SlideShare a Scribd company logo
1 of 50
FILSAFAT DALAM DESAIN
A.DESAIN
Desain adalah solusi yang disengaja dari sebuah masalah, dengan membuat rencana untuk hal
baru, di mana rencana tidak akan langsung terlihat, oleh orang yang dapat dipercaya, sebagai
solusi yang tidak memadai. Dalam kajian ini filsafat berperan penting dalam ilmu penalaran di
dalam desain. Salah satunya adalah pengembangan pikiran yang berujung dengan imajinasi
B.Proses Desain
Mencari Informasi Kebutuhan
Jika anda ingin membuat sebuah desain maka perlu mengumpulkan informasi terkait klien dan
produk serta tujuan dalam pembuatan desain tersebut. Jangan pula informasi tentang
kebutuhan, sasaran audiens serta goal dari sebuah proyek desain tersebut.
Membuat Kerangka Kerja
Setelah informasi dikumpulkan maka selanjutnya adalah menyusun kerangka kerja agar tidak
ada kemunduran atau pengulangan konsep dan sesuai dengan kesepakatan antara desainer dan
klien. Susunan kerja minimal terdapat beberapa informasi seperti di bawah ini:
 Kebutuhan Desain
 Tema
 Data Yang Dibutuhkan
 Batas Waktu
Mencari Ide Kreatif
Mencari dan menetapkan ide kreatif merupakan salah satu tahap penting karena tahapan ini
dapat menjadi salah satu indikator nilai jual seorang desainer.
Proses pencarian dan penetapan sebuah ide dapat muncul dari berbagai sumber dan cara.
Beberapa sumber dan cara dalam penggalian atau pencarian ide kreatif dapat ditempuh melalui
penyusunan sketsa-sketsa ide, brainstorming / tukar pikiran atau melihat dan memodifikasi
karya desain yang sudah ada.
Visualisasi
Setelah ide didapatkan maka proses selanjutnya adalah penetapan visualisasi dengan pemilihan
atau fokus pada hal – hal teknis desain seperti layout, background, pemilihan jenis huruf/font,
warna atau elemen desain lainnya.
Desainer yang baik harus memiliki alasan kuat dalam berpikir bahwa produknya akan
berhasil.Tapi mengingat itu novel dan belum pernah menjalani pengujian coba-coba. Menurut
tradisi, Sang Perancang tampaknya dibiarkan tanpa alasan untuk mempercayai dirinya
kemampuan untuk memenuhi tujuan yang diciptakannya
C.MODERNISME DESAIN
Modernisme pertama-tama menafsirkan kembali mengucapkan “kriteria kunci Desain
fungsional, [estetika,] simbolik [mantan pressive], dan mediating ”yang diperkenalkan Parsons
di bagian Modernisme juga mengklaim menemukan “hubungan penting antara [kriteria ini]
yang mungkin memfasilitasi upaya Desainer untuk memuaskan mereka semua. Parsons
mengingatkan kita bahwa “menyelesaikan Desain.
Hasil dari interpretasi Parsons atas bukti sejarah adalah bahwa Modernisme, sejak awal, adalah
"gerakan normatif" yang berusaha menggantikan gagasan umum tentang desain populer
dengan gagasan yang lebih mengakar kualitas, untuk “massa sendiri mungkin tidak menyadari
apa yang mereka butuhkan. Daripada mengikuti selera kontemporer, Perancang harus
memimpin jalan dengan menyampaikan ering item dengan kualitas asli. Tujuan kaum
Modernis adalah Bukan untuk mengubah Desain menjadi 'seni rupa' atau kerajinan berbasis
tradisi, tetapi untuk memadukan yang terbaik unsur ketrampilan tradisional, produksi massal
modern, dan seni rupa menjadi cara baru memproduksi barang material yang masuk akal dalam
konteks sosial kehidupan kontemporer
Parsons mengemukakan bahwa menurut pemikiran Modernis, ada keterkaitan antara fungsi
dan jenis nilai estetika tertentu istilahnya (func-keindahan nasional). Karya Loos, tetapi juga
mencatat bahwa itu meluas lebih jauh ke belakang, ke Yunani kuno.“Modernisme memasuki
tradisi lama yang memandang fungsionalitas sesuatu, atau kesesuaiannya dengan tujuannya,
seperti menimbulkan keindahan atau daya tarik estetika.
Self-Knowledge by Proxy: Parsons on Philosophy of Design and the Modernist Vision
Volume 2, Number 4, Winter 2016
Page 1
322
she ji The Journal of Design, Economics, and Innovation Volume 2, Number 4, Winter 2016
Keywords
Definition of design
Epistemology of design
Modernism
Philosophy of design
Received February 16, 2017
Accepted May 15, 2017
Email
For Galle
(corresponding author)
pga@kadk.dk
Self-Knowledge by Proxy:
Parsons on Philosophy of Design and
the Modernist Vision
Per Galle, RoyalDanish Academy of Fine Arts, School of Design, Denmark
Abstract Glenn Parsons’s 2016 work, The Philosophy of Design, looks deeply
at design in general, and at the Modernist approach to design in particular.
The book would make an excellent textbook, but one could equally treat
it as a research monograph. This article provides a detailed review of the
book as a contribution to design research. The author’s efforts are original
and commendable, although the work is not entirely immune to disagree-
ment. The article highlights the main line of reasoning to guide future
readers, and develops a number of considerations.These include a reflec-
tion on the feasibility of Modernist design thinking, some background on
the nature and origins of the philosophy of design as a discipline, a defense
of the notion of a stable essence ofthe concept of design, and a critical
analysis of Parsons’s definition of design.
Copyright © 2016, Tongji University and Tongji University Press.
Publishing services by Elsevier B.V. This is an open access article under the
CC BY-NC-ND license (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by -nc-nd/4.0/).
The peer review process is the responsibility of Tongji University and Tongji University Press.
http://www.journals.elsevier.com/she-ji-the-journal-of-design-economics-and-innovation
https://doi.org/10.1016/j.sheji.2017.05.001
Page 2
323
Introduction
Serious reflection on the wonders and puzzles of design is a delightful way to tickle
your mind. If you are a student or practitioner of design, it is potentially empow-
ering, too, because it affords you a deeper understanding of what you are doing, and
awareness of the consequences your work may lead to. For example, such reflection
may enable you to appreciate design as a means of affecting people’s everyday lives
for the better in many small ways, and perhaps some bigger ones. And it may draw
your attention to the moral responsibility you incur as a designer.
To be effective, serious reflection on design requires philosophicalflair and
craftsmanship at a level that designers are not trained to master. How fortunatewe
are, therefore, that a professional philosopher came along, took the time and effort
to acquire a thorough understanding of design, its history, and its literature, and
then present his philosophical reflection about what design is and how it works.
His insights are about us, in our capacity as human beings in general, and designers
in particular. That is what Glenn Parsons has done in his recent book The Philosophy
of Design.1 Parsons is thefirst philosopher ever—as far as I am aware—to generously
offer us an entire book full of deep, professional self-knowledge to be gained by
proxy, as it were. All we need to do is find a good chair and the requisite peace of
mind to read and contemplate what he has to say.
This paper offers a thorough review of Parsons’s book, and responds to certain
parts of it. Arguably, the book has a dual aim—first, to function as a textbook intro-
ducing broadly the philosophy of design as a (rather new) subject in its own right;
and second, to explore an original research problem within that broad field. I will
consider thebook primarily in its capacity as a contribution to design research.2
In the following section, I outline Parsons’s aim(s), main line of reasoning, and
contributions, and I make some comments along the way. I hopeother readers of
The Philosophy of Design will use the outline as a convenient, pocket-sized roadmap
showing themain roads and distinctive landmarks of therich philosophical terrain
the book surveys in much greater detail. In this way, I also aim to highlight Par-
sons’s original research contribution. Parsons is far too modest about the merits of
his work. For example, he announces that he “will consider the book worthwhileif
it succeeds in showing that design is a realm worthy of philosophical exploration
in its own right.”3 Parsons not only demonstrates this in his book—he also contrib-
utes to that exploration in a substantialway.
After the outline follows a discussion. On a cursory reading, this section may
be skipped, in whole or in part. It provides some background information on the
nature and origins of thephilosophy of design and also features a more critical and
in-depth consideration of certain aspects of the book that caught my attention.
The exposition and discussion of Parsons’s book ends with a short conclu-
sion—including a warm recommendation.
Aims, Main Line of Reasoning, and Contributions—an Outline
The introduction (pp. 1–3)4
Parsons gently introduces philosophy as a means of cultivating the “ability to see
one’s daily practice” from “abroader perspective,”in “relation to other important
dimensions of human life,” and thus to “think through its place in thegrander
scheme of things.”5 When applied to the daily practice of design, philosophy so
conceived may be a source of professional self-knowledge for designers, as I suggest
above.
According to Parsons, philosophers have largely neglected design so far, at
least as a subject for study in its own right. But since “design today has a prevalence
1 Glenn Parsons, The Philosophy
of Design (Cambridge: Polity
Press, 2016).
2 The present review was
originally commissioned as a
traditional book review by the
editor-in-chief of She Ji. It grew
into something more research
oriented. As a result, the editor
suggested it be considered a
hybrid “full-length article in the
form of a book review.” For a
review with a different profile
of emphasis, see Mona Sloane,
“Book Review: The Philosophy
of Design by Glenn Parsons,”
London School of Economics
and Political Science, April 27,
2016, http://blogs.lse.ac.uk/
lsereviewofbooks/2016/04/27/
book-review-the-philosophy-of-
design-by-glenn-parsons/.
3 Parsons, The Philosophy of
Design, 3.
4 I include page ranges so that
page numbers cited in the
Discussion section can be traced
back to the relevant part of this
outline.
5 Parsons, The Philosophy of
Design, 2.
Self-Knowledge by Proxy
Page 3
324
she ji The Journal of Design, Economics, and Innovation Volume 2, Number 4, Winter 2016
and prestige that makes its neglect by philosophy rather glaring,” he finds that “the
time is ripe for a philosophical consideration of design.”6
To consider design philosophically, however, there is no need for Parsons to
start from scratch. For, as he notes, “plenty of excellent philosophical work” al-
ready exists which is directly relevant to design, even though it may not be focused
specifically on it, including the work done in philosophical disciplines such as
“aesthetics, epistemology, metaphysics, and the philosophy of science.” So, Parsons
says, “Morethan anything else, this book aims to bring this work together into a
systematictreatment.”7
Parsons writes clearly, carefully avoiding insider jargon that might dishearten
readers, and he does not assume his readers are familiar with thefew technical
terms that precision and convention require. As promised, he brings much relevant
material systematically together. He maintains a steady progression from general
considerations to more detailed and specialized aspects of his subject matter.
Along the way, he makes good use of illustrative examples (though visually-minded
readers will look in vain for illustrations in theliteral sense). In these respects,
the book resembles an excellent textbook—one which should certainly be used,
in whole or in part, for teaching purposes. But ThePhilosophy of Design is much too
ambitious to be appreciated as a textbook alone. Parsons does not limit himself to
eclectically explaining to students what others have had to say about design from a
philosophical point of view. He has quite a few points of his own to make, particu-
larly regarding the Modernist movement.
He rejects the conventional view of Modernism as merely a “stylisticphasethat
had its day and then passed into thehistory of Taste.”8 On thecontrary, he con-
tends, “theModernists saw, more clearly than anyone else, the central philosoph-
ical issues relevant to design, and theconnections between them, even if they often
failed to develop their philosophicalinsights.”9 Therefore, a “major element of this
book”—indeed a worthy aim in its own right—is to “reconstruct key Modernist
ideas and subject them to a critical analysis.”10 Although these ideas “do not always
succeed,” Parsons aims to exploit them as “a vital starting point for a philosophical
investigation,” to achieve the desired “systematictreatment”of design. That is a
highly original and ambitious research agenda, and it certainly reaches far beyond
what one would expect of a textbook.
Chapter 1, “What is Design?” (pp. 4–27)
In chapter 1, Parsons addresses themost fundamental of questions about design:
what is it? Not yet drawing on the Modernist ideas, he offers an instructivedemon-
stration of one of the key competencies of a philosopher of theanalytic tradition—
the noble art of developing a philosophicaldefinition. By such a definition one tries
to capture theessence of a concept, by stating necessary and sufficient conditions
for something to fall under that concept. Parsons first shows some examples of
how not to do it, then presents adefinition by Greg Bamford,11 glosses it in simpler
language, and augments it by adding a further condition. What he ends up with is
this:
“Design is the intentional solution of a problem, by the creation of plans for a
new sort of thing, where the plans would not be immediately seen, by a rea-
sonable person, as an inadequate solution.”12
Unlike some definitions in thedesign-theoretical literature, Parsons’s definition is
not just stipulated. Each of its elements is discussed and justified. So, despiteits ac-
knowledged roots in Bamford’s work, the definition constitutes an original contri-
bution. Although (like much else in philosophy) it is not immune to critical discus-
sion, it has considerable prima facie plausibility, and it works all right for the book.
6 Ibid.
7 Ibid.
8 Ibid.
9 Ibid., 2–3.
10 Ibid., 3.
11 Greg Bamford, “Design,
Science, and Conceptual Analy-
sis,” in Architectural Science and
Design in Harmony, Proceedings
of the Joint ANZAScA/ADTRA
Conference, ed. Jim Plume (Kens-
ington: University of New South
Wales, 1990), 234. Bamford
holds an unusual combination of
formal degrees in both architec-
ture and philosophy. In the paper
cited, he stresses the importance
of avoiding conceptual muddle in
thinking about design.
12 Parsons, The Philosophy of
Design, 11.
Page 4
325
The definition raises some “ontological issues” that Parsons discusses in section 1.2.
This makes for interesting and stimulating reading but is not essential to the main
line of reasoning.
Moreimportantly, hedecides in section 1.3 that within the broad class of
activities captured by his definition and called “design,” he will limit the scopeof
his inquiry to a sub-class, which he calls “Design” (spelled with an uppercaseD).13
The general idea of Design is, roughly, that it is supposed to include what thelikes
of Eames, Ive and Starck14 —peopletypically called “designers”—are doing when
designing, and exclude what other good folks, such as scientists, plumbers, and engi-
neers are doing when they are designing.
I argue in the Discussion below that Parsons fails to provide a satisfactory
characterization, let alone a philosophical definition, of Design as distinguished
from design. However, as I will also argue, this doesn’t matter much—it does not
undermine the main line of reasoning that we are considering here. So, for now,
we’ll make do with the above loose sketch of the notion of Design as a special kind
of design.15
Chapter 2, “The Design Process” (pp. 28–53)
The second chapter contains interesting discussions, based on extensive literature
studies, of the nature and complexity of the design problems that Designers try to
solve, how Design may interact with social structures in intricate ways, how Design
problems and their solutions tend to evolve under mutual influence,16 and more.17
Of particular importance to the main line of reasoning, as developed in sub-
sequent chapters, are the four aspects—or criteria, as Parsons calls them later—of
“good Design” discussed in section 2.1. These are functionality;18 aesthetic appeal;
expressive or symbolic qualities suggesting a particular lifestyle or values; and mediation
of the relationship between human beings and theworld—an idea developed by
philosopher Peter Paul Verbeek, among others.19 Parsons returns to these criteria
of good Design in an important passage in chapter 3 (quoted below) and again in
more detail later. Function he treats at length in chapter 5, expression in chapter 4,
aesthetics in chapter 6, and mediation resurfaces in chapter 7, in connection with
“Design ethics.”
One of the delightfully mind-tickling passages of the book is section 2.4, where
Parsons challenges the contention, widely shared among design researchers, that
design problems belong to the kind of planning problems famously called “wicked”
by Rittel and Webber.20 As he puts it,
“On this view, it is not only large-scale problems of public policy, such as the
ones discussed by Rittel and Webber, that are wicked or ill defined, but all
Design problems, down to mundane examples like laying out a factory control
room, or designing a new piece of furniture. But is this really so?”21
Parsons first reviews some arguments supportingthis idea, but rejects them and
concludes “wedo not have a compelling reason to extend Rittel and Webber’s
notion of thewicked problem to Design problems in general: Design problems are
not always ill-defined”—although he admits that “sometimes they are.”22
Rittel and Webber list ten defining characteristics of wicked problems. It only
takes a moment’s contemplation of that list to see that Parsons is right—his “mun-
dane” examples (and many more one might come up with) do not exhibit all, or
even many or most of theten characteristics.23
Next, Parsons returns to the acknowledged possibility that some (lowercase d)
design problems—he cites the example of creating a more efficient office—actu-
ally are “wicked.” The idea he now subjects to critical scrutiny is that when facing
a wicked problem, designers might hope to find some support in what Ritteland
13 The d/D notation is also part
of the heritage from Bamford,
but Parsons elaborates on it
considerably.
14 Charles and Ray Eames,
Jonathan Ive, and Philippe
Starck—celebrated designers,
renowned for their design of
(among other things) character-
istic and innovative chairs, the
Apple iPod, and the Alessi “Juicy
Salif” lemon juicer, respectively.
15 I neither endorse the
distinction, nor the use of
the d/D notation to signal it.
Nevertheless, I will adopt both
for the purposes of this paper, in
order to avoid confusion about
differences between Parsons’s
terminology and mine.
16 This phenomenon is often
referred to in the literature as
“co-evolution of problem and
solution.” For example, see Kees
Dorst and Nigel Cross, “Cre-
ativity in the Design Process:
Co-evolution of Problem – Solu-
tion,” Design Studies 22, no. 5
(2001): 425–37; Bruce Archer,
“Whatever Became of Design
Methodology?,” Design Studies 1,
no. 1 (1979): 17–18; Nigel Cross,
Designerly Ways of Knowing
(London: Springer, 2006), 80;
Steve Harfield, “On Design
‘Problematization’: Theorising
Differences in Designed Out-
comes,” Design Studies 28, no. 2
(2007): 159-73; Donald A. Nice,
The Reflective Practitioner: How
Professionals Think in Action
(New York: Basic Books, 1983),
100.
17 Despite the persistence of
the design/Design distinction
Parsons employs throughout the
book, much of what he argues
applies to design in general.
18 “Functionality” and “func-
tion” are used synonymously in
the book.
19 Parsons, The Philosophy
of Design, 29–30; Peter-Paul
Verbeek, What Things Do:
Philosophical Reflections on
Technology, Agency, and Design
(University Park: The Pennsylva-
nia State University Press, 2005).
20 Horst J. Rittel, “On the
Planning Crisis: Systems Analysis
of the ‘First and Second Gen-
erations, '”The Business Economist ,
no. 8 (1972): 390–96; Horst J.
Rittel and Melvin M. Webber,
“Planning Problems Are Wicked
Problems,” in Developments in
Self-Knowledge by Proxy
Page 5
326
she ji The Journal of Design, Economics, and Innovation Volume 2, Number 4, Winter 2016
Webber have to say about such problems in general.
In their discussion of the first characteristic (“Thereis no definite formulation
of a wicked problem”) Rittel and Webber come up with thefollowing dictum—
which seems promising from thedesigner’s point of view: “Theformulation of
a wicked problem is the problem!”24 To support that claim, they analyzea core
example of a wicked problem, the poverty problem, which Parsons also discusses.25
Poverty partly means low income. But low income, in turn, might be put down to
“deficiency of the national or regional economies,” or “deficiencies of cognitive
and occupational skills within thelabor force,” or “deficient physicaland mental
health”—and each ramification may lead to new ones. According to Ritteland
Webber’s dictum, the key to finding a solution is finding thecorrect formulation of
the problem, which amounts to identifying its crucial ramification(s). “Thus, if we
recognize deficient mental health services as part of the problem, then—trivially
enough—‘improvement of mental health services’ is a specification of solution.”26
Referring to Rittel and Webber’s poverty example, Parsons argues that “con-
trary to what they say, when the ambiguity in a wicked problem is eliminated,”—
in other words, by settling for one or more of its ramifications—“the problem is
hardly solved.”27 For, as he says, “‘improvemental health services’ is far from being
a ‘plan’ one can see as likely to succeed: this is an aim, not a plan.”28 Again, I agree
with Parsons: what we can learn from Rittel and Webber is at best how to analyze
(wicked) design problems, not how to solve them.
Wrapping up his discussion of wicked problems, Parsons concludes that “In
sum, the difficulty of Design cannot be attributed entirely to theambiguity of
the problems it addresses: Designers do confront genuine problems that call for
a rational approach.”And he poses his central question—with which, as we have
seen by now, Rittel and Webber’s ideas promise no help—“how is such an approach
possible?”29
That is one way of puttingwhat Parsons calls “thefundamental problem for
the Design process.”30 Shortly after, he describes it in more detail:
“Theepistemological difficulty for Design is, in Galle’s words:‘How … could
the designer know (or be confident) at that time that theartifact would eventu-
ally serve its purpose?’”31
At the time of designing—referred to as “that time” in the passage quoted—there
is no object available for observation or experiment. Moreover, this epistemological
problem exists—or is exacerbated—to the extent the designer is creatively planning
for a novel artifact that will differ radically from thosewe already know. As Parsons
puts it,
“… a good Designer must be justified in thinking that his product will work.
But given that it is novel32 and has not been subjected to trial-and-error testing
by tradition, theDesigner seems to be left with no reason for confidence in its
ability to satisfy theaims for which it was created.”33
The last two sections of chapter 2 are dedicated to discussions of various possible
responses to this epistemological problem. One by one, Parsons rejects them as in-
adequate or incomplete. That discussion constitutes a well-argued and original part
of the book, but I shall refrain from summarizing it here.
He ends the chapter by singling out one particular responseto theepistemo-
logical problem for further examination: “changing our conception of the nature of
the Design problem so as to emphasizethe search for functionality and downplay
other aspects such as symbolism [elsewhere called “expression”] and aesthetics,
where any guiding principles are harder to find.”34 This is the Modernist approach to
Design.
Design Methodology, ed. Nigel
Cross (Chichester: John Wiley &
Sons, 1984), 135–44, previously
published as part of Horst J.
Rittel and Melvin M. Webber,
“Dilemmas in a General Theory
of Planning,” Policy Sciences 4,
no. 2 (1973): 155–69.
21 Parsons, The Philosophy of
Design, 42.
22 Ibid., 43.
23 To convey the gist of Rittel
and Webber’s list to readers
not familiar with it, here is a
summary of its ten character-
istics in grossly simplified form.
Wicked problems (1) have no
definite formulation; (2) have no
stopping rule; (3) have solutions
that are good or bad, rather
than true or false; (4) have no
test revealing long-term conse-
quences of solutions; (5) offer no
way of undoing consequences of
implemented solutions; (6) have
no clearly-outlined set of poten-
tial solutions; (7) are essentially
unique; (8) are symptoms of
other problems; (9) are solvable
only in ways that depend on how
one explains their occurrence,
which can be done in numerous
ways; and (10) hold planners
entirely liable for mistakes.
24 Rittel and Webber, “Dilem-
mas in a General Theory of
Planning,” 161.
25 Parsons, The Philosophy of
Design, 41.
26 Rittel and Webber, “Dilem-
mas in a General Theory of
Planning,” 161.
27 This passage appears in the
following context—“Indeed,
even when dealing with wicked
problems, there is still more to the
Design process than described by
Rittel and Webber. For, contrary
to what they say …” (Parsons,
The Philosophy of Design,
43, emphasis mine). Above I
omit the italicized part, for it
might suggest that according
to Parsons, Rittel and Webber
themselves present Design prob-
lems as “wicked.” They do not—
so if that is what Parsons wants
to imply here, he is mistaken. (I
am indebted to an anonymous
reviewer for pointing this out to
me.) I tend to think, however,
that what Parsons wanted to say
was something like “Even when
Design is dealing with wicked
problems, there is still more to
the Design process than what
Page 6
327
follows from Rittel and Webber’s
general characterization of such
problems.”
28 Parsons, The Philosophy of
Design, 43.
29 Ibid.
30 Ibid., 35.
31 Ibid., 36. The passage Parsons
quotes here is from Per Galle,
“Foundational and Instrumental
Design Theory,” Design Issues 27,
no. 4 (2011): 94.
32 Compare this with the
phrase “plans for a new sort of
thing” in the definition of design
quoted earlier. For a discussion
of novelty in design, see particu-
larly Parsons, The Philosophy of
Design, 48, 100.
33 Parsons, The Philosophy of
Design, 36–37.
34 Ibid., 53.
35 Ibid., 54.
36 The terminology is not
entirely consistent throughout
the book, which makes it a bit
difficult at times for the reader
to keep track. Parsons, The
Philosophy of Design, 54.
37 Parsons, The Philosophy of
Design, 54.
38 Ibid., 58–59.
39 Ibid., 59.
40 Ibid., 56.
41 Ibid., 58. Those were heady
days, when notions of progress
for the masses, and expertise,
did not trigger accusations of
elitism. Anyone attempting to
reinstate the central tenets of
Modernist thinking in design
today is likely to face these
accusations. They should prepare
to face them, or perhaps take
measures to steer clear.
42 Parsons, The Philosophy of
Design, 58.
43 Ibid., 59.
44 Ibid., 61. Parsons elaborates
further on the Zeitgeist idea in
chapter 4.
45 Parsons uses “aesthetic
value” and “beauty” inter-
changeably, although in the
literature their meanings are
sometimes distinguished. See
Parsons, The Philosophy of
Design, 166, note 3.
Chapter 3, “Modernism” (pp. 54–68)
In the third chapter, Parsons introduces the Modernist approach to Design—“an
approach that promises to alleviate [the epistemological problem].”35
He focuses on Modernismin “its role as a philosophical position,”which “sup-
ported a rational conception of Design in two ways.”Modernismfirstly reinter-
preted the “key criteria of Design—the functional, [theaesthetic,] the symbolic [ex-
pressive], and themediating” that Parsons introduced in section 2.1.36 Modernism
also claims to find “important linkages between [these criteria] that might facilitate
the Designer’s effort to satisfy themall.”37 Parsons reminds us that “solving Design
problems—producing good Designs—is fraught with a basic epistemological diffi-
culty,”38 and adds that “Modernist thinking… addresses the problem … by inviting
us to reconceive the very nature of Design problems.”39
To provide some background, he offers a short exposition on theorigins of
Modernismand continues by explaining the reinterpretation and linkages I men-
tion above. I was impressed by his unique presentation of familiar historical figures
and ideas—Marx, William Morris, Ruskin, Le Corbusier, Gropius and his Bauhaus
school, Adolf Loos, Sullivan—in relation to theunfamiliar idea of Modernism as a
philosophy promising a solution to theepistemological problem of Design.
The upshot of Parsons’s interpretation of the historical evidence is that Mod-
ernism, from its very beginning, was “a normative movement” which sought to
replace commonplace notions of popular design by more deeply-rooted notions of
quality,40 for “themasses themselves might well be unaware of what they need.
Rather than follow contemporary taste, theDesigner must lead the way by deliv-
ering items of genuine quality—good Design.”41 The aim of the Modernists was
“not to turn Design into a ‘fine art’ or tradition-based craft, but to blend the best
elements of traditional craftsmanship, modern mass production, and fine art into
a new way of producing material goods that made sense in the social context of
contemporary life.”42
And as for theModernists’ rational conception of Design and the criteria for
good Design, a first element is Loos’ rejection of ornamentation—“decoration or
adornment … that bears no relation to … utilitarian purpose.”43 However, ac-
cording to Parsons the Modernists did not see the elimination of ornament “as an
impoverishment of the symbolic or expressive aspect of Design, but as an enrich-
ment of it.” Design products, they thought, can express something via their func-
tional elements—in other words, by being planned with function in mind. In par-
ticular, products should represent the Zeitgeist—the “spirit of theage,” as Gropius
would have it.44
Furthermore, Parsons suggests that according to Modernist thinking, there is a
linkage between function and a particular kind of aesthetic value45 he terms “func-
tional beauty,” which returns as a theme in section 6.4. He finds this idea present in
Loos’ work, but also notes that it extends much further back, to the ancient Greeks.
“Modernismtaps into a long-standing tradition that views a thing’s functionality,
or its fitness for its purpose, as giving rise to beauty or aesthetic appeal.” The idea
had been dormant, Parsons tells us, but was rejuvenated with the advent of “spec-
tacular machines such as the steam engine.”46 (Figure 1.)
At the end of section 3.2, Parsons sums up the Modernist reconceptualization
of Design problems as follows:
“If the Designer merely constructs theobject [or rather, creates plans for an
artifact] to perform its function, then expression, aesthetic value, and mediation
become, as it were, ‘spin-off’ values that follow effortlessly. When coupled with
the idea—explored in chapter 2—that the Designer can have access to reli-
able general principles when it comes to function, the allure of the Modernist
vision becomes plain. By focusing on producing functional goods, Designers
Self-Knowledge by Proxy
Page 7
328
she ji The Journal of Design, Economics, and Innovation Volume 2, Number 4, Winter 2016
can rationally tackle the problems that confront them, creating a material
world that is not only useful [functional] but meaningful [expressive], socially
progressive [mediating], and beautiful [aesthetically valuable].”47
As indicated by the italicized words, the Modernist approach to Design, as con-
strued by Parsons, promises to help the designer fulfill thecriteria he introduced
in section 2.1. It seems plausible enough that thesearch for function can be ratio-
nally guided by reliable general principles—akin, perhaps, to thelaws of physics
exploited by engineers48 or to Don Norman’s principles concerning functionality.49
And if the alleged associations or linkages actually hold—and work—between
function and the other three criteria for good Design, then indeed we glimpse the
beginnings of a responseto the epistemological problem of Design.50
The chapter closes with a rebuttal of various attacks that have been mounted
against Modernismover theyears. Parsons is very convincing here—like a compe-
tent defense lawyer, he calmly and methodically dismantles his opponents’ argu-
ments one by one and gets his client acquitted.
Status at the watershed
Let us pauseto consider the main line of reasoning Parsons has developed so far.
Up to and including chapter 3, he has
• Introduced the epistemological problem as “thefundamental problem for
the Design process;”51
• Convincingly attempted to “reconstruct key Modernist ideas”52 from scat-
tered historical evidence, which results in an explicit formulation of “the
46 Parsons, The Philosophy of
Design, 62.
47 Ibid., 63, emphasis mine.
48 Ibid., 51.
49 Ibid., 51–52.
50 Perhaps it is helpful to
anticipate here a condensed re-
capitulation that appears much
later in the book. “According to
the Modernist view, aesthetic,
mediating and expressive
aspects need not be brought into
the Design problem: it is a purely
functional one.” Parsons, The
Philosophy of Design, 103.
51 Parsons, The Philosophy of
Design, 35.
52 Ibid., 2.
Figure 1 “Functional beauty”
hard at work. A class E locomo-
tive leaves Frederica, Denmark,
hauling a northbound goods
train in the summer of 1967.
Designed by a team led by
Carl Flodin in Sweden between
1912 and 1914, the E-class was
adopted and modified in 1937 by
Danish State Railways, where it
remained in regular service till
1970. See Steffen Dresler, DSB
Letter E. The Swedish and Danish
built Express train locomotives
hos DSB 1937–1970 , vol. 27,
Special edition (Næstved: Lokomo-
tivet, 2006), 4, 35. Photograph ©
2017 For Galle.
Page 8
329
Modernist vision” involving a set of criteria for good Design, and (postu-
lated) linkages between them;53
• Shown that theModernist vision promises to solve the epistemological
problem of Design—which arguably it will, provided the “linkages” between
functionality and theother criteria for good Design (expression, aesthetic
value, and mediation) work as intended; and
• Delivered a cogent defense of Modernismagainst various attacks which
might otherwise have rendered the Modernist vision null and void.
Once my reading of chapter 3 was complete, I felt themain line of reasoning had
reached a watershed. Parsons had provided me with an exciting insight about the
Modernist vision. However, it was not clear to me what to expect from his proposed
“critical analysis”54 of it, nor where theenvisioned “systematictreatment”55 was
supposed to lead me. I wondered if the remaining chapters of thebook would
satisfy my growing curiosity regarding thefeasibility of the Modernist vision. To
what extent could Parsons’s reconstructed Modernist vision have been, or become,
a feasible approach to Designing—one that not only promises but offers a workable
solution to the epistemological problem of Design?
In my outline of theremaining chapters, I will take my compass bearings on
this question of feasibility as a means of perceiving theoverall direction of what I
see as Parsons’s main line of reasoning.
Chapter 4, “Expression” (pp. 69–84)
In the opening paragraph of chapter 4, Parsons briefly refers to his reconstruction
of the Modernist vision, and announces—true to his promise from the Introduc-
tion—that he will now “begin a critical examination of this approach.”56 In chapter
4 he addresses the question of how the Modernist’s alleged linkage between a focus
on function and the quality of expression may work. This suggests that we are
moving towards an answer to the feasibility question.
He first smoothly explores theliterature on meaning in design and the possi-
bility of expressing a variety of meanings—such as social status or lifestylevalues—
through design. It seems the Modernist vision does not allow for theexpression
of such (increasingly important) meanings—it “provides us with, at best, a quite
impoverished conception of [the expressive dimension of consumer goods].”57 How-
ever, this “does not undercut thefundamental Modernist claim that good Design
expresses only the Zeitgeist since that claim is a normative one…. That is … even if
peopledo value goods for expressing other things … they ought not to do so.”58
After that follows a rational reconstruction59 of a Loos-inspired Modernist ar-
gument for how meaningful expression may be attained by focusing on function
rather than ornament. Oddly enough, this discussion does not restrict consider-
ation to an expression of the Zeitgeist. Parsons enters into an extended sequence
of arguments and alternating counter-arguments to test by fire the Modernist idea
concerning the linkage between function and theexpression of meaning.
The outcome of this quasi-dialogue60 is that the Modernist idea survives—if
only just. And yet, some doubt still surrounds the Modernist claim that functional
Design will “automatically” express theZeitgeist.
Chapter 5, “The Concept of Function” (pp. 85–102)
Though perhaps not settling the matter of Zeitgeist-expression for good, chapter 5
expounds an “evolutionary account of function” which, as Parsons very cautiously
puts it, “might seem to lend some support to theModernist ideathat functional
Design will be … expressive of a culture’s Zeitgeist.”61 The Zeitgeist issue is not
taken up again later in thebook, nor is the question of whether functional Design
53 Further reconstruction
follows in later chapters.
54 Parsons, The Philosophy of
Design, 3.
55 Ibid., 2.
56 Ibid., 69.
57 Ibid., 73.
58 Ibid., 74, emphasis original.
59 “Rational reconstruction” is
a philosophical method that is
central to Parsons’s project. For
comparison, see Parsons, The
Philosophy of Design, 59, and 161,
note 5. The passage mentioned
here is particularly illustrative of
the method.
60 This sequence is another nice
illustration of a philosophical
method at work—one with roots
stretching back, presumably, to
Plato’s dialogues.
61 Parsons, The Philosophy of
Design, 100.
Self-Knowledge by Proxy
Page 9
330
she ji The Journal of Design, Economics, and Innovation Volume 2, Number 4, Winter 2016
62 Ibid., 86.
63 Ibid., 87.
64 Ibid., 92.
65 Ibid., 36.
66 Ibid., 37.
67 Ibid.,101.
68 Ibid., 102.
69 Ibid., emphasis original.
70 Ibid., 103. The original phrase,
repeated several times by
Sullivan, actually is “form ever
follows function.” See Louis H.
Sullivan, “The Tall Office Building
Artistically Considered,” in
Kindergarten Chats (Revised
1918) and Other Writings, ed.
Isabella Athey (New York: 1947
[1896]), accessed May 22, 2017,
http://academics.triton.edu/
faculty/fheitzman/tallofficebuild-
ing.html.
might express other meanings related to lifestyle, social status, and so on. So as for
the link between function and meaningful expression, we may conclude that at
best the Modernist vision allows for a “rather impoverished” expression via func-
tion—namely expression of the Zeitgeist, but even this is somewhat uncertain.
Chapter 5 is not primarily focused on the expression issue, however. It features
a much broader exploration and critical analysis of thenotion of function, which is
of fundamental importance to the Modernist vision. Although we often speak con-
fidently about function, it is not at all evident what the function of an artifact is. Is
the function of an artifact what the designer intended as its use, or is it how people
actually use it? If “I buy a chair and use it, not for sitting, but to display some books
in my living room, or to hang thenext day’s clothes on before I go to bed, aren’t
these things the ‘function’ of that artifact?” Parsons asks.62
He introduces a notion of proper function to clarify this “indeterminacy,”63 and
suggests that perhaps an evolutionary account fills the bill for a workable concep-
tion of proper functions of artifacts. The main idea is that the proper function of
an artifact depends on thehistory of its “ancestors”64 —it is what, in thepast, led
to the production of that kind of artifact. So, the “indeterminacy of function” with
which the chapter began is not fatal to the (potential) feasibility of theModernist
vision so far.
Later on, Parsons returns to the epistemological problem of how theDesigner
can “know (or be confident)” that a novel artifact will “eventually serve its pur-
pose” 65— that it will be able to “satisfy theaims for which it was created.”66 The
epistemological problem, you will recall, was triggered by the novelty of thepro-
posed artifact. But if theevolutionary theory of proper functions is right—that the
proper function of an artifact is “asocial aspect of an already-existing artifact type
that has evolved through its use and reproduction,”67 and hence not determined
by the Designer—then perhaps thereis no genuine novelty involved in Design,
and the whole epistemological problem dissolves! For example, “when the Wright
brothers invented theairplane they could draw upon an established body of empir-
ical knowledge about theproperties of kites.”68 However, Parsons rejects the possi-
bility of eliminating the epistemological problem because even if Designers “tinker
with existing types [of artifacts], they tinker with them for use in novel contexts,
or to do new things.”69 The epistemological problem of Design is not so easily done
away with.
So, at this point of Parsons’s critical analysis it remains an open question to
what extent theModernist vision, as reconstructed by him, is feasible—whether it
offers a workable solution to the epistemological problem. For the vision to do so,
it must plausibly support theDesigner’s confidence that a proposed novelartifact
will fulfill the four criteria that theModernists saw as the aims of good Design,
according to Parsons:functionality, expression (of the Zeitgeist), aesthetic value,
and mediation (of the human-to-world relationship). Arguably, functionality can be
achieved via general principles, but does this ensure that the other criteria will be
fulfilled automatically, as the Modernist vision has it? Expression of theZeitgeist
may be claimed, though not very convincingly, as we have seen. How will theMod-
ernist vision fare when it comes to aesthetic value and mediation?
Chapter 6, “Function, Form and Aesthetics” (pp. 103–128)
Chapter 6 explores theModernists’ postulated linkage between function and aes-
thetic value (beauty), which Parsons initially describes as the crucial Modernist idea
“that when ‘Form follows Function’ the result will be beauty.”70
The slogan “form follows function” attributed to architect Louis Sullivan
postulates what Parsons calls a linkage between form and function. He seems to
agree with critics of theslogan who maintain that, in general, there is no uniquely
Page 10
331
71 I suppose the form (shape)
of cogwheels, lenses, or turbine
blades must be fairly strictly
determined by the proper func-
tion (and the material) of those
artifacts. But consider a fashion
designer sketching an overcoat
or a pair of trousers. The proper
function of them would pre-
sumably be to cover the human
body, keep it warm, and so
forth—which would do very little
to determine a form, at least
concerning the crucial details. A
huge range of form options are
left open to the designer, to be
decided upon through consider-
ations of aesthetics, expression,
and the price, plus the availabil-
ity and provenance of materials,
and so on.
72 Parsons, The Philosophy of
Design, 106.
73 Ibid., 106–107.
74 Glenn Parsons and Allen
Carlson, Functional Beauty
(Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 2008).
75 Ibid., 228.
76 Ibid., 231.
77 Ibid., 231–32. The example
they attribute to Stephen
Davies.
78 Parsons, The Philosophy of
Design, 119.
79 Beyond, perhaps, a certain
sturdiness that the vital com-
ponents need for the vehicle to
carry heavy loads.
determinable form of an artifact which is optimalwith respect to (proper) func-
tion—perhaps except some purely technical artifacts.71 So, as he writes, “theun-
der-determination of form by function no doubt complicates the picturefor the
Modernist.”72
But given the way Parsons has reconstructed theModernist vision, its feasi-
bility as an antidoteto theepistemological problem of design does not stand and
fall with the truth of Sullivan’s slogan. Recall that Parsons’s rendition of theMod-
ernist vision does not assume any strict function–form linkage—only the function–
beauty, function–expression (considered in chapter 5), and function–mediation
linkages. As Parsons puts it, even though form may not follow function, “perhaps
the view that beauty can be realized through the pursuit of functionality can still
be maintained.”73 This gives Parsons the opportunity to delveinto theextensive lit-
erature on the nature of beauty, particularly in thecontext of design. The resulting
survey would no doubt be excellent reading for a course on design aesthetics. It
covers the notions of “functional beauty” and good and bad tastein design, among
other topics.
But our focus is the feasibility of the Modernist vision, so let us consider the
question whether or not thefunction–beauty linkage will work.
Seen from this vantage point, readers will find themost important topicin
chapter 6 in thesection titled “Functional Beauty.”It is quite a complex concept
that relies on material introduced in earlier sections, but thebasic idea is simple
enough: theway an object’s form is related to its (proper) function may endow that
object with a particular kind of beauty. This applies to a natural object—a bird’s
wing, for example—as well as an artifact.
In support of this, let us take a brief look at Functional Beauty, a book Parsons
published with Allen Carlson.74 In it, they write“some aesthetic qualities, not all,
involve function, or to put thepoint another way,… Functional Beauty is one spe-
cies of beauty, rather than beauty per se.”75 They say that theterm is ambiguous
between “beauty that emerges from function” and “beauty that is functional.”76
The latter might involve “a chair’s elegant curvature [that] fits with or contributes
to its function by making for a comfortable seat.”77 What the authors have chosen
to develop is the former notion—that of beauty emerging from function.
Drawing on his work with Allen Carlson, Parsons distinguishes four kinds of
functional beauty. Suffice it to mention one here, for illustration—theaesthetic
quality of “looking fit.” Things have this quality when their properties
“are indicative of a high degree of functionality. Thus, for example, pickup
trucks have a particular aesthetic that one can describe in terms of their
looking suited to move heavy loads—looking ‘chunky’ and ‘muscular.’ The
same sort of features would not be aesthetically pleasing in a different sort of
vehicle (a hearse, or a sports car, say).”78
Judging by this example, it is very plausible that there is some connection between
function and beauty. But is it a “linkage” of thesort the Modernist vision postu-
lates? No, not if we require that by virtue of thelinkage, beauty follows automat-
ically or “effortlessly”once one has taken care of function, or as a byproduct of
doing so. In the case of the pickup truck, that clunky and muscular look is chosen
deliberately by thedesigner.79 Similarly, thepointed shape of thesmoke box
door at thefront of thelocomotive in Figure 1 has little or nothing to do with its
functional capacity for speed but arguably contributes to its “looking fit” for its
purpose.
So, is theModernist vision unfeasible after all? Yes—if we use a very strict and
literal interpretation, it is. On the other hand, thefunctions of the pickup truck
and the express loco might have led designers to intentionally select individual
Self-Knowledge by Proxy
Page 11
332
she ji The Journal of Design, Economics, and Innovation Volume 2, Number 4, Winter 2016
80 This argument applies to
the “looking fit” version of
functional beauty. I believe
similar arguments in favor of the
function–beauty linkage could
be constructed with regard to
the remaining three versions of
functional beauty (Parsons, The
Philosophy of Design, 118–20).
They may be achieved on the
basis of functional consid-
erations, though not always
without a conscious effort on the
part of the designer.
81 Parsons, The Philosophy of
Design, 120.
82 Provided we have accepted
the somewhat shaky notion
of Zeitgeist-expression as the
sufficient manifestation of a link
between function and expres-
sion.
83 Parsons, The Philosophy of
Design, 129.
84 Ibid., 133.
85 Ibid., 132. Parsons takes this
example from Anke Van Gorp
and Ibo Van de Poel, “Deciding
on Ethical Issues in Engineering
Design,” in Philosophy and
Design: From Engineering to
Architecture, ed. Peter Kroes,
Pieter E. Vermaas, Andrew Light,
and Steven A. Moore (Dordrecht:
Springer Science+Business
Media BV, 2008), 77–78.
86 Parsons, The Philosophy of
Design, 29, quoting Verbeek,
What Things Do.
87 Ibid., 133, emphasis mine.
88 Ibid., emphasis original.
properties—chunkiness, pointiness—to makethose vehicles “look fit” for their
functions. This suggests that deliberately focusing on function helps the designer
achieve functional beauty in theartifact. If so, the Modernists’ function–beauty
linkage works after all—with a little help from the designer.80
Parsons reaches a verdict rather less charitable than mine. “Themere fact that
a given Design is functional will not make it beautiful,” he says, and concludes his
deliberation with “thepursuit of functionality will not always producethis sort of
beauty, but there are instances in which it will.”81
Where does this leave theModernist vision, I wonder? Giving it the benefit of
the doubt, we might conclude that the function–beauty link generally works, though
not entirely without effort on the part of theDesigner.
Chapter 7, “Ethics” (pp. 129–151)
If we accept theabove conclusion, the only thing required to reach a definite con-
clusion regarding thefeasibility of the Modernist vision as a whole is a good argu-
ment showing that thelast of its linkages will work—thetie between function and
mediation.82
In chapter 7, the term “ethics” is mainly used in its broad philosophical sense,
as referring to “a concern with the question of how one should live, or what a good
human life consists in.”83 This includes, but is not limited to, questions about what
rules of conduct one should abide by, and—of particular relevance to Design—what
values one should pursue, or, in cases of value conflict, should prefer. Safety, for
example, is a value that may conflict with thevalue of freedom, as in thecase of
seatbelt-linked ignition systems in automobiles; and security systems that effec-
tively protect public safety may compromise privacy.84 Designers, whether aware of
it or not, inevitably make decisions that may further certain values at the expense
of others, as these examples illustrate. Another example would be a decision about
whether to let the default print setting of a photocopier be “one-sided” or “two-
sided,” which obviously affects the paper consumption and thus has implications
for environmental sustainability.85
Thus, Design affects how we live in the world in many, often subtle ways. This
is what the author calls mediation earlier in thebook—the sense in which design
shapes “a relation between human beings and theworld.”86 In chapter 7, Parsons
presents mediation as one aspect of themuch broader subject of design ethics.
According to Parsons, the fact that much of design ethics is about paying
attention to values and resolving value conflicts “has an important implication for
the Modernist’s claim that purely functional Design will be ethically good Design. Clearly,
this thesis cannot be maintained, if we consider the ethical values relevant to
Design in the broadest sense,” because “highly functional Designs can negatively
affect freedom, privacy, and other ethical values.”87 Here, I assume that by “will be
ethically good Design” he means “will mediate thehuman–world relationship in
an ethically sound manner.” If so, the passage quoted clearly expresses a skeptical
stance towards the function–mediation linkage.
Parsons points out the possibility that somemight take the function–medi-
ation linkage to mean that purely functional design would “be beneficial in one
respect, by combating wasteful consumerism.”88 For example, a levelheaded focus
on function might prevent automobile Designers from redesigning their products
year after year to stimulate environmentally harmful over-consumption. But, on
the other hand, such focus would not halt unethical design behavior. It is entirely
possibleto design highly functional artifacts that are wasteful—Parsons submits
the example of a leaf-blower—simply because they solve a problem that does not
need solving.
So, for theModernist function–mediation linkage to work against wasteful
Page 12
333
consumerism, it is necessary to Design selectively and promotefunctions that
satisfy real needs, rather than mere wants. “TheModernist could then claim that
functional Design that addresses needs leads to ethically Good Design [in other
words, ‘mediates properly’], at least in thesense of reducing consumption,” which
would be well aligned with therejection of ornamentation advocated by Loos.89
Of course, “theidea that Designers, or anyone for that matter, can pronounce
about what counts as ‘genuine need’ invites objections.”90 Parsons acknowledges
this difficulty, but comes to the rescue of theDesigner, stating that “claims about
value can be mere prejudice but they can also be well thought out and grounded
in good reasons. It is plainly not true that making judgments of value will lead to
authoritarianism.”91
Even so, the fact remains that a daunting responsibility befalls theDesigner
as an ethical decision maker—a theme Parsons takes up in the closing section of
his chapter on ethics. As he puts it, “thequestion confronting the Designer is not
simply theempirical question—will this device do what it is supposed to?92 —but
rather the ethical question—should there be a device that does this?” And later, he
asks “how is theDesigner to decide … what things should do—what peopletruly
need?”
Parsons considers various methodological approaches intended to relieve
Designers of some of the burden of coping with these normative questions. He
ends up suggesting that “if the Designer is not, or cannot be, an ethicist, theethical
dimension of her task should be handled by a distinct person, working in conjunc-
tion with the Designer.”93 For example, “in the Design of health-care protocols …
‘qualified ethicists’ (usually philosophers)”are already employed.94
As for the Modernist’s alleged function–mediation linkage, Parsons draws no
definite conclusion as to its efficacy. However, from what I have summarized above,
it is fairly clear that the Modernist optimismabout an effortless resolution of
broader ethical issues of Design, via a focus on function, is wishful thinking rather
than a real possibility.
“Epilogue: The Meaning of Modernism” (pp. 152–153)
In his short concluding epilogue, Parsons focuses again on “theModernist’s at-
tempt to understand the significance of, and the prospects for, the Designer’s
project,” which, as he says, “has been a theme throughout our investigation of
Design.”95 Given that theModernist vision has been a recurring theme throughout
the book and has given Parsons the opportunity to discuss much philosophical
work on design, he has achieved the “systematictreatment”of such work that he
envisioned at theoutset. But what is theoutcome of his “critical analysis” of Mod-
ernist ideas?96
Earlier, I wondered whether theModernist vision might be a feasible approach
to Designing, in the sense of offering a workable solution to the epistemological
problem. There is no clear-cut answer to this feasibility question in theEpilogue—
nor elsewhere in the book—but there are hints at it, nevertheless. Parsons credits
the Modernists for having brought into focus “thekey issues of expression, func-
tion, aesthetics, and consumerism”97 and arranging them in a systemof connec-
tions. “While the Modernist’s ideas may not survive in their original form,” he says,
“their investigations, more than any others, provide thepoint around which a true
Philosophy of Design might crystalize.”98 Thelast part of this remark reflects his
interests as a philosopher, while thefeasibility question probably reflects a more
instrumental interest of mine, as a theorist of design—can designers use this? Even
so, Parsons’s remark suggests a partially negative reply to my feasibility question,
which is compatible with what I have suggested.
In sum, it appears that focusing on function may be a useful starting point for
89 Ibid., 134.
90 Ibid., 139.
91 Ibid.
92 Ibid., 146. This is one way
of putting the epistemological
problem of Design, as discussed
earlier.
93 Ibid, 151.
94 Ibid., 171, note 16.
95 Ibid., 152.
96 Ibid., 2–3.
97 Parsons’s use of “consumer-
ism” here, rather than “media-
tion” or “ethics,” which he uses
elsewhere in similar contexts,
is a bit puzzling. Perhaps it is a
trace of an earlier version of the
text that escaped editing?
98 Parsons, The Philosophy of
Design, 152.
Self-Knowledge by Proxy
Page 13
334
she ji The Journal of Design, Economics, and Innovation Volume 2, Number 4, Winter 2016
Design.99 “Functional beauty”may to some extent ensue without too much effort,
but ensuring a proper handling of expression and ethics (mediation) in Design re-
quires a good deal more hard work—and Design theory—than theModernists imag-
ined. There is no easy solution to the epistemological problem of Design, although
Modernist (rational) thinking might be worth considering in that connection.
A Modernist revival?
Reading Parsons’s cogent defense of Modernismin chapter 3, one might get the
idea that perhaps weshould seriously consider restoring Modernismto its former
glory, or at least amending its shortcomings to see if we could adapt it to a contem-
porary context? So, as an extrapolation of Parsons’s critical analysis—and leaving
aside thehuge issue of theepistemological problem100 —let me briefly play with
the idea of a Modernist revival in Design.
Given the partially negative reply to thefeasibility question summarized
above, and assuming one agrees with theModernists—that function, beauty, ex-
pression, and ethics (mediation) are the key criteria of good Design, with function
taking precedence—it follows that a feasible approach to futureDesign might grow
from the Modernist vision. Indeed, this would be possibleif we could overcome its
two major shortcomings: (1) the weak linkage between function and expression,
and (2) the lack of linkage between function and ethics.
Consider (1), function–expression. As Parsons showed in chapter 4, the Modernist
hopewas that a strict focus on function would enable theDesigner somehow to
express the Zeitgeist. This is even more problematic than Parsons suggested, for
independent reasons. Suppose, for the sake of argument, that theModernists were
right that their preoccupation with function and disregard for ornament would
automatically lead to artifacts that expressed theZeitgeist. Then, presumably, that
would be the spirit of their time—the early twentieth century. Now supposethat
today we began to practice theModernist approach to Design. What Zeitgeist would
we express—that of their time, or that of our own? In the first case, it would hardly
be relevant any more. In the second case, how would we achieve novel results using
the same Modernist method a hundred years later? Admittedly, designing for the
function of selfie sticks, surveillance cameras, and other recently introduced gad-
gets may express the spirit of our times. But what “spirit”would Designers com-
municate via contemporary Designs for shoes, teapots, road signs, newspapers, and
other kinds of artifacts that were also around in theheyday of Modernism? Stub-
bornly clinging to the idea of expressing the Zeitgeist leads to nowhere but trouble.
What matters for the contemporary Designer is making artifacts express what
they are intended for. This may involve their functions, but also other aspects, such as
easy maintenance, sustainable reuse of materials, theaffordance of a good experi-
ence (which overlaps with aesthetics and ethics), and much more. In short, we need
to master Design as a means of multiple kinds of communication. Judging from the
existing literature,101 this goal has already been achieved to a considerable degree.
But, it also seems fairly clear that there is no tie from function to expression which
automatically ensures that an artifact communicates whatever it should, merely
because we focus on its function.
Now consider (2), function–ethics. Similarly, attention to function is no shortcut
to mastering theethics of Design. Doing so takes a serious, conscious, well-in-
formed effort that calls for a strong dedication to teaching Designers a practical
application of ethical principles, and perhaps teamwork with qualified specialists
in ethics, as Parsons suggests.102 We are not left to our own devices, however. There
is considerable literature to provide us with the requisite concepts.103 The Contemplation
porary notion of “nudging”104 is remarkable as an overt attempt at “mediating”
the “human–world relation,” but nudging without competent, ethical reflection
99 This idea has considerable
currency in contemporary theo-
rizing and philosophizing about
design. See, for example, John S.
Gero and Udo Kannengiesser,
“The Situated Function-Be-
haviour-Structure Framework,”
Design Studies 25, no. 4 (2004):
373–91; and Peter Kroes,
Technical Artefacts: Creations of
Mind and Matter: A Philosophy of
Engineering Design (Dordrecht:
Springer Science+Business
Media BV, 2012), 135–40.
100 For some attempts to
grapple with it, see Per Galle,
“Candidate Worldviews for
Design Theory,” Design Studies
29, no. 3 (2008): 267–303.
101 A few relevant examples
are Nathan Crilly, David Good,
DerekMatravers, and P. John
Clarkson, “Design as Commu-
nication: Exploring the Validity
and Utility of Relating Intention
to Interpretation,” Design
Studies 29, no. 5 (2008): 425–57;
Donald A. Norman, The Design
of Everyday Things, rev. exp. ed.
(New York: Basic Books, 2013).
See also the literature cited by
Parsons in section 4.1 of The
Philosophy of Design, 69–73.
102 Parsons, The Philosophy of
Design, 151.
103 For example, see Verbeek,
What Things Do. In chapter 7,
Parsons cites Verbeekamong
many other relevant items of
literature. See also “Suggestions
for Further Reading,” The
Philosophy of Design, 172.
104 Pieter M. A. Desmet and
Anna E. Pohlmeyer, “Positive
Design: An Introduction to
Design for Subjective Well-Be-
ing,” International Journal of
Design 7, no. 3 (2013): 5–19;
Richard H. Thaler and Cass R.
Sunstein, Nudge: Improving De-
cisions About Health, Wealth, and
Happiness (New York: Penguin
Books, 2009).
Page 14
335
amounts to irresponsible manipulation.
Moreradical revisions of Modernismthan what I have considered here are
conceivable, of course. An obvious move would be to question the privileged role
of function as the (only) starting point for Designing.105 This raises thequestion of
the number and extent of the changes a revival of the Modernist idea could involve
before theresulting approach to Design can no longer go by the name of “Mod-
ernism.” However, I would pragmatically suggest that we should not worry about
that, but gratefully adopt whatever we can use from our Modernist heritage, and
move on.
Discussionof Selected Issues
As Parsons admits on behalf of his profession, “philosophy tends to producea
range of plausible positions, each with merits and difficulties, rather than unequiv-
ocal results.”106 Philosophy asks questions such as “under what conditions is a
counterfactual conditional statement true?” or “how much can a material object
change and yet remain the same thing?” or, indeed, “what is design?” Theseques-
tions cannot be settled by appealing to empirical evidence in the same robust way
as questions typically asked in science. Consequently, philosophers have developed
and refined a culture of competing “positions”that they test viathefriendly fire of
mutual criticism. Very seldom, however, is it possibleto come up with knockdown
arguments against particular positions, precisely because of thenature of the ques-
tions under debate. This means that several surviving but mutually incompatible
positions tend to live on side by side.107
As a user of philosophy for design research, I am regularly frustrated by the
numerous competing positions about virtually any philosophical question I want
to ask—what is knowledge, for example; what are properties; what does if mean; what
does it mean for something to be possible?108 But in my present capacity as a re-
viewer of a book on philosophy, it comes in handy that philosophical positions and
claims by their very nature invite critical commentary.
The philosophyof design—what and whence?
Parsons seeks to anticipateand dispelany confusion by making a distinction
between design theory—some of which has been referred to misleadingly as “phi-
losophy of design” in the literature—and what he takes to be philosophy of design
proper.109 Design theory is primarily motivated by and focused on “thepractice of
design,” and questions posed by design theory are “driven and framed by current
practical considerations in a way that those of philosophy arenot,”Parsons con-
tends. A philosophy of design, on theother hand, “would examine design, and its
specific aims and problems, in light of the fundamental questions that philosophy
examines: questions about knowledge, ethics, aesthetics, and the nature of reality.”110
I find it more disputablewhen Parsons claims “therehas not yet been a dis-
tinct field of inquiry called ‘thephilosophy of design.’”111 This naturally depends
on how one defines theterm. The following passage would seem to come close to a
definition that is quite compatible with the way Parsons himself presents thephi-
losophy of design. It stems from a special issue of Design Studies published in 2002,
dedicated to the theme “Philosophy of Design.”
“Rational reflection [on questions beyond theempirical realm], and the cultiva-
tion of such argumentative power and conceptual awareness as it takes, is the
business of philosophy as I understand it. If we can agree on this, we can prob-
ably also agree on characterising the philosophy of design straightforwardly as
the pursuit of insights about design by philosophical means.”112
105 For example, Norman
and others have suggested
emotions to be invoked. Donald
A. Norman, Emotional Design:
Why We Love (or Hate) Everyday
Things (New York: Basic Books,
2004); Steven F. Fokkinga and
Pieter M. A. Desmet, “Ten Ways
to Design for Disgust, Sadness,
and Other Enjoyments: A Design
Approach to Enrich Product
Experiences with Negative
Emotions,” International Journal
of Design 7, no. 1 (2013): 19–36.
Drawing on the ancient tradition
of epideictic rhetoric, Halstrøm
suggests that values to be cele-
brated may play a similar pivotal
role. Per Liljenberg Halstrøm,
“Design as Value Celebration:
Rethinking Design Arguments-
tation,” Design Issues 32, no. 4
(2016): 40–51.
106 Parsons, The Philosophy of
Design, 2.
107 Christopher Daly, “Per-
sistent Philosophical Disagree-
ment,” in Proceedings of the
Aristotelian Society CXVII, no. 1
(in press, 2017). For an explana-
tion of this persistent philosophi-
cal disagreement in terms of the
maintenance of logical consisten-
cy among basic assumptions, see
Nicholas Rescher, The Strife of
Systems: An Essay on the Grounds
and Implications of Philosoph-
ical Diversity (Pittsburgh: The
University of Pittsburgh Press,
1985); Nicholas Rescher, Aporet-
ics: Rational Deliberation in the
Face of Inconsistency (Pittsburgh:
The University of Pittsburgh
Press, 2009). A shorter summary
of Rescher’s main ideas can
be found in Nicholas Rescher,
“Apory,” in On Certainty: And
Other Philosophical Essays
on Cognition, ed. Nicholas
Rescher (Heusenstamm: Ontos
Verlag, 2011), 25–35. Of course,
in science everything is not
peace and harmony. Progress,
it has been argued, takes place
in terms of a revolutionary
succession of incompatible
“paradigms” (Kuhn), or co-ex-
isting, but competing “research
programs ”(Lakatos). Yet
on the whole, it makes sense
for (empirical) science to strive
for consensus in a way that
it does not for philosophy.
On paradigms, see Thomas S.
Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific
Revolutions, 3rd ed. (Chicago:
The University of Chicago Press,
1996). On research programmes,
see Imre Lakatos, “Falsification
Self-Knowledge by Proxy
Page 15
336
she ji The Journal of Design, Economics, and Innovation Volume 2, Number 4, Winter 2016
Even earlier, evidence of a nascent philosophy of design appeared in theproceed-
ings of a conference held in La Clusaz, France, in July 2000;113 but tracing the
origins of the field is difficult, so it would seem that no date, and no publication,
clearly marks its inception.114
As noted above, Parsons points out that “plenty of excellent philosophical
work … on, or relevant to, design”115 has been done in various fields of philosophy.
So thedifficulty of tracing the origins of the philosophy of design is probably con-
nected with difficulty in locating the relevant literature—there would seem to be
much work that could be classified both as philosophy of design and as something
else, such as philosophy of technology, or design methodology for example. But
overcoming this difficulty is rather a matter of librarianship than of philosophy or
design research, so I shall not pursueit here—nor indeed hold it against Parsons
that he doesn’t.
Essence and change
On page 6, in a discussion that leads up to his philosophical definition of design,
Parsons admits that formulating such definitions is controversial. He cites Jane
Forsey, who “rejects the possibility of a philosophical definition, or essence, for
design, on the grounds that design is a phenomenon that evolves historically.” Per-
sonally, I find it a difficult but fruitful exercise to try to develop increasingly better
and more accurate definitions of “design” and other key terms used in our field.
Such definitions serve as a basis for philosophy and theory of design alike, and I
wholeheartedly side with Parsons against Forsey’s skepticalview on the matter.
As he says, “Thefact that a phenomenon changes does not entail that it changes
its essential properties:cars are faster than they were 80 years ago, but this would
hardly be a reason to rethink our definition of ‘automobile.’”116
Likewise, what changes about design is not the nature (the essential properties)
of that activity itself, but the methods employed—such as introducing participatory
design methods, or ethnographic observation of user behavior—and the range of
things (artifacts) planned by designing. Nowadays, wesolve problems by making
plans for interactive computer games, surveillance cameras, selfie sticks, industrial
robots, branding campaigns, and many other kinds of artifacts that were unknown
a few generations back. Making such purposefulplans for a computer game, for
example, fits Parsons’s definition just as well as did making purposefulplans for
the engine of a paddle steamer, or for Queen Victoria’s wedding dress.
In recent years, it has become popular among some design theorists to talk
about “theexpanded design concept,”117 presumably for their discourse to accom-
modate rapid or significant developments in society. But for the reasons I have
stated, I find this phrasemore confusing than helpful for theorizing about devel-
opments in design practice or society at large. Fundamental concepts should be
carefully chosen and defined with longevity in mind, in the manner Parsons does,
particularly if they are to be useful for philosophizingand theorizing about a world
in flux. If our concept of X—our concept of design, or artifact, or function, and so
on—kept changing over time, how could we ever tell and understand thedifference
between an instance of X back then and an instance of X now?
What exactly is the essence of design?
So, I agree with Parsons that we can think fruitfully of design as having an essence—
some relatively stable properties that can be adduced as its defining characteristics
which the philosopher of design must disclose. But I have some minor reservations
concerning the particular essence of design that Parsons proposes in his definition:
“Design is the intentional solution of a problem, by the creation of plans for
a new sort of thing, where the plans would not be immediately seen, by a reasonable
and the Methodology of Scien-
tific Research Programmes,” in
The Methodology of Scientific
Research Programs: Philo-
sophical Papers, Volume I, eds.
John Worrall and Gregory
Currie (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1978), 8–101.
For a clear introduction to
Kuhn and Lakatos, see Peter
Godfrey-Smith, Theory and
Reality: An Introduction to the
Philosophy of Science (Chicago:
The University of Chicago Press,
2003), 75–135.
108 That frustration is tem-
pered, though, by my conviction
that such questions are import-
ant and must be approached.
The only approach to them
other than philosophy would
be dogmatism. Philosophy is
inherently rational—dogmatism
is not—and rationality is a value
to be cherished in research.
109 Parsons, The Philosophy of
Design, 1.
110 Ibid., 1–2.
111 Ibid., 2.
112 Per Galle, “Philosophy
of Design: An Editorial Intro-
duction,” Design Studies 23,
no. 3 (2002): 216, emphasis
as in original. For a short
introduction to the (emerging)
field of philosophy of design,
see Per Galle, “Philosophy of
Design: An Introduction,” Det
Royal Danish Academy of Fine Arts
Schools of Architecture, Design and
Conservation , revised January 16,
2009, https://kadk.dk/node/2071.
This web document is an edited
version of material from the
editorial introduction to the
special issue and the original
call for papers, Per Galle, “Call
for Papers: Special Issue on the
Philosophy of Design,” Design
Studies 21, no. 6 (2000): 607–10.
113 See “Session 1” in David
Durling and Ken Friedman,
Doctoral Education in Design:
Foundations for the Future
(Stroke-on-Trent: Staffordshire
University Press, 2000).
114 For an attempt to trace
the evasive origins of the
philosophy of design, see Per
Galle, “The Emergence of a
Philosophy of Design, ” Det
Royal Danish Academy of Fine Arts
Schools of Architecture, Design and
Conservation , February 7, 2007,
https://kadk.dk/node/2384, and
the accompanying bibliography
Page 16
337
person, as an inadequate solution.”118
First, what exactly does this non-inadequacy condition mean? To clarify this, con-
sider a passage just before the definition, where Parsons mentions a case that he
wants not to count as design, and which he uses as a motivation for adding the
condition in question. In that passage, he describes a person who plans out a time
machine by merely imagining thething, without any serious attempt at justifying
the effectiveness of those plans. Parsons says,
“Theproblem … is not that the plan does not work, but that it is so implau-
sible that any [i.e., every] reasonable person can see immediately that it [i.e., the plan]
will not work.”119
Negating the highlighted portion of this statement to find a condition that should,
presumably, be satisfied by a proper design case, we get
not every reasonable person would see immediately that theplan is an inade-
quate solution;
and an equivalent reformulation of this would be
not every reasonable person would immediately see theplan[s]120 as an inade-
quate solution.
By standard rules of logic, this is equivalent to
(1) some [at least one] reasonable person would not immediately see theplans as
an inadequate solution.
So, given the immediate context of the definition, (1) is a correct reading of the last
condition in Parsons’s definition.
On theother hand, it is also possible to read thephrase “areasonable person”
as “thetypical reasonable person”—in other words, “mostreasonable persons.”
It may even be read as “anyreasonable person”—in other words, “every reason-
able person.”Under these readings, thecondition assumes theforms (2) and (3),
respectively
(2) most reasonable peoplewould not immediately see theplans as an inade-
quate solution.
(3) every reasonable person would not immediately see the plans as an inade-
quate solution.
So it would seem that there are three plausible but logically different readings of
the non-inadequacy condition. Version (3) is stronger than (2), and version (2) is
stronger than (1), where “stronger than” means “more restrictive than,” “excluding
more cases than.”
This ambiguity may bother no one but nit-picking reviewers, and as I said, Par-
sons’s definition works all right for his book. Still, one may object—and this is my
second reservation—that at times the non-inadequacy condition makes thedefini-
tion rather non-operational, or difficult to apply to individual cases.
Consider a negative case, one that we do not want to count as design. Suppose
someone named Jones made plans for a time machine as in the example Parsons
discusses. Would Jones’s action be correctly dismissed by the definition as non-de-
sign, as Parsons claims it would?
According to reading (3), the answer is “yes,”since it would be easy to find one
or more reasonable persons who would immediately see Jones’s plans as an inade-
quate solution to the problem they purport to solve. Condition (3) clearly comes out
false.
According to reading (2), we might again find a number of reasonable persons
who would immediately see Jones’s plans as inadequate; but for (2) to come out
(up to 2011) by Per Galle, “The
CEPHAD Bibliography on the
Philosophy of Design, ” Det
Royal Danish Academy of Fine Arts
Schools of Architecture, Design and
Conservation , February 7 2007,
https://kadk.dk/node/2380. The
CEPHAD website, which con-
tains the three web documents
just cited, is being maintained as
an archive for reference, but is
no longer actively updated.
115 Parsons, The Philosophy of
Design, 2.
116 Ibid., 6.
117 Ken Friedman, “It Expands
ede Design concept, ”the magazine
Humanities 20, no. 3 (2005): 4–7.
For a recent discussion, see “The
Design Concept, ” eds. Charlie
I. Breindahl, Ida Engholm, Maria
Mackinney-Valentin, and Kirsten
Marie Raahauge, special issue,
Artifact 3, no. 4 (2015), available
at https://scholarworks.iu.edu/
journals/index.php/artifact/
issue/view/1166 , in which the
contributors debate the concept
of design. For a brief survey,
see Kirsten Marie Raahauge,
“Introduction: The Design
Concept – Anything, Everything,
Something or Nothing,” Artifact
3, no. 4 (2015): 1.1–1.6. A notion
related to “the expanded design
concept” is “design thinking,”
for which several conceptions
also exist. See, for example, Lucy
Kimbell, “Rethinking Design
Thinking: Part I,” Design and
Culture 3, no. 3 (2011): 285–306.
118 Parsons, The Philosophy of
Design, 11, emphasis mine.
119 Ibid., 11, emphasis mine.
I have enclosed alternative
formulations in brackets. These
are intended to preserve the
meaning while exposing connec-
tions to other statements in the
argument that follows.
120 By way of assimilation of my
wording to Parsons’s definition,
where he uses “plans,” I do the
same from here onwards. This
does not distort the meaning,
because in his discussion of the
time machine example, Parsons
could have used “plans” just
as well as “plan,” without any
significant change of meaning.
Self-Knowledge by Proxy
Page 17
338
she ji The Journal of Design, Economics, and Innovation Volume 2, Number 4, Winter 2016
false, as it should, half or more of all reasonable persons would have to see the plan
as inadequate. And how could this be established?
According to reading (1)—the reading for which we found supportingevidence
in the context of the definition—we would have to ask every reasonable person to
make sure that all of them immediately saw theplans as inadequate. And only then
would we know that (1) comes out false, as it should. But obviously, this is a hope-
lessly impractical procedure.
Now consider a positive case, one that we do want to count as design. We could
think of Jonathan Ive planning out the iPod, which is used by Parsons as such a pos-
itive case. Would Ive’s planning be correctly deemed worthy of the label “design,”
according to thedefinition, as it should?
According to reading (1), the answer is “yes.”It is easy to find a reasonable
person who does not immediately reject theplan. Presumably, Jonathan Ive himself
would take that point of view and be a reasonable person. And so the condition
comes out true, as desired.
According to reading (2), for the condition to come out true, we would have to
find more than half of all reasonable persons who would confirm that they did not
immediately see the plans as inadequate—not exactly an easy task.
According to reading (3), we would have to ask every reasonable person to
make sure that none of them immediately saw the plans as inadequate. Only thus
could we establish that thecondition comes out true, as desired. Clearly, this is an
impractical procedure.
To sum up, this thought experiment involves a negative and a positivecase,
each considered in relation to all three readings of Parsons’s non-inadequacy con-
dition. It provides some evidence in support of theconclusion that thedefinition
is operational for negative cases only for reading (3), and that it is operational for
positivecases only for reading (1). To be fair, however, Parsons does not promise
that his definition will be operational in the sense considered here. I find it a virtue
if a definition is operational—but once again, the one under consideration works
for the book.
My third reservation about the definition concerns the fact that it is time-depen-
dent. At one point in time, a reasonable person (living at that time) might not see
a particular set of plans as inadequate for a given purpose, while at another time
a reasonable person (living at that other time) might see the plans as inadequate.
The perpetualmotion device is a case in point. Over a century and a half ago, rea-
sonable peopletook the possibility of such devices seriously, and sometimes even
imagined that perpetualmotion devices could carry out useful work.121 In our
time, on the other hand, many reasonable peopleknow that perpetualmotion
devices cannot work as intended. So, making plans for a perpetualmotion device in
the seventeenth or eighteenth century might well count as design, according to the
definition (under any of its three readings). However, making the same plans today
would not—except possibly under reading (1), if some reasonable person failed to
have sufficient knowledge of physics to reject theplans.
Such time dependency122 of theoutcome when applyingthedefinition to
identical or similar cases is not desirable—it does not accord with Parsons’s idea of
a stable essence of the concept of design.
Parsons himself expands somewhat on his non-inadequacy condition. It is only
intended to rule out “plans that are obviously inadequate in principle,” not “plans
that are hopeless for practical reasons, such as time constraints, theexpense in-
volved, or therarity of necessary materials.”123 I agree that a definition of design
should leave room for failure. But why accept failure with regard to practical
matters, and rule out inadequacy in principle? Or conversely, if thelatter must be
ruled out by definition, then why not rule out the former as well? To do so, one
121 For a fascinatingly serious
treatise on the topic, see Henry
Dircks, Perpetuum Mobile; or
Seaech for Self-Motive Power,
During the 17th, 18th, and 19th
Centuries (London: E. & F. N.
Spon, 1870), available at https://
archive.org/details/perpetuum-
mobile00dircgoog.
122 More precisely: dependency
on the general level of enlight-
enment in society at different
times.
123 Parsons, The Philosophy of
Design, 11.
Page 18
339
could simply expand the third condition, somewhat like this: “… where theplans
would not be immediately seen, by a reasonable person, as an inadequate solution
in principle or practically.” This would rule out both a proposalfor a perpetualmotion
device made by a person ignorant of physics, and a proposalfor some excessively
expensive bathroom (say), made by a person ignorant of the cost of fixtures, mate-
rials, and labor.
However, I am not suggesting Parsons should have done this. In my view, a
philosophical definition of design should capturethe essence of the concept, and
nothing else. The properties of being good or poor are not part of the essence of
design, since (I assume) there are different cases of what we want to call “design”
which exhibit one, the other, and neither of these two properties.
What I am suggesting is that once we decide to proceed with a philosophical
definition of design that captures some essence, then we can begin to consider
the good/poor distinction as applied to cases that fall under the defined concept.
In other words, we can then start to develop normative criteria to determine the
goodness and poorness of such cases. To the extent ethical considerations are in-
volved, developing such criteria may still be a matter of philosophy of design. But
just as much, or even more, distinguishing good from poor design may be a matter
of design theory—and the empirical question of the extent to which a given case is
“good” or “poor”with respect to given criteria certainly is.124
The design/Design distinction and the epistemological problem
Reflecting on his definition of design, Parsons worries that it is too inclusive because
it also comprises theplan-making activities of peoplewe do not usually call “de-
signers.” As he says, “how are we to account for the linguistic fact […] that Madison,
Einstein and your plumber [all of whom design in the sense of the definition] are
not called ‘designers’, whereas Eames, Ive and Starck are?”125
Considering this problem, Parsons quickly gives up adding further conditions
to the definition itself, so as to narrow down the class of activities it captures.
Instead, he ends up accepting it as a definition of “design” (spelled with a lower-
case d), understood as a broad class of rather generic cognitive activities. And then,
within this class, he seeks to delimit a subclass, named “Design” (spelled with an
uppercaseD), including only the design activities of “Designers” such as Ives and
Eames, whom we do not hesitate to call “designers.”
I suspect—and this is a mere guess, since it is not explicitly stated in the book—
that this move has little or nothing to do with Parsons’s deep interest in the“lin-
guistic fact” that what peoplelike presidents, inventors, and plumbers do is not
called design.126 What I think is his real motivation for introducing the design/
Design distinction is to focus exclusively on Design, to preparethe ground for
the important idea he advances later on in the book—namely, that the Modernist
approach to Designing127 promises a solution to “theepistemological problem.”128
Presumably, Modernist ideas were, and perhaps still are, at work in the practices of
Design that include architectural and industrial design, among other disciplines—
but not in other design practices, such as chemical and other kinds of engineering
design, for example, or plumbing for that matter. Limiting thescope of inquiry in
preparation for what is to follow on Modernismis a legitimate move, but one that
nevertheless calls for two comments.
First, the epistemological problem is a problem pertaining to design in gen-
eral, not only to design as practiced by peoplewhom we traditionally call “design-
ers.”129 So by limiting the scopeof inquiry to Design, and treating the epistemo-
logical problem as a “difficulty for Design,” Parsons restricts himself to considering
only a partialsolution to the epistemological problem.130
Second, since limiting the scopeof inquiry to Design is so important for
124 An interesting and system-
atic set of generic criteria for
good design, relatively to various
stakeholders, was recently
proposed in chapter 14 of
Andreasen, Hansen, and Cash,
Conceptual Design. Interpreta-
tions, Mindset and Models. The
authors do not offer a philo-
sophical definition of design in
Parsons’s sense, but suggest that
“Design in the broadest sense
describes innovating or improv-
ing the means (either material
or immaterial) for addressing
human needs.” Mogens M.
Andreasen, Claus T. Hansen, and
Philip Cash, Conceptual Design:
Interpretations, Mindset and
Models (Cham: Springer Inter-
national Publishing Switzerland,
2015), 2, emphasis original.
125 Parsons, The Philosophy of
Design, 21.
126 Ibid., 21. Indeed, why bother
to account for it? After all,
conceptual analysis in philosophy
need not be concerned with
providing definitions of linguistic
expressions, faithfully reflecting
every twist and turn of ordinary
native-speaker practice. That is
the job of lexicographers prepar-
ing a dictionary for a particular
language. In the development
of philosophical definitions,
linguistic practice may act as
a guidance, and should not be
drastically violated if that can be
avoided. But a certain amount of
normativity may be acceptable,
or even useful—at least if the
aim is to hone our (academic)
language and concepts, to make
them serve our understanding
of the world in the best possible
way. For a concise introduction
to some of these issues, see
Norman Swartz, “Definitions,
Dictionaries, and Meanings,”
Philosophical Notes, last mod-
ified November 8, 2010, http: //
www.sfu.ca/~swartz/definitions.
htm.
127 Parsons, The Philosophy of
Design, 63; see also the outline of
chapter 3 above.
128 See the outline of chapter 2.
129 I can say this with convic-
tion because, as already noted in
the outline of chapter 2, Parsons
is kind enough to state the epis-
temological problem by means
of a quote from a paper of
mine: Galle, “Foundational and
Instrumental Design Theory.” In
that paper I was talking about
Self-Knowledge by Proxy
Page 19
340
she ji The Journal of Design, Economics, and Innovation Volume 2, Number 4, Winter 2016
what Parsons wants to say about theModernist approach to the epistemological
problem, it is only natural that he wants to define or at least characterize his con-
cept of Design in a systematicand principled way, simply because this would add to
the theoretical elegance of his analyses of Modernist ideas. Unfortunately, as I have
come to realize on a close re-reading of section 1.3, his attempt to systematize the
design/Design distinction does not work. I will argue this point below.
Meanwhile, let me emphasizethat this criticism is by no means fatal to the
main line of reasoning presented in the book. A straightforward way to achieve
the desired limitation of scopewould have been to define the concept of Design131
simply by enumerating the kinds of design to be labeled “Design.” As you read the
book, you can compile such a list for yourself (at least partially) based on theexam-
ples he offers.
The alleged characteristics of Design in particularas opposed to design in general
However, as noted above, Parsons makes an attempt at defining or characterizing
his concept of Design in a more systematicand principled way.
He begins by posing the question “what makes certain peoplemembers of the
Design profession or practice, as opposed to merely peopleengaging in the activity of
design?”132 His responsecomes in two separatepassages, namely
(1) “Design practice [stands apart] from design in general by its focus on con-
ceiving, rather than constructing, the surfaces of primarily practical things;”133 and
(2) “TheDesigner attempts to create plans for the surface features of a novel
device or process that will solve some primarily practical problem.”134
I find this way of distinguishing Design from design unconvincing. Let me explain
why.
According to Parsons’s definition of design, all design is about conceiving
rather than constructing. The definition mentions “creation of plans for a new
sort of thing”135 —that is conceiving—but says nothing about constructing anything
according to those plans. And since Design is supposed to bea special kind of design,
conceiving rather than constructing cannot be a distinctive feature of Design.
Furthermore, in my experience (mainly involving students and colleagues
at theRoyal Danish Academy of Fine Arts), designers such as architects—whom
Parsons would call “Designers”— admittedly do tend to conceive rather than con-
struct buildings, for rather obvious reasons. However, fashion designers, graphic
designers, game designers, production designers,136 furniture designers, and to
some extent industrial designers, for example—all of whom Parsons would also
label “Designers”—tend to construct as well as conceive the artifacts for which they
are creating plans. At thevery least, they build mock-ups or scale models or proto-
types—indeed, they sometimes conceive by the very act of constructing.137 No one
would deny them the privilege of being called professional (uppercaseD) Designers
once they have graduated. So, for this reason, too, we cannot use “conceiving,
rather than constructing” as a distinctive feature of Design.
How about the alleged focus on “primarily practical things” as something
characteristic of Designers? Parsons motivates this idea by contrasting the aim of
Design with those of science and art. He says that “despitemany differences, the
arts and sciences seem to share the primary aim of enriching our understanding of
the world rather than [aiming, as Design does, at] allowing us to change it.”138 He
admits that a focus on practical function as a characteristic of Design may not fit
very well in areas such as fashion or interior design, where aesthetic considerations
may be stronger. Nevertheless, he insists, “beautiful rooms that one cannot live in,
and beautiful clothes that cannot be worn may succeed as art, but not as Design.”
Even if we grant Parsons that, it would seem that all he can claim by this argument
design in a broad sense, not
(only) about what Parsons calls
(uppercase D) “Design.”
130 More comprehensive
solutions have been proposed,
however. For example, recent
work by van Eck can be read as
such a proposal. Dingmar van
Eck, “Dissolving the ‘Problem
of the Absent Artifact’: Design
Representations as Means for
Counterfactual Understanding
and Knowledge Generalisation, ”
Design Studies 39 (2015): 1–18.
131 Personally, I prefer to con-
sider definitions as statements
that describe the conditions
under which a particular lin-
guistic expression can be applied
(for example, “Design”), but it is
quite common to consider defi-
nitions as something applied to
concepts (for example, design).
This seems to be what Parsons
does, so in this paper I will follow
his practice.
132 Parsons, The Philosophy of
Design, 21, emphasis original.
133 Ibid., 24, emphasis mine.
134 Ibid., 28, emphasis mine.
135 Ibid., 11.
136 Production designers are
responsible for the scenography
and other effects used in the film
industry.
137 At the Academy, we consid-
er tool handling and workshop
experience in design education
a valuable heritage from the
Bauhaus school.
138 Parsons, The Philosophy of
Design, 22.
Page 20
341
is to have made a distinction between design on the one hand, and art and science
on the other—not, as intended, between design and Design.
This leaves us with Parsons’s third and final proposalfor a feature distin-
guishing Design from design: Design, but not the rest of design, is concerned with
the surface features of novel devices. Parsons makes it clear that, in this context,
“surface” involves “theway the object is used and the way it responds to use.”139
“In other words,” he adds, “theDesigner’s point of view on the object is that of the
user,” along the lines of Krippendorff’s second-order understanding.140
So far, so good. But then Parsons goes on to claim “only thosecomponents or
aspects of theobject that figure in theuser’s relation to the object are theprovince
of the Designer. This is in contrast to the perspectiveof the engineer….”141
I highly doubt that my design students would sign a declaration to the effect
that their focus is limited to the user’s relation to an artifact. Very often, they are
Filsafat dalam desain
Filsafat dalam desain

More Related Content

What's hot

Urgensi Pancasila Sebagai Ideologi Negara Indonesia
Urgensi Pancasila Sebagai Ideologi Negara IndonesiaUrgensi Pancasila Sebagai Ideologi Negara Indonesia
Urgensi Pancasila Sebagai Ideologi Negara Indonesiadayurikaperdana19
 
Organisasi Pembelajaran (Learning Organization)
Organisasi Pembelajaran (Learning Organization)Organisasi Pembelajaran (Learning Organization)
Organisasi Pembelajaran (Learning Organization)Tri Widodo W. UTOMO
 
Modul 4.2 Teknik dan Kriteria dalam Analisis Kebijakan
Modul 4.2 Teknik dan Kriteria dalam Analisis KebijakanModul 4.2 Teknik dan Kriteria dalam Analisis Kebijakan
Modul 4.2 Teknik dan Kriteria dalam Analisis Kebijakanunitpublikasi
 
Monev Partisipatif. Evaluasi Dampak Berbasis Masyarakat. Sebuah Panduan untuk...
Monev Partisipatif. Evaluasi Dampak Berbasis Masyarakat. Sebuah Panduan untuk...Monev Partisipatif. Evaluasi Dampak Berbasis Masyarakat. Sebuah Panduan untuk...
Monev Partisipatif. Evaluasi Dampak Berbasis Masyarakat. Sebuah Panduan untuk...Oswar Mungkasa
 
Konsep Dasar Perencanaan
Konsep Dasar PerencanaanKonsep Dasar Perencanaan
Konsep Dasar PerencanaanDadang Solihin
 
Model Formulasi Kebijakan
Model Formulasi KebijakanModel Formulasi Kebijakan
Model Formulasi KebijakanZakiah dr
 
Kel.4 pancasila sebagai ideologi bangsa 222
Kel.4 pancasila sebagai ideologi bangsa 222Kel.4 pancasila sebagai ideologi bangsa 222
Kel.4 pancasila sebagai ideologi bangsa 222dayurikaperdana19
 
Penyusunan Indikator Kinerja Pembangunan
Penyusunan Indikator Kinerja PembangunanPenyusunan Indikator Kinerja Pembangunan
Penyusunan Indikator Kinerja PembangunanDadang Solihin
 
Sekelumit Tentang Penyusunan Policy Brief
Sekelumit Tentang Penyusunan Policy BriefSekelumit Tentang Penyusunan Policy Brief
Sekelumit Tentang Penyusunan Policy BriefRusman R. Manik
 
Konsep Pemantauan dan Evaluasi
Konsep Pemantauan dan  EvaluasiKonsep Pemantauan dan  Evaluasi
Konsep Pemantauan dan EvaluasiDadang Solihin
 
Struktur Teks dan Genre Mikro pada Artikel Penelitian
Struktur Teks dan Genre Mikro pada Artikel PenelitianStruktur Teks dan Genre Mikro pada Artikel Penelitian
Struktur Teks dan Genre Mikro pada Artikel PenelitianUwes Chaeruman
 
Konsep Dasar Perencanaan
Konsep Dasar PerencanaanKonsep Dasar Perencanaan
Konsep Dasar PerencanaanDadang Solihin
 
Konsep Monitoring dan Evaluasi
Konsep Monitoring dan Evaluasi Konsep Monitoring dan Evaluasi
Konsep Monitoring dan Evaluasi Dadang Solihin
 
Evaluasi Formatif dan Sumatif
Evaluasi Formatif dan SumatifEvaluasi Formatif dan Sumatif
Evaluasi Formatif dan SumatifMuhammad Bahrudin
 
Aktualisasi Pancasila Di Kampus
Aktualisasi Pancasila Di KampusAktualisasi Pancasila Di Kampus
Aktualisasi Pancasila Di KampusAbida Muttaqiena
 
Faktor faktor yang mempengaruhi perilaku
Faktor faktor yang mempengaruhi perilakuFaktor faktor yang mempengaruhi perilaku
Faktor faktor yang mempengaruhi perilakuhanafieminence
 

What's hot (20)

Urgensi Pancasila Sebagai Ideologi Negara Indonesia
Urgensi Pancasila Sebagai Ideologi Negara IndonesiaUrgensi Pancasila Sebagai Ideologi Negara Indonesia
Urgensi Pancasila Sebagai Ideologi Negara Indonesia
 
Organisasi Pembelajaran (Learning Organization)
Organisasi Pembelajaran (Learning Organization)Organisasi Pembelajaran (Learning Organization)
Organisasi Pembelajaran (Learning Organization)
 
siklus kebijakan publik
siklus kebijakan publiksiklus kebijakan publik
siklus kebijakan publik
 
Modul 4.2 Teknik dan Kriteria dalam Analisis Kebijakan
Modul 4.2 Teknik dan Kriteria dalam Analisis KebijakanModul 4.2 Teknik dan Kriteria dalam Analisis Kebijakan
Modul 4.2 Teknik dan Kriteria dalam Analisis Kebijakan
 
Monev Partisipatif. Evaluasi Dampak Berbasis Masyarakat. Sebuah Panduan untuk...
Monev Partisipatif. Evaluasi Dampak Berbasis Masyarakat. Sebuah Panduan untuk...Monev Partisipatif. Evaluasi Dampak Berbasis Masyarakat. Sebuah Panduan untuk...
Monev Partisipatif. Evaluasi Dampak Berbasis Masyarakat. Sebuah Panduan untuk...
 
Konsep Dasar Perencanaan
Konsep Dasar PerencanaanKonsep Dasar Perencanaan
Konsep Dasar Perencanaan
 
Pertemuan ke 3 - perencanaan sosial
Pertemuan ke 3 - perencanaan  sosialPertemuan ke 3 - perencanaan  sosial
Pertemuan ke 3 - perencanaan sosial
 
Model Formulasi Kebijakan
Model Formulasi KebijakanModel Formulasi Kebijakan
Model Formulasi Kebijakan
 
Kel.4 pancasila sebagai ideologi bangsa 222
Kel.4 pancasila sebagai ideologi bangsa 222Kel.4 pancasila sebagai ideologi bangsa 222
Kel.4 pancasila sebagai ideologi bangsa 222
 
Penyusunan Indikator Kinerja Pembangunan
Penyusunan Indikator Kinerja PembangunanPenyusunan Indikator Kinerja Pembangunan
Penyusunan Indikator Kinerja Pembangunan
 
Sekelumit Tentang Penyusunan Policy Brief
Sekelumit Tentang Penyusunan Policy BriefSekelumit Tentang Penyusunan Policy Brief
Sekelumit Tentang Penyusunan Policy Brief
 
Konsep Pemantauan dan Evaluasi
Konsep Pemantauan dan  EvaluasiKonsep Pemantauan dan  Evaluasi
Konsep Pemantauan dan Evaluasi
 
Struktur Teks dan Genre Mikro pada Artikel Penelitian
Struktur Teks dan Genre Mikro pada Artikel PenelitianStruktur Teks dan Genre Mikro pada Artikel Penelitian
Struktur Teks dan Genre Mikro pada Artikel Penelitian
 
Konsep Dasar Perencanaan
Konsep Dasar PerencanaanKonsep Dasar Perencanaan
Konsep Dasar Perencanaan
 
Konsep Monitoring dan Evaluasi
Konsep Monitoring dan Evaluasi Konsep Monitoring dan Evaluasi
Konsep Monitoring dan Evaluasi
 
Evaluasi Formatif dan Sumatif
Evaluasi Formatif dan SumatifEvaluasi Formatif dan Sumatif
Evaluasi Formatif dan Sumatif
 
Aktualisasi Pancasila Di Kampus
Aktualisasi Pancasila Di KampusAktualisasi Pancasila Di Kampus
Aktualisasi Pancasila Di Kampus
 
Isu kontemporer
Isu kontemporerIsu kontemporer
Isu kontemporer
 
Modul 7 sub modul 2
Modul 7 sub modul 2Modul 7 sub modul 2
Modul 7 sub modul 2
 
Faktor faktor yang mempengaruhi perilaku
Faktor faktor yang mempengaruhi perilakuFaktor faktor yang mempengaruhi perilaku
Faktor faktor yang mempengaruhi perilaku
 

Similar to Filsafat dalam desain

A Practical Guide To Better Research And Writing For Design Students
A Practical Guide To Better Research And Writing For Design StudentsA Practical Guide To Better Research And Writing For Design Students
A Practical Guide To Better Research And Writing For Design StudentsKayla Smith
 
Personal study essay guide
Personal study essay guidePersonal study essay guide
Personal study essay guidemissfcmay
 
A2 Personal Study Guide
A2 Personal Study GuideA2 Personal Study Guide
A2 Personal Study Guidemissfcmay
 
Rothman discourse essay prompt context when y
Rothman discourse essay prompt   context  when yRothman discourse essay prompt   context  when y
Rothman discourse essay prompt context when yaryan532920
 
A2 personal study essay guide
A2 personal study essay guide A2 personal study essay guide
A2 personal study essay guide missfcmay
 
A2 personal study guide 2013
A2 personal study guide 2013A2 personal study guide 2013
A2 personal study guide 2013missfcmay
 
How to Get a PhD
How to Get a PhDHow to Get a PhD
How to Get a PhDadil raja
 
Final 1.3.12 cs 2 module 3 wbs3760
Final 1.3.12 cs 2 module 3 wbs3760Final 1.3.12 cs 2 module 3 wbs3760
Final 1.3.12 cs 2 module 3 wbs3760Paula Nottingham
 
Typefesto: Co-creation Toolkit
Typefesto: Co-creation ToolkitTypefesto: Co-creation Toolkit
Typefesto: Co-creation ToolkitBrittany Garuk
 
Reference manual project report2
Reference manual project report2Reference manual project report2
Reference manual project report2Vidhushri
 
Final m3 session 2 15.3.17
Final m3 session 2 15.3.17 Final m3 session 2 15.3.17
Final m3 session 2 15.3.17 Paula Nottingham
 
Aspects Of Research Through Design
Aspects Of Research Through DesignAspects Of Research Through Design
Aspects Of Research Through DesignAndrea Porter
 
The Science, Engineering and Social Impact of Nanotechnology.docx
The Science, Engineering and Social Impact of Nanotechnology.docxThe Science, Engineering and Social Impact of Nanotechnology.docx
The Science, Engineering and Social Impact of Nanotechnology.docxoreo10
 
Updated session 2 m3 29.10.15
Updated session 2 m3 29.10.15Updated session 2 m3 29.10.15
Updated session 2 m3 29.10.15Paula Nottingham
 
Chapter 4 (review of literature)
Chapter 4 (review of literature)Chapter 4 (review of literature)
Chapter 4 (review of literature)BoreyThai1
 
CHAPTER 2 REVIEW OF THE LITERATUREBesides selecting a quantita
CHAPTER 2 REVIEW OF THE LITERATUREBesides selecting a quantitaCHAPTER 2 REVIEW OF THE LITERATUREBesides selecting a quantita
CHAPTER 2 REVIEW OF THE LITERATUREBesides selecting a quantitaEstelaJeffery653
 
Literature Review © 2017 Laureate Education, Inc. .docx
Literature Review  © 2017 Laureate Education, Inc.  .docxLiterature Review  © 2017 Laureate Education, Inc.  .docx
Literature Review © 2017 Laureate Education, Inc. .docxcroysierkathey
 
Role of review of literature in research process
Role of review of literature in research processRole of review of literature in research process
Role of review of literature in research processKrishnanchalil
 
An Account Of Writing As Creative Design
An Account Of Writing As Creative DesignAn Account Of Writing As Creative Design
An Account Of Writing As Creative DesignSandra Long
 

Similar to Filsafat dalam desain (20)

A Practical Guide To Better Research And Writing For Design Students
A Practical Guide To Better Research And Writing For Design StudentsA Practical Guide To Better Research And Writing For Design Students
A Practical Guide To Better Research And Writing For Design Students
 
Personal study essay guide
Personal study essay guidePersonal study essay guide
Personal study essay guide
 
A2 Personal Study Guide
A2 Personal Study GuideA2 Personal Study Guide
A2 Personal Study Guide
 
Rothman discourse essay prompt context when y
Rothman discourse essay prompt   context  when yRothman discourse essay prompt   context  when y
Rothman discourse essay prompt context when y
 
A2 personal study essay guide
A2 personal study essay guide A2 personal study essay guide
A2 personal study essay guide
 
A2 personal study guide 2013
A2 personal study guide 2013A2 personal study guide 2013
A2 personal study guide 2013
 
How to Get a PhD
How to Get a PhDHow to Get a PhD
How to Get a PhD
 
Final 1.3.12 cs 2 module 3 wbs3760
Final 1.3.12 cs 2 module 3 wbs3760Final 1.3.12 cs 2 module 3 wbs3760
Final 1.3.12 cs 2 module 3 wbs3760
 
Typefesto: Co-creation Toolkit
Typefesto: Co-creation ToolkitTypefesto: Co-creation Toolkit
Typefesto: Co-creation Toolkit
 
Reference manual project report2
Reference manual project report2Reference manual project report2
Reference manual project report2
 
Final m3 session 2 15.3.17
Final m3 session 2 15.3.17 Final m3 session 2 15.3.17
Final m3 session 2 15.3.17
 
Aspects Of Research Through Design
Aspects Of Research Through DesignAspects Of Research Through Design
Aspects Of Research Through Design
 
The Science, Engineering and Social Impact of Nanotechnology.docx
The Science, Engineering and Social Impact of Nanotechnology.docxThe Science, Engineering and Social Impact of Nanotechnology.docx
The Science, Engineering and Social Impact of Nanotechnology.docx
 
Updated session 2 m3 29.10.15
Updated session 2 m3 29.10.15Updated session 2 m3 29.10.15
Updated session 2 m3 29.10.15
 
Chapter 4 (review of literature)
Chapter 4 (review of literature)Chapter 4 (review of literature)
Chapter 4 (review of literature)
 
Chapter4 review of literature
Chapter4 review of literatureChapter4 review of literature
Chapter4 review of literature
 
CHAPTER 2 REVIEW OF THE LITERATUREBesides selecting a quantita
CHAPTER 2 REVIEW OF THE LITERATUREBesides selecting a quantitaCHAPTER 2 REVIEW OF THE LITERATUREBesides selecting a quantita
CHAPTER 2 REVIEW OF THE LITERATUREBesides selecting a quantita
 
Literature Review © 2017 Laureate Education, Inc. .docx
Literature Review  © 2017 Laureate Education, Inc.  .docxLiterature Review  © 2017 Laureate Education, Inc.  .docx
Literature Review © 2017 Laureate Education, Inc. .docx
 
Role of review of literature in research process
Role of review of literature in research processRole of review of literature in research process
Role of review of literature in research process
 
An Account Of Writing As Creative Design
An Account Of Writing As Creative DesignAn Account Of Writing As Creative Design
An Account Of Writing As Creative Design
 

Recently uploaded

Unit 3 Emotional Intelligence and Spiritual Intelligence.pdf
Unit 3 Emotional Intelligence and Spiritual Intelligence.pdfUnit 3 Emotional Intelligence and Spiritual Intelligence.pdf
Unit 3 Emotional Intelligence and Spiritual Intelligence.pdfDr Vijay Vishwakarma
 
Micro-Scholarship, What it is, How can it help me.pdf
Micro-Scholarship, What it is, How can it help me.pdfMicro-Scholarship, What it is, How can it help me.pdf
Micro-Scholarship, What it is, How can it help me.pdfPoh-Sun Goh
 
How to Give a Domain for a Field in Odoo 17
How to Give a Domain for a Field in Odoo 17How to Give a Domain for a Field in Odoo 17
How to Give a Domain for a Field in Odoo 17Celine George
 
COMMUNICATING NEGATIVE NEWS - APPROACHES .pptx
COMMUNICATING NEGATIVE NEWS - APPROACHES .pptxCOMMUNICATING NEGATIVE NEWS - APPROACHES .pptx
COMMUNICATING NEGATIVE NEWS - APPROACHES .pptxannathomasp01
 
ICT role in 21st century education and it's challenges.
ICT role in 21st century education and it's challenges.ICT role in 21st century education and it's challenges.
ICT role in 21st century education and it's challenges.MaryamAhmad92
 
2024-NATIONAL-LEARNING-CAMP-AND-OTHER.pptx
2024-NATIONAL-LEARNING-CAMP-AND-OTHER.pptx2024-NATIONAL-LEARNING-CAMP-AND-OTHER.pptx
2024-NATIONAL-LEARNING-CAMP-AND-OTHER.pptxMaritesTamaniVerdade
 
Exploring_the_Narrative_Style_of_Amitav_Ghoshs_Gun_Island.pptx
Exploring_the_Narrative_Style_of_Amitav_Ghoshs_Gun_Island.pptxExploring_the_Narrative_Style_of_Amitav_Ghoshs_Gun_Island.pptx
Exploring_the_Narrative_Style_of_Amitav_Ghoshs_Gun_Island.pptxPooja Bhuva
 
Plant propagation: Sexual and Asexual propapagation.pptx
Plant propagation: Sexual and Asexual propapagation.pptxPlant propagation: Sexual and Asexual propapagation.pptx
Plant propagation: Sexual and Asexual propapagation.pptxUmeshTimilsina1
 
On_Translating_a_Tamil_Poem_by_A_K_Ramanujan.pptx
On_Translating_a_Tamil_Poem_by_A_K_Ramanujan.pptxOn_Translating_a_Tamil_Poem_by_A_K_Ramanujan.pptx
On_Translating_a_Tamil_Poem_by_A_K_Ramanujan.pptxPooja Bhuva
 
This PowerPoint helps students to consider the concept of infinity.
This PowerPoint helps students to consider the concept of infinity.This PowerPoint helps students to consider the concept of infinity.
This PowerPoint helps students to consider the concept of infinity.christianmathematics
 
80 ĐỀ THI THỬ TUYỂN SINH TIẾNG ANH VÀO 10 SỞ GD – ĐT THÀNH PHỐ HỒ CHÍ MINH NĂ...
80 ĐỀ THI THỬ TUYỂN SINH TIẾNG ANH VÀO 10 SỞ GD – ĐT THÀNH PHỐ HỒ CHÍ MINH NĂ...80 ĐỀ THI THỬ TUYỂN SINH TIẾNG ANH VÀO 10 SỞ GD – ĐT THÀNH PHỐ HỒ CHÍ MINH NĂ...
80 ĐỀ THI THỬ TUYỂN SINH TIẾNG ANH VÀO 10 SỞ GD – ĐT THÀNH PHỐ HỒ CHÍ MINH NĂ...Nguyen Thanh Tu Collection
 
HMCS Vancouver Pre-Deployment Brief - May 2024 (Web Version).pptx
HMCS Vancouver Pre-Deployment Brief - May 2024 (Web Version).pptxHMCS Vancouver Pre-Deployment Brief - May 2024 (Web Version).pptx
HMCS Vancouver Pre-Deployment Brief - May 2024 (Web Version).pptxmarlenawright1
 
Jual Obat Aborsi Hongkong ( Asli No.1 ) 085657271886 Obat Penggugur Kandungan...
Jual Obat Aborsi Hongkong ( Asli No.1 ) 085657271886 Obat Penggugur Kandungan...Jual Obat Aborsi Hongkong ( Asli No.1 ) 085657271886 Obat Penggugur Kandungan...
Jual Obat Aborsi Hongkong ( Asli No.1 ) 085657271886 Obat Penggugur Kandungan...ZurliaSoop
 
Application orientated numerical on hev.ppt
Application orientated numerical on hev.pptApplication orientated numerical on hev.ppt
Application orientated numerical on hev.pptRamjanShidvankar
 
Google Gemini An AI Revolution in Education.pptx
Google Gemini An AI Revolution in Education.pptxGoogle Gemini An AI Revolution in Education.pptx
Google Gemini An AI Revolution in Education.pptxDr. Sarita Anand
 
Kodo Millet PPT made by Ghanshyam bairwa college of Agriculture kumher bhara...
Kodo Millet  PPT made by Ghanshyam bairwa college of Agriculture kumher bhara...Kodo Millet  PPT made by Ghanshyam bairwa college of Agriculture kumher bhara...
Kodo Millet PPT made by Ghanshyam bairwa college of Agriculture kumher bhara...pradhanghanshyam7136
 
General Principles of Intellectual Property: Concepts of Intellectual Proper...
General Principles of Intellectual Property: Concepts of Intellectual  Proper...General Principles of Intellectual Property: Concepts of Intellectual  Proper...
General Principles of Intellectual Property: Concepts of Intellectual Proper...Poonam Aher Patil
 
Sensory_Experience_and_Emotional_Resonance_in_Gabriel_Okaras_The_Piano_and_Th...
Sensory_Experience_and_Emotional_Resonance_in_Gabriel_Okaras_The_Piano_and_Th...Sensory_Experience_and_Emotional_Resonance_in_Gabriel_Okaras_The_Piano_and_Th...
Sensory_Experience_and_Emotional_Resonance_in_Gabriel_Okaras_The_Piano_and_Th...Pooja Bhuva
 
Beyond_Borders_Understanding_Anime_and_Manga_Fandom_A_Comprehensive_Audience_...
Beyond_Borders_Understanding_Anime_and_Manga_Fandom_A_Comprehensive_Audience_...Beyond_Borders_Understanding_Anime_and_Manga_Fandom_A_Comprehensive_Audience_...
Beyond_Borders_Understanding_Anime_and_Manga_Fandom_A_Comprehensive_Audience_...Pooja Bhuva
 
How to Add New Custom Addons Path in Odoo 17
How to Add New Custom Addons Path in Odoo 17How to Add New Custom Addons Path in Odoo 17
How to Add New Custom Addons Path in Odoo 17Celine George
 

Recently uploaded (20)

Unit 3 Emotional Intelligence and Spiritual Intelligence.pdf
Unit 3 Emotional Intelligence and Spiritual Intelligence.pdfUnit 3 Emotional Intelligence and Spiritual Intelligence.pdf
Unit 3 Emotional Intelligence and Spiritual Intelligence.pdf
 
Micro-Scholarship, What it is, How can it help me.pdf
Micro-Scholarship, What it is, How can it help me.pdfMicro-Scholarship, What it is, How can it help me.pdf
Micro-Scholarship, What it is, How can it help me.pdf
 
How to Give a Domain for a Field in Odoo 17
How to Give a Domain for a Field in Odoo 17How to Give a Domain for a Field in Odoo 17
How to Give a Domain for a Field in Odoo 17
 
COMMUNICATING NEGATIVE NEWS - APPROACHES .pptx
COMMUNICATING NEGATIVE NEWS - APPROACHES .pptxCOMMUNICATING NEGATIVE NEWS - APPROACHES .pptx
COMMUNICATING NEGATIVE NEWS - APPROACHES .pptx
 
ICT role in 21st century education and it's challenges.
ICT role in 21st century education and it's challenges.ICT role in 21st century education and it's challenges.
ICT role in 21st century education and it's challenges.
 
2024-NATIONAL-LEARNING-CAMP-AND-OTHER.pptx
2024-NATIONAL-LEARNING-CAMP-AND-OTHER.pptx2024-NATIONAL-LEARNING-CAMP-AND-OTHER.pptx
2024-NATIONAL-LEARNING-CAMP-AND-OTHER.pptx
 
Exploring_the_Narrative_Style_of_Amitav_Ghoshs_Gun_Island.pptx
Exploring_the_Narrative_Style_of_Amitav_Ghoshs_Gun_Island.pptxExploring_the_Narrative_Style_of_Amitav_Ghoshs_Gun_Island.pptx
Exploring_the_Narrative_Style_of_Amitav_Ghoshs_Gun_Island.pptx
 
Plant propagation: Sexual and Asexual propapagation.pptx
Plant propagation: Sexual and Asexual propapagation.pptxPlant propagation: Sexual and Asexual propapagation.pptx
Plant propagation: Sexual and Asexual propapagation.pptx
 
On_Translating_a_Tamil_Poem_by_A_K_Ramanujan.pptx
On_Translating_a_Tamil_Poem_by_A_K_Ramanujan.pptxOn_Translating_a_Tamil_Poem_by_A_K_Ramanujan.pptx
On_Translating_a_Tamil_Poem_by_A_K_Ramanujan.pptx
 
This PowerPoint helps students to consider the concept of infinity.
This PowerPoint helps students to consider the concept of infinity.This PowerPoint helps students to consider the concept of infinity.
This PowerPoint helps students to consider the concept of infinity.
 
80 ĐỀ THI THỬ TUYỂN SINH TIẾNG ANH VÀO 10 SỞ GD – ĐT THÀNH PHỐ HỒ CHÍ MINH NĂ...
80 ĐỀ THI THỬ TUYỂN SINH TIẾNG ANH VÀO 10 SỞ GD – ĐT THÀNH PHỐ HỒ CHÍ MINH NĂ...80 ĐỀ THI THỬ TUYỂN SINH TIẾNG ANH VÀO 10 SỞ GD – ĐT THÀNH PHỐ HỒ CHÍ MINH NĂ...
80 ĐỀ THI THỬ TUYỂN SINH TIẾNG ANH VÀO 10 SỞ GD – ĐT THÀNH PHỐ HỒ CHÍ MINH NĂ...
 
HMCS Vancouver Pre-Deployment Brief - May 2024 (Web Version).pptx
HMCS Vancouver Pre-Deployment Brief - May 2024 (Web Version).pptxHMCS Vancouver Pre-Deployment Brief - May 2024 (Web Version).pptx
HMCS Vancouver Pre-Deployment Brief - May 2024 (Web Version).pptx
 
Jual Obat Aborsi Hongkong ( Asli No.1 ) 085657271886 Obat Penggugur Kandungan...
Jual Obat Aborsi Hongkong ( Asli No.1 ) 085657271886 Obat Penggugur Kandungan...Jual Obat Aborsi Hongkong ( Asli No.1 ) 085657271886 Obat Penggugur Kandungan...
Jual Obat Aborsi Hongkong ( Asli No.1 ) 085657271886 Obat Penggugur Kandungan...
 
Application orientated numerical on hev.ppt
Application orientated numerical on hev.pptApplication orientated numerical on hev.ppt
Application orientated numerical on hev.ppt
 
Google Gemini An AI Revolution in Education.pptx
Google Gemini An AI Revolution in Education.pptxGoogle Gemini An AI Revolution in Education.pptx
Google Gemini An AI Revolution in Education.pptx
 
Kodo Millet PPT made by Ghanshyam bairwa college of Agriculture kumher bhara...
Kodo Millet  PPT made by Ghanshyam bairwa college of Agriculture kumher bhara...Kodo Millet  PPT made by Ghanshyam bairwa college of Agriculture kumher bhara...
Kodo Millet PPT made by Ghanshyam bairwa college of Agriculture kumher bhara...
 
General Principles of Intellectual Property: Concepts of Intellectual Proper...
General Principles of Intellectual Property: Concepts of Intellectual  Proper...General Principles of Intellectual Property: Concepts of Intellectual  Proper...
General Principles of Intellectual Property: Concepts of Intellectual Proper...
 
Sensory_Experience_and_Emotional_Resonance_in_Gabriel_Okaras_The_Piano_and_Th...
Sensory_Experience_and_Emotional_Resonance_in_Gabriel_Okaras_The_Piano_and_Th...Sensory_Experience_and_Emotional_Resonance_in_Gabriel_Okaras_The_Piano_and_Th...
Sensory_Experience_and_Emotional_Resonance_in_Gabriel_Okaras_The_Piano_and_Th...
 
Beyond_Borders_Understanding_Anime_and_Manga_Fandom_A_Comprehensive_Audience_...
Beyond_Borders_Understanding_Anime_and_Manga_Fandom_A_Comprehensive_Audience_...Beyond_Borders_Understanding_Anime_and_Manga_Fandom_A_Comprehensive_Audience_...
Beyond_Borders_Understanding_Anime_and_Manga_Fandom_A_Comprehensive_Audience_...
 
How to Add New Custom Addons Path in Odoo 17
How to Add New Custom Addons Path in Odoo 17How to Add New Custom Addons Path in Odoo 17
How to Add New Custom Addons Path in Odoo 17
 

Filsafat dalam desain

  • 1. FILSAFAT DALAM DESAIN A.DESAIN Desain adalah solusi yang disengaja dari sebuah masalah, dengan membuat rencana untuk hal baru, di mana rencana tidak akan langsung terlihat, oleh orang yang dapat dipercaya, sebagai solusi yang tidak memadai. Dalam kajian ini filsafat berperan penting dalam ilmu penalaran di dalam desain. Salah satunya adalah pengembangan pikiran yang berujung dengan imajinasi B.Proses Desain Mencari Informasi Kebutuhan Jika anda ingin membuat sebuah desain maka perlu mengumpulkan informasi terkait klien dan produk serta tujuan dalam pembuatan desain tersebut. Jangan pula informasi tentang kebutuhan, sasaran audiens serta goal dari sebuah proyek desain tersebut. Membuat Kerangka Kerja Setelah informasi dikumpulkan maka selanjutnya adalah menyusun kerangka kerja agar tidak ada kemunduran atau pengulangan konsep dan sesuai dengan kesepakatan antara desainer dan klien. Susunan kerja minimal terdapat beberapa informasi seperti di bawah ini:  Kebutuhan Desain  Tema  Data Yang Dibutuhkan  Batas Waktu Mencari Ide Kreatif Mencari dan menetapkan ide kreatif merupakan salah satu tahap penting karena tahapan ini dapat menjadi salah satu indikator nilai jual seorang desainer. Proses pencarian dan penetapan sebuah ide dapat muncul dari berbagai sumber dan cara. Beberapa sumber dan cara dalam penggalian atau pencarian ide kreatif dapat ditempuh melalui penyusunan sketsa-sketsa ide, brainstorming / tukar pikiran atau melihat dan memodifikasi karya desain yang sudah ada. Visualisasi Setelah ide didapatkan maka proses selanjutnya adalah penetapan visualisasi dengan pemilihan atau fokus pada hal – hal teknis desain seperti layout, background, pemilihan jenis huruf/font, warna atau elemen desain lainnya.
  • 2. Desainer yang baik harus memiliki alasan kuat dalam berpikir bahwa produknya akan berhasil.Tapi mengingat itu novel dan belum pernah menjalani pengujian coba-coba. Menurut tradisi, Sang Perancang tampaknya dibiarkan tanpa alasan untuk mempercayai dirinya kemampuan untuk memenuhi tujuan yang diciptakannya C.MODERNISME DESAIN Modernisme pertama-tama menafsirkan kembali mengucapkan “kriteria kunci Desain fungsional, [estetika,] simbolik [mantan pressive], dan mediating ”yang diperkenalkan Parsons di bagian Modernisme juga mengklaim menemukan “hubungan penting antara [kriteria ini] yang mungkin memfasilitasi upaya Desainer untuk memuaskan mereka semua. Parsons mengingatkan kita bahwa “menyelesaikan Desain. Hasil dari interpretasi Parsons atas bukti sejarah adalah bahwa Modernisme, sejak awal, adalah "gerakan normatif" yang berusaha menggantikan gagasan umum tentang desain populer dengan gagasan yang lebih mengakar kualitas, untuk “massa sendiri mungkin tidak menyadari apa yang mereka butuhkan. Daripada mengikuti selera kontemporer, Perancang harus memimpin jalan dengan menyampaikan ering item dengan kualitas asli. Tujuan kaum Modernis adalah Bukan untuk mengubah Desain menjadi 'seni rupa' atau kerajinan berbasis tradisi, tetapi untuk memadukan yang terbaik unsur ketrampilan tradisional, produksi massal modern, dan seni rupa menjadi cara baru memproduksi barang material yang masuk akal dalam konteks sosial kehidupan kontemporer Parsons mengemukakan bahwa menurut pemikiran Modernis, ada keterkaitan antara fungsi dan jenis nilai estetika tertentu istilahnya (func-keindahan nasional). Karya Loos, tetapi juga mencatat bahwa itu meluas lebih jauh ke belakang, ke Yunani kuno.“Modernisme memasuki tradisi lama yang memandang fungsionalitas sesuatu, atau kesesuaiannya dengan tujuannya, seperti menimbulkan keindahan atau daya tarik estetika. Self-Knowledge by Proxy: Parsons on Philosophy of Design and the Modernist Vision Volume 2, Number 4, Winter 2016
  • 3. Page 1 322 she ji The Journal of Design, Economics, and Innovation Volume 2, Number 4, Winter 2016 Keywords Definition of design Epistemology of design Modernism Philosophy of design Received February 16, 2017 Accepted May 15, 2017 Email For Galle (corresponding author) pga@kadk.dk Self-Knowledge by Proxy: Parsons on Philosophy of Design and the Modernist Vision Per Galle, RoyalDanish Academy of Fine Arts, School of Design, Denmark Abstract Glenn Parsons’s 2016 work, The Philosophy of Design, looks deeply at design in general, and at the Modernist approach to design in particular. The book would make an excellent textbook, but one could equally treat it as a research monograph. This article provides a detailed review of the book as a contribution to design research. The author’s efforts are original and commendable, although the work is not entirely immune to disagree- ment. The article highlights the main line of reasoning to guide future readers, and develops a number of considerations.These include a reflec- tion on the feasibility of Modernist design thinking, some background on the nature and origins of the philosophy of design as a discipline, a defense of the notion of a stable essence ofthe concept of design, and a critical analysis of Parsons’s definition of design. Copyright © 2016, Tongji University and Tongji University Press. Publishing services by Elsevier B.V. This is an open access article under the CC BY-NC-ND license (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by -nc-nd/4.0/). The peer review process is the responsibility of Tongji University and Tongji University Press. http://www.journals.elsevier.com/she-ji-the-journal-of-design-economics-and-innovation
  • 4. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.sheji.2017.05.001 Page 2 323 Introduction Serious reflection on the wonders and puzzles of design is a delightful way to tickle your mind. If you are a student or practitioner of design, it is potentially empow- ering, too, because it affords you a deeper understanding of what you are doing, and awareness of the consequences your work may lead to. For example, such reflection may enable you to appreciate design as a means of affecting people’s everyday lives for the better in many small ways, and perhaps some bigger ones. And it may draw your attention to the moral responsibility you incur as a designer. To be effective, serious reflection on design requires philosophicalflair and craftsmanship at a level that designers are not trained to master. How fortunatewe are, therefore, that a professional philosopher came along, took the time and effort to acquire a thorough understanding of design, its history, and its literature, and then present his philosophical reflection about what design is and how it works. His insights are about us, in our capacity as human beings in general, and designers in particular. That is what Glenn Parsons has done in his recent book The Philosophy of Design.1 Parsons is thefirst philosopher ever—as far as I am aware—to generously offer us an entire book full of deep, professional self-knowledge to be gained by proxy, as it were. All we need to do is find a good chair and the requisite peace of mind to read and contemplate what he has to say. This paper offers a thorough review of Parsons’s book, and responds to certain parts of it. Arguably, the book has a dual aim—first, to function as a textbook intro- ducing broadly the philosophy of design as a (rather new) subject in its own right; and second, to explore an original research problem within that broad field. I will consider thebook primarily in its capacity as a contribution to design research.2 In the following section, I outline Parsons’s aim(s), main line of reasoning, and contributions, and I make some comments along the way. I hopeother readers of The Philosophy of Design will use the outline as a convenient, pocket-sized roadmap showing themain roads and distinctive landmarks of therich philosophical terrain the book surveys in much greater detail. In this way, I also aim to highlight Par- sons’s original research contribution. Parsons is far too modest about the merits of his work. For example, he announces that he “will consider the book worthwhileif it succeeds in showing that design is a realm worthy of philosophical exploration
  • 5. in its own right.”3 Parsons not only demonstrates this in his book—he also contrib- utes to that exploration in a substantialway. After the outline follows a discussion. On a cursory reading, this section may be skipped, in whole or in part. It provides some background information on the nature and origins of thephilosophy of design and also features a more critical and in-depth consideration of certain aspects of the book that caught my attention. The exposition and discussion of Parsons’s book ends with a short conclu- sion—including a warm recommendation. Aims, Main Line of Reasoning, and Contributions—an Outline The introduction (pp. 1–3)4 Parsons gently introduces philosophy as a means of cultivating the “ability to see one’s daily practice” from “abroader perspective,”in “relation to other important dimensions of human life,” and thus to “think through its place in thegrander scheme of things.”5 When applied to the daily practice of design, philosophy so conceived may be a source of professional self-knowledge for designers, as I suggest above. According to Parsons, philosophers have largely neglected design so far, at least as a subject for study in its own right. But since “design today has a prevalence 1 Glenn Parsons, The Philosophy of Design (Cambridge: Polity Press, 2016). 2 The present review was originally commissioned as a traditional book review by the editor-in-chief of She Ji. It grew into something more research oriented. As a result, the editor suggested it be considered a hybrid “full-length article in the form of a book review.” For a review with a different profile of emphasis, see Mona Sloane, “Book Review: The Philosophy of Design by Glenn Parsons,” London School of Economics and Political Science, April 27, 2016, http://blogs.lse.ac.uk/ lsereviewofbooks/2016/04/27/ book-review-the-philosophy-of- design-by-glenn-parsons/. 3 Parsons, The Philosophy of
  • 6. Design, 3. 4 I include page ranges so that page numbers cited in the Discussion section can be traced back to the relevant part of this outline. 5 Parsons, The Philosophy of Design, 2. Self-Knowledge by Proxy Page 3 324 she ji The Journal of Design, Economics, and Innovation Volume 2, Number 4, Winter 2016 and prestige that makes its neglect by philosophy rather glaring,” he finds that “the time is ripe for a philosophical consideration of design.”6 To consider design philosophically, however, there is no need for Parsons to start from scratch. For, as he notes, “plenty of excellent philosophical work” al- ready exists which is directly relevant to design, even though it may not be focused specifically on it, including the work done in philosophical disciplines such as “aesthetics, epistemology, metaphysics, and the philosophy of science.” So, Parsons says, “Morethan anything else, this book aims to bring this work together into a systematictreatment.”7 Parsons writes clearly, carefully avoiding insider jargon that might dishearten readers, and he does not assume his readers are familiar with thefew technical terms that precision and convention require. As promised, he brings much relevant material systematically together. He maintains a steady progression from general considerations to more detailed and specialized aspects of his subject matter. Along the way, he makes good use of illustrative examples (though visually-minded readers will look in vain for illustrations in theliteral sense). In these respects, the book resembles an excellent textbook—one which should certainly be used, in whole or in part, for teaching purposes. But ThePhilosophy of Design is much too ambitious to be appreciated as a textbook alone. Parsons does not limit himself to eclectically explaining to students what others have had to say about design from a philosophical point of view. He has quite a few points of his own to make, particu- larly regarding the Modernist movement. He rejects the conventional view of Modernism as merely a “stylisticphasethat had its day and then passed into thehistory of Taste.”8 On thecontrary, he con-
  • 7. tends, “theModernists saw, more clearly than anyone else, the central philosoph- ical issues relevant to design, and theconnections between them, even if they often failed to develop their philosophicalinsights.”9 Therefore, a “major element of this book”—indeed a worthy aim in its own right—is to “reconstruct key Modernist ideas and subject them to a critical analysis.”10 Although these ideas “do not always succeed,” Parsons aims to exploit them as “a vital starting point for a philosophical investigation,” to achieve the desired “systematictreatment”of design. That is a highly original and ambitious research agenda, and it certainly reaches far beyond what one would expect of a textbook. Chapter 1, “What is Design?” (pp. 4–27) In chapter 1, Parsons addresses themost fundamental of questions about design: what is it? Not yet drawing on the Modernist ideas, he offers an instructivedemon- stration of one of the key competencies of a philosopher of theanalytic tradition— the noble art of developing a philosophicaldefinition. By such a definition one tries to capture theessence of a concept, by stating necessary and sufficient conditions for something to fall under that concept. Parsons first shows some examples of how not to do it, then presents adefinition by Greg Bamford,11 glosses it in simpler language, and augments it by adding a further condition. What he ends up with is this: “Design is the intentional solution of a problem, by the creation of plans for a new sort of thing, where the plans would not be immediately seen, by a rea- sonable person, as an inadequate solution.”12 Unlike some definitions in thedesign-theoretical literature, Parsons’s definition is not just stipulated. Each of its elements is discussed and justified. So, despiteits ac- knowledged roots in Bamford’s work, the definition constitutes an original contri- bution. Although (like much else in philosophy) it is not immune to critical discus- sion, it has considerable prima facie plausibility, and it works all right for the book. 6 Ibid. 7 Ibid. 8 Ibid. 9 Ibid., 2–3. 10 Ibid., 3. 11 Greg Bamford, “Design, Science, and Conceptual Analy- sis,” in Architectural Science and Design in Harmony, Proceedings of the Joint ANZAScA/ADTRA Conference, ed. Jim Plume (Kens- ington: University of New South
  • 8. Wales, 1990), 234. Bamford holds an unusual combination of formal degrees in both architec- ture and philosophy. In the paper cited, he stresses the importance of avoiding conceptual muddle in thinking about design. 12 Parsons, The Philosophy of Design, 11. Page 4 325 The definition raises some “ontological issues” that Parsons discusses in section 1.2. This makes for interesting and stimulating reading but is not essential to the main line of reasoning. Moreimportantly, hedecides in section 1.3 that within the broad class of activities captured by his definition and called “design,” he will limit the scopeof his inquiry to a sub-class, which he calls “Design” (spelled with an uppercaseD).13 The general idea of Design is, roughly, that it is supposed to include what thelikes of Eames, Ive and Starck14 —peopletypically called “designers”—are doing when designing, and exclude what other good folks, such as scientists, plumbers, and engi- neers are doing when they are designing. I argue in the Discussion below that Parsons fails to provide a satisfactory characterization, let alone a philosophical definition, of Design as distinguished from design. However, as I will also argue, this doesn’t matter much—it does not undermine the main line of reasoning that we are considering here. So, for now, we’ll make do with the above loose sketch of the notion of Design as a special kind of design.15 Chapter 2, “The Design Process” (pp. 28–53) The second chapter contains interesting discussions, based on extensive literature studies, of the nature and complexity of the design problems that Designers try to solve, how Design may interact with social structures in intricate ways, how Design problems and their solutions tend to evolve under mutual influence,16 and more.17 Of particular importance to the main line of reasoning, as developed in sub- sequent chapters, are the four aspects—or criteria, as Parsons calls them later—of “good Design” discussed in section 2.1. These are functionality;18 aesthetic appeal; expressive or symbolic qualities suggesting a particular lifestyle or values; and mediation
  • 9. of the relationship between human beings and theworld—an idea developed by philosopher Peter Paul Verbeek, among others.19 Parsons returns to these criteria of good Design in an important passage in chapter 3 (quoted below) and again in more detail later. Function he treats at length in chapter 5, expression in chapter 4, aesthetics in chapter 6, and mediation resurfaces in chapter 7, in connection with “Design ethics.” One of the delightfully mind-tickling passages of the book is section 2.4, where Parsons challenges the contention, widely shared among design researchers, that design problems belong to the kind of planning problems famously called “wicked” by Rittel and Webber.20 As he puts it, “On this view, it is not only large-scale problems of public policy, such as the ones discussed by Rittel and Webber, that are wicked or ill defined, but all Design problems, down to mundane examples like laying out a factory control room, or designing a new piece of furniture. But is this really so?”21 Parsons first reviews some arguments supportingthis idea, but rejects them and concludes “wedo not have a compelling reason to extend Rittel and Webber’s notion of thewicked problem to Design problems in general: Design problems are not always ill-defined”—although he admits that “sometimes they are.”22 Rittel and Webber list ten defining characteristics of wicked problems. It only takes a moment’s contemplation of that list to see that Parsons is right—his “mun- dane” examples (and many more one might come up with) do not exhibit all, or even many or most of theten characteristics.23 Next, Parsons returns to the acknowledged possibility that some (lowercase d) design problems—he cites the example of creating a more efficient office—actu- ally are “wicked.” The idea he now subjects to critical scrutiny is that when facing a wicked problem, designers might hope to find some support in what Ritteland 13 The d/D notation is also part of the heritage from Bamford, but Parsons elaborates on it considerably. 14 Charles and Ray Eames, Jonathan Ive, and Philippe Starck—celebrated designers, renowned for their design of (among other things) character- istic and innovative chairs, the Apple iPod, and the Alessi “Juicy Salif” lemon juicer, respectively. 15 I neither endorse the
  • 10. distinction, nor the use of the d/D notation to signal it. Nevertheless, I will adopt both for the purposes of this paper, in order to avoid confusion about differences between Parsons’s terminology and mine. 16 This phenomenon is often referred to in the literature as “co-evolution of problem and solution.” For example, see Kees Dorst and Nigel Cross, “Cre- ativity in the Design Process: Co-evolution of Problem – Solu- tion,” Design Studies 22, no. 5 (2001): 425–37; Bruce Archer, “Whatever Became of Design Methodology?,” Design Studies 1, no. 1 (1979): 17–18; Nigel Cross, Designerly Ways of Knowing (London: Springer, 2006), 80; Steve Harfield, “On Design ‘Problematization’: Theorising Differences in Designed Out- comes,” Design Studies 28, no. 2 (2007): 159-73; Donald A. Nice, The Reflective Practitioner: How Professionals Think in Action (New York: Basic Books, 1983), 100. 17 Despite the persistence of the design/Design distinction Parsons employs throughout the book, much of what he argues applies to design in general. 18 “Functionality” and “func- tion” are used synonymously in the book. 19 Parsons, The Philosophy of Design, 29–30; Peter-Paul Verbeek, What Things Do: Philosophical Reflections on Technology, Agency, and Design (University Park: The Pennsylva- nia State University Press, 2005).
  • 11. 20 Horst J. Rittel, “On the Planning Crisis: Systems Analysis of the ‘First and Second Gen- erations, '”The Business Economist , no. 8 (1972): 390–96; Horst J. Rittel and Melvin M. Webber, “Planning Problems Are Wicked Problems,” in Developments in Self-Knowledge by Proxy Page 5 326 she ji The Journal of Design, Economics, and Innovation Volume 2, Number 4, Winter 2016 Webber have to say about such problems in general. In their discussion of the first characteristic (“Thereis no definite formulation of a wicked problem”) Rittel and Webber come up with thefollowing dictum— which seems promising from thedesigner’s point of view: “Theformulation of a wicked problem is the problem!”24 To support that claim, they analyzea core example of a wicked problem, the poverty problem, which Parsons also discusses.25 Poverty partly means low income. But low income, in turn, might be put down to “deficiency of the national or regional economies,” or “deficiencies of cognitive and occupational skills within thelabor force,” or “deficient physicaland mental health”—and each ramification may lead to new ones. According to Ritteland Webber’s dictum, the key to finding a solution is finding thecorrect formulation of the problem, which amounts to identifying its crucial ramification(s). “Thus, if we recognize deficient mental health services as part of the problem, then—trivially enough—‘improvement of mental health services’ is a specification of solution.”26 Referring to Rittel and Webber’s poverty example, Parsons argues that “con- trary to what they say, when the ambiguity in a wicked problem is eliminated,”— in other words, by settling for one or more of its ramifications—“the problem is hardly solved.”27 For, as he says, “‘improvemental health services’ is far from being a ‘plan’ one can see as likely to succeed: this is an aim, not a plan.”28 Again, I agree with Parsons: what we can learn from Rittel and Webber is at best how to analyze (wicked) design problems, not how to solve them. Wrapping up his discussion of wicked problems, Parsons concludes that “In sum, the difficulty of Design cannot be attributed entirely to theambiguity of the problems it addresses: Designers do confront genuine problems that call for
  • 12. a rational approach.”And he poses his central question—with which, as we have seen by now, Rittel and Webber’s ideas promise no help—“how is such an approach possible?”29 That is one way of puttingwhat Parsons calls “thefundamental problem for the Design process.”30 Shortly after, he describes it in more detail: “Theepistemological difficulty for Design is, in Galle’s words:‘How … could the designer know (or be confident) at that time that theartifact would eventu- ally serve its purpose?’”31 At the time of designing—referred to as “that time” in the passage quoted—there is no object available for observation or experiment. Moreover, this epistemological problem exists—or is exacerbated—to the extent the designer is creatively planning for a novel artifact that will differ radically from thosewe already know. As Parsons puts it, “… a good Designer must be justified in thinking that his product will work. But given that it is novel32 and has not been subjected to trial-and-error testing by tradition, theDesigner seems to be left with no reason for confidence in its ability to satisfy theaims for which it was created.”33 The last two sections of chapter 2 are dedicated to discussions of various possible responses to this epistemological problem. One by one, Parsons rejects them as in- adequate or incomplete. That discussion constitutes a well-argued and original part of the book, but I shall refrain from summarizing it here. He ends the chapter by singling out one particular responseto theepistemo- logical problem for further examination: “changing our conception of the nature of the Design problem so as to emphasizethe search for functionality and downplay other aspects such as symbolism [elsewhere called “expression”] and aesthetics, where any guiding principles are harder to find.”34 This is the Modernist approach to Design. Design Methodology, ed. Nigel Cross (Chichester: John Wiley & Sons, 1984), 135–44, previously published as part of Horst J. Rittel and Melvin M. Webber, “Dilemmas in a General Theory of Planning,” Policy Sciences 4, no. 2 (1973): 155–69. 21 Parsons, The Philosophy of Design, 42. 22 Ibid., 43. 23 To convey the gist of Rittel
  • 13. and Webber’s list to readers not familiar with it, here is a summary of its ten character- istics in grossly simplified form. Wicked problems (1) have no definite formulation; (2) have no stopping rule; (3) have solutions that are good or bad, rather than true or false; (4) have no test revealing long-term conse- quences of solutions; (5) offer no way of undoing consequences of implemented solutions; (6) have no clearly-outlined set of poten- tial solutions; (7) are essentially unique; (8) are symptoms of other problems; (9) are solvable only in ways that depend on how one explains their occurrence, which can be done in numerous ways; and (10) hold planners entirely liable for mistakes. 24 Rittel and Webber, “Dilem- mas in a General Theory of Planning,” 161. 25 Parsons, The Philosophy of Design, 41. 26 Rittel and Webber, “Dilem- mas in a General Theory of Planning,” 161. 27 This passage appears in the following context—“Indeed, even when dealing with wicked problems, there is still more to the Design process than described by Rittel and Webber. For, contrary to what they say …” (Parsons, The Philosophy of Design, 43, emphasis mine). Above I omit the italicized part, for it might suggest that according to Parsons, Rittel and Webber themselves present Design prob- lems as “wicked.” They do not— so if that is what Parsons wants
  • 14. to imply here, he is mistaken. (I am indebted to an anonymous reviewer for pointing this out to me.) I tend to think, however, that what Parsons wanted to say was something like “Even when Design is dealing with wicked problems, there is still more to the Design process than what Page 6 327 follows from Rittel and Webber’s general characterization of such problems.” 28 Parsons, The Philosophy of Design, 43. 29 Ibid. 30 Ibid., 35. 31 Ibid., 36. The passage Parsons quotes here is from Per Galle, “Foundational and Instrumental Design Theory,” Design Issues 27, no. 4 (2011): 94. 32 Compare this with the phrase “plans for a new sort of thing” in the definition of design quoted earlier. For a discussion of novelty in design, see particu- larly Parsons, The Philosophy of Design, 48, 100. 33 Parsons, The Philosophy of Design, 36–37. 34 Ibid., 53. 35 Ibid., 54. 36 The terminology is not entirely consistent throughout the book, which makes it a bit difficult at times for the reader to keep track. Parsons, The Philosophy of Design, 54. 37 Parsons, The Philosophy of Design, 54. 38 Ibid., 58–59.
  • 15. 39 Ibid., 59. 40 Ibid., 56. 41 Ibid., 58. Those were heady days, when notions of progress for the masses, and expertise, did not trigger accusations of elitism. Anyone attempting to reinstate the central tenets of Modernist thinking in design today is likely to face these accusations. They should prepare to face them, or perhaps take measures to steer clear. 42 Parsons, The Philosophy of Design, 58. 43 Ibid., 59. 44 Ibid., 61. Parsons elaborates further on the Zeitgeist idea in chapter 4. 45 Parsons uses “aesthetic value” and “beauty” inter- changeably, although in the literature their meanings are sometimes distinguished. See Parsons, The Philosophy of Design, 166, note 3. Chapter 3, “Modernism” (pp. 54–68) In the third chapter, Parsons introduces the Modernist approach to Design—“an approach that promises to alleviate [the epistemological problem].”35 He focuses on Modernismin “its role as a philosophical position,”which “sup- ported a rational conception of Design in two ways.”Modernismfirstly reinter- preted the “key criteria of Design—the functional, [theaesthetic,] the symbolic [ex- pressive], and themediating” that Parsons introduced in section 2.1.36 Modernism also claims to find “important linkages between [these criteria] that might facilitate the Designer’s effort to satisfy themall.”37 Parsons reminds us that “solving Design problems—producing good Designs—is fraught with a basic epistemological diffi- culty,”38 and adds that “Modernist thinking… addresses the problem … by inviting us to reconceive the very nature of Design problems.”39 To provide some background, he offers a short exposition on theorigins of Modernismand continues by explaining the reinterpretation and linkages I men- tion above. I was impressed by his unique presentation of familiar historical figures
  • 16. and ideas—Marx, William Morris, Ruskin, Le Corbusier, Gropius and his Bauhaus school, Adolf Loos, Sullivan—in relation to theunfamiliar idea of Modernism as a philosophy promising a solution to theepistemological problem of Design. The upshot of Parsons’s interpretation of the historical evidence is that Mod- ernism, from its very beginning, was “a normative movement” which sought to replace commonplace notions of popular design by more deeply-rooted notions of quality,40 for “themasses themselves might well be unaware of what they need. Rather than follow contemporary taste, theDesigner must lead the way by deliv- ering items of genuine quality—good Design.”41 The aim of the Modernists was “not to turn Design into a ‘fine art’ or tradition-based craft, but to blend the best elements of traditional craftsmanship, modern mass production, and fine art into a new way of producing material goods that made sense in the social context of contemporary life.”42 And as for theModernists’ rational conception of Design and the criteria for good Design, a first element is Loos’ rejection of ornamentation—“decoration or adornment … that bears no relation to … utilitarian purpose.”43 However, ac- cording to Parsons the Modernists did not see the elimination of ornament “as an impoverishment of the symbolic or expressive aspect of Design, but as an enrich- ment of it.” Design products, they thought, can express something via their func- tional elements—in other words, by being planned with function in mind. In par- ticular, products should represent the Zeitgeist—the “spirit of theage,” as Gropius would have it.44 Furthermore, Parsons suggests that according to Modernist thinking, there is a linkage between function and a particular kind of aesthetic value45 he terms “func- tional beauty,” which returns as a theme in section 6.4. He finds this idea present in Loos’ work, but also notes that it extends much further back, to the ancient Greeks. “Modernismtaps into a long-standing tradition that views a thing’s functionality, or its fitness for its purpose, as giving rise to beauty or aesthetic appeal.” The idea had been dormant, Parsons tells us, but was rejuvenated with the advent of “spec- tacular machines such as the steam engine.”46 (Figure 1.) At the end of section 3.2, Parsons sums up the Modernist reconceptualization of Design problems as follows: “If the Designer merely constructs theobject [or rather, creates plans for an artifact] to perform its function, then expression, aesthetic value, and mediation become, as it were, ‘spin-off’ values that follow effortlessly. When coupled with the idea—explored in chapter 2—that the Designer can have access to reli-
  • 17. able general principles when it comes to function, the allure of the Modernist vision becomes plain. By focusing on producing functional goods, Designers Self-Knowledge by Proxy Page 7 328 she ji The Journal of Design, Economics, and Innovation Volume 2, Number 4, Winter 2016 can rationally tackle the problems that confront them, creating a material world that is not only useful [functional] but meaningful [expressive], socially progressive [mediating], and beautiful [aesthetically valuable].”47 As indicated by the italicized words, the Modernist approach to Design, as con- strued by Parsons, promises to help the designer fulfill thecriteria he introduced in section 2.1. It seems plausible enough that thesearch for function can be ratio- nally guided by reliable general principles—akin, perhaps, to thelaws of physics exploited by engineers48 or to Don Norman’s principles concerning functionality.49 And if the alleged associations or linkages actually hold—and work—between function and the other three criteria for good Design, then indeed we glimpse the beginnings of a responseto the epistemological problem of Design.50 The chapter closes with a rebuttal of various attacks that have been mounted against Modernismover theyears. Parsons is very convincing here—like a compe- tent defense lawyer, he calmly and methodically dismantles his opponents’ argu- ments one by one and gets his client acquitted. Status at the watershed Let us pauseto consider the main line of reasoning Parsons has developed so far. Up to and including chapter 3, he has • Introduced the epistemological problem as “thefundamental problem for the Design process;”51 • Convincingly attempted to “reconstruct key Modernist ideas”52 from scat- tered historical evidence, which results in an explicit formulation of “the 46 Parsons, The Philosophy of Design, 62. 47 Ibid., 63, emphasis mine. 48 Ibid., 51. 49 Ibid., 51–52. 50 Perhaps it is helpful to anticipate here a condensed re- capitulation that appears much
  • 18. later in the book. “According to the Modernist view, aesthetic, mediating and expressive aspects need not be brought into the Design problem: it is a purely functional one.” Parsons, The Philosophy of Design, 103. 51 Parsons, The Philosophy of Design, 35. 52 Ibid., 2. Figure 1 “Functional beauty” hard at work. A class E locomo- tive leaves Frederica, Denmark, hauling a northbound goods train in the summer of 1967. Designed by a team led by Carl Flodin in Sweden between 1912 and 1914, the E-class was adopted and modified in 1937 by Danish State Railways, where it remained in regular service till 1970. See Steffen Dresler, DSB Letter E. The Swedish and Danish built Express train locomotives hos DSB 1937–1970 , vol. 27, Special edition (Næstved: Lokomo- tivet, 2006), 4, 35. Photograph © 2017 For Galle. Page 8 329 Modernist vision” involving a set of criteria for good Design, and (postu- lated) linkages between them;53 • Shown that theModernist vision promises to solve the epistemological problem of Design—which arguably it will, provided the “linkages” between functionality and theother criteria for good Design (expression, aesthetic value, and mediation) work as intended; and • Delivered a cogent defense of Modernismagainst various attacks which might otherwise have rendered the Modernist vision null and void. Once my reading of chapter 3 was complete, I felt themain line of reasoning had reached a watershed. Parsons had provided me with an exciting insight about the
  • 19. Modernist vision. However, it was not clear to me what to expect from his proposed “critical analysis”54 of it, nor where theenvisioned “systematictreatment”55 was supposed to lead me. I wondered if the remaining chapters of thebook would satisfy my growing curiosity regarding thefeasibility of the Modernist vision. To what extent could Parsons’s reconstructed Modernist vision have been, or become, a feasible approach to Designing—one that not only promises but offers a workable solution to the epistemological problem of Design? In my outline of theremaining chapters, I will take my compass bearings on this question of feasibility as a means of perceiving theoverall direction of what I see as Parsons’s main line of reasoning. Chapter 4, “Expression” (pp. 69–84) In the opening paragraph of chapter 4, Parsons briefly refers to his reconstruction of the Modernist vision, and announces—true to his promise from the Introduc- tion—that he will now “begin a critical examination of this approach.”56 In chapter 4 he addresses the question of how the Modernist’s alleged linkage between a focus on function and the quality of expression may work. This suggests that we are moving towards an answer to the feasibility question. He first smoothly explores theliterature on meaning in design and the possi- bility of expressing a variety of meanings—such as social status or lifestylevalues— through design. It seems the Modernist vision does not allow for theexpression of such (increasingly important) meanings—it “provides us with, at best, a quite impoverished conception of [the expressive dimension of consumer goods].”57 How- ever, this “does not undercut thefundamental Modernist claim that good Design expresses only the Zeitgeist since that claim is a normative one…. That is … even if peopledo value goods for expressing other things … they ought not to do so.”58 After that follows a rational reconstruction59 of a Loos-inspired Modernist ar- gument for how meaningful expression may be attained by focusing on function rather than ornament. Oddly enough, this discussion does not restrict consider- ation to an expression of the Zeitgeist. Parsons enters into an extended sequence of arguments and alternating counter-arguments to test by fire the Modernist idea concerning the linkage between function and theexpression of meaning. The outcome of this quasi-dialogue60 is that the Modernist idea survives—if only just. And yet, some doubt still surrounds the Modernist claim that functional Design will “automatically” express theZeitgeist. Chapter 5, “The Concept of Function” (pp. 85–102) Though perhaps not settling the matter of Zeitgeist-expression for good, chapter 5
  • 20. expounds an “evolutionary account of function” which, as Parsons very cautiously puts it, “might seem to lend some support to theModernist ideathat functional Design will be … expressive of a culture’s Zeitgeist.”61 The Zeitgeist issue is not taken up again later in thebook, nor is the question of whether functional Design 53 Further reconstruction follows in later chapters. 54 Parsons, The Philosophy of Design, 3. 55 Ibid., 2. 56 Ibid., 69. 57 Ibid., 73. 58 Ibid., 74, emphasis original. 59 “Rational reconstruction” is a philosophical method that is central to Parsons’s project. For comparison, see Parsons, The Philosophy of Design, 59, and 161, note 5. The passage mentioned here is particularly illustrative of the method. 60 This sequence is another nice illustration of a philosophical method at work—one with roots stretching back, presumably, to Plato’s dialogues. 61 Parsons, The Philosophy of Design, 100. Self-Knowledge by Proxy Page 9 330 she ji The Journal of Design, Economics, and Innovation Volume 2, Number 4, Winter 2016 62 Ibid., 86. 63 Ibid., 87. 64 Ibid., 92. 65 Ibid., 36. 66 Ibid., 37. 67 Ibid.,101. 68 Ibid., 102. 69 Ibid., emphasis original. 70 Ibid., 103. The original phrase, repeated several times by
  • 21. Sullivan, actually is “form ever follows function.” See Louis H. Sullivan, “The Tall Office Building Artistically Considered,” in Kindergarten Chats (Revised 1918) and Other Writings, ed. Isabella Athey (New York: 1947 [1896]), accessed May 22, 2017, http://academics.triton.edu/ faculty/fheitzman/tallofficebuild- ing.html. might express other meanings related to lifestyle, social status, and so on. So as for the link between function and meaningful expression, we may conclude that at best the Modernist vision allows for a “rather impoverished” expression via func- tion—namely expression of the Zeitgeist, but even this is somewhat uncertain. Chapter 5 is not primarily focused on the expression issue, however. It features a much broader exploration and critical analysis of thenotion of function, which is of fundamental importance to the Modernist vision. Although we often speak con- fidently about function, it is not at all evident what the function of an artifact is. Is the function of an artifact what the designer intended as its use, or is it how people actually use it? If “I buy a chair and use it, not for sitting, but to display some books in my living room, or to hang thenext day’s clothes on before I go to bed, aren’t these things the ‘function’ of that artifact?” Parsons asks.62 He introduces a notion of proper function to clarify this “indeterminacy,”63 and suggests that perhaps an evolutionary account fills the bill for a workable concep- tion of proper functions of artifacts. The main idea is that the proper function of an artifact depends on thehistory of its “ancestors”64 —it is what, in thepast, led to the production of that kind of artifact. So, the “indeterminacy of function” with which the chapter began is not fatal to the (potential) feasibility of theModernist vision so far. Later on, Parsons returns to the epistemological problem of how theDesigner can “know (or be confident)” that a novel artifact will “eventually serve its pur- pose” 65— that it will be able to “satisfy theaims for which it was created.”66 The epistemological problem, you will recall, was triggered by the novelty of thepro- posed artifact. But if theevolutionary theory of proper functions is right—that the proper function of an artifact is “asocial aspect of an already-existing artifact type that has evolved through its use and reproduction,”67 and hence not determined by the Designer—then perhaps thereis no genuine novelty involved in Design, and the whole epistemological problem dissolves! For example, “when the Wright
  • 22. brothers invented theairplane they could draw upon an established body of empir- ical knowledge about theproperties of kites.”68 However, Parsons rejects the possi- bility of eliminating the epistemological problem because even if Designers “tinker with existing types [of artifacts], they tinker with them for use in novel contexts, or to do new things.”69 The epistemological problem of Design is not so easily done away with. So, at this point of Parsons’s critical analysis it remains an open question to what extent theModernist vision, as reconstructed by him, is feasible—whether it offers a workable solution to the epistemological problem. For the vision to do so, it must plausibly support theDesigner’s confidence that a proposed novelartifact will fulfill the four criteria that theModernists saw as the aims of good Design, according to Parsons:functionality, expression (of the Zeitgeist), aesthetic value, and mediation (of the human-to-world relationship). Arguably, functionality can be achieved via general principles, but does this ensure that the other criteria will be fulfilled automatically, as the Modernist vision has it? Expression of theZeitgeist may be claimed, though not very convincingly, as we have seen. How will theMod- ernist vision fare when it comes to aesthetic value and mediation? Chapter 6, “Function, Form and Aesthetics” (pp. 103–128) Chapter 6 explores theModernists’ postulated linkage between function and aes- thetic value (beauty), which Parsons initially describes as the crucial Modernist idea “that when ‘Form follows Function’ the result will be beauty.”70 The slogan “form follows function” attributed to architect Louis Sullivan postulates what Parsons calls a linkage between form and function. He seems to agree with critics of theslogan who maintain that, in general, there is no uniquely Page 10 331 71 I suppose the form (shape) of cogwheels, lenses, or turbine blades must be fairly strictly determined by the proper func- tion (and the material) of those artifacts. But consider a fashion designer sketching an overcoat or a pair of trousers. The proper function of them would pre- sumably be to cover the human body, keep it warm, and so
  • 23. forth—which would do very little to determine a form, at least concerning the crucial details. A huge range of form options are left open to the designer, to be decided upon through consider- ations of aesthetics, expression, and the price, plus the availabil- ity and provenance of materials, and so on. 72 Parsons, The Philosophy of Design, 106. 73 Ibid., 106–107. 74 Glenn Parsons and Allen Carlson, Functional Beauty (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008). 75 Ibid., 228. 76 Ibid., 231. 77 Ibid., 231–32. The example they attribute to Stephen Davies. 78 Parsons, The Philosophy of Design, 119. 79 Beyond, perhaps, a certain sturdiness that the vital com- ponents need for the vehicle to carry heavy loads. determinable form of an artifact which is optimalwith respect to (proper) func- tion—perhaps except some purely technical artifacts.71 So, as he writes, “theun- der-determination of form by function no doubt complicates the picturefor the Modernist.”72 But given the way Parsons has reconstructed theModernist vision, its feasi- bility as an antidoteto theepistemological problem of design does not stand and fall with the truth of Sullivan’s slogan. Recall that Parsons’s rendition of theMod- ernist vision does not assume any strict function–form linkage—only the function– beauty, function–expression (considered in chapter 5), and function–mediation linkages. As Parsons puts it, even though form may not follow function, “perhaps the view that beauty can be realized through the pursuit of functionality can still be maintained.”73 This gives Parsons the opportunity to delveinto theextensive lit- erature on the nature of beauty, particularly in thecontext of design. The resulting survey would no doubt be excellent reading for a course on design aesthetics. It
  • 24. covers the notions of “functional beauty” and good and bad tastein design, among other topics. But our focus is the feasibility of the Modernist vision, so let us consider the question whether or not thefunction–beauty linkage will work. Seen from this vantage point, readers will find themost important topicin chapter 6 in thesection titled “Functional Beauty.”It is quite a complex concept that relies on material introduced in earlier sections, but thebasic idea is simple enough: theway an object’s form is related to its (proper) function may endow that object with a particular kind of beauty. This applies to a natural object—a bird’s wing, for example—as well as an artifact. In support of this, let us take a brief look at Functional Beauty, a book Parsons published with Allen Carlson.74 In it, they write“some aesthetic qualities, not all, involve function, or to put thepoint another way,… Functional Beauty is one spe- cies of beauty, rather than beauty per se.”75 They say that theterm is ambiguous between “beauty that emerges from function” and “beauty that is functional.”76 The latter might involve “a chair’s elegant curvature [that] fits with or contributes to its function by making for a comfortable seat.”77 What the authors have chosen to develop is the former notion—that of beauty emerging from function. Drawing on his work with Allen Carlson, Parsons distinguishes four kinds of functional beauty. Suffice it to mention one here, for illustration—theaesthetic quality of “looking fit.” Things have this quality when their properties “are indicative of a high degree of functionality. Thus, for example, pickup trucks have a particular aesthetic that one can describe in terms of their looking suited to move heavy loads—looking ‘chunky’ and ‘muscular.’ The same sort of features would not be aesthetically pleasing in a different sort of vehicle (a hearse, or a sports car, say).”78 Judging by this example, it is very plausible that there is some connection between function and beauty. But is it a “linkage” of thesort the Modernist vision postu- lates? No, not if we require that by virtue of thelinkage, beauty follows automat- ically or “effortlessly”once one has taken care of function, or as a byproduct of doing so. In the case of the pickup truck, that clunky and muscular look is chosen deliberately by thedesigner.79 Similarly, thepointed shape of thesmoke box door at thefront of thelocomotive in Figure 1 has little or nothing to do with its functional capacity for speed but arguably contributes to its “looking fit” for its purpose. So, is theModernist vision unfeasible after all? Yes—if we use a very strict and
  • 25. literal interpretation, it is. On the other hand, thefunctions of the pickup truck and the express loco might have led designers to intentionally select individual Self-Knowledge by Proxy Page 11 332 she ji The Journal of Design, Economics, and Innovation Volume 2, Number 4, Winter 2016 80 This argument applies to the “looking fit” version of functional beauty. I believe similar arguments in favor of the function–beauty linkage could be constructed with regard to the remaining three versions of functional beauty (Parsons, The Philosophy of Design, 118–20). They may be achieved on the basis of functional consid- erations, though not always without a conscious effort on the part of the designer. 81 Parsons, The Philosophy of Design, 120. 82 Provided we have accepted the somewhat shaky notion of Zeitgeist-expression as the sufficient manifestation of a link between function and expres- sion. 83 Parsons, The Philosophy of Design, 129. 84 Ibid., 133. 85 Ibid., 132. Parsons takes this example from Anke Van Gorp and Ibo Van de Poel, “Deciding on Ethical Issues in Engineering Design,” in Philosophy and Design: From Engineering to Architecture, ed. Peter Kroes, Pieter E. Vermaas, Andrew Light, and Steven A. Moore (Dordrecht: Springer Science+Business Media BV, 2008), 77–78.
  • 26. 86 Parsons, The Philosophy of Design, 29, quoting Verbeek, What Things Do. 87 Ibid., 133, emphasis mine. 88 Ibid., emphasis original. properties—chunkiness, pointiness—to makethose vehicles “look fit” for their functions. This suggests that deliberately focusing on function helps the designer achieve functional beauty in theartifact. If so, the Modernists’ function–beauty linkage works after all—with a little help from the designer.80 Parsons reaches a verdict rather less charitable than mine. “Themere fact that a given Design is functional will not make it beautiful,” he says, and concludes his deliberation with “thepursuit of functionality will not always producethis sort of beauty, but there are instances in which it will.”81 Where does this leave theModernist vision, I wonder? Giving it the benefit of the doubt, we might conclude that the function–beauty link generally works, though not entirely without effort on the part of theDesigner. Chapter 7, “Ethics” (pp. 129–151) If we accept theabove conclusion, the only thing required to reach a definite con- clusion regarding thefeasibility of the Modernist vision as a whole is a good argu- ment showing that thelast of its linkages will work—thetie between function and mediation.82 In chapter 7, the term “ethics” is mainly used in its broad philosophical sense, as referring to “a concern with the question of how one should live, or what a good human life consists in.”83 This includes, but is not limited to, questions about what rules of conduct one should abide by, and—of particular relevance to Design—what values one should pursue, or, in cases of value conflict, should prefer. Safety, for example, is a value that may conflict with thevalue of freedom, as in thecase of seatbelt-linked ignition systems in automobiles; and security systems that effec- tively protect public safety may compromise privacy.84 Designers, whether aware of it or not, inevitably make decisions that may further certain values at the expense of others, as these examples illustrate. Another example would be a decision about whether to let the default print setting of a photocopier be “one-sided” or “two- sided,” which obviously affects the paper consumption and thus has implications for environmental sustainability.85 Thus, Design affects how we live in the world in many, often subtle ways. This is what the author calls mediation earlier in thebook—the sense in which design shapes “a relation between human beings and theworld.”86 In chapter 7, Parsons
  • 27. presents mediation as one aspect of themuch broader subject of design ethics. According to Parsons, the fact that much of design ethics is about paying attention to values and resolving value conflicts “has an important implication for the Modernist’s claim that purely functional Design will be ethically good Design. Clearly, this thesis cannot be maintained, if we consider the ethical values relevant to Design in the broadest sense,” because “highly functional Designs can negatively affect freedom, privacy, and other ethical values.”87 Here, I assume that by “will be ethically good Design” he means “will mediate thehuman–world relationship in an ethically sound manner.” If so, the passage quoted clearly expresses a skeptical stance towards the function–mediation linkage. Parsons points out the possibility that somemight take the function–medi- ation linkage to mean that purely functional design would “be beneficial in one respect, by combating wasteful consumerism.”88 For example, a levelheaded focus on function might prevent automobile Designers from redesigning their products year after year to stimulate environmentally harmful over-consumption. But, on the other hand, such focus would not halt unethical design behavior. It is entirely possibleto design highly functional artifacts that are wasteful—Parsons submits the example of a leaf-blower—simply because they solve a problem that does not need solving. So, for theModernist function–mediation linkage to work against wasteful Page 12 333 consumerism, it is necessary to Design selectively and promotefunctions that satisfy real needs, rather than mere wants. “TheModernist could then claim that functional Design that addresses needs leads to ethically Good Design [in other words, ‘mediates properly’], at least in thesense of reducing consumption,” which would be well aligned with therejection of ornamentation advocated by Loos.89 Of course, “theidea that Designers, or anyone for that matter, can pronounce about what counts as ‘genuine need’ invites objections.”90 Parsons acknowledges this difficulty, but comes to the rescue of theDesigner, stating that “claims about value can be mere prejudice but they can also be well thought out and grounded in good reasons. It is plainly not true that making judgments of value will lead to authoritarianism.”91 Even so, the fact remains that a daunting responsibility befalls theDesigner as an ethical decision maker—a theme Parsons takes up in the closing section of
  • 28. his chapter on ethics. As he puts it, “thequestion confronting the Designer is not simply theempirical question—will this device do what it is supposed to?92 —but rather the ethical question—should there be a device that does this?” And later, he asks “how is theDesigner to decide … what things should do—what peopletruly need?” Parsons considers various methodological approaches intended to relieve Designers of some of the burden of coping with these normative questions. He ends up suggesting that “if the Designer is not, or cannot be, an ethicist, theethical dimension of her task should be handled by a distinct person, working in conjunc- tion with the Designer.”93 For example, “in the Design of health-care protocols … ‘qualified ethicists’ (usually philosophers)”are already employed.94 As for the Modernist’s alleged function–mediation linkage, Parsons draws no definite conclusion as to its efficacy. However, from what I have summarized above, it is fairly clear that the Modernist optimismabout an effortless resolution of broader ethical issues of Design, via a focus on function, is wishful thinking rather than a real possibility. “Epilogue: The Meaning of Modernism” (pp. 152–153) In his short concluding epilogue, Parsons focuses again on “theModernist’s at- tempt to understand the significance of, and the prospects for, the Designer’s project,” which, as he says, “has been a theme throughout our investigation of Design.”95 Given that theModernist vision has been a recurring theme throughout the book and has given Parsons the opportunity to discuss much philosophical work on design, he has achieved the “systematictreatment”of such work that he envisioned at theoutset. But what is theoutcome of his “critical analysis” of Mod- ernist ideas?96 Earlier, I wondered whether theModernist vision might be a feasible approach to Designing, in the sense of offering a workable solution to the epistemological problem. There is no clear-cut answer to this feasibility question in theEpilogue— nor elsewhere in the book—but there are hints at it, nevertheless. Parsons credits the Modernists for having brought into focus “thekey issues of expression, func- tion, aesthetics, and consumerism”97 and arranging them in a systemof connec- tions. “While the Modernist’s ideas may not survive in their original form,” he says, “their investigations, more than any others, provide thepoint around which a true Philosophy of Design might crystalize.”98 Thelast part of this remark reflects his interests as a philosopher, while thefeasibility question probably reflects a more instrumental interest of mine, as a theorist of design—can designers use this? Even
  • 29. so, Parsons’s remark suggests a partially negative reply to my feasibility question, which is compatible with what I have suggested. In sum, it appears that focusing on function may be a useful starting point for 89 Ibid., 134. 90 Ibid., 139. 91 Ibid. 92 Ibid., 146. This is one way of putting the epistemological problem of Design, as discussed earlier. 93 Ibid, 151. 94 Ibid., 171, note 16. 95 Ibid., 152. 96 Ibid., 2–3. 97 Parsons’s use of “consumer- ism” here, rather than “media- tion” or “ethics,” which he uses elsewhere in similar contexts, is a bit puzzling. Perhaps it is a trace of an earlier version of the text that escaped editing? 98 Parsons, The Philosophy of Design, 152. Self-Knowledge by Proxy Page 13 334 she ji The Journal of Design, Economics, and Innovation Volume 2, Number 4, Winter 2016 Design.99 “Functional beauty”may to some extent ensue without too much effort, but ensuring a proper handling of expression and ethics (mediation) in Design re- quires a good deal more hard work—and Design theory—than theModernists imag- ined. There is no easy solution to the epistemological problem of Design, although Modernist (rational) thinking might be worth considering in that connection. A Modernist revival? Reading Parsons’s cogent defense of Modernismin chapter 3, one might get the idea that perhaps weshould seriously consider restoring Modernismto its former glory, or at least amending its shortcomings to see if we could adapt it to a contem- porary context? So, as an extrapolation of Parsons’s critical analysis—and leaving aside thehuge issue of theepistemological problem100 —let me briefly play with the idea of a Modernist revival in Design.
  • 30. Given the partially negative reply to thefeasibility question summarized above, and assuming one agrees with theModernists—that function, beauty, ex- pression, and ethics (mediation) are the key criteria of good Design, with function taking precedence—it follows that a feasible approach to futureDesign might grow from the Modernist vision. Indeed, this would be possibleif we could overcome its two major shortcomings: (1) the weak linkage between function and expression, and (2) the lack of linkage between function and ethics. Consider (1), function–expression. As Parsons showed in chapter 4, the Modernist hopewas that a strict focus on function would enable theDesigner somehow to express the Zeitgeist. This is even more problematic than Parsons suggested, for independent reasons. Suppose, for the sake of argument, that theModernists were right that their preoccupation with function and disregard for ornament would automatically lead to artifacts that expressed theZeitgeist. Then, presumably, that would be the spirit of their time—the early twentieth century. Now supposethat today we began to practice theModernist approach to Design. What Zeitgeist would we express—that of their time, or that of our own? In the first case, it would hardly be relevant any more. In the second case, how would we achieve novel results using the same Modernist method a hundred years later? Admittedly, designing for the function of selfie sticks, surveillance cameras, and other recently introduced gad- gets may express the spirit of our times. But what “spirit”would Designers com- municate via contemporary Designs for shoes, teapots, road signs, newspapers, and other kinds of artifacts that were also around in theheyday of Modernism? Stub- bornly clinging to the idea of expressing the Zeitgeist leads to nowhere but trouble. What matters for the contemporary Designer is making artifacts express what they are intended for. This may involve their functions, but also other aspects, such as easy maintenance, sustainable reuse of materials, theaffordance of a good experi- ence (which overlaps with aesthetics and ethics), and much more. In short, we need to master Design as a means of multiple kinds of communication. Judging from the existing literature,101 this goal has already been achieved to a considerable degree. But, it also seems fairly clear that there is no tie from function to expression which automatically ensures that an artifact communicates whatever it should, merely because we focus on its function. Now consider (2), function–ethics. Similarly, attention to function is no shortcut to mastering theethics of Design. Doing so takes a serious, conscious, well-in- formed effort that calls for a strong dedication to teaching Designers a practical application of ethical principles, and perhaps teamwork with qualified specialists
  • 31. in ethics, as Parsons suggests.102 We are not left to our own devices, however. There is considerable literature to provide us with the requisite concepts.103 The Contemplation porary notion of “nudging”104 is remarkable as an overt attempt at “mediating” the “human–world relation,” but nudging without competent, ethical reflection 99 This idea has considerable currency in contemporary theo- rizing and philosophizing about design. See, for example, John S. Gero and Udo Kannengiesser, “The Situated Function-Be- haviour-Structure Framework,” Design Studies 25, no. 4 (2004): 373–91; and Peter Kroes, Technical Artefacts: Creations of Mind and Matter: A Philosophy of Engineering Design (Dordrecht: Springer Science+Business Media BV, 2012), 135–40. 100 For some attempts to grapple with it, see Per Galle, “Candidate Worldviews for Design Theory,” Design Studies 29, no. 3 (2008): 267–303. 101 A few relevant examples are Nathan Crilly, David Good, DerekMatravers, and P. John Clarkson, “Design as Commu- nication: Exploring the Validity and Utility of Relating Intention to Interpretation,” Design Studies 29, no. 5 (2008): 425–57; Donald A. Norman, The Design of Everyday Things, rev. exp. ed. (New York: Basic Books, 2013). See also the literature cited by Parsons in section 4.1 of The Philosophy of Design, 69–73. 102 Parsons, The Philosophy of Design, 151. 103 For example, see Verbeek, What Things Do. In chapter 7, Parsons cites Verbeekamong many other relevant items of literature. See also “Suggestions
  • 32. for Further Reading,” The Philosophy of Design, 172. 104 Pieter M. A. Desmet and Anna E. Pohlmeyer, “Positive Design: An Introduction to Design for Subjective Well-Be- ing,” International Journal of Design 7, no. 3 (2013): 5–19; Richard H. Thaler and Cass R. Sunstein, Nudge: Improving De- cisions About Health, Wealth, and Happiness (New York: Penguin Books, 2009). Page 14 335 amounts to irresponsible manipulation. Moreradical revisions of Modernismthan what I have considered here are conceivable, of course. An obvious move would be to question the privileged role of function as the (only) starting point for Designing.105 This raises thequestion of the number and extent of the changes a revival of the Modernist idea could involve before theresulting approach to Design can no longer go by the name of “Mod- ernism.” However, I would pragmatically suggest that we should not worry about that, but gratefully adopt whatever we can use from our Modernist heritage, and move on. Discussionof Selected Issues As Parsons admits on behalf of his profession, “philosophy tends to producea range of plausible positions, each with merits and difficulties, rather than unequiv- ocal results.”106 Philosophy asks questions such as “under what conditions is a counterfactual conditional statement true?” or “how much can a material object change and yet remain the same thing?” or, indeed, “what is design?” Theseques- tions cannot be settled by appealing to empirical evidence in the same robust way as questions typically asked in science. Consequently, philosophers have developed and refined a culture of competing “positions”that they test viathefriendly fire of mutual criticism. Very seldom, however, is it possibleto come up with knockdown arguments against particular positions, precisely because of thenature of the ques- tions under debate. This means that several surviving but mutually incompatible positions tend to live on side by side.107
  • 33. As a user of philosophy for design research, I am regularly frustrated by the numerous competing positions about virtually any philosophical question I want to ask—what is knowledge, for example; what are properties; what does if mean; what does it mean for something to be possible?108 But in my present capacity as a re- viewer of a book on philosophy, it comes in handy that philosophical positions and claims by their very nature invite critical commentary. The philosophyof design—what and whence? Parsons seeks to anticipateand dispelany confusion by making a distinction between design theory—some of which has been referred to misleadingly as “phi- losophy of design” in the literature—and what he takes to be philosophy of design proper.109 Design theory is primarily motivated by and focused on “thepractice of design,” and questions posed by design theory are “driven and framed by current practical considerations in a way that those of philosophy arenot,”Parsons con- tends. A philosophy of design, on theother hand, “would examine design, and its specific aims and problems, in light of the fundamental questions that philosophy examines: questions about knowledge, ethics, aesthetics, and the nature of reality.”110 I find it more disputablewhen Parsons claims “therehas not yet been a dis- tinct field of inquiry called ‘thephilosophy of design.’”111 This naturally depends on how one defines theterm. The following passage would seem to come close to a definition that is quite compatible with the way Parsons himself presents thephi- losophy of design. It stems from a special issue of Design Studies published in 2002, dedicated to the theme “Philosophy of Design.” “Rational reflection [on questions beyond theempirical realm], and the cultiva- tion of such argumentative power and conceptual awareness as it takes, is the business of philosophy as I understand it. If we can agree on this, we can prob- ably also agree on characterising the philosophy of design straightforwardly as the pursuit of insights about design by philosophical means.”112 105 For example, Norman and others have suggested emotions to be invoked. Donald A. Norman, Emotional Design: Why We Love (or Hate) Everyday Things (New York: Basic Books, 2004); Steven F. Fokkinga and Pieter M. A. Desmet, “Ten Ways to Design for Disgust, Sadness, and Other Enjoyments: A Design Approach to Enrich Product Experiences with Negative
  • 34. Emotions,” International Journal of Design 7, no. 1 (2013): 19–36. Drawing on the ancient tradition of epideictic rhetoric, Halstrøm suggests that values to be cele- brated may play a similar pivotal role. Per Liljenberg Halstrøm, “Design as Value Celebration: Rethinking Design Arguments- tation,” Design Issues 32, no. 4 (2016): 40–51. 106 Parsons, The Philosophy of Design, 2. 107 Christopher Daly, “Per- sistent Philosophical Disagree- ment,” in Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society CXVII, no. 1 (in press, 2017). For an explana- tion of this persistent philosophi- cal disagreement in terms of the maintenance of logical consisten- cy among basic assumptions, see Nicholas Rescher, The Strife of Systems: An Essay on the Grounds and Implications of Philosoph- ical Diversity (Pittsburgh: The University of Pittsburgh Press, 1985); Nicholas Rescher, Aporet- ics: Rational Deliberation in the Face of Inconsistency (Pittsburgh: The University of Pittsburgh Press, 2009). A shorter summary of Rescher’s main ideas can be found in Nicholas Rescher, “Apory,” in On Certainty: And Other Philosophical Essays on Cognition, ed. Nicholas Rescher (Heusenstamm: Ontos Verlag, 2011), 25–35. Of course, in science everything is not peace and harmony. Progress, it has been argued, takes place in terms of a revolutionary succession of incompatible “paradigms” (Kuhn), or co-ex-
  • 35. isting, but competing “research programs ”(Lakatos). Yet on the whole, it makes sense for (empirical) science to strive for consensus in a way that it does not for philosophy. On paradigms, see Thomas S. Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, 3rd ed. (Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1996). On research programmes, see Imre Lakatos, “Falsification Self-Knowledge by Proxy Page 15 336 she ji The Journal of Design, Economics, and Innovation Volume 2, Number 4, Winter 2016 Even earlier, evidence of a nascent philosophy of design appeared in theproceed- ings of a conference held in La Clusaz, France, in July 2000;113 but tracing the origins of the field is difficult, so it would seem that no date, and no publication, clearly marks its inception.114 As noted above, Parsons points out that “plenty of excellent philosophical work … on, or relevant to, design”115 has been done in various fields of philosophy. So thedifficulty of tracing the origins of the philosophy of design is probably con- nected with difficulty in locating the relevant literature—there would seem to be much work that could be classified both as philosophy of design and as something else, such as philosophy of technology, or design methodology for example. But overcoming this difficulty is rather a matter of librarianship than of philosophy or design research, so I shall not pursueit here—nor indeed hold it against Parsons that he doesn’t. Essence and change On page 6, in a discussion that leads up to his philosophical definition of design, Parsons admits that formulating such definitions is controversial. He cites Jane Forsey, who “rejects the possibility of a philosophical definition, or essence, for design, on the grounds that design is a phenomenon that evolves historically.” Per- sonally, I find it a difficult but fruitful exercise to try to develop increasingly better and more accurate definitions of “design” and other key terms used in our field. Such definitions serve as a basis for philosophy and theory of design alike, and I
  • 36. wholeheartedly side with Parsons against Forsey’s skepticalview on the matter. As he says, “Thefact that a phenomenon changes does not entail that it changes its essential properties:cars are faster than they were 80 years ago, but this would hardly be a reason to rethink our definition of ‘automobile.’”116 Likewise, what changes about design is not the nature (the essential properties) of that activity itself, but the methods employed—such as introducing participatory design methods, or ethnographic observation of user behavior—and the range of things (artifacts) planned by designing. Nowadays, wesolve problems by making plans for interactive computer games, surveillance cameras, selfie sticks, industrial robots, branding campaigns, and many other kinds of artifacts that were unknown a few generations back. Making such purposefulplans for a computer game, for example, fits Parsons’s definition just as well as did making purposefulplans for the engine of a paddle steamer, or for Queen Victoria’s wedding dress. In recent years, it has become popular among some design theorists to talk about “theexpanded design concept,”117 presumably for their discourse to accom- modate rapid or significant developments in society. But for the reasons I have stated, I find this phrasemore confusing than helpful for theorizing about devel- opments in design practice or society at large. Fundamental concepts should be carefully chosen and defined with longevity in mind, in the manner Parsons does, particularly if they are to be useful for philosophizingand theorizing about a world in flux. If our concept of X—our concept of design, or artifact, or function, and so on—kept changing over time, how could we ever tell and understand thedifference between an instance of X back then and an instance of X now? What exactly is the essence of design? So, I agree with Parsons that we can think fruitfully of design as having an essence— some relatively stable properties that can be adduced as its defining characteristics which the philosopher of design must disclose. But I have some minor reservations concerning the particular essence of design that Parsons proposes in his definition: “Design is the intentional solution of a problem, by the creation of plans for a new sort of thing, where the plans would not be immediately seen, by a reasonable and the Methodology of Scien- tific Research Programmes,” in The Methodology of Scientific Research Programs: Philo- sophical Papers, Volume I, eds. John Worrall and Gregory Currie (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1978), 8–101.
  • 37. For a clear introduction to Kuhn and Lakatos, see Peter Godfrey-Smith, Theory and Reality: An Introduction to the Philosophy of Science (Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 2003), 75–135. 108 That frustration is tem- pered, though, by my conviction that such questions are import- ant and must be approached. The only approach to them other than philosophy would be dogmatism. Philosophy is inherently rational—dogmatism is not—and rationality is a value to be cherished in research. 109 Parsons, The Philosophy of Design, 1. 110 Ibid., 1–2. 111 Ibid., 2. 112 Per Galle, “Philosophy of Design: An Editorial Intro- duction,” Design Studies 23, no. 3 (2002): 216, emphasis as in original. For a short introduction to the (emerging) field of philosophy of design, see Per Galle, “Philosophy of Design: An Introduction,” Det Royal Danish Academy of Fine Arts Schools of Architecture, Design and Conservation , revised January 16, 2009, https://kadk.dk/node/2071. This web document is an edited version of material from the editorial introduction to the special issue and the original call for papers, Per Galle, “Call for Papers: Special Issue on the Philosophy of Design,” Design Studies 21, no. 6 (2000): 607–10. 113 See “Session 1” in David Durling and Ken Friedman, Doctoral Education in Design:
  • 38. Foundations for the Future (Stroke-on-Trent: Staffordshire University Press, 2000). 114 For an attempt to trace the evasive origins of the philosophy of design, see Per Galle, “The Emergence of a Philosophy of Design, ” Det Royal Danish Academy of Fine Arts Schools of Architecture, Design and Conservation , February 7, 2007, https://kadk.dk/node/2384, and the accompanying bibliography Page 16 337 person, as an inadequate solution.”118 First, what exactly does this non-inadequacy condition mean? To clarify this, con- sider a passage just before the definition, where Parsons mentions a case that he wants not to count as design, and which he uses as a motivation for adding the condition in question. In that passage, he describes a person who plans out a time machine by merely imagining thething, without any serious attempt at justifying the effectiveness of those plans. Parsons says, “Theproblem … is not that the plan does not work, but that it is so implau- sible that any [i.e., every] reasonable person can see immediately that it [i.e., the plan] will not work.”119 Negating the highlighted portion of this statement to find a condition that should, presumably, be satisfied by a proper design case, we get not every reasonable person would see immediately that theplan is an inade- quate solution; and an equivalent reformulation of this would be not every reasonable person would immediately see theplan[s]120 as an inade- quate solution. By standard rules of logic, this is equivalent to (1) some [at least one] reasonable person would not immediately see theplans as an inadequate solution. So, given the immediate context of the definition, (1) is a correct reading of the last condition in Parsons’s definition.
  • 39. On theother hand, it is also possible to read thephrase “areasonable person” as “thetypical reasonable person”—in other words, “mostreasonable persons.” It may even be read as “anyreasonable person”—in other words, “every reason- able person.”Under these readings, thecondition assumes theforms (2) and (3), respectively (2) most reasonable peoplewould not immediately see theplans as an inade- quate solution. (3) every reasonable person would not immediately see the plans as an inade- quate solution. So it would seem that there are three plausible but logically different readings of the non-inadequacy condition. Version (3) is stronger than (2), and version (2) is stronger than (1), where “stronger than” means “more restrictive than,” “excluding more cases than.” This ambiguity may bother no one but nit-picking reviewers, and as I said, Par- sons’s definition works all right for his book. Still, one may object—and this is my second reservation—that at times the non-inadequacy condition makes thedefini- tion rather non-operational, or difficult to apply to individual cases. Consider a negative case, one that we do not want to count as design. Suppose someone named Jones made plans for a time machine as in the example Parsons discusses. Would Jones’s action be correctly dismissed by the definition as non-de- sign, as Parsons claims it would? According to reading (3), the answer is “yes,”since it would be easy to find one or more reasonable persons who would immediately see Jones’s plans as an inade- quate solution to the problem they purport to solve. Condition (3) clearly comes out false. According to reading (2), we might again find a number of reasonable persons who would immediately see Jones’s plans as inadequate; but for (2) to come out (up to 2011) by Per Galle, “The CEPHAD Bibliography on the Philosophy of Design, ” Det Royal Danish Academy of Fine Arts Schools of Architecture, Design and Conservation , February 7 2007, https://kadk.dk/node/2380. The CEPHAD website, which con- tains the three web documents just cited, is being maintained as an archive for reference, but is no longer actively updated.
  • 40. 115 Parsons, The Philosophy of Design, 2. 116 Ibid., 6. 117 Ken Friedman, “It Expands ede Design concept, ”the magazine Humanities 20, no. 3 (2005): 4–7. For a recent discussion, see “The Design Concept, ” eds. Charlie I. Breindahl, Ida Engholm, Maria Mackinney-Valentin, and Kirsten Marie Raahauge, special issue, Artifact 3, no. 4 (2015), available at https://scholarworks.iu.edu/ journals/index.php/artifact/ issue/view/1166 , in which the contributors debate the concept of design. For a brief survey, see Kirsten Marie Raahauge, “Introduction: The Design Concept – Anything, Everything, Something or Nothing,” Artifact 3, no. 4 (2015): 1.1–1.6. A notion related to “the expanded design concept” is “design thinking,” for which several conceptions also exist. See, for example, Lucy Kimbell, “Rethinking Design Thinking: Part I,” Design and Culture 3, no. 3 (2011): 285–306. 118 Parsons, The Philosophy of Design, 11, emphasis mine. 119 Ibid., 11, emphasis mine. I have enclosed alternative formulations in brackets. These are intended to preserve the meaning while exposing connec- tions to other statements in the argument that follows. 120 By way of assimilation of my wording to Parsons’s definition, where he uses “plans,” I do the same from here onwards. This does not distort the meaning, because in his discussion of the time machine example, Parsons
  • 41. could have used “plans” just as well as “plan,” without any significant change of meaning. Self-Knowledge by Proxy Page 17 338 she ji The Journal of Design, Economics, and Innovation Volume 2, Number 4, Winter 2016 false, as it should, half or more of all reasonable persons would have to see the plan as inadequate. And how could this be established? According to reading (1)—the reading for which we found supportingevidence in the context of the definition—we would have to ask every reasonable person to make sure that all of them immediately saw theplans as inadequate. And only then would we know that (1) comes out false, as it should. But obviously, this is a hope- lessly impractical procedure. Now consider a positive case, one that we do want to count as design. We could think of Jonathan Ive planning out the iPod, which is used by Parsons as such a pos- itive case. Would Ive’s planning be correctly deemed worthy of the label “design,” according to thedefinition, as it should? According to reading (1), the answer is “yes.”It is easy to find a reasonable person who does not immediately reject theplan. Presumably, Jonathan Ive himself would take that point of view and be a reasonable person. And so the condition comes out true, as desired. According to reading (2), for the condition to come out true, we would have to find more than half of all reasonable persons who would confirm that they did not immediately see the plans as inadequate—not exactly an easy task. According to reading (3), we would have to ask every reasonable person to make sure that none of them immediately saw the plans as inadequate. Only thus could we establish that thecondition comes out true, as desired. Clearly, this is an impractical procedure. To sum up, this thought experiment involves a negative and a positivecase, each considered in relation to all three readings of Parsons’s non-inadequacy con- dition. It provides some evidence in support of theconclusion that thedefinition is operational for negative cases only for reading (3), and that it is operational for positivecases only for reading (1). To be fair, however, Parsons does not promise that his definition will be operational in the sense considered here. I find it a virtue
  • 42. if a definition is operational—but once again, the one under consideration works for the book. My third reservation about the definition concerns the fact that it is time-depen- dent. At one point in time, a reasonable person (living at that time) might not see a particular set of plans as inadequate for a given purpose, while at another time a reasonable person (living at that other time) might see the plans as inadequate. The perpetualmotion device is a case in point. Over a century and a half ago, rea- sonable peopletook the possibility of such devices seriously, and sometimes even imagined that perpetualmotion devices could carry out useful work.121 In our time, on the other hand, many reasonable peopleknow that perpetualmotion devices cannot work as intended. So, making plans for a perpetualmotion device in the seventeenth or eighteenth century might well count as design, according to the definition (under any of its three readings). However, making the same plans today would not—except possibly under reading (1), if some reasonable person failed to have sufficient knowledge of physics to reject theplans. Such time dependency122 of theoutcome when applyingthedefinition to identical or similar cases is not desirable—it does not accord with Parsons’s idea of a stable essence of the concept of design. Parsons himself expands somewhat on his non-inadequacy condition. It is only intended to rule out “plans that are obviously inadequate in principle,” not “plans that are hopeless for practical reasons, such as time constraints, theexpense in- volved, or therarity of necessary materials.”123 I agree that a definition of design should leave room for failure. But why accept failure with regard to practical matters, and rule out inadequacy in principle? Or conversely, if thelatter must be ruled out by definition, then why not rule out the former as well? To do so, one 121 For a fascinatingly serious treatise on the topic, see Henry Dircks, Perpetuum Mobile; or Seaech for Self-Motive Power, During the 17th, 18th, and 19th Centuries (London: E. & F. N. Spon, 1870), available at https:// archive.org/details/perpetuum- mobile00dircgoog. 122 More precisely: dependency on the general level of enlight- enment in society at different times. 123 Parsons, The Philosophy of
  • 43. Design, 11. Page 18 339 could simply expand the third condition, somewhat like this: “… where theplans would not be immediately seen, by a reasonable person, as an inadequate solution in principle or practically.” This would rule out both a proposalfor a perpetualmotion device made by a person ignorant of physics, and a proposalfor some excessively expensive bathroom (say), made by a person ignorant of the cost of fixtures, mate- rials, and labor. However, I am not suggesting Parsons should have done this. In my view, a philosophical definition of design should capturethe essence of the concept, and nothing else. The properties of being good or poor are not part of the essence of design, since (I assume) there are different cases of what we want to call “design” which exhibit one, the other, and neither of these two properties. What I am suggesting is that once we decide to proceed with a philosophical definition of design that captures some essence, then we can begin to consider the good/poor distinction as applied to cases that fall under the defined concept. In other words, we can then start to develop normative criteria to determine the goodness and poorness of such cases. To the extent ethical considerations are in- volved, developing such criteria may still be a matter of philosophy of design. But just as much, or even more, distinguishing good from poor design may be a matter of design theory—and the empirical question of the extent to which a given case is “good” or “poor”with respect to given criteria certainly is.124 The design/Design distinction and the epistemological problem Reflecting on his definition of design, Parsons worries that it is too inclusive because it also comprises theplan-making activities of peoplewe do not usually call “de- signers.” As he says, “how are we to account for the linguistic fact […] that Madison, Einstein and your plumber [all of whom design in the sense of the definition] are not called ‘designers’, whereas Eames, Ive and Starck are?”125 Considering this problem, Parsons quickly gives up adding further conditions to the definition itself, so as to narrow down the class of activities it captures. Instead, he ends up accepting it as a definition of “design” (spelled with a lower- case d), understood as a broad class of rather generic cognitive activities. And then, within this class, he seeks to delimit a subclass, named “Design” (spelled with an uppercaseD), including only the design activities of “Designers” such as Ives and
  • 44. Eames, whom we do not hesitate to call “designers.” I suspect—and this is a mere guess, since it is not explicitly stated in the book— that this move has little or nothing to do with Parsons’s deep interest in the“lin- guistic fact” that what peoplelike presidents, inventors, and plumbers do is not called design.126 What I think is his real motivation for introducing the design/ Design distinction is to focus exclusively on Design, to preparethe ground for the important idea he advances later on in the book—namely, that the Modernist approach to Designing127 promises a solution to “theepistemological problem.”128 Presumably, Modernist ideas were, and perhaps still are, at work in the practices of Design that include architectural and industrial design, among other disciplines— but not in other design practices, such as chemical and other kinds of engineering design, for example, or plumbing for that matter. Limiting thescope of inquiry in preparation for what is to follow on Modernismis a legitimate move, but one that nevertheless calls for two comments. First, the epistemological problem is a problem pertaining to design in gen- eral, not only to design as practiced by peoplewhom we traditionally call “design- ers.”129 So by limiting the scopeof inquiry to Design, and treating the epistemo- logical problem as a “difficulty for Design,” Parsons restricts himself to considering only a partialsolution to the epistemological problem.130 Second, since limiting the scopeof inquiry to Design is so important for 124 An interesting and system- atic set of generic criteria for good design, relatively to various stakeholders, was recently proposed in chapter 14 of Andreasen, Hansen, and Cash, Conceptual Design. Interpreta- tions, Mindset and Models. The authors do not offer a philo- sophical definition of design in Parsons’s sense, but suggest that “Design in the broadest sense describes innovating or improv- ing the means (either material or immaterial) for addressing human needs.” Mogens M. Andreasen, Claus T. Hansen, and Philip Cash, Conceptual Design: Interpretations, Mindset and Models (Cham: Springer Inter-
  • 45. national Publishing Switzerland, 2015), 2, emphasis original. 125 Parsons, The Philosophy of Design, 21. 126 Ibid., 21. Indeed, why bother to account for it? After all, conceptual analysis in philosophy need not be concerned with providing definitions of linguistic expressions, faithfully reflecting every twist and turn of ordinary native-speaker practice. That is the job of lexicographers prepar- ing a dictionary for a particular language. In the development of philosophical definitions, linguistic practice may act as a guidance, and should not be drastically violated if that can be avoided. But a certain amount of normativity may be acceptable, or even useful—at least if the aim is to hone our (academic) language and concepts, to make them serve our understanding of the world in the best possible way. For a concise introduction to some of these issues, see Norman Swartz, “Definitions, Dictionaries, and Meanings,” Philosophical Notes, last mod- ified November 8, 2010, http: // www.sfu.ca/~swartz/definitions. htm. 127 Parsons, The Philosophy of Design, 63; see also the outline of chapter 3 above. 128 See the outline of chapter 2. 129 I can say this with convic- tion because, as already noted in the outline of chapter 2, Parsons is kind enough to state the epis- temological problem by means of a quote from a paper of mine: Galle, “Foundational and
  • 46. Instrumental Design Theory.” In that paper I was talking about Self-Knowledge by Proxy Page 19 340 she ji The Journal of Design, Economics, and Innovation Volume 2, Number 4, Winter 2016 what Parsons wants to say about theModernist approach to the epistemological problem, it is only natural that he wants to define or at least characterize his con- cept of Design in a systematicand principled way, simply because this would add to the theoretical elegance of his analyses of Modernist ideas. Unfortunately, as I have come to realize on a close re-reading of section 1.3, his attempt to systematize the design/Design distinction does not work. I will argue this point below. Meanwhile, let me emphasizethat this criticism is by no means fatal to the main line of reasoning presented in the book. A straightforward way to achieve the desired limitation of scopewould have been to define the concept of Design131 simply by enumerating the kinds of design to be labeled “Design.” As you read the book, you can compile such a list for yourself (at least partially) based on theexam- ples he offers. The alleged characteristics of Design in particularas opposed to design in general However, as noted above, Parsons makes an attempt at defining or characterizing his concept of Design in a more systematicand principled way. He begins by posing the question “what makes certain peoplemembers of the Design profession or practice, as opposed to merely peopleengaging in the activity of design?”132 His responsecomes in two separatepassages, namely (1) “Design practice [stands apart] from design in general by its focus on con- ceiving, rather than constructing, the surfaces of primarily practical things;”133 and (2) “TheDesigner attempts to create plans for the surface features of a novel device or process that will solve some primarily practical problem.”134 I find this way of distinguishing Design from design unconvincing. Let me explain why. According to Parsons’s definition of design, all design is about conceiving rather than constructing. The definition mentions “creation of plans for a new sort of thing”135 —that is conceiving—but says nothing about constructing anything according to those plans. And since Design is supposed to bea special kind of design, conceiving rather than constructing cannot be a distinctive feature of Design.
  • 47. Furthermore, in my experience (mainly involving students and colleagues at theRoyal Danish Academy of Fine Arts), designers such as architects—whom Parsons would call “Designers”— admittedly do tend to conceive rather than con- struct buildings, for rather obvious reasons. However, fashion designers, graphic designers, game designers, production designers,136 furniture designers, and to some extent industrial designers, for example—all of whom Parsons would also label “Designers”—tend to construct as well as conceive the artifacts for which they are creating plans. At thevery least, they build mock-ups or scale models or proto- types—indeed, they sometimes conceive by the very act of constructing.137 No one would deny them the privilege of being called professional (uppercaseD) Designers once they have graduated. So, for this reason, too, we cannot use “conceiving, rather than constructing” as a distinctive feature of Design. How about the alleged focus on “primarily practical things” as something characteristic of Designers? Parsons motivates this idea by contrasting the aim of Design with those of science and art. He says that “despitemany differences, the arts and sciences seem to share the primary aim of enriching our understanding of the world rather than [aiming, as Design does, at] allowing us to change it.”138 He admits that a focus on practical function as a characteristic of Design may not fit very well in areas such as fashion or interior design, where aesthetic considerations may be stronger. Nevertheless, he insists, “beautiful rooms that one cannot live in, and beautiful clothes that cannot be worn may succeed as art, but not as Design.” Even if we grant Parsons that, it would seem that all he can claim by this argument design in a broad sense, not (only) about what Parsons calls (uppercase D) “Design.” 130 More comprehensive solutions have been proposed, however. For example, recent work by van Eck can be read as such a proposal. Dingmar van Eck, “Dissolving the ‘Problem of the Absent Artifact’: Design Representations as Means for Counterfactual Understanding and Knowledge Generalisation, ” Design Studies 39 (2015): 1–18. 131 Personally, I prefer to con- sider definitions as statements that describe the conditions under which a particular lin-
  • 48. guistic expression can be applied (for example, “Design”), but it is quite common to consider defi- nitions as something applied to concepts (for example, design). This seems to be what Parsons does, so in this paper I will follow his practice. 132 Parsons, The Philosophy of Design, 21, emphasis original. 133 Ibid., 24, emphasis mine. 134 Ibid., 28, emphasis mine. 135 Ibid., 11. 136 Production designers are responsible for the scenography and other effects used in the film industry. 137 At the Academy, we consid- er tool handling and workshop experience in design education a valuable heritage from the Bauhaus school. 138 Parsons, The Philosophy of Design, 22. Page 20 341 is to have made a distinction between design on the one hand, and art and science on the other—not, as intended, between design and Design. This leaves us with Parsons’s third and final proposalfor a feature distin- guishing Design from design: Design, but not the rest of design, is concerned with the surface features of novel devices. Parsons makes it clear that, in this context, “surface” involves “theway the object is used and the way it responds to use.”139 “In other words,” he adds, “theDesigner’s point of view on the object is that of the user,” along the lines of Krippendorff’s second-order understanding.140 So far, so good. But then Parsons goes on to claim “only thosecomponents or aspects of theobject that figure in theuser’s relation to the object are theprovince of the Designer. This is in contrast to the perspectiveof the engineer….”141 I highly doubt that my design students would sign a declaration to the effect that their focus is limited to the user’s relation to an artifact. Very often, they are