SlideShare a Scribd company logo
Spence 1
Clay Spence
Prof. Jim Kreines
Metaphysics
4/29/2015
Is the Contemplative Life Best?
What sort of persons ought we to be? In the Nicomachean Ethics, Aristotle takes the
reasonable view that we ought to be happy; that happiness is our ultimate aim. He outlines two
kinds of wisdom – practical wisdom and philosophical wisdom – corresponding with two kinds of
lives: the moral life and the contemplative life. Ultimately, Aristotle thinks that the contemplative
life is best; that contemplation makes us happiest. This essay argues that Aristotle’s arguments fall
short in justifying this conclusion. While contemplation may play a crucial role in living a happy
life, it isn’t necessary to live happily. Instead, conducting oneself in a morally virtuous manner
towards other human beings is of primary importance in living the good life. I conclude that human
beings are inescapably drawn to some species of the moral life as best.
Aristotle provides two standards for determining the end at which we ultimately aim:
completeness and self-sufficiency. Completeness here means something like “finality” or
“intrinsic goodness” – our ultimate aim must inhere in an end which is an end-in-itself. If we aim
at an end “A” that is actually a means to another end “B,” then A could not be the ultimate object
of our aim. It would instead be a means to our ultimate goal, or an intermediate aim. Aristotle
writes, “If there is some one thing that is complete in itself, this would be what is being sought…the
simply complete thing, then, is that which is always chosen for itself and never on account of
something else” (11).1 Aristotle defines self-sufficiency as “that which by itself makes life
1 All quotes are from the Bartlett and Collins translation unless specified otherwise, which is the most recent
translation.
Spence 2
choiceworthy and in need of nothing” (11). Aristotle thinks that our ultimate aim inheres in a
singular end rather than a multiplicity of ends. In order for there to be a singular object of our
ultimate aim, that object must stand independent of other possible ends – that is, it must be self-
sufficient.
In light of the completeness and self-sufficiency standards, I find it useful to conceive of
Aristotle’s Ethics as a hierarchical “tree structure” – with a series of conceptual divisions branching
off from a singular starting point or idea. Aristotle identifies this starting point as eudaimonia,
which means “happiness” but connotes “flourishing” and “living well.” For Aristotle, happiness
is the complete and self-sufficient end at which we ultimately aim. Happiness fulfills the
completeness criterion: “honor, pleasure, intellect, and every virtue…we choose them also for the
sake of happiness, because we suppose that, through them, we will be happy. But nobody chooses
happiness for the sake of these things, or, more generally, on account of anything else” (11).
Aristotle thinks happiness also fulfills the self-sufficiency criterion – when faced with a choice
between happiness and some other conflicting aim, Aristotle thinks we will do what makes us
happy. This second point sounds controversial, but it is important to bear in mind that eudaimonia
is something different than pure pleasure (hedonia). Aristotle isn’t suggesting that we should
always choose the most pleasurable option, but rather that we should ultimately choose what makes
us happy. Moreover, it is important to bear in mind that the subject of Aristotle’s ethics isn’t
particular ethical acts, primarily – Aristotle is trying to discern which form-of-life taken as a whole
is ethically best. Aristotle thinks that we should choose a lifestyle which makes us happy over any
other kind of lifestyle.
This of course raises the question: what sort of lifestyle is conducive to happiness? What
does happiness involve or consist in? Aristotle’s answer comes in the form of his famous “function
Spence 3
argument.” For Aristotle, we come closest to realizing our ultimate aim if we act (and exist) in
accordance with our distinct function as human beings, which is the activity of the soul in
accordance with virtue. The argument goes like this: A flute player aims at playing well because
that is her distinct function and her good as a flute player. Similarly, a carpenter aims at doing
good carpentry because that is his distinct function and good as a carpenter. These examples justify
the general principle that each thing aims at its distinct function and good, and therefore the
particular conclusion that human beings aim at living a human life well because that is their
function as human beings. What is distinctive about the human life is our capacity to reason, since
nutrition-fueled growth is a quality we share with plants, and sensory perception is a quality shared
by animals. Since “what is peculiar to human beings is being sought,” by the process of elimination
the reasoned life must be the lifestyle most conducive to happiness (12). By “the activity of the
soul in accordance with virtue,” Aristotle thus means something like “the reasoned life” (13).
Now obviously this argument moves too hastily – grooming children for sexual abuse is
also a distinctly human characteristic, but nobody would go so far as to say that the happiest human
lives involve that kind of morally repulsive behavior. Yet Aristotle’s argument does have serious
intuitive appeal, particularly since we’re still living in Kant’s shadow. For one thing, a capacity
for reason is a distinctively human character trait that is almost universally shared amongst human
beings2, whereas a proclivity for pedophilia is not. For another, shared rationality seems to be an
explanatorily much deeper feature of human nature than pedophilia – after all, it seems as though
we do almost everything we do for reasons...even pedophiles have reasons. In light of these
considerations, I am game to accept Aristotle’s function argument and see where it gets him. At
2 Or universally shared, depending on your view. It’s hard to imagine an account which holds that very few human
beings are ‘rational’ in any meaningful sense of the word.
Spence 4
the very least, it is interesting to flesh out Aristotle’s account of rationality in order to see where
his argument leads.
Since the “activity of the soul in accordance with virtue” turns out to mean “the reasoned
life,” we must investigate the virtues of the rational part of the soul – namely, the intellectual
virtues. In the Nicomachean Ethics Aristotle defends moral virtues (e.g. liberality, moderation) in
addition to the intellectual virtues. However, my suspicion is that an analysis of the moral virtues
comes most naturally after a discussion of the virtues of the intellect. In any case, it is necessary
to tease out the intellectual virtues in order to determine what sort of rational stance a person ought
to take with regards to the moral virtues, that is, how to understand them. The remainder of this
paper will endeavor to do so.
Aristotle spends much of the Nicomachean Ethics discussing two major intellectual virtues:
phronesis and sophia. These words are tough to translate. Bartlett and Collins translate phronesis
as “prudence,” but this move is somewhat misleading. While the word “prudence” may connote
“shyness” or “pragmatism instrumental to self-interest,” phronesis properly understood involves
neither of these. I instead favor WD Ross’ translation of phronesis as “practical wisdom.” Practical
wisdom might be understood as “ethical know-how,” or the ability to make concrete ethical
judgments – an ability that needn’t involve theoretical knowledge. As Aristotle writes, “[practical
wisdom] is bound up with action, and action concerns particulars. Hence even some who are
without knowledge – those who have experience, among others – are more skilled in acting than
are others who do have knowledge” (124). Practical wisdom is a perceptual skill one acquires
through one’s upbringing, analogous to the skill of telling good wine from bad based on taste. With
respect to sophia I think a fair translation is “philosophical wisdom.” While sophia transliterates
as “wisdom” (and appears as such in Bartlett and Collins’ translation), it connotes abstract,
Spence 5
theoretical thinking of the kind a philosopher engaged in.3 Aristotle writes, “we suppose that there
are some wise people who are wise generally and not partially, or in some other respect…The wise
person, therefore, ought not only to know what proceeds from the principles but also to attain the
truth about the principles” (122-123). Philosophical wisdom involves two kinds of thinking:
intuitive reasoning out of bedrock truths, and the fleshing out of those truths via ‘scientific’
inquiry.4
Aristotle writes that “if there are several virtues,” then the human good is the activity of
the soul “in accord with the best and most complete one.” We now have two candidates on the
table: practical wisdom (phronesis) and philosophical wisdom (sophia). Each virtue corresponds
with a kind of lifestyle. Practical wisdom corresponds with what I will call “the Moral Life.”5 The
moral life is the life of virtuous action in accordance with practical reason, and it is therefore no
surprise that statesmen – great politicians and generals – are exemplars.6 Aristotle writes,
“[practical wisdom] is a true characteristic that is bound up with action, accompanied by reason,
and concerned with things good and bad for a human being…On account of this, we suppose
Pericles and those of that sort to be prudent – because they are able to observe the good things for
themselves and those for human beings” (120). By contrast, the contemplative life is concerned
with knowing rather than doing. Bartlett and Collins describe contemplation as “the act of looking
upon something so as to understand it, an understanding that is sought as an end in itself and hence
3 This connotation explains the etymology of the word “philosopher” from philia (lover) and sophia (wisdom).
4 Where, of course,the word “science” had a wildly different meaning for Aristotle than it does for us. In Aristotle’s
day, all knowledge was basically scientific, including philosophical knowledge.
5 This term is imperfect, but it is visually symmetrical with “the Contemplative Life” in a nice way. I will try to be
explicit enough about what “the Moral Life” involves to avoid any confusion.
6 Or in the case ofPericles, both.Pericles was the incredibly charismatic populist political leader and military strategist
who ushered in a golden age for the arts and sciences in Athens.
Spence 6
without regard to any subsequent doing or making” (307). Naturally, the representative for this
sort of lifestyle is Socrates, who died rather than give up his pursuit of philosophical wisdom.7
Which is better: the moral life or the contemplative life? In book X of the Nicomachean
Ethics Aristotle argues that it is the latter. His argument consists in a familiar appeal to the self-
sufficiency and completeness standards introduced in the discussion on happiness. With respect to
self-sufficiency, Aristotle argues that the contemplative life can be lived virtually alone since all
it requires is for you to engage with your thoughts – though he concedes that “it is perhaps better
to have those with whom [one] may work…” (224). By contrast, the moral life necessarily requires
other persons to be virtuous to; a politician like Pericles needs discord to overcome, and a just man
needs injustice to fight. My sense is that Aristotle’s argument is unsound. Aristotle wants to know
which kind of life (moral or contemplative) is best for a human being, and human beings do not
exist in a vacuum. Instead we are constitutively members of a species. As Aristotle remarks in
Book I, “We do not mean by self-sufficient suffices for someone by himself, living a solitary life,
but what is sufficient also with respect to parents, offspring, a wife, and in general, one’s friends
and fellow citizens, since by nature a human being is political” (11). Aristotle’s application of the
self-sufficiency standard to the life of the individual is thus a strange departure from the logic of
the function argument, which inquires into the function of a human being as a representative of
the human species, taken generally. And it looks to me like a feature of human nature and human
fragility is that there will always be others who need ethical concern, such that the moral life is a
self-sufficient way of being. As Madison wrote in the Federalist #51, “if men were angels, no
government would be necessary.” But men are not angels and, consequently, there will always be
a demand for practically wise individuals to solve human problems. Madison’s view does have its
7 For Aristotle, and for many modern philosophers and political theorists.
Spence 7
discontents – on a Marxist interpretation of Hegel, when we arrive at the end of history men will
start to act something like angels. In Marx’s utopia, individuals will peacefully exercise their
artistic impulses in harmony with other members of their commune. Nonetheless, we have not
reached the endpoint of Marx’s teleology, and the lesson of history thus far has decisively been:
perpetual peace is unlikely, and human conflict is omnipresent. In light of these considerations, I
think that while the contemplative life may plausibly eke out a slight win in this category, it
certainly does not do so in a decisive way.
With respect to the completeness standard, Aristotle argues that the contemplative life is
more final than the moral life because while virtuous actions are means to the end of virtuous states
of affairs (justice, peace), contemplation does not aim at anything other than itself. For Aristotle,
contemplation is pure leisure, and the pleasures of wisdom are “pure and stable” because they are
independent of most worldly concerns (224). To me, this seems like intellectual gerrymandering
rather than substantive argument on Aristotle’s part. After all, isn’t contemplation a striving after
a state of wisdom or knowledge of the truth? Perhaps Aristotle means that the contemplative life
is conducted by those who already know the truth. He writes, “those who are knowers conduct
their lives with greater pleasure than do those who are seeking knowledge” (224). But what does
this cryptic line mean? One interpretation is that contemplation is just a consideration of multiple
angles on a singular truth-object, such that as long as you have one good angle on the object, you
know ‘the truth.’ However this interpretation cannot sustain a completeness argument on this front
because it makes contemplation seem extraneous and maybe even meaningless. What is the
purpose of contemplation if one already understands the truth? Moreover, this interpretation would
probably collapse the distinction between the moral life and the contemplative life. Surely ordinary
people have some understanding of the truth. Instead, I think a more reasonable interpretation of
Spence 8
the contemplative life is to think that the life of contemplation involves a continual striving after
the truth, after wisdom. Unfortunately, this makes it look like the life of contemplation is just as
incomplete as the moral life.
Aristotle’s last card to play is an argument that the contemplative life is the most god-like,
since our rational capacity is the most divine part of our nature. He writes, “It is strange if someone
supposes the political art or [practical wisdom] to be most serious, if a human being is not the best
of things in the cosmos” (123). Aristotle suggests that the gods live a strictly contemplative life,
as they are too perfectly peaceful to need the moral virtues. This move marks a return to the
function argument: man’s good is determined by his nature, which is to strive after godliness. A
number of problems plague this stance. In the first place, Aristotle’s view in Book X that we should
cultivate our divine nature seems inconsistent with the function argument as articulated in Book I.
If you will recall, Aristotle’s argument for defining happiness as the reasoned life was that man
ought to live in accord with his distinctive, rational nature rather than in accord with his animal or
plant functions. From this perspective, it looks like a striving after a godly life may be a striving
after too much. Man may be better off cultivating practical wisdom in himself, and living a virtuous
life in relation to his fellow human beings. As Aristotle writes, “The activities that accord with
[phronesis] are characteristically human ones: it is in relation to one another that we do what is
just, courageous and whatever else accords with the virtues” (226).
This is confusing stuff, and seems obviously contradictory. One possible response for
Aristotle is to suggest that man is made in god’s image such that part of human nature is to try to
realize our divine aspect. Judeo-Christian theology strongly makes this move, and (for Christians)
God’s love for us – his mortal simulacra – is most exquisitely articulated in the sacrifice of himself
as the Christ, who was both fully human and fully divine. Yet this raises the question of what our
Spence 9
divine nature consists in, exactly. Ironically, it looks like on the Christian view the moral life is
actually best. Onthis account, God’s nature is to spread the good news of peace and ethical concern
for fellow man in the form of Jesus’ pacifistic ministry, and in the ultimate symbolic act of Christ’s
death upon the cross. Of course, one needn’t be a Christian. But a similar problem arises in other
traditions as well. Who is Aristotle to say that the gods exist in a state of contemplation? On eastern
mystical views God is in fact so perfect that he doesn’t even contemplate – in Buddhist tradition
God exists in a nirvanic state of unconscious bliss, freed of all earthly concerns and one with the
universe. And indeed, if God or the gods have perfect knowledge, it seems like they would not
have anything left to contemplate. Secular people like to say, “Really it is man that creates God in
his own image” – and this may be true. But if it is, there is an open question of whether that nature
is to be practically or philosophically wise. Finally, Aristotle’s argument about godliness raises a
variant of the Euthyphro dilemma: is the contemplative life good because the gods live that way,
or do the gods live that way because it is good? Aristotle spends the bulk of the Nicomachean
Ethics embracing the latter, rationalist horn of the dilemma and trying to reason out what the
human good is. It is thus surprising when he jumps ship and goes for Euthyphro’s approach in
Book X. In light of these considerations, I propose that we don’t take Aristotle’s godliness
argument very seriously.
Where does this leave us? Having finished the Nicomachean Ethics it looks like the moral
life is, in fact, best. While the contemplative life may be slightly more self-sufficient, it is equally
incomplete to the moral life. Moreover it looks like the function argument rules out a striving after
godly contemplation as a suitable form of life for a human beings or at least begs the question (per
the Euthyphro dilemma) and cuts against the grain of most of Aristotle’s text. I am hard pressed
to rehabilitate any of Aristotle’s arguments for the contemplative life as best. Now, you might
Spence 10
think that practical wisdom requires philosophical wisdom; e.g. you can’t have one without the
other. This would generate the conclusion that the best human life will involve both practical
wisdom and philosophical contemplation. This subtext certainly seems to be at play in Aristotle –
I believe Aristotle would characterize himself as a representative of each kind of wisdom. The bulk
of the Nicomachean Ethics engages with intermediate ethical principles (about the mean relative
to us for the 11 virtues) and specific examples, but the work as a whole tries to unify Aristotle’s
ethical theory in an abstract way (culminating in the highly theoretical Book X). It may be that in
order to really know how to do the right thing in a concrete situation, you need a command of more
theoretical ethical principles; that to say that we cultivate virtue in young people through
upbringing is strangely vague since what we really do is try to teach children abstract ethical
principles like the Golden rule. Moreover, you might think that philosophical wisdom must be
acquired and transmitted by learning from others and teaching younger people in turn. This kind
of information transmission is certainly interpersonal enough to qualify as an ethical act – so it
looks like the contemplative life is a kind of moral life. Coming at the issue from the other
direction, you might construe the moral life as a kind of “lived wisdom.” I would suggest that we
say the Dalai Lama is wise not, primarily, because he is very learned, but more because he radiates
general spiritual well-being and genuine ethical concern for others. This would suggest that
wisdom is more of an attitudinal state, or a happiness baseline. Isn’t wisdom about knowing how
to live well, ultimately? But none of these considerations justify the conclusion that the
contemplative life is best. On this view, the contemplative life is either instrumental to the pursuit
of the moral life, a species of the moral life, or identical with the moral life. But none of these
Spence 11
arguments justify the contemplative life as best, and seem instead to ground the value of
contemplation in moral virtue.8
These arguments do, however, carve out a role for contemplation as a possible component
of the good life, perhaps even for the contemplative life as a possible good life. This is good news
if, like me, you are academically inclined. But at the end of the day, it looks like the moral life is
best. Doing philosophy is good. But it’s only good if you share it with others, and if you realize
that other modes of virtue (e.g. the life of a Pericles) are minimally just as good and likely even
better than the life of the scholar. If we take Aristotle’s function argument seriously, it looks as
though the moral life is the best sort of life we can live. We are “all too human,” and permanently
cloistering ourselves away from others to grapple with philosophical questions is, for almost all of
us, an unsustainable and unhappy way to live.
8 Moreover, the view that the moral life and the contemplative life are identical come at the cost of failing to justify
the kind of academic contemplation Aristotle clearly had in mind in book X.
Spence 12
Bibliography:
Aristotle, “Nicomachean Ethics.” Trans. Robert Bartlett and Susan Collins. U Chicago P. London,
2011. Print.
Aristotle, “Nicomachean Ethics.” Trans. WD Ross. Oxford U.P., 1980. Print.

More Related Content

What's hot

Rationalism
RationalismRationalism
Rationalism
Buhsra
 
Introduction to Logic
Introduction to LogicIntroduction to Logic
Introduction to Logic
Ruby Angela
 
Objectivism: The Philosophy of Ayn Rand
Objectivism: The Philosophy of Ayn RandObjectivism: The Philosophy of Ayn Rand
Objectivism: The Philosophy of Ayn Rand
Karl Meisenbach
 
Is there any difference between philosophy and common sense
Is there any difference between philosophy and common senseIs there any difference between philosophy and common sense
Is there any difference between philosophy and common sense
Mahima Zaman
 
fund.phil
fund.philfund.phil
Philosophy PPT
Philosophy PPTPhilosophy PPT
Philosophy PPT
Dr.omprakash hudegolmath
 
Knowledge and Truth
Knowledge and TruthKnowledge and Truth
Knowledge and Truth
Abir Chaaban
 
Chapter 1. lecture 1. know thyself
Chapter 1. lecture 1. know thyself Chapter 1. lecture 1. know thyself
Chapter 1. lecture 1. know thyself
Mayramarie Flor
 
Values Education - Western Philo
Values Education - Western PhiloValues Education - Western Philo
Values Education - Western Philo
Chester Relleve
 
Synoptic excursus of ancient greek concept of mind from thales to the stoics
Synoptic excursus of ancient greek concept of mind from thales to the stoicsSynoptic excursus of ancient greek concept of mind from thales to the stoics
Synoptic excursus of ancient greek concept of mind from thales to the stoics
Alexander Decker
 
Chapter 2: Why Philosophy?
Chapter 2: Why Philosophy?Chapter 2: Why Philosophy?
Chapter 2: Why Philosophy?
Carla Faner
 
Report in philosophy
Report in philosophyReport in philosophy
Report in philosophy
NonatoBalboa
 
Aristotle' s realism presentation
Aristotle' s realism presentationAristotle' s realism presentation
Aristotle' s realism presentation
nighat parveen
 
Novesteras Ramilo Philosophy of Man
Novesteras Ramilo Philosophy of ManNovesteras Ramilo Philosophy of Man
Novesteras Ramilo Philosophy of Man
Rossite Ramilo
 
Aristotle
AristotleAristotle
Materialism and dualism
Materialism and dualismMaterialism and dualism
Materialism and dualism
mattgbowman
 
Philosophy of Man
Philosophy of ManPhilosophy of Man
Philosophy of Man
RoxanneMae Birador
 
Chapter 1 lesson1 the meaning of philosophy
Chapter 1 lesson1 the meaning of philosophyChapter 1 lesson1 the meaning of philosophy
Chapter 1 lesson1 the meaning of philosophy
ZherylVillaseran
 
classical empiricism
classical empiricism classical empiricism
classical empiricism
International advisers
 
Filsafat fkm-2-sejarah-filsafat (1)
Filsafat fkm-2-sejarah-filsafat (1)Filsafat fkm-2-sejarah-filsafat (1)
Filsafat fkm-2-sejarah-filsafat (1)
Mu'amar ad darory
 

What's hot (20)

Rationalism
RationalismRationalism
Rationalism
 
Introduction to Logic
Introduction to LogicIntroduction to Logic
Introduction to Logic
 
Objectivism: The Philosophy of Ayn Rand
Objectivism: The Philosophy of Ayn RandObjectivism: The Philosophy of Ayn Rand
Objectivism: The Philosophy of Ayn Rand
 
Is there any difference between philosophy and common sense
Is there any difference between philosophy and common senseIs there any difference between philosophy and common sense
Is there any difference between philosophy and common sense
 
fund.phil
fund.philfund.phil
fund.phil
 
Philosophy PPT
Philosophy PPTPhilosophy PPT
Philosophy PPT
 
Knowledge and Truth
Knowledge and TruthKnowledge and Truth
Knowledge and Truth
 
Chapter 1. lecture 1. know thyself
Chapter 1. lecture 1. know thyself Chapter 1. lecture 1. know thyself
Chapter 1. lecture 1. know thyself
 
Values Education - Western Philo
Values Education - Western PhiloValues Education - Western Philo
Values Education - Western Philo
 
Synoptic excursus of ancient greek concept of mind from thales to the stoics
Synoptic excursus of ancient greek concept of mind from thales to the stoicsSynoptic excursus of ancient greek concept of mind from thales to the stoics
Synoptic excursus of ancient greek concept of mind from thales to the stoics
 
Chapter 2: Why Philosophy?
Chapter 2: Why Philosophy?Chapter 2: Why Philosophy?
Chapter 2: Why Philosophy?
 
Report in philosophy
Report in philosophyReport in philosophy
Report in philosophy
 
Aristotle' s realism presentation
Aristotle' s realism presentationAristotle' s realism presentation
Aristotle' s realism presentation
 
Novesteras Ramilo Philosophy of Man
Novesteras Ramilo Philosophy of ManNovesteras Ramilo Philosophy of Man
Novesteras Ramilo Philosophy of Man
 
Aristotle
AristotleAristotle
Aristotle
 
Materialism and dualism
Materialism and dualismMaterialism and dualism
Materialism and dualism
 
Philosophy of Man
Philosophy of ManPhilosophy of Man
Philosophy of Man
 
Chapter 1 lesson1 the meaning of philosophy
Chapter 1 lesson1 the meaning of philosophyChapter 1 lesson1 the meaning of philosophy
Chapter 1 lesson1 the meaning of philosophy
 
classical empiricism
classical empiricism classical empiricism
classical empiricism
 
Filsafat fkm-2-sejarah-filsafat (1)
Filsafat fkm-2-sejarah-filsafat (1)Filsafat fkm-2-sejarah-filsafat (1)
Filsafat fkm-2-sejarah-filsafat (1)
 

Similar to Aristotle Paper

Sources of ethics
Sources of ethicsSources of ethics
Sources of ethics
ramveerchakravarthi
 
ETHICS-REPORT (2).pdf
ETHICS-REPORT (2).pdfETHICS-REPORT (2).pdf
ETHICS-REPORT (2).pdf
jayamaesabas
 
Frameworks-and-Principles-Behind-Moral-Disposition-1-2-1.pptx
Frameworks-and-Principles-Behind-Moral-Disposition-1-2-1.pptxFrameworks-and-Principles-Behind-Moral-Disposition-1-2-1.pptx
Frameworks-and-Principles-Behind-Moral-Disposition-1-2-1.pptx
HannaFlores10
 
L2 ethics the greeks
L2 ethics the greeksL2 ethics the greeks
L2 ethics the greeks
Arnel Rivera
 
Introduction to Ethics
Introduction to EthicsIntroduction to Ethics
Introduction to Ethics
Noel Jopson
 
1 ARISTOTLE (384-322 BCE) Introduction Aristotle.docx
1  ARISTOTLE (384-322 BCE) Introduction Aristotle.docx1  ARISTOTLE (384-322 BCE) Introduction Aristotle.docx
1 ARISTOTLE (384-322 BCE) Introduction Aristotle.docx
oswald1horne84988
 
Aristotle
AristotleAristotle
Aristotle
Owen CL Phelps
 
ethic's 1download.pdfIOJ HKJHJPGDH NURSINGG
ethic's 1download.pdfIOJ HKJHJPGDH NURSINGGethic's 1download.pdfIOJ HKJHJPGDH NURSINGG
ethic's 1download.pdfIOJ HKJHJPGDH NURSINGG
Akmal Khan
 
Virtue ethics aristotle 2207
Virtue ethics aristotle 2207Virtue ethics aristotle 2207
Virtue ethics aristotle 2207
Daevid Abalos
 
Aristotle by Derrick,C.Ss.R.
Aristotle by Derrick,C.Ss.R.Aristotle by Derrick,C.Ss.R.
Aristotle by Derrick,C.Ss.R.
Derrick Augustin
 
ARISTOTLE (VIRTUE ETHICS).pptx
ARISTOTLE (VIRTUE ETHICS).pptxARISTOTLE (VIRTUE ETHICS).pptx
ARISTOTLE (VIRTUE ETHICS).pptx
AbigailPanes1
 
Virtue Ethics Essay
Virtue Ethics EssayVirtue Ethics Essay
Virtue Ethics Essay
Paper Writing Services Reviews
 
Aristotle
AristotleAristotle
Aristotle
lawrenceandre
 
4.-VITUE-ETHICS.pptx hahajevakdgqkegoabw
4.-VITUE-ETHICS.pptx hahajevakdgqkegoabw4.-VITUE-ETHICS.pptx hahajevakdgqkegoabw
4.-VITUE-ETHICS.pptx hahajevakdgqkegoabw
2023100072n
 
Frameworks and principles behind our moral disposition
Frameworks and principles behind our moral dispositionFrameworks and principles behind our moral disposition
Frameworks and principles behind our moral disposition
marymaypaleyan
 
PHILOSOPHICAL PERSPECTIVES (2).pptx
PHILOSOPHICAL PERSPECTIVES (2).pptxPHILOSOPHICAL PERSPECTIVES (2).pptx
PHILOSOPHICAL PERSPECTIVES (2).pptx
JenevieveMercader1
 
Aristotle’s Virtue Ethics.docx
Aristotle’s Virtue Ethics.docxAristotle’s Virtue Ethics.docx
Aristotle’s Virtue Ethics.docx
ChristineAlejandro2
 
Realism
RealismRealism
Realism
leony espin
 
Moral Motivation Across Ethical TheoriesWhat Can We Learn.docx
Moral Motivation Across Ethical TheoriesWhat Can We Learn.docxMoral Motivation Across Ethical TheoriesWhat Can We Learn.docx
Moral Motivation Across Ethical TheoriesWhat Can We Learn.docx
moirarandell
 

Similar to Aristotle Paper (19)

Sources of ethics
Sources of ethicsSources of ethics
Sources of ethics
 
ETHICS-REPORT (2).pdf
ETHICS-REPORT (2).pdfETHICS-REPORT (2).pdf
ETHICS-REPORT (2).pdf
 
Frameworks-and-Principles-Behind-Moral-Disposition-1-2-1.pptx
Frameworks-and-Principles-Behind-Moral-Disposition-1-2-1.pptxFrameworks-and-Principles-Behind-Moral-Disposition-1-2-1.pptx
Frameworks-and-Principles-Behind-Moral-Disposition-1-2-1.pptx
 
L2 ethics the greeks
L2 ethics the greeksL2 ethics the greeks
L2 ethics the greeks
 
Introduction to Ethics
Introduction to EthicsIntroduction to Ethics
Introduction to Ethics
 
1 ARISTOTLE (384-322 BCE) Introduction Aristotle.docx
1  ARISTOTLE (384-322 BCE) Introduction Aristotle.docx1  ARISTOTLE (384-322 BCE) Introduction Aristotle.docx
1 ARISTOTLE (384-322 BCE) Introduction Aristotle.docx
 
Aristotle
AristotleAristotle
Aristotle
 
ethic's 1download.pdfIOJ HKJHJPGDH NURSINGG
ethic's 1download.pdfIOJ HKJHJPGDH NURSINGGethic's 1download.pdfIOJ HKJHJPGDH NURSINGG
ethic's 1download.pdfIOJ HKJHJPGDH NURSINGG
 
Virtue ethics aristotle 2207
Virtue ethics aristotle 2207Virtue ethics aristotle 2207
Virtue ethics aristotle 2207
 
Aristotle by Derrick,C.Ss.R.
Aristotle by Derrick,C.Ss.R.Aristotle by Derrick,C.Ss.R.
Aristotle by Derrick,C.Ss.R.
 
ARISTOTLE (VIRTUE ETHICS).pptx
ARISTOTLE (VIRTUE ETHICS).pptxARISTOTLE (VIRTUE ETHICS).pptx
ARISTOTLE (VIRTUE ETHICS).pptx
 
Virtue Ethics Essay
Virtue Ethics EssayVirtue Ethics Essay
Virtue Ethics Essay
 
Aristotle
AristotleAristotle
Aristotle
 
4.-VITUE-ETHICS.pptx hahajevakdgqkegoabw
4.-VITUE-ETHICS.pptx hahajevakdgqkegoabw4.-VITUE-ETHICS.pptx hahajevakdgqkegoabw
4.-VITUE-ETHICS.pptx hahajevakdgqkegoabw
 
Frameworks and principles behind our moral disposition
Frameworks and principles behind our moral dispositionFrameworks and principles behind our moral disposition
Frameworks and principles behind our moral disposition
 
PHILOSOPHICAL PERSPECTIVES (2).pptx
PHILOSOPHICAL PERSPECTIVES (2).pptxPHILOSOPHICAL PERSPECTIVES (2).pptx
PHILOSOPHICAL PERSPECTIVES (2).pptx
 
Aristotle’s Virtue Ethics.docx
Aristotle’s Virtue Ethics.docxAristotle’s Virtue Ethics.docx
Aristotle’s Virtue Ethics.docx
 
Realism
RealismRealism
Realism
 
Moral Motivation Across Ethical TheoriesWhat Can We Learn.docx
Moral Motivation Across Ethical TheoriesWhat Can We Learn.docxMoral Motivation Across Ethical TheoriesWhat Can We Learn.docx
Moral Motivation Across Ethical TheoriesWhat Can We Learn.docx
 

Aristotle Paper

  • 1. Spence 1 Clay Spence Prof. Jim Kreines Metaphysics 4/29/2015 Is the Contemplative Life Best? What sort of persons ought we to be? In the Nicomachean Ethics, Aristotle takes the reasonable view that we ought to be happy; that happiness is our ultimate aim. He outlines two kinds of wisdom – practical wisdom and philosophical wisdom – corresponding with two kinds of lives: the moral life and the contemplative life. Ultimately, Aristotle thinks that the contemplative life is best; that contemplation makes us happiest. This essay argues that Aristotle’s arguments fall short in justifying this conclusion. While contemplation may play a crucial role in living a happy life, it isn’t necessary to live happily. Instead, conducting oneself in a morally virtuous manner towards other human beings is of primary importance in living the good life. I conclude that human beings are inescapably drawn to some species of the moral life as best. Aristotle provides two standards for determining the end at which we ultimately aim: completeness and self-sufficiency. Completeness here means something like “finality” or “intrinsic goodness” – our ultimate aim must inhere in an end which is an end-in-itself. If we aim at an end “A” that is actually a means to another end “B,” then A could not be the ultimate object of our aim. It would instead be a means to our ultimate goal, or an intermediate aim. Aristotle writes, “If there is some one thing that is complete in itself, this would be what is being sought…the simply complete thing, then, is that which is always chosen for itself and never on account of something else” (11).1 Aristotle defines self-sufficiency as “that which by itself makes life 1 All quotes are from the Bartlett and Collins translation unless specified otherwise, which is the most recent translation.
  • 2. Spence 2 choiceworthy and in need of nothing” (11). Aristotle thinks that our ultimate aim inheres in a singular end rather than a multiplicity of ends. In order for there to be a singular object of our ultimate aim, that object must stand independent of other possible ends – that is, it must be self- sufficient. In light of the completeness and self-sufficiency standards, I find it useful to conceive of Aristotle’s Ethics as a hierarchical “tree structure” – with a series of conceptual divisions branching off from a singular starting point or idea. Aristotle identifies this starting point as eudaimonia, which means “happiness” but connotes “flourishing” and “living well.” For Aristotle, happiness is the complete and self-sufficient end at which we ultimately aim. Happiness fulfills the completeness criterion: “honor, pleasure, intellect, and every virtue…we choose them also for the sake of happiness, because we suppose that, through them, we will be happy. But nobody chooses happiness for the sake of these things, or, more generally, on account of anything else” (11). Aristotle thinks happiness also fulfills the self-sufficiency criterion – when faced with a choice between happiness and some other conflicting aim, Aristotle thinks we will do what makes us happy. This second point sounds controversial, but it is important to bear in mind that eudaimonia is something different than pure pleasure (hedonia). Aristotle isn’t suggesting that we should always choose the most pleasurable option, but rather that we should ultimately choose what makes us happy. Moreover, it is important to bear in mind that the subject of Aristotle’s ethics isn’t particular ethical acts, primarily – Aristotle is trying to discern which form-of-life taken as a whole is ethically best. Aristotle thinks that we should choose a lifestyle which makes us happy over any other kind of lifestyle. This of course raises the question: what sort of lifestyle is conducive to happiness? What does happiness involve or consist in? Aristotle’s answer comes in the form of his famous “function
  • 3. Spence 3 argument.” For Aristotle, we come closest to realizing our ultimate aim if we act (and exist) in accordance with our distinct function as human beings, which is the activity of the soul in accordance with virtue. The argument goes like this: A flute player aims at playing well because that is her distinct function and her good as a flute player. Similarly, a carpenter aims at doing good carpentry because that is his distinct function and good as a carpenter. These examples justify the general principle that each thing aims at its distinct function and good, and therefore the particular conclusion that human beings aim at living a human life well because that is their function as human beings. What is distinctive about the human life is our capacity to reason, since nutrition-fueled growth is a quality we share with plants, and sensory perception is a quality shared by animals. Since “what is peculiar to human beings is being sought,” by the process of elimination the reasoned life must be the lifestyle most conducive to happiness (12). By “the activity of the soul in accordance with virtue,” Aristotle thus means something like “the reasoned life” (13). Now obviously this argument moves too hastily – grooming children for sexual abuse is also a distinctly human characteristic, but nobody would go so far as to say that the happiest human lives involve that kind of morally repulsive behavior. Yet Aristotle’s argument does have serious intuitive appeal, particularly since we’re still living in Kant’s shadow. For one thing, a capacity for reason is a distinctively human character trait that is almost universally shared amongst human beings2, whereas a proclivity for pedophilia is not. For another, shared rationality seems to be an explanatorily much deeper feature of human nature than pedophilia – after all, it seems as though we do almost everything we do for reasons...even pedophiles have reasons. In light of these considerations, I am game to accept Aristotle’s function argument and see where it gets him. At 2 Or universally shared, depending on your view. It’s hard to imagine an account which holds that very few human beings are ‘rational’ in any meaningful sense of the word.
  • 4. Spence 4 the very least, it is interesting to flesh out Aristotle’s account of rationality in order to see where his argument leads. Since the “activity of the soul in accordance with virtue” turns out to mean “the reasoned life,” we must investigate the virtues of the rational part of the soul – namely, the intellectual virtues. In the Nicomachean Ethics Aristotle defends moral virtues (e.g. liberality, moderation) in addition to the intellectual virtues. However, my suspicion is that an analysis of the moral virtues comes most naturally after a discussion of the virtues of the intellect. In any case, it is necessary to tease out the intellectual virtues in order to determine what sort of rational stance a person ought to take with regards to the moral virtues, that is, how to understand them. The remainder of this paper will endeavor to do so. Aristotle spends much of the Nicomachean Ethics discussing two major intellectual virtues: phronesis and sophia. These words are tough to translate. Bartlett and Collins translate phronesis as “prudence,” but this move is somewhat misleading. While the word “prudence” may connote “shyness” or “pragmatism instrumental to self-interest,” phronesis properly understood involves neither of these. I instead favor WD Ross’ translation of phronesis as “practical wisdom.” Practical wisdom might be understood as “ethical know-how,” or the ability to make concrete ethical judgments – an ability that needn’t involve theoretical knowledge. As Aristotle writes, “[practical wisdom] is bound up with action, and action concerns particulars. Hence even some who are without knowledge – those who have experience, among others – are more skilled in acting than are others who do have knowledge” (124). Practical wisdom is a perceptual skill one acquires through one’s upbringing, analogous to the skill of telling good wine from bad based on taste. With respect to sophia I think a fair translation is “philosophical wisdom.” While sophia transliterates as “wisdom” (and appears as such in Bartlett and Collins’ translation), it connotes abstract,
  • 5. Spence 5 theoretical thinking of the kind a philosopher engaged in.3 Aristotle writes, “we suppose that there are some wise people who are wise generally and not partially, or in some other respect…The wise person, therefore, ought not only to know what proceeds from the principles but also to attain the truth about the principles” (122-123). Philosophical wisdom involves two kinds of thinking: intuitive reasoning out of bedrock truths, and the fleshing out of those truths via ‘scientific’ inquiry.4 Aristotle writes that “if there are several virtues,” then the human good is the activity of the soul “in accord with the best and most complete one.” We now have two candidates on the table: practical wisdom (phronesis) and philosophical wisdom (sophia). Each virtue corresponds with a kind of lifestyle. Practical wisdom corresponds with what I will call “the Moral Life.”5 The moral life is the life of virtuous action in accordance with practical reason, and it is therefore no surprise that statesmen – great politicians and generals – are exemplars.6 Aristotle writes, “[practical wisdom] is a true characteristic that is bound up with action, accompanied by reason, and concerned with things good and bad for a human being…On account of this, we suppose Pericles and those of that sort to be prudent – because they are able to observe the good things for themselves and those for human beings” (120). By contrast, the contemplative life is concerned with knowing rather than doing. Bartlett and Collins describe contemplation as “the act of looking upon something so as to understand it, an understanding that is sought as an end in itself and hence 3 This connotation explains the etymology of the word “philosopher” from philia (lover) and sophia (wisdom). 4 Where, of course,the word “science” had a wildly different meaning for Aristotle than it does for us. In Aristotle’s day, all knowledge was basically scientific, including philosophical knowledge. 5 This term is imperfect, but it is visually symmetrical with “the Contemplative Life” in a nice way. I will try to be explicit enough about what “the Moral Life” involves to avoid any confusion. 6 Or in the case ofPericles, both.Pericles was the incredibly charismatic populist political leader and military strategist who ushered in a golden age for the arts and sciences in Athens.
  • 6. Spence 6 without regard to any subsequent doing or making” (307). Naturally, the representative for this sort of lifestyle is Socrates, who died rather than give up his pursuit of philosophical wisdom.7 Which is better: the moral life or the contemplative life? In book X of the Nicomachean Ethics Aristotle argues that it is the latter. His argument consists in a familiar appeal to the self- sufficiency and completeness standards introduced in the discussion on happiness. With respect to self-sufficiency, Aristotle argues that the contemplative life can be lived virtually alone since all it requires is for you to engage with your thoughts – though he concedes that “it is perhaps better to have those with whom [one] may work…” (224). By contrast, the moral life necessarily requires other persons to be virtuous to; a politician like Pericles needs discord to overcome, and a just man needs injustice to fight. My sense is that Aristotle’s argument is unsound. Aristotle wants to know which kind of life (moral or contemplative) is best for a human being, and human beings do not exist in a vacuum. Instead we are constitutively members of a species. As Aristotle remarks in Book I, “We do not mean by self-sufficient suffices for someone by himself, living a solitary life, but what is sufficient also with respect to parents, offspring, a wife, and in general, one’s friends and fellow citizens, since by nature a human being is political” (11). Aristotle’s application of the self-sufficiency standard to the life of the individual is thus a strange departure from the logic of the function argument, which inquires into the function of a human being as a representative of the human species, taken generally. And it looks to me like a feature of human nature and human fragility is that there will always be others who need ethical concern, such that the moral life is a self-sufficient way of being. As Madison wrote in the Federalist #51, “if men were angels, no government would be necessary.” But men are not angels and, consequently, there will always be a demand for practically wise individuals to solve human problems. Madison’s view does have its 7 For Aristotle, and for many modern philosophers and political theorists.
  • 7. Spence 7 discontents – on a Marxist interpretation of Hegel, when we arrive at the end of history men will start to act something like angels. In Marx’s utopia, individuals will peacefully exercise their artistic impulses in harmony with other members of their commune. Nonetheless, we have not reached the endpoint of Marx’s teleology, and the lesson of history thus far has decisively been: perpetual peace is unlikely, and human conflict is omnipresent. In light of these considerations, I think that while the contemplative life may plausibly eke out a slight win in this category, it certainly does not do so in a decisive way. With respect to the completeness standard, Aristotle argues that the contemplative life is more final than the moral life because while virtuous actions are means to the end of virtuous states of affairs (justice, peace), contemplation does not aim at anything other than itself. For Aristotle, contemplation is pure leisure, and the pleasures of wisdom are “pure and stable” because they are independent of most worldly concerns (224). To me, this seems like intellectual gerrymandering rather than substantive argument on Aristotle’s part. After all, isn’t contemplation a striving after a state of wisdom or knowledge of the truth? Perhaps Aristotle means that the contemplative life is conducted by those who already know the truth. He writes, “those who are knowers conduct their lives with greater pleasure than do those who are seeking knowledge” (224). But what does this cryptic line mean? One interpretation is that contemplation is just a consideration of multiple angles on a singular truth-object, such that as long as you have one good angle on the object, you know ‘the truth.’ However this interpretation cannot sustain a completeness argument on this front because it makes contemplation seem extraneous and maybe even meaningless. What is the purpose of contemplation if one already understands the truth? Moreover, this interpretation would probably collapse the distinction between the moral life and the contemplative life. Surely ordinary people have some understanding of the truth. Instead, I think a more reasonable interpretation of
  • 8. Spence 8 the contemplative life is to think that the life of contemplation involves a continual striving after the truth, after wisdom. Unfortunately, this makes it look like the life of contemplation is just as incomplete as the moral life. Aristotle’s last card to play is an argument that the contemplative life is the most god-like, since our rational capacity is the most divine part of our nature. He writes, “It is strange if someone supposes the political art or [practical wisdom] to be most serious, if a human being is not the best of things in the cosmos” (123). Aristotle suggests that the gods live a strictly contemplative life, as they are too perfectly peaceful to need the moral virtues. This move marks a return to the function argument: man’s good is determined by his nature, which is to strive after godliness. A number of problems plague this stance. In the first place, Aristotle’s view in Book X that we should cultivate our divine nature seems inconsistent with the function argument as articulated in Book I. If you will recall, Aristotle’s argument for defining happiness as the reasoned life was that man ought to live in accord with his distinctive, rational nature rather than in accord with his animal or plant functions. From this perspective, it looks like a striving after a godly life may be a striving after too much. Man may be better off cultivating practical wisdom in himself, and living a virtuous life in relation to his fellow human beings. As Aristotle writes, “The activities that accord with [phronesis] are characteristically human ones: it is in relation to one another that we do what is just, courageous and whatever else accords with the virtues” (226). This is confusing stuff, and seems obviously contradictory. One possible response for Aristotle is to suggest that man is made in god’s image such that part of human nature is to try to realize our divine aspect. Judeo-Christian theology strongly makes this move, and (for Christians) God’s love for us – his mortal simulacra – is most exquisitely articulated in the sacrifice of himself as the Christ, who was both fully human and fully divine. Yet this raises the question of what our
  • 9. Spence 9 divine nature consists in, exactly. Ironically, it looks like on the Christian view the moral life is actually best. Onthis account, God’s nature is to spread the good news of peace and ethical concern for fellow man in the form of Jesus’ pacifistic ministry, and in the ultimate symbolic act of Christ’s death upon the cross. Of course, one needn’t be a Christian. But a similar problem arises in other traditions as well. Who is Aristotle to say that the gods exist in a state of contemplation? On eastern mystical views God is in fact so perfect that he doesn’t even contemplate – in Buddhist tradition God exists in a nirvanic state of unconscious bliss, freed of all earthly concerns and one with the universe. And indeed, if God or the gods have perfect knowledge, it seems like they would not have anything left to contemplate. Secular people like to say, “Really it is man that creates God in his own image” – and this may be true. But if it is, there is an open question of whether that nature is to be practically or philosophically wise. Finally, Aristotle’s argument about godliness raises a variant of the Euthyphro dilemma: is the contemplative life good because the gods live that way, or do the gods live that way because it is good? Aristotle spends the bulk of the Nicomachean Ethics embracing the latter, rationalist horn of the dilemma and trying to reason out what the human good is. It is thus surprising when he jumps ship and goes for Euthyphro’s approach in Book X. In light of these considerations, I propose that we don’t take Aristotle’s godliness argument very seriously. Where does this leave us? Having finished the Nicomachean Ethics it looks like the moral life is, in fact, best. While the contemplative life may be slightly more self-sufficient, it is equally incomplete to the moral life. Moreover it looks like the function argument rules out a striving after godly contemplation as a suitable form of life for a human beings or at least begs the question (per the Euthyphro dilemma) and cuts against the grain of most of Aristotle’s text. I am hard pressed to rehabilitate any of Aristotle’s arguments for the contemplative life as best. Now, you might
  • 10. Spence 10 think that practical wisdom requires philosophical wisdom; e.g. you can’t have one without the other. This would generate the conclusion that the best human life will involve both practical wisdom and philosophical contemplation. This subtext certainly seems to be at play in Aristotle – I believe Aristotle would characterize himself as a representative of each kind of wisdom. The bulk of the Nicomachean Ethics engages with intermediate ethical principles (about the mean relative to us for the 11 virtues) and specific examples, but the work as a whole tries to unify Aristotle’s ethical theory in an abstract way (culminating in the highly theoretical Book X). It may be that in order to really know how to do the right thing in a concrete situation, you need a command of more theoretical ethical principles; that to say that we cultivate virtue in young people through upbringing is strangely vague since what we really do is try to teach children abstract ethical principles like the Golden rule. Moreover, you might think that philosophical wisdom must be acquired and transmitted by learning from others and teaching younger people in turn. This kind of information transmission is certainly interpersonal enough to qualify as an ethical act – so it looks like the contemplative life is a kind of moral life. Coming at the issue from the other direction, you might construe the moral life as a kind of “lived wisdom.” I would suggest that we say the Dalai Lama is wise not, primarily, because he is very learned, but more because he radiates general spiritual well-being and genuine ethical concern for others. This would suggest that wisdom is more of an attitudinal state, or a happiness baseline. Isn’t wisdom about knowing how to live well, ultimately? But none of these considerations justify the conclusion that the contemplative life is best. On this view, the contemplative life is either instrumental to the pursuit of the moral life, a species of the moral life, or identical with the moral life. But none of these
  • 11. Spence 11 arguments justify the contemplative life as best, and seem instead to ground the value of contemplation in moral virtue.8 These arguments do, however, carve out a role for contemplation as a possible component of the good life, perhaps even for the contemplative life as a possible good life. This is good news if, like me, you are academically inclined. But at the end of the day, it looks like the moral life is best. Doing philosophy is good. But it’s only good if you share it with others, and if you realize that other modes of virtue (e.g. the life of a Pericles) are minimally just as good and likely even better than the life of the scholar. If we take Aristotle’s function argument seriously, it looks as though the moral life is the best sort of life we can live. We are “all too human,” and permanently cloistering ourselves away from others to grapple with philosophical questions is, for almost all of us, an unsustainable and unhappy way to live. 8 Moreover, the view that the moral life and the contemplative life are identical come at the cost of failing to justify the kind of academic contemplation Aristotle clearly had in mind in book X.
  • 12. Spence 12 Bibliography: Aristotle, “Nicomachean Ethics.” Trans. Robert Bartlett and Susan Collins. U Chicago P. London, 2011. Print. Aristotle, “Nicomachean Ethics.” Trans. WD Ross. Oxford U.P., 1980. Print.