SlideShare a Scribd company logo
1 of 62
PROJECT #3
RETAIL LOCATIONS
Instructions:
1. In an Word document, use the list provided at the end of
these instructions to describe the following for each retail
establishment listed:
a. Type of retail location
b. Factors affecting location (consumer shopping situations)
c. What considerations might the retailer had to have considered
when thinking about their location
d. Parking considerations?
e. Who is close to this particular retailer? How will that affect
the business?
f. What is their trade area? Tapestry Segment (focus segment)?
2. List of retailers:
a. Belks
b. JCPenney
c. Trendy Pieces
d. Lowes
e. Kohl’s
f. Dollar General
The Return of the Repressed
Psychology's Problematic Relations With Psychoanalysis, 1909-
1960
Gail A. Hornstein Mount Holyoke College
When psychoanalysis first arrived in the United States,
most psychologists ignored it. By the 1920s, however, psy-
choanalysis had so captured the public imagination that
it threatened to eclipse experimental psychology entirely.
This article analyzes the complex nature of this threat
and the myriad ways that psychologists responded to it.
Because psychoanalysis entailed precisely the sort of rad-
ical subjectivity that psychologists had renounced as un-
scientific, core assumptions about the meaning of science
were at stake. Psychologists' initial response was to retreat
into positivism, thereby further limiting psychology's rel-
evance and scope. By the 1950s, a new strategy had
emerged: Psychoanalytic concepts would be put to exper-
imental test, and those that qualified as "scientific" would
be retained. This reinstated psychologists as arbiters of
the mental world and restored "objective" criteria as the
basis for making claims. A later tactic—co-opting psy-
choanalytic concepts into mainstream psychology—had
the ironic effect of helping make psychology a more flexible
and broad-based discipline.
Freud and Jung were having dinner in Bremen. It was
the evening before they set sail for the Clark conference,
the occasion of Freud's only visit to America. Jung started
talking about certain mummies in the lead cellars of the
city. Freud became visibly disturbed. "Why are you so
concerned with these corpses?" he asked several times.
Jung went on talking. Suddenly, without warning, Freud
fell to the floor in a faint. When he recovered, he accused
Jung of harboring death wishes against him. But it was
not Jung who wanted Freud dead. Had Freud only known
what American psychologists were about to do to psy-
choanalysis, he might never have gotten up off the floor.
There is no easy way to talk about psychology's re-
lations with psychoanalysis.1 It is a story dense with dis-
illusionment and the shapeless anger of rejection. Each
side behaved badly, and then compounded its insensitivity
with disdain. Their fates bound together like Romulus
and Remus, psychology and psychoanalysis struggled to
find their separate spheres, only to end up pitted against
one another at every turn. Too much was at stake—prop-
erty lines, areas of influence, and a deeper question:
Which field would ultimately dictate the ground rules for
a science of the mind?
In the 1890s, when this struggle began, there was
little sign that it would become another Hundred Years'
War. Psychologists had just begun to apply experimental
methods to some of the classic problems of metaphysics,
with the hope of answering questions that had bedeviled
philosophers for centuries. By systematically organizing
the psychological world into a set of discrete variables,
these methods brought the unruly phenomena of mind
within the purview of science. It was a heady time, a time
of possibility and change and the reckless felicity of the
new. American psychologists raced around founding lab-
oratories at every college that would let them, in closets,
basements or wherever they could snatch a little space,
setting up apparatus in their own homes if necessary. They
invented new forms of measurement, odd devices, tests
of all sorts. Reports of their findings poured into the jour-
nals that sprang up suddenly to fill the need. The new
psychology, as they liked to call it, seemed destined even
in its infancy to do what had been declared since Kant
to be impossible—to create a truly scientific approach to
mind.
Psychoanalysts thrust themselves directly into the
middle of this scene, brazenly trying to supplant the new
psychology at the moment of its greatest promise. At first
psychologists stood aside, astonished, as the analysts,
bursting with self-importance and an almost frightening
zealotry, pronounced themselves the real scientists of the
mind. By the time psychologists began to take this threat
seriously, psychoanalysis had so captured the public
imagination that even its pretensions could not be ig-
nored.2
The question was how to define science. To the an-
alysts, science had nothing to do with method, with con-
I gratefully acknowledge Winifred Connerton's excellent
research assis-
tance and Verlyn Klinkenborg's incisive comments on earlier
drafts. I
also thank several groups of colleagues at Mount Holyoke for
their en-
couragement and suggestions, and John Burnham for his careful
reading
of a later draft. Preparation of this article was supported by a
fellowship
from the Mary Ingraham Bunting Institute of Radcliffe College.
Correspondence concerning this article should be addressed to
Gail
A. Hornstein, Department of Psychology, Mount Holyoke
College, South
Hadley, MA 01075.
1 The standard reference on this whole topic is Shakow and
Rapaport
(1964). Their study remains invaluable as a thoughtful,
systematic review
of much of what psychologists have had to say about
psychoanalysis.
However, because their goal was to document Freud's influence
on
American psychology, they focused more on positive effects
than on
negative ones. My goal is to characterize psychologists'
attitudes toward
psychoanalysis. Many psychologists saw psychoanalysis as a
threat and
not as a positive influence, and thus my version of the story is
inevitably
more conflicted than Shakow and Rapaport's.
2 A discussion of the popular reception of psychoanalysis in
America
is beyond the scope of this article. See Hale (1971, 1978) and
Burnham
(1968, 1978, 1979, 1987) for detailed treatments of this issue.
254 February 1992 • American Psychologist
Copyright 1992 by the American Psychological Association,
Inc. 0OO3-O66X/92/$2.0O
Vol. 47, No. 2, 254-263
trolling variables or counting things. What made some-
thing scientific was that it was true. Constructing a science
of the mind could mean only one thing—finding some
way to peer through the watery murk of consciousness
to the subaquean reality that lay beyond. The efforts of
psychologists, with their bulky equipment and piles of
charts and graphs, seemed superficial and largely irrele-
vant to this goal.3
For their part, psychologists initially saw psycho-
analysis as just another of the "mind cures" that flashed
across the American landscape in the 1890s—like Chris-
tian Science or the Emmanuel movement—a popular
craze that had nothing to do with the scientific study of
mind. Most psychologists who attended Freud's Clark
lectures in 1909 saw his speculations about dreams and
sex as a pleasant diversion, about as relevant to their work
as Mrs. Eddy's epistles. The occasional articles about
psychoanalysis that appeared in psychology journals be-
fore 1910 (e.g., Putnam, 1906; Scott, 1908) made it seem
mildly interesting, but not essentially different from re-
lated methods like suggestion.
By 1915, readers of a publication like The Journal
of Abnormal Psychology had an opportunity for more
varied exposure to psychoanalytic ideas.4 Books by Freud,
Jung, and A. A. Brill were regularly reviewed. Articles
demonstrating the therapeutic effectiveness of psycho-
analytic techniques began to appear, along with some dis-
cussion of the theory itself (see, e.g., Coriat, 1910; Emer-
son, 1912-1913; Gordon, 1917; MacCurdy, 1913; Mae-
der, 1910; Putnam, 1909-1910). Criticisms, when made,
were fair-minded and well within the spirit of scientific
repartee. Donley (1911), for example, suggested that
anxiety neurosis might have other causes beyond those
considered by Freud. Bellamy (1915a) argued that dreams
fulfill fears or states of anger just as often as they represent
wishes. Taylor (1911) noted that there were cases of neu-
rosis in which patients recovered without having had their
childhood or sexual life dissected. Even critics with a
broader focus expressed little ire. Wells (1913) was con-
cerned about "looseness in the formulation of psycho-
analytic theories" (p. 227). Solomon (1916) argued that
the term sexual was used inconsistently by analytic writ-
ers. The psychiatrist Morton Prince (1910) expressed the
common view that psychoanalysts "fit the facts to the
universal concepts which dominate the school" (p. 349).
There were occasional writers who became exasper-
ated and called psychoanalysis "weird" (Donley, 1911),
"esoteric" (Carrington, 1914), or "grotesque" (Bellamy,
1915a), its assumptions "fantastic" or "sheer nonsense"
(Humphrey, 1920b), but these imprecations were unusual
in the early years. The sexual nature of psychoanalytic
interpretation was a problem for some; Bellamy (1915b),
for example, in reviewing a book by Coriat, made plain
his relief that "there is not a word or sentence in this
book that a precise maiden lady need hesitate to read to
her Sunday school class or at a pink tea" (p. 434). On
the whole, however, psychologists were initially so sup-
portive of psychoanalysis that when Roback reviewed
Dunlap's (1920) Mysticism, Freudianism and Scientific
Psychology, he felt he had to defend its critical tone on
grounds of balance: "Freud has had so many warm ad-
vocates of his views in this country and so few systematic
critics among the psychologists that Dunlap's discussion
is both timely and important" (Roback, 1921, p. 406).
These positive attitudes might well have resulted
from more than psychologists' open-mindedness. Ana-
lysts, ever worried about their public image, left little to
chance. Soon after the Clark conference they embarked
on a systematic campaign to win Americans to their
cause. A. A. Brill, the founder of the New York Psycho-
analytic Society, was charged with disseminating infor-
mation about psychoanalysis in that city; Ernest Jones,
Freud's scrappy lieutenant, took the rest of the country
for himself (Burnham, 1967, pp. 134-137). Psychologists
were among the major recipients of Jones's educational
largess; by 1916, they had been treated to 20 of his articles,
abstracts, reviews, and comments in the Journal of Ab-
normal Psychology alone. Most of these pieces were pa-
tient expositions of psychoanalytic concepts, designed to
lead the uninitiated to a correct understanding of the the-
ory. But Jones also maintained a vigilant watch over what
psychologists were writing about psychoanalysis, and shot
back a tart riposte whenever he encountered an "erro-
neous" statement (see also Tannenbaum, 1916, 1917).
Neither Jones nor his colleagues gave serious atten-
tion to the careful criticisms that psychologists leveled
against psychoanalysis in the early years. Acutely aware
of the tenuous status of their own new field, psychologists
found this highly disconcerting. After all, they were con-
stantly obliged to defend their science against attacks from
philosophy and biology; what gave analysts the right not
only to ignore legitimate criticism but to patronize their
opponents? Who knows what might have happened had
analysts been more responsive; what did happen was that
psychologists sharpened their pencils and began to fight.
The first skirmish actually occurred as early as 1916,
when the Princeton philosopher Warner Fite reviewed
Jung's Psychology of the Unconscious for The Nation (Fite,
1916). His surprisingly nasty tone incited a riot of re-
sponse from psychologists. In her letter to the editor,
Christine Ladd-Franklin, the eminent experimentalist,
characterized psychoanalysis as a product of the "unde-
veloped . . . German mind" (hardly a compliment in
1916), and concluded ominously that "unless means can
speedily be found to prevent its spread . . . the prognosis
3 Psychologists were not alone in having to struggle with
competing
definitions of science. Kuklick's (1980) analysis of boundary
maintenance
in sociology offers a general model for understanding how each
of the
social sciences resolved this dilemma.
4 Of all major psychology journals of the period, the Journal of
Abnormal Psychology was the one with the greatest number of
articles
relevant to psychoanalysis (both pro and con). Not all were
written by
psychologists, but they were clearly intended for this audience.
G. Stanley
Hall published the text of Freud's, Jung's, and Ferenczi's Clark
lectures
in his American Journal of Psychology in 1910, but from then
on that
journal concentrated primarily on reviews of the psychoanalytic
literature
(both German and English) and carried very few original
articles by
psychologists.
February 1992 • American Psychologist 255
for civilization is unfavorable" (Ladd-Franklin, 1916, p.
374). R. S. Woodworth of Columbia (1916), a bit more
circumspect, called psychoanalysis an "uncanny religion"
(probably not the psychologist's highest accolade) that
led "even apparently sane individuals" to absurd asso-
ciations and nonsensical conclusions. In a telling illus-
tration, he showed how the words Freudian principles led
to a train of thought that revealed his own "deep-seated
wish . . . for a career of unbridled lust" (p. 396).
Woodworth went on to publish an extensive critique
of "Freudism" in the 1917 volume of the Journal of Ab-
normal Psychology. Adopting the peevish tone that soon
became commonplace in these sorts of articles, he com-
plained that analysts disregarded psychological research,
contemptuously dismissed it as superficial, and treated
psychologists "shabbily" (Woodworth, 1917, p. 175).
What most annoyed Woodworth was the analysts' slip-
pery dodge, their way of attributing any criticism of psy-
choanalysis to unconscious resistance on the part of the
critic.
Other writers echoed these complaints, often with
less poignancy and considerably more pique than Wood-
worth. But what soon emerged as the real irritant for
psychologists was the analysts' insistence, at times mor-
alistic, at times snide, that only those who had themselves
undergone a personal psychoanalysis were qualified to
evaluate the theory. To an experimental psychology whose
raison d'etre was to differentiate itself from religion, this
talk of initiation rites and secret knowledge was anathema.
Such a rule also conveniently disenfranchised just about
every psychologist from serving as a potential critic; even
those Americans who sought analysis had a hard time
finding it in this country before 1920. Of course the real
issue here was not who had been analyzed and who had
not (a good thing, since Freud and his closest colleagues
would have had to disqualify themselves); what was at
stake was the fundamental question of subjectivity in sci-
ence.
For experimental psychologists, being scientific
meant creating distance. It meant opening up a space, a
"no man's land," between themselves and the things they
studied, a place whose boundary could be patrolled so
that needs or desires or feelings could never infiltrate the
work itself. Every aspect of the experimental situation
was bent toward this goal—the "blind subjects," the
mechanized recording devices, the quantified measures,
and statistically represented results (Danziger, 1990;
Hornstein, 1988; Morawski, 1988). What united exper-
imental psychologists more than anything else was a dis-
trust of personal experience, a sense that feelings in par-
ticular were dangerous and had to be held carefully in
check lest they flood in and destroy the very foundations
of the work. They were willing to make a number of sac-
rifices to protect psychology from this threat, including
a radical narrowing of the field to include only phenomena
that could be studied "objectively."
Having gone to these lengths, psychologists found it
profoundly disquieting to have analysts claim that being
psychoanalyzed was what made someone a credible sci-
entist. This implied that science was subjective, that it
was ultimately about personal experience rather than rig-
orous method. Even worse, it suggested that the uncon-
scious was so powerful a part of mind that its force had
to be experienced directly, in one's own life, in order to
understand the psychology of others.
Such a view could not go unchallenged. "Voodoo-
ism," Watson (1927, p. 502) called it. "A delusion,"
echoed Jastrow (1932, p. 285). The very idea of an un-
conscious conjured up the chaos and irrationality that
psychologists had banded together to escape. If analysts
wanted to plunge into that nightmare world and call it
science, so be it, but they could not be allowed to drag
everyone else down with them.
The technique of free association came in for par-
ticular scorn (Heidbreder, 1933). It struck psychologists
as an elaborate subterfuge, a way for analysts to appear
not to influence patients when of course they did. Inter-
pretation, they argued, was nothing but a new name for
suggestion; that patients were gullible enough to mistake
it for truth was hardly proof of its scientific status. Analysts
were "free," all right—free to define as evidence whatever
would meet their needs, free to label any challenge "re-
sistance," free to pretend that they were doing nothing
of the sort.
Heidbreder (1933), in her typically fair-minded way,
struggled to make these practices sound reasonable. But
even she could muster only this faint defense: Just because
"psychoanalysts offer a different kind of evidence from
that accepted by science . . . does not mean that they
offer no evidence" (p. 402). To most psychologists, calling
an analyst's retrospective musings about events that oc-
curred in the secrecy of the consulting room evidence
was an insult to science. Even first-year students knew
that the cardinal rule of scientific proof was publicly ver-
ifiable data. Knight Dunlap (1920, p. 8) put it bluntly:
"psychoanalysis attempts to creep in wearing the uniform
of science, and to strangle it from the inside."5
By the mid-1920s, psychologists seem to have de-
cided that the best way to defend science was simply to
do it. Critiques of psychoanalysis began to be displaced
in the literature by enthusiastic works like Great Exper-
iments in Psychology (Garrett, 1930). Any remaining ag-
gressive tendencies were easily absorbed by the intermin-
able debates over behaviorism and Gestalt psychology.6
Psychologists did not need psychoanalysis, and it surely
did not need them.
Or so it seemed, until one day in the fall of 1934
when the rumor got out that Edwin Garrigues Boring,
5 With characteristic irony, Dunlap (1920) concluded that
psycho-
analysis might ultimately prove beneficial to psychology: "Just
as Chris-
tian Science has tremendously accelerated the progress of
Scientific
Medicine, so Psychoanalysis, by compelling psychology to put
its house
in order, will eventually help in the development of the
Scientific Psy-
chology it aims to thrust aside" (p. 9).
' See, for example, a classic work like Psychologies of 1925
(Mur-
chison, 1926), which allots four chapters to behaviorism, three
to Gestalt,
and even three to the dying gasps of structuralism, but none to
psycho-
analysis.
256 February 1992 • American Psychologist
the self-acknowledged dean of experimental psychology,
had entered analytic treatment. To preserve his reputa-
tion, he told colleagues that he was studying the relation
between the two fields; actually, he was depressed, fright-
ened, and unable to work. The strange saga of Boring's
analysis gives a glimpse into psychologists' continuing
ambivalence about psychoanalysis.
Boring chose as his analyst the emigre Berliner,
Hanns Sachs, who had been a member of Freud's inner
circle and was therefore above reproach. Despite his
depression, Boring embarked on the analysis with cus-
tomary gusto, quickly absorbing the daily analytic sessions
into the swirl of his 80-hour work week.
Boring struggled to make the analysis a success. He
missed no sessions. He wept. He threw things. He made
enough of a financial sacrifice to demonstrate the seri-
ousness of his commitment. He discussed his childhood,
explored his dreams, and scrutinized the motivations for
his actions. Then, at the end of 10 months, he ran out of
money, time, and desire. He had completed 168 sessions,
for which he had paid $1,680, more than a fifth of his
yearly salary. But his efforts brought little relief:
[A]ll that happened was that the analysis petered out in an un-
eventful session on June 21 st and my analyst went abroad!. . .
I was distraught. I had tried a last resource, and it had failed.
Yet, unwilling to accept so bitter a conclusion, I found myself
seizing on the analyst's casual statement that I ought to wait a
month. I waited anxiously, hoping for a new personality by July
21st. None came. Finally I sought out my psychologist-friends
who believe in psychoanalysis, and we sat in conference dis-
cussing this sad immutability of my personality—on August
21st, as I suddenly realized. Their advice was patience, the less
haste the more speed; wait at least until December 21st, they
urged. So I waited. . . . And finally I ceased to expect a miracle.
(Boring, 1940, pp. 9-10)7
How could a man like Boring, whose name was
practically synonymous with hard-nosed experimenta-
tion, have such childlike faith in psychoanalysis? He ac-
tually seemed to expect that he would wake up a new
man, that "a light from heaven" would change him "from
Saul to Paul" (p. 9). There are certainly no hints of these
hopes in his published writings. In the first edition of his
classic History of Experimental Psychology (Boring,
1929), published just five years before the analysis, there
were only four brief mentions of Freud in almost 700
pages. Psychoanalysis did not even appear in the index
of Psychology: A Factual Textbook, the text Boring pub-
lished with Langfeld and Weld in 1935, the same year he
saw Sachs.
Yet in his own life, Boring kept searching for some
sign that the analysis might have worked. Five years
passed. Still no light. In 1940, he tried a new strategy. He
proposed to the Journal of Abnormal and Social Psy-
chology that it locate other well-known psychologists who
had been analyzed, solicit reports of their experiences,
and publish them in a special issue. Perhaps they would
reveal something that he had missed. Leaving nothing to
chance, Boring even persuaded Sachs to write a compan-
ion piece to his own account, evaluating the analysis from
the analyst's perspective.
Psychologists turned out to be surprisingly excited
by the prospect of reading about their colleagues' adven-
tures on the couch. The American Psychological Asso-
ciation even reprinted the articles and sold them as a set,
exhausting the entire edition within a few months. Boring,
ever hopeful, titled his piece "Was This Analysis a Suc-
cess?" Sachs (1940) replied with a tactful " n o . " Wistful
and perplexed by the whole experience, Boring struggled
to come to terms with his sense of loss: "There is so much
about this personality of mine that would be better if
different, so much that analysis might have done and did
not!" (Boring, 1940, p. 10). Yet he refrained from at-
tacking psychoanalysis directly. His colleagues, however,
knew where to lay the blame for their own failed attempts.
Carney Landis of Columbia parodied his experience with
a statistical analysis of how much time he had allocated
to each of eight topics during free association. To Landis,
analysts were scientific illiterates who did little but mouth
received dogma in order to make themselves rich. Hinting
that his "neurosis" was created by the analysis itself,
Landis (1940) concluded his tirade by warning that psy-
choanalysis was safe only when used by experimental
psychologists to produce psychopathic phenomena in the
laboratory.
The editor of the Journal of Abnormal and Social
Psychology, apparently concerned about the lack of bal-
ance in these articles, invited the eminent analyst Franz
Alexander to contribute a rejoinder. Instead of critiquing
the other papers, Alexander (1940) made a parable of his
own life. Like his readers, he had spent his youth as a
devotee of laboratory science. When he first tried to read
Freud's work, he found its "vague and ambiguous mental
excursions . . . equal almost to physical pain" (p. 312).
He turned to psychoanalysis only when the evidence in
support of it became undeniable. This meant sacrificing
his promising academic career, enduring the opprobrium
of his colleagues, and being forced from home by his irate
philosopher father, who considered psychoanalysis a
"spiritual gutter." But for Alexander, there was no
choice—having committed himself to empiricism, he had
to adopt whatever view had the most evidence, regardless
of how distasteful it might be on other grounds. Of course,
in the end, his quest for truth was vindicated when his
father, near death, gave up his own lifelong belief in the
superiority of natural science to express the fervent wish
that "psychoanalysis will enthrone again real under-
standing in place of fumbling—the rule of thought in
place of that of the gadget" (p. 314).
7 Among those Boring consulted was his colleague Henry
Murray,
who advised him to let Sachs have it "right between his eyes. . .
. give
him the works—don't omit a single grievance, not one." (H.
Murray to
E. G. Boring [n. d., August 1935?], Box 43, Folder 919, E. G.
Boring
Papers, Harvard University Archives quoted by permission.)
There is
no evidence that Boring took this advice: He and Sachs
maintained a
cordial relationship for some time thereafter, dining together at
the Har-
vard Club and exchanging papers and letters on professional
topics.
February 1992 • American Psychologist 257
Alexander's inspiring tale fell on closed ears. Dis-
trusting subjectivity in all its forms, psychologists put little
stock in personal testimony, even that of fellow scientists.
This series of articles clearly had less to do with evaluating
psychoanalysis than it did with assuaging the anxiety of
its contributors, many of whom were worried, like Boring,
that their analyses had failed. What they needed was re-
assurance. But the tangible benefits of this kind of therapy
are always elusive. Recall Janet Malcolm's (1984) sardonic
comment: "The crowning paradox of psychoanalysis is
the near-uselessness of its insights. To 'make the uncon-
scious conscious' . . . is to pour water into a sieve. The
moisture that remains on the surface of the mesh is the
benefit of analysis" (p. 25). Ultimately, these articles were
exercises in self-persuasion, attempts by the contributors
to convince themselves that psychoanalysis was too ri-
diculous or too ineffectual to be taken seriously. If they
managed in the process to warn off colleagues who might
have been tempted to try the thing themselves, so much
the better.
By the early 1940s, the situation had reached a crit-
ical stage. Psychoanalysis was becoming so popular that
it threatened to eclipse psychology entirely. Journalists
seemed oblivious to the differences between the two fields,
and exasperated psychologists often found their discipline
being portrayed as if it were nothing but a branch of psy-
choanalytic inquiry. This was especially galling because
most psychologists assumed that psychoanalytic claims
were not even true. But how could they prove this? The
critiques of the early years had not worked. Attacking
psychoanalysis from the couch had simply allowed Al-
exander to make psychologists look foolish. There had to
be a better way.
The solution turned out to be so obvious that it is
hard to believe it took until the mid-1940s to appear.
Psychologists would set themselves the job of determining
through carefully controlled experiments which, if any,
psychoanalytic concepts were valid. This reinstated psy-
chologists as arbiters of the mental world, able to make
the final judgment about what would and would not count
as psychological knowledge. It allowed them to evaluate
psychoanalysis, rather than be overshadowed or absorbed
by it. Most important, it restored the objective criterion
of the experiment as the basis for making claims and
settling disputes, undermining the analysts' attempts to
substitute a new, subjective standard for psychological
truth.
Psychologists took to their new role with a vengeance.
Every conceivable psychoanalytic concept was put to the
test, in hundreds of studies whose creativity was matched
only by the uselessness of their findings. Mowrer (1940)
demonstrated that regression and reaction formation
could be produced in rats. Blum and Miller (1952) found
that children who were categorized as having an "oral
character" ate significantly more ice cream than did other
children. Scodel (1957) showed that "high-dependency"
men did not manifest the predicted preference for women
with large breasts. Schwartz (1956) found more castration
anxiety among men than women, with homosexual men
scoring the highest of all. Sarnoff and Corwin (1959) re-
ported that "high castration anxious" men showed a
greater increase in fear of death than did "low anxious"
men after being exposed to photographs of nude women.
And Friedman (1952) found that when children were
shown a picture of a father and a child near some stairs,
more girls than boys fantasized that the father would
mount the stairs and enter the room.
Topics like oedipal relations and anal personality had
their aficionados, but it was perceptual defense that really
captured the imagination of psychological researchers.
Their hypothesis was a simple one: If the mind did defend
against forbidden material, then words with disturbing
or salacious associations should be recalled less easily than
more neutral stimuli. Fresh-faced graduate students spent
hours making certain that items like whore and bugger
were matched in length and salience with their sexless
counterparts. Controversies erupted left and right: Were
taboo words difficult to recognize just because they were
not used very frequently? Wiener's (1955) famous "pussy-
balls" study dispatched that idea by demonstrating that
the context, not the words themselves, made certain
stimuli threatening. But was exposure to a list of scatal-
ogical words really analogous to the sort of trauma that
necessitated repression? Blum (1954) addressed that
problem with a new methodology based on the Blacky
Pictures, a set of cartoon images of a dog depicted in
various psychoanalytically relevant poses (licking his
genitals, observing his parents having sex, defecating out-
side their kennel). When studies with Blacky were found
to support the earlier word-item findings, repression
gained the sort of empirical reality that only psychologists
could give it.
By the 1950s, research on psychoanalysis had be-
come so popular that psychologists were drowning in it.
No one could possibly read all the studies that were being
published, much less keep track of their results.8 A new
cottage industry was born of this need, with workers who
did nothing but summarize and evaluate these studies.
Robert Sears had been the first such laborer, commis-
sioned in 1943 by the Social Science Research Council
to write an objective review of the scientific literature on
psychoanalytic theory. Sears's approach, used by all sub-
sequent evaluators, was straightforward: Having first di-
vided the literature into topic categories (fixation, sex-
uality, object choice), he then counted how many studies
in each area supported Freud's claims. The larger the
number, the more scientific the claim. Taken together,
these individual scores were supposed to provide an an-
swer to the overall question of whether psychoanalytic
theory was valid.
Sears (1943) hedged, saying that some of it was, and
some of it was not. Such caution soon vanished. The self-
appointed judges whose reports appeared up through the
"Fisher and Greenberg's (1977) review includes more than 400
studies from the 1940s and 1950s alone. By the mid-1970s,
there were
at least 1,000 more.
258 February 1992 • American Psychologist
early 1970s placed themselves squarely on one side of the
debate or the other. Evaluation studies quickly became
as difficult to sort out as research on psychoanalysis itself,
and much less fun to read (see, for example, Fisher &
Greenberg, 1977; Kline, 1972). Each report took a tone
yet more strident than the last, and the original goal of
providing an objective review was lost entirely. This was
nowhere more evident than in Eysenck and Wilson's
(1973) polemic. Every shred of evidence seeming to sup-
port psychoanalysis was scrutinized for methodological
flaws, whereas studies opposing the theory were flaunted
as examples of good science.
No one especially cared that the evaluation literature
was becoming debased. It made little difference what the
findings were; as long as psychoanalytic phenomena were
made subservient to empirical test, empiricism was vin-
dicated.9 That much of this research supported Freud's
theory was an irony appreciated by few. It was the act of
doing these studies, of piling them up and sorting them
out and arguing about them that was important, not what
they revealed about psychoanalysis. Some psychologists
found these activities so salubrious that they recom-
mended them even to analysts. As Albert Ellis (1950)
cheerfully noted, "sociologists, who but a decade or two
ago were mostly concerned with pure theory, now fre-
quently design and execute crucial experiments which
enable them to support or discredit hypotheses. There is
no basic reason why psychoanalysts cannot do likewise"
(p. 190).
Analysts were in no position to point out that the
content of these psychological studies had only the dim-
mest relation to Freud's theory. "Every country creates
the psychoanalysis it [unconsciously] needs," said Kurz-
weil (1989, p. 1), and disciplines surely do the same. Re-
search on psychoanalysis was invigorating because it gave
psychologists a sense of mastery: They had ventured onto
the battlefield of the unconscious and returned, trium-
phant, with a set of dependent variables. Some psychol-
ogists even managed to convince themselves that the dan-
ger had been exaggerated all along, that they had really
been in control. They scoffed that psychoanalysis had
never been much more than an inflated way of talking
about conditioning, one of psychology's oldest topics. By
the time Dollard and Miller (1950) actually began trans-
lating every psychoanalytic concept into its learning the-
ory equivalent, their efforts were almost redundant.
These behaviorist reworkings of Freud, although of-
ten clumsy, did signal a new strategy in dealing with psy-
choanalysis—co-optation. More satisfying than silence,
with none of the pitfalls of criticism, the appropriation
of psychoanalytic concepts into mainstream psychology
seemed an ideal compromise. Like the Christianizing of
paganism, the dangerous parts were still there somewhere,
but in such diluted form as to pose no real threat.10
Watson had tried to move in this direction as early
as the 1920s. By relabeling the unconscious as the unver-
balized, he could sweep most psychoanalytic phenomena
into the neat piles of behaviorist theory. Emotions became
sets of habits; neurosis was conditioning; therapy, uncon-
ditioning. Watson never denied the reality of Freud's
findings; he simply cast them in his own terms (e.g., when
he warned [1928, p. 80] that sexual frustration made
mothers want to kiss rather than shake hands with their
children). At times, Watson even took to calling himself
an analyst, as if, like some ancient warrior, he could mag-
ically disarm his enemy by assuming his name.11
Other behaviorists continued where Watson left off.
Humphrey (1920a), following Holt's (1915) earlier lead,
dissolved wishes into conditioned reflexes. Keller and
Schoenfeld (1950) laid claim to such psychoanalytic sta-
ples as the slip of the tongue (yet another reflex) and the
oedipal complex (a consequence of early conditioning).
But it was Skinner who took the task of appropriating
Freud most seriously. In Science and Human Behavior
(1953), he systematically redefined each of the defense
mechanisms in operant terms {repression: a "response
which is successful in avoiding the conditioned aversive
stimulation generated by punishment," p. 292; reaction
formation: "an extension of a technique of self-control
in which the environment is altered so that it becomes
less likely to generate punished behavior," p. 365). By the
end of the book, even symbols and dreams had taken on
the veneer of conditioned responses. Artful as these efforts
were, they did not really solve the problem. Freud was
still there. His new operant outfit gave him a natty Amer-
ican look, but there was no mistaking that sardonic smile.
As long as psychoanalytic concepts remained identifiable
as such, they were potential rivals to psychology's own
constructs.
Help with this problem came from an unlikely
source—introductory textbook writers. Typically dis-
missed as nothing but purveyors of pabulum for college
students, these authors, many of them prominent psy-
chologists, played a major role in advancing the co-op-
tation of psychoanalytic theory. This is not so surprising.
As Morawski (1992, this issue) shows, introductory texts
exist in a liminal space, neither popular nor professional,
9 Hilgard (1952) was the only evaluator who seemed willing to
grant
this point. He chastised psychologists for doing experiments
that "give
merely trivial illustrations of what psychoanalysts have
demonstrated
. . . in clinical work," and argued that although "such
illustrations may
be useful as propaganda," they "do not really do much for
science." In
his view, psychoanalytic research "ought to advance our
understanding,
not merely confirm or deny the theories that someone [else] has
stated"
(p. 43).
10 Precisely the same thing was done with Gestalt psychology.
At
first, the philosophic assumptions of the theory were seen as a
challenge
to American (behaviorist) psychology, and Gestalt was
explicitly opposed.
Then the dangerous aspects were simply stripped away, making
it appear
as if the principles of organization were empirical observations
that had
arisen out of nowhere. A contemporary student of perceptual
psychology
would have no idea that these principles were originally
formulated in
opposition to behaviorist thought.
1' "I venture to predict that 20 years from now an analyst using
Freudian concepts and Freudian terminology will be placed
upon the
same plane as a phrenologist. And yet analysis based upon
behavioristic
principles is here to stay and is a necessary profession in
society—to be
placed upon a par with internal medicine and surgery" (Watson,
1925,
p. 243). The comparison of psychoanalysis to phrenology was a
favorite
among psychologists; Dallenbach (1955) later wrote an entire
article on
this theme.
February 1992 • American Psychologist 259
yet somehow both. They function simultaneously as
translators of standard doctrine and contributors to it.
Because new texts constantly supplant older ones, they
become disciplinary artifacts, frozen moments of taken-
for-granted knowledge, X rays of the uncontroversial.
Textbook writers took advantage of their role by as-
similating psychoanalytic concepts into mainstream psy-
chology without mentioning their origins. An early ex-
ample was Walter Hunter's 1923 text, General Psychology,
in which the various defense mechanisms were stripped
of any connection to the unconscious, much the way ba-
gels now appear in the frozen-food sections of Peoria su-
permarkets. Other writers soon adopted this practice,
sometimes using the term adjustment mechanisms to ex-
punge any remaining whifFof psychodynamics (Guthrie
& Edwards, 1949; Kimble, 1956).
These appropriations took place amidst a general
silence in these texts about psychoanalytic theory itself.
Many writers ignored the topic entirely: Robinson and
Robinson's 665-page Readings in General Psychology
(1923) included the contributions of every conceivable
psychologist, even Helen Keller and the Lord Archbishop
of York, but had nothing by Freud or any other psy-
choanalyst (the section titled "Dreams as a Vehicle of
Wish Fulfillment" was written by Watson). Readers of
well-known texts like Seashore's (1923) Introduction to
Psychology or Warren and Carmichael's (1930) Elements
of Human Psychology would never have known that psy-
choanalysis existed. Even as late as 1958, a classic like
Hebb's Textbook of Psychology barely mentioned the
topic. When Freud did make an appearance, it was more
likely to be in the section on punishment or motivation—
topics dear to the heart of experimentalists—than in ex-
pected places like the chapter on abnormality.
Of course some textbook writers did discuss psy-
choanalysis in more depth, but few besides Hilgard (1953)
did so sympathetically.n Kimble (1956) went to the trou-
ble of including a special section in his introduction
warning readers not to make the common error of con-
fusing psychology with psychoanalysis. It was not that
Freud had no value: Kimble called his work "one of the
great milestones in the history of human thought" with
"insights [that] have never been equaled" (pp. 369-370).
Psychoanalysis just happened to be "entirely literary and
not worth discussion" in a scientific text (p. 370).
In 1956, Gardner Murphy was asked to determine
the extent of Freud's impact on the various subfields of
psychology. He likened the overall effect to the erosion of
the rocky coastline in Maine, but admitted that some
areas had remained untouched by the psychoanalytic
current. His results, on a numerical scale, of course, con-
stitute what one might call an index of introgression,
ranging from 0, Freud never had a chance, to 6, he made
it all the way in. Here are Murphy's ratings: intelligence
and physiological = 0; comparative, learning, thinking,
perception, and vocational = 1; memory, drive and emo-
tion, child and adolescent = 2; social and industrial = 3;
imagination = 4; abnormal = 5; personality and clini-
cal = 6.
What is surprising about these results is that there
are any high scores at all. How could a discipline that
had spent 50 years protecting its chastity end up seduced
by a ladykiller like Freud? Of course the problem was
really only with the clinicians, but there were thousands
of them, and more every year (Gilgen, 1982; Kelly, 1947).
When the American Psychological Association surveyed
a sample of its members in 1954, asking who had influ-
enced them to enter the field, Freud, of all people, got
the greatest number of mentions (Clark, 1957, pp. 17-
18). True, by that time, 37% of APA members were cli-
nicians (p. 116), but how had that happened? Why were
so many psychologists fleeing the laboratory?
Perhaps it was just the money. Or the effects of the
war. But what if this exodus had a more ominous
meaning?
Repression is a perverse process. It appears to efface
the offending material, but this is an illusion—the con-
tents of the unconscious are indestructible. Repressed
material, like radioactive waste, lies there in leaky can-
isters, never losing potency, eternally dangerous. What
is worse, it actively presses for expression, constantly
threatening to erupt into consciousness. No one can con-
trol these forces; the best we can do is try to deflect them.
It is a sign of health if we can accomplish this with a few
judiciously used defenses. We know we're in trouble when
we have to resort to the rigidity of symptoms.
Experimentalists took a calculated risk in trying to
create a psychology in which subjective phenomena were
banned from study. They knew that this would be difficult,
that it would require erecting a set of defenses (the ex-
perimental method and all its appurtenances) and being
vigilant about their use. But subjectivity creeps through
every crevice and finds its way around even the strongest
barricade. In the early years, this threat was manageable
and psychology was willing to tolerate some narrowing
of its operations in exchange for the reduction of anxiety
its defenses allowed. Psychoanalysis tore this fragile equi-
librium to pieces. By embracing subjectivity—sometimes
even reveling in it—while still proclaiming itself a science,
psychoanalysis forced psychology to define itself in ever
more positivist terms. This was no ordinary battle over
intellectual turf. It was more like a nightmare, in which
psychologists watched, horrified, as the very phenomena
they had sought to banish now returned to haunt them.
They did what they could to contain the threat, but each
new tactic only made things worse. Co-opting analytic
concepts proved to be especially disastrous because it let
the banned phenomena inside psychology itself. Even in
scientific disguise, they were still dangerous, like a well-
dressed hitchhiker who pulls a knife after getting into the
car. With the threat now internal as well as external, ex-
12 Buys (1976) has argued that it was only in the 1970s that
positive
portrayals of psychoanalysis became common in introductory
texts. See
also Herma, Kris, & Shor (1943), whose study focused on how
Freud's
theory of dreams was presented in such texts. They found such a
high
degree of criticism that they were forced to make separate
tallies for
ridicule, rejection on moral grounds, and sheer denial.
260 February 1992 • American Psychologist
perimental psychology was forced to harden itself still
further. What had once been science became scientism,
the neurotic symptom of a frightened discipline.
In retrospect, we might say that this was all to the
good. The psychology that emerged from these wrenching
experiences was stronger and more resilient, able to tol-
erate a degree of diversity among its members that would
once have been unthinkable. The past 30 years have been
a time of exponential growth, as older areas like learning
have reorganized and newer ones like clinical have ma-
tured. The "cognitive revolution" that brought the mind
back to psychology transformed even the most hard-core
behaviorist, and terms like self-perception are now ban-
died about the laboratory as if they had been there all
along. The rigid experimentalism of the 1940s now seems
vaguely embarrassing, one of those righteous crusades of
adolescence that pales before the complex realities of
middle age.
There were many reasons for these changes, and cer-
tainly the threat from psychoanalysis was only one of a
host of factors pushing psychology toward greater flexi-
bility. But, as Burnham (1978) has argued, psychoanalysis
did represent an extreme position against which more
conservative disciplines like psychology and psychiatry
had to define themselves. The willingness of analysts to
occupy the radical frontiers of subjectivity gave psychol-
ogists room to maneuver, to create a middle ground in
which previously excluded phenomena could enter with-
out threatening the scientific standards psychologists had
fought so hard to establish.
Equally important were the changes in psychoanal-
ysis itself. During the period from 1940 to 1960, inter-
necine warfare reached new heights among American an-
alysts. The purges in the New York Psychoanalytic Insti-
tute were only the most visible sign that the field had
become increasingly intolerant of dissent, and the huge
influx of candidates after the war accelerated this slide
toward conformity and conservatism (Hale, 1978; Jacoby,
1983). Psychoanalysis in 1950 was fundamentally differ-
ent from what it had been in 1920, and its new main-
stream mentality made it far easier for psychologists to
accept.
The Second World War also played a significant role
in these dynamics. Psychologists made substantive con-
tributions to the diagnosis and treatment of war-related
disturbances, as well as to myriad other problems from
personnel selection to instrument design. These efforts
enhanced the reputation of professional psychology and
stimulated a massive increase in funding for psychological
research. The war also brought to America European ref-
ugee psychologists, many of whom saw psychoanalytic
ideas as part of the psychological canon. Psychologists
began to spend less time worrying about whether analysts
were eroding the fragile boundary between legitimate and
popular psychology (Morawski & Hornstein, 1991) and
took advantage of opportunities to get some favorable
press of their own.13
American psychology has always been distinguished
by an uncanny ability to adapt itself to cultural trends
as quickly as they emerge. Once it became clear that the
public found psychoanalysis irresistible, psychologists
found ways of accommodating to it. Instead of concen-
trating all their efforts on criticism, they identified those
parts of the theory that were potentially useful to their
own ends and incorporated them. As psychoanalysis be-
came less threatening, psychologists were able to notice
that the two fields actually shared many of the same basic
assumptions: a commitment to psychic determinism, a
belief in the cardinal importance of childhood experience,
and an optimistic outlook about the possibility of change.
It has been only 70 years since James McKeen Cattell
rose from his seat at the annual meeting of the American
Psychological Association to castigate a colleague for
having mentioned Freud's name at a gathering of scientists
(Dallenbach, 1955, p. 523). Today that same APA cele-
brates the success of its lawsuit against the psychoanalytic
establishment, a suit which gave psychologists the right
to become bona fide candidates at the analytic institute
of their choice (Buie, 1988). As the moribund institutes
prepare to be enlivened by a rush of eager psychologists,
perhaps it is not too much to suggest that psychology
itself has benefited from having had the psychoanalytic
wolf at its door.
REFERENCES
Alexander, F. (1940). A jury trial of psychoanalysis. Journal of
Abnormal
and Social Psychology, 35, 305-323.
Bellamy, R. (1915a). An act of everyday life treated as a
pretended dream
and reinterpreted by psychoanalysis. Journal of Abnormal
Psychology,
10, 32-45.
Bellamy, R. (1915b). Review of Coriat's The meaning of
dreams. Journal
of Abnormal Psychology, 10, 433-434.
Blum, G. S. (1954). An experimental reunion of psychoanalytic
theory
with perceptual vigilance and defense. Journal of Abnormal and
Social
Psychology, 49, 94-98.
Blum, G. S., & Miller, D. R. (1952). Exploring the
psychoanalytic theory
of the "oral character." Journal of Personality, 20, 287-304.
Boring, E. G. (1929). A history of experimental psychology.
New York:
Century.
Boring, E. G. (1940). Was this analysis a success? Journal of
Abnormal
and Social Psychology, 35, 4-10.
Boring, E. G., Langfeld, H. S., & Weld, H. P. (1935).
Psychology: A
factual textbook. New York: Wiley.
Buie, J. (1988). Psychoanalytic group bolstered by legal win.
APA Monitor,
19,21.
Burnham, J. C. (1967). Psychoanalysis and American medicine,
1894-
1918. New York: International Universities Press.
Burnham, J. C. (1968). The new psychology: From narcissism to
social
control. In J. Braeman, R. H. Bremmer, & D. Brody (Eds.),
Change
and continuity in twentieth-century America: The 1920s (pp. 3 5
1 -
398). Columbus: Ohio State University Press.
Burnham, J. C. (1978). The influence of psychoanalysis upon
American
culture. In J. M. Quen & E. T. Carlson (Eds.), American
psycho-
analysis: Origins and development (pp. 52-72). New York:
Brunner/
Mazel.
Burnham, J. C. (1979). From avant-garde to specialism:
Psychoanalysis
13 See, for example, Gengerelli's (1957) rhetorical romp in the
Sat-
urday Review, which painted psychologists as tireless laborers
in the
"scientific vineyard" and analysts as "muddle-headed, sob-
sisters" (p.
11) who are the cause of every social ill from delinquency to
early mar-
riage.
February 1992 • American Psychologist 261
in America. Journal of the History of the Behavioral Sciences
15
128-134.
Burnham, J. C. (1987). How superstition won and science lost:
Popu-
larizing science and health in the United States. New
Brunswick, NJ:
Rutgers University Press.
Buys, C. J. (1976). Freud in introductory psychology texts.
Teaching of
Psychology, 3, 160-167.
Carrington, H. (1914). Freudian psychology and psychical
research.
Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 9, 411 -416.
Clark, K. E. (1957). America's psychologists: A survey of a
growing
profession. Washington, DC: American Psychological
Association.
Coriat, I. H. (1910). The psycho-analysis of a case of sensory
automatism.
Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 5, 93-99.
Dallenbach, K. M. (1955). Phrenology versus psychoanalysis.
American
Journal of Psychology, 68, 511-525.
Danziger, K. (1990). Constructing the subject: Historical
origins of psy-
chological research. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Dollard, J., & Miller, N. E. (1950). Personality and
psychotherapy. New
York: McGraw-Hill.
Donley, J. E. (1911). Freud's anxiety neurosis. Journal of
Abnormal
Psychology, 6, 126-134.
Dunlap, K. (1920). Mysticism, Freudianism and scientific
psychology.
St. Louis, MO: Mosby.
Ellis, A. (1950). An introduction to the principles of scientific
psycho-
analysis. Genetic Psychology Monographs, 41, 147-212.
Emerson, L. E. (1912-1913). A psychoanalytic study of a severe
case of
hysteria. Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 7, 385-406; 8, 44-56,
180-
207.
Eysenck, H. J., & Wilson, G. D. (1973). The experimental study
of
Freudian theories. London: Methuen.
Fisher, S., & Greenberg, R. P. (1977). The scientific credibility
of Freud's
theories and therapy. New York: Basic Books.
Fite, W. (1916). Psycho-analysis and sex-psychology. The
Nation, 103,
127-129.
Friedman, S. M. (1952). An empirical study of the castration
and Oedipus
complexes. Genetic Psychology Monographs, 46, 61-130.
Garrett, H. E. (1930). Great experiments in psychology. New
York: Cen-
tury.
Gengerelli, J. A. (1957, March 23). The limitations of
psychoanalysis:
Dogma or discipline? The Saturday Review, pp. 9 - 1 1 , 40.
Gilgen, A. R. (1982). American psychology since World War II:
A profile
of the discipline. Westport, CT: Greenwood Press.
Gordon, A. (1917). Obsessive hallucinations and
psychoanalysis. Journal
of Abnormal Psychology, 12, 423-430.
Guthrie, E. R., & Edwards, A. L. (1949). Psychology: A first
course in
human behavior. New York: Harper.
Hale, N. G. (1971). Freud and the Americans: The beginnings of
psy-
choanalysis in the United States, 1876-1917. New York: Oxford
Uni-
versity Press.
Hale, N. G. (1978). From Bergasse XIX to Central Park West:
The
Americanization of psychoanalysis, 1919-1940. Journal of the
History
of the Behavioral Sciences, 14, 299-315.
Heidbreder, E. (1933). Seven psychologies. Englewood Cliffs,
NJ: Prentice-
Hall.
Hebb, D. O. (1958). A textbook of psychology. Philadelphia: W.
B. Saun-
ders.
Herma, H., Kris, E., & Shor, J. (1943). Freud's theory of the
dream in
American textbooks. Journal of Abnormal and Social
Psychology, 38,
319-334.
Hilgard, E. R. (1952). Experimental approaches to
psychoanalysis. In
E. Pumpian-Mindlin (Ed.), Psychoanalysis as science (pp. 3-45).
New
York: Basic Books.
Hilgard, E. R. (1953). Introduction to psychology. New York:
Harcourt,
Brace.
Holt, E. B. (1915). The Freudian wish and its place in ethics.
New York:
Holt.
Hornstein, G. A. (1988). Quantifying psychological phenomena:
Debates,
dilemmas, and implications. In J. G. Morawski (Ed.), The rise
of
experimental psychology (pp. 1-34). New Haven, CT: Yale
University
Press.
Humphrey, G. (1920a). The conditioned reflex and the Freudian
wish.
Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 14, 388-392.
Humphrey, G. (1920b). Education and Freudianism. Journal of
Abnor-
mal Psychology, 15, 350-386.
Hunter, W. (1923). General psychology. (Rev. ed.). Chicago:
University
of Chicago Press.
Jacoby, R. (1983). The repression of psychoanalysis: Otto
Fenichel and
the political Freudians. New York: Basic Books.
Jastrow, J. (1932). The house that Freud built. New York:
Chilton.
Keller, F , & Schoenfeld, W. (1950). Principles of psychology:
A systematic
text in the science of behavior. New York: Appleton-Century-
Crofts.
Kelly, E. L. (1947). Clinical psychology. In W. Dennis et. al.
(Eds.),
Current trends in psychology, (pp. 75-108). Pittsburgh, PA:
University
of Pittsburgh Press.
Kimble, G. A. (1956). Principles of general psychology. New
York: Ronald
Press.
Kline, P. (1972). Fact and fantasy in Freudian theory. London:
Methuen.
Kuklick, H. (1980). Boundary maintenance in American
sociology:
Limitations to academic "professionalization." Journal of the
History
of the Behavioral Sciences, 16, 201-219.
Kurzweil, E. (1989). The Freudians: A comparative perspective.
New
Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
Ladd-Franklin, C. (1916). Letter to the editor. The Nation, 103,
373-
374.
Landis, C. (1940). Psychoanalytic phenomena. Journal of
Abnormal and
Social Psychology, 35, 17-28.
MacCurdy, J. T. (1913). The productions in a manic-like state
illustrating
Freudian mechanisms. Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 8, 361-
375.
Maeder, A. (1910). Psycho-analysis in a case of melancholic
depression.
Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 5, 130-131.
Malcolm, J. (1984). In the Freud archives. New York: Knopf.
Morawski, J. G. (1988). Introduction. In J. G. Morawski (Ed.),
The rise
of experimentation in American psychology (pp. vii-xvii). New
Haven,
CT: Yale University Press.
Morawski, J. G. (1992). There is more to our history of giving:
The
place of introductory textbooks in American psychology.
American
Psychologist, 47, 161-169.
Morawski, J. G., & Hornstein, G. A. (1991). Quandary of the
quacks:
The struggle for expert knowledge in American psychology,
1890-
1940. In D. van Keuren & J. Brown (Eds.), The estate of social
knowl-
edge (pp. 106-133). Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.
Mowrer, O. H. (1940). An experimental analogue of
"regression" with
incidental observations on "reaction-formation." Journal of
Abnormal
and Social Psychology, 35, 56-87.
Murchison, C. (1926). Psychologies of 1925. Worcester, MA:
Clark Uni-
versity Press.
Murphy, G. (1956). The current impact of Freud upon
psychology.
American Psychologist, 11, 663-672.
Prince, M. (1910). The mechanism and interpretation of
dreams—A
reply to Dr. Jones. Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 5, 337-
353.
Putnam, J. J. (1906). Recent experiences in the study and
treatment of
hysteria at the Massachusetts General Hospital with remarks on
Freud's method of treatment by "psycho-analysis." Journal of
Ab-
normal Psychology, 1, 26-41.
Putnam, J. J. (1909-1910). Personal impressions of Sigmund
Freud and
his work, with special reference to his recent lectures at Clark
Uni-
versity. Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 4, 293-310, 372-379.
Roback, A. A. (1921). Review of Dunlap's Mysticism,
Freudianism and
scientific psychology. Journal of Abnormal and Social
Psychology, 16,
406-408.
Robinson, E. S., & Robinson, F. R. (1923). Readings in general
psy-
chology. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Sachs, H. (1940). Was this analysis a success?: Comment.
Journal of
Abnormal and Social Psychology, 35, 11-16.
Sarnoff, I., & Corwin, S. M. (1959). Castration anxiety and the
fear of
death. Journal of Personality, 27, 374-385.
Schwartz, B. J. (1956). An empirical test of two Freudian
hypotheses
concerning castration anxiety. Journal of Personality, 24, 318-
327.
Scodel, A. (1957). Heterosexual somatic preference and fantasy
depen-
dency. Journal of Consulting Psychology, 21, 371-374.
Scott, W. D. (1908). An interpretation of the psycho-analytic
method
in psychotherapy with a report of a case so treated. Journal of
Ab-
normal Psychology, 3, 371-379.
262 February 1992 • American Psychologist
Sears, R. R. (1943). Survey of objective studies of
psychoanalytic concepts.
New York: Social Science Research Council.
Seashore, C. E. (1923). Introduction to psychology. New York:
Macmillan.
Shakow, D., & Rapaport, D. (1964). The influence of Freud on
American
psychology. New York: International Universities Press.
Skinner, B. F. (1953). Science and human behavior. New York:
Macmillan.
Solomon, M. (1916). Critical review of the conception of
sexuality as-
sumed by the Freudian school. Journal of Abnormal Psychology,
11,
59-60.
Tannenbaum, S. A. (1916). Letter to the editor. The Nation,
103, 2 1 8 -
219.
Tannenbaum, S. A. (1917). Some current misconceptions of
psycho-
analysis. Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 12, 390-422.
Taylor, E. W. (1911). Possibilities of a modified
psychoanalysis. Journal
of Abnormal Psychology, 6, 449-455.
Warren, H. C , & Carmichael, L. (1930). Elements of human
psychology
(Rev. ed.). Boston: Houghton Mifflin.
Watson, J. B. (1925). Behaviorism. New York: Norton.
Watson, J. B. (1927). The myth of the unconscious. Harpers,
155, 502-
508.
Watson, J. B. (1928). Psychological care of the infant and child.
New
York: Norton.
Wells, F. L. (1913). On formulation in psychoanalysis. Journal
of Ab-
normal Psychology, 8, 217-227.
Wiener, M. (1955). Word frequency or motivation in perceptual
defense.
Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology, 51, 214-218.
Woodworth, R. S. (1916). Letter to the editor. The Nation, 103,
396.
Woodworth, R. S. (1917). Some criticisms of the Freudian
psychology.
Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 12, 174-194.
February 1992 • American Psychologist 263
SECOND LECTURE
THE PSYCHOLOGY OF ERRORS
W
E begin with an investigation, not with hypotheses.
To this end we choose certain phenomena which
are very frequent, very familiar and very little
heeded, and which have nothing to do with the
pathological, inasmuch as they can be observed in every normal
person. I refer to the errors which an individual commits—•
as for example, errors of speech in which he wishes to say
some-
thing and uses the wrong word; or those which happen to him in
writing, and which he may or may not notice; or the case of
misreading, in which one reads in the print or writing something
different from what is actually there. A similar phenomenon
occurs in those cases of mishearing what is said to one, where
there is no question of an organic disturbance of the auditory
function. Another series of such occurrences is based on for-
getfulness—but on a forgetfulness which is not permanent, but
temporary, as for instance when one cannot think of a name
which one knows and always recognizes; or when one forgets
to carry out a project at the proper time but which one re-
members again later, and therefore has only forgotten for a
certain interval. In a third class this characteristic of transience
is lacking, as for example in mislaying things so that they
cannot
t>e found again, or in the analogous case of losing things. Here
we are dealing with a kind of forgetfulness to which one reacts
differently from the other cases, a forgetfulness at which one is
surprised and annoyed, instead of considering it
comprehensible.
Allied with these phenomena is that of erroneous ideas—in
which the element of transience is again prominent, inasmuch
as for a while one believes something which, before and after
that time, one knows to be untrue—and a number of similar
phenomena of different designations.
These are all occurrences whose inner connection is expressed
10
The Psychology of Errors 11
in the use of the same prefix of designation.1 They are almost
all unimportant, generally temporary and without much signifi-
cance in the life of the individual. It is only rarely that one of
them, such as the phenomenon of losing things, attains to a cer-
tain practical importance. For that reason also they do not
attract much attention, they arouse only weak affects.
It is, therefore, to these phenomena that I would now direct
your attention. But you will object, with annoyance: "There
are so many sublime riddles in the external world, just as there
are in the narrower world of the psychic life, and so many
wonders in the field of psychic disturbances which demand and
deserve elucidation, that it really seems frivolous to waste labor
and interest on such trifles. If you can explain to us how an
individual with sound eyes and ears can, in broad daylight, see
and hear things that do not exist, or why another individual
suddenly believes himself persecuted by those whom up to that
time he loved best, or defend, with the most ingenious
arguments,
delusions which must seem nonsense to any child, then we will
be willing to consider psychoanalysis seriously. But if psycho-
analysis can do nothing better than to occupy us with the ques-
tion of why a speaker used the wrong word, or why a
housekeeper
mislaid her keys, or such trifles, then we know something better
to do with our time and interest."
My reply is: "Patience, ladies and gentlemen. I think your
criticism is not on the right track. It is true that psychoanalysis
cannot boast that it has never occupied itself with trifles. On
the contrary, the objects of its observations are generally those
simple occurrences which the other sciences have thrown aside
as much too insignificant, the waste products of the phenomenal
world. But are you not confounding, in your criticism, the
sublimity of the problems with the eonspicuousness of their
manifestations? Are there not very important things which
under certain circumstances, and at certain times, can betray
themselves only by very faint signs ? I could easily cite a great
many instances of this kind. From what vague signs, for in-
stance, do the young gentlemen of this audience conclude that
they have won the favor of a lady? Do you await an explicit
declaration, an ardent embrace, or does not a glance, scarcely
perceptible to others, a fleeting gesture, the prolonging of a
*" IW-leistungen."
12 Introduction to Psychoanalysis
hand-shake by one second, suffice? And if you are a criminal
lawyer, and engaged in the investigation of a murder, do you
actually expect the murderer to leave his photograph and
address
on the scene of the crime, or would you, of necessity, content
yourself with fainter and less certain traces of that individual ?
Therefore, let us not undervalue small signs; perhaps by means
of them we will succeed in getting on the track of greater
things.
I agree with you that the larger problems of the world and of
science have the first claim on our interest. But it is generally
of little avail to form the definite resolution to devote oneself to
the investigation of this or that problem. Often one does not
know in which direction to take the next step. In scientific
research it is more fruitful to attempt what happens to be before
one at the moment and for whose investigation there is a dis-
coverable method. If one does that thoroughly without prejudice
or predisposition, one may, with good fortune, and by virtue
of the connection which links each thing to every other (hence
also the small to the great) discover even from such modest
research a point of approach to the study of the big problems."
Thus would I answer, in order to secure your attention for
the consideration of these apparently insignificant errors made
by normal people. At this point, we will question a stranger to
psychoanalysis and ask him how he explains these occurrences.
His first answer is sure to be, "Oh, they are not worth an
explanation; they are merely slight accidents." What does he
mean by this? Does he mean to assert that there are any
occurrences so insignificant that they fall out of the causal
sequence of things, or that they might just as well be something
different from what they are ? If an^r one thus denies the deter-
mination of natural phenomena at one bach point, he has
vitiated
the entire scientific viewpoint. One can then point out to him
how much more consistent is the religious point of view, when
it explicitly asserts that "No sparrow falls from the roof
without God's special wish." I imagine our friend will not be
willing to follow his first answer to its logical conclusion; he
will interrupt and say that if he were to study these things
he would probably find an explanation for them. He will say
that this is a case of slight functional disturbance, of an in-
accurate psychic act whose eausal factors can be outlined. A
man
who otherwise speaks correctly may make a slip of the tongue—
*
The Psychology of Errors 13
when he is slightly ill or fatigued; when he is excited*
when his attention is concentrated on something else. It is
easy to prove these statements. Slips of the tongue do really
occur with special frequency when one is tired, when one has
a headache or when one is indisposed. Forgetting proper names
is a very frequent occurrence under these circumstances. Many
persons even recognize the imminence of an indisposition by
the
inability to recall proper names. Often also one mixes up words
or objects during excitement, one picks up the wrong things;
and the forgetting of projects, as well as the doing of any num-
ber of other unintentional acts, becomes conspicuous when one
is distracted; in other words, when one's attention is concen-
trated on other things. A familiar instance of such distraction
is the professor in Fliegende Blatter, who takes the wrong hat
because he is thinking of the problems which he wishes to treat
in his next book. Each of us knows from experience some ex-
amples of how one can forget projects which one has planned
and promises which one has made, because an experience has
intervened which has preoccupied one deeply.
This seems both comprehensible and irrefutable. It is perhaps
not very interesting, not as we expected it to be. But let us
consider this explanation of errors. The conditions which have
been cited as necessary for the occurrence of these phenomena
are not all identical. Illness and disorders of circulation afford
a physiological basis. Excitement, fatigue and distraction are
conditions of a different sort, which one could designate as
psycho-physiological. About these latter it is easy to theorize.
Fatigue, as well as distraction, and perhaps also general excite-
ment, cause a scattering of the attention which can result in the
act in progress not receiving sufficient attention. This act can
then be more easily interrupted than usual, and may be in-
exactly carried out. A slight illness, or a change in the distribu-
tion of blood in the central organ of the nervous system, can
have
the same effect, inasmuch as it influences the determining
factor,
the distribution of attention, in a similar way. In all eases,
therefore, it is a question of the effects of a distraction of the
attention, caused either by organic or psychic factors.
But this does not seem to yield much of interest for our
psychoanalytic investigation. We might even feel tempted to
give up the subject. To be sure, when we look more closely we
14 Introduction to Psychoanalysis
find that not everything squares with this attention theory of
psychological errors, or that at any rate not everything can be
directly deduced from it. We find that such errors and such
forgetting occur even when people are not fatigued, distracted
or excited, but are in every way in their normal state; unless,
in consequence of these errors, one were to attribute to them
an excitement which they themselves do not acknowledge. Nor
is the mechanism so simple that the success of an act is assured
by an intensification of the attention bestowed upon it, and
endangered by its diminution. There are many acts which one
performs in a purely automatic way and with very little atten-
tion, but which are yet carried out quite successfully. The
pedestrian who scarcely knows where he is going, nevertheless
keeps to the right road and stops at his destination without hav-
ing gone astray. At least, this is the rule. The practiced
pianist touches the right keys without thinking of them. He
may, of course, also make an occasional mistake, but if auto-
matic playing increased the likelihood of errors, it would be
just the virtuoso whose playing has, through practice, become
most automatic, who would be the most exposed to this danger.
Yet we see, on the contrary, that many acts are most
successfully
carried out when they are not the objects of particularly con-
centrated attention, and that the mistakes occur just at the
point where one is most anxious to be accurate—where a dis-
traction of the necessary attention is therefore surely least
permissible. One could then say that this is the effect of the
"excitement," but we do not understand why the excitement
does not intensify the concentration of attention on the goal
that is so much desired. If in an important speech or discus-
sion anyone says the opposite of what he means, then that can
hardly be explained according to the psycho-physiological or
the
attention theories.
There are also many other small phenomena accompanying
these errors, which are not understood and which have not been
rendered comprehensible to us by these explanations. For in-
stance, when one has temporarily forgotten a name, one is
annoyed, one is determined to recall it and is unable to give up
the attempt. "Why is it that despite his annoyance the indi-
vidual cannot succeed, as he wishes, in directing his attention
to the word which is "on the tip of his tongue," and which he
The Psychology of Errors 15
instantly recognizes when it is pronouneed to him? Or, to
take another example, there are cases in which the errors mul-
tiply, link themselves together, substitute for each other. The
first time one forgets an appointment; the next time, after
having
made a special resolution not to forget it, one discovers that one
has made a mistake in the day or hour. Or one tries by devious
means to remember a forgotten word, and in the course of so
doing loses track of a second name which would have been of
use in finding the first. If one then pursues this second name,
a third gets lost, and so on. It is notorious that the same thing
can happen in the ease of misprints, which are of oeurse to be
considered as errors of the typesetter. A stubborn error of this
sort is said to have crept into a Social-Democratic paper, where,
in the account of a certain festivity was printed, "Among those
present was His Highness, the Clown Prince." The next day
a correction was attempted. The paper apologized and said,
"The sentence should, of course, have read' The Clown Prince.'
"
One likes to attribute these occurrences to the printer's devil,
to the goblin of the typesetting machine, and the like — figura-
tive expressions which at least go beyond a psycho-
physiological
theory of the misprint.
I do not know if you are acquainted with the fact that one
can provoke slips of the tongue, can call them forth by sugges-
tion, as it were. An anecdote will serve to illustrate this. Once
when a novice on the stage was entrusted with the important
role in The Maid of Orleans of announcing to the King,'' Conne-
table sheathes his sword," the star played the joke of repeating
to the frightened beginner during the rehearsal, instead of the
text, the following, "Comfortable sends back his steed,"2 and
he attained his end. In the performance the unfortunate actor
actually made his debut with this distorted announcement; even
after he had been amply warned against so doing, or perhaps
just for that reason.
These little characteristics of errors are not exactly illuminated
by the theory of diverted attention. But that does not neces-
sarily prove the whole theory wrong. There is perhaps some-
thing missing, a complement by the addition of which the theory
2 In the German, the correct announcement is, tf Connetable
schickt sein
Bchwert zuriiek." The novice, as a result of the suggestion,
announced
instead that " Komfortabel schickt sein Pferd zuriiek."
16 Introduction to Psychoanalysis
would be made completely satisfactory. But many of the errors
themselves can be regarded from another aspect.
Let us select slips of the tongue, as best suited to our purposes.
"We might equally well choose slips of the pen or of reading.
But at this point, we must make clear to ourselves the fact that
so far we have inquired only as to when and under what con-
ditions one's tongue slips, and have received an answer on this
point only. One can, however, direct one's interest elsewhere
and ask why one makes just this particular slip and no other;
one can consider what the slip results in. You must realize that
as long as one does not answer this question—does not explain
the effect produced by the slip—the phenomenon in its psycho-
logical aspect remains an accident, even if its physiological ex-
planation has been found. When it happens that I commit a
slip of the tongue, I could obviously make any one of an in-
finite number of slips, and in place of the one right word say
any one of a thousand others, make innumerable distortions of
the right word. Now, is there anything which forces upon me in
a specific instance just this one special slip out of all those
which are possible, or does that remain accidental and arbitrary,
and can nothing rational be found in answer to this question ?
Two authors, Meringer and Mayer (a philologist and a psychi-
atrist) did indeed in 1895 make the attempt to approach the
problem of slips of the tongue from this side. They collected
examples and first treated them from a purely descriptive stand-
point. That, of course, does not yet furnish any explanation, but
may open the way to one. They differentiated the distortions
which the intended phrase suffered through the slip, into: inter-
changes of positions of words, interchanges of parts of words,
perseverations, compoundings and substitutions. I will give
you examples of these authors' main categories. It is a case of
interchange of the first sort if someone says "the Milo of
Venus"
instead of "the Venus of Milo." An example of the second
type of interchange, " I had a blush of rood to the head" instead
of "rush of blood"; a perseveration would be the familiar mis-
placed toast, " I ask you to join me in hiccoughing the health
of our chief."8 These three forms of slips are not very frequent.
You will find those cases much more frequent in which the slip
results from a drawing together or compounding of syllables ,•
•"Aufstossen" instead of " anstossen."
The Psychology of Errors 17
for example, a gentleman on the street addresses a lady with
the words, " I f you will allow me, madame, I should be very
glad to inscort you."* In the compounded word there is ob-
viously besides the word "escort," also the word "insult" (and
parenthetically we may remark that the young man will not find
much favor with the lady). As an example of the substitution,
Meringer and Mayer cite the following: " A man says, ' I put
the specimens in the letterbox,' instead of 'in the hot-bed,' and
the like."6
The explanation which the two authors attempt to formulate
on the basis of this collection of examples is peculiarly inade-
quate. They hold that the sounds and syllables of words have
different values, and that the production and perception of
more highly valued syllables can interfere with those of lower
values. They obviously base this conclusion on the cases of
fore-
sounding and perseveration which are not at all frequent; in
other cases of slips of the tongue the question of such sound
priorities, if any exist, does not enter at all. The most frequent
cases of slips of the tongue are those in which instead of a cer-
tain word one says another which resembles it; and one may
consider this resemblance sufficient explanation. For example,
a professor says in his initial lecture, " I am not inclined to
evaluate the merits of my predecessor."6 Or another professor
says, " I n the case of the female genital, despite many tempta-
tions . . . I mean many attempts . . . etc."7
The most common, and also the most conspicuous form of
slips of the tongue, however, is that of saying the exact opposite
of what one meant to say. In such cases, one goes far afield
from the problem of sound relations and resemblance effects,
and can cite, instead of these, the fact that opposites have an
obviously close relationship to each other, and have particularly
close relations in the psychology of association. There are his*
torical examples of this sort. A president of our House of Eep-
resentatives once opened the assembly with the words, "Gentle*
men, I declare a quorum present, and herewith declare thG
assembly closed."
*"Begleit-digen" compounded of "begleiten" and "beleidigen."
U( Briefkasten" instead of ' ' Briitkasten."
ct< Geneigt " instead of " geeignet."
*' * Versuchungen ' ' instead of ' ' Versuche.''
f 8 Introduction to Psychoanalysis
Similar, in its trickiness, to the relation of opposites is the
effect of any other facile association which may under certain
circumstances arise most inopportunely. Thus, for instance,
there is the story which relates that on the occasion of a
festivity
in honor of the marriage of a child of H. Helmholtz with a
child of the well-known discoverer and captain of industry,
W. Siemon, the famous physiologist Dubois-Reymond was
asked
to speak. He concluded his undoubtedly sparkling toast with
the words, "Success to the new firm—Siemens and—Halskit"
That, of course, was the name of the well-known old firm. The
association of the two names must have been about as easy for
a native of Berlin as "Weber and Fields" to an American.
Thus we must add to the sound relations and word resem-
blances the influence of word associations. But that is not all.
In a series of cases, an explanation of the observed slip is un-
successful unless we take into account what phrase had been
said or even thought previously. This again makes it a case of
perseveration of the sort stressed by Meringer, but of a longer
duration. I must admit, I am on the whole of the impression
that we are further than ever from an explanation of slips of
the tongue!
However, I hope I am not wrong when I say that during the
above investigation of these examples of slips of the tongue, we
have all obtained a new impression on which it will be of value
to dwell. "We sought the general conditions under which slips
of the tongue occur, and then the influences which determine
the kind of distortion resulting from the slip, but we have in
no way yet considered the effect of the slip of the tongue in
itself, without regard to its origin. And if we should decide
to do so we must finally have the courage to assert, " I n some
of the examples cited, the product of the slip also makes sense."
What do we mean by " i t makes sense"? It means, I think, that
the product of the slip has itself a right to be considered as a
valid psychic act which also has its purpose, as a manifestation
having content and meaning. Hitherto we have always spoken
of errors, but now it seems as if sometimes the error itself were
quite a normal act, except that it has thrust itself into the place
of some other expected or intended act.
In isolated cases this valid meaning seems obvious and unmis-
takable. When the president with his opening words closes the
The Psychology of Errors 19
session of the House of Representatives, instead of opening it,
we
are inclined to consider this error meaningful by reason of our
knowledge of the circumstances under which the slip occurred.
He expects no good of the assembly, and would be glad if he
could terminate it immediately. The pointing out of this mean-
ing, the interpretation of this error, gives us no difficulty. Or a
lady, pretending to admire, says to another, " I am sure you
must have messed up this charming hat yourself.' '8 No
scientific
quibbles in the world can keep us from discovering in this slip
the idea "this hat is a mess." Or a lady who is known for her
energetic disposition, relates, "My husband asked the doctor to
what diet he should keep. But the doctor said he didn 't need
any
diet, he should eat and drink whatever I want." This slip of
tongue is quite an unmistakable expression of a consistent
purpose.
Ladies and gentlemen, if it should turn out that not only a
few cases of slips of the tongue and of errors in general, but
the larger part of them, have a meaning, then this meaning of
errors of which we have hitherto made no mention, will un-
avoidably become of the greatest interest to us and will, with
justice, force all other points of view into the background. We
could then ignore all physiological and psycho-physiological
con-
ditions and devote ourselves to the purely psychological investi-
gations of the sense, that is, the meaning, the purpose of these
errors. To this end therefore we will not fail, shortly, to study
a more extensive compilation of material.
But before we undertake this task, I should like to invite you
to follow another line of thought with me. It has repeatedly
happened that a poet has made use of slips of the tongue or
some other error as a means of poetic presentation. This fact
in itself must prove to us that he considers the error, the slip
of the tongue for instance, as meaningful; for he creates it on
purpose, and it is not a case of the poet committing an acci-
dental slip of the pen and then letting his pen-slip stand as a
tongue-slip of his character. He wants to make something clear
to us by this slip of the tongue, and we may examine what it is,
whether he wishes to indicate by this that the person in question
is distracted or fatigued. Of course, we do not wish to exagger-
ate the importance of the fact that the poet did mak$ use of
•*' Aufgepatzt " instead of " aufgeputrit."
20 Introduction to Psychoanalysis
a slip to express his meaning. It could nevertheless really be a
psychic accident, or meaningful only in very rare cases, and
the poet would still retain the right to infuse it with meaning
through his setting. As to their poetic use, however, it would
not be surprising if we should glean more information concern-
ing slips of the tongue from the poet than from the philologist
or the psychiatrist.
Such an example of a slip of the tongue occurs in Wallenstein
{Piccolomini, Act 1, Scene 5). In the previous scene, Max Pic-
colomini has most passionately sided with the Herzog, and
dilated
ardently on the blessings of peace which disclosed themselves
to him during the trip on which he accompanied Wallenstein's
daughter to the camp. He leaves his father and the courtier,
Questenberg, plunged in deepest consternation. And then the
fifth scene continues:
Q.
Alas! Alas! and stands it so ?
What friend! and do we let him go away
In this delusion—let him go away ?
Not call him back immediately, not open
His eyes upon the spot ?
OCTAVIO.
{Recovering himself out of a deep study)
He has now opened mine,
And I see more than pleases me.
Q.
What is it?
OCTAVIO.
A curse on this journey!
Q.
But why so ? What is it ?
OCTAVIO.
Come, come along, friend! I must follow up
The ominous track immediately. Mine eyes
Are opened now, and I must use them. Come!
(Draws Q. on with him.)
Q-
What now ? Wh ere go you then ?
The Psychology of Errors 21
OCTAVIO.
(Hastily.) To her herself
To—
OCTAVIO.
(Interrupting him and correcting himself.)
To the duke. Come, let us go—.
Octavio meant to say, "To him, to the lord," but his tongue
Blips and through his words "to her" he betrays to us, at least,
the fact that he had quite clearly recognized the influence which
makes the young war hero dream of peace.
A still more impressive example was found by 0 . Bank in
Shakespeare. It occurs in the Merchant of Venice, in the famous
scene in which the fortunate suitor makes his choice among the
three caskets; and perhaps I can do no better than to read to you
here Rank's short account of the incident:
" A slip of the tongue which occurs in Shakespeare's Merchant
of Venice, Act III, Scene II, is exceedingly delicate in its poetic
motivation and technically brilliant in its handling. Like the
slip in Wallenstein quoted by Freud (Psychopathology of
Everyday Life, 2d ed., p. 48), it shows that the poets well
know the meaning of these errors and assume their compre-
hensibility to the audience. Portia, who by her father's wish
has been bound to the choice of a husband by lot, has so far
escaped all her unfavored suitors through the fortunes of
chance.
Since she has finally found in Bassanio the suitor to whom she
is attached, she fears that he, too, will choose the wrong casket.
She would like to tell him that even in that event he may rest
assured of her love, but is prevented from so doing by her oath.
In this inner conflict the poet makes her say to the welcome
suitor:
PORTIA :
I pray you tarry; pause a day or two,
Before you hazard; for, in choosing wrong
I lose your company; therefore, forbear a while:
There's something tells me, (but it is not love)
I would not lose you: * * *
• * * I could teach you
How to choose right, but then I am forsworn,
22 Introduction to Psychoanalysis
So will I never be: so may you miss me ;
But if you do, you 11 make me wish, a sin
That I had been forsworn. Beshrew your eyes.
They have o'erlook'd me, and divided me;
One half of me is yours, the other half yours,
Mine own, I would say: but if mine, then yours,
And so all yours.
Just that, therefore, which she meant merely to indicate faintly
to him or really to conceal from him entirely, namely that even
before the choice of the lot she was his and loved him, this the
poet—with admirable psychological delicacy of feeling—makes
apparent by her slip; and is able, by this artistic device, to quiet
the unbearable uncertainty of the lover, as well as the equal sus-
pense of the audience as to the issue of the choice."
Notice, at the end, how subtly Portia reconciles the two decla-
rations which are contained in the slip, how she resolves the
contradiction between them and finally still manages to keep
her
promise:
<<# # # k ^ ^ m j n e > then yours,
And so all yours."
Another thinker, alien to the field of medicine, accidentally
disclosed the meaning of errors by an observation which has
anticipated our attempts at explanation. You all know the clever
satires of Lichtenberg (1742-1749), of which Goethe said, *'
Where
he jokes, there lurks a problem concealed." Not infrequently
the joke also brings to light the solution of the problem.
Lichten-
berg mentions in his jokes and satiric comments the remark that
he always read "Agamemnon" for "angenomen,"9 so intently
had he read Homer. Herein is really contained the whole theory
of misreadings.
At the next session we will see whether we can agree with the
poets in their conception of the meaning of psychological
errors.
•*' Angenomen " is a verb, meaning " to aecepK"
PROJECT #3RETAIL LOCATIONSInstructions1. In an Word d.docx

More Related Content

Similar to PROJECT #3RETAIL LOCATIONSInstructions1. In an Word d.docx

General Quotes For Essays.pdf
General Quotes For Essays.pdfGeneral Quotes For Essays.pdf
General Quotes For Essays.pdfTrina Locklear
 
Hist Over Psych Anth S10
Hist Over Psych Anth S10Hist Over Psych Anth S10
Hist Over Psych Anth S10cherrybloosom89
 
On Clinical Techniques in Freud and Lacan, Clinical Notes Series
On Clinical Techniques in Freud and Lacan, Clinical Notes SeriesOn Clinical Techniques in Freud and Lacan, Clinical Notes Series
On Clinical Techniques in Freud and Lacan, Clinical Notes SeriesShiva Kumar Srinivasan
 
On Lacanian Literary Criticism (October 2016)
On Lacanian Literary Criticism (October 2016)On Lacanian Literary Criticism (October 2016)
On Lacanian Literary Criticism (October 2016)Shiva Kumar Srinivasan
 
Paul Schimmel (2014). Sigmund Freud’s Discovery of Psychoanalysis: Conquistad...
Paul Schimmel (2014). Sigmund Freud’s Discovery of Psychoanalysis: Conquistad...Paul Schimmel (2014). Sigmund Freud’s Discovery of Psychoanalysis: Conquistad...
Paul Schimmel (2014). Sigmund Freud’s Discovery of Psychoanalysis: Conquistad...iosrjce
 
Article One Hundred Years After Sigmund Freud S Lectures In America Towards ...
Article One Hundred Years After Sigmund Freud S Lectures In America  Towards ...Article One Hundred Years After Sigmund Freud S Lectures In America  Towards ...
Article One Hundred Years After Sigmund Freud S Lectures In America Towards ...Sophia Diaz
 
Why have the Loyalists largely been forgotten in history  Do you .docx
Why have the Loyalists largely been forgotten in history  Do you .docxWhy have the Loyalists largely been forgotten in history  Do you .docx
Why have the Loyalists largely been forgotten in history  Do you .docxalanfhall8953
 
Psychology module 2
Psychology module 2Psychology module 2
Psychology module 2asuncion
 
Psychology module 2
Psychology module 2Psychology module 2
Psychology module 2asuncion
 
Prominent person during the period of 1600 ad
Prominent person during the period of 1600 adProminent person during the period of 1600 ad
Prominent person during the period of 1600 adMonica Belarte
 
Carl Jung y la Parapsicología
Carl Jung y la ParapsicologíaCarl Jung y la Parapsicología
Carl Jung y la Parapsicologíasocialsciences
 
How To Write A Excellent Essay
How To Write A Excellent EssayHow To Write A Excellent Essay
How To Write A Excellent EssayJessica Baker
 
Sigmund Freud's Autobiographical Study
Sigmund Freud's Autobiographical StudySigmund Freud's Autobiographical Study
Sigmund Freud's Autobiographical StudyShiva Kumar Srinivasan
 
Jung parapsicologia-091203114944-phpapp01
Jung parapsicologia-091203114944-phpapp01Jung parapsicologia-091203114944-phpapp01
Jung parapsicologia-091203114944-phpapp01Jordi Garrigosa Ayuso
 
A history of_philosophy_in_america_1720-2000
A history of_philosophy_in_america_1720-2000A history of_philosophy_in_america_1720-2000
A history of_philosophy_in_america_1720-2000Vinalle Francois
 
Man's Search for Meaning- Viktor E. Frankl.pdf
Man's Search for Meaning- Viktor E. Frankl.pdfMan's Search for Meaning- Viktor E. Frankl.pdf
Man's Search for Meaning- Viktor E. Frankl.pdfJohnReymerSaplan1
 

Similar to PROJECT #3RETAIL LOCATIONSInstructions1. In an Word d.docx (17)

General Quotes For Essays.pdf
General Quotes For Essays.pdfGeneral Quotes For Essays.pdf
General Quotes For Essays.pdf
 
Hist Over Psych Anth S10
Hist Over Psych Anth S10Hist Over Psych Anth S10
Hist Over Psych Anth S10
 
On Clinical Techniques in Freud and Lacan, Clinical Notes Series
On Clinical Techniques in Freud and Lacan, Clinical Notes SeriesOn Clinical Techniques in Freud and Lacan, Clinical Notes Series
On Clinical Techniques in Freud and Lacan, Clinical Notes Series
 
On Lacanian Literary Criticism (October 2016)
On Lacanian Literary Criticism (October 2016)On Lacanian Literary Criticism (October 2016)
On Lacanian Literary Criticism (October 2016)
 
Paul Schimmel (2014). Sigmund Freud’s Discovery of Psychoanalysis: Conquistad...
Paul Schimmel (2014). Sigmund Freud’s Discovery of Psychoanalysis: Conquistad...Paul Schimmel (2014). Sigmund Freud’s Discovery of Psychoanalysis: Conquistad...
Paul Schimmel (2014). Sigmund Freud’s Discovery of Psychoanalysis: Conquistad...
 
Article One Hundred Years After Sigmund Freud S Lectures In America Towards ...
Article One Hundred Years After Sigmund Freud S Lectures In America  Towards ...Article One Hundred Years After Sigmund Freud S Lectures In America  Towards ...
Article One Hundred Years After Sigmund Freud S Lectures In America Towards ...
 
Why have the Loyalists largely been forgotten in history  Do you .docx
Why have the Loyalists largely been forgotten in history  Do you .docxWhy have the Loyalists largely been forgotten in history  Do you .docx
Why have the Loyalists largely been forgotten in history  Do you .docx
 
Psychology module 2
Psychology module 2Psychology module 2
Psychology module 2
 
Psychology module 2
Psychology module 2Psychology module 2
Psychology module 2
 
Prominent person during the period of 1600 ad
Prominent person during the period of 1600 adProminent person during the period of 1600 ad
Prominent person during the period of 1600 ad
 
Carl Jung y la Parapsicología
Carl Jung y la ParapsicologíaCarl Jung y la Parapsicología
Carl Jung y la Parapsicología
 
How To Write A Excellent Essay
How To Write A Excellent EssayHow To Write A Excellent Essay
How To Write A Excellent Essay
 
Sigmund Freud's Autobiographical Study
Sigmund Freud's Autobiographical StudySigmund Freud's Autobiographical Study
Sigmund Freud's Autobiographical Study
 
Jung parapsicologia-091203114944-phpapp01
Jung parapsicologia-091203114944-phpapp01Jung parapsicologia-091203114944-phpapp01
Jung parapsicologia-091203114944-phpapp01
 
A history of_philosophy_in_america_1720-2000
A history of_philosophy_in_america_1720-2000A history of_philosophy_in_america_1720-2000
A history of_philosophy_in_america_1720-2000
 
Western Literature on Stupidity Reviewed
Western Literature on Stupidity ReviewedWestern Literature on Stupidity Reviewed
Western Literature on Stupidity Reviewed
 
Man's Search for Meaning- Viktor E. Frankl.pdf
Man's Search for Meaning- Viktor E. Frankl.pdfMan's Search for Meaning- Viktor E. Frankl.pdf
Man's Search for Meaning- Viktor E. Frankl.pdf
 

More from briancrawford30935

You have collected the following documents (unstructured) and pl.docx
You have collected the following documents (unstructured) and pl.docxYou have collected the following documents (unstructured) and pl.docx
You have collected the following documents (unstructured) and pl.docxbriancrawford30935
 
You have been working as a technology associate the information .docx
You have been working as a technology associate the information .docxYou have been working as a technology associate the information .docx
You have been working as a technology associate the information .docxbriancrawford30935
 
You have chosen to join WHO. They are particularly interested in.docx
You have chosen to join WHO. They are particularly interested in.docxYou have chosen to join WHO. They are particularly interested in.docx
You have chosen to join WHO. They are particularly interested in.docxbriancrawford30935
 
You have been tasked to present at a town hall meeting in your local.docx
You have been tasked to present at a town hall meeting in your local.docxYou have been tasked to present at a town hall meeting in your local.docx
You have been tasked to present at a town hall meeting in your local.docxbriancrawford30935
 
You have been tasked as the health care administrator of a major hos.docx
You have been tasked as the health care administrator of a major hos.docxYou have been tasked as the health care administrator of a major hos.docx
You have been tasked as the health care administrator of a major hos.docxbriancrawford30935
 
You have been tasked to devise a program to address the needs of.docx
You have been tasked to devise a program to address the needs of.docxYou have been tasked to devise a program to address the needs of.docx
You have been tasked to devise a program to address the needs of.docxbriancrawford30935
 
You have been successful in your application for the position be.docx
You have been successful in your application for the position be.docxYou have been successful in your application for the position be.docx
You have been successful in your application for the position be.docxbriancrawford30935
 
You have been hired as a project management consultant by compan.docx
You have been hired as a project management consultant by compan.docxYou have been hired as a project management consultant by compan.docx
You have been hired as a project management consultant by compan.docxbriancrawford30935
 
You have been hired to manage a particular aspect of the new ad.docx
You have been hired to manage a particular aspect of the new ad.docxYou have been hired to manage a particular aspect of the new ad.docx
You have been hired to manage a particular aspect of the new ad.docxbriancrawford30935
 
You have been hired by Red Didgeridoo Technologies. They know th.docx
You have been hired by Red Didgeridoo Technologies. They know th.docxYou have been hired by Red Didgeridoo Technologies. They know th.docx
You have been hired by Red Didgeridoo Technologies. They know th.docxbriancrawford30935
 
You have been hired by TMI to design an application using shell scri.docx
You have been hired by TMI to design an application using shell scri.docxYou have been hired by TMI to design an application using shell scri.docx
You have been hired by TMI to design an application using shell scri.docxbriancrawford30935
 
You have been hired as the CSO (Chief Security Officer) for an org.docx
You have been hired as the CSO (Chief Security Officer) for an org.docxYou have been hired as the CSO (Chief Security Officer) for an org.docx
You have been hired as the CSO (Chief Security Officer) for an org.docxbriancrawford30935
 
You have been hired to evaluate the volcanic hazards associated .docx
You have been hired to evaluate the volcanic hazards associated .docxYou have been hired to evaluate the volcanic hazards associated .docx
You have been hired to evaluate the volcanic hazards associated .docxbriancrawford30935
 
You have been hired as an assistant to the public health officer for.docx
You have been hired as an assistant to the public health officer for.docxYou have been hired as an assistant to the public health officer for.docx
You have been hired as an assistant to the public health officer for.docxbriancrawford30935
 
You have been engaged to develop a special calculator program. T.docx
You have been engaged to develop a special calculator program. T.docxYou have been engaged to develop a special calculator program. T.docx
You have been engaged to develop a special calculator program. T.docxbriancrawford30935
 
You have now delivered the project to your customer ahead of schedul.docx
You have now delivered the project to your customer ahead of schedul.docxYou have now delivered the project to your customer ahead of schedul.docx
You have now delivered the project to your customer ahead of schedul.docxbriancrawford30935
 
You have now delivered the project to your customer. The project was.docx
You have now delivered the project to your customer. The project was.docxYou have now delivered the project to your customer. The project was.docx
You have now delivered the project to your customer. The project was.docxbriancrawford30935
 
You have now experienced the work of various scholars, artists and m.docx
You have now experienced the work of various scholars, artists and m.docxYou have now experienced the work of various scholars, artists and m.docx
You have now experienced the work of various scholars, artists and m.docxbriancrawford30935
 
You have learned that Mr. Moore does not drink alcohol in the mornin.docx
You have learned that Mr. Moore does not drink alcohol in the mornin.docxYou have learned that Mr. Moore does not drink alcohol in the mornin.docx
You have learned that Mr. Moore does not drink alcohol in the mornin.docxbriancrawford30935
 
You have been hired by a large hospitality firm (e.g., Marriot.docx
You have been hired by a large hospitality firm (e.g., Marriot.docxYou have been hired by a large hospitality firm (e.g., Marriot.docx
You have been hired by a large hospitality firm (e.g., Marriot.docxbriancrawford30935
 

More from briancrawford30935 (20)

You have collected the following documents (unstructured) and pl.docx
You have collected the following documents (unstructured) and pl.docxYou have collected the following documents (unstructured) and pl.docx
You have collected the following documents (unstructured) and pl.docx
 
You have been working as a technology associate the information .docx
You have been working as a technology associate the information .docxYou have been working as a technology associate the information .docx
You have been working as a technology associate the information .docx
 
You have chosen to join WHO. They are particularly interested in.docx
You have chosen to join WHO. They are particularly interested in.docxYou have chosen to join WHO. They are particularly interested in.docx
You have chosen to join WHO. They are particularly interested in.docx
 
You have been tasked to present at a town hall meeting in your local.docx
You have been tasked to present at a town hall meeting in your local.docxYou have been tasked to present at a town hall meeting in your local.docx
You have been tasked to present at a town hall meeting in your local.docx
 
You have been tasked as the health care administrator of a major hos.docx
You have been tasked as the health care administrator of a major hos.docxYou have been tasked as the health care administrator of a major hos.docx
You have been tasked as the health care administrator of a major hos.docx
 
You have been tasked to devise a program to address the needs of.docx
You have been tasked to devise a program to address the needs of.docxYou have been tasked to devise a program to address the needs of.docx
You have been tasked to devise a program to address the needs of.docx
 
You have been successful in your application for the position be.docx
You have been successful in your application for the position be.docxYou have been successful in your application for the position be.docx
You have been successful in your application for the position be.docx
 
You have been hired as a project management consultant by compan.docx
You have been hired as a project management consultant by compan.docxYou have been hired as a project management consultant by compan.docx
You have been hired as a project management consultant by compan.docx
 
You have been hired to manage a particular aspect of the new ad.docx
You have been hired to manage a particular aspect of the new ad.docxYou have been hired to manage a particular aspect of the new ad.docx
You have been hired to manage a particular aspect of the new ad.docx
 
You have been hired by Red Didgeridoo Technologies. They know th.docx
You have been hired by Red Didgeridoo Technologies. They know th.docxYou have been hired by Red Didgeridoo Technologies. They know th.docx
You have been hired by Red Didgeridoo Technologies. They know th.docx
 
You have been hired by TMI to design an application using shell scri.docx
You have been hired by TMI to design an application using shell scri.docxYou have been hired by TMI to design an application using shell scri.docx
You have been hired by TMI to design an application using shell scri.docx
 
You have been hired as the CSO (Chief Security Officer) for an org.docx
You have been hired as the CSO (Chief Security Officer) for an org.docxYou have been hired as the CSO (Chief Security Officer) for an org.docx
You have been hired as the CSO (Chief Security Officer) for an org.docx
 
You have been hired to evaluate the volcanic hazards associated .docx
You have been hired to evaluate the volcanic hazards associated .docxYou have been hired to evaluate the volcanic hazards associated .docx
You have been hired to evaluate the volcanic hazards associated .docx
 
You have been hired as an assistant to the public health officer for.docx
You have been hired as an assistant to the public health officer for.docxYou have been hired as an assistant to the public health officer for.docx
You have been hired as an assistant to the public health officer for.docx
 
You have been engaged to develop a special calculator program. T.docx
You have been engaged to develop a special calculator program. T.docxYou have been engaged to develop a special calculator program. T.docx
You have been engaged to develop a special calculator program. T.docx
 
You have now delivered the project to your customer ahead of schedul.docx
You have now delivered the project to your customer ahead of schedul.docxYou have now delivered the project to your customer ahead of schedul.docx
You have now delivered the project to your customer ahead of schedul.docx
 
You have now delivered the project to your customer. The project was.docx
You have now delivered the project to your customer. The project was.docxYou have now delivered the project to your customer. The project was.docx
You have now delivered the project to your customer. The project was.docx
 
You have now experienced the work of various scholars, artists and m.docx
You have now experienced the work of various scholars, artists and m.docxYou have now experienced the work of various scholars, artists and m.docx
You have now experienced the work of various scholars, artists and m.docx
 
You have learned that Mr. Moore does not drink alcohol in the mornin.docx
You have learned that Mr. Moore does not drink alcohol in the mornin.docxYou have learned that Mr. Moore does not drink alcohol in the mornin.docx
You have learned that Mr. Moore does not drink alcohol in the mornin.docx
 
You have been hired by a large hospitality firm (e.g., Marriot.docx
You have been hired by a large hospitality firm (e.g., Marriot.docxYou have been hired by a large hospitality firm (e.g., Marriot.docx
You have been hired by a large hospitality firm (e.g., Marriot.docx
 

Recently uploaded

Solving Puzzles Benefits Everyone (English).pptx
Solving Puzzles Benefits Everyone (English).pptxSolving Puzzles Benefits Everyone (English).pptx
Solving Puzzles Benefits Everyone (English).pptxOH TEIK BIN
 
Capitol Tech U Doctoral Presentation - April 2024.pptx
Capitol Tech U Doctoral Presentation - April 2024.pptxCapitol Tech U Doctoral Presentation - April 2024.pptx
Capitol Tech U Doctoral Presentation - April 2024.pptxCapitolTechU
 
Painted Grey Ware.pptx, PGW Culture of India
Painted Grey Ware.pptx, PGW Culture of IndiaPainted Grey Ware.pptx, PGW Culture of India
Painted Grey Ware.pptx, PGW Culture of IndiaVirag Sontakke
 
Hierarchy of management that covers different levels of management
Hierarchy of management that covers different levels of managementHierarchy of management that covers different levels of management
Hierarchy of management that covers different levels of managementmkooblal
 
ECONOMIC CONTEXT - LONG FORM TV DRAMA - PPT
ECONOMIC CONTEXT - LONG FORM TV DRAMA - PPTECONOMIC CONTEXT - LONG FORM TV DRAMA - PPT
ECONOMIC CONTEXT - LONG FORM TV DRAMA - PPTiammrhaywood
 
DATA STRUCTURE AND ALGORITHM for beginners
DATA STRUCTURE AND ALGORITHM for beginnersDATA STRUCTURE AND ALGORITHM for beginners
DATA STRUCTURE AND ALGORITHM for beginnersSabitha Banu
 
Introduction to ArtificiaI Intelligence in Higher Education
Introduction to ArtificiaI Intelligence in Higher EducationIntroduction to ArtificiaI Intelligence in Higher Education
Introduction to ArtificiaI Intelligence in Higher Educationpboyjonauth
 
ENGLISH 7_Q4_LESSON 2_ Employing a Variety of Strategies for Effective Interp...
ENGLISH 7_Q4_LESSON 2_ Employing a Variety of Strategies for Effective Interp...ENGLISH 7_Q4_LESSON 2_ Employing a Variety of Strategies for Effective Interp...
ENGLISH 7_Q4_LESSON 2_ Employing a Variety of Strategies for Effective Interp...JhezDiaz1
 
Procuring digital preservation CAN be quick and painless with our new dynamic...
Procuring digital preservation CAN be quick and painless with our new dynamic...Procuring digital preservation CAN be quick and painless with our new dynamic...
Procuring digital preservation CAN be quick and painless with our new dynamic...Jisc
 
Presiding Officer Training module 2024 lok sabha elections
Presiding Officer Training module 2024 lok sabha electionsPresiding Officer Training module 2024 lok sabha elections
Presiding Officer Training module 2024 lok sabha electionsanshu789521
 
Types of Journalistic Writing Grade 8.pptx
Types of Journalistic Writing Grade 8.pptxTypes of Journalistic Writing Grade 8.pptx
Types of Journalistic Writing Grade 8.pptxEyham Joco
 
Full Stack Web Development Course for Beginners
Full Stack Web Development Course  for BeginnersFull Stack Web Development Course  for Beginners
Full Stack Web Development Course for BeginnersSabitha Banu
 
POINT- BIOCHEMISTRY SEM 2 ENZYMES UNIT 5.pptx
POINT- BIOCHEMISTRY SEM 2 ENZYMES UNIT 5.pptxPOINT- BIOCHEMISTRY SEM 2 ENZYMES UNIT 5.pptx
POINT- BIOCHEMISTRY SEM 2 ENZYMES UNIT 5.pptxSayali Powar
 
“Oh GOSH! Reflecting on Hackteria's Collaborative Practices in a Global Do-It...
“Oh GOSH! Reflecting on Hackteria's Collaborative Practices in a Global Do-It...“Oh GOSH! Reflecting on Hackteria's Collaborative Practices in a Global Do-It...
“Oh GOSH! Reflecting on Hackteria's Collaborative Practices in a Global Do-It...Marc Dusseiller Dusjagr
 
Employee wellbeing at the workplace.pptx
Employee wellbeing at the workplace.pptxEmployee wellbeing at the workplace.pptx
Employee wellbeing at the workplace.pptxNirmalaLoungPoorunde1
 
AmericanHighSchoolsprezentacijaoskolama.
AmericanHighSchoolsprezentacijaoskolama.AmericanHighSchoolsprezentacijaoskolama.
AmericanHighSchoolsprezentacijaoskolama.arsicmarija21
 
Computed Fields and api Depends in the Odoo 17
Computed Fields and api Depends in the Odoo 17Computed Fields and api Depends in the Odoo 17
Computed Fields and api Depends in the Odoo 17Celine George
 
Enzyme, Pharmaceutical Aids, Miscellaneous Last Part of Chapter no 5th.pdf
Enzyme, Pharmaceutical Aids, Miscellaneous Last Part of Chapter no 5th.pdfEnzyme, Pharmaceutical Aids, Miscellaneous Last Part of Chapter no 5th.pdf
Enzyme, Pharmaceutical Aids, Miscellaneous Last Part of Chapter no 5th.pdfSumit Tiwari
 

Recently uploaded (20)

Solving Puzzles Benefits Everyone (English).pptx
Solving Puzzles Benefits Everyone (English).pptxSolving Puzzles Benefits Everyone (English).pptx
Solving Puzzles Benefits Everyone (English).pptx
 
Capitol Tech U Doctoral Presentation - April 2024.pptx
Capitol Tech U Doctoral Presentation - April 2024.pptxCapitol Tech U Doctoral Presentation - April 2024.pptx
Capitol Tech U Doctoral Presentation - April 2024.pptx
 
Painted Grey Ware.pptx, PGW Culture of India
Painted Grey Ware.pptx, PGW Culture of IndiaPainted Grey Ware.pptx, PGW Culture of India
Painted Grey Ware.pptx, PGW Culture of India
 
Hierarchy of management that covers different levels of management
Hierarchy of management that covers different levels of managementHierarchy of management that covers different levels of management
Hierarchy of management that covers different levels of management
 
ECONOMIC CONTEXT - LONG FORM TV DRAMA - PPT
ECONOMIC CONTEXT - LONG FORM TV DRAMA - PPTECONOMIC CONTEXT - LONG FORM TV DRAMA - PPT
ECONOMIC CONTEXT - LONG FORM TV DRAMA - PPT
 
DATA STRUCTURE AND ALGORITHM for beginners
DATA STRUCTURE AND ALGORITHM for beginnersDATA STRUCTURE AND ALGORITHM for beginners
DATA STRUCTURE AND ALGORITHM for beginners
 
Introduction to ArtificiaI Intelligence in Higher Education
Introduction to ArtificiaI Intelligence in Higher EducationIntroduction to ArtificiaI Intelligence in Higher Education
Introduction to ArtificiaI Intelligence in Higher Education
 
ENGLISH 7_Q4_LESSON 2_ Employing a Variety of Strategies for Effective Interp...
ENGLISH 7_Q4_LESSON 2_ Employing a Variety of Strategies for Effective Interp...ENGLISH 7_Q4_LESSON 2_ Employing a Variety of Strategies for Effective Interp...
ENGLISH 7_Q4_LESSON 2_ Employing a Variety of Strategies for Effective Interp...
 
Procuring digital preservation CAN be quick and painless with our new dynamic...
Procuring digital preservation CAN be quick and painless with our new dynamic...Procuring digital preservation CAN be quick and painless with our new dynamic...
Procuring digital preservation CAN be quick and painless with our new dynamic...
 
Presiding Officer Training module 2024 lok sabha elections
Presiding Officer Training module 2024 lok sabha electionsPresiding Officer Training module 2024 lok sabha elections
Presiding Officer Training module 2024 lok sabha elections
 
ESSENTIAL of (CS/IT/IS) class 06 (database)
ESSENTIAL of (CS/IT/IS) class 06 (database)ESSENTIAL of (CS/IT/IS) class 06 (database)
ESSENTIAL of (CS/IT/IS) class 06 (database)
 
Types of Journalistic Writing Grade 8.pptx
Types of Journalistic Writing Grade 8.pptxTypes of Journalistic Writing Grade 8.pptx
Types of Journalistic Writing Grade 8.pptx
 
Full Stack Web Development Course for Beginners
Full Stack Web Development Course  for BeginnersFull Stack Web Development Course  for Beginners
Full Stack Web Development Course for Beginners
 
POINT- BIOCHEMISTRY SEM 2 ENZYMES UNIT 5.pptx
POINT- BIOCHEMISTRY SEM 2 ENZYMES UNIT 5.pptxPOINT- BIOCHEMISTRY SEM 2 ENZYMES UNIT 5.pptx
POINT- BIOCHEMISTRY SEM 2 ENZYMES UNIT 5.pptx
 
“Oh GOSH! Reflecting on Hackteria's Collaborative Practices in a Global Do-It...
“Oh GOSH! Reflecting on Hackteria's Collaborative Practices in a Global Do-It...“Oh GOSH! Reflecting on Hackteria's Collaborative Practices in a Global Do-It...
“Oh GOSH! Reflecting on Hackteria's Collaborative Practices in a Global Do-It...
 
Employee wellbeing at the workplace.pptx
Employee wellbeing at the workplace.pptxEmployee wellbeing at the workplace.pptx
Employee wellbeing at the workplace.pptx
 
AmericanHighSchoolsprezentacijaoskolama.
AmericanHighSchoolsprezentacijaoskolama.AmericanHighSchoolsprezentacijaoskolama.
AmericanHighSchoolsprezentacijaoskolama.
 
Model Call Girl in Bikash Puri Delhi reach out to us at 🔝9953056974🔝
Model Call Girl in Bikash Puri  Delhi reach out to us at 🔝9953056974🔝Model Call Girl in Bikash Puri  Delhi reach out to us at 🔝9953056974🔝
Model Call Girl in Bikash Puri Delhi reach out to us at 🔝9953056974🔝
 
Computed Fields and api Depends in the Odoo 17
Computed Fields and api Depends in the Odoo 17Computed Fields and api Depends in the Odoo 17
Computed Fields and api Depends in the Odoo 17
 
Enzyme, Pharmaceutical Aids, Miscellaneous Last Part of Chapter no 5th.pdf
Enzyme, Pharmaceutical Aids, Miscellaneous Last Part of Chapter no 5th.pdfEnzyme, Pharmaceutical Aids, Miscellaneous Last Part of Chapter no 5th.pdf
Enzyme, Pharmaceutical Aids, Miscellaneous Last Part of Chapter no 5th.pdf
 

PROJECT #3RETAIL LOCATIONSInstructions1. In an Word d.docx

  • 1. PROJECT #3 RETAIL LOCATIONS Instructions: 1. In an Word document, use the list provided at the end of these instructions to describe the following for each retail establishment listed: a. Type of retail location b. Factors affecting location (consumer shopping situations) c. What considerations might the retailer had to have considered when thinking about their location d. Parking considerations? e. Who is close to this particular retailer? How will that affect the business? f. What is their trade area? Tapestry Segment (focus segment)? 2. List of retailers: a. Belks b. JCPenney c. Trendy Pieces d. Lowes e. Kohl’s f. Dollar General The Return of the Repressed Psychology's Problematic Relations With Psychoanalysis, 1909- 1960 Gail A. Hornstein Mount Holyoke College When psychoanalysis first arrived in the United States,
  • 2. most psychologists ignored it. By the 1920s, however, psy- choanalysis had so captured the public imagination that it threatened to eclipse experimental psychology entirely. This article analyzes the complex nature of this threat and the myriad ways that psychologists responded to it. Because psychoanalysis entailed precisely the sort of rad- ical subjectivity that psychologists had renounced as un- scientific, core assumptions about the meaning of science were at stake. Psychologists' initial response was to retreat into positivism, thereby further limiting psychology's rel- evance and scope. By the 1950s, a new strategy had emerged: Psychoanalytic concepts would be put to exper- imental test, and those that qualified as "scientific" would be retained. This reinstated psychologists as arbiters of the mental world and restored "objective" criteria as the basis for making claims. A later tactic—co-opting psy- choanalytic concepts into mainstream psychology—had the ironic effect of helping make psychology a more flexible and broad-based discipline. Freud and Jung were having dinner in Bremen. It was the evening before they set sail for the Clark conference, the occasion of Freud's only visit to America. Jung started talking about certain mummies in the lead cellars of the city. Freud became visibly disturbed. "Why are you so concerned with these corpses?" he asked several times. Jung went on talking. Suddenly, without warning, Freud fell to the floor in a faint. When he recovered, he accused Jung of harboring death wishes against him. But it was not Jung who wanted Freud dead. Had Freud only known what American psychologists were about to do to psy- choanalysis, he might never have gotten up off the floor. There is no easy way to talk about psychology's re- lations with psychoanalysis.1 It is a story dense with dis- illusionment and the shapeless anger of rejection. Each
  • 3. side behaved badly, and then compounded its insensitivity with disdain. Their fates bound together like Romulus and Remus, psychology and psychoanalysis struggled to find their separate spheres, only to end up pitted against one another at every turn. Too much was at stake—prop- erty lines, areas of influence, and a deeper question: Which field would ultimately dictate the ground rules for a science of the mind? In the 1890s, when this struggle began, there was little sign that it would become another Hundred Years' War. Psychologists had just begun to apply experimental methods to some of the classic problems of metaphysics, with the hope of answering questions that had bedeviled philosophers for centuries. By systematically organizing the psychological world into a set of discrete variables, these methods brought the unruly phenomena of mind within the purview of science. It was a heady time, a time of possibility and change and the reckless felicity of the new. American psychologists raced around founding lab- oratories at every college that would let them, in closets, basements or wherever they could snatch a little space, setting up apparatus in their own homes if necessary. They invented new forms of measurement, odd devices, tests of all sorts. Reports of their findings poured into the jour- nals that sprang up suddenly to fill the need. The new psychology, as they liked to call it, seemed destined even in its infancy to do what had been declared since Kant to be impossible—to create a truly scientific approach to mind. Psychoanalysts thrust themselves directly into the middle of this scene, brazenly trying to supplant the new psychology at the moment of its greatest promise. At first psychologists stood aside, astonished, as the analysts,
  • 4. bursting with self-importance and an almost frightening zealotry, pronounced themselves the real scientists of the mind. By the time psychologists began to take this threat seriously, psychoanalysis had so captured the public imagination that even its pretensions could not be ig- nored.2 The question was how to define science. To the an- alysts, science had nothing to do with method, with con- I gratefully acknowledge Winifred Connerton's excellent research assis- tance and Verlyn Klinkenborg's incisive comments on earlier drafts. I also thank several groups of colleagues at Mount Holyoke for their en- couragement and suggestions, and John Burnham for his careful reading of a later draft. Preparation of this article was supported by a fellowship from the Mary Ingraham Bunting Institute of Radcliffe College. Correspondence concerning this article should be addressed to Gail A. Hornstein, Department of Psychology, Mount Holyoke College, South Hadley, MA 01075. 1 The standard reference on this whole topic is Shakow and Rapaport (1964). Their study remains invaluable as a thoughtful, systematic review of much of what psychologists have had to say about psychoanalysis. However, because their goal was to document Freud's influence on
  • 5. American psychology, they focused more on positive effects than on negative ones. My goal is to characterize psychologists' attitudes toward psychoanalysis. Many psychologists saw psychoanalysis as a threat and not as a positive influence, and thus my version of the story is inevitably more conflicted than Shakow and Rapaport's. 2 A discussion of the popular reception of psychoanalysis in America is beyond the scope of this article. See Hale (1971, 1978) and Burnham (1968, 1978, 1979, 1987) for detailed treatments of this issue. 254 February 1992 • American Psychologist Copyright 1992 by the American Psychological Association, Inc. 0OO3-O66X/92/$2.0O Vol. 47, No. 2, 254-263 trolling variables or counting things. What made some- thing scientific was that it was true. Constructing a science of the mind could mean only one thing—finding some way to peer through the watery murk of consciousness to the subaquean reality that lay beyond. The efforts of psychologists, with their bulky equipment and piles of charts and graphs, seemed superficial and largely irrele- vant to this goal.3 For their part, psychologists initially saw psycho- analysis as just another of the "mind cures" that flashed across the American landscape in the 1890s—like Chris-
  • 6. tian Science or the Emmanuel movement—a popular craze that had nothing to do with the scientific study of mind. Most psychologists who attended Freud's Clark lectures in 1909 saw his speculations about dreams and sex as a pleasant diversion, about as relevant to their work as Mrs. Eddy's epistles. The occasional articles about psychoanalysis that appeared in psychology journals be- fore 1910 (e.g., Putnam, 1906; Scott, 1908) made it seem mildly interesting, but not essentially different from re- lated methods like suggestion. By 1915, readers of a publication like The Journal of Abnormal Psychology had an opportunity for more varied exposure to psychoanalytic ideas.4 Books by Freud, Jung, and A. A. Brill were regularly reviewed. Articles demonstrating the therapeutic effectiveness of psycho- analytic techniques began to appear, along with some dis- cussion of the theory itself (see, e.g., Coriat, 1910; Emer- son, 1912-1913; Gordon, 1917; MacCurdy, 1913; Mae- der, 1910; Putnam, 1909-1910). Criticisms, when made, were fair-minded and well within the spirit of scientific repartee. Donley (1911), for example, suggested that anxiety neurosis might have other causes beyond those considered by Freud. Bellamy (1915a) argued that dreams fulfill fears or states of anger just as often as they represent wishes. Taylor (1911) noted that there were cases of neu- rosis in which patients recovered without having had their childhood or sexual life dissected. Even critics with a broader focus expressed little ire. Wells (1913) was con- cerned about "looseness in the formulation of psycho- analytic theories" (p. 227). Solomon (1916) argued that the term sexual was used inconsistently by analytic writ- ers. The psychiatrist Morton Prince (1910) expressed the common view that psychoanalysts "fit the facts to the universal concepts which dominate the school" (p. 349).
  • 7. There were occasional writers who became exasper- ated and called psychoanalysis "weird" (Donley, 1911), "esoteric" (Carrington, 1914), or "grotesque" (Bellamy, 1915a), its assumptions "fantastic" or "sheer nonsense" (Humphrey, 1920b), but these imprecations were unusual in the early years. The sexual nature of psychoanalytic interpretation was a problem for some; Bellamy (1915b), for example, in reviewing a book by Coriat, made plain his relief that "there is not a word or sentence in this book that a precise maiden lady need hesitate to read to her Sunday school class or at a pink tea" (p. 434). On the whole, however, psychologists were initially so sup- portive of psychoanalysis that when Roback reviewed Dunlap's (1920) Mysticism, Freudianism and Scientific Psychology, he felt he had to defend its critical tone on grounds of balance: "Freud has had so many warm ad- vocates of his views in this country and so few systematic critics among the psychologists that Dunlap's discussion is both timely and important" (Roback, 1921, p. 406). These positive attitudes might well have resulted from more than psychologists' open-mindedness. Ana- lysts, ever worried about their public image, left little to chance. Soon after the Clark conference they embarked on a systematic campaign to win Americans to their cause. A. A. Brill, the founder of the New York Psycho- analytic Society, was charged with disseminating infor- mation about psychoanalysis in that city; Ernest Jones, Freud's scrappy lieutenant, took the rest of the country for himself (Burnham, 1967, pp. 134-137). Psychologists were among the major recipients of Jones's educational largess; by 1916, they had been treated to 20 of his articles, abstracts, reviews, and comments in the Journal of Ab- normal Psychology alone. Most of these pieces were pa- tient expositions of psychoanalytic concepts, designed to
  • 8. lead the uninitiated to a correct understanding of the the- ory. But Jones also maintained a vigilant watch over what psychologists were writing about psychoanalysis, and shot back a tart riposte whenever he encountered an "erro- neous" statement (see also Tannenbaum, 1916, 1917). Neither Jones nor his colleagues gave serious atten- tion to the careful criticisms that psychologists leveled against psychoanalysis in the early years. Acutely aware of the tenuous status of their own new field, psychologists found this highly disconcerting. After all, they were con- stantly obliged to defend their science against attacks from philosophy and biology; what gave analysts the right not only to ignore legitimate criticism but to patronize their opponents? Who knows what might have happened had analysts been more responsive; what did happen was that psychologists sharpened their pencils and began to fight. The first skirmish actually occurred as early as 1916, when the Princeton philosopher Warner Fite reviewed Jung's Psychology of the Unconscious for The Nation (Fite, 1916). His surprisingly nasty tone incited a riot of re- sponse from psychologists. In her letter to the editor, Christine Ladd-Franklin, the eminent experimentalist, characterized psychoanalysis as a product of the "unde- veloped . . . German mind" (hardly a compliment in 1916), and concluded ominously that "unless means can speedily be found to prevent its spread . . . the prognosis 3 Psychologists were not alone in having to struggle with competing definitions of science. Kuklick's (1980) analysis of boundary maintenance in sociology offers a general model for understanding how each of the social sciences resolved this dilemma.
  • 9. 4 Of all major psychology journals of the period, the Journal of Abnormal Psychology was the one with the greatest number of articles relevant to psychoanalysis (both pro and con). Not all were written by psychologists, but they were clearly intended for this audience. G. Stanley Hall published the text of Freud's, Jung's, and Ferenczi's Clark lectures in his American Journal of Psychology in 1910, but from then on that journal concentrated primarily on reviews of the psychoanalytic literature (both German and English) and carried very few original articles by psychologists. February 1992 • American Psychologist 255 for civilization is unfavorable" (Ladd-Franklin, 1916, p. 374). R. S. Woodworth of Columbia (1916), a bit more circumspect, called psychoanalysis an "uncanny religion" (probably not the psychologist's highest accolade) that led "even apparently sane individuals" to absurd asso- ciations and nonsensical conclusions. In a telling illus- tration, he showed how the words Freudian principles led to a train of thought that revealed his own "deep-seated wish . . . for a career of unbridled lust" (p. 396). Woodworth went on to publish an extensive critique of "Freudism" in the 1917 volume of the Journal of Ab- normal Psychology. Adopting the peevish tone that soon became commonplace in these sorts of articles, he com-
  • 10. plained that analysts disregarded psychological research, contemptuously dismissed it as superficial, and treated psychologists "shabbily" (Woodworth, 1917, p. 175). What most annoyed Woodworth was the analysts' slip- pery dodge, their way of attributing any criticism of psy- choanalysis to unconscious resistance on the part of the critic. Other writers echoed these complaints, often with less poignancy and considerably more pique than Wood- worth. But what soon emerged as the real irritant for psychologists was the analysts' insistence, at times mor- alistic, at times snide, that only those who had themselves undergone a personal psychoanalysis were qualified to evaluate the theory. To an experimental psychology whose raison d'etre was to differentiate itself from religion, this talk of initiation rites and secret knowledge was anathema. Such a rule also conveniently disenfranchised just about every psychologist from serving as a potential critic; even those Americans who sought analysis had a hard time finding it in this country before 1920. Of course the real issue here was not who had been analyzed and who had not (a good thing, since Freud and his closest colleagues would have had to disqualify themselves); what was at stake was the fundamental question of subjectivity in sci- ence. For experimental psychologists, being scientific meant creating distance. It meant opening up a space, a "no man's land," between themselves and the things they studied, a place whose boundary could be patrolled so that needs or desires or feelings could never infiltrate the work itself. Every aspect of the experimental situation was bent toward this goal—the "blind subjects," the mechanized recording devices, the quantified measures, and statistically represented results (Danziger, 1990;
  • 11. Hornstein, 1988; Morawski, 1988). What united exper- imental psychologists more than anything else was a dis- trust of personal experience, a sense that feelings in par- ticular were dangerous and had to be held carefully in check lest they flood in and destroy the very foundations of the work. They were willing to make a number of sac- rifices to protect psychology from this threat, including a radical narrowing of the field to include only phenomena that could be studied "objectively." Having gone to these lengths, psychologists found it profoundly disquieting to have analysts claim that being psychoanalyzed was what made someone a credible sci- entist. This implied that science was subjective, that it was ultimately about personal experience rather than rig- orous method. Even worse, it suggested that the uncon- scious was so powerful a part of mind that its force had to be experienced directly, in one's own life, in order to understand the psychology of others. Such a view could not go unchallenged. "Voodoo- ism," Watson (1927, p. 502) called it. "A delusion," echoed Jastrow (1932, p. 285). The very idea of an un- conscious conjured up the chaos and irrationality that psychologists had banded together to escape. If analysts wanted to plunge into that nightmare world and call it science, so be it, but they could not be allowed to drag everyone else down with them. The technique of free association came in for par- ticular scorn (Heidbreder, 1933). It struck psychologists as an elaborate subterfuge, a way for analysts to appear not to influence patients when of course they did. Inter- pretation, they argued, was nothing but a new name for suggestion; that patients were gullible enough to mistake
  • 12. it for truth was hardly proof of its scientific status. Analysts were "free," all right—free to define as evidence whatever would meet their needs, free to label any challenge "re- sistance," free to pretend that they were doing nothing of the sort. Heidbreder (1933), in her typically fair-minded way, struggled to make these practices sound reasonable. But even she could muster only this faint defense: Just because "psychoanalysts offer a different kind of evidence from that accepted by science . . . does not mean that they offer no evidence" (p. 402). To most psychologists, calling an analyst's retrospective musings about events that oc- curred in the secrecy of the consulting room evidence was an insult to science. Even first-year students knew that the cardinal rule of scientific proof was publicly ver- ifiable data. Knight Dunlap (1920, p. 8) put it bluntly: "psychoanalysis attempts to creep in wearing the uniform of science, and to strangle it from the inside."5 By the mid-1920s, psychologists seem to have de- cided that the best way to defend science was simply to do it. Critiques of psychoanalysis began to be displaced in the literature by enthusiastic works like Great Exper- iments in Psychology (Garrett, 1930). Any remaining ag- gressive tendencies were easily absorbed by the intermin- able debates over behaviorism and Gestalt psychology.6 Psychologists did not need psychoanalysis, and it surely did not need them. Or so it seemed, until one day in the fall of 1934 when the rumor got out that Edwin Garrigues Boring, 5 With characteristic irony, Dunlap (1920) concluded that psycho-
  • 13. analysis might ultimately prove beneficial to psychology: "Just as Chris- tian Science has tremendously accelerated the progress of Scientific Medicine, so Psychoanalysis, by compelling psychology to put its house in order, will eventually help in the development of the Scientific Psy- chology it aims to thrust aside" (p. 9). ' See, for example, a classic work like Psychologies of 1925 (Mur- chison, 1926), which allots four chapters to behaviorism, three to Gestalt, and even three to the dying gasps of structuralism, but none to psycho- analysis. 256 February 1992 • American Psychologist the self-acknowledged dean of experimental psychology, had entered analytic treatment. To preserve his reputa- tion, he told colleagues that he was studying the relation between the two fields; actually, he was depressed, fright- ened, and unable to work. The strange saga of Boring's analysis gives a glimpse into psychologists' continuing ambivalence about psychoanalysis. Boring chose as his analyst the emigre Berliner, Hanns Sachs, who had been a member of Freud's inner circle and was therefore above reproach. Despite his depression, Boring embarked on the analysis with cus- tomary gusto, quickly absorbing the daily analytic sessions into the swirl of his 80-hour work week.
  • 14. Boring struggled to make the analysis a success. He missed no sessions. He wept. He threw things. He made enough of a financial sacrifice to demonstrate the seri- ousness of his commitment. He discussed his childhood, explored his dreams, and scrutinized the motivations for his actions. Then, at the end of 10 months, he ran out of money, time, and desire. He had completed 168 sessions, for which he had paid $1,680, more than a fifth of his yearly salary. But his efforts brought little relief: [A]ll that happened was that the analysis petered out in an un- eventful session on June 21 st and my analyst went abroad!. . . I was distraught. I had tried a last resource, and it had failed. Yet, unwilling to accept so bitter a conclusion, I found myself seizing on the analyst's casual statement that I ought to wait a month. I waited anxiously, hoping for a new personality by July 21st. None came. Finally I sought out my psychologist-friends who believe in psychoanalysis, and we sat in conference dis- cussing this sad immutability of my personality—on August 21st, as I suddenly realized. Their advice was patience, the less haste the more speed; wait at least until December 21st, they urged. So I waited. . . . And finally I ceased to expect a miracle. (Boring, 1940, pp. 9-10)7 How could a man like Boring, whose name was practically synonymous with hard-nosed experimenta- tion, have such childlike faith in psychoanalysis? He ac- tually seemed to expect that he would wake up a new man, that "a light from heaven" would change him "from Saul to Paul" (p. 9). There are certainly no hints of these hopes in his published writings. In the first edition of his classic History of Experimental Psychology (Boring, 1929), published just five years before the analysis, there were only four brief mentions of Freud in almost 700 pages. Psychoanalysis did not even appear in the index
  • 15. of Psychology: A Factual Textbook, the text Boring pub- lished with Langfeld and Weld in 1935, the same year he saw Sachs. Yet in his own life, Boring kept searching for some sign that the analysis might have worked. Five years passed. Still no light. In 1940, he tried a new strategy. He proposed to the Journal of Abnormal and Social Psy- chology that it locate other well-known psychologists who had been analyzed, solicit reports of their experiences, and publish them in a special issue. Perhaps they would reveal something that he had missed. Leaving nothing to chance, Boring even persuaded Sachs to write a compan- ion piece to his own account, evaluating the analysis from the analyst's perspective. Psychologists turned out to be surprisingly excited by the prospect of reading about their colleagues' adven- tures on the couch. The American Psychological Asso- ciation even reprinted the articles and sold them as a set, exhausting the entire edition within a few months. Boring, ever hopeful, titled his piece "Was This Analysis a Suc- cess?" Sachs (1940) replied with a tactful " n o . " Wistful and perplexed by the whole experience, Boring struggled to come to terms with his sense of loss: "There is so much about this personality of mine that would be better if different, so much that analysis might have done and did not!" (Boring, 1940, p. 10). Yet he refrained from at- tacking psychoanalysis directly. His colleagues, however, knew where to lay the blame for their own failed attempts. Carney Landis of Columbia parodied his experience with a statistical analysis of how much time he had allocated to each of eight topics during free association. To Landis, analysts were scientific illiterates who did little but mouth received dogma in order to make themselves rich. Hinting
  • 16. that his "neurosis" was created by the analysis itself, Landis (1940) concluded his tirade by warning that psy- choanalysis was safe only when used by experimental psychologists to produce psychopathic phenomena in the laboratory. The editor of the Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology, apparently concerned about the lack of bal- ance in these articles, invited the eminent analyst Franz Alexander to contribute a rejoinder. Instead of critiquing the other papers, Alexander (1940) made a parable of his own life. Like his readers, he had spent his youth as a devotee of laboratory science. When he first tried to read Freud's work, he found its "vague and ambiguous mental excursions . . . equal almost to physical pain" (p. 312). He turned to psychoanalysis only when the evidence in support of it became undeniable. This meant sacrificing his promising academic career, enduring the opprobrium of his colleagues, and being forced from home by his irate philosopher father, who considered psychoanalysis a "spiritual gutter." But for Alexander, there was no choice—having committed himself to empiricism, he had to adopt whatever view had the most evidence, regardless of how distasteful it might be on other grounds. Of course, in the end, his quest for truth was vindicated when his father, near death, gave up his own lifelong belief in the superiority of natural science to express the fervent wish that "psychoanalysis will enthrone again real under- standing in place of fumbling—the rule of thought in place of that of the gadget" (p. 314). 7 Among those Boring consulted was his colleague Henry Murray, who advised him to let Sachs have it "right between his eyes. . . . give him the works—don't omit a single grievance, not one." (H.
  • 17. Murray to E. G. Boring [n. d., August 1935?], Box 43, Folder 919, E. G. Boring Papers, Harvard University Archives quoted by permission.) There is no evidence that Boring took this advice: He and Sachs maintained a cordial relationship for some time thereafter, dining together at the Har- vard Club and exchanging papers and letters on professional topics. February 1992 • American Psychologist 257 Alexander's inspiring tale fell on closed ears. Dis- trusting subjectivity in all its forms, psychologists put little stock in personal testimony, even that of fellow scientists. This series of articles clearly had less to do with evaluating psychoanalysis than it did with assuaging the anxiety of its contributors, many of whom were worried, like Boring, that their analyses had failed. What they needed was re- assurance. But the tangible benefits of this kind of therapy are always elusive. Recall Janet Malcolm's (1984) sardonic comment: "The crowning paradox of psychoanalysis is the near-uselessness of its insights. To 'make the uncon- scious conscious' . . . is to pour water into a sieve. The moisture that remains on the surface of the mesh is the benefit of analysis" (p. 25). Ultimately, these articles were exercises in self-persuasion, attempts by the contributors to convince themselves that psychoanalysis was too ri- diculous or too ineffectual to be taken seriously. If they managed in the process to warn off colleagues who might have been tempted to try the thing themselves, so much the better.
  • 18. By the early 1940s, the situation had reached a crit- ical stage. Psychoanalysis was becoming so popular that it threatened to eclipse psychology entirely. Journalists seemed oblivious to the differences between the two fields, and exasperated psychologists often found their discipline being portrayed as if it were nothing but a branch of psy- choanalytic inquiry. This was especially galling because most psychologists assumed that psychoanalytic claims were not even true. But how could they prove this? The critiques of the early years had not worked. Attacking psychoanalysis from the couch had simply allowed Al- exander to make psychologists look foolish. There had to be a better way. The solution turned out to be so obvious that it is hard to believe it took until the mid-1940s to appear. Psychologists would set themselves the job of determining through carefully controlled experiments which, if any, psychoanalytic concepts were valid. This reinstated psy- chologists as arbiters of the mental world, able to make the final judgment about what would and would not count as psychological knowledge. It allowed them to evaluate psychoanalysis, rather than be overshadowed or absorbed by it. Most important, it restored the objective criterion of the experiment as the basis for making claims and settling disputes, undermining the analysts' attempts to substitute a new, subjective standard for psychological truth. Psychologists took to their new role with a vengeance. Every conceivable psychoanalytic concept was put to the test, in hundreds of studies whose creativity was matched only by the uselessness of their findings. Mowrer (1940) demonstrated that regression and reaction formation could be produced in rats. Blum and Miller (1952) found
  • 19. that children who were categorized as having an "oral character" ate significantly more ice cream than did other children. Scodel (1957) showed that "high-dependency" men did not manifest the predicted preference for women with large breasts. Schwartz (1956) found more castration anxiety among men than women, with homosexual men scoring the highest of all. Sarnoff and Corwin (1959) re- ported that "high castration anxious" men showed a greater increase in fear of death than did "low anxious" men after being exposed to photographs of nude women. And Friedman (1952) found that when children were shown a picture of a father and a child near some stairs, more girls than boys fantasized that the father would mount the stairs and enter the room. Topics like oedipal relations and anal personality had their aficionados, but it was perceptual defense that really captured the imagination of psychological researchers. Their hypothesis was a simple one: If the mind did defend against forbidden material, then words with disturbing or salacious associations should be recalled less easily than more neutral stimuli. Fresh-faced graduate students spent hours making certain that items like whore and bugger were matched in length and salience with their sexless counterparts. Controversies erupted left and right: Were taboo words difficult to recognize just because they were not used very frequently? Wiener's (1955) famous "pussy- balls" study dispatched that idea by demonstrating that the context, not the words themselves, made certain stimuli threatening. But was exposure to a list of scatal- ogical words really analogous to the sort of trauma that necessitated repression? Blum (1954) addressed that problem with a new methodology based on the Blacky Pictures, a set of cartoon images of a dog depicted in various psychoanalytically relevant poses (licking his
  • 20. genitals, observing his parents having sex, defecating out- side their kennel). When studies with Blacky were found to support the earlier word-item findings, repression gained the sort of empirical reality that only psychologists could give it. By the 1950s, research on psychoanalysis had be- come so popular that psychologists were drowning in it. No one could possibly read all the studies that were being published, much less keep track of their results.8 A new cottage industry was born of this need, with workers who did nothing but summarize and evaluate these studies. Robert Sears had been the first such laborer, commis- sioned in 1943 by the Social Science Research Council to write an objective review of the scientific literature on psychoanalytic theory. Sears's approach, used by all sub- sequent evaluators, was straightforward: Having first di- vided the literature into topic categories (fixation, sex- uality, object choice), he then counted how many studies in each area supported Freud's claims. The larger the number, the more scientific the claim. Taken together, these individual scores were supposed to provide an an- swer to the overall question of whether psychoanalytic theory was valid. Sears (1943) hedged, saying that some of it was, and some of it was not. Such caution soon vanished. The self- appointed judges whose reports appeared up through the "Fisher and Greenberg's (1977) review includes more than 400 studies from the 1940s and 1950s alone. By the mid-1970s, there were at least 1,000 more. 258 February 1992 • American Psychologist
  • 21. early 1970s placed themselves squarely on one side of the debate or the other. Evaluation studies quickly became as difficult to sort out as research on psychoanalysis itself, and much less fun to read (see, for example, Fisher & Greenberg, 1977; Kline, 1972). Each report took a tone yet more strident than the last, and the original goal of providing an objective review was lost entirely. This was nowhere more evident than in Eysenck and Wilson's (1973) polemic. Every shred of evidence seeming to sup- port psychoanalysis was scrutinized for methodological flaws, whereas studies opposing the theory were flaunted as examples of good science. No one especially cared that the evaluation literature was becoming debased. It made little difference what the findings were; as long as psychoanalytic phenomena were made subservient to empirical test, empiricism was vin- dicated.9 That much of this research supported Freud's theory was an irony appreciated by few. It was the act of doing these studies, of piling them up and sorting them out and arguing about them that was important, not what they revealed about psychoanalysis. Some psychologists found these activities so salubrious that they recom- mended them even to analysts. As Albert Ellis (1950) cheerfully noted, "sociologists, who but a decade or two ago were mostly concerned with pure theory, now fre- quently design and execute crucial experiments which enable them to support or discredit hypotheses. There is no basic reason why psychoanalysts cannot do likewise" (p. 190). Analysts were in no position to point out that the content of these psychological studies had only the dim- mest relation to Freud's theory. "Every country creates
  • 22. the psychoanalysis it [unconsciously] needs," said Kurz- weil (1989, p. 1), and disciplines surely do the same. Re- search on psychoanalysis was invigorating because it gave psychologists a sense of mastery: They had ventured onto the battlefield of the unconscious and returned, trium- phant, with a set of dependent variables. Some psychol- ogists even managed to convince themselves that the dan- ger had been exaggerated all along, that they had really been in control. They scoffed that psychoanalysis had never been much more than an inflated way of talking about conditioning, one of psychology's oldest topics. By the time Dollard and Miller (1950) actually began trans- lating every psychoanalytic concept into its learning the- ory equivalent, their efforts were almost redundant. These behaviorist reworkings of Freud, although of- ten clumsy, did signal a new strategy in dealing with psy- choanalysis—co-optation. More satisfying than silence, with none of the pitfalls of criticism, the appropriation of psychoanalytic concepts into mainstream psychology seemed an ideal compromise. Like the Christianizing of paganism, the dangerous parts were still there somewhere, but in such diluted form as to pose no real threat.10 Watson had tried to move in this direction as early as the 1920s. By relabeling the unconscious as the unver- balized, he could sweep most psychoanalytic phenomena into the neat piles of behaviorist theory. Emotions became sets of habits; neurosis was conditioning; therapy, uncon- ditioning. Watson never denied the reality of Freud's findings; he simply cast them in his own terms (e.g., when he warned [1928, p. 80] that sexual frustration made mothers want to kiss rather than shake hands with their children). At times, Watson even took to calling himself an analyst, as if, like some ancient warrior, he could mag-
  • 23. ically disarm his enemy by assuming his name.11 Other behaviorists continued where Watson left off. Humphrey (1920a), following Holt's (1915) earlier lead, dissolved wishes into conditioned reflexes. Keller and Schoenfeld (1950) laid claim to such psychoanalytic sta- ples as the slip of the tongue (yet another reflex) and the oedipal complex (a consequence of early conditioning). But it was Skinner who took the task of appropriating Freud most seriously. In Science and Human Behavior (1953), he systematically redefined each of the defense mechanisms in operant terms {repression: a "response which is successful in avoiding the conditioned aversive stimulation generated by punishment," p. 292; reaction formation: "an extension of a technique of self-control in which the environment is altered so that it becomes less likely to generate punished behavior," p. 365). By the end of the book, even symbols and dreams had taken on the veneer of conditioned responses. Artful as these efforts were, they did not really solve the problem. Freud was still there. His new operant outfit gave him a natty Amer- ican look, but there was no mistaking that sardonic smile. As long as psychoanalytic concepts remained identifiable as such, they were potential rivals to psychology's own constructs. Help with this problem came from an unlikely source—introductory textbook writers. Typically dis- missed as nothing but purveyors of pabulum for college students, these authors, many of them prominent psy- chologists, played a major role in advancing the co-op- tation of psychoanalytic theory. This is not so surprising. As Morawski (1992, this issue) shows, introductory texts exist in a liminal space, neither popular nor professional, 9 Hilgard (1952) was the only evaluator who seemed willing to
  • 24. grant this point. He chastised psychologists for doing experiments that "give merely trivial illustrations of what psychoanalysts have demonstrated . . . in clinical work," and argued that although "such illustrations may be useful as propaganda," they "do not really do much for science." In his view, psychoanalytic research "ought to advance our understanding, not merely confirm or deny the theories that someone [else] has stated" (p. 43). 10 Precisely the same thing was done with Gestalt psychology. At first, the philosophic assumptions of the theory were seen as a challenge to American (behaviorist) psychology, and Gestalt was explicitly opposed. Then the dangerous aspects were simply stripped away, making it appear as if the principles of organization were empirical observations that had arisen out of nowhere. A contemporary student of perceptual psychology would have no idea that these principles were originally formulated in opposition to behaviorist thought. 1' "I venture to predict that 20 years from now an analyst using Freudian concepts and Freudian terminology will be placed upon the same plane as a phrenologist. And yet analysis based upon behavioristic
  • 25. principles is here to stay and is a necessary profession in society—to be placed upon a par with internal medicine and surgery" (Watson, 1925, p. 243). The comparison of psychoanalysis to phrenology was a favorite among psychologists; Dallenbach (1955) later wrote an entire article on this theme. February 1992 • American Psychologist 259 yet somehow both. They function simultaneously as translators of standard doctrine and contributors to it. Because new texts constantly supplant older ones, they become disciplinary artifacts, frozen moments of taken- for-granted knowledge, X rays of the uncontroversial. Textbook writers took advantage of their role by as- similating psychoanalytic concepts into mainstream psy- chology without mentioning their origins. An early ex- ample was Walter Hunter's 1923 text, General Psychology, in which the various defense mechanisms were stripped of any connection to the unconscious, much the way ba- gels now appear in the frozen-food sections of Peoria su- permarkets. Other writers soon adopted this practice, sometimes using the term adjustment mechanisms to ex- punge any remaining whifFof psychodynamics (Guthrie & Edwards, 1949; Kimble, 1956). These appropriations took place amidst a general silence in these texts about psychoanalytic theory itself. Many writers ignored the topic entirely: Robinson and Robinson's 665-page Readings in General Psychology
  • 26. (1923) included the contributions of every conceivable psychologist, even Helen Keller and the Lord Archbishop of York, but had nothing by Freud or any other psy- choanalyst (the section titled "Dreams as a Vehicle of Wish Fulfillment" was written by Watson). Readers of well-known texts like Seashore's (1923) Introduction to Psychology or Warren and Carmichael's (1930) Elements of Human Psychology would never have known that psy- choanalysis existed. Even as late as 1958, a classic like Hebb's Textbook of Psychology barely mentioned the topic. When Freud did make an appearance, it was more likely to be in the section on punishment or motivation— topics dear to the heart of experimentalists—than in ex- pected places like the chapter on abnormality. Of course some textbook writers did discuss psy- choanalysis in more depth, but few besides Hilgard (1953) did so sympathetically.n Kimble (1956) went to the trou- ble of including a special section in his introduction warning readers not to make the common error of con- fusing psychology with psychoanalysis. It was not that Freud had no value: Kimble called his work "one of the great milestones in the history of human thought" with "insights [that] have never been equaled" (pp. 369-370). Psychoanalysis just happened to be "entirely literary and not worth discussion" in a scientific text (p. 370). In 1956, Gardner Murphy was asked to determine the extent of Freud's impact on the various subfields of psychology. He likened the overall effect to the erosion of the rocky coastline in Maine, but admitted that some areas had remained untouched by the psychoanalytic current. His results, on a numerical scale, of course, con- stitute what one might call an index of introgression, ranging from 0, Freud never had a chance, to 6, he made it all the way in. Here are Murphy's ratings: intelligence
  • 27. and physiological = 0; comparative, learning, thinking, perception, and vocational = 1; memory, drive and emo- tion, child and adolescent = 2; social and industrial = 3; imagination = 4; abnormal = 5; personality and clini- cal = 6. What is surprising about these results is that there are any high scores at all. How could a discipline that had spent 50 years protecting its chastity end up seduced by a ladykiller like Freud? Of course the problem was really only with the clinicians, but there were thousands of them, and more every year (Gilgen, 1982; Kelly, 1947). When the American Psychological Association surveyed a sample of its members in 1954, asking who had influ- enced them to enter the field, Freud, of all people, got the greatest number of mentions (Clark, 1957, pp. 17- 18). True, by that time, 37% of APA members were cli- nicians (p. 116), but how had that happened? Why were so many psychologists fleeing the laboratory? Perhaps it was just the money. Or the effects of the war. But what if this exodus had a more ominous meaning? Repression is a perverse process. It appears to efface the offending material, but this is an illusion—the con- tents of the unconscious are indestructible. Repressed material, like radioactive waste, lies there in leaky can- isters, never losing potency, eternally dangerous. What is worse, it actively presses for expression, constantly threatening to erupt into consciousness. No one can con- trol these forces; the best we can do is try to deflect them. It is a sign of health if we can accomplish this with a few judiciously used defenses. We know we're in trouble when we have to resort to the rigidity of symptoms.
  • 28. Experimentalists took a calculated risk in trying to create a psychology in which subjective phenomena were banned from study. They knew that this would be difficult, that it would require erecting a set of defenses (the ex- perimental method and all its appurtenances) and being vigilant about their use. But subjectivity creeps through every crevice and finds its way around even the strongest barricade. In the early years, this threat was manageable and psychology was willing to tolerate some narrowing of its operations in exchange for the reduction of anxiety its defenses allowed. Psychoanalysis tore this fragile equi- librium to pieces. By embracing subjectivity—sometimes even reveling in it—while still proclaiming itself a science, psychoanalysis forced psychology to define itself in ever more positivist terms. This was no ordinary battle over intellectual turf. It was more like a nightmare, in which psychologists watched, horrified, as the very phenomena they had sought to banish now returned to haunt them. They did what they could to contain the threat, but each new tactic only made things worse. Co-opting analytic concepts proved to be especially disastrous because it let the banned phenomena inside psychology itself. Even in scientific disguise, they were still dangerous, like a well- dressed hitchhiker who pulls a knife after getting into the car. With the threat now internal as well as external, ex- 12 Buys (1976) has argued that it was only in the 1970s that positive portrayals of psychoanalysis became common in introductory texts. See also Herma, Kris, & Shor (1943), whose study focused on how Freud's theory of dreams was presented in such texts. They found such a high degree of criticism that they were forced to make separate tallies for
  • 29. ridicule, rejection on moral grounds, and sheer denial. 260 February 1992 • American Psychologist perimental psychology was forced to harden itself still further. What had once been science became scientism, the neurotic symptom of a frightened discipline. In retrospect, we might say that this was all to the good. The psychology that emerged from these wrenching experiences was stronger and more resilient, able to tol- erate a degree of diversity among its members that would once have been unthinkable. The past 30 years have been a time of exponential growth, as older areas like learning have reorganized and newer ones like clinical have ma- tured. The "cognitive revolution" that brought the mind back to psychology transformed even the most hard-core behaviorist, and terms like self-perception are now ban- died about the laboratory as if they had been there all along. The rigid experimentalism of the 1940s now seems vaguely embarrassing, one of those righteous crusades of adolescence that pales before the complex realities of middle age. There were many reasons for these changes, and cer- tainly the threat from psychoanalysis was only one of a host of factors pushing psychology toward greater flexi- bility. But, as Burnham (1978) has argued, psychoanalysis did represent an extreme position against which more conservative disciplines like psychology and psychiatry had to define themselves. The willingness of analysts to occupy the radical frontiers of subjectivity gave psychol- ogists room to maneuver, to create a middle ground in which previously excluded phenomena could enter with-
  • 30. out threatening the scientific standards psychologists had fought so hard to establish. Equally important were the changes in psychoanal- ysis itself. During the period from 1940 to 1960, inter- necine warfare reached new heights among American an- alysts. The purges in the New York Psychoanalytic Insti- tute were only the most visible sign that the field had become increasingly intolerant of dissent, and the huge influx of candidates after the war accelerated this slide toward conformity and conservatism (Hale, 1978; Jacoby, 1983). Psychoanalysis in 1950 was fundamentally differ- ent from what it had been in 1920, and its new main- stream mentality made it far easier for psychologists to accept. The Second World War also played a significant role in these dynamics. Psychologists made substantive con- tributions to the diagnosis and treatment of war-related disturbances, as well as to myriad other problems from personnel selection to instrument design. These efforts enhanced the reputation of professional psychology and stimulated a massive increase in funding for psychological research. The war also brought to America European ref- ugee psychologists, many of whom saw psychoanalytic ideas as part of the psychological canon. Psychologists began to spend less time worrying about whether analysts were eroding the fragile boundary between legitimate and popular psychology (Morawski & Hornstein, 1991) and took advantage of opportunities to get some favorable press of their own.13 American psychology has always been distinguished by an uncanny ability to adapt itself to cultural trends as quickly as they emerge. Once it became clear that the
  • 31. public found psychoanalysis irresistible, psychologists found ways of accommodating to it. Instead of concen- trating all their efforts on criticism, they identified those parts of the theory that were potentially useful to their own ends and incorporated them. As psychoanalysis be- came less threatening, psychologists were able to notice that the two fields actually shared many of the same basic assumptions: a commitment to psychic determinism, a belief in the cardinal importance of childhood experience, and an optimistic outlook about the possibility of change. It has been only 70 years since James McKeen Cattell rose from his seat at the annual meeting of the American Psychological Association to castigate a colleague for having mentioned Freud's name at a gathering of scientists (Dallenbach, 1955, p. 523). Today that same APA cele- brates the success of its lawsuit against the psychoanalytic establishment, a suit which gave psychologists the right to become bona fide candidates at the analytic institute of their choice (Buie, 1988). As the moribund institutes prepare to be enlivened by a rush of eager psychologists, perhaps it is not too much to suggest that psychology itself has benefited from having had the psychoanalytic wolf at its door. REFERENCES Alexander, F. (1940). A jury trial of psychoanalysis. Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology, 35, 305-323. Bellamy, R. (1915a). An act of everyday life treated as a pretended dream and reinterpreted by psychoanalysis. Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 10, 32-45.
  • 32. Bellamy, R. (1915b). Review of Coriat's The meaning of dreams. Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 10, 433-434. Blum, G. S. (1954). An experimental reunion of psychoanalytic theory with perceptual vigilance and defense. Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology, 49, 94-98. Blum, G. S., & Miller, D. R. (1952). Exploring the psychoanalytic theory of the "oral character." Journal of Personality, 20, 287-304. Boring, E. G. (1929). A history of experimental psychology. New York: Century. Boring, E. G. (1940). Was this analysis a success? Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology, 35, 4-10. Boring, E. G., Langfeld, H. S., & Weld, H. P. (1935). Psychology: A factual textbook. New York: Wiley. Buie, J. (1988). Psychoanalytic group bolstered by legal win. APA Monitor, 19,21. Burnham, J. C. (1967). Psychoanalysis and American medicine, 1894- 1918. New York: International Universities Press. Burnham, J. C. (1968). The new psychology: From narcissism to
  • 33. social control. In J. Braeman, R. H. Bremmer, & D. Brody (Eds.), Change and continuity in twentieth-century America: The 1920s (pp. 3 5 1 - 398). Columbus: Ohio State University Press. Burnham, J. C. (1978). The influence of psychoanalysis upon American culture. In J. M. Quen & E. T. Carlson (Eds.), American psycho- analysis: Origins and development (pp. 52-72). New York: Brunner/ Mazel. Burnham, J. C. (1979). From avant-garde to specialism: Psychoanalysis 13 See, for example, Gengerelli's (1957) rhetorical romp in the Sat- urday Review, which painted psychologists as tireless laborers in the "scientific vineyard" and analysts as "muddle-headed, sob- sisters" (p. 11) who are the cause of every social ill from delinquency to early mar- riage. February 1992 • American Psychologist 261 in America. Journal of the History of the Behavioral Sciences 15 128-134.
  • 34. Burnham, J. C. (1987). How superstition won and science lost: Popu- larizing science and health in the United States. New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University Press. Buys, C. J. (1976). Freud in introductory psychology texts. Teaching of Psychology, 3, 160-167. Carrington, H. (1914). Freudian psychology and psychical research. Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 9, 411 -416. Clark, K. E. (1957). America's psychologists: A survey of a growing profession. Washington, DC: American Psychological Association. Coriat, I. H. (1910). The psycho-analysis of a case of sensory automatism. Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 5, 93-99. Dallenbach, K. M. (1955). Phrenology versus psychoanalysis. American Journal of Psychology, 68, 511-525. Danziger, K. (1990). Constructing the subject: Historical origins of psy- chological research. New York: Cambridge University Press. Dollard, J., & Miller, N. E. (1950). Personality and psychotherapy. New York: McGraw-Hill. Donley, J. E. (1911). Freud's anxiety neurosis. Journal of
  • 35. Abnormal Psychology, 6, 126-134. Dunlap, K. (1920). Mysticism, Freudianism and scientific psychology. St. Louis, MO: Mosby. Ellis, A. (1950). An introduction to the principles of scientific psycho- analysis. Genetic Psychology Monographs, 41, 147-212. Emerson, L. E. (1912-1913). A psychoanalytic study of a severe case of hysteria. Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 7, 385-406; 8, 44-56, 180- 207. Eysenck, H. J., & Wilson, G. D. (1973). The experimental study of Freudian theories. London: Methuen. Fisher, S., & Greenberg, R. P. (1977). The scientific credibility of Freud's theories and therapy. New York: Basic Books. Fite, W. (1916). Psycho-analysis and sex-psychology. The Nation, 103, 127-129. Friedman, S. M. (1952). An empirical study of the castration and Oedipus complexes. Genetic Psychology Monographs, 46, 61-130. Garrett, H. E. (1930). Great experiments in psychology. New York: Cen- tury.
  • 36. Gengerelli, J. A. (1957, March 23). The limitations of psychoanalysis: Dogma or discipline? The Saturday Review, pp. 9 - 1 1 , 40. Gilgen, A. R. (1982). American psychology since World War II: A profile of the discipline. Westport, CT: Greenwood Press. Gordon, A. (1917). Obsessive hallucinations and psychoanalysis. Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 12, 423-430. Guthrie, E. R., & Edwards, A. L. (1949). Psychology: A first course in human behavior. New York: Harper. Hale, N. G. (1971). Freud and the Americans: The beginnings of psy- choanalysis in the United States, 1876-1917. New York: Oxford Uni- versity Press. Hale, N. G. (1978). From Bergasse XIX to Central Park West: The Americanization of psychoanalysis, 1919-1940. Journal of the History of the Behavioral Sciences, 14, 299-315. Heidbreder, E. (1933). Seven psychologies. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice- Hall. Hebb, D. O. (1958). A textbook of psychology. Philadelphia: W. B. Saun- ders.
  • 37. Herma, H., Kris, E., & Shor, J. (1943). Freud's theory of the dream in American textbooks. Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology, 38, 319-334. Hilgard, E. R. (1952). Experimental approaches to psychoanalysis. In E. Pumpian-Mindlin (Ed.), Psychoanalysis as science (pp. 3-45). New York: Basic Books. Hilgard, E. R. (1953). Introduction to psychology. New York: Harcourt, Brace. Holt, E. B. (1915). The Freudian wish and its place in ethics. New York: Holt. Hornstein, G. A. (1988). Quantifying psychological phenomena: Debates, dilemmas, and implications. In J. G. Morawski (Ed.), The rise of experimental psychology (pp. 1-34). New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. Humphrey, G. (1920a). The conditioned reflex and the Freudian wish. Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 14, 388-392. Humphrey, G. (1920b). Education and Freudianism. Journal of Abnor- mal Psychology, 15, 350-386.
  • 38. Hunter, W. (1923). General psychology. (Rev. ed.). Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Jacoby, R. (1983). The repression of psychoanalysis: Otto Fenichel and the political Freudians. New York: Basic Books. Jastrow, J. (1932). The house that Freud built. New York: Chilton. Keller, F , & Schoenfeld, W. (1950). Principles of psychology: A systematic text in the science of behavior. New York: Appleton-Century- Crofts. Kelly, E. L. (1947). Clinical psychology. In W. Dennis et. al. (Eds.), Current trends in psychology, (pp. 75-108). Pittsburgh, PA: University of Pittsburgh Press. Kimble, G. A. (1956). Principles of general psychology. New York: Ronald Press. Kline, P. (1972). Fact and fantasy in Freudian theory. London: Methuen. Kuklick, H. (1980). Boundary maintenance in American sociology: Limitations to academic "professionalization." Journal of the History of the Behavioral Sciences, 16, 201-219.
  • 39. Kurzweil, E. (1989). The Freudians: A comparative perspective. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. Ladd-Franklin, C. (1916). Letter to the editor. The Nation, 103, 373- 374. Landis, C. (1940). Psychoanalytic phenomena. Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology, 35, 17-28. MacCurdy, J. T. (1913). The productions in a manic-like state illustrating Freudian mechanisms. Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 8, 361- 375. Maeder, A. (1910). Psycho-analysis in a case of melancholic depression. Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 5, 130-131. Malcolm, J. (1984). In the Freud archives. New York: Knopf. Morawski, J. G. (1988). Introduction. In J. G. Morawski (Ed.), The rise of experimentation in American psychology (pp. vii-xvii). New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. Morawski, J. G. (1992). There is more to our history of giving: The place of introductory textbooks in American psychology. American Psychologist, 47, 161-169. Morawski, J. G., & Hornstein, G. A. (1991). Quandary of the
  • 40. quacks: The struggle for expert knowledge in American psychology, 1890- 1940. In D. van Keuren & J. Brown (Eds.), The estate of social knowl- edge (pp. 106-133). Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press. Mowrer, O. H. (1940). An experimental analogue of "regression" with incidental observations on "reaction-formation." Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology, 35, 56-87. Murchison, C. (1926). Psychologies of 1925. Worcester, MA: Clark Uni- versity Press. Murphy, G. (1956). The current impact of Freud upon psychology. American Psychologist, 11, 663-672. Prince, M. (1910). The mechanism and interpretation of dreams—A reply to Dr. Jones. Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 5, 337- 353. Putnam, J. J. (1906). Recent experiences in the study and treatment of hysteria at the Massachusetts General Hospital with remarks on Freud's method of treatment by "psycho-analysis." Journal of Ab- normal Psychology, 1, 26-41. Putnam, J. J. (1909-1910). Personal impressions of Sigmund Freud and his work, with special reference to his recent lectures at Clark
  • 41. Uni- versity. Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 4, 293-310, 372-379. Roback, A. A. (1921). Review of Dunlap's Mysticism, Freudianism and scientific psychology. Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology, 16, 406-408. Robinson, E. S., & Robinson, F. R. (1923). Readings in general psy- chology. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Sachs, H. (1940). Was this analysis a success?: Comment. Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology, 35, 11-16. Sarnoff, I., & Corwin, S. M. (1959). Castration anxiety and the fear of death. Journal of Personality, 27, 374-385. Schwartz, B. J. (1956). An empirical test of two Freudian hypotheses concerning castration anxiety. Journal of Personality, 24, 318- 327. Scodel, A. (1957). Heterosexual somatic preference and fantasy depen- dency. Journal of Consulting Psychology, 21, 371-374. Scott, W. D. (1908). An interpretation of the psycho-analytic method in psychotherapy with a report of a case so treated. Journal of Ab- normal Psychology, 3, 371-379.
  • 42. 262 February 1992 • American Psychologist Sears, R. R. (1943). Survey of objective studies of psychoanalytic concepts. New York: Social Science Research Council. Seashore, C. E. (1923). Introduction to psychology. New York: Macmillan. Shakow, D., & Rapaport, D. (1964). The influence of Freud on American psychology. New York: International Universities Press. Skinner, B. F. (1953). Science and human behavior. New York: Macmillan. Solomon, M. (1916). Critical review of the conception of sexuality as- sumed by the Freudian school. Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 11, 59-60. Tannenbaum, S. A. (1916). Letter to the editor. The Nation, 103, 2 1 8 - 219. Tannenbaum, S. A. (1917). Some current misconceptions of psycho- analysis. Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 12, 390-422. Taylor, E. W. (1911). Possibilities of a modified psychoanalysis. Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 6, 449-455. Warren, H. C , & Carmichael, L. (1930). Elements of human
  • 43. psychology (Rev. ed.). Boston: Houghton Mifflin. Watson, J. B. (1925). Behaviorism. New York: Norton. Watson, J. B. (1927). The myth of the unconscious. Harpers, 155, 502- 508. Watson, J. B. (1928). Psychological care of the infant and child. New York: Norton. Wells, F. L. (1913). On formulation in psychoanalysis. Journal of Ab- normal Psychology, 8, 217-227. Wiener, M. (1955). Word frequency or motivation in perceptual defense. Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology, 51, 214-218. Woodworth, R. S. (1916). Letter to the editor. The Nation, 103, 396. Woodworth, R. S. (1917). Some criticisms of the Freudian psychology. Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 12, 174-194. February 1992 • American Psychologist 263 SECOND LECTURE THE PSYCHOLOGY OF ERRORS
  • 44. W E begin with an investigation, not with hypotheses. To this end we choose certain phenomena which are very frequent, very familiar and very little heeded, and which have nothing to do with the pathological, inasmuch as they can be observed in every normal person. I refer to the errors which an individual commits—• as for example, errors of speech in which he wishes to say some- thing and uses the wrong word; or those which happen to him in writing, and which he may or may not notice; or the case of misreading, in which one reads in the print or writing something different from what is actually there. A similar phenomenon occurs in those cases of mishearing what is said to one, where there is no question of an organic disturbance of the auditory function. Another series of such occurrences is based on for- getfulness—but on a forgetfulness which is not permanent, but temporary, as for instance when one cannot think of a name which one knows and always recognizes; or when one forgets to carry out a project at the proper time but which one re- members again later, and therefore has only forgotten for a certain interval. In a third class this characteristic of transience is lacking, as for example in mislaying things so that they cannot t>e found again, or in the analogous case of losing things. Here we are dealing with a kind of forgetfulness to which one reacts differently from the other cases, a forgetfulness at which one is surprised and annoyed, instead of considering it comprehensible. Allied with these phenomena is that of erroneous ideas—in which the element of transience is again prominent, inasmuch as for a while one believes something which, before and after that time, one knows to be untrue—and a number of similar phenomena of different designations.
  • 45. These are all occurrences whose inner connection is expressed 10 The Psychology of Errors 11 in the use of the same prefix of designation.1 They are almost all unimportant, generally temporary and without much signifi- cance in the life of the individual. It is only rarely that one of them, such as the phenomenon of losing things, attains to a cer- tain practical importance. For that reason also they do not attract much attention, they arouse only weak affects. It is, therefore, to these phenomena that I would now direct your attention. But you will object, with annoyance: "There are so many sublime riddles in the external world, just as there are in the narrower world of the psychic life, and so many wonders in the field of psychic disturbances which demand and deserve elucidation, that it really seems frivolous to waste labor and interest on such trifles. If you can explain to us how an individual with sound eyes and ears can, in broad daylight, see and hear things that do not exist, or why another individual suddenly believes himself persecuted by those whom up to that time he loved best, or defend, with the most ingenious arguments, delusions which must seem nonsense to any child, then we will be willing to consider psychoanalysis seriously. But if psycho- analysis can do nothing better than to occupy us with the ques- tion of why a speaker used the wrong word, or why a housekeeper mislaid her keys, or such trifles, then we know something better to do with our time and interest." My reply is: "Patience, ladies and gentlemen. I think your
  • 46. criticism is not on the right track. It is true that psychoanalysis cannot boast that it has never occupied itself with trifles. On the contrary, the objects of its observations are generally those simple occurrences which the other sciences have thrown aside as much too insignificant, the waste products of the phenomenal world. But are you not confounding, in your criticism, the sublimity of the problems with the eonspicuousness of their manifestations? Are there not very important things which under certain circumstances, and at certain times, can betray themselves only by very faint signs ? I could easily cite a great many instances of this kind. From what vague signs, for in- stance, do the young gentlemen of this audience conclude that they have won the favor of a lady? Do you await an explicit declaration, an ardent embrace, or does not a glance, scarcely perceptible to others, a fleeting gesture, the prolonging of a *" IW-leistungen." 12 Introduction to Psychoanalysis hand-shake by one second, suffice? And if you are a criminal lawyer, and engaged in the investigation of a murder, do you actually expect the murderer to leave his photograph and address on the scene of the crime, or would you, of necessity, content yourself with fainter and less certain traces of that individual ? Therefore, let us not undervalue small signs; perhaps by means of them we will succeed in getting on the track of greater things. I agree with you that the larger problems of the world and of science have the first claim on our interest. But it is generally of little avail to form the definite resolution to devote oneself to the investigation of this or that problem. Often one does not know in which direction to take the next step. In scientific
  • 47. research it is more fruitful to attempt what happens to be before one at the moment and for whose investigation there is a dis- coverable method. If one does that thoroughly without prejudice or predisposition, one may, with good fortune, and by virtue of the connection which links each thing to every other (hence also the small to the great) discover even from such modest research a point of approach to the study of the big problems." Thus would I answer, in order to secure your attention for the consideration of these apparently insignificant errors made by normal people. At this point, we will question a stranger to psychoanalysis and ask him how he explains these occurrences. His first answer is sure to be, "Oh, they are not worth an explanation; they are merely slight accidents." What does he mean by this? Does he mean to assert that there are any occurrences so insignificant that they fall out of the causal sequence of things, or that they might just as well be something different from what they are ? If an^r one thus denies the deter- mination of natural phenomena at one bach point, he has vitiated the entire scientific viewpoint. One can then point out to him how much more consistent is the religious point of view, when it explicitly asserts that "No sparrow falls from the roof without God's special wish." I imagine our friend will not be willing to follow his first answer to its logical conclusion; he will interrupt and say that if he were to study these things he would probably find an explanation for them. He will say that this is a case of slight functional disturbance, of an in- accurate psychic act whose eausal factors can be outlined. A man who otherwise speaks correctly may make a slip of the tongue— *
  • 48. The Psychology of Errors 13 when he is slightly ill or fatigued; when he is excited* when his attention is concentrated on something else. It is easy to prove these statements. Slips of the tongue do really occur with special frequency when one is tired, when one has a headache or when one is indisposed. Forgetting proper names is a very frequent occurrence under these circumstances. Many persons even recognize the imminence of an indisposition by the inability to recall proper names. Often also one mixes up words or objects during excitement, one picks up the wrong things; and the forgetting of projects, as well as the doing of any num- ber of other unintentional acts, becomes conspicuous when one is distracted; in other words, when one's attention is concen- trated on other things. A familiar instance of such distraction is the professor in Fliegende Blatter, who takes the wrong hat because he is thinking of the problems which he wishes to treat in his next book. Each of us knows from experience some ex- amples of how one can forget projects which one has planned and promises which one has made, because an experience has intervened which has preoccupied one deeply. This seems both comprehensible and irrefutable. It is perhaps not very interesting, not as we expected it to be. But let us consider this explanation of errors. The conditions which have been cited as necessary for the occurrence of these phenomena are not all identical. Illness and disorders of circulation afford a physiological basis. Excitement, fatigue and distraction are conditions of a different sort, which one could designate as psycho-physiological. About these latter it is easy to theorize. Fatigue, as well as distraction, and perhaps also general excite- ment, cause a scattering of the attention which can result in the act in progress not receiving sufficient attention. This act can then be more easily interrupted than usual, and may be in- exactly carried out. A slight illness, or a change in the distribu-
  • 49. tion of blood in the central organ of the nervous system, can have the same effect, inasmuch as it influences the determining factor, the distribution of attention, in a similar way. In all eases, therefore, it is a question of the effects of a distraction of the attention, caused either by organic or psychic factors. But this does not seem to yield much of interest for our psychoanalytic investigation. We might even feel tempted to give up the subject. To be sure, when we look more closely we 14 Introduction to Psychoanalysis find that not everything squares with this attention theory of psychological errors, or that at any rate not everything can be directly deduced from it. We find that such errors and such forgetting occur even when people are not fatigued, distracted or excited, but are in every way in their normal state; unless, in consequence of these errors, one were to attribute to them an excitement which they themselves do not acknowledge. Nor is the mechanism so simple that the success of an act is assured by an intensification of the attention bestowed upon it, and endangered by its diminution. There are many acts which one performs in a purely automatic way and with very little atten- tion, but which are yet carried out quite successfully. The pedestrian who scarcely knows where he is going, nevertheless keeps to the right road and stops at his destination without hav- ing gone astray. At least, this is the rule. The practiced pianist touches the right keys without thinking of them. He may, of course, also make an occasional mistake, but if auto- matic playing increased the likelihood of errors, it would be just the virtuoso whose playing has, through practice, become most automatic, who would be the most exposed to this danger.
  • 50. Yet we see, on the contrary, that many acts are most successfully carried out when they are not the objects of particularly con- centrated attention, and that the mistakes occur just at the point where one is most anxious to be accurate—where a dis- traction of the necessary attention is therefore surely least permissible. One could then say that this is the effect of the "excitement," but we do not understand why the excitement does not intensify the concentration of attention on the goal that is so much desired. If in an important speech or discus- sion anyone says the opposite of what he means, then that can hardly be explained according to the psycho-physiological or the attention theories. There are also many other small phenomena accompanying these errors, which are not understood and which have not been rendered comprehensible to us by these explanations. For in- stance, when one has temporarily forgotten a name, one is annoyed, one is determined to recall it and is unable to give up the attempt. "Why is it that despite his annoyance the indi- vidual cannot succeed, as he wishes, in directing his attention to the word which is "on the tip of his tongue," and which he The Psychology of Errors 15 instantly recognizes when it is pronouneed to him? Or, to take another example, there are cases in which the errors mul- tiply, link themselves together, substitute for each other. The first time one forgets an appointment; the next time, after having made a special resolution not to forget it, one discovers that one has made a mistake in the day or hour. Or one tries by devious means to remember a forgotten word, and in the course of so
  • 51. doing loses track of a second name which would have been of use in finding the first. If one then pursues this second name, a third gets lost, and so on. It is notorious that the same thing can happen in the ease of misprints, which are of oeurse to be considered as errors of the typesetter. A stubborn error of this sort is said to have crept into a Social-Democratic paper, where, in the account of a certain festivity was printed, "Among those present was His Highness, the Clown Prince." The next day a correction was attempted. The paper apologized and said, "The sentence should, of course, have read' The Clown Prince.' " One likes to attribute these occurrences to the printer's devil, to the goblin of the typesetting machine, and the like — figura- tive expressions which at least go beyond a psycho- physiological theory of the misprint. I do not know if you are acquainted with the fact that one can provoke slips of the tongue, can call them forth by sugges- tion, as it were. An anecdote will serve to illustrate this. Once when a novice on the stage was entrusted with the important role in The Maid of Orleans of announcing to the King,'' Conne- table sheathes his sword," the star played the joke of repeating to the frightened beginner during the rehearsal, instead of the text, the following, "Comfortable sends back his steed,"2 and he attained his end. In the performance the unfortunate actor actually made his debut with this distorted announcement; even after he had been amply warned against so doing, or perhaps just for that reason. These little characteristics of errors are not exactly illuminated by the theory of diverted attention. But that does not neces- sarily prove the whole theory wrong. There is perhaps some- thing missing, a complement by the addition of which the theory 2 In the German, the correct announcement is, tf Connetable
  • 52. schickt sein Bchwert zuriiek." The novice, as a result of the suggestion, announced instead that " Komfortabel schickt sein Pferd zuriiek." 16 Introduction to Psychoanalysis would be made completely satisfactory. But many of the errors themselves can be regarded from another aspect. Let us select slips of the tongue, as best suited to our purposes. "We might equally well choose slips of the pen or of reading. But at this point, we must make clear to ourselves the fact that so far we have inquired only as to when and under what con- ditions one's tongue slips, and have received an answer on this point only. One can, however, direct one's interest elsewhere and ask why one makes just this particular slip and no other; one can consider what the slip results in. You must realize that as long as one does not answer this question—does not explain the effect produced by the slip—the phenomenon in its psycho- logical aspect remains an accident, even if its physiological ex- planation has been found. When it happens that I commit a slip of the tongue, I could obviously make any one of an in- finite number of slips, and in place of the one right word say any one of a thousand others, make innumerable distortions of the right word. Now, is there anything which forces upon me in a specific instance just this one special slip out of all those which are possible, or does that remain accidental and arbitrary, and can nothing rational be found in answer to this question ? Two authors, Meringer and Mayer (a philologist and a psychi- atrist) did indeed in 1895 make the attempt to approach the problem of slips of the tongue from this side. They collected examples and first treated them from a purely descriptive stand-
  • 53. point. That, of course, does not yet furnish any explanation, but may open the way to one. They differentiated the distortions which the intended phrase suffered through the slip, into: inter- changes of positions of words, interchanges of parts of words, perseverations, compoundings and substitutions. I will give you examples of these authors' main categories. It is a case of interchange of the first sort if someone says "the Milo of Venus" instead of "the Venus of Milo." An example of the second type of interchange, " I had a blush of rood to the head" instead of "rush of blood"; a perseveration would be the familiar mis- placed toast, " I ask you to join me in hiccoughing the health of our chief."8 These three forms of slips are not very frequent. You will find those cases much more frequent in which the slip results from a drawing together or compounding of syllables ,• •"Aufstossen" instead of " anstossen." The Psychology of Errors 17 for example, a gentleman on the street addresses a lady with the words, " I f you will allow me, madame, I should be very glad to inscort you."* In the compounded word there is ob- viously besides the word "escort," also the word "insult" (and parenthetically we may remark that the young man will not find much favor with the lady). As an example of the substitution, Meringer and Mayer cite the following: " A man says, ' I put the specimens in the letterbox,' instead of 'in the hot-bed,' and the like."6 The explanation which the two authors attempt to formulate on the basis of this collection of examples is peculiarly inade- quate. They hold that the sounds and syllables of words have different values, and that the production and perception of
  • 54. more highly valued syllables can interfere with those of lower values. They obviously base this conclusion on the cases of fore- sounding and perseveration which are not at all frequent; in other cases of slips of the tongue the question of such sound priorities, if any exist, does not enter at all. The most frequent cases of slips of the tongue are those in which instead of a cer- tain word one says another which resembles it; and one may consider this resemblance sufficient explanation. For example, a professor says in his initial lecture, " I am not inclined to evaluate the merits of my predecessor."6 Or another professor says, " I n the case of the female genital, despite many tempta- tions . . . I mean many attempts . . . etc."7 The most common, and also the most conspicuous form of slips of the tongue, however, is that of saying the exact opposite of what one meant to say. In such cases, one goes far afield from the problem of sound relations and resemblance effects, and can cite, instead of these, the fact that opposites have an obviously close relationship to each other, and have particularly close relations in the psychology of association. There are his* torical examples of this sort. A president of our House of Eep- resentatives once opened the assembly with the words, "Gentle* men, I declare a quorum present, and herewith declare thG assembly closed." *"Begleit-digen" compounded of "begleiten" and "beleidigen." U( Briefkasten" instead of ' ' Briitkasten." ct< Geneigt " instead of " geeignet." *' * Versuchungen ' ' instead of ' ' Versuche.'' f 8 Introduction to Psychoanalysis Similar, in its trickiness, to the relation of opposites is the
  • 55. effect of any other facile association which may under certain circumstances arise most inopportunely. Thus, for instance, there is the story which relates that on the occasion of a festivity in honor of the marriage of a child of H. Helmholtz with a child of the well-known discoverer and captain of industry, W. Siemon, the famous physiologist Dubois-Reymond was asked to speak. He concluded his undoubtedly sparkling toast with the words, "Success to the new firm—Siemens and—Halskit" That, of course, was the name of the well-known old firm. The association of the two names must have been about as easy for a native of Berlin as "Weber and Fields" to an American. Thus we must add to the sound relations and word resem- blances the influence of word associations. But that is not all. In a series of cases, an explanation of the observed slip is un- successful unless we take into account what phrase had been said or even thought previously. This again makes it a case of perseveration of the sort stressed by Meringer, but of a longer duration. I must admit, I am on the whole of the impression that we are further than ever from an explanation of slips of the tongue! However, I hope I am not wrong when I say that during the above investigation of these examples of slips of the tongue, we have all obtained a new impression on which it will be of value to dwell. "We sought the general conditions under which slips of the tongue occur, and then the influences which determine the kind of distortion resulting from the slip, but we have in no way yet considered the effect of the slip of the tongue in itself, without regard to its origin. And if we should decide to do so we must finally have the courage to assert, " I n some of the examples cited, the product of the slip also makes sense." What do we mean by " i t makes sense"? It means, I think, that the product of the slip has itself a right to be considered as a
  • 56. valid psychic act which also has its purpose, as a manifestation having content and meaning. Hitherto we have always spoken of errors, but now it seems as if sometimes the error itself were quite a normal act, except that it has thrust itself into the place of some other expected or intended act. In isolated cases this valid meaning seems obvious and unmis- takable. When the president with his opening words closes the The Psychology of Errors 19 session of the House of Representatives, instead of opening it, we are inclined to consider this error meaningful by reason of our knowledge of the circumstances under which the slip occurred. He expects no good of the assembly, and would be glad if he could terminate it immediately. The pointing out of this mean- ing, the interpretation of this error, gives us no difficulty. Or a lady, pretending to admire, says to another, " I am sure you must have messed up this charming hat yourself.' '8 No scientific quibbles in the world can keep us from discovering in this slip the idea "this hat is a mess." Or a lady who is known for her energetic disposition, relates, "My husband asked the doctor to what diet he should keep. But the doctor said he didn 't need any diet, he should eat and drink whatever I want." This slip of tongue is quite an unmistakable expression of a consistent purpose. Ladies and gentlemen, if it should turn out that not only a few cases of slips of the tongue and of errors in general, but the larger part of them, have a meaning, then this meaning of errors of which we have hitherto made no mention, will un-
  • 57. avoidably become of the greatest interest to us and will, with justice, force all other points of view into the background. We could then ignore all physiological and psycho-physiological con- ditions and devote ourselves to the purely psychological investi- gations of the sense, that is, the meaning, the purpose of these errors. To this end therefore we will not fail, shortly, to study a more extensive compilation of material. But before we undertake this task, I should like to invite you to follow another line of thought with me. It has repeatedly happened that a poet has made use of slips of the tongue or some other error as a means of poetic presentation. This fact in itself must prove to us that he considers the error, the slip of the tongue for instance, as meaningful; for he creates it on purpose, and it is not a case of the poet committing an acci- dental slip of the pen and then letting his pen-slip stand as a tongue-slip of his character. He wants to make something clear to us by this slip of the tongue, and we may examine what it is, whether he wishes to indicate by this that the person in question is distracted or fatigued. Of course, we do not wish to exagger- ate the importance of the fact that the poet did mak$ use of •*' Aufgepatzt " instead of " aufgeputrit." 20 Introduction to Psychoanalysis a slip to express his meaning. It could nevertheless really be a psychic accident, or meaningful only in very rare cases, and the poet would still retain the right to infuse it with meaning through his setting. As to their poetic use, however, it would not be surprising if we should glean more information concern- ing slips of the tongue from the poet than from the philologist or the psychiatrist.
  • 58. Such an example of a slip of the tongue occurs in Wallenstein {Piccolomini, Act 1, Scene 5). In the previous scene, Max Pic- colomini has most passionately sided with the Herzog, and dilated ardently on the blessings of peace which disclosed themselves to him during the trip on which he accompanied Wallenstein's daughter to the camp. He leaves his father and the courtier, Questenberg, plunged in deepest consternation. And then the fifth scene continues: Q. Alas! Alas! and stands it so ? What friend! and do we let him go away In this delusion—let him go away ? Not call him back immediately, not open His eyes upon the spot ? OCTAVIO. {Recovering himself out of a deep study) He has now opened mine, And I see more than pleases me. Q. What is it? OCTAVIO. A curse on this journey! Q. But why so ? What is it ? OCTAVIO.
  • 59. Come, come along, friend! I must follow up The ominous track immediately. Mine eyes Are opened now, and I must use them. Come! (Draws Q. on with him.) Q- What now ? Wh ere go you then ? The Psychology of Errors 21 OCTAVIO. (Hastily.) To her herself To— OCTAVIO. (Interrupting him and correcting himself.) To the duke. Come, let us go—. Octavio meant to say, "To him, to the lord," but his tongue Blips and through his words "to her" he betrays to us, at least, the fact that he had quite clearly recognized the influence which makes the young war hero dream of peace. A still more impressive example was found by 0 . Bank in Shakespeare. It occurs in the Merchant of Venice, in the famous scene in which the fortunate suitor makes his choice among the three caskets; and perhaps I can do no better than to read to you here Rank's short account of the incident: " A slip of the tongue which occurs in Shakespeare's Merchant
  • 60. of Venice, Act III, Scene II, is exceedingly delicate in its poetic motivation and technically brilliant in its handling. Like the slip in Wallenstein quoted by Freud (Psychopathology of Everyday Life, 2d ed., p. 48), it shows that the poets well know the meaning of these errors and assume their compre- hensibility to the audience. Portia, who by her father's wish has been bound to the choice of a husband by lot, has so far escaped all her unfavored suitors through the fortunes of chance. Since she has finally found in Bassanio the suitor to whom she is attached, she fears that he, too, will choose the wrong casket. She would like to tell him that even in that event he may rest assured of her love, but is prevented from so doing by her oath. In this inner conflict the poet makes her say to the welcome suitor: PORTIA : I pray you tarry; pause a day or two, Before you hazard; for, in choosing wrong I lose your company; therefore, forbear a while: There's something tells me, (but it is not love) I would not lose you: * * * • * * I could teach you How to choose right, but then I am forsworn, 22 Introduction to Psychoanalysis So will I never be: so may you miss me ; But if you do, you 11 make me wish, a sin That I had been forsworn. Beshrew your eyes. They have o'erlook'd me, and divided me; One half of me is yours, the other half yours, Mine own, I would say: but if mine, then yours, And so all yours.
  • 61. Just that, therefore, which she meant merely to indicate faintly to him or really to conceal from him entirely, namely that even before the choice of the lot she was his and loved him, this the poet—with admirable psychological delicacy of feeling—makes apparent by her slip; and is able, by this artistic device, to quiet the unbearable uncertainty of the lover, as well as the equal sus- pense of the audience as to the issue of the choice." Notice, at the end, how subtly Portia reconciles the two decla- rations which are contained in the slip, how she resolves the contradiction between them and finally still manages to keep her promise: <<# # # k ^ ^ m j n e > then yours, And so all yours." Another thinker, alien to the field of medicine, accidentally disclosed the meaning of errors by an observation which has anticipated our attempts at explanation. You all know the clever satires of Lichtenberg (1742-1749), of which Goethe said, *' Where he jokes, there lurks a problem concealed." Not infrequently the joke also brings to light the solution of the problem. Lichten- berg mentions in his jokes and satiric comments the remark that he always read "Agamemnon" for "angenomen,"9 so intently had he read Homer. Herein is really contained the whole theory of misreadings. At the next session we will see whether we can agree with the poets in their conception of the meaning of psychological errors. •*' Angenomen " is a verb, meaning " to aecepK"