SlideShare a Scribd company logo
1 of 11
Download to read offline
Please	
  refer	
  to	
  the	
  published	
  version	
  in	
  3:AM	
  Magazine:	
  
http://www.3ammagazine.com/3am/reality-­‐and-­‐its-­‐dreams/	
  	
  
	
  
Raymond	
  Geuss,	
  Reality	
  and	
  Its	
  Dreams	
  
Harvard	
  University	
  Press,	
  Cambridge,	
  Massachusetts	
  and	
  London,	
  England,	
  2016.	
  
312	
  pp.,	
  £	
  25.00	
  hb.	
  
ISBN	
  9780674504950	
  
	
  
Reviewed	
  by	
  John	
  Rapko	
  
	
  
	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  Raymond	
  Geuss’s	
  latest	
  collection	
  of	
  essays,	
  Reality	
  and	
  Its	
  Dreams,	
  discusses	
  a	
  
range	
  of	
  topics	
  unusually	
  wide	
  even	
  for	
  Geuss.	
  Earlier	
  books	
  of	
  his	
  juxtaposed	
  
discussions	
  of	
  ancient	
  Greek	
  and	
  Roman	
  philosophy	
  and	
  poetry	
  with	
  sympathetic	
  
reconstructive	
  accounts	
  of	
  German	
  philosophers,	
  especially	
  Marx,	
  Nietzsche,	
  and	
  
Adorno,	
  and	
  largely	
  critical	
  accounts	
  of	
  Kant,	
  John	
  Rawls,	
  and	
  Robert	
  Nozick.	
  The	
  
new	
  book	
  contains	
  discussion	
  of	
  all	
  of	
  these,	
  but	
  expands	
  an	
  interest	
  exhibited	
  in	
  his	
  
two	
  prior	
  collections	
  in	
  addressing	
  contemporary	
  political	
  and	
  artistic	
  phenomena,	
  
including	
  some	
  contemporary	
  paintings,	
  a	
  recent	
  play	
  about	
  a	
  Holocaust	
  survivor,	
  
and	
  the	
  political	
  thought	
  of	
  the	
  British	
  comedian	
  Russell	
  Brand.	
  Geuss	
  proposes	
  that	
  
what	
  unites	
  these	
  essays	
  is	
  the	
  concern	
  to	
  attack	
  ‘normativism’,	
  a	
  philosophical	
  
orientation	
  that	
  aims	
  to	
  present	
  an	
  abstract	
  and	
  unified	
  set	
  of	
  criteria	
  for	
  evaluating	
  
and	
  judging	
  the	
  legitimacy	
  of	
  social	
  and	
  political	
  phenomena	
  and	
  practices.	
  One	
  of	
  
the	
  motifs	
  of	
  Geuss’s	
  political	
  thought	
  is	
  that	
  political	
  utterances	
  are	
  never	
  merely	
  
statements	
  of	
  doctrine,	
  but	
  also	
  actions.	
  Where	
  normativism	
  constructs	
  political	
  
concepts	
  and	
  judgments	
  prior	
  to	
  or	
  in	
  abstraction	
  from	
  their	
  concrete	
  contexts,	
  
Geuss	
  considers	
  and	
  criticizes	
  normativism	
  in	
  light	
  of	
  the	
  actions	
  it	
  motivates	
  and	
  
the	
  guidance	
  for	
  practices	
  it	
  provides.	
  Another	
  motif	
  is	
  that	
  orientations	
  and	
  
doctrines	
  are	
  variously	
  and	
  to	
  various	
  degrees	
  embodied	
  in	
  acts,	
  practices,	
  and	
  
institutions.	
  Geuss’s	
  criticism	
  of	
  normativisim	
  is	
  accordingly	
  not	
  only	
  a	
  critical	
  
account	
  and	
  rejection	
  of	
  certain	
  philosophical	
  doctrines,	
  but	
  also	
  a	
  defense	
  against	
  
certain	
  kinds	
  of	
  political	
  speech	
  that	
  are	
  ignored	
  or	
  slighted	
  by	
  normativist	
  thinkers,	
  
and	
  a	
  critique	
  of	
  political	
  institutions	
  and	
  practices	
  to	
  the	
  degree	
  that	
  they	
  embody	
  
4normativist	
  doctrines.	
  	
  
	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  The	
  central	
  characteristic	
  of	
  normativism	
  as	
  a	
  philosophical	
  orientation	
  is	
  the	
  
assumption	
  that	
  there	
  is	
  a	
  ‘realm’	
  consisting	
  of	
  principles,	
  claims,	
  concepts	
  et	
  alia,	
  
that	
  is	
  in	
  conception	
  distinct	
  and	
  underived	
  from	
  how	
  the	
  world	
  or,	
  perhaps	
  better,	
  
empirical	
  reality	
  is.	
  Normativist	
  philosophers	
  disagree	
  on	
  the	
  contents	
  of	
  this	
  realm	
  
and	
  the	
  relation	
  it	
  bears	
  to	
  empirical	
  reality,	
  but	
  they	
  are	
  united	
  in	
  thinking	
  that	
  	
  
appeals	
  to	
  inquiries	
  or	
  results	
  in	
  anthropology,	
  sociology,	
  psychology,	
  or	
  history	
  
play	
  no	
  role	
  in	
  determining	
  the	
  contents	
  of	
  this	
  realm.	
  Rather,	
  one	
  arrives	
  at	
  the	
  
contents	
  through	
  on	
  or	
  another	
  of	
  both	
  of	
  two	
  methods:	
  eliciting	
  ‘intuitions’	
  and	
  
constructing	
  thought	
  experiments.	
  Say	
  I’m	
  a	
  capable	
  swimmer,	
  and	
  I	
  see	
  two	
  people,	
  
a	
  child	
  and	
  an	
  adult,	
  floundering	
  in	
  the	
  ocean.	
  Who	
  should	
  I	
  attempt	
  to	
  save	
  first,	
  
and	
  why?	
  Although	
  in	
  the	
  hands	
  of	
  any	
  particular	
  philosopher	
  the	
  results	
  of	
  
applying	
  these	
  methods	
  may	
  be	
  extremely	
  intricate,	
  it	
  is	
  further	
  assumed	
  by	
  
normativist	
  philosophers	
  that	
  the	
  resulting	
  structure	
  must	
  be	
  coherent;	
  but	
  what	
  
the	
  criteria	
  of	
  coherence	
  are	
  and	
  what	
  counts	
  as	
  coherent	
  are	
  themselves	
  matters	
  of	
  
dispute	
  among	
  normativists.	
  
	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  Geuss	
  claims	
  that	
  in	
  political	
  philosophy	
  there	
  has	
  been	
  a	
  kind	
  of	
  ‘normative	
  turn’,	
  
analogous	
  to	
  the	
  ‘linguistic	
  turn’	
  diagnosed	
  by	
  the	
  philosopher	
  Richard	
  Rorty	
  in	
  the	
  
1970’s.	
  In	
  the	
  ‘linguistic	
  turn’	
  philosophers	
  passed	
  from	
  treating	
  philosophical	
  
activity	
  as	
  the	
  analysis	
  of	
  concepts	
  to	
  one	
  basically	
  engaged	
  in	
  the	
  analysis	
  of	
  bits	
  of	
  
language.	
  In	
  the	
  ‘normative	
  turn’	
  philosophy	
  passes	
  from	
  historically	
  informed	
  and	
  
socially	
  diagnostic	
  works	
  such	
  as	
  Simone	
  de	
  Beauvoir’s	
  The	
  Second	
  Sex,	
  Herbert	
  
Marcuse’s	
  One-­Dimensional	
  Man,	
  and	
  Guy	
  Debord’s	
  Society	
  of	
  the	
  Spectacle	
  to	
  works	
  
aiming	
  to	
  analyze	
  concepts	
  such	
  as	
  ‘justice’	
  or	
  ‘rights’,	
  but	
  without	
  reference	
  to	
  their	
  
historical	
  development	
  or	
  social	
  embodiment	
  in	
  practices	
  and	
  institutions.	
  The	
  
paradigmatic	
  works	
  of	
  the	
  incipient	
  normative	
  political	
  philosophy	
  of	
  the	
  1970’s	
  are	
  
John	
  Rawls’s	
  A	
  Theory	
  of	
  Justice	
  (1971)	
  and	
  Robert	
  Nozick’s	
  Anarchy,	
  State,	
  and	
  
Utopia	
  (1974).	
  In	
  that	
  same	
  decade	
  one	
  sees	
  the	
  beginnings	
  of	
  our	
  period	
  of	
  political	
  
reaction	
  that	
  soon	
  effloresced	
  under	
  Margaret	
  Thatcher	
  in	
  the	
  United	
  Kingdom	
  and	
  
Ronald	
  Reagan	
  in	
  the	
  United	
  States.	
  Geuss	
  sees	
  an	
  elective	
  affinity	
  between	
  
normativism	
  in	
  political	
  philosophy	
  and	
  political	
  reaction	
  in	
  the	
  former’s	
  attempt	
  to	
  
draw	
  attention	
  away	
  from	
  historically	
  concrete	
  and	
  complex	
  instances	
  of	
  
oppression,	
  exploitation,	
  alienation,	
  and	
  above	
  all	
  inequality.	
  Political	
  reaction	
  and	
  
normativist	
  political	
  philosophy	
  likewise	
  treat	
  politics	
  as	
  a	
  kind	
  of	
  applied	
  morality,	
  
wherein	
  judgments	
  are	
  made	
  and	
  actions	
  motivated	
  in	
  terms	
  of	
  simple	
  dichotomies.	
  
Geuss’s	
  favored	
  example	
  is	
  Tony	
  Blair’s	
  attempt	
  to	
  justify	
  the	
  invasion	
  of	
  Iraq	
  with	
  
the	
  simple	
  statement:	
  ‘Saddam	
  Hussein	
  is	
  evil’.	
  Insofar	
  as	
  normativist	
  political	
  
philosophy	
  deigns	
  to	
  examine	
  the	
  world,	
  it	
  contents	
  itself	
  with	
  simple	
  judgments	
  of	
  
approval	
  and	
  disapproval,	
  issued	
  without	
  reflection	
  upon	
  historical	
  and	
  contextual	
  
considerations.	
  Geuss	
  likens	
  the	
  claim	
  to	
  authority	
  of	
  such	
  judgments	
  to	
  that	
  
claimed	
  by	
  main	
  lines	
  of	
  Christian	
  preaching:	
  the	
  categorical	
  framework	
  is	
  never	
  
called	
  into	
  question,	
  and	
  the	
  very	
  articulation	
  and	
  uttering	
  of	
  the	
  judgment	
  would	
  
allegedly	
  convince	
  any	
  uncorrupted	
  person	
  of	
  its	
  rightness.	
  
	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  Geuss	
  here	
  and	
  in	
  previous	
  books	
  presents	
  an	
  array	
  of	
  arguments	
  against	
  the	
  
basic	
  conceptual	
  moves	
  of	
  normativist	
  philosophy.	
  His	
  core	
  objections	
  are	
  that	
  its	
  
elaborate	
  conceptual	
  structures	
  are	
  invariably	
  based	
  upon	
  simplistic	
  and	
  naïve	
  
conceptions	
  of	
  actual	
  human	
  life;	
  and	
  further	
  that	
  because	
  of	
  the	
  abstractness	
  of	
  the	
  
constructions	
  and	
  their	
  great	
  distance	
  from	
  actual	
  political	
  problems	
  and	
  
historically	
  specific	
  cultural	
  diagnoses	
  results,	
  in	
  practice	
  they	
  cannot	
  but	
  help	
  
function	
  as	
  compensatory	
  phantasies	
  for	
  academics,	
  who	
  feel	
  themselves	
  to	
  be	
  
clever	
  in	
  pondering	
  and	
  analyzing	
  the	
  intricacies	
  of	
  the	
  structures	
  and	
  somehow	
  in	
  
contact	
  with	
  realities	
  more	
  profound	
  than	
  those	
  of	
  everyday	
  instances	
  of	
  power,	
  
oppression,	
  and	
  inequality.	
  As	
  such,	
  normativism	
  never	
  issues	
  in	
  imaginative	
  
projects	
  aiming	
  at	
  fundamental	
  reforms	
  or	
  revolutionary	
  proposals.	
  Instead,	
  
normativist	
  political	
  philosophy,	
  when	
  not	
  simply	
  ratifying	
  and	
  providing	
  an	
  
ideological	
  justification	
  for	
  current	
  conditions,	
  can	
  at	
  most	
  recommend	
  small	
  
palliative	
  measures.	
  For	
  there	
  to	
  be	
  some	
  trickling	
  down	
  of	
  wealth	
  under	
  our	
  ever-­‐
intensifying	
  global	
  conditions	
  of	
  massive	
  inequality,	
  normativists	
  fret	
  over	
  just	
  how	
  
many	
  centimeters	
  the	
  spigot	
  should	
  be	
  turned.	
  	
  
	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  In	
  his	
  thoroughgoing	
  rejection	
  of	
  normativism,	
  Geuss	
  is	
  close	
  to	
  the	
  thought	
  of	
  
John	
  Dewey,	
  particularly	
  in	
  how	
  both	
  see	
  the	
  appeal	
  of	
  dualisms,	
  especially	
  the	
  
distinction	
  between	
  the	
  empirical	
  and	
  the	
  ideal,	
  as	
  stemming	
  from	
  the	
  failure	
  of	
  
imagination	
  and	
  a	
  panicked	
  reaction	
  the	
  supposed	
  threat	
  of	
  relativism.	
  Geuss	
  
diagnoses	
  the	
  appeal	
  of	
  normativism	
  as	
  stemming	
  from	
  the	
  acceptance	
  of	
  a	
  single	
  
and	
  spectacularly	
  bad	
  argument	
  dubbed	
  ‘The	
  Platonist	
  Blackmail’:	
  ‘if	
  you	
  do	
  not	
  
have	
  a	
  guide	
  to	
  action	
  that	
  is	
  absolute	
  [sic]	
  certain	
  and	
  absolute	
  [sic]	
  universal,	
  you	
  
have	
  nothing	
  at	
  all.”	
  (60)	
  Against	
  this	
  Geuss	
  asserts,	
  first,	
  that	
  it	
  is	
  simply	
  false	
  to	
  say	
  
that	
  human	
  beings	
  require	
  access	
  and	
  adherence	
  to	
  some	
  ultimate	
  framework	
  for	
  
routinely	
  successful	
  orientation	
  and	
  guidance	
  in	
  everyday	
  actions.	
  His	
  preferred	
  
example	
  is	
  thirst:	
  if	
  I’m	
  thirsty	
  and	
  am	
  told	
  that	
  there’s	
  a	
  water	
  fountain	
  over	
  there	
  
to	
  the	
  left,	
  I	
  need	
  no	
  systematic	
  theory	
  for	
  action;	
  when	
  I	
  head	
  off	
  in	
  that	
  direction,	
  I	
  
am	
  not	
  acting	
  randomly.	
  Secondly,	
  and	
  rapidly	
  generalizing,	
  Geuss	
  further	
  asserts	
  
that	
  we	
  need	
  no	
  “single	
  systematic	
  theory	
  that	
  provides	
  us,	
  either	
  individually	
  or	
  
collectively,	
  with	
  a	
  certain	
  way	
  of	
  proceeding	
  in	
  all	
  situations.”	
  Instead	
  we	
  should	
  
treat	
  the	
  need	
  for	
  orientation	
  as	
  piecemeal	
  and	
  context-­‐specific,	
  and	
  accordingly	
  
something	
  that	
  may	
  well	
  be	
  satisfied	
  through	
  pragmatically	
  organized	
  activities	
  of	
  
“observation,	
  theorization,	
  and	
  rational	
  argumentation.”	
  (61)	
  Another	
  way	
  of	
  
putting	
  this	
  point	
  would	
  be	
  to	
  say	
  that	
  there	
  are	
  no	
  context-­‐free	
  needs	
  for	
  human	
  
beings	
  aside	
  from	
  whatever	
  is	
  required	
  for	
  the	
  sustainability	
  of	
  individual	
  lives	
  and	
  
collective	
  life;	
  a	
  potentially	
  fruitful	
  response	
  to	
  an	
  emergent,	
  contingent,	
  and	
  local	
  
need	
  for	
  orientation	
  is	
  rightly	
  understood	
  as	
  an	
  imaginative	
  response,	
  one	
  that	
  
arises	
  precisely	
  because	
  the	
  existing	
  state	
  of	
  affairs	
  is	
  unsatisfactory	
  and	
  does	
  not	
  
obviously	
  offer	
  the	
  resources	
  for	
  finding	
  one’s	
  way	
  out.	
  Normativism	
  understood	
  as	
  
an	
  imaginative	
  construct	
  is	
  a	
  notably	
  fruitless	
  and	
  impoverishing	
  way	
  of	
  answering	
  
this	
  need.	
  
	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  The	
  second	
  focus	
  of	
  the	
  book	
  is	
  an	
  attack	
  on	
  neoliberalism	
  in	
  the	
  forms	
  of	
  
excavating	
  and	
  scrutinizing	
  into	
  most	
  basic	
  conceptions	
  and	
  assumptions.	
  As	
  the	
  
dominant	
  ideology	
  of	
  capitalism	
  in	
  its	
  latest	
  phase,	
  one	
  that	
  emerges	
  in	
  the	
  1970’s	
  
and	
  works	
  for	
  justifying	
  the	
  current	
  period	
  of	
  political	
  reaction	
  marked	
  by	
  the	
  
ascendency	
  of	
  Margaret	
  Thatcher	
  and	
  Ronald	
  Reagan.	
  As	
  an	
  ideology	
  governing	
  
political	
  and	
  economic	
  activity	
  in	
  the	
  past	
  forty	
  years,	
  neoliberalism	
  is	
  marked	
  by	
  an	
  
overriding	
  concern	
  with	
  individual	
  liberty	
  secured	
  by	
  property	
  rights,	
  a	
  rejection	
  of	
  
collective	
  control	
  and	
  public	
  ownership	
  of	
  the	
  means	
  and	
  conditions	
  of	
  social	
  life,	
  
and	
  the	
  attempt	
  to	
  treat	
  all	
  spheres	
  of	
  human	
  life	
  as	
  analogous	
  to,	
  or	
  indeed	
  as	
  
constituted	
  by,	
  market	
  relations.	
  Neoliberalism	
  is	
  “constituted	
  by	
  two	
  theses”:	
  (a)	
  
“the	
  good	
  life	
  must	
  be	
  the	
  life	
  of	
  the	
  human	
  individual,	
  and	
  its	
  goodness	
  is	
  
constituted	
  by	
  a	
  triad	
  of	
  three	
  components:	
  welfare,	
  as	
  measured	
  by	
  the	
  level	
  of	
  
access	
  to	
  goods	
  and	
  services,	
  the	
  satisfaction	
  of	
  desire,	
  and	
  freedom”;	
  (b)	
  the	
  theory	
  
of	
  the	
  free	
  market,	
  wherein	
  independent	
  individuals	
  exchange	
  goods	
  and	
  services	
  
without	
  thereby	
  drawing	
  from	
  or	
  developing	
  further	
  social	
  relations	
  among	
  
themselves.	
  (154)	
  A	
  typical	
  neoliberal	
  position	
  derives	
  from,	
  exaggerates,	
  and	
  
dramatizes	
  an	
  inflated	
  terminology	
  of	
  the	
  anti-­‐paternalist	
  strain	
  of	
  classical	
  
liberalism,	
  a	
  strain	
  that	
  starts	
  with	
  the	
  insistence	
  that	
  in	
  every	
  case	
  an	
  individual	
  is	
  
or	
  should	
  be	
  the	
  final	
  arbiter	
  of	
  what	
  is	
  good	
  for	
  herself.	
  The	
  neoliberal	
  demands	
  
that	
  everyone’s	
  desires	
  and	
  preferences	
  be	
  taken	
  at	
  face	
  value	
  and	
  be	
  given	
  equal	
  
weight	
  in	
  public	
  deliberation	
  and	
  political	
  activity.	
  Additionally,	
  the	
  neoliberal	
  
position	
  treats	
  the	
  free	
  market	
  as	
  the	
  ideal	
  social	
  mechanism	
  for	
  making	
  the	
  good	
  
life	
  available,	
  both	
  for	
  individuals	
  qua	
  individuals,	
  and	
  for	
  individuals	
  treated	
  as	
  
parts	
  of	
  aggregates.	
  
	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  Geuss	
  raises	
  a	
  range	
  of	
  considerations	
  against	
  both	
  these	
  in	
  aiming	
  to	
  undermine	
  
their	
  seeming	
  attractiveness	
  and/or	
  inevitability.	
  With	
  regard	
  to	
  the	
  model	
  of	
  a	
  free	
  
and	
  self-­‐regulating	
  market,	
  Geuss	
  concedes	
  a	
  degree	
  of	
  plausibility	
  to	
  neoliberalism	
  
during	
  its	
  triumphant	
  first	
  phase	
  from	
  the	
  late	
  1970’s	
  through	
  2008.	
  However,	
  the	
  
aftermath	
  of	
  the	
  economic	
  downturn	
  shows	
  quite	
  plainly	
  that	
  existing	
  markets	
  and	
  
their	
  mechanisms	
  are	
  not	
  in	
  any	
  sense	
  self-­‐regulating.	
  The	
  chapter	
  ‘Economies:	
  
Good,	
  Bad,	
  and	
  Indifferent’	
  presents	
  Geuss’s	
  most	
  sustained	
  criticism	
  of	
  the	
  
neoliberal	
  model	
  of	
  a	
  free	
  market.	
  He	
  attacks	
  the	
  psychological	
  and	
  anthropological	
  
preconceptions	
  of	
  the	
  free	
  market	
  model.	
  In	
  that	
  model	
  buyers	
  and	
  sellers	
  are	
  first	
  
characterized	
  by	
  the	
  possession	
  of	
  a	
  set	
  of	
  desires	
  and	
  preferences	
  considered	
  in	
  
abstraction	
  from	
  how	
  they	
  were	
  acquired,	
  from	
  the	
  advisability	
  of	
  satisfying	
  them,	
  
or	
  from	
  the	
  possibilities	
  of	
  transforming	
  them.	
  There	
  is	
  no	
  significant	
  conceptual	
  
distinction	
  between	
  desires	
  and	
  preferences;	
  both	
  are	
  typically	
  latent	
  
characteristics	
  of	
  consumers	
  that	
  are	
  activated	
  under	
  contingent	
  market	
  
circumstances	
  regarding	
  the	
  availability	
  of	
  particular	
  goods	
  the	
  promise	
  of	
  which	
  
would	
  prima	
  facie	
  satisfy	
  some	
  pre-­‐existent	
  desire.	
  So	
  prior	
  to	
  the	
  marketing	
  of	
  a	
  
certain	
  kind	
  of	
  car,	
  one	
  has	
  no	
  overt	
  desire	
  for	
  this	
  car.	
  But	
  once	
  marketed,	
  the	
  car	
  
activates	
  consumers’	
  desire	
  for	
  it,	
  perhaps	
  so	
  intensely	
  that	
  they	
  think	
  of	
  themselves	
  
as	
  ‘needing’	
  the	
  car.	
  Since	
  the	
  free	
  market	
  model	
  is	
  abstracted	
  from	
  history,	
  in	
  
particular	
  from	
  the	
  sorts	
  of	
  changes	
  in	
  social	
  possibilities	
  of	
  human	
  development	
  
that	
  Marx	
  viewed	
  as	
  partially	
  inducing	
  the	
  emergence	
  of	
  new	
  needs,	
  its	
  conception	
  
of	
  human	
  nature	
  is	
  static,	
  and	
  it	
  can	
  only	
  conceptualize	
  emergent	
  desires	
  as	
  the	
  
activation	
  of	
  some	
  prior	
  disposition.	
  The	
  individual’s	
  set	
  of	
  desires	
  as	
  such	
  is	
  
unchanging.	
  
	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  Against	
  this	
  narrow	
  conception	
  Geuss	
  brings	
  three	
  points:	
  First,	
  the	
  presupposed	
  
conception	
  of	
  the	
  economy	
  fails	
  to	
  include	
  considerations	
  of	
  sustainability.	
  Second,	
  
the	
  kinds	
  of	
  consideration	
  addressed	
  by	
  a	
  conception	
  of	
  the	
  economy	
  that	
  is	
  suitably	
  
capacious	
  to	
  include	
  sustainability	
  cannot	
  be	
  restricted	
  to	
  (pre-­‐existent)	
  desires	
  and	
  
preferences,	
  but	
  must	
  also	
  include	
  needs	
  and	
  interests.	
  Needs,	
  desires,	
  and	
  interests	
  
are	
  irreducible	
  to	
  each	
  other,	
  and	
  are	
  all	
  subject	
  to	
  historical	
  variation	
  and	
  
development.	
  Third,	
  because	
  of	
  its	
  limitation	
  to	
  considerations	
  motivating	
  liberal	
  
anti-­‐paternalism,	
  the	
  free	
  market	
  model	
  blocks	
  the	
  possibility	
  of	
  including	
  
considerations	
  wherein	
  existing	
  desires	
  and	
  preferences	
  might	
  be	
  subjected	
  to	
  
criticism,	
  or	
  might	
  become	
  open	
  to	
  learning	
  and	
  transformation.	
  The	
  free	
  market	
  
model	
  is	
  thus	
  an	
  instance	
  of	
  ‘positivism’	
  in	
  Adorno’s	
  sense,	
  a	
  piece	
  of	
  social	
  ideology	
  
that	
  blocks	
  criticism	
  and	
  discourages	
  acts	
  of	
  collective	
  deliberation	
  and	
  imagination	
  
in	
  the	
  service	
  of	
  transforming	
  societies.	
  
	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  A	
  number	
  of	
  previous	
  reviews	
  of	
  Geuss’s	
  works	
  have	
  disapprovingly	
  noted	
  a	
  tone	
  
of	
  ‘bleakness’	
  there,	
  and	
  complained	
  that	
  the	
  battery	
  of	
  criticisms	
  Geuss	
  brings	
  
against	
  normativist	
  philosophers	
  like	
  Kant	
  and	
  Rawls	
  or	
  liberals	
  like	
  J.S.Mill	
  and	
  
Isaiah	
  Berlin	
  are	
  unconstructive,	
  in	
  that	
  Geuss	
  offers	
  no	
  alternative	
  to	
  the	
  views	
  
criticized.	
  Geuss’s	
  chief	
  implicit	
  response	
  in	
  previous	
  books	
  and	
  elaborated	
  here	
  is	
  
to	
  defend	
  and	
  elaborate	
  another	
  claim	
  of	
  Adorno’s,	
  namely,	
  that	
  one	
  major	
  form	
  of	
  
criticism	
  is	
  ‘internal’.	
  Such	
  criticism	
  is	
  a	
  context-­‐specific	
  activity	
  prominently	
  
involving	
  	
  juxtaposing	
  descriptions	
  of	
  practices	
  with	
  the	
  aims	
  whose	
  realization	
  
might	
  plausibly	
  be	
  thought	
  to	
  guide	
  such	
  practices.	
  The	
  addressee	
  of	
  the	
  criticism	
  is	
  
left	
  to	
  note	
  the	
  lack	
  of	
  fit	
  between	
  the	
  two.	
  Internal	
  criticism,	
  for	
  Geuss	
  as	
  for	
  
Adorno,	
  is	
  not	
  typically	
  ‘productive’	
  in	
  offering	
  a	
  solution	
  for	
  the	
  problems	
  criticized.	
  
But	
  here	
  he	
  also	
  offers	
  a	
  second	
  implicit	
  response	
  to	
  the	
  charge	
  of	
  bleakness	
  in	
  
developing	
  a	
  philosophical	
  account	
  of	
  ‘utopian	
  thinking’,	
  an	
  imaginative	
  activity	
  that	
  
addresses	
  discontents	
  and	
  persistent,	
  unsatisfied	
  desires	
  in	
  the	
  present.	
  The	
  
exploration	
  of	
  utopian	
  thinking	
  in	
  philosophy	
  and	
  the	
  arts	
  is	
  the	
  third	
  focus	
  of	
  the	
  
book.	
  	
  
	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  Geuss	
  forcefully	
  presents	
  the	
  surprising	
  claim	
  that	
  Utopianism	
  is	
  an	
  aspect	
  of	
  
some	
  of	
  the	
  range	
  of	
  theoretical	
  and	
  practical	
  positions	
  grasped	
  under	
  the	
  umbrella	
  
term	
  ‘Realism’.	
  As	
  a	
  theoretical	
  position,	
  Realism	
  is	
  initially	
  negatively	
  characterized	
  
by	
  its	
  rejection	
  of	
  ‘moralism’,	
  which	
  Geuss	
  construes	
  narrowly	
  as	
  views	
  that	
  treat	
  
morality	
  as	
  an	
  absolute	
  and	
  unchanging	
  framework	
  for	
  evaluation.	
  Morality	
  consists	
  
in	
  principles	
  and	
  rules	
  for	
  judgment	
  of	
  the	
  goodness	
  and	
  badness	
  or	
  evil	
  of	
  actions.	
  
Moralism	
  further	
  insists	
  that	
  moral	
  judgments	
  are	
  in	
  a	
  sense	
  self-­‐realizing,	
  in	
  that	
  
the	
  sheer	
  recognition	
  and	
  understanding	
  of	
  the	
  judgment	
  results	
  in	
  the	
  appropriate	
  
attitude	
  of	
  approval	
  or	
  disapproval	
  in	
  the	
  mind	
  of	
  an	
  uncorrupted	
  receiver	
  of	
  the	
  
judgment.	
  The	
  range	
  of	
  Realisms	
  that	
  reject	
  moralism	
  are	
  not	
  as	
  such	
  opposed	
  to	
  
utopian	
  thinking,	
  and	
  Geuss	
  suggests	
  (43)	
  that	
  some	
  incorporate	
  a	
  ‘realistic’	
  (in	
  the	
  
colloquial	
  sense)	
  recognition	
  that	
  in	
  a	
  society	
  the	
  distinction	
  between	
  what	
  is	
  
socially	
  and	
  politically	
  possible	
  and	
  what	
  is	
  impossible	
  is	
  itself	
  “to	
  some	
  extent	
  a	
  
social	
  construct”.	
  The	
  Utopianism	
  that	
  ensues	
  is	
  not	
  the	
  classical	
  sort	
  exemplified	
  by	
  
Plato	
  and	
  Thomas	
  More,	
  one	
  which	
  proposes	
  a	
  ‘perfect’	
  and	
  unchanging	
  society	
  as	
  a	
  
counter-­‐image	
  to	
  our	
  corrupt	
  society,	
  and	
  without	
  specifying	
  mechanisms	
  for	
  
passing	
  from	
  our	
  current	
  state	
  to	
  the	
  perfected	
  state;	
  rather,	
  the	
  Utopian	
  that	
  
attends	
  a	
  range	
  of	
  Realisms	
  involves	
  focusing	
  upon	
  the	
  existing	
  desires	
  within	
  a	
  
present	
  society,	
  and	
  offering	
  proposals	
  for	
  changing	
  society	
  that	
  if	
  enacted	
  would	
  
more	
  fully	
  satisfy	
  the	
  desires	
  than	
  is	
  possible	
  under	
  current	
  arrangements.	
  Some	
  
examples	
  cited	
  by	
  Geuss	
  are	
  Russell	
  Brand’s	
  suggestions	
  that	
  private	
  debt	
  be	
  
cancelled,	
  co-­‐ops	
  created,	
  and	
  the	
  life	
  span	
  of	
  corporations	
  be	
  limited	
  (78);	
  Geuss	
  
correlatively	
  notes	
  that	
  the	
  mainstream	
  academic	
  normativist	
  philosophies	
  of	
  John	
  
Rawls	
  and	
  Robert	
  Nozick,	
  as	
  well	
  as	
  the	
  exemplarily	
  neoliberal	
  thought	
  of	
  Margaret	
  
Thatcher,	
  can	
  offer	
  little	
  or	
  nothing	
  responsive	
  to	
  Utopian	
  desires.	
  
	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  In	
  his	
  previous	
  book	
  Geuss	
  had	
  suggested	
  three	
  means	
  of	
  escape	
  from	
  his	
  own	
  
institutional	
  setting,	
  something	
  motivated	
  by	
  his	
  sense	
  of	
  the	
  institutional	
  world	
  of	
  
teaching	
  philosophy	
  at	
  a	
  university	
  as	
  “a	
  penitential	
  domain	
  of	
  reason-­‐mongering”	
  
(Geuss	
  2014,	
  p.232).	
  One	
  possible	
  escape	
  route	
  is	
  what	
  Hegel	
  and	
  Heidegger	
  
attempted,	
  to	
  turn	
  ratiocination	
  against	
  itself.	
  A	
  second	
  it	
  to	
  act	
  in	
  such	
  a	
  way	
  that	
  
“the	
  spider’s	
  web	
  of	
  bogus	
  rationalizations”	
  is	
  destroyed	
  and	
  new	
  ways	
  of	
  speaking	
  
and	
  new	
  facts	
  are	
  created.	
  Geuss	
  takes	
  the	
  third	
  route:	
  to	
  engage	
  in	
  a	
  kind	
  of	
  
imaginative	
  activity	
  that	
  invites	
  people	
  to	
  observe	
  novel	
  juxtapositions,	
  such	
  as	
  the	
  
images	
  of	
  a	
  Prime	
  Minister	
  addressing	
  the	
  House	
  of	
  Commons	
  placed	
  next	
  to	
  the	
  
image	
  of	
  a	
  pile	
  of	
  corpses.	
  Along	
  with	
  having	
  written	
  and	
  published	
  a	
  small	
  body	
  of	
  
poetry,	
  Geuss	
  here	
  broadens	
  and	
  generalizes	
  this	
  route	
  in	
  several	
  places,	
  especially	
  
in	
  the	
  essay	
  ‘What	
  Time	
  Is	
  It?’,	
  which	
  juxtaposes	
  reflections	
  on	
  a	
  commentary	
  on	
  
Pindar,	
  a	
  performance	
  of	
  a	
  play	
  in	
  Paris,	
  and	
  the	
  conversations	
  after	
  the	
  
performance.	
  	
  
	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  The	
  key	
  desire	
  that	
  Geuss	
  discusses,	
  again	
  arising	
  from	
  the	
  sense	
  of	
  being	
  trapped	
  
in	
  a	
  conformist	
  and	
  repressive	
  verbal	
  universe,	
  is	
  most	
  clearly	
  stated	
  in	
  the	
  previous	
  
book	
  as	
  ‘Anywhere	
  outside	
  this	
  world’.	
  (ibid)	
  The	
  Utopian	
  method	
  that	
  offers	
  an	
  
alternative	
  to	
  Plato	
  and	
  More	
  is	
  that	
  of	
  Gustav	
  Landauer,	
  who	
  in	
  the	
  early	
  twentieth-­‐
century	
  had	
  treated	
  socialism	
  not	
  as	
  a	
  state	
  but	
  as	
  “a	
  tendency	
  of	
  the	
  human	
  will	
  and	
  
an	
  insight	
  into	
  conditions	
  and	
  ways	
  that	
  lead	
  to	
  its	
  accomplishment.”	
  (Landauer,	
  29)	
  
It	
  is	
  characteristic	
  of	
  this	
  thinking	
  to	
  treat	
  the	
  world	
  as	
  ‘open’,	
  that	
  is,	
  both	
  subject	
  to	
  
transformation	
  through	
  action	
  and	
  as	
  rejecting	
  the	
  claim	
  that	
  it	
  can	
  be	
  surveyed	
  and	
  
encompassed	
  from	
  a	
  single	
  viewpoint.	
  The	
  imaginative	
  possibilities	
  that	
  arise	
  from	
  
treating	
  the	
  world	
  as	
  ‘open’	
  are	
  explored	
  most	
  directly	
  in	
  the	
  essays	
  on	
  the	
  paintings	
  
of	
  the	
  Romanian	
  artist	
  Adrian	
  Ghennie	
  and	
  on	
  the	
  three	
  under-­‐appreciated	
  
achievements	
  of	
  Augustine’s	
  thought.	
  Ghennie’s	
  painting	
  ‘Dada	
  is	
  Dead’	
  shows	
  a	
  
glowing	
  wolf	
  in	
  what	
  looks	
  to	
  be	
  the	
  otherwise	
  abandoned	
  and	
  decrepit	
  interior	
  
famous	
  from	
  Hannah	
  Höch’s	
  photograph	
  of	
  the	
  First	
  International	
  Dada	
  Fair	
  in	
  
Berlin	
  in	
  1920.	
  Geuss	
  begins	
  with	
  an	
  account	
  of	
  Dadaism	
  that	
  stresses	
  its	
  concern	
  
with	
  the	
  limits	
  of	
  meaning:	
  “If	
  one	
  thinks	
  of	
  the	
  two	
  major	
  strands	
  in	
  the	
  philosophy	
  
of	
  art	
  as	
  emphasizing,	
  respectively,	
  the	
  production	
  of	
  the	
  
beautiful/harmonious/well	
  ordered/symmetrical,	
  and	
  the	
  production	
  of	
  the	
  
meaningful/significant/worthwhile,	
  then	
  Dada	
  rejected	
  both	
  these	
  strands.”	
  (230)	
  
He	
  interprets	
  Dada	
  as	
  an	
  exploration	
  of	
  the	
  boundaries	
  of	
  sense:	
  “What,	
  then,	
  is	
  
inside	
  and	
  what	
  is	
  outside	
  any	
  given	
  framework	
  is	
  always	
  a	
  matter	
  of	
  importance.”	
  
(231)	
  Part	
  of	
  the	
  implication	
  of	
  holding	
  that	
  there	
  is	
  a	
  final	
  framework	
  of	
  meaning	
  is	
  
that	
  there	
  is	
  likewise	
  a	
  final	
  framework	
  of	
  meaninglessness;	
  the	
  possibilities	
  of	
  
offering	
  different	
  ways	
  of	
  framing	
  phenomena	
  and	
  of	
  creating	
  connections	
  among	
  
them	
  is	
  circumscribed.	
  Geuss	
  urges	
  the	
  thought	
  that	
  if	
  one	
  drops	
  the	
  commitment	
  to	
  
a	
  final	
  framework	
  of	
  meaning,	
  then	
  the	
  seeming	
  meaninglessness	
  of	
  non-­‐rational	
  
Dadaist	
  thought	
  and	
  actions	
  does	
  not	
  necessarily	
  reflect	
  badly	
  upon	
  Dada,	
  but	
  rather	
  
might	
  bring	
  out	
  the	
  ways	
  in	
  which	
  our	
  life	
  is	
  so	
  rigid	
  and	
  conformist	
  as	
  to	
  block	
  the	
  
imagination	
  of	
  a	
  world	
  in	
  which	
  these	
  seemingly	
  non-­‐rational	
  works	
  would	
  make	
  
sense.	
  (236)	
  Similarly	
  the	
  open	
  playfulness	
  of	
  Ghennie’s	
  painting,	
  are	
  not	
  
necessarily	
  signs	
  of	
  artistic	
  failure	
  or	
  deviancy;	
  rather,	
  these	
  characteristics	
  reflect	
  
badly	
  “on	
  our	
  life	
  and	
  our	
  conception	
  of	
  significance.”	
  Our	
  way	
  of	
  life	
  might	
  be	
  
thought	
  so	
  unimaginative	
  and	
  conformist	
  that	
  we	
  cannot	
  find	
  a	
  place	
  for	
  these	
  
works	
  within	
  it,	
  and	
  thereby	
  be	
  induced	
  to	
  develop	
  a	
  Landauerian-­‐type	
  desire	
  for	
  
something	
  better.	
  
	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  In	
  the	
  essay	
  “Augustine	
  on	
  Love,	
  Perspective,	
  and	
  Human	
  Nature”	
  Geuss	
  finds	
  a	
  
related	
  thought	
  in	
  the	
  great	
  thinker	
  of	
  late	
  Antiquity	
  among	
  three	
  underappreciated	
  
views	
  advanced	
  by	
  Augustine.	
  These	
  three	
  views	
  are	
  his	
  account	
  of	
  the	
  variability	
  of	
  
human	
  nature	
  as	
  shown	
  in	
  the	
  way	
  it	
  changes	
  as	
  a	
  result	
  of	
  the	
  coming	
  of	
  Christ;	
  the	
  
account	
  of	
  love	
  as	
  the	
  passion	
  more	
  fundamental	
  than	
  reason;	
  and	
  the	
  way	
  in	
  which	
  
the	
  extended	
  account	
  of	
  the	
  two	
  cities	
  in	
  The	
  City	
  of	
  God	
  provides	
  a	
  set	
  of	
  paired	
  
alternative	
  perspectives	
  on	
  any	
  phenomenon	
  in	
  human	
  life.	
  The	
  essay	
  is	
  strikingly	
  
original	
  throughout,	
  and	
  something	
  of	
  Geuss’s	
  more	
  general	
  aims	
  is	
  brought	
  out	
  in	
  
the	
  discussion	
  of	
  the	
  latter	
  two	
  views.	
  Human	
  beings	
  for	
  Augustine	
  are	
  
fundamentally	
  creatures	
  of	
  contingent	
  relations	
  of	
  love	
  and	
  desire.	
  The	
  objects	
  of	
  
love	
  and	
  desire	
  are	
  always	
  particulars,	
  and	
  the	
  search	
  animating	
  human	
  life	
  is	
  to	
  
find	
  objects	
  worthy	
  of	
  love.	
  Since	
  the	
  objects	
  are	
  not	
  given	
  through	
  or	
  as	
  a	
  result	
  of	
  
the	
  exercise	
  of	
  reason,	
  but	
  through	
  contingent	
  encounters,	
  we	
  are	
  driven	
  
“continually	
  to	
  negotiate	
  the	
  jagged	
  edges	
  of	
  the	
  world”	
  (270)	
  In	
  this	
  context	
  the	
  
‘jagged	
  edges’	
  are	
  where	
  contingency	
  meets	
  reason;	
  reason	
  is	
  a	
  retrospective	
  
activity	
  that	
  justifies	
  the	
  already	
  encountered	
  and	
  already	
  contingently	
  loved	
  object	
  
as	
  worthy	
  of	
  love.	
  Further,	
  for	
  Augustine	
  this	
  is	
  not	
  only	
  the	
  activity	
  of	
  individuals,	
  
but	
  also	
  has	
  a	
  collective	
  dimension	
  in	
  the	
  establishment	
  and	
  maintenance	
  of	
  a	
  
church,	
  a	
  set	
  of	
  institutions	
  that	
  sustains	
  and	
  fosters	
  orientation	
  towards	
  
appropriate	
  objects	
  of	
  love.	
  (271)	
  With	
  regard	
  to	
  the	
  third	
  view,	
  the	
  two-­‐cities	
  
perspectives	
  are	
  themselves	
  products	
  of	
  different	
  conceptions	
  of	
  what	
  merits	
  love.	
  
Geuss’s	
  discussion	
  of	
  this	
  is	
  cryptic,	
  but	
  he	
  insinuates	
  that	
  anyone	
  living	
  now,	
  that	
  is,	
  
under	
  neoliberalism	
  and	
  in	
  the	
  face	
  of	
  environmental	
  catastrophe,	
  needs	
  access	
  to	
  a	
  
multiplicity	
  of	
  perspectives	
  as	
  an	
  aid	
  to	
  radical	
  social	
  criticism.	
  
	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  What	
  is	
  the	
  pressing	
  need	
  for	
  multiple	
  perspectives	
  right	
  now,	
  for	
  us	
  living	
  in	
  the	
  
rubble	
  of	
  the	
  collapse	
  of	
  neoliberalism?	
  Geuss	
  at	
  two	
  points	
  appeals	
  to	
  Thomas	
  
Friedman’s	
  The	
  World	
  is	
  Flat	
  to	
  characterize	
  the	
  general	
  features	
  of	
  contemporary	
  
life,	
  that	
  “of	
  late	
  liberal	
  capitalism	
  and	
  its	
  aesthetic	
  subdivision—fashion.”	
  (250)	
  
Normativism	
  is	
  the	
  philosophical	
  ideology	
  of	
  the	
  present	
  in	
  its	
  insistence	
  upon	
  a	
  
single,	
  overarching,	
  and	
  internally	
  consistent	
  framework	
  of	
  evaluation.	
  So	
  the	
  very	
  
insistence	
  upon	
  multiple	
  perspectives	
  breaks	
  the	
  spell	
  of	
  normativism,	
  and	
  reduces	
  
its	
  appeal	
  to	
  whatever	
  it	
  can	
  offer	
  piecemeal	
  for	
  context-­‐specific	
  issues.	
  Geuss	
  offers	
  
as	
  an	
  alternative	
  philosophical	
  vision	
  a	
  conception	
  of	
  philosophy	
  as	
  the	
  ceaseless	
  
process	
  of	
  creation	
  and	
  destruction	
  of	
  meaning	
  through	
  imaginative	
  proposals	
  
altering	
  with	
  ascetic	
  analyses.	
  Likewise,	
  the	
  insistence	
  upon	
  plural	
  perspectives	
  
undermines	
  key	
  features	
  of	
  neoliberalism,	
  in	
  particular	
  its	
  market	
  fundamentalism	
  
and	
  reductivist	
  conception	
  of	
  human	
  beings	
  as	
  congeries	
  of	
  desires	
  and	
  beliefs.	
  
Finally,	
  the	
  arts	
  under	
  a	
  pluralist	
  conception	
  treat	
  the	
  boundary	
  between	
  meaning	
  
and	
  meaninglessness	
  as	
  contingent	
  and	
  subject	
  to	
  alteration.	
  For	
  the	
  normativist,	
  
our	
  failures	
  are	
  fundamentally	
  our	
  inability	
  to	
  live	
  up	
  to	
  our	
  reasonable	
  ideals.	
  For	
  
Geuss,	
  our	
  failures	
  are	
  primarily	
  collective	
  and,	
  in	
  a	
  number	
  of	
  senses	
  explored	
  in	
  
this	
  book,	
  are	
  fundamentally	
  failures	
  of	
  imagination.	
  
 	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  
	
  
	
  
	
  
	
  
References:	
  
	
  
Thomas	
  Friedman,	
  The	
  World	
  is	
  Flat,	
  Farrar,	
  Straus	
  and	
  Giroux,	
  2005	
  
	
  
Raymond	
  Geuss,	
  A	
  World	
  without	
  Why,	
  Princeton	
  University	
  Press,	
  2014	
  
	
  
Gustav	
  Landauer,	
  For	
  Socialism.	
  Telos	
  Press,	
  1978	
  (1911)	
  

More Related Content

What's hot

Critical theory
Critical theoryCritical theory
Critical theoryWHS
 
TP1-Effects of Elitism on Social Psychology
TP1-Effects of Elitism on Social PsychologyTP1-Effects of Elitism on Social Psychology
TP1-Effects of Elitism on Social PsychologyDeborah Thornton
 
Political Compass
Political CompassPolitical Compass
Political Compasszmiers
 
Dialectic process in history and constitutive politics
Dialectic process in history and constitutive politicsDialectic process in history and constitutive politics
Dialectic process in history and constitutive politicsAlexander Decker
 
SOCIOLOGY: Theoretical Paradigms
SOCIOLOGY: Theoretical ParadigmsSOCIOLOGY: Theoretical Paradigms
SOCIOLOGY: Theoretical ParadigmsCzarri Capuso
 
DISS - Introduction, Research, Disciplines:History, Political Science, Langua...
DISS - Introduction, Research, Disciplines:History, Political Science, Langua...DISS - Introduction, Research, Disciplines:History, Political Science, Langua...
DISS - Introduction, Research, Disciplines:History, Political Science, Langua...RomlaineOlaso1
 
Soc 2113-ch-1-2017
Soc 2113-ch-1-2017Soc 2113-ch-1-2017
Soc 2113-ch-1-2017WendyScott34
 
An Introduction to the introduction of sociology
An Introduction to the introduction of sociologyAn Introduction to the introduction of sociology
An Introduction to the introduction of sociologyEric Strayer
 
EMERGENCE OF THE SOCIAL SCIENCES
EMERGENCE OF THE SOCIAL SCIENCESEMERGENCE OF THE SOCIAL SCIENCES
EMERGENCE OF THE SOCIAL SCIENCESMiss Ivy
 
Sociology intro
Sociology introSociology intro
Sociology introFreya Ava
 
SociologyReport
SociologyReportSociologyReport
SociologyReportEmilyaa27
 
CH 1: What's Sociology?
CH 1: What's Sociology?CH 1: What's Sociology?
CH 1: What's Sociology?MBurke1621
 
Narcisismo cultural best seller q2
Narcisismo cultural best seller q2Narcisismo cultural best seller q2
Narcisismo cultural best seller q2hectorjpr
 
An Analysis of Theory of Jürgen Habermas and John Locke on Human Freedom
An Analysis of Theory of Jürgen Habermas and John Locke on Human FreedomAn Analysis of Theory of Jürgen Habermas and John Locke on Human Freedom
An Analysis of Theory of Jürgen Habermas and John Locke on Human Freedominventionjournals
 
Hoshaw_WritingSample_PCC_F11
Hoshaw_WritingSample_PCC_F11Hoshaw_WritingSample_PCC_F11
Hoshaw_WritingSample_PCC_F11Crystal Hoshaw
 
Social theories
Social theoriesSocial theories
Social theoriesDuaShaban
 
Introduction to sociology 1
Introduction to sociology 1Introduction to sociology 1
Introduction to sociology 1angelickhan2
 

What's hot (20)

Critical theory
Critical theoryCritical theory
Critical theory
 
TP1-Effects of Elitism on Social Psychology
TP1-Effects of Elitism on Social PsychologyTP1-Effects of Elitism on Social Psychology
TP1-Effects of Elitism on Social Psychology
 
Political Compass
Political CompassPolitical Compass
Political Compass
 
Dialectic process in history and constitutive politics
Dialectic process in history and constitutive politicsDialectic process in history and constitutive politics
Dialectic process in history and constitutive politics
 
SOCIOLOGY: Theoretical Paradigms
SOCIOLOGY: Theoretical ParadigmsSOCIOLOGY: Theoretical Paradigms
SOCIOLOGY: Theoretical Paradigms
 
Micro macro
Micro macroMicro macro
Micro macro
 
DISS - Introduction, Research, Disciplines:History, Political Science, Langua...
DISS - Introduction, Research, Disciplines:History, Political Science, Langua...DISS - Introduction, Research, Disciplines:History, Political Science, Langua...
DISS - Introduction, Research, Disciplines:History, Political Science, Langua...
 
Soc 2113-ch-1-2017
Soc 2113-ch-1-2017Soc 2113-ch-1-2017
Soc 2113-ch-1-2017
 
An Introduction to the introduction of sociology
An Introduction to the introduction of sociologyAn Introduction to the introduction of sociology
An Introduction to the introduction of sociology
 
Introduction to sociology
Introduction to sociologyIntroduction to sociology
Introduction to sociology
 
EMERGENCE OF THE SOCIAL SCIENCES
EMERGENCE OF THE SOCIAL SCIENCESEMERGENCE OF THE SOCIAL SCIENCES
EMERGENCE OF THE SOCIAL SCIENCES
 
Sociology intro
Sociology introSociology intro
Sociology intro
 
SociologyReport
SociologyReportSociologyReport
SociologyReport
 
CH 1: What's Sociology?
CH 1: What's Sociology?CH 1: What's Sociology?
CH 1: What's Sociology?
 
Narcisismo cultural best seller q2
Narcisismo cultural best seller q2Narcisismo cultural best seller q2
Narcisismo cultural best seller q2
 
An Analysis of Theory of Jürgen Habermas and John Locke on Human Freedom
An Analysis of Theory of Jürgen Habermas and John Locke on Human FreedomAn Analysis of Theory of Jürgen Habermas and John Locke on Human Freedom
An Analysis of Theory of Jürgen Habermas and John Locke on Human Freedom
 
Hoshaw_WritingSample_PCC_F11
Hoshaw_WritingSample_PCC_F11Hoshaw_WritingSample_PCC_F11
Hoshaw_WritingSample_PCC_F11
 
Social theories
Social theoriesSocial theories
Social theories
 
Introduction to sociology 1
Introduction to sociology 1Introduction to sociology 1
Introduction to sociology 1
 
Www.efluniversity.ac.in ph d english literature entrance test the english and...
Www.efluniversity.ac.in ph d english literature entrance test the english and...Www.efluniversity.ac.in ph d english literature entrance test the english and...
Www.efluniversity.ac.in ph d english literature entrance test the english and...
 

Viewers also liked (14)

2014_Rec_Christos Georgios Kollias
2014_Rec_Christos Georgios Kollias2014_Rec_Christos Georgios Kollias
2014_Rec_Christos Georgios Kollias
 
Buildnomics ppt
Buildnomics pptBuildnomics ppt
Buildnomics ppt
 
Foi deus
Foi deusFoi deus
Foi deus
 
masters certificate
masters certificatemasters certificate
masters certificate
 
UN-Managing: 1. quando il non-dirigere sprigiona le forze creative
UN-Managing: 1. quando il non-dirigere sprigiona le forze creative UN-Managing: 1. quando il non-dirigere sprigiona le forze creative
UN-Managing: 1. quando il non-dirigere sprigiona le forze creative
 
Costello, Marie recomend ltr Joanne
Costello, Marie recomend ltr JoanneCostello, Marie recomend ltr Joanne
Costello, Marie recomend ltr Joanne
 
Redwine summer 4.4
Redwine summer 4.4Redwine summer 4.4
Redwine summer 4.4
 
Internet
InternetInternet
Internet
 
Perla hugo gabinete
Perla hugo gabinetePerla hugo gabinete
Perla hugo gabinete
 
Presentation SP Mais Serviços Ltda
Presentation SP Mais Serviços LtdaPresentation SP Mais Serviços Ltda
Presentation SP Mais Serviços Ltda
 
Esperimetua maider
Esperimetua maiderEsperimetua maider
Esperimetua maider
 
Receita marmelo para o colexio
Receita marmelo para o colexioReceita marmelo para o colexio
Receita marmelo para o colexio
 
Aparatocirculatorio
AparatocirculatorioAparatocirculatorio
Aparatocirculatorio
 
El ciclo de vida del cliente
El ciclo de vida del clienteEl ciclo de vida del cliente
El ciclo de vida del cliente
 

Similar to Review of Raymond Geuss, Reality and Its Dreams

Political thought ass
Political thought assPolitical thought ass
Political thought assMuktarEdris
 
Political thought ass
Political thought assPolitical thought ass
Political thought assMuktarEdris
 
Political thought ass copy
Political thought ass   copyPolitical thought ass   copy
Political thought ass copyMuktarEdris
 
Political thought ass
Political thought assPolitical thought ass
Political thought assMuktarEdris
 
Notes of sociology (Part 1)
Notes of sociology (Part 1)Notes of sociology (Part 1)
Notes of sociology (Part 1)Pragyan
 
An Appreciation To The Contributions Of Weber To The Discipline Of Sociology
An Appreciation To The Contributions Of Weber To The Discipline Of SociologyAn Appreciation To The Contributions Of Weber To The Discipline Of Sociology
An Appreciation To The Contributions Of Weber To The Discipline Of SociologySheila Sinclair
 
mordern political theory
mordern political theorymordern political theory
mordern political theoryChiradityaMohan
 
185096_16349950SSACXAASXCACAACCCCCCC37.ppt
185096_16349950SSACXAASXCACAACCCCCCC37.ppt185096_16349950SSACXAASXCACAACCCCCCC37.ppt
185096_16349950SSACXAASXCACAACCCCCCC37.pptSamKuruvilla5
 
[Jason_Glynos,_David_Howarth]_Logics_of_Critical_E(BookFi).pdf
[Jason_Glynos,_David_Howarth]_Logics_of_Critical_E(BookFi).pdf[Jason_Glynos,_David_Howarth]_Logics_of_Critical_E(BookFi).pdf
[Jason_Glynos,_David_Howarth]_Logics_of_Critical_E(BookFi).pdfAlexandraJimnez28
 
Polsc22 1 introduction to political philosophy
Polsc22   1 introduction to political philosophyPolsc22   1 introduction to political philosophy
Polsc22 1 introduction to political philosophyYvan Gumbao
 
political_theory.pdf
political_theory.pdfpolitical_theory.pdf
political_theory.pdfWaniBasim
 
Review of International Studies (2007), 33, 3–24 Copyright B.docx
Review of International Studies (2007), 33, 3–24 Copyright  B.docxReview of International Studies (2007), 33, 3–24 Copyright  B.docx
Review of International Studies (2007), 33, 3–24 Copyright B.docxmichael591
 
Positivism and Its Criticism
Positivism and Its CriticismPositivism and Its Criticism
Positivism and Its CriticismND Arisanti
 
Theory in anthropology since the sixties sherry ortner
Theory in anthropology since the sixties sherry ortnerTheory in anthropology since the sixties sherry ortner
Theory in anthropology since the sixties sherry ortnerLaura Calle
 
Amartya Sen S Quot The Idea Of Social Justice Quot An Alternative Theory O...
Amartya Sen S  Quot The Idea Of Social Justice Quot   An Alternative Theory O...Amartya Sen S  Quot The Idea Of Social Justice Quot   An Alternative Theory O...
Amartya Sen S Quot The Idea Of Social Justice Quot An Alternative Theory O...Christine Maffla
 
Early anthropologist
Early anthropologistEarly anthropologist
Early anthropologistRAJ SP
 
Introduction of sociology
Introduction of sociologyIntroduction of sociology
Introduction of sociologyFreya Ava
 

Similar to Review of Raymond Geuss, Reality and Its Dreams (20)

Political thought ass
Political thought assPolitical thought ass
Political thought ass
 
Political thought ass
Political thought assPolitical thought ass
Political thought ass
 
Political thought ass copy
Political thought ass   copyPolitical thought ass   copy
Political thought ass copy
 
Political thought ass
Political thought assPolitical thought ass
Political thought ass
 
Notes of sociology (Part 1)
Notes of sociology (Part 1)Notes of sociology (Part 1)
Notes of sociology (Part 1)
 
An Appreciation To The Contributions Of Weber To The Discipline Of Sociology
An Appreciation To The Contributions Of Weber To The Discipline Of SociologyAn Appreciation To The Contributions Of Weber To The Discipline Of Sociology
An Appreciation To The Contributions Of Weber To The Discipline Of Sociology
 
mordern political theory
mordern political theorymordern political theory
mordern political theory
 
185096_1634995037.ppt
185096_1634995037.ppt185096_1634995037.ppt
185096_1634995037.ppt
 
185096_16349950SSACXAASXCACAACCCCCCC37.ppt
185096_16349950SSACXAASXCACAACCCCCCC37.ppt185096_16349950SSACXAASXCACAACCCCCCC37.ppt
185096_16349950SSACXAASXCACAACCCCCCC37.ppt
 
[Jason_Glynos,_David_Howarth]_Logics_of_Critical_E(BookFi).pdf
[Jason_Glynos,_David_Howarth]_Logics_of_Critical_E(BookFi).pdf[Jason_Glynos,_David_Howarth]_Logics_of_Critical_E(BookFi).pdf
[Jason_Glynos,_David_Howarth]_Logics_of_Critical_E(BookFi).pdf
 
Polsc22 1 introduction to political philosophy
Polsc22   1 introduction to political philosophyPolsc22   1 introduction to political philosophy
Polsc22 1 introduction to political philosophy
 
political_theory.pdf
political_theory.pdfpolitical_theory.pdf
political_theory.pdf
 
Review of International Studies (2007), 33, 3–24 Copyright B.docx
Review of International Studies (2007), 33, 3–24 Copyright  B.docxReview of International Studies (2007), 33, 3–24 Copyright  B.docx
Review of International Studies (2007), 33, 3–24 Copyright B.docx
 
MaxWeber.pptx
MaxWeber.pptxMaxWeber.pptx
MaxWeber.pptx
 
Positivism and Its Criticism
Positivism and Its CriticismPositivism and Its Criticism
Positivism and Its Criticism
 
Theory in anthropology since the sixties sherry ortner
Theory in anthropology since the sixties sherry ortnerTheory in anthropology since the sixties sherry ortner
Theory in anthropology since the sixties sherry ortner
 
Amartya Sen S Quot The Idea Of Social Justice Quot An Alternative Theory O...
Amartya Sen S  Quot The Idea Of Social Justice Quot   An Alternative Theory O...Amartya Sen S  Quot The Idea Of Social Justice Quot   An Alternative Theory O...
Amartya Sen S Quot The Idea Of Social Justice Quot An Alternative Theory O...
 
Early anthropologist
Early anthropologistEarly anthropologist
Early anthropologist
 
Introduction of sociology
Introduction of sociologyIntroduction of sociology
Introduction of sociology
 
sociology
sociologysociology
sociology
 

Review of Raymond Geuss, Reality and Its Dreams

  • 1. Please  refer  to  the  published  version  in  3:AM  Magazine:   http://www.3ammagazine.com/3am/reality-­‐and-­‐its-­‐dreams/       Raymond  Geuss,  Reality  and  Its  Dreams   Harvard  University  Press,  Cambridge,  Massachusetts  and  London,  England,  2016.   312  pp.,  £  25.00  hb.   ISBN  9780674504950     Reviewed  by  John  Rapko              Raymond  Geuss’s  latest  collection  of  essays,  Reality  and  Its  Dreams,  discusses  a   range  of  topics  unusually  wide  even  for  Geuss.  Earlier  books  of  his  juxtaposed   discussions  of  ancient  Greek  and  Roman  philosophy  and  poetry  with  sympathetic   reconstructive  accounts  of  German  philosophers,  especially  Marx,  Nietzsche,  and   Adorno,  and  largely  critical  accounts  of  Kant,  John  Rawls,  and  Robert  Nozick.  The   new  book  contains  discussion  of  all  of  these,  but  expands  an  interest  exhibited  in  his   two  prior  collections  in  addressing  contemporary  political  and  artistic  phenomena,   including  some  contemporary  paintings,  a  recent  play  about  a  Holocaust  survivor,   and  the  political  thought  of  the  British  comedian  Russell  Brand.  Geuss  proposes  that   what  unites  these  essays  is  the  concern  to  attack  ‘normativism’,  a  philosophical   orientation  that  aims  to  present  an  abstract  and  unified  set  of  criteria  for  evaluating   and  judging  the  legitimacy  of  social  and  political  phenomena  and  practices.  One  of   the  motifs  of  Geuss’s  political  thought  is  that  political  utterances  are  never  merely   statements  of  doctrine,  but  also  actions.  Where  normativism  constructs  political   concepts  and  judgments  prior  to  or  in  abstraction  from  their  concrete  contexts,   Geuss  considers  and  criticizes  normativism  in  light  of  the  actions  it  motivates  and   the  guidance  for  practices  it  provides.  Another  motif  is  that  orientations  and   doctrines  are  variously  and  to  various  degrees  embodied  in  acts,  practices,  and   institutions.  Geuss’s  criticism  of  normativisim  is  accordingly  not  only  a  critical   account  and  rejection  of  certain  philosophical  doctrines,  but  also  a  defense  against   certain  kinds  of  political  speech  that  are  ignored  or  slighted  by  normativist  thinkers,  
  • 2. and  a  critique  of  political  institutions  and  practices  to  the  degree  that  they  embody   4normativist  doctrines.              The  central  characteristic  of  normativism  as  a  philosophical  orientation  is  the   assumption  that  there  is  a  ‘realm’  consisting  of  principles,  claims,  concepts  et  alia,   that  is  in  conception  distinct  and  underived  from  how  the  world  or,  perhaps  better,   empirical  reality  is.  Normativist  philosophers  disagree  on  the  contents  of  this  realm   and  the  relation  it  bears  to  empirical  reality,  but  they  are  united  in  thinking  that     appeals  to  inquiries  or  results  in  anthropology,  sociology,  psychology,  or  history   play  no  role  in  determining  the  contents  of  this  realm.  Rather,  one  arrives  at  the   contents  through  on  or  another  of  both  of  two  methods:  eliciting  ‘intuitions’  and   constructing  thought  experiments.  Say  I’m  a  capable  swimmer,  and  I  see  two  people,   a  child  and  an  adult,  floundering  in  the  ocean.  Who  should  I  attempt  to  save  first,   and  why?  Although  in  the  hands  of  any  particular  philosopher  the  results  of   applying  these  methods  may  be  extremely  intricate,  it  is  further  assumed  by   normativist  philosophers  that  the  resulting  structure  must  be  coherent;  but  what   the  criteria  of  coherence  are  and  what  counts  as  coherent  are  themselves  matters  of   dispute  among  normativists.            Geuss  claims  that  in  political  philosophy  there  has  been  a  kind  of  ‘normative  turn’,   analogous  to  the  ‘linguistic  turn’  diagnosed  by  the  philosopher  Richard  Rorty  in  the   1970’s.  In  the  ‘linguistic  turn’  philosophers  passed  from  treating  philosophical   activity  as  the  analysis  of  concepts  to  one  basically  engaged  in  the  analysis  of  bits  of   language.  In  the  ‘normative  turn’  philosophy  passes  from  historically  informed  and   socially  diagnostic  works  such  as  Simone  de  Beauvoir’s  The  Second  Sex,  Herbert   Marcuse’s  One-­Dimensional  Man,  and  Guy  Debord’s  Society  of  the  Spectacle  to  works   aiming  to  analyze  concepts  such  as  ‘justice’  or  ‘rights’,  but  without  reference  to  their   historical  development  or  social  embodiment  in  practices  and  institutions.  The   paradigmatic  works  of  the  incipient  normative  political  philosophy  of  the  1970’s  are   John  Rawls’s  A  Theory  of  Justice  (1971)  and  Robert  Nozick’s  Anarchy,  State,  and   Utopia  (1974).  In  that  same  decade  one  sees  the  beginnings  of  our  period  of  political   reaction  that  soon  effloresced  under  Margaret  Thatcher  in  the  United  Kingdom  and   Ronald  Reagan  in  the  United  States.  Geuss  sees  an  elective  affinity  between  
  • 3. normativism  in  political  philosophy  and  political  reaction  in  the  former’s  attempt  to   draw  attention  away  from  historically  concrete  and  complex  instances  of   oppression,  exploitation,  alienation,  and  above  all  inequality.  Political  reaction  and   normativist  political  philosophy  likewise  treat  politics  as  a  kind  of  applied  morality,   wherein  judgments  are  made  and  actions  motivated  in  terms  of  simple  dichotomies.   Geuss’s  favored  example  is  Tony  Blair’s  attempt  to  justify  the  invasion  of  Iraq  with   the  simple  statement:  ‘Saddam  Hussein  is  evil’.  Insofar  as  normativist  political   philosophy  deigns  to  examine  the  world,  it  contents  itself  with  simple  judgments  of   approval  and  disapproval,  issued  without  reflection  upon  historical  and  contextual   considerations.  Geuss  likens  the  claim  to  authority  of  such  judgments  to  that   claimed  by  main  lines  of  Christian  preaching:  the  categorical  framework  is  never   called  into  question,  and  the  very  articulation  and  uttering  of  the  judgment  would   allegedly  convince  any  uncorrupted  person  of  its  rightness.            Geuss  here  and  in  previous  books  presents  an  array  of  arguments  against  the   basic  conceptual  moves  of  normativist  philosophy.  His  core  objections  are  that  its   elaborate  conceptual  structures  are  invariably  based  upon  simplistic  and  naïve   conceptions  of  actual  human  life;  and  further  that  because  of  the  abstractness  of  the   constructions  and  their  great  distance  from  actual  political  problems  and   historically  specific  cultural  diagnoses  results,  in  practice  they  cannot  but  help   function  as  compensatory  phantasies  for  academics,  who  feel  themselves  to  be   clever  in  pondering  and  analyzing  the  intricacies  of  the  structures  and  somehow  in   contact  with  realities  more  profound  than  those  of  everyday  instances  of  power,   oppression,  and  inequality.  As  such,  normativism  never  issues  in  imaginative   projects  aiming  at  fundamental  reforms  or  revolutionary  proposals.  Instead,   normativist  political  philosophy,  when  not  simply  ratifying  and  providing  an   ideological  justification  for  current  conditions,  can  at  most  recommend  small   palliative  measures.  For  there  to  be  some  trickling  down  of  wealth  under  our  ever-­‐ intensifying  global  conditions  of  massive  inequality,  normativists  fret  over  just  how   many  centimeters  the  spigot  should  be  turned.              In  his  thoroughgoing  rejection  of  normativism,  Geuss  is  close  to  the  thought  of   John  Dewey,  particularly  in  how  both  see  the  appeal  of  dualisms,  especially  the  
  • 4. distinction  between  the  empirical  and  the  ideal,  as  stemming  from  the  failure  of   imagination  and  a  panicked  reaction  the  supposed  threat  of  relativism.  Geuss   diagnoses  the  appeal  of  normativism  as  stemming  from  the  acceptance  of  a  single   and  spectacularly  bad  argument  dubbed  ‘The  Platonist  Blackmail’:  ‘if  you  do  not   have  a  guide  to  action  that  is  absolute  [sic]  certain  and  absolute  [sic]  universal,  you   have  nothing  at  all.”  (60)  Against  this  Geuss  asserts,  first,  that  it  is  simply  false  to  say   that  human  beings  require  access  and  adherence  to  some  ultimate  framework  for   routinely  successful  orientation  and  guidance  in  everyday  actions.  His  preferred   example  is  thirst:  if  I’m  thirsty  and  am  told  that  there’s  a  water  fountain  over  there   to  the  left,  I  need  no  systematic  theory  for  action;  when  I  head  off  in  that  direction,  I   am  not  acting  randomly.  Secondly,  and  rapidly  generalizing,  Geuss  further  asserts   that  we  need  no  “single  systematic  theory  that  provides  us,  either  individually  or   collectively,  with  a  certain  way  of  proceeding  in  all  situations.”  Instead  we  should   treat  the  need  for  orientation  as  piecemeal  and  context-­‐specific,  and  accordingly   something  that  may  well  be  satisfied  through  pragmatically  organized  activities  of   “observation,  theorization,  and  rational  argumentation.”  (61)  Another  way  of   putting  this  point  would  be  to  say  that  there  are  no  context-­‐free  needs  for  human   beings  aside  from  whatever  is  required  for  the  sustainability  of  individual  lives  and   collective  life;  a  potentially  fruitful  response  to  an  emergent,  contingent,  and  local   need  for  orientation  is  rightly  understood  as  an  imaginative  response,  one  that   arises  precisely  because  the  existing  state  of  affairs  is  unsatisfactory  and  does  not   obviously  offer  the  resources  for  finding  one’s  way  out.  Normativism  understood  as   an  imaginative  construct  is  a  notably  fruitless  and  impoverishing  way  of  answering   this  need.            The  second  focus  of  the  book  is  an  attack  on  neoliberalism  in  the  forms  of   excavating  and  scrutinizing  into  most  basic  conceptions  and  assumptions.  As  the   dominant  ideology  of  capitalism  in  its  latest  phase,  one  that  emerges  in  the  1970’s   and  works  for  justifying  the  current  period  of  political  reaction  marked  by  the   ascendency  of  Margaret  Thatcher  and  Ronald  Reagan.  As  an  ideology  governing   political  and  economic  activity  in  the  past  forty  years,  neoliberalism  is  marked  by  an   overriding  concern  with  individual  liberty  secured  by  property  rights,  a  rejection  of  
  • 5. collective  control  and  public  ownership  of  the  means  and  conditions  of  social  life,   and  the  attempt  to  treat  all  spheres  of  human  life  as  analogous  to,  or  indeed  as   constituted  by,  market  relations.  Neoliberalism  is  “constituted  by  two  theses”:  (a)   “the  good  life  must  be  the  life  of  the  human  individual,  and  its  goodness  is   constituted  by  a  triad  of  three  components:  welfare,  as  measured  by  the  level  of   access  to  goods  and  services,  the  satisfaction  of  desire,  and  freedom”;  (b)  the  theory   of  the  free  market,  wherein  independent  individuals  exchange  goods  and  services   without  thereby  drawing  from  or  developing  further  social  relations  among   themselves.  (154)  A  typical  neoliberal  position  derives  from,  exaggerates,  and   dramatizes  an  inflated  terminology  of  the  anti-­‐paternalist  strain  of  classical   liberalism,  a  strain  that  starts  with  the  insistence  that  in  every  case  an  individual  is   or  should  be  the  final  arbiter  of  what  is  good  for  herself.  The  neoliberal  demands   that  everyone’s  desires  and  preferences  be  taken  at  face  value  and  be  given  equal   weight  in  public  deliberation  and  political  activity.  Additionally,  the  neoliberal   position  treats  the  free  market  as  the  ideal  social  mechanism  for  making  the  good   life  available,  both  for  individuals  qua  individuals,  and  for  individuals  treated  as   parts  of  aggregates.            Geuss  raises  a  range  of  considerations  against  both  these  in  aiming  to  undermine   their  seeming  attractiveness  and/or  inevitability.  With  regard  to  the  model  of  a  free   and  self-­‐regulating  market,  Geuss  concedes  a  degree  of  plausibility  to  neoliberalism   during  its  triumphant  first  phase  from  the  late  1970’s  through  2008.  However,  the   aftermath  of  the  economic  downturn  shows  quite  plainly  that  existing  markets  and   their  mechanisms  are  not  in  any  sense  self-­‐regulating.  The  chapter  ‘Economies:   Good,  Bad,  and  Indifferent’  presents  Geuss’s  most  sustained  criticism  of  the   neoliberal  model  of  a  free  market.  He  attacks  the  psychological  and  anthropological   preconceptions  of  the  free  market  model.  In  that  model  buyers  and  sellers  are  first   characterized  by  the  possession  of  a  set  of  desires  and  preferences  considered  in   abstraction  from  how  they  were  acquired,  from  the  advisability  of  satisfying  them,   or  from  the  possibilities  of  transforming  them.  There  is  no  significant  conceptual   distinction  between  desires  and  preferences;  both  are  typically  latent   characteristics  of  consumers  that  are  activated  under  contingent  market  
  • 6. circumstances  regarding  the  availability  of  particular  goods  the  promise  of  which   would  prima  facie  satisfy  some  pre-­‐existent  desire.  So  prior  to  the  marketing  of  a   certain  kind  of  car,  one  has  no  overt  desire  for  this  car.  But  once  marketed,  the  car   activates  consumers’  desire  for  it,  perhaps  so  intensely  that  they  think  of  themselves   as  ‘needing’  the  car.  Since  the  free  market  model  is  abstracted  from  history,  in   particular  from  the  sorts  of  changes  in  social  possibilities  of  human  development   that  Marx  viewed  as  partially  inducing  the  emergence  of  new  needs,  its  conception   of  human  nature  is  static,  and  it  can  only  conceptualize  emergent  desires  as  the   activation  of  some  prior  disposition.  The  individual’s  set  of  desires  as  such  is   unchanging.            Against  this  narrow  conception  Geuss  brings  three  points:  First,  the  presupposed   conception  of  the  economy  fails  to  include  considerations  of  sustainability.  Second,   the  kinds  of  consideration  addressed  by  a  conception  of  the  economy  that  is  suitably   capacious  to  include  sustainability  cannot  be  restricted  to  (pre-­‐existent)  desires  and   preferences,  but  must  also  include  needs  and  interests.  Needs,  desires,  and  interests   are  irreducible  to  each  other,  and  are  all  subject  to  historical  variation  and   development.  Third,  because  of  its  limitation  to  considerations  motivating  liberal   anti-­‐paternalism,  the  free  market  model  blocks  the  possibility  of  including   considerations  wherein  existing  desires  and  preferences  might  be  subjected  to   criticism,  or  might  become  open  to  learning  and  transformation.  The  free  market   model  is  thus  an  instance  of  ‘positivism’  in  Adorno’s  sense,  a  piece  of  social  ideology   that  blocks  criticism  and  discourages  acts  of  collective  deliberation  and  imagination   in  the  service  of  transforming  societies.            A  number  of  previous  reviews  of  Geuss’s  works  have  disapprovingly  noted  a  tone   of  ‘bleakness’  there,  and  complained  that  the  battery  of  criticisms  Geuss  brings   against  normativist  philosophers  like  Kant  and  Rawls  or  liberals  like  J.S.Mill  and   Isaiah  Berlin  are  unconstructive,  in  that  Geuss  offers  no  alternative  to  the  views   criticized.  Geuss’s  chief  implicit  response  in  previous  books  and  elaborated  here  is   to  defend  and  elaborate  another  claim  of  Adorno’s,  namely,  that  one  major  form  of   criticism  is  ‘internal’.  Such  criticism  is  a  context-­‐specific  activity  prominently   involving    juxtaposing  descriptions  of  practices  with  the  aims  whose  realization  
  • 7. might  plausibly  be  thought  to  guide  such  practices.  The  addressee  of  the  criticism  is   left  to  note  the  lack  of  fit  between  the  two.  Internal  criticism,  for  Geuss  as  for   Adorno,  is  not  typically  ‘productive’  in  offering  a  solution  for  the  problems  criticized.   But  here  he  also  offers  a  second  implicit  response  to  the  charge  of  bleakness  in   developing  a  philosophical  account  of  ‘utopian  thinking’,  an  imaginative  activity  that   addresses  discontents  and  persistent,  unsatisfied  desires  in  the  present.  The   exploration  of  utopian  thinking  in  philosophy  and  the  arts  is  the  third  focus  of  the   book.              Geuss  forcefully  presents  the  surprising  claim  that  Utopianism  is  an  aspect  of   some  of  the  range  of  theoretical  and  practical  positions  grasped  under  the  umbrella   term  ‘Realism’.  As  a  theoretical  position,  Realism  is  initially  negatively  characterized   by  its  rejection  of  ‘moralism’,  which  Geuss  construes  narrowly  as  views  that  treat   morality  as  an  absolute  and  unchanging  framework  for  evaluation.  Morality  consists   in  principles  and  rules  for  judgment  of  the  goodness  and  badness  or  evil  of  actions.   Moralism  further  insists  that  moral  judgments  are  in  a  sense  self-­‐realizing,  in  that   the  sheer  recognition  and  understanding  of  the  judgment  results  in  the  appropriate   attitude  of  approval  or  disapproval  in  the  mind  of  an  uncorrupted  receiver  of  the   judgment.  The  range  of  Realisms  that  reject  moralism  are  not  as  such  opposed  to   utopian  thinking,  and  Geuss  suggests  (43)  that  some  incorporate  a  ‘realistic’  (in  the   colloquial  sense)  recognition  that  in  a  society  the  distinction  between  what  is   socially  and  politically  possible  and  what  is  impossible  is  itself  “to  some  extent  a   social  construct”.  The  Utopianism  that  ensues  is  not  the  classical  sort  exemplified  by   Plato  and  Thomas  More,  one  which  proposes  a  ‘perfect’  and  unchanging  society  as  a   counter-­‐image  to  our  corrupt  society,  and  without  specifying  mechanisms  for   passing  from  our  current  state  to  the  perfected  state;  rather,  the  Utopian  that   attends  a  range  of  Realisms  involves  focusing  upon  the  existing  desires  within  a   present  society,  and  offering  proposals  for  changing  society  that  if  enacted  would   more  fully  satisfy  the  desires  than  is  possible  under  current  arrangements.  Some   examples  cited  by  Geuss  are  Russell  Brand’s  suggestions  that  private  debt  be   cancelled,  co-­‐ops  created,  and  the  life  span  of  corporations  be  limited  (78);  Geuss   correlatively  notes  that  the  mainstream  academic  normativist  philosophies  of  John  
  • 8. Rawls  and  Robert  Nozick,  as  well  as  the  exemplarily  neoliberal  thought  of  Margaret   Thatcher,  can  offer  little  or  nothing  responsive  to  Utopian  desires.            In  his  previous  book  Geuss  had  suggested  three  means  of  escape  from  his  own   institutional  setting,  something  motivated  by  his  sense  of  the  institutional  world  of   teaching  philosophy  at  a  university  as  “a  penitential  domain  of  reason-­‐mongering”   (Geuss  2014,  p.232).  One  possible  escape  route  is  what  Hegel  and  Heidegger   attempted,  to  turn  ratiocination  against  itself.  A  second  it  to  act  in  such  a  way  that   “the  spider’s  web  of  bogus  rationalizations”  is  destroyed  and  new  ways  of  speaking   and  new  facts  are  created.  Geuss  takes  the  third  route:  to  engage  in  a  kind  of   imaginative  activity  that  invites  people  to  observe  novel  juxtapositions,  such  as  the   images  of  a  Prime  Minister  addressing  the  House  of  Commons  placed  next  to  the   image  of  a  pile  of  corpses.  Along  with  having  written  and  published  a  small  body  of   poetry,  Geuss  here  broadens  and  generalizes  this  route  in  several  places,  especially   in  the  essay  ‘What  Time  Is  It?’,  which  juxtaposes  reflections  on  a  commentary  on   Pindar,  a  performance  of  a  play  in  Paris,  and  the  conversations  after  the   performance.              The  key  desire  that  Geuss  discusses,  again  arising  from  the  sense  of  being  trapped   in  a  conformist  and  repressive  verbal  universe,  is  most  clearly  stated  in  the  previous   book  as  ‘Anywhere  outside  this  world’.  (ibid)  The  Utopian  method  that  offers  an   alternative  to  Plato  and  More  is  that  of  Gustav  Landauer,  who  in  the  early  twentieth-­‐ century  had  treated  socialism  not  as  a  state  but  as  “a  tendency  of  the  human  will  and   an  insight  into  conditions  and  ways  that  lead  to  its  accomplishment.”  (Landauer,  29)   It  is  characteristic  of  this  thinking  to  treat  the  world  as  ‘open’,  that  is,  both  subject  to   transformation  through  action  and  as  rejecting  the  claim  that  it  can  be  surveyed  and   encompassed  from  a  single  viewpoint.  The  imaginative  possibilities  that  arise  from   treating  the  world  as  ‘open’  are  explored  most  directly  in  the  essays  on  the  paintings   of  the  Romanian  artist  Adrian  Ghennie  and  on  the  three  under-­‐appreciated   achievements  of  Augustine’s  thought.  Ghennie’s  painting  ‘Dada  is  Dead’  shows  a   glowing  wolf  in  what  looks  to  be  the  otherwise  abandoned  and  decrepit  interior   famous  from  Hannah  Höch’s  photograph  of  the  First  International  Dada  Fair  in   Berlin  in  1920.  Geuss  begins  with  an  account  of  Dadaism  that  stresses  its  concern  
  • 9. with  the  limits  of  meaning:  “If  one  thinks  of  the  two  major  strands  in  the  philosophy   of  art  as  emphasizing,  respectively,  the  production  of  the   beautiful/harmonious/well  ordered/symmetrical,  and  the  production  of  the   meaningful/significant/worthwhile,  then  Dada  rejected  both  these  strands.”  (230)   He  interprets  Dada  as  an  exploration  of  the  boundaries  of  sense:  “What,  then,  is   inside  and  what  is  outside  any  given  framework  is  always  a  matter  of  importance.”   (231)  Part  of  the  implication  of  holding  that  there  is  a  final  framework  of  meaning  is   that  there  is  likewise  a  final  framework  of  meaninglessness;  the  possibilities  of   offering  different  ways  of  framing  phenomena  and  of  creating  connections  among   them  is  circumscribed.  Geuss  urges  the  thought  that  if  one  drops  the  commitment  to   a  final  framework  of  meaning,  then  the  seeming  meaninglessness  of  non-­‐rational   Dadaist  thought  and  actions  does  not  necessarily  reflect  badly  upon  Dada,  but  rather   might  bring  out  the  ways  in  which  our  life  is  so  rigid  and  conformist  as  to  block  the   imagination  of  a  world  in  which  these  seemingly  non-­‐rational  works  would  make   sense.  (236)  Similarly  the  open  playfulness  of  Ghennie’s  painting,  are  not   necessarily  signs  of  artistic  failure  or  deviancy;  rather,  these  characteristics  reflect   badly  “on  our  life  and  our  conception  of  significance.”  Our  way  of  life  might  be   thought  so  unimaginative  and  conformist  that  we  cannot  find  a  place  for  these   works  within  it,  and  thereby  be  induced  to  develop  a  Landauerian-­‐type  desire  for   something  better.            In  the  essay  “Augustine  on  Love,  Perspective,  and  Human  Nature”  Geuss  finds  a   related  thought  in  the  great  thinker  of  late  Antiquity  among  three  underappreciated   views  advanced  by  Augustine.  These  three  views  are  his  account  of  the  variability  of   human  nature  as  shown  in  the  way  it  changes  as  a  result  of  the  coming  of  Christ;  the   account  of  love  as  the  passion  more  fundamental  than  reason;  and  the  way  in  which   the  extended  account  of  the  two  cities  in  The  City  of  God  provides  a  set  of  paired   alternative  perspectives  on  any  phenomenon  in  human  life.  The  essay  is  strikingly   original  throughout,  and  something  of  Geuss’s  more  general  aims  is  brought  out  in   the  discussion  of  the  latter  two  views.  Human  beings  for  Augustine  are   fundamentally  creatures  of  contingent  relations  of  love  and  desire.  The  objects  of   love  and  desire  are  always  particulars,  and  the  search  animating  human  life  is  to  
  • 10. find  objects  worthy  of  love.  Since  the  objects  are  not  given  through  or  as  a  result  of   the  exercise  of  reason,  but  through  contingent  encounters,  we  are  driven   “continually  to  negotiate  the  jagged  edges  of  the  world”  (270)  In  this  context  the   ‘jagged  edges’  are  where  contingency  meets  reason;  reason  is  a  retrospective   activity  that  justifies  the  already  encountered  and  already  contingently  loved  object   as  worthy  of  love.  Further,  for  Augustine  this  is  not  only  the  activity  of  individuals,   but  also  has  a  collective  dimension  in  the  establishment  and  maintenance  of  a   church,  a  set  of  institutions  that  sustains  and  fosters  orientation  towards   appropriate  objects  of  love.  (271)  With  regard  to  the  third  view,  the  two-­‐cities   perspectives  are  themselves  products  of  different  conceptions  of  what  merits  love.   Geuss’s  discussion  of  this  is  cryptic,  but  he  insinuates  that  anyone  living  now,  that  is,   under  neoliberalism  and  in  the  face  of  environmental  catastrophe,  needs  access  to  a   multiplicity  of  perspectives  as  an  aid  to  radical  social  criticism.            What  is  the  pressing  need  for  multiple  perspectives  right  now,  for  us  living  in  the   rubble  of  the  collapse  of  neoliberalism?  Geuss  at  two  points  appeals  to  Thomas   Friedman’s  The  World  is  Flat  to  characterize  the  general  features  of  contemporary   life,  that  “of  late  liberal  capitalism  and  its  aesthetic  subdivision—fashion.”  (250)   Normativism  is  the  philosophical  ideology  of  the  present  in  its  insistence  upon  a   single,  overarching,  and  internally  consistent  framework  of  evaluation.  So  the  very   insistence  upon  multiple  perspectives  breaks  the  spell  of  normativism,  and  reduces   its  appeal  to  whatever  it  can  offer  piecemeal  for  context-­‐specific  issues.  Geuss  offers   as  an  alternative  philosophical  vision  a  conception  of  philosophy  as  the  ceaseless   process  of  creation  and  destruction  of  meaning  through  imaginative  proposals   altering  with  ascetic  analyses.  Likewise,  the  insistence  upon  plural  perspectives   undermines  key  features  of  neoliberalism,  in  particular  its  market  fundamentalism   and  reductivist  conception  of  human  beings  as  congeries  of  desires  and  beliefs.   Finally,  the  arts  under  a  pluralist  conception  treat  the  boundary  between  meaning   and  meaninglessness  as  contingent  and  subject  to  alteration.  For  the  normativist,   our  failures  are  fundamentally  our  inability  to  live  up  to  our  reasonable  ideals.  For   Geuss,  our  failures  are  primarily  collective  and,  in  a  number  of  senses  explored  in   this  book,  are  fundamentally  failures  of  imagination.  
  • 11.                     References:     Thomas  Friedman,  The  World  is  Flat,  Farrar,  Straus  and  Giroux,  2005     Raymond  Geuss,  A  World  without  Why,  Princeton  University  Press,  2014     Gustav  Landauer,  For  Socialism.  Telos  Press,  1978  (1911)