 345Phase 2 IPBusiness MemoToWarehouse ManagerFrom[You.docx
andreecapon
 
MGMT 3720 – Organizational BehaviorEXAM 3(CH. 9, 10, 11, & 12).docx
MGMT 3720 – Organizational BehaviorEXAM 3(CH. 9, 10, 11, & 12).docxMGMT 3720 – Organizational BehaviorEXAM 3(CH. 9, 10, 11, & 12).docx
MGMT 3720 – Organizational BehaviorEXAM 3(CH. 9, 10, 11, & 12).docx
andreecapon
 
Mexico, Page 1 Running Head MEXICO’S CULTURAL, ECONOMI.docx
Mexico, Page 1  Running Head MEXICO’S CULTURAL, ECONOMI.docxMexico, Page 1  Running Head MEXICO’S CULTURAL, ECONOMI.docx
Mexico, Page 1 Running Head MEXICO’S CULTURAL, ECONOMI.docx
andreecapon
 
MGM316-1401B-01Quesadra D. GoodrumClass Discussion Phase2.docx
MGM316-1401B-01Quesadra D. GoodrumClass Discussion Phase2.docxMGM316-1401B-01Quesadra D. GoodrumClass Discussion Phase2.docx
MGM316-1401B-01Quesadra D. GoodrumClass Discussion Phase2.docx
andreecapon
 
METROPOLITAN PLANNING ANDENVIRONMENTAL ISSUESn May 2008, the N.docx
METROPOLITAN PLANNING ANDENVIRONMENTAL ISSUESn May 2008, the N.docxMETROPOLITAN PLANNING ANDENVIRONMENTAL ISSUESn May 2008, the N.docx
METROPOLITAN PLANNING ANDENVIRONMENTAL ISSUESn May 2008, the N.docx
andreecapon
 
Methods of Moral Decision Making REL 330 Christian Moralit.docx
Methods of Moral Decision Making       REL 330 Christian Moralit.docxMethods of Moral Decision Making       REL 330 Christian Moralit.docx
Methods of Moral Decision Making REL 330 Christian Moralit.docx
andreecapon
 
MEPS_Inpatient Stay database.csduidpiddupersidevntidxeventrnerhevi.docx
MEPS_Inpatient Stay database.csduidpiddupersidevntidxeventrnerhevi.docxMEPS_Inpatient Stay database.csduidpiddupersidevntidxeventrnerhevi.docx
MEPS_Inpatient Stay database.csduidpiddupersidevntidxeventrnerhevi.docx
andreecapon
 
METHODS TO STOP DIFFERENT CYBER CRIMES .docx
METHODS TO STOP DIFFERENT CYBER CRIMES                            .docxMETHODS TO STOP DIFFERENT CYBER CRIMES                            .docx
METHODS TO STOP DIFFERENT CYBER CRIMES .docx
andreecapon
 
Mexico The Third War Security Weekly Wednesday, February 18.docx
Mexico The Third War Security Weekly Wednesday, February 18.docxMexico The Third War Security Weekly Wednesday, February 18.docx
Mexico The Third War Security Weekly Wednesday, February 18.docx
andreecapon
 
Mercy College .docx
Mercy College                                                   .docxMercy College                                                   .docx
Mercy College .docx
andreecapon
 
Merger AnalysisMerger Analysis Case Study© 2007 South UniversityFr.docx
Merger AnalysisMerger Analysis Case Study© 2007 South UniversityFr.docxMerger AnalysisMerger Analysis Case Study© 2007 South UniversityFr.docx
Merger AnalysisMerger Analysis Case Study© 2007 South UniversityFr.docx
andreecapon
 
MGMT 301 EOY Group” Case Study and Power Point Presentation G.docx
MGMT 301 EOY Group” Case Study and Power Point Presentation G.docxMGMT 301 EOY Group” Case Study and Power Point Presentation G.docx
MGMT 301 EOY Group” Case Study and Power Point Presentation G.docx
andreecapon
 
MGMT 464New Manager’s Case Study Case Analysis Worksheet #.docx
MGMT 464New Manager’s Case Study Case Analysis Worksheet #.docxMGMT 464New Manager’s Case Study Case Analysis Worksheet #.docx
MGMT 464New Manager’s Case Study Case Analysis Worksheet #.docx
andreecapon
 
META-INFMANIFEST.MFManifest-Version 1.0.classpath.docx
META-INFMANIFEST.MFManifest-Version 1.0.classpath.docxMETA-INFMANIFEST.MFManifest-Version 1.0.classpath.docx
META-INFMANIFEST.MFManifest-Version 1.0.classpath.docx
andreecapon
 
Menu Management Options· · APRN504 - 5886 - HEALTH POLICY .docx
Menu Management Options· · APRN504 - 5886 - HEALTH POLICY .docxMenu Management Options· · APRN504 - 5886 - HEALTH POLICY .docx
Menu Management Options· · APRN504 - 5886 - HEALTH POLICY .docx
andreecapon
 
MGMT 673 Problem Set 51. For each of the following economic cond.docx
MGMT 673 Problem Set 51. For each of the following economic cond.docxMGMT 673 Problem Set 51. For each of the following economic cond.docx
MGMT 673 Problem Set 51. For each of the following economic cond.docx
andreecapon
 
Mental Illness Stigma and the Fundamental Components ofSuppo.docx
Mental Illness Stigma and the Fundamental Components ofSuppo.docxMental Illness Stigma and the Fundamental Components ofSuppo.docx
Mental Illness Stigma and the Fundamental Components ofSuppo.docx
andreecapon
 

More from andreecapon (20)

MGMT 511Location ProblemGeorge Heller was so successful in.docx
MGMT 511Location ProblemGeorge Heller was so successful in.docxMGMT 511Location ProblemGeorge Heller was so successful in.docx
MGMT 511Location ProblemGeorge Heller was so successful in.docx
 
MGMT 464From Snowboarders to Lawnmowers Case Study Case An.docx
MGMT 464From Snowboarders to Lawnmowers Case Study Case An.docxMGMT 464From Snowboarders to Lawnmowers Case Study Case An.docx
MGMT 464From Snowboarders to Lawnmowers Case Study Case An.docx
 
MG345_Lead from Middle.pptLeading from the Middle Exe.docx
MG345_Lead from Middle.pptLeading from the Middle Exe.docxMG345_Lead from Middle.pptLeading from the Middle Exe.docx
MG345_Lead from Middle.pptLeading from the Middle Exe.docx
 
MGMT 345Phase 2 IPBusiness MemoToWarehouse ManagerFrom[You.docx
MGMT 345Phase 2 IPBusiness MemoToWarehouse ManagerFrom[You.docxMGMT 345Phase 2 IPBusiness MemoToWarehouse ManagerFrom[You.docx
MGMT 345Phase 2 IPBusiness MemoToWarehouse ManagerFrom[You.docx
 
MGMT 3720 – Organizational BehaviorEXAM 3(CH. 9, 10, 11, & 12).docx
MGMT 3720 – Organizational BehaviorEXAM 3(CH. 9, 10, 11, & 12).docxMGMT 3720 – Organizational BehaviorEXAM 3(CH. 9, 10, 11, & 12).docx
MGMT 3720 – Organizational BehaviorEXAM 3(CH. 9, 10, 11, & 12).docx
 
Mexico, Page 1 Running Head MEXICO’S CULTURAL, ECONOMI.docx
Mexico, Page 1  Running Head MEXICO’S CULTURAL, ECONOMI.docxMexico, Page 1  Running Head MEXICO’S CULTURAL, ECONOMI.docx
Mexico, Page 1 Running Head MEXICO’S CULTURAL, ECONOMI.docx
 
MGM316-1401B-01Quesadra D. GoodrumClass Discussion Phase2.docx
MGM316-1401B-01Quesadra D. GoodrumClass Discussion Phase2.docxMGM316-1401B-01Quesadra D. GoodrumClass Discussion Phase2.docx
MGM316-1401B-01Quesadra D. GoodrumClass Discussion Phase2.docx
 
METROPOLITAN PLANNING ANDENVIRONMENTAL ISSUESn May 2008, the N.docx
METROPOLITAN PLANNING ANDENVIRONMENTAL ISSUESn May 2008, the N.docxMETROPOLITAN PLANNING ANDENVIRONMENTAL ISSUESn May 2008, the N.docx
METROPOLITAN PLANNING ANDENVIRONMENTAL ISSUESn May 2008, the N.docx
 
Methods of Moral Decision Making REL 330 Christian Moralit.docx
Methods of Moral Decision Making       REL 330 Christian Moralit.docxMethods of Moral Decision Making       REL 330 Christian Moralit.docx
Methods of Moral Decision Making REL 330 Christian Moralit.docx
 
MEPS_Inpatient Stay database.csduidpiddupersidevntidxeventrnerhevi.docx
MEPS_Inpatient Stay database.csduidpiddupersidevntidxeventrnerhevi.docxMEPS_Inpatient Stay database.csduidpiddupersidevntidxeventrnerhevi.docx
MEPS_Inpatient Stay database.csduidpiddupersidevntidxeventrnerhevi.docx
 
METHODS TO STOP DIFFERENT CYBER CRIMES .docx
METHODS TO STOP DIFFERENT CYBER CRIMES                            .docxMETHODS TO STOP DIFFERENT CYBER CRIMES                            .docx
METHODS TO STOP DIFFERENT CYBER CRIMES .docx
 
Mexico The Third War Security Weekly Wednesday, February 18.docx
Mexico The Third War Security Weekly Wednesday, February 18.docxMexico The Third War Security Weekly Wednesday, February 18.docx
Mexico The Third War Security Weekly Wednesday, February 18.docx
 
Mercy College .docx
Mercy College                                                   .docxMercy College                                                   .docx
Mercy College .docx
 
Merger AnalysisMerger Analysis Case Study© 2007 South UniversityFr.docx
Merger AnalysisMerger Analysis Case Study© 2007 South UniversityFr.docxMerger AnalysisMerger Analysis Case Study© 2007 South UniversityFr.docx
Merger AnalysisMerger Analysis Case Study© 2007 South UniversityFr.docx
 
MGMT 301 EOY Group” Case Study and Power Point Presentation G.docx
MGMT 301 EOY Group” Case Study and Power Point Presentation G.docxMGMT 301 EOY Group” Case Study and Power Point Presentation G.docx
MGMT 301 EOY Group” Case Study and Power Point Presentation G.docx
 
MGMT 464New Manager’s Case Study Case Analysis Worksheet #.docx
MGMT 464New Manager’s Case Study Case Analysis Worksheet #.docxMGMT 464New Manager’s Case Study Case Analysis Worksheet #.docx
MGMT 464New Manager’s Case Study Case Analysis Worksheet #.docx
 
META-INFMANIFEST.MFManifest-Version 1.0.classpath.docx
META-INFMANIFEST.MFManifest-Version 1.0.classpath.docxMETA-INFMANIFEST.MFManifest-Version 1.0.classpath.docx
META-INFMANIFEST.MFManifest-Version 1.0.classpath.docx
 
Menu Management Options· · APRN504 - 5886 - HEALTH POLICY .docx
Menu Management Options· · APRN504 - 5886 - HEALTH POLICY .docxMenu Management Options· · APRN504 - 5886 - HEALTH POLICY .docx
Menu Management Options· · APRN504 - 5886 - HEALTH POLICY .docx
 
MGMT 673 Problem Set 51. For each of the following economic cond.docx
MGMT 673 Problem Set 51. For each of the following economic cond.docxMGMT 673 Problem Set 51. For each of the following economic cond.docx
MGMT 673 Problem Set 51. For each of the following economic cond.docx
 
Mental Illness Stigma and the Fundamental Components ofSuppo.docx
Mental Illness Stigma and the Fundamental Components ofSuppo.docxMental Illness Stigma and the Fundamental Components ofSuppo.docx
Mental Illness Stigma and the Fundamental Components ofSuppo.docx
 

Recently uploaded

Spellings Wk 4 and Wk 5 for Grade 4 at CAPS
Spellings Wk 4 and Wk 5 for Grade 4 at CAPSSpellings Wk 4 and Wk 5 for Grade 4 at CAPS
Spellings Wk 4 and Wk 5 for Grade 4 at CAPS
AnaAcapella
 
QUATER-1-PE-HEALTH-LC2- this is just a sample of unpacked lesson
QUATER-1-PE-HEALTH-LC2- this is just a sample of unpacked lessonQUATER-1-PE-HEALTH-LC2- this is just a sample of unpacked lesson
QUATER-1-PE-HEALTH-LC2- this is just a sample of unpacked lesson
httgc7rh9c
 

Recently uploaded (20)

How to setup Pycharm environment for Odoo 17.pptx
How to setup Pycharm environment for Odoo 17.pptxHow to setup Pycharm environment for Odoo 17.pptx
How to setup Pycharm environment for Odoo 17.pptx
 
How to Add New Custom Addons Path in Odoo 17
How to Add New Custom Addons Path in Odoo 17How to Add New Custom Addons Path in Odoo 17
How to Add New Custom Addons Path in Odoo 17
 
Our Environment Class 10 Science Notes pdf
Our Environment Class 10 Science Notes pdfOur Environment Class 10 Science Notes pdf
Our Environment Class 10 Science Notes pdf
 
REMIFENTANIL: An Ultra short acting opioid.pptx
REMIFENTANIL: An Ultra short acting opioid.pptxREMIFENTANIL: An Ultra short acting opioid.pptx
REMIFENTANIL: An Ultra short acting opioid.pptx
 
FICTIONAL SALESMAN/SALESMAN SNSW 2024.pdf
FICTIONAL SALESMAN/SALESMAN SNSW 2024.pdfFICTIONAL SALESMAN/SALESMAN SNSW 2024.pdf
FICTIONAL SALESMAN/SALESMAN SNSW 2024.pdf
 
Spellings Wk 4 and Wk 5 for Grade 4 at CAPS
Spellings Wk 4 and Wk 5 for Grade 4 at CAPSSpellings Wk 4 and Wk 5 for Grade 4 at CAPS
Spellings Wk 4 and Wk 5 for Grade 4 at CAPS
 
FSB Advising Checklist - Orientation 2024
FSB Advising Checklist - Orientation 2024FSB Advising Checklist - Orientation 2024
FSB Advising Checklist - Orientation 2024
 
PANDITA RAMABAI- Indian political thought GENDER.pptx
PANDITA RAMABAI- Indian political thought GENDER.pptxPANDITA RAMABAI- Indian political thought GENDER.pptx
PANDITA RAMABAI- Indian political thought GENDER.pptx
 
Simple, Complex, and Compound Sentences Exercises.pdf
Simple, Complex, and Compound Sentences Exercises.pdfSimple, Complex, and Compound Sentences Exercises.pdf
Simple, Complex, and Compound Sentences Exercises.pdf
 
What is 3 Way Matching Process in Odoo 17.pptx
What is 3 Way Matching Process in Odoo 17.pptxWhat is 3 Way Matching Process in Odoo 17.pptx
What is 3 Way Matching Process in Odoo 17.pptx
 
NO1 Top Black Magic Specialist In Lahore Black magic In Pakistan Kala Ilam Ex...
NO1 Top Black Magic Specialist In Lahore Black magic In Pakistan Kala Ilam Ex...NO1 Top Black Magic Specialist In Lahore Black magic In Pakistan Kala Ilam Ex...
NO1 Top Black Magic Specialist In Lahore Black magic In Pakistan Kala Ilam Ex...
 
COMMUNICATING NEGATIVE NEWS - APPROACHES .pptx
COMMUNICATING NEGATIVE NEWS - APPROACHES .pptxCOMMUNICATING NEGATIVE NEWS - APPROACHES .pptx
COMMUNICATING NEGATIVE NEWS - APPROACHES .pptx
 
OSCM Unit 2_Operations Processes & Systems
OSCM Unit 2_Operations Processes & SystemsOSCM Unit 2_Operations Processes & Systems
OSCM Unit 2_Operations Processes & Systems
 
Towards a code of practice for AI in AT.pptx
Towards a code of practice for AI in AT.pptxTowards a code of practice for AI in AT.pptx
Towards a code of practice for AI in AT.pptx
 
Introduction to TechSoup’s Digital Marketing Services and Use Cases
Introduction to TechSoup’s Digital Marketing  Services and Use CasesIntroduction to TechSoup’s Digital Marketing  Services and Use Cases
Introduction to TechSoup’s Digital Marketing Services and Use Cases
 
How to Create and Manage Wizard in Odoo 17
How to Create and Manage Wizard in Odoo 17How to Create and Manage Wizard in Odoo 17
How to Create and Manage Wizard in Odoo 17
 
TỔNG ÔN TẬP THI VÀO LỚP 10 MÔN TIẾNG ANH NĂM HỌC 2023 - 2024 CÓ ĐÁP ÁN (NGỮ Â...
TỔNG ÔN TẬP THI VÀO LỚP 10 MÔN TIẾNG ANH NĂM HỌC 2023 - 2024 CÓ ĐÁP ÁN (NGỮ Â...TỔNG ÔN TẬP THI VÀO LỚP 10 MÔN TIẾNG ANH NĂM HỌC 2023 - 2024 CÓ ĐÁP ÁN (NGỮ Â...
TỔNG ÔN TẬP THI VÀO LỚP 10 MÔN TIẾNG ANH NĂM HỌC 2023 - 2024 CÓ ĐÁP ÁN (NGỮ Â...
 
QUATER-1-PE-HEALTH-LC2- this is just a sample of unpacked lesson
QUATER-1-PE-HEALTH-LC2- this is just a sample of unpacked lessonQUATER-1-PE-HEALTH-LC2- this is just a sample of unpacked lesson
QUATER-1-PE-HEALTH-LC2- this is just a sample of unpacked lesson
 
Understanding Accommodations and Modifications
Understanding  Accommodations and ModificationsUnderstanding  Accommodations and Modifications
Understanding Accommodations and Modifications
 
Beyond_Borders_Understanding_Anime_and_Manga_Fandom_A_Comprehensive_Audience_...
Beyond_Borders_Understanding_Anime_and_Manga_Fandom_A_Comprehensive_Audience_...Beyond_Borders_Understanding_Anime_and_Manga_Fandom_A_Comprehensive_Audience_...
Beyond_Borders_Understanding_Anime_and_Manga_Fandom_A_Comprehensive_Audience_...
 

MATTHIAS KAISER, KATE MILLAR, ERIK THORSTENSEN, and SANDYTOM.docx

  • 1. MATTHIAS KAISER, KATE MILLAR, ERIK THORSTENSEN, and SANDY TOMKINS DEVELOPING THE ETHICAL MATRIX AS A DECISION SUPPORT FRAMEWORK: GM FISH AS A CASE STUDY (Accepted in revised form October 25, 2006) ABSTRACT. The Ethical Matrix was developed to help decision-makers explore the ethical issues raised by agri-food biotechnologies. Over the decade since its inception the Ethical Matrix has been used by a number of organizations and the philosophical basis of the framework has been discussed and analyzed extensively. The role of tools such as the Ethical Matrix in public policy decision-making has received increasing attention. In order to further develop the methodological aspects of the Ethical Matrix method, work was carried out to study the potential role of the Ethical Matrix as a decision support framework. When considering which frameworks to apply when analyzing the ethical dimensions of the application of agri-food bio- technologies, it is important to clarify the substantive nature of
  • 2. any prospective framework. In order to further investigate this issue, reflections on the neologism ‘‘ethical soundness’’ of an ethical framework are presented here. This concept is introduced in order to provide more structured evaluations of a range of ethical tools, including ethical frameworks such as the Ethical Matrix. As well as examining the philosophical dimensions of the method, theoretical analysis and literature studies were combined with stakeholder engagement exercises and consultations in order to review the Ethical Matrix from a user perspective. This work resulted in the development of an Ethical Matrix Manual, which is intended to act as a guide for potential user groups. KEY WORDS: biotechnology, decision support, Ethical frameworks, Ethical Matrix, GM fish 1. INTRODUCTION One of the first decision-support frameworks to be developed to explore the ethical issues raised by agri-food biotechnologies was the Ethical Matrix, proposed by Mepham of the University of Nottingham in the
  • 3. mid 1990s. Since then, the Matrix has been applied to a number of case studies, such as bST, xenotransplantation and bioremediation, by Mepham and his col- leagues at the University of Nottingham (e.g., Mepham, 1996, 2000, 2001; Mepham and Tomkins, 2003; Moore, 1996; Millar, 2002) and in the Food Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics (2007) 20:65– 80 DOI 10.1007/s10806-006-9023-8 � Springer 2007 Ethics Council, and by others working at several different institutions (e.g., Kaiser and Forsberg, 2001; Kaiser, 2004; Schroeder and Palmer, 2003; FAO/WHO, 2003; Chadwick et al., 2003). Over the decade since its incep- tion, the Ethical Matrix has attracted considerable attention from specialists in the field of bioethics, and the philosophical and methodological basis of the framework has been discussed and analyzed extensively.
  • 4. Therefore, we shall not attempt to survey and present all pertinent aspects and justifica- tions of the Ethical Matrix in this paper (refer to Mepham et al., 2006 and cf. also Forsberg, 2007). The role of tools such as the Ethical Matrix in public policy decision- making has received increasing attention over the last few years, with a number of practitioners exploring the use of new and novel frameworks and tools, in particular in regard to applied ethics. In order to further develop the methodological aspects of the Ethical Matrix method, the authors have studied the potential role of the Ethical Matrix as a decision support frame- work in the field of biotechnology and food regulation. Theoretical analysis and literature studies were combined with stakeholder engagement exercises and consultations in order to study various aspects of the Ethical Matrix
  • 5. from a user perspective. This work resulted in the development of an Ethical Matrix Manual (Mepham et al., 2006). The aim of the paper is to clarify some general evaluation criteria for the uses of the Ethical Matrix as a decision support framework, and to exemplify briefly two participatory approaches. 2. ETHICAL SOUNDNESS OF THE FRAMEWORKS When considering which frameworks are appropriate for use when ana- lyzing the ethical dimensions of agri-food biotechnologies, it is important to clarify the substantive nature of any prospective framework. In order to investigate this, we have attempted to present some reflections on the neologism ‘‘ethical soundness’’ of an ethical framework. This concept is introduced in order to provide more structured evaluations of a wider range of ethical frameworks. 1
  • 6. The term ‘‘soundness’’ in this context is adapted from the philosophical work on logic. An inference is normally termed ‘‘sound’’ if, and only if, the logical form of the argument is valid (i.e., truth preserving) and all its premises are true. An axiom system is sound if, and only if, all the axioms and theorems are true under all interpretations. Accordingly, one would say that an ethical argument is sound if, and only if, the logical form of the normative argument is valid (e.g., in a version of deontic logic, namely, a 1 For a list of several such frameworks see the website of the project Ethical Bio TA Tools: http://www.ethicaltools.info/. MATTHIAS KAISER ET AL.66 logic of normative concepts) and all its premises are either true or valid (here in the sense of the German term ‘‘gültig’’; ‘‘normative rightness’’). It could
  • 7. then be said that a normative system (theory) is sound if, and only if, all its axioms and derived theorems are valid under all normative interpretations. However, an ethical framework is not to be confused with a particular ethical theory. An ethical theory would, ideally, distinguish all morally right from all morally wrong or morally neutral actions. A framework on the other hand only assists us in reaching a reflected ethical insight or normative conclusion. A framework is not composed of statements that together make up a normative theory; rather it is a tool on a meta-level, since it makes use of a variety of ethical theories and normative arguments. Given this variety, the above description of ethical soundness cannot apply to such a frame- work, since viewpoints might be included that arise from very different theoretical conceptions and that may collide with each other. Thus, ethical
  • 8. soundness of a framework cannot mean normative validity under all interpretations. But a framework is also a practical and pragmatic tool, since it should allow us to extract all relevant information for decision- making involving ethical issues, without necessarily implying a unique an- swer to all issues. Ethical frameworks are not material objects, or even sets of statements; rather, they are conceptual or procedural devices, which are designed to facilitate explicit ethical decision-making, typically by a body consisting of several individuals with varying viewpoints. They are tools that are dependent on the competency of users, i.e., as moral individuals. Given this definition of an ethical framework, the use of ethical soundness in this context is therefore conjectural and non-traditional, and requires further analysis. This analysis should take account of the essential function of
  • 9. ethical frameworks to assist public bodies in making ethically justified decisions. The question then arises, what should be preserved and accentuated if one transposes ethical soundness from normative ethical theory to ethical frameworks that are developed to aid decision-making. The intuitive notion is that a decision support framework works well, i.e., is ethically sound, if it allows competent access to all relevant normative considerations and facts of an issue, and leaves the users free to draw conclusions based upon their own priorities, but informed by insights into alternative viewpoints. Frameworks that have an inbuilt bias towards a particular ethical position should not be regarded as ‘‘ethically sound.’’ Similarly, frameworks used within a given knowledge base that systematically neglect information that
  • 10. is crucial for certain normative viewpoints, are also not ethically sound. All frameworks should ensure that the normative reasoning put forward by potential users is transparent to all external reviewers and evaluators. GM FISH AS A CASE STUDY 67 Therefore it is proposed that an ethical framework is ethically sound, if and only if, its application produces understanding of ethically relevant con- siderations in such a way that within a given body of knowledge and on con- dition of its competent use no further considerations would decisively alter the normative conclusions drawn from the framework by the users. Such a definition of soundness of an ethical framework in some way parallels proposed definitions of, e.g., scientific objectivity (cf. Føllesdal et al., 1986, pp. 354–360). 2 It is clear that a definition of this kind with an
  • 11. inbuilt counterfactual clause cannot be checked in any direct manner as to whether it applies or not. However, a test of ethical soundness is to ask whether certain ideal criteria are sufficiently respected in a competent use of a framework, such as the Ethical Matrix. These criteria could then be seen as indicators of ethical soundness, in much the same way as one talks of indicators of sustainability etc. The indicators would be such that neglecting them would weaken the value of the framework as a decision support tool and typically lead to different normative conclusions or different reasons for given conclusions. It should also be recognized that these indicators could be used to evaluate the performance of several alternative ethical frame- works (of which the Ethical Matrix is just one). Thus, in the decision-making context addressed here, i.e., a context
  • 12. where a decision-maker is faced with competing value claims in society and a plurality of ethical theories appealed to by various groups, several con- siderations enter the picture that may indicate the ethical soundness of frameworks. The main properties of ethically sound frameworks, as we tentatively see them, are the following: (1) Inclusion of values at stake (2) Transparency (3) Multiplicity of viewpoints (4) Exposition of case-relevant ethically-relevant aspects (5) Inclusion of ethical arguments 2.1. Inclusion of Values at Stake Moral decisions represent choices between different moral impacts or assessments. Therefore, an explicit listing of all the values that are at stake in a decision is instrumental for the ethical soundness of the framework. If a relevant value is overlooked, the outcome of the moral
  • 13. evaluation will typically be different. 2 Føllesdal et al. (1986) characterizes scientific objectivity as the ideal that is reached when a given scientific claim would not be evaluated differently by adding more pertinent facts in its justification. MATTHIAS KAISER ET AL.68 2.2. Transparency One of the main challenges of ethical frameworks is to overcome the opaqueness of moral decision-making. The challenge is thus that the process of decision-making becomes transparent. Transparency is a precondition for (a) allowing a wide and inclusive social debate on the issue, and (b) making decisions that are socially robust and not immediately challenged by public voices on the basis of information gaps. All too often political actors and
  • 14. decision-makers seem to assume that ethical positions are simply taken, without clarification of why and how they are reached and how they could be challenged. This opacity leads to instability in moral evaluation. 3 2.3. Multiplicity of Viewpoints Democratic societies are by definition pluralist societies, and this extends naturally to the sphere of ethics. Any given or automatic dominance of a particular ethical viewpoint, be it a utilitarian viewpoint or Kantian ethics, etc., would infringe on the rights of those who adhere to alternative ethical viewpoints. Not seriously considering other ethical viewpoints would also be deeply unjust and run counter to ideals of equity. An ethical framework should, therefore, take account of this multiplicity of known ethical view- points. To the extent that this is not guaranteed by the competent use of a
  • 15. framework, the ethical soundness of the framework is threatened, since consideration of alternative conceptions may alter the outcome. 2.4. Exposition of Case-specific Ethically Relevant Aspects Ethical decision-making presupposes that all ethically relevant aspects of the issue are adequately accounted for. As well as appropriately specified ethical principles, ethically relevant aspects include factual information, the inclusion of which potentially contributes to strengthening or weakening a particular moral outcome or judgment. 2.5. Inclusion of Ethical Arguments Frameworks seem to differ in regard to the extent to which they aspire to represent ethical argumentation. In ethical theory, the ideal is that an ethical position is reached through a reflective argument, based on the available 3 Even transparent decisions may of course be challenged, but then disagreements may either
  • 16. point to a lack of specific information that was not duly considered, or to a simple disagreement on the weighing of values. Currently we see that a number of decisions are challenged simply on the basis of being ‘‘unethical’’ or for presenting the wrong ethical position. Ethical frameworks aspire to extend beyond this rhetoric by ensuring the transparency of the ethical reasoning behind any given decision. GM FISH AS A CASE STUDY 69 information and the ethical principles of the theory. This applies in par- ticular to situations where different principles run into conflict and one has to weigh and balance them. Knowledge of the arguments behind particular decisions enables rational critique and debate. Thus, we might see this aspect as instrumental for the ethical soundness of a framework. The concept of ethical soundness was applied to evaluate the suitability
  • 17. of different candidates to operate as ethical tools in democratic decision- making processes. For instance, a committee approach (that might be ranked as a procedural decision support framework) might not easily, or necessarily, satisfy all requirements for transparency, e.g., in terms of how the final recommendation was reached and who discussed what. However, it is clearly very difficult to provide a definite characterization of all possible frameworks. Examining the Ethical Matrix, and the process for translating the prin- ciples for such a matrix, reveals that the criterion of transparency seems optimally to be realized. A judgment formed on the basis of a Matrix shows clearly what information was available and which considerations were judged to be dominant and how they were weighed. Similarly, one can say that the multiplicity of viewpoints is optimally accounted for by
  • 18. the explicit listing of stakeholder viewpoints. In principle, there is also a good chance that an Ethical Matrix will account for all ethically relevant information and all ethical arguments. Yet, there are some caveats: these features are dependent on the information that is available and included in the analysis. Typically, this will depend on the scientific training and ethical competence of the users of the framework, such as organizers of a workshop and the participants or a committee secretariat. To the extent that all users are challenged by information overload, it may be difficult to be at the cutting edge of all issues. This may be reflected, for example, in the quality of the information included in the Matrix. In spite of this caveat, it seems that the probability of including all relevant values at stake would be high, since this is a criterion for compiling a list of interest groups. In
  • 19. summary, the Ethical Matrix would appear to score relatively highly on the indicators of ethical soundness. One of the purposes of conducting an exercise to determine ethical soundness is to recognize that not all frameworks score alike under the five specified criteria. It appears that no framework could easily fulfill all the ethical soundness criteria. This may be due to the following factors: (i) the list of conditions may not really be comprehensive for this purpose; (ii) some frameworks may consciously be built upon leaving out certain aspects in order to optimize other aspects, e.g., playing down ethical argument in favor of transparency and multiplicity of viewpoints; (iii) the nature of ethical decision-making may be such that one in effect has to choose between a MATTHIAS KAISER ET AL.70
  • 20. broad and inclusive framework and an in-depth framework with detailed expert arguments; and (iv) different frameworks may be intended for dif- ferent stages of the decision making process. In view of such limitations, one should be careful to consider the five properties as tentative indicators for reviewing the ethical soundness of a framework, and not as conditions that together define ethical soundness. The aim of the above characterization was to clarify further the needs of decision-makers with regards to ethical frameworks. While one may easily agree that an ethical framework should facilitate the decision- making pro- cess, one also needs to pay closer attention to the variety of possible uses to which these frameworks can be put. 3. DEVELOPING A USER MANUAL FOR THE ETHICAL MATRIX
  • 21. When considering the conceptual basis of the Ethical Matrix, as articulated by Mepham et al. (2006), it is at its simplest level a checklist of concerns, structured around established ethical theory. However, it can also be used as a means of promoting structured discussion. The interest groups, the weighting of each cell, and even the appropriateness of the principles may all be challenged or modified by those using it. At best, it helps those involved in making a decision to put themselves in the shoes of others. At the very least, it ensures that more than the usual narrow range of concerns are raised and considered. In order to review the needs of potential users of the Ethical Matrix and to develop a user manual for the Ethical Matrix, two workshops were convened, in each of which the potential use of GM fish was chosen as the case study. This case was chosen in order that the exercises
  • 22. could relate directly to the decision-making process involving the Norwegian Ethical Board on the Ethics of Patents. However, it is not the intention of this article to present a detailed ethical discussion of the chosen case study. The main focus of this article is to discuss a number of structural features of the Ethical Matrix approach that are of interest when evaluating it as a decision support framework. One workshop was conducted in Edinburgh with a group of experts, while a second workshop was conducted in Oslo with ‘‘lay’’ participants. One of the previously reported strengths of the Ethical Matrix is that it can be used by numerous groups and does not presuppose that participants should all be knowledgeable stakeholders. The research team reviewed aspects of the operation of an expert group with a group of lay people when using the Ethical Matrix. However, within
  • 23. a European context there are notable differences in scientific and political culture. While some countries seek ethical advice from broadly composed GM FISH AS A CASE STUDY 71 and highly qualified expert groups (which can include lay members), other countries, notably in Northern Europe, seek to further include members of the lay public, in the processes that lead to such advice. The research team worked on the assumption that there may not be any general or a priori arguments for or against either of these approaches, but that both require transparent justification of their ethical assessments. Building on published material on the Ethical Matrix and the practical experiences of the research team, a provisional protocol was devised as a basis for the development of a Manual for the framework (see the diagram
  • 24. in Figure 1 for a summary). This protocol set out a clear methodology for potential users. The protocol gave guidance on the application of the method and both Research Groups used this protocol in two workshop trials. The protocol was then evaluated to determine its applicability and was further developed. In order to explore the two methodological ap- proaches to the Ethical Matrix that have emerged, the two research groups independently applied a top-down approach (TDA), or the classical form of the method, and a bottom up approach (BUA) that are described below. The Ethical Matrix may be used in several ways and by different groups of people, or even by individuals. So organizational requirements are likely to be quite different in different circumstances, and to be critically influenced by factors that are not directly related to the nature of the Ethical Matrix as an
  • 25. ethical tool. Such factors not only include financial and time limitations but also the degree to which participants in a group exercise are encouraged to set the agenda themselves rather than follow a prescribed step-by- step proce- dure. With reference to the latter point, the different ways in which the Ethical Matrix may be used will be greatly influenced by whether its use conforms more to a ‘‘top-down’’ approach than to a ‘‘bottom- up’’ approach. 4. ETHICAL MATRIX TOP DOWN APPROACH (TDA) In a TDA, the specifications of the Ethical Matrix principles are largely set by the organizers of the workshop, who have acknowledged expertise in facilitating bioethical deliberation, and play a prominent role in structuring the exercise. In order to examine whether expert participants found the TDA Ethical Matrix approach useful when applied in a participatory setting,
  • 26. a workshop was organized in September 2005 in the UK. Using the potential use of GM salmon in aquaculture as a case study, nine ‘‘expert’’ participants applied the Ethical Matrix to discuss key issues raised by the use of the GM technology. The notion of ‘‘expert status’’ was designated to the participants on the basis that they are actively involved with the aquaculture industry, or biotech- MATTHIAS KAISER ET AL.72 nology research and development. The group�s expertise covered areas such as marine biology; aquaculture industry; fish welfare; regulation; and molecular biology, etc. The final selection of participating experts was done by the workshop organizers. The final list of participants was determined by a combination of considerations, such as interest and willingness to partic- ipate, area of expertise, recognized standing in the profession,
  • 27. etc. DEFINE SUBJECT AREA * Consideration of the technological claims * Consideration of key ethical issues associated with implementing the technology DEFINE THE ETHICAL MATRIX * Define the relevant interest groups * Define the specifications of principles for each of the cells WORKSHOP OBJECTIVES * Define the aim of the workshop * Define the scope of the discussion * Define the outcomes expected from the workshop WORKSHOP MATERIALS * Prepare an introductory presentation * Define the meeting sessions * Define the role of the facilitator * Prepare a briefing paper on the key ethical issues FEEDBACK FORMS * Prepare meeting feedback forms to review process and the methodology * Prepare SWOT analysis forms for assessing the methodology SELECT WORKSHOP PARTICIPANTS
  • 28. * Define the relevant stakeholders * Determine the relevant areas of expertise * Ensure that there is a diversity of opinion and interests represented PARTICIPANT INVITATION * Clarify the terms of reference for the workshop * Clarify the reporting procedure and the role of each participant * Send out participant documents including a description of the method and topic briefing paper WORKSHOP * Opening session that defines the methodology, sets out the aims of the meeting, clarifies the context of the discussions and clarifies the reporting process for presenting the results of the meeting. * Balanced presentation of experts’ views * Work through the cells of the matrix in a series of discussion sessions * Conclude with an overview session that draws out participants’ overview of the issues * Completion of the feedback forms ANALYSIS OF THE DATA BY FACILITATOR * Qualitative analysis of the discussion * Quantitative analysis of data
  • 29. * Qualitative analysis of the feedback forms * Report on findings FEEDBACK TO PARTICIPANTS * Send draft of the workshop data analysis back to participants to allow them to check and review the representation of their input FINAL ANALYSIS AND REPORT Figure 1. Summary of a generic protocol of the Ethical Matrix. GM FISH AS A CASE STUDY 73 Participants were sent briefing documents prior to the meeting, including a copy of the Ethical Matrix methodology. The workshop was held over one day andatthestartof theevent,participantsweregivenanintroductiontotheEthical Matrix and the potential issues raised by the case study. During this process, the classic TDA Ethical Matrix was used, where the principles are pre-specified for each of the interest groups (cf. Table 1). One justification for using the ‘‘classic’’
  • 30. Ethical Matrix approach was that it had proven useful in many earlier settings, and that its form and content are well documented (cf. Mepham, 2005). The participants used the Ethical Matrix to map out the key issued raised. As part of their assessment, they were asked to comment on the use of the Ethical Matrix and its potential value. When examining participants� views of the Ethical Matrix in relation to the notion of ethical soundness, many felt that the strengths of the framework were its inclusion of a mul- tiplicity of viewpoints and the discussion of the key (ethical) arguments. Participants commented on the value of working through the pre-defined Ethical Matrix as it facilitated a structured debate amongst the group. When asked to complete a SWOT-analysis (setting out strengths, weak- nesses, opportunities, and threats) of the method, common weaknesses were described as: the lack of time to discuss each issue and the
  • 31. potential limita- tions of the knowledge of the participants. Participants noted the need to ensure that a broader range of stakeholders are involved in the discussion, therefore, the involvement of additional participants with complementary backgrounds would have been welcomed by the group. These potential limitations should be further explored within the context of other partici- patory methods, since many of the limitations identified can relate to these methods per se. As part of the written feedback, all participants believed the use of the Ethical Matrix helped the process. Although this was a limited exercise conducted in a UK setting, the findings from this workshop appeared to reinforce the perception that expert groups prefer to work with a TDA. 5. ETHICAL MATRIX BOTTOM UP APPROACH (BUA) In a bottom-up approach, the organizers provide less explicit guidance, and
  • 32. defer to the majority views of the (usually) lay participants in specifying the principles and conducting ethical deliberation. In order to further analyze and develop the BUA Ethical Matrix method, a workshop was organized in Oslo (November 2004). The use of GM salmon in aquaculture was again chosen as the case for study. Ten lay participants were chosen from a sample of 70 (standardized demographic balancing was applied) self selecting citizens who had responded to an advertisement placed in a public newspaper. The ten participants were MATTHIAS KAISER ET AL.74 T a b le 1 .
  • 47. o f th e en v ir o n m en t GM FISH AS A CASE STUDY 75 chosen on the basis of criteria such as gender, age, variety in educational background, and apparent motivation in application. Participants were sent briefing documents on the potential use of GM salmon and the workshop was conducted in two sessions on two separate days. On the first day, the participants were introduced to the case study and during the second day the group worked through the issues using the Ethical Matrix. For this BUA approach, the research group applied a BUA
  • 48. Ethical Matrix based on the four principles – with well-being specified separately as increased benefits and reduced harm, autonomy, and fairness. The partici- pants translated these ethical principles into specifications for the interest groups and as a result of discussions the principle Autonomy was modified and the term Dignity was subsequently used in the Matrix. The participants also added additional stakeholders to the original list. Some participants argued for the inclusion of ‘‘future generations’’ as a stakeholder group, but it was agreed that these considerations could be included under the Con- sumer group. Others perceived ‘‘Research and Knowledge Production’’ to be an important issue. As a result of this discussion, an additional stake- holder group, ‘‘Research Community,’’ was added to the Matrix. Five interest groups were, therefore, used in this BUA Matrix. The
  • 49. Ethical Matrix articulated and agreed to by workshop participants is set out in Table 2. It should be noted that the Ethical Matrix method was introduced to the participants at the beginning of the discussion. Although, participants appreciated the organizers initial presentation of an Ethical Matrix as a starting point for their discussions, they claimed that if given more time, they might have proposed further changes, both in the list of ethical prin- ciples and in the list of stakeholders. Participants stated that the Matrix applied during the workshop should be seen as a first approximation to the problem, but they also highlighted that it would not necessarily rank as a ‘‘natural’’ classification scheme. The organizers interpreted this view as indicating a level of abstraction in the Ethical Matrix method that requires some familiarity with, and knowledge of, ethical assessment
  • 50. procedures. In terms of outcomes from the workshop, much discussion centered on what the principles ‘‘Increased benefits’’ and ‘‘Reduced harm’’ actually re- ferred to. It was, for instance, not obvious to the participants that ‘‘Food safety’’ was a correct specification of reduced harm for consumers. On the second day, the participants discussed the potential ethical impacts for the defined stakeholders (interest groups). This was referred to as specifying the consequence matrix. The organizers proposed a completed consequence matrix, but the participants wished to propose their own analysis of the issues without assistance. In terms of feedback from the participants and in view of the notion of ethical soundness, some individuals were of the opinion that the ethical MATTHIAS KAISER ET AL.76
  • 65. o w n re se a rc h ‘‘ U n d efi n ed ’’ GM FISH AS A CASE STUDY 77 arguments were not fully clarified. This may be a limitation of the BUA, where principles are not predefined. Since this workshop was conducted with lay participants, it was felt that there should be sufficient time for a learning process to occur, in terms of the process and the subject. Giving more time for participants to reflect upon their own judgments could im-
  • 66. prove the process. The evolution of specification of the different cells and their contents are dependent upon interpretation, and this interpretation depends on the participants� background and preparation. This may be seen as a limitation for the use of the BUA approach with lay participants. However, the completed cells create compartmentalized data on the par- ticipants� views of the issues. The completion of the cells demanded a fo- cused debate over how one perceives a decision to affect the interested parties. This leads to a debate over values and potential ethical impacts. In addition to the comments on the methodology, several participants reported that some of their views changed as a result of conducting the process. For instance, while they raised ethical concerns with regards to commercial use of growth enhanced GM salmon, they also felt that the development of sterile GM salmon might reduce the significance of some of the major
  • 67. concerns, since it might address current concerns relating to wild stock levels. Thus they found that they did not fundamentally object to the use of GM technology in animal production, but options were dependent on the distribution of implied benefits. According to the participants, many of the advantages demonstrated in this study were procedural. There is room for further development of the methodology as a tool relevant for engaging with lay participants. Some of these developments are interrelated, e.g., time and clarity. It is conceivable that some more time – or stretching the exercise over a longer period – could lead to more reflection on ethical arguments. CONCLUSIONS Applying both the TDA and BUA approaches to the case of GM salmon pro- vided valuable insights that allowed further development of the Ethical Manual.
  • 68. The workshops highlighted the fact that, although the Ethical Matrix does not emerge as a very simple tool to use as a participatory ethical framework, it does show its potential to structure ethical concerns under varying conditions. It is not possible to conduct a direct comparison of the outcomes from the two workshops, since the participant sample is too small and the method- ological approach differed, in terms of preconditions and type of participant. However, even with these varying conditions, the two applications of the method, TDA and BUA, have allowed the analysis of some crucial indica- tors relating to the ethical soundness of decision support frameworks. MATTHIAS KAISER ET AL.78 Examining the discourse from the workshops, the participants were able to present their ethical reasoning in relation to the technology that allowed
  • 69. their evaluations to be more transparent, the reference to ethical values and argument was made explicit. The use of both methodologies, TDA and BUA, allowed individuals to present varying ethical viewpoints, even to the extent that they may not have coincided with participants original viewpoints. Conducting further participatory events would establish how comprehensive the recorded considered ethical viewpoints were in this study. With regards to ethically relevant factual information, both groups seemed to endorse the view that a broad range of expertise should be involved in the preparation of technology evaluation of this nature. This represents a significant challenge and responsibility for the organizers of this type of consultation process. These trial workshops highlighted that there are further opportunities to explore and develop the Ethical Matrix for use as a participatory tool.
  • 70. However, some interesting outcomes were observed from these exercises. The expert group felt that the use of the Ethical Matrix provided a needed structure for the discussion, allowing all participants to contribute and participate. It was interesting to note that the lay panel, which at the start of the process had voiced some skepticism towards biotechnology, ended up with a more positive evaluation of the potential use of GM salmon by the end of the process. No inherent technophobia seemed dominant in their evalu- ation and it seemed as if the close examination of this case study on the basis of an Ethical Matrix approach provided an overview that allowed partici- pants to distance themselves from preconceived ideas and judge on the basis of information and principles that are designed to serve the common good. Thus, it is hoped that for both applications, lay and expert, that the Ethical
  • 71. Matrix may actively contribute to what one may call ethical discourses. ACKNOWLEDGMENTS This work was conducted as part of the EC funded project under DG Re- search, FP5, Quality of Life program, ‘‘Ethical Bio TA tools,’’ (QLG6- CT-2002-02594). The funding and the inspiring collaboration of all other consortium members are gratefully acknowledged. REFERENCES Beauchamp, T. L. and J. F. Childress (2002), Principles of Biomedical Ethics, 5th ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Chadwick, R. S., B. Henson, G. Moseley, M. Koenen, C. Liakopoulos, A. Midden, G. Palou, D. Rechkemmer, D. Schroeder, and A. Wright (2003), Functional Foods, Berlin: Springer Verlag. GM FISH AS A CASE STUDY 79 FAO/WHO (2003), FAO/WHO expert consultation on the safety assessment of foods derived from genetically modified animals including fish, November 2003, Rome: FAO/WHO, pp. 17–21.
  • 72. Føllesdal, D., L. Walløe, and J. Elster (1986), Rationale Argumentation, Berlin, New York: W. de Gruyter. Forsberg, E. M. (2007), ‘‘Value Pluralism and Coherentist Justification of Ethical Advice.’’ Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics, 20. Doi: 10.1007/ S10806-006-9017-16. Kaiser, M. (2004), ‘‘Xenotransplantation – Ethical Considerations Based on Human and Societal Perspectives,’’ in W. Farstad, Ø. Andresen, O. Nyberg, and B. Christensen (eds.), Acta Veterinaria Scandinavica, Proceedings of the 16th Inter- nordic Symposium of the Nordic Committee for Veterinary Scientific Cooperation on Animal Organs to Save Human Lives, Suppl. 99, pp. 65–73. Kaiser, M. and E. M. Forsberg (2001), ‘‘Assessing Fisheries – Using an Ethical Matrix in a Participatory Process.’’ Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics, 14, pp. 192–200. Mepham, B. (1996). ‘‘Ethical Analysis of Food Biotechnologies: An Evaluative Framework,’’ in B. Mepham (ed.), Food Ethics, London: Routledge, pp. 101–119. Mepham, B. (2000), ‘‘A Framework for the Ethical Analysis of Novel Foods: The Ethical Matrix.’’ Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics, 12, pp. 165–176.
  • 73. Mepham, B. (2001), ‘‘Novel Foods,’’ in R. Chadwick (ed.), Concise Encyclopaedia of Ethics and New Technologies, San Diego: Academic Press, pp. 300–313. Mepham, B. (2005), Bioethics: An Introduction for the Biosciences, Oxford: Oxford University Press. Mepham, B. and S. Tomkins (2003), Ethics and Animal Farming: An Interactive Web Program. www.ethicalmatrix.net. Mepham, B., M. Kaiser, E. Thorstensen, S. Tomkins, and K. Millar (2006), Ethical Matrix User Manual, The Netherlands: Agricultural Economics Research Institute. Millar, K. (2002), ‘‘Thinking about Cleaning Up: The Ethics of Bioremediation.’’ Science and Public Affairs, 3, pp. 20–21. Moore, C. J. (1996), A Bioethical Analysis of Transgenesis in Animals. PhD thesis, University of Nottingham. Schroeder, D. and C. Palmer (2003), ‘‘Technology Assessment and the Ethical Matrix.’’ Poiesis Praxis, 1, pp. 295–307. MATTHIAS KAISER and ERIK THORSTENSEN National Committee for Research Ethics in Science and Technology (NENT) P.O. Box 522 Sentrum, Prinsensgate 18 0105, Oslo, Norway
  • 74. E-mail: [email protected] KATE MILLAR and SANDY TOMKINS Centre for Applied Bioethics, School of Biosciences, University of Nottingham, Sutton Bonington Campus Loughborough, Leics, LE12 5RD, UK E-mails: [email protected]; [email protected] MATTHIAS KAISER ET AL.80 Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission. << /ASCII85EncodePages false /AllowTransparency false /AutoPositionEPSFiles true /AutoRotatePages /None /Binding /Left /CalGrayProfile (None) /CalRGBProfile (sRGB IEC61966-2.1) /CalCMYKProfile (ISO Coated) /sRGBProfile (sRGB IEC61966-2.1) /CannotEmbedFontPolicy /Error /CompatibilityLevel 1.3 /CompressObjects /Off /CompressPages true /ConvertImagesToIndexed true /PassThroughJPEGImages true /CreateJDFFile false /CreateJobTicket false /DefaultRenderingIntent /Perceptual /DetectBlends true /ColorConversionStrategy /sRGB /DoThumbnails true /EmbedAllFonts true
  • 75. /EmbedJobOptions true /DSCReportingLevel 0 /SyntheticBoldness 1.00 /EmitDSCWarnings false /EndPage -1 /ImageMemory 524288 /LockDistillerParams true /MaxSubsetPct 100 /Optimize true /OPM 1 /ParseDSCComments true /ParseDSCCommentsForDocInfo true /PreserveCopyPage true /PreserveEPSInfo true /PreserveHalftoneInfo false /PreserveOPIComments false /PreserveOverprintSettings true /StartPage 1 /SubsetFonts false /TransferFunctionInfo /Apply /UCRandBGInfo /Preserve /UsePrologue false /ColorSettingsFile () /AlwaysEmbed [ true ] /NeverEmbed [ true ] /AntiAliasColorImages false /DownsampleColorImages true /ColorImageDownsampleType /Bicubic /ColorImageResolution 150 /ColorImageDepth -1 /ColorImageDownsampleThreshold 1.50000 /EncodeColorImages true /ColorImageFilter /DCTEncode /AutoFilterColorImages false
  • 76. /ColorImageAutoFilterStrategy /JPEG /ColorACSImageDict << /QFactor 0.76 /HSamples [2 1 1 2] /VSamples [2 1 1 2] >> /ColorImageDict << /QFactor 0.76 /HSamples [2 1 1 2] /VSamples [2 1 1 2] >> /JPEG2000ColorACSImageDict << /TileWidth 256 /TileHeight 256 /Quality 30 >> /JPEG2000ColorImageDict << /TileWidth 256 /TileHeight 256 /Quality 30 >> /AntiAliasGrayImages false /DownsampleGrayImages true /GrayImageDownsampleType /Bicubic /GrayImageResolution 150 /GrayImageDepth -1 /GrayImageDownsampleThreshold 1.50000 /EncodeGrayImages true /GrayImageFilter /DCTEncode /AutoFilterGrayImages true /GrayImageAutoFilterStrategy /JPEG /GrayACSImageDict << /QFactor 0.76 /HSamples [2 1 1 2] /VSamples [2 1 1 2] >> /GrayImageDict << /QFactor 0.15 /HSamples [1 1 1 1] /VSamples [1 1 1 1]
  • 77. >> /JPEG2000GrayACSImageDict << /TileWidth 256 /TileHeight 256 /Quality 30 >> /JPEG2000GrayImageDict << /TileWidth 256 /TileHeight 256 /Quality 30 >> /AntiAliasMonoImages false /DownsampleMonoImages true /MonoImageDownsampleType /Bicubic /MonoImageResolution 600 /MonoImageDepth -1 /MonoImageDownsampleThreshold 1.50000 /EncodeMonoImages true /MonoImageFilter /CCITTFaxEncode /MonoImageDict << /K -1 >> /AllowPSXObjects false /PDFX1aCheck false /PDFX3Check false /PDFXCompliantPDFOnly false /PDFXNoTrimBoxError true /PDFXTrimBoxToMediaBoxOffset [ 0.00000 0.00000 0.00000 0.00000 ] /PDFXSetBleedBoxToMediaBox true /PDFXBleedBoxToTrimBoxOffset [ 0.00000
  • 78. 0.00000 0.00000 0.00000 ] /PDFXOutputIntentProfile (None) /PDFXOutputCondition () /PDFXRegistryName (http://www.color.org?) /PDFXTrapped /False /Description << /DEU <FEFF004a006f0062006f007000740069006f006e007300200066 006f00720020004100630072006f0062006100740020004400690 07300740069006c006c0065007200200036002e000d0050007200 6f006400750063006500730020005000440046002000660069006 c0065007300200077006800690063006800200061007200650020 007500730065006400200066006f0072002000640069006700690 0740061006c0020007000720069006e00740069006e0067002000 61006e00640020006f006e006c0069006e0065002000750073006 100670065002e000d002800630029002000320030003000340020 0053007000720069006e006700650072002d005600650072006c0 061006700200047006d0062004800200061006e00640020004900 6d007000720065007300730065006400200047006d00620048000 d000d0054006800650020006c0061007400650073007400200076 0065007200730069006f006e002000630061006e0020006200650 0200064006f0077006e006c006f00610064006500640020006100 7400200068007400740070003a002f002f00700072006f00640075 006300740069006f006e002e0073007000720069006e006700650 072002e00640065002f007000640066002f000d00540068006500 72006500200079006f0075002000630061006e00200061006c007 3006f002000660069006e00640020006100200073007500690074 00610062006c006500200045006e0066006f00630075007300200 05000440046002000500072006f00660069006c00650020006600 6f0072002000500069007400530074006f0070002000500072006 f00660065007300730069006f006e0061006c0020003600200061 006e0064002000500069007400530074006f00700020005300650
  • 79. 0720076006500720020003300200066006f007200200070007200 650066006c00690067006800740069006e006700200079006f007 500720020005000440046002000660069006c0065007300200062 00650066006f007200650020006a006f006200200073007500620 06d0069007300730069006f006e002e> /ENU <FEFF004a006f0062006f007000740069006f006e007300200066 006f00720020004100630072006f0062006100740020004400690 07300740069006c006c0065007200200036002e000d0050007200 6f006400750063006500730020005000440046002000660069006 c0065007300200077006800690063006800200061007200650020 007500730065006400200066006f0072002000640069006700690 0740061006c0020007000720069006e00740069006e0067002000 61006e00640020006f006e006c0069006e0065002000750073006 100670065002e000d002800630029002000320030003000340020 0053007000720069006e00670065007200200061006e006400200 049006d007000720065007300730065006400200047006d006200 48> >> >> setdistillerparams << /HWResolution [2400 2400] /PageSize [2834.646 2834.646] >> setpagedevice Brion J. Fox, JD, University of Wisconsin Comprehensive Cancer Center, Madison, Wisconsin; Joanna E. Cohen, PhD, Ontario Tobacco Research Unit, University of Toronto, Toronto, Ontario, Canada, and Department of Public Health Sciences, University of Toronto,
  • 80. Toronto, Ontario, Canada. This work was carried out at the Center for Tobacco Research and Intervention, University of Wisconsin Medical School, and at the Ontario Tobacco Research Unit. Corespondence: Brion J. Fox, J.D., University of Wisconsin Comprehensive Cancer Center, Room 385 WARF Bldg., 610 Walnut St., Madison, WI 53726, USA. Tel.: + 1 (608) 262-3894; fax: + 1 (608) 262-2425; E-mail: [email protected] u Review Tobacco harm reduction: A call to address the ethical dilemmas Brion J. Fox, Joanna E. Cohen [Received 31 July 31, 2001; accepted 18 February 2002] The 2001 Institute of Medicine report Clearing the Smoke: Assessing the Science Base for Tobacco Harm Reduction has helped to focus attention on the scientific basis for assessing tobacco harm reduction products. As the tobacco research and policy communities tackle the challenges of evaluating harm reduction, there are ethical issues that must also be addressed. There has, however, been very little writing on the ethics of this field. In an effort to spur research into answering these ethical questions, we present two complementary approaches. First we outline three overarching topics in tobacco harm reduction that would particularly lend themselves to study: (a) Is the pursuit of tobacco harm reduction an ethical
  • 81. goal? (b) What are the ethical considerations of tobacco harm reduction vis-à-vis pharmaceutical companies? and (c) What are the ethical considerations for harm reduction vis-à-vis tobacco companies? We then present one possible framework for analyzing the ethical issues that accompany particular tobacco harm reduction strategies. By considering the ethical dilemmas attendant to tobacco harm reduction in a prospective and thoughtful manner, we will be better prepared to handle the challenges that face us individually as researchers and collectively as a tobacco control community. Introduction In 2001, the Institute of Medicine published a report assessing the science base for tobacco harm reduction (Stratton, Shetty, Wallace, & Bondurant, 2001). In that report, the term harm reduction referred to strategies that lower tobacco-related mortality and morbidity even though there continues to be exposure to one or more tobacco-related toxicants. There are a wide variety of harm reduction strategies. Some of these strategies include using nicotine replacement therapies to reduce smoking, the development of ‘safer’ cigarettes, and the implementation of behavioral strategies to reduce the total number of cigarettes a person smokes. The Institute of Medicine report has helped spur the tobacco research and policy community to examine more closely the prospect of developing products and strate- gies for tobacco harm reduction. This effort comes bearing a myriad of challenges, including the scientific difficulties in developing and evaluating new products, the prospect that individual benefits may be outweighed by population harms, and the reality that many ideas
  • 82. may arise, and indeed may be encouraged to arise (Stratton et al., 2001), from the tobacco and pharma- ceutical industries. Some have argued that tobacco harm reduction strategies are inevitable because the tobacco and pharma- ceutical industries are pursuing reduced risk products independently. This, however, merely abdicates responsi- bility for exploring whether a harm reduction approach is desirable. We in the tobacco control community have an obligation to make choices about our own behavior and to act as advisors to clinicians, consumers, policymakers, and other researchers. These roles are especially impor- tant when examining tobacco harm reduction because of the uncertain nature of the information and the possible unintended consequences of harm reduction strategies. As tobacco scientists and policymakers address these ISSN 1462-2203 print/ISSN 1469-994X online/02/0600S81-07 © 2002 Society for Research on Nicotine and Tobacco DOI: 10.1080/1462220021000032861 Nicotine & Tobacco Research (2002), S81– S87 challenges, it is imperative to confront head-on the ethical questions that they present. If we fail to examine these issues proactively, we may find ourselves reacting to potential dilemmas as individual moral actors, rather than defining as a community the standards to which we should hold research and researchers. By engaging in this dialogue early, we will be able to respond thoughtfully to many of the ethical challenges posed. In the hope of provoking these discussions, we suggest
  • 83. below three topics that should be the focus of greater study as the tobacco control community evaluates the advantages and disadvantages of pursuing a harm reduction strategy: (a) Is the pursuit of tobacco harm reduction an ethical goal? (b) What are the ethical considerations of tobacco harm reduction vis-à-vis pharmaceutical companies? and (c) What are the ethical considerations for harm reduction vis-à-vis tobacco companies? Because of the overarching nature of these questions, they will not be answered quickly, nor should they be. These questions should be part of an ongoing dialogue and series of analyses that encompass the wide range of interests of the tobacco control community. Given, however, that there is an immediate need to understand some of the ethical implications of particular harm reduction strategies, we also present and discuss an ethical framework for analyzing proposed harm reduc- tion strategies. Should the tobacco control community pursue tobacco harm reduction? As the Institute of Medicine report discusses, harm reduction strategies that have been adopted in fields other than tobacco control can provide analogies to possible tobacco harm reduction strategies. For example, improving the safety of automobiles is analogous to removing toxicants from tobacco smoke; providing clean needles through needle exchange programs is analogous to heating rather than burning tobacco products; and providing methadone to heroin addicts is analogous to providing long-term nicotine replacement therapy to people who are addicted to nicotine. In many cases, these harm reduction strategies were reported to be successful, although recently there has been growing criticism of a harm reduction approach (Erickson, 1999; Mangham,
  • 84. 2001; Mugford, 1992). Part of the desire to pursue a tobacco harm reduction strategy is based upon the belief that we will be unable to achieve our health goals through current efforts to prevent and treat tobacco use. For example, it is believed that there remains a significant core of individuals who are unable to quit, are increasingly recalcitrant or otherwise impervious to the public health messages (e.g., Irvin & Brandon, 2000), and who would benefit from harm reduction strategies. In addition, even the most efficacious treatments or prevention programs will not reach all smokers. In fact, there is a core of smokers, often poorer, less educated, or suffering from a co- morbidity such as mental illness, that would dispropor- tionately benefit from safer products. The difficult question, however, is whether efforts taken to reach hard core smokers will overshadow efforts that could help a larger number of smokers. The recently published Public Health Service Clinical Practice Guideline Treating Tobacco Use and Depend- ence concluded, ‘There is insufficient evidence to support a recommendation regarding harm reduction strategies’ (Fiore et al., 2000). The Guideline describes numerous strategies and approaches for the effective treatment of tobacco dependence, and speaks of ‘opti- mism’ for a ‘promising era in the treatment of tobacco use and dependence’ (Fiore et al., 2000). The report identifies the failure to systematically implement the guideline recommendations as the key barrier to increas- ing quit rates; that is, it may be too soon to give up hope on treating the great majority of smokers. This is not because our tools are insufficient, but because we have been inadequate in adopting and applying the tools. This
  • 85. view was supported by the publication of a prevention priorities project that identified that adult tobacco cessation treatment was among the most effective, cost- effective, yet under-utilized prevention interventions (Coffield et al., 2001). Similarly, the Centers for Disease Control and Pre- vention have identified Best Practices for states devel- oping programs to reduce tobacco use (Centers for Disease Control and Prevention, 1999). The neglect of many states to fully fund programs to promote these best practices shows another failure to live up to the full promise of what we can accomplish in reducing tobacco use. Indeed, the U.S. Surgeon General has declared that a 50% reduction in youth and adult smoking could be achieved by applying what we already know (U.S. Department of Health and Human Services, 2000). The concern is that if clinicians and public health professionals are encouraged to implement harm reduc- tion strategies, it is possible that this would be done at the expense of delivering the cessation messages and developing the prevention programs that we know are effective. We fail not because current strategies are ineffective, but because of a lack of commitment to strategies that we know work. The conundrum thus posed is whether it is ethical to invest time, energy, and resources in the development and testing of new harm reduction strategies when strategies known to be effec- tive have not been fully implemented. The challenge remains even if a private company introduces the harm reduction strategy– i.e., the tobacco control community will need to decide if it endorses or uses the product. It is not as simple as saying that we can pursue all
  • 86. approaches simultaneously. One of the difficulties in persuading clinicians to provide treatment is the con- founding nature of the multiple messages they receive. Similarly, it has been shown that with the advent of low tar and nicotine cigarettes, smokers used the lower-risk messages to continue their smoking behavior (National Cancer Institute, 2001). In assessing the potential value S82 ETHICAL DILEMMAS of a harm reduction product, there must be some recognition that there will be a tradeoff for other public health efforts. On the other hand, there should also be a recognition that there is nothing foreseeable that suggests the current approaches will ‘solve’ the problem in the near future, and eventually some form of harm reduction product may be necessary. What are the ethical considerations of harm reduction with regard to pharmaceutical companies? Any consideration of pursuing or recognizing the legitimacy of tobacco harm reduction raises the specter of involvement with pharmaceutical companies. These companies currently market nicotine replacement prod- ucts and non-nicotine therapies, such as bupropion SR. These agents have been approved for use as cessation devices in a number of countries, and have established the pharmaceutical companies as partners in the effort to promote tobacco cessation. In the future, these com- panies may seek to promote these or newly developed products as harm reduction products, which could put them at odds with the cessation community.
  • 87. The participation of pharmaceutical companies in the debate on harm reduction raises challenging ethical issues. Despite the positive advances that have been made by the drug industry, they are private corporations driven by a profit motive. In the pursuit of harm reduction, this business ethic may conflict with a public health ethic. There are a number of ways that this conflict could be realized. For example, the development of competitive nicotine delivery devices that would replace cigarette smoking with long-term nicotine maintenance (Warner, Slade, & Sweanor, 1997) could subject the pharmaceutical companies to the criticism that they are simply replacing one addiction with another. Moreover, if the pharmaceutical industry produces new products that reduce harm but do not promote cessation, or market existing products as a complement to smoking that will reduce overall harm, the presumed beneficence of the industry may be lost. There may also be ethical issues with respect to having researchers collaborate with pharmaceutical companies. These companies have an economic interest in the outcomes of studies they fund that may conflict with the independence that researchers desire. There is an asso- ciation between positions that are favorable to the pharmaceutical industry and financial relationships of the authors with this industry (Stelfox, Chua, O’Rourke, & Detsky, 1998). There is evidence that proceedings from pharmaceutical-sponsored symposia tend to have misleading titles, to use brand names, and to not be peer reviewed (Bero, Galbraith, & Rennie, 1992). Further, many contracts between the pharmaceutical industry and investigators have unacceptable publication clauses, and a substantial number of articles that are published include authorship lists that do not meet accepted criteria
  • 88. for authorship (Bodenheimer, 2000). An uncomfortabl e reality is that pharmaceutical companies and, potentially, tobacco researchers who receive support from the pharmaceutical industry, could have a vested interest in the types of harm reduction strategies explored. Recent efforts have addressed the publication of data from sponsored clinical trials (e.g., Davidoff et al., 2001) and have established guidelines for industry collabora- tion (Centers for Disease Control and Prevention, 1997). These efforts provide guidance as to how to conduct collaborations but do not discuss whether to pursue the collaboration in the first place. Moreover, because drug companies are able to invest great resources in the development of pharmaceutical products, they may be in a position to control the tobacco harm reduction research agenda. Drug-free harm reduction strategies, such as banning smoking in workplaces (Chapman et al., 1999; Evans, Farrelly, & Montgomery, 1999; Glasgow, Cum- mings, & Hyland, 1997), may get left out of any serious discussion of tobacco harm reduction. A final difficulty is that, although it is possible to get public money to study pharmaceutical products, the majority of funds for clinical drug trials in the U.S. is provided by pharmaceutical companies. Academic medi- cal centers are now receiving a minority of those funds, with for-profit contract-research and site-management organizations the favored providers of clinical trial services (Bodenheimer, 2000); thus, researchers who choose to pursue harm reduction products may be required to work with this industry. What are the ethical considerations of harm reduction with regard to tobacco companies?
  • 89. With respect to harm reduction, the greatest incentive for creating safer products may come from the tobacco industry itself. Many of the private lawsuits have been based upon a failure of the industry to create a safer product, misleading the public into thinking that a product is safe, or, in the case of public plaintiffs, to not pursue research into safer products. The industry thus has incentives, in the form of improved public relations and the avoidance of future litigation, to create a safer product. Any company that develops a safer product is also likely to have a significant market advantage over its competitors. Furthermore, the tobacco companies may be best situated to understand the subtleties of nicotine delivery and the development of a safer cigarette. Indeed, there are many industry products that are already being tested or discussed. As a result of these factors, it is likely that the tobacco control community will face the prospect of having to assess a tobacco-industry-produced harm reduction product. This assessment may include direct collaboration in the development or testing of such a product, or responding to the presence of such a produc t in the market. There are reasons that the tobacco control community may be cautious of such a collaboration. It is well established that the tobacco industry has perverted NICOTINE & TOBACCO RESEARCH S83 science for its own purposes by creating artificial controversy, attacking the reputation of tobacco control
  • 90. researchers, and filtering science through lawyers (Bero, Barnes, Hanauer, Slade, & Glantz, 1995; Saloojee & Dagli, 2000). Efforts by the tobacco industry to sponsor forums to discuss scientific issues or promote collabora- tion have been met with scorn and have been boycotted by many in tobacco control. Similarly, efforts to enlist reputable scientists to review or support the work funded by the industry have been met with derision (Gardiner, 2001). Distrust of the industry runs so deep that many have argued that relationships with the tobacco industry are unacceptable (Shield, 2001), that universities should refuse money from the tobacco industry (Chapman & Shatenstein, 2001; Cohen, Ashley, Goldstein, Ferrence, & Brewster, 1999) and that journal editors should refuse to publish articles based on research sponsored by the tobacco industry (King, Yamey, & Smith, 2000). Even analyses of legal settlements with the industry have been described as ‘dealing with the Devil’ (Annas, 1997). One would be hard-pressed to find anything positive about the past behavior of the tobacco industry that would warrant faith in moving forward in collaboration with this industry, and many organizations have specific policies against collaboration with the tobacco industry (Cohen, 2001). It is feared that collaboration, complicity, or acquiescence of the public health community in tobacco industry efforts could result in increased credi- bility of the tobacco industry, making it harder to oppos e industry efforts that are genuinely detrimental to the public health. Given the innate distrust of the tobacco industry, researchers are likely to want to test independently any products developed by this industry. In addition, there will be an innate skepticism of industry motives; for
  • 91. example, is the industry using harm reduction as a means to increase the number of smokers, or to decrease the number of smokers who quit? This skepticism will also lead researchers to critically examine the broader implications of the proposed product. This independent testing may simply delay rather than answer certain ethical questions, because independent testing could result in confirming that the products meet the claims of the industry. There are risks to rejecting potential future relation- ships with the tobacco industry. As the pharmaceutical companies bear the cost of testing their products, there is an argument that tobacco companies should bear the cost of testing their products. In addition, if science is built upon open discourse, censorship of the industry could marginalize the tobacco control community. To reject all future collaborations assumes that the industry is beyond redemption, which may be a faulty and risky assumption. For example, the industry’s reputation is extraordinarily low in the eyes of the public. The result of this has been a drive for regulation and litigation. If the industry changes and the tobacco control community is not prepared to deal with an industry that is not easily demonized, the tobacco control community may lose its own credibility. Before initiating any collaboration with tobacco companies on harm reduction strategies or tools, thoughtful analyses will be needed to define the appropriate scope and nature of the associations. Ethical considerations will vary depending on the proximity of the funds to the tobacco industry and the level of restrictions on the use of the funds. For example, there seems to be a spectrum of funding risks from clearly
  • 92. inappropriate to acceptable that includes: the sponsorship of a researcher or student, the direct funding of a research project, the unrestricted funding to an institution, and the use of litigation settlement funds for research. Similarly, significant ethical consideration should be given to determine how the public health community should react to industry efforts even if there is no collaboration. Over time, these reactions may prove to be what changes the most, should the industry actually reform, even if, for the immediate future, skepticism is warranted. A framework for analyzing tobacco harm reduction strategies If the tobacco control community can answer the questions laid out above in a way that supports pursuing tobacco harm reduction, there will still be a need to examine the ethics of individual tobacco harm reduction strategies. We propose an ethical framework under which such strategies could be analyzed similar to frameworks produced in other contexts (see for example Kass, 2001). An ethical framework will not predetermine answers to all ethical questions, nor will it guarantee that any two parties using the framework will arrive at the same outcome. What it can assist with is a rigorous analysis of the relevant questions that can then lead to an increased understanding of the principles at stake. Such a frame- work could also assist in the development of analyses and standards for scientific conduct, and the develop- ment of future research questions. Ethicists have generally agreed upon a series of cross- cutting principles that can serve as the basis for a framework for analysis. Among these principles are: beneficence – the principle of doing good; nonmalefi- cence – the principle of not doing harm; self-determina-
  • 93. tion – the principle of allowing individuals to make their own decisions; and justice – the principle of fairness (Beauchamp & Steinbock, 1999). These principles also serve as the basis for many of the ethical theories, including utilitarian, Kantian, and communitarian theo- ries (Beauchamp & Steinbock, 1999). For our framework we have chosen to use a utilitarian approach, which evaluates and balances the likely benefits and burdens of the proposed strategy. This balancing should be done in such a manner that it takes into account the cross-cutting ethical principles as they come to bear on the underlying question. The framework that follows will account for many of the ethical questions raised earlier in this paper. S84 ETHICAL DILEMMAS What are the proposed benefits? A proposed tobacco harm reduction strategy should be analyzed for its probable real world benefits and should be examined for efficacy and for effectiveness. Fur- thermore, care should be taken to understand the true penetration of the proposed strategy into the market. For example, promoting nicotine replacement products as a part of a harm reduction strategy could fail if the products are not used or are used incorrectly. Similarly, new products will have limited effect if they are not purchased and used by consumers because of inadequate taste or nicotine delivery. Where evidence is suggestive of a strong potential benefit, one should not necessarily withhold the strategy in favor of scientific certainty, but it should be coupled with specific research questions to be able to promote the long-term analysis of the
  • 94. proposed strategy. A primary difficulty in assessing effectiveness is that the time for scientific discovery is lengthy, and the net epidemiologic effects of new products cannot be known for years. On the one hand, too cautious a stance may discourage the development of new products that are potentially effective in reducing at least some of the risks of smoking. On the other hand, proposed tobacco harm reduction strategies should result in more good than harm, and not simply substitute harms. For example, much has been written about the failure of low tar cigarettes as a harm reduction approach. Initially these products were seen as potentially beneficial for health because they were supposed to deliver lower levels of tar. In the end, however, these products were determined to be no better than conventional products because of the innate hazards of tobacco products and how smokers actually used the product, which offset much of the benefit that could have been realized. Although an ethical analysis of low tar cigarettes may not have prevented the mistakes which occurred, a thorough ethical discussion could have identified the risks and tradeoffs that were being made, and promoted research to assist in evaluat- ing the potential risks versus the potential benefits. What are the possible harms? Even if a particular harm reduction strategy suggests great promise, it must be scrutinized for the potential burdens that accompany it. These burdens could be inherent in the product or the result of replacing one risk with another. An historical example of this kind of burden would be the original Kent micronite filter, which was found to have high levels of crocidolite asbestos fibers (Longo, Rigler, & Slade, 1995).
  • 95. Burdens could also arise from secondary conse- quences accompanying the harm reduction product. For example, by creating a safer product there could be a reduced incentive to quit smoking or avoid initiation. Therefore, a presumed-safer product could have the perverse effect of creating a greater population-wide harm if prevalence is increased. The overarching issues related to opportunity costs discussed above are espe- cially appropriate to this part of the framework. Sim- ilarly, certain types of products may remove other motivations to quit or maintain abstinence. For example, a product that reduces or eliminates second-hand smoke could remove the incentive for individuals to quit in order to protect those around them. It could also serve to remove incentives for employers, home-owners, or policymakers to promote smoke-free environments. Other burdens may be more regulatory in nature. If a product is developed that escapes definition as a cigarette, it may avoid taxation, advertising restrictions, and so forth. Although the solution could be regulatory, such an outcome should be considered in an ethical analysis. Just as the proposed benefits are to some degree speculative, the proposed burdens will also be a matter of some prognostication; nevertheless, efforts should be made to understand the likely harms as well as the gaps in research that need to be filled to explain the true nature of the burden. For example, a better understanding of how individuals process risk messages is important to understanding the probable impact a reduced risk product may have on prevalence rates. In addition, research such as that published recently by Kozlowski
  • 96. and colleagues (Kozlowski, Strasser, Giovino, Erickson, & Terza, 2001), which provides a model for how one can balance the reduction in risk of a harm-reducing produc t against the increased use of that product, can assist in the calculation of the scope of the burden. Would the possible benefits and harms be distributed across the population equitably? Even if a product appears on balance to be beneficial, with the probable risks outweighing the burdens, the proposed product should be analyzed for its implications for social justice. If there exists a truly beneficial produc t that significantly reduces the risk of disease related to smoking, but that product is expensive, there arises a social justice question. What mechanisms are in place, or need to be put in place, to make a safer produc t accessible to all who might need it? This opens an additional set of problems, however. If no mechanism exists, should the product be abandoned even if such an action would prohibit benefit to those who could afford it? Conversely, it would be awkward at best for the tobacco control community to argue for increased availability of a tobacco product, albeit a reduced-risk one. There also could be cultural or other barriers to products that may create a social disparity. For example, smokeless tobacco, which may be considered a reduced- harm product, is almost exclusively used by males. The answers to these and comparable social justice questions lie outside the scope of this paper; nevertheless, at a minimum an examination of these questions should be made prior to the endorsement of a particular tobacco harm reduction strategy.
  • 97. NICOTINE & TOBACCO RESEARCH S85 What additional benefits and risks accompany the proposed strategy because of the involvement of private industry? A further level of scrutiny that a proposed harm reduction product or strategy should undergo is whether the development or promotion of the product involves the pharmaceutical or tobacco industries. In addition to the industry analyses proposed above, one must make transparent any biases or conflicts of interest that could arise due to industry involvement. The mere existence of a bias may not be deleterious, but the proposed analysis would require the disclosure of all potential biases. Financial disclosures are clearly the most apparent and have found their way into the requirements for peer review publications and general researcher behavior. However, biases can also be experi- entially based. For example, as discussed above, the inherent mistrust of the tobacco industry and its motives runs deep, which itself may cause one to prejudge a product from the industry. These biases should also be disclosed when endorsing or criticizing a tobacco harm reduction strategy. An example of how industry involvement could create an ethical dilemma can be seen in the following hypothetical situation. How should the tobacco control community react if essentially identical reduced-risk products arise out of both the pharmaceutical and tobacco industries? If the products otherwise pass ethical muster, the tobacco control community may choose to
  • 98. support the pharmaceutical company product because of the historical burdens that are associated with the tobacco industry. Alternatively, the tobacco control community may shy away from endorsing the pharma- ceutical company product because of an appearance of impropriety if this company had funded tobacco control programs or researchers. Silence could result in a slowing of the dissemination of the proposed product. Whichever solution individuals choose to follow, their biases should be disclosed. Discussion One potential interpretation of this commentary is that the tobacco control community should operate under a single set of ethics. We are not advocating either for or against this proposition, and we believe this idea should be thoughtfully examined prior to any recommendation. One of the strengths of tobacco-related research is that it represents the coming together of a range of disciplines and perspectives. It is possible that the forced homoge- neity of a single set of ethics could eliminate some of the diversity we currently enjoy. If we examine the most basic sources of principle that exist in our discipline, we can see how the issues conflict as much as they overlap. Clinicians who operate under the medical model, treating disease one patient at a time, could value a harm reduction strategy that benefits an individual much more than do public health profession- als who are trying to address population-based problems. Indeed, one could argue that a failure to prescribe a harm reduction product to a particular patient who could benefit from its use could be seen as a violation of a biomedical ethic. Alternatively, one could see that public
  • 99. health workers could consider it unethical to support a harm reduction product that had a negative effect on the overall population. Similarly, non-profit organizations may be driven by a mission to improve health of all people, whereas for profit corporations are, by definition, responsible for maximizing profits for their shareholders. If a commercially viable and individually-beneficial harm reduction product was available but nevertheless had a negative net population-based effect, one could not expect private corporations to shy away from that product, nor is it ethically clear that they should. Our position is simply stated: Individuals should, prior to adopting a stance on a particular harm reduction strategy, conduct a rigorous ethical analysis such as that presented in this paper. Moreover, to best protect the interests of researchers and policymakers, we urge that ethical studies be embraced as a necessary part of any larger commitment to pursue harm reduction. These studies should involve thoughtful analyses of the issues from a variety of perspectives, including biomedical, public health, corporate, legal, and policy. We have presented but one approach for determining the appro- priateness of harm reduction strategies. We hope that it stimulates discussion and encourages others to improve upon the framework. Acknowledgments and disclosures Preparation of this manuscript by the first author was supported, in part, by the Robert Wood Johnson Foundation program Developin g Leadership in Reducing Substance Abuse. Dr. Cohen received funding from the Canadian Institute of Health Research. The authors would like
  • 100. to thank Stella Aguinaga Bialous, Mary Jane Ashley, Roberta Ferrence, Pam Kaufman, and Kenneth Warner for their helpful comments on earlier drafts of this manuscript . References Annas, G. J. ( 1997). Tobacco litigation as cancer prevention: dealing with the devil. New England Journal of Medicine, 336, 304– 308. Beauchamp, D. E., Steinbock, B. (1999). New ethics for the public’s health. New York: Oxford University Press. Bero, L., Barnes, D. E., Hanauer, P., Slade, J., Glantz, S. A. (1995). Lawyer control of the tobacco industry’s external research program: The Brown and Williamson documents. Journal of the American Medical Association, 274, 241– 247. Bero, L. A., Galbraith, A., Rennie, D. (1992). The publication of sponsored symposiums in medical journals. New England Journal of Medicine, 327, 1135 –1140. Bodenheimer, T. (2000). Uneasy alliance: Clinical investigators and the pharmaceutical industry. New England Journal of Medicine, 342, 1539– 1544.
  • 101. Centers for Disease Control and Prevention. (1997, February). Guidance for collaboration with the private sector. Retrieved February 10, 2002, from http://www.cdc.gov/od/foia/policies/ collabor.htm Centers for Disease Control and Prevention. (1999). Best practices for comprehensive tobacco control program s. Atlanta, GA: Office on Smoking and Health. Chapman, S., Borland, R., Scollo, M., Brownson, R. C., Dominello, A., Woodward, S. (1999). The impact of smoke-free workplaces on declining cigarette consumption in Australia and the United States. American Journal of Public Health, 89, 1018–1023. S86 ETHICAL DILEMMAS Chapman, S., Shatenstein, S. (2001). The ethics of the cash register: Taking tobacco research dollars. Tobacco Control, 10, 1– 2. Coffield, A. B., Maciosek, M. V., McGinnis, J. M., Harris, J. R., Caldwell, M. B., Teutsch, S. M., Atkins, D., Richland, J. H., Haddix, A. (2001). Priorities among recommended clinical preventive services. American Journal of Preventive Medicine, 21, 1– 9. Cohen, J. E., Ashley, M. J., Goldstein, A. O., Ferrence, R., Brewster, J. M. (1999). Institutional addiction to tobacco. Tobacco Control,
  • 102. 8, 70– 74. Cohen, J. E. (2001). Universities and tobacco money: some universities are accomplices in the tobacco epidemic. British Medical Journal, 323, 1– 2. Davidoff, F., DeAngelis, C. D., Drazen, J. M., Hoey, J., Højgaard, L., Horton, R., Kotzin, S., Nicholls, M. G., Nylenna, M., Overbeke, A. J., Sox, H. C., Van Der Weyden, M. B., Wilkes, M. S. (2001). Sponsorship, authorship, and acountability. Journal of the American Medical Association, 286, 1232 –1234. Erickson, P. G. (1999). Introduction: The three phases of harm reduction. An examination of emerging concepts, methodologies , and critiques. Substance Use & Misuse, 34, 1–7. Evans, W. N., Farrelly, M. C., Montgomery, E. (1999). Do workplace smoking bans reduce smoking? American Economic Review, 89, 728–747. Fiore, M. C., Bailey, W. C., Cohen, S. J., et al. (2000). Treating Tobacco Use and Dependence. Clinical Practice Guideline. Rockville, MD: Public Health Service. Gardiner, P. (2001). The Philip Morris external research program; fig
  • 103. leaf optional. Burning Issues: TRDRP Newsletter, 4, 7–10. Glasgow, R. E., Cummings, K. M., Hyland, A. ( 1997). Relationship of worksite smoking policy to changes in employee tobacco use: Findings from COMMIT. Tobacco Control, 6(Suppl 2), S44- S48. Irvin, J. E., Brandon, T. H. (2000). The increasing recalcitrance of smokers in clinical trials. Nicotine & Tobacco Research, 2, 79– 84. Kass, N. E. (2001). An ethics framework for public health. American Journal of Public Health, 91, 1776–1782. King, J., Yamey, G., Smith, R. (2000). For and against: Why journals should not publish articles funded by the tobacco industry. British Medical Journa l, 321, 1074. Kozlowski, L. T., Strasser, A. A., Giovino, G. A., Erickson, P. A., Terza, J. V. (2001). Applying the risk/use equilibrium: use medicinal nicotine now for harm reduction. Tobacco Control, 10, 201– 203. Longo, W. E., Rigler, M. W., Slade, J. ( 1995). Crocidolite asbestos fibers in smoke from original Kent cigarettes. Cancer Research, 55, 2232– 2235.
  • 104. Mangham, C. (2001). Harm reduction and illegal drugs: the real debate. Canadian Journal of Public Health, 92, 204– 205. Mugford, S. (1992). Harm reduction: Does it lead where its proponent s imagine? In N. Heather, A. Wodak, E. Nadelmann, & P. O’Hare (Eds.), Psychoactive drugs and harm reduction – from faith to science. London: Whurr Publishers. National Cancer Institute. (2001). Risks associated with smoking cigarettes with low machine-measured yields of tar and nicotine. Smoking and Tobacco Control Monograph No. 13. (NIH Publication No. 02– 5074). Retrieved July 10, 2002, from http://cancercon- trol.cancer.gov/tcrb/monographs /13/ Saloojee, Y., & Dagli, E. (2000). Tobacco industry tactics for resisting public policy on health. Bulletin of the World Health Organization, 78, 902– 910. Shield, M. (2001). Policies and positions of other funding organizations on the funding controversy. Burning Issues: TRDRP Newsletter, 4, 2– 4. Stelfox, H. T., Chua, G., O’Rourke, K., & Detsky, A. S. (1998). Conflict of interest in the debate over calcium-channel antagonists . New England Journal of Medicine, 327, 101– 106.
  • 105. Stratton, K., Shetty, P., Wallace, R., & Bondurant, S. (Eds.). (2001). Clearing the smoke: Assessing the science base for tobacco harm reduction . Washington, DC: National Academy Press. U. S. Department of Health and Human Services. ( 2000). Reducing tobacco use. A report of the Surgeon General. Washington, DC: U. S. Government Printing Office. Retrieved July 10, 2002, from http:/ /www.cdc.gov/tobacco/sgr/sgr_2000.htm Warner, K. E., Slade, J., Sweanor, D. T. (1997). The emerging market for long-term nicotine maintenance. Journal of the American Medical Association, 278, 1087–1092. NICOTINE & TOBACCO RESEARCH S87 March/April 2009 229 he financial fiascos at Enron, Tyco, WorldCom, Global Cross- ing, Qwest, HealthSouth, and the vari- ous hedge fund investments managed by securities firms that were highly questionable from an ethical perspec- tive have received extensive coverage
  • 106. in the media. As these unethical—if not illegal events unfolded—the pressure mounted for regulatory agencies such as the Securities and Exchange Com- mission to enforce tightened restrictions and for legislative bodies, including the U.S. Congress, to prohibit some of the more deliberate misrepresentations. For example, the Sarbanes-Oxley Act (2002), with its Public Companies Accounting Oversight Board, has made an attempt to address aspects of this far-reaching problem. Some of the business profes- sionals involved in these incidents active- ly participated in cover-ups, shredding documentary evidence of their corporate misconduct (e.g., Arthur Andersen) and creating an elaborate web of intentional- ly misleading corporate structures. Some of these professionals merely looked the other way as such deceptions occurred in the workplace. However, when a course of action has been undertaken, it is often difficult for subsequent players to effec- tively challenge the status quo (Demski, 2003). In a 2005–2006 survey devel- oped by KPMG (an international public accounting and consulting firm), nearly 75% of the respondents reported that they had observed misconduct in their current organization during the previous 12 months (Williams, 2006). During the same time period, a study by Walker Infor- mation, as reported in a meta-analysis by Verschoor (2006), found that 42% of
  • 107. respondents thought their organization’s senior leaders were unethical. Walker Information’s study also reported that 25% of the respondents had knowledge of, or suspected, an ethics violation in the previous 2 years (Verschoor). The widespread nature of the recently publicized scandals suggests that there has been a deterioration of ethical stan- dards in the corporate workplace and rais- es the question of whether regulatory or legislative actions alone are sufficient to ensure that the next generation of workers demonstrate ethical decision making. Although professional ethics contin- ues to be a growing concern for busi- nesses and government in the United States, interest has surfaced about the ethics of college students who are tomorrow’s business leaders. The pres- ent study focuses on college students’ perceptions of professional ethics and how these perceptions can be evaluated using academic situations as surrogates for business situations. BACKGROUND In our research, we used cheating by students as an indicator of future ethical Students’ Perceptions of Business Ethics: Using Cheating as a Surrogate for Business Situations
  • 108. LYNNETTE S. SMYTH CHARLES O. KRONCKE GORDON COLLEGE COLLEGE OF MOUNT SAINT JOSEPH BARNESVILLE, GEORGIA CINCINNATI, OHIO JAMES R. DAVIS ANDERSON UNIVERSITY ANDERSON, SOUTH CAROLINA TABSTRACT. Today’s college students are entering the workplace at a time when ethical issues are under greater scrutiny. Thus, the authors examined students’ per- ceptions of varying ethical situations, sam- pling 786 college students at 3 institutions (1 public, 1 Baptist affiliated, 1 Catholic affiliated). The authors used an anonymous survey and statistically analyzed student assessment of questionable academic and business situations. The survey results indi- cated that (a) nonbusiness majors, on aver- age, are more ethical than business majors; (b) female students are more ethical than male students; and (c) when analyzing the
  • 109. results by class, upper division students are more ethical than lower division students. Keywords: business ethics, cheating and ethics, student cheating Copyright © 2009 Heldref Publications 230 Journal of Education for Business behavior, which was, in part, based on research by Sims (1993), who found that past cheating is a strong predictor of future cheating. Although cheating, the college student’s most common avenue for unethical behavior, is an ongoing concern, it has greater potential conse- quences for those students who become tomorrow’s business professionals. It is troubling that a significant percent- age of college students engage in some form of cheating (Diekhoff et al., 1996; Grimes, 2002). Academic cheating can be as simple as using crib notes in class or plagiarizing others’ written assign- ments, or it can be as extreme as using unauthorized sources for take-home exams or even hiring professionals to write papers and prepare case reports. It is certain that the continued growth of the Internet is making the more flagrant forms of cheating widely accessible to a
  • 110. growing number of students. Much research has been conducted to examine collegiate cheating by vari- ous demographic variables other than academic major. Crown and Spiller (1998) examined 16 previous studies on the relation between gender and cheat- ing, and found mixed statistical results. Studies that focused on cheating and the student’s academic year in college also yielded inconsistent results. Baird (1980) reported that upperclassmen cheat less often; Lipson and McGav- ern (1993) determined that sophomores cheat the most; and Haines, Diekhoff, LeBeff, and Clark’s (1986) research showed no significant difference in cheating behavior on the basis of aca- demic classes. Davis and Welton (1991) found that lower division students have lower ethical standards than do upper division students, a difference not found between upper division students and graduate students. Similarly, younger students cheat more than their older peers (Diekhoff et al., 1996; Graham, Monday, O’Brien, & Steffen, 1994; Haines et al.). It is undoubtable that current trends in the global business environment (and in pending legislation) ensure that business professionals will come under closer scrutiny in the future and will likely be expected to hold a higher level of ethi-
  • 111. cal standards than has been the case in recent years. Rocha and Teixeira (2006) conducted a large multinational study on academic cheating and found that the magnitude of academic fraud is not constant across countries and that there is a positive correlation between the amount of academic fraud in a country and its level of real-world business cor- ruption. It is clear that higher education must give student exposure to ethics a greater priority, beginning with ethical decision making in students’ lives in their academic communities. Cheating is a form of unethical behavior, and students who cheat in college today may soon become professionals engaging in similar unethical behaviors in the work- place of tomorrow (Sims, 1993; Smith, Davy, Rosenberg, & Haight, 2002). DATA AND METHODOLOGY To examine the prevalence of unethical attitudes and behavior in the college envi- ronment, we examined the issue of cheat- ing at three institutions: one 2-year public college and two private 4-year colleges. Data During the spring semester of 2006, we surveyed 786 students regarding their attitudes toward, and experiences with, cheating and their perceptions of
  • 112. professional ethics in business. We con- ducted the survey at three institutions with enrollments of less than 3,500 students (residential and commuter): Anderson University, a 4-year private Baptist-affiliated college in Anderson, South Carolina; Gordon College, a 2- year public college of the University System of Georgia, located in Barnes- ville, Georgia; and the College of Mount Saint Joseph, a 4-year Catholic college in Cincinnati, Ohio. In this article, we denote these three colleges as Baptist college, public college, and Catholic college, respectively. In an effort to obtain a broad cross- section of students, we gave surveys dur- ing classroom time in selected courses representing the various majors at each institution to sample approximately 10% of the student body at each institu- tion. We provided all respondents the assurances of confidentiality and ano- nymity, an especially important require- ment in researching student experiences with cheating and unethical behavior. Because of participant requirements, each student was given the choice of not participating in the study, and fewer than 1% declined. Students were given a set of ques- tions regarding various aspects of cheating that included generalized
  • 113. inquiries into how often they cheated in college, how often they observed collegiate cheating and its detection by faculty members, their willingness to participate in cheating, and their sense of ethics and acceptability of cheating. In addition, students were asked to rate on a 7-point Likert-type scale ranging from 1 (not dishonest at all) to 7 (very severe dishonesty) their assessments of the dishonesty level of a number of business and academic situations. A number of demographic variables were also collected for each respondent to assess how student attitudes regarding cheating may differ by demographic grouping. Methodology We analyzed the student responses in a variety of ways. To investigate the internal consistency of the surveyed eth- ical statements, Cronbach’s alpha was calculated for the 26 statements with a resulting value of .97. In addition, the deletion of each statement one at a time did not significantly increase the value of alpha. This suggests that the items measure the same underlying unidimen- sional construct: ethical perspective. For much of the analysis, the data were processed using the chi-square sta- tistical test for independence and the corresponding nonparametric Cramer’s
  • 114. V statistic to correct for the possible influence of sample size. Cramer’s V tests for the strength of the degree of association among the variables being tested, and thus the null hypothesis has no degree of association. For this analy- sis and given the large sample size, there was little difference, if any, between the p values of the two methods; therefore, the Cramer’s V statistics were the pri- mary basis for the conclusions given for this research project. In addition, in an effort to assess if business majors have significantly different perceptions of unethical behavior compared with their nonbusiness majors counterparts, the mean responses of each group were March/April 2009 231 compared for each statement using a simple two-tailed independent t test, with a null hypothesis of equal means between the two groups. For each state- ment, the equal variance assumption of the t test was evaluated using Levene’s F test statistic; for those cases in which the equal variance assumption was rejected, the separate variance formulation was used to form the t statistic value. The primary focus of this article is on two sets of situations, each containing 13 statements for evaluation: ethical situa-
  • 115. tions in the academic environment and similar situations in a business setting. The statements can be categorized as pertaining to lying and deceiving, cheat- ing, cheating others, stealing, assisting others in wrongdoing, and contemplat- ing unethical behavior. It is important to note that, although these academic and business situations were paired for this analysis, they were not paired on the survey instrument, and thus respondents considered each situation separately. RESULTS General Cheating From the demographics collected, we were able to determine that student bod- ies at the surveyed colleges predomi- nately comprised full-time students (an average of 86%). Approximately 40% of students were business majors. The gender split was estimated at 57% (56.8) female students, and 43% (43.1) male students because 10% (10.1) of respon- dents did not report their gender. From the set of questions regarding cheating in general, we found that 55% of the respondents reported having cheated in college at least once, a value that is in line with two studies: (a) Grimes (2002), in which 49.8% reported hav- ing cheated, and (b) Smyth and Davis (2004), in which 46% of respondents reported having cheated in college at