SlideShare a Scribd company logo
1 of 6
Download to read offline
Dave Nearing
HY106
Thursday, 13 October
Human Rights in French Revolutionary Literature and The Communist Manifesto
As far back as the 17th
century, philosophers have argued that man is in possession of
certain natural rights, and that those in possession of such rights have those rights in a universal
context. Unfortunately, the method of determination by which those privileged with the
possession of rights and those not so possessed has often varied widely and been a matter of
intense debate. The coming of the French Revolution and the concurrent publication of the
Declaration of the Rights of Man and Citizen (1789) brought a new model of human rights into
view which radically changed the way society in France and elsewhere viewed its various
constituent populations and their relationships. With the advent of the modern age, the general
view of universal rights was once again called into question, this time by Karl Marx and
Friedrich Engels. In each case, the criteria for admission to universal rights, the scope of those
rights, and their nature were modified to accommodate the societal issues of the day.
Prior to the publication of the Declaration, the concept of universal rights was a largely
nebulous one. In an era where feudal tradition and divine right were the driving concepts behind
the legitimacy of government, a population of persons equal under the law and separated from
their supposed betters only in point of property represented a significant threat to the social and
political mores of the age. Even John Locke, the first philosopher to establish a significant link
between the rights of man and the function of government and propose the idea of the social
contract and political legitimacy as a function of popular consent to be governed, did not argue in
favor of universal human rights. Instead, he argued in favor of rights for those members of
society sufficiently elevated to own property, which at the time excluded a majority of people,
including slaves, servants, women, and the poor (Hunt, 5). In the Encyclopedia, Diderot took an
important step in the evolution of natural rights by arguing, among other things, “that the laws
should be made for everyone, and not for one person,” (Diderot, “Natural Law.” Hunt 37). This
concept, coupled with the theme of general equality under the law insofar as the human condition
was concerned was extremely threatening to the standing power bases of the time. It can be
argued that Diderot’s conception of natural rights was necessarily universal, for it predicated
upon mere humanity as opposed to more feudal concepts which assigned varying levels of
“right” to different classes.
This viewpoint evolved into perhaps its most effective form in Siyés’ What is the Third
Estate?, in which Siyés extended the concept of natural rights from equal protection under the
legal system to equal (or at least representative) participation in that system. At the time, the
Third Estate in France was being governed by the nobility and the church, two essentially
nonproductive factions of French society, despite the fact that the Third Estate not only
outnumbered the other two Estates by at least nine to one (Siyés, What is the Third Estate? Hunt
65), but also was almost entirely responsible for the production, refining, and distribution of
goods as well as the labor used to maintain French society. (servants &c.). Siyés saw this as a
crucial imbalance and believed that its correction was of the first importance.
However, Siyés did not advocate the extension of universal suffrage (and by the same
token, a national right to hold office) to French citizens. Siyés believed that placing restrictions
upon civic participation was necessary in order to ensure that officials would act out of the best
possible representative interest and in the closest pursuit of the “common interest.” The concept
of the “common interest” that Siyés proposes is one that holds true with the idea of the “general
will” proposed by Diderot as the plan for the construction and upkeep of society. Just as Locke
and Rousseau had theorized years before, the political philosophers of the revolutionary period
believed that action stemming from self-interest necessarily ran counter to right action in the
pursuit of the interests of society and viewed the law as a safeguard against such actions as
opposed to a proactive entity. As Siyés puts it, “[t]he influence of personal interest ought to
count for nothing in [society]…[t]he law grants nothing; it protects what already exists until such
time as what exists begins to harm the common interest,” (Siyés, Third Estate. Hunt 69). This
concept of law as a protector allows for Siyés further idea that the rights of citizens existed
irrespective of “inequalities of age, sex, size, etc.” (Siyés, Third Estate. Hunt 69), but that
advantages/disadvantages granted by such conditions were outside the scope of the legal system
to actively create or take away.
Persons who happened to be subject to these inequalities, such as women, slaves, non-
Catholics, and Jewish citizens represented special cases within the development of the
revolutionary definition of rights. Throughout the revolutionary period, various writers analyzed
the cases of these minorities and argued both for and against their admission into the enjoyment
of rights as full French citizens. While rights and citizenship were eventually extended to slaves
in the colonies and Jews willing to take an oath of citizenship, and in the case of the Jews,
“[renounce] the privileges and exceptions introduced previously in their favor,” (Admission of
Jews to the Rights of Citizenship. Hunt 101), such concessions were never made to women. This
is largely because while it was the case that France stood to lose much by refusing to extend
rights to the slaves (who were agitating in the colonies, a primary source of French revenue),
non-Catholics (who had held varying amounts of local influence that they stood to lose under the
new law), and Jews (who had heretofore enjoyed special treatment within France not extended to
adherents of other religions such as Islam), it stood to gain little from refusing to admit women to
the rights of citizenship. Women’s political clubs agitated for the right to hold office and enjoy
participatory rights, but it was only by virtue of their recent receipt of civil rights that this was
made possible. The sociopolitical climate of the day was such that a firm statement outlining the
limits of the rights of woman could be tried and decided out of hand by the faction in control and
as such it was decided that women, being “hardly capable of lofty conceptions and serious
cogitations,” (Discussion of Women’s Political Clubs and Their Supression. Hunt 137) should be
limited to the enjoyment of protection under the law and excluded from the exercise of political
rights.
In short, the concept of rights advanced by the thinkers of the French Revolution was the
idea that all persons enjoyed the natural rights to life, liberty, property, and equal protection of
these rights under the law irrespective of social distinctions. The French definition of citizen was
officially a person who was officially French, was at least 25, had lived in a canton for one year
or longer, paid direct taxes at a rate equal to three days of work, and was not a servant/dependent
(Hunt, 82). This was predicated on the notion that only persons with a demonstrated and vested
interest in the nation should have a hand in directing its policies.
Marx’s view of rights is much simpler than that of the French revolutionaries. In the
Manifesto, Marx advocates the elevation of those without rights to the enjoyment of rights and
the demotion of those with more rights than others to a level in common with everyone else.
Marx has as his main goal the transfiguration of persons in society who make their living off of
the work of others into productive members of society with the common good as the end object.
Marx seeks to end the state of affairs which the industrial revolution has produced, namely that,
“[n]o sooner is the exploitation of the labourer by the manufacturer, so far at an end, that he
receives his wages in cash, than he is set upon by the other portions of the bourgeoisie,” (Marx,
11) thus creating a self-sustaining division of economic classes. Marx differs from the French
revolutionaries mainly in that he does not see qualification for participation in political activity
as a valid concept and also in that he is heavily in favor of the “Abolition of property in land and
application of all rents of land to public purposes,” (Marx, 31).
Like the French, Marx wishes to promote the free development of the individual to their
maximum potential in a state protected by the law, however, unlike the French, Marx believes
that the law should take an active role in the creation of divisions and the apportionment of
resources in pursuit of that end whereas the French believed that the law should exist only as a
protector of right as opposed to an active promoter of right. Marx’s strategy for increasing
individual rights requires the government to demand that certain persons sacrifice their rights to
property that is not “the fruit of [their] own labour,” (Marx, 22) in order that the common good
be served to the maximum possible degree through its redistribution/reorganization. The French
revolutionaries would most likely be against this, as they appear to stand united in their assertion
that the law must protect property. The fact that Marx’s determination that “[e]qual liability of
all to labour,” is necessary for his end goal and that the government would be directly involved
in the organization of labor seems to run contrary to the French idea of liberty.
With respect to minorities such as women, Marx apparently does not see them as
fundamentally separate from men and/or citizens with respect to political participation or indeed
with respect to rights in general. He proposes instead that with the coming of widespread
industry, “differences of age and sex have no longer any distinctive social validity for the
working class. All are instruments of labour,” (Marx, 11). This condition is specific to the
Industrial Era, and has little correlation to the pre-revolutionary period, however, so it is difficult
to determine whether a similar sentiment would have been held by the French if they had been
faced with a laboring population of productive women as opposed to a mostly domestic
population.
Where the French concerned themselves with extending rights to individuals and
protecting those rights that they extended, Marx sought to enforce the extension of rights to all
individuals in a manner that would eventually do away with the need for their enforcement
through the elimination of the primary sources of conflict and inequality that he saw in society.
These two separate views are both reactions to the existence of social conflict at the time of their
inception, and while they share some aspects, they differ so fundamentally in their genesis that
analyzing one in the context of the other is difficult, and as such it is better to examine each one
as a valid reaction to the conditions and challenges facing the authors’ societies rather than as an
attempt to answer the general philosophical question of who should receive which rights and in
what capacity.

More Related Content

What's hot

Exploration of the 18th and 19th century thinkers lacey pilgrim
Exploration of the 18th and 19th century thinkers  lacey pilgrimExploration of the 18th and 19th century thinkers  lacey pilgrim
Exploration of the 18th and 19th century thinkers lacey pilgrimLaceyP
 
Human rights 1st lecture presentation
Human rights 1st lecture presentationHuman rights 1st lecture presentation
Human rights 1st lecture presentationMostafa Ahmed
 
Human Rights: perspective, approaches and classification
Human Rights: perspective, approaches and classificationHuman Rights: perspective, approaches and classification
Human Rights: perspective, approaches and classificationAbdul Momin
 
Government involvement is often criticized in a democratic government that ho...
Government involvement is often criticized in a democratic government that ho...Government involvement is often criticized in a democratic government that ho...
Government involvement is often criticized in a democratic government that ho...U of A Mec E Student
 
Western Civilization
Western CivilizationWestern Civilization
Western Civilizationkt806393
 
overview of liberalism part 1 08
overview of liberalism part 1 08overview of liberalism part 1 08
overview of liberalism part 1 08sarahbutterworth
 
Theory of social contract
Theory of social contractTheory of social contract
Theory of social contractHumairaTariq3
 
Philosophy of Human Rights
Philosophy of Human RightsPhilosophy of Human Rights
Philosophy of Human RightsRA Detuya
 
Human Rights, Housing and Health in Post-Earthquake Haiti
Human Rights, Housing and Health in Post-Earthquake HaitiHuman Rights, Housing and Health in Post-Earthquake Haiti
Human Rights, Housing and Health in Post-Earthquake HaitiJordan Exantus, LEED AP
 
Ss30 old ideologies chapter 2
Ss30 old ideologies chapter 2Ss30 old ideologies chapter 2
Ss30 old ideologies chapter 2Danielle Downey
 
The Social Contract by J.J. Rousseau
The Social Contract by J.J. RousseauThe Social Contract by J.J. Rousseau
The Social Contract by J.J. RousseauChristina Wibisono
 

What's hot (18)

Exploration of the 18th and 19th century thinkers lacey pilgrim
Exploration of the 18th and 19th century thinkers  lacey pilgrimExploration of the 18th and 19th century thinkers  lacey pilgrim
Exploration of the 18th and 19th century thinkers lacey pilgrim
 
Human rights 1st lecture presentation
Human rights 1st lecture presentationHuman rights 1st lecture presentation
Human rights 1st lecture presentation
 
Human Rights: perspective, approaches and classification
Human Rights: perspective, approaches and classificationHuman Rights: perspective, approaches and classification
Human Rights: perspective, approaches and classification
 
Common Law, And Constitutional Democracy
Common Law, And Constitutional DemocracyCommon Law, And Constitutional Democracy
Common Law, And Constitutional Democracy
 
The Law
The LawThe Law
The Law
 
Government involvement is often criticized in a democratic government that ho...
Government involvement is often criticized in a democratic government that ho...Government involvement is often criticized in a democratic government that ho...
Government involvement is often criticized in a democratic government that ho...
 
SOC486A Human Rights & Theory
SOC486A Human Rights & TheorySOC486A Human Rights & Theory
SOC486A Human Rights & Theory
 
Fascism vs totalitarianism
Fascism vs totalitarianismFascism vs totalitarianism
Fascism vs totalitarianism
 
Rosseau
RosseauRosseau
Rosseau
 
Western Civilization
Western CivilizationWestern Civilization
Western Civilization
 
overview of liberalism part 1 08
overview of liberalism part 1 08overview of liberalism part 1 08
overview of liberalism part 1 08
 
Theory of social contract
Theory of social contractTheory of social contract
Theory of social contract
 
How power of state is conquered
How power of state  is conqueredHow power of state  is conquered
How power of state is conquered
 
Philosophy of Human Rights
Philosophy of Human RightsPhilosophy of Human Rights
Philosophy of Human Rights
 
Human Rights, Housing and Health in Post-Earthquake Haiti
Human Rights, Housing and Health in Post-Earthquake HaitiHuman Rights, Housing and Health in Post-Earthquake Haiti
Human Rights, Housing and Health in Post-Earthquake Haiti
 
Ss30 old ideologies chapter 2
Ss30 old ideologies chapter 2Ss30 old ideologies chapter 2
Ss30 old ideologies chapter 2
 
The Social Contract by J.J. Rousseau
The Social Contract by J.J. RousseauThe Social Contract by J.J. Rousseau
The Social Contract by J.J. Rousseau
 
Enlightenment Society & Politics
Enlightenment Society & PoliticsEnlightenment Society & Politics
Enlightenment Society & Politics
 

Viewers also liked

Viewers also liked (12)

Human rights through world literature
Human rights through world literatureHuman rights through world literature
Human rights through world literature
 
Widows of the civil war south
Widows of the civil war southWidows of the civil war south
Widows of the civil war south
 
Lane341 3rdlect
Lane341 3rdlectLane341 3rdlect
Lane341 3rdlect
 
Human Rights and Literature
Human Rights and LiteratureHuman Rights and Literature
Human Rights and Literature
 
Enlightenment and the french revolution
Enlightenment and the french revolutionEnlightenment and the french revolution
Enlightenment and the french revolution
 
4 french revolution ppt
4 french revolution ppt4 french revolution ppt
4 french revolution ppt
 
English literature ppt
English literature pptEnglish literature ppt
English literature ppt
 
What is Literature?
What is Literature?What is Literature?
What is Literature?
 
Human rights powerpoint
Human rights powerpointHuman rights powerpoint
Human rights powerpoint
 
Literature
LiteratureLiterature
Literature
 
Human Rights
Human RightsHuman Rights
Human Rights
 
An Introduction To Human Rights
An Introduction To Human RightsAn Introduction To Human Rights
An Introduction To Human Rights
 

Similar to Human Rights in French Revolutionary Literature and The Communist Manifesto

HUman Rights Law 1 -Notes-mekele.pptx
HUman Rights Law 1 -Notes-mekele.pptxHUman Rights Law 1 -Notes-mekele.pptx
HUman Rights Law 1 -Notes-mekele.pptxdavezeethiopia
 
Theories of human rights full paper
Theories of human rights full paperTheories of human rights full paper
Theories of human rights full papersadish p.
 
Thinkers
ThinkersThinkers
Thinkerstwad
 
Human rights in international perspective
Human rights in international perspectiveHuman rights in international perspective
Human rights in international perspectiverobiulalamsifat2
 
Rationality and Enlightenment
Rationality and EnlightenmentRationality and Enlightenment
Rationality and EnlightenmentHareem_syed
 
France and EnglandBy 1700, France eclipsed Spain as pre-eminen.docx
France and EnglandBy 1700, France eclipsed Spain as pre-eminen.docxFrance and EnglandBy 1700, France eclipsed Spain as pre-eminen.docx
France and EnglandBy 1700, France eclipsed Spain as pre-eminen.docxbudbarber38650
 
The French Revolution 1st essay
The French Revolution 1st essayThe French Revolution 1st essay
The French Revolution 1st essayStephen Cheng
 
Thinkers
ThinkersThinkers
Thinkershmoulds
 
Human rights grupo4
Human rights grupo4Human rights grupo4
Human rights grupo4M.Amparo
 
Human rights grupo4
Human rights grupo4Human rights grupo4
Human rights grupo4M.Amparo
 
Sst ppt presentation
Sst ppt presentationSst ppt presentation
Sst ppt presentationArkya Bagchi
 
The relative Universality of Human Righgts by Jack Donnelly.pdf
The relative Universality of Human Righgts by Jack Donnelly.pdfThe relative Universality of Human Righgts by Jack Donnelly.pdf
The relative Universality of Human Righgts by Jack Donnelly.pdfBasemManardas
 
Human rights: Concepts, Origin, sources and ideological foundation pdf
Human rights: Concepts, Origin, sources and ideological foundation pdfHuman rights: Concepts, Origin, sources and ideological foundation pdf
Human rights: Concepts, Origin, sources and ideological foundation pdfAbdul Momin
 
Introduction to human rights with a special focus on indian constitution, uni...
Introduction to human rights with a special focus on indian constitution, uni...Introduction to human rights with a special focus on indian constitution, uni...
Introduction to human rights with a special focus on indian constitution, uni...Shahnawaz Ahmed Malik
 

Similar to Human Rights in French Revolutionary Literature and The Communist Manifesto (20)

HUman Rights Law 1 -Notes-mekele.pptx
HUman Rights Law 1 -Notes-mekele.pptxHUman Rights Law 1 -Notes-mekele.pptx
HUman Rights Law 1 -Notes-mekele.pptx
 
Human rights final
Human rights final Human rights final
Human rights final
 
Human Rights Final
Human Rights  FinalHuman Rights  Final
Human Rights Final
 
Democracy theories
Democracy theoriesDemocracy theories
Democracy theories
 
Theories of human rights full paper
Theories of human rights full paperTheories of human rights full paper
Theories of human rights full paper
 
2007 What is PI
2007 What is PI2007 What is PI
2007 What is PI
 
Thinkers
ThinkersThinkers
Thinkers
 
Human rights in international perspective
Human rights in international perspectiveHuman rights in international perspective
Human rights in international perspective
 
Rationality and Enlightenment
Rationality and EnlightenmentRationality and Enlightenment
Rationality and Enlightenment
 
France and EnglandBy 1700, France eclipsed Spain as pre-eminen.docx
France and EnglandBy 1700, France eclipsed Spain as pre-eminen.docxFrance and EnglandBy 1700, France eclipsed Spain as pre-eminen.docx
France and EnglandBy 1700, France eclipsed Spain as pre-eminen.docx
 
The French Revolution 1st essay
The French Revolution 1st essayThe French Revolution 1st essay
The French Revolution 1st essay
 
Thinkers
ThinkersThinkers
Thinkers
 
Human rights grupo4
Human rights grupo4Human rights grupo4
Human rights grupo4
 
Human rights grupo4
Human rights grupo4Human rights grupo4
Human rights grupo4
 
Sst ppt presentation
Sst ppt presentationSst ppt presentation
Sst ppt presentation
 
Human rights
Human rightsHuman rights
Human rights
 
Human rights lecturer 1
Human rights lecturer 1Human rights lecturer 1
Human rights lecturer 1
 
The relative Universality of Human Righgts by Jack Donnelly.pdf
The relative Universality of Human Righgts by Jack Donnelly.pdfThe relative Universality of Human Righgts by Jack Donnelly.pdf
The relative Universality of Human Righgts by Jack Donnelly.pdf
 
Human rights: Concepts, Origin, sources and ideological foundation pdf
Human rights: Concepts, Origin, sources and ideological foundation pdfHuman rights: Concepts, Origin, sources and ideological foundation pdf
Human rights: Concepts, Origin, sources and ideological foundation pdf
 
Introduction to human rights with a special focus on indian constitution, uni...
Introduction to human rights with a special focus on indian constitution, uni...Introduction to human rights with a special focus on indian constitution, uni...
Introduction to human rights with a special focus on indian constitution, uni...
 

Human Rights in French Revolutionary Literature and The Communist Manifesto

  • 1. Dave Nearing HY106 Thursday, 13 October Human Rights in French Revolutionary Literature and The Communist Manifesto As far back as the 17th century, philosophers have argued that man is in possession of certain natural rights, and that those in possession of such rights have those rights in a universal context. Unfortunately, the method of determination by which those privileged with the possession of rights and those not so possessed has often varied widely and been a matter of intense debate. The coming of the French Revolution and the concurrent publication of the Declaration of the Rights of Man and Citizen (1789) brought a new model of human rights into view which radically changed the way society in France and elsewhere viewed its various constituent populations and their relationships. With the advent of the modern age, the general view of universal rights was once again called into question, this time by Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels. In each case, the criteria for admission to universal rights, the scope of those rights, and their nature were modified to accommodate the societal issues of the day. Prior to the publication of the Declaration, the concept of universal rights was a largely nebulous one. In an era where feudal tradition and divine right were the driving concepts behind the legitimacy of government, a population of persons equal under the law and separated from their supposed betters only in point of property represented a significant threat to the social and political mores of the age. Even John Locke, the first philosopher to establish a significant link between the rights of man and the function of government and propose the idea of the social contract and political legitimacy as a function of popular consent to be governed, did not argue in
  • 2. favor of universal human rights. Instead, he argued in favor of rights for those members of society sufficiently elevated to own property, which at the time excluded a majority of people, including slaves, servants, women, and the poor (Hunt, 5). In the Encyclopedia, Diderot took an important step in the evolution of natural rights by arguing, among other things, “that the laws should be made for everyone, and not for one person,” (Diderot, “Natural Law.” Hunt 37). This concept, coupled with the theme of general equality under the law insofar as the human condition was concerned was extremely threatening to the standing power bases of the time. It can be argued that Diderot’s conception of natural rights was necessarily universal, for it predicated upon mere humanity as opposed to more feudal concepts which assigned varying levels of “right” to different classes. This viewpoint evolved into perhaps its most effective form in Siyés’ What is the Third Estate?, in which Siyés extended the concept of natural rights from equal protection under the legal system to equal (or at least representative) participation in that system. At the time, the Third Estate in France was being governed by the nobility and the church, two essentially nonproductive factions of French society, despite the fact that the Third Estate not only outnumbered the other two Estates by at least nine to one (Siyés, What is the Third Estate? Hunt 65), but also was almost entirely responsible for the production, refining, and distribution of goods as well as the labor used to maintain French society. (servants &c.). Siyés saw this as a crucial imbalance and believed that its correction was of the first importance. However, Siyés did not advocate the extension of universal suffrage (and by the same token, a national right to hold office) to French citizens. Siyés believed that placing restrictions upon civic participation was necessary in order to ensure that officials would act out of the best possible representative interest and in the closest pursuit of the “common interest.” The concept
  • 3. of the “common interest” that Siyés proposes is one that holds true with the idea of the “general will” proposed by Diderot as the plan for the construction and upkeep of society. Just as Locke and Rousseau had theorized years before, the political philosophers of the revolutionary period believed that action stemming from self-interest necessarily ran counter to right action in the pursuit of the interests of society and viewed the law as a safeguard against such actions as opposed to a proactive entity. As Siyés puts it, “[t]he influence of personal interest ought to count for nothing in [society]…[t]he law grants nothing; it protects what already exists until such time as what exists begins to harm the common interest,” (Siyés, Third Estate. Hunt 69). This concept of law as a protector allows for Siyés further idea that the rights of citizens existed irrespective of “inequalities of age, sex, size, etc.” (Siyés, Third Estate. Hunt 69), but that advantages/disadvantages granted by such conditions were outside the scope of the legal system to actively create or take away. Persons who happened to be subject to these inequalities, such as women, slaves, non- Catholics, and Jewish citizens represented special cases within the development of the revolutionary definition of rights. Throughout the revolutionary period, various writers analyzed the cases of these minorities and argued both for and against their admission into the enjoyment of rights as full French citizens. While rights and citizenship were eventually extended to slaves in the colonies and Jews willing to take an oath of citizenship, and in the case of the Jews, “[renounce] the privileges and exceptions introduced previously in their favor,” (Admission of Jews to the Rights of Citizenship. Hunt 101), such concessions were never made to women. This is largely because while it was the case that France stood to lose much by refusing to extend rights to the slaves (who were agitating in the colonies, a primary source of French revenue), non-Catholics (who had held varying amounts of local influence that they stood to lose under the
  • 4. new law), and Jews (who had heretofore enjoyed special treatment within France not extended to adherents of other religions such as Islam), it stood to gain little from refusing to admit women to the rights of citizenship. Women’s political clubs agitated for the right to hold office and enjoy participatory rights, but it was only by virtue of their recent receipt of civil rights that this was made possible. The sociopolitical climate of the day was such that a firm statement outlining the limits of the rights of woman could be tried and decided out of hand by the faction in control and as such it was decided that women, being “hardly capable of lofty conceptions and serious cogitations,” (Discussion of Women’s Political Clubs and Their Supression. Hunt 137) should be limited to the enjoyment of protection under the law and excluded from the exercise of political rights. In short, the concept of rights advanced by the thinkers of the French Revolution was the idea that all persons enjoyed the natural rights to life, liberty, property, and equal protection of these rights under the law irrespective of social distinctions. The French definition of citizen was officially a person who was officially French, was at least 25, had lived in a canton for one year or longer, paid direct taxes at a rate equal to three days of work, and was not a servant/dependent (Hunt, 82). This was predicated on the notion that only persons with a demonstrated and vested interest in the nation should have a hand in directing its policies. Marx’s view of rights is much simpler than that of the French revolutionaries. In the Manifesto, Marx advocates the elevation of those without rights to the enjoyment of rights and the demotion of those with more rights than others to a level in common with everyone else. Marx has as his main goal the transfiguration of persons in society who make their living off of the work of others into productive members of society with the common good as the end object. Marx seeks to end the state of affairs which the industrial revolution has produced, namely that,
  • 5. “[n]o sooner is the exploitation of the labourer by the manufacturer, so far at an end, that he receives his wages in cash, than he is set upon by the other portions of the bourgeoisie,” (Marx, 11) thus creating a self-sustaining division of economic classes. Marx differs from the French revolutionaries mainly in that he does not see qualification for participation in political activity as a valid concept and also in that he is heavily in favor of the “Abolition of property in land and application of all rents of land to public purposes,” (Marx, 31). Like the French, Marx wishes to promote the free development of the individual to their maximum potential in a state protected by the law, however, unlike the French, Marx believes that the law should take an active role in the creation of divisions and the apportionment of resources in pursuit of that end whereas the French believed that the law should exist only as a protector of right as opposed to an active promoter of right. Marx’s strategy for increasing individual rights requires the government to demand that certain persons sacrifice their rights to property that is not “the fruit of [their] own labour,” (Marx, 22) in order that the common good be served to the maximum possible degree through its redistribution/reorganization. The French revolutionaries would most likely be against this, as they appear to stand united in their assertion that the law must protect property. The fact that Marx’s determination that “[e]qual liability of all to labour,” is necessary for his end goal and that the government would be directly involved in the organization of labor seems to run contrary to the French idea of liberty. With respect to minorities such as women, Marx apparently does not see them as fundamentally separate from men and/or citizens with respect to political participation or indeed with respect to rights in general. He proposes instead that with the coming of widespread industry, “differences of age and sex have no longer any distinctive social validity for the working class. All are instruments of labour,” (Marx, 11). This condition is specific to the
  • 6. Industrial Era, and has little correlation to the pre-revolutionary period, however, so it is difficult to determine whether a similar sentiment would have been held by the French if they had been faced with a laboring population of productive women as opposed to a mostly domestic population. Where the French concerned themselves with extending rights to individuals and protecting those rights that they extended, Marx sought to enforce the extension of rights to all individuals in a manner that would eventually do away with the need for their enforcement through the elimination of the primary sources of conflict and inequality that he saw in society. These two separate views are both reactions to the existence of social conflict at the time of their inception, and while they share some aspects, they differ so fundamentally in their genesis that analyzing one in the context of the other is difficult, and as such it is better to examine each one as a valid reaction to the conditions and challenges facing the authors’ societies rather than as an attempt to answer the general philosophical question of who should receive which rights and in what capacity.