SlideShare a Scribd company logo
1 of 100
The Relative Universality of Human Rights
Jack Donnelly
Human Rights Quarterly, Volume 29, Number 2, May 2007, pp.
281-306 (Article)
Published by Johns Hopkins University Press
DOI:
For additional information about this article
Access provided by University of Washington @ Seattle (31 Jan
2018 00:24 GMT)
https://doi.org/10.1353/hrq.2007.0016
https://muse.jhu.edu/article/215033
https://doi.org/10.1353/hrq.2007.0016
https://muse.jhu.edu/article/215033
HUMAN RIGHTS QUARTERLY
Human Rights Quarterly 29 (2007) 281–306 © 2007 by The
Johns Hopkins University Press
The Relative Universality of
Human Rights
Jack Donnelly*
AbSTRAcT
Human rights as an international political project are closely
tied to claims
of universality. Attacks on the universality of human rights,
however, are
also widespread. And some versions of universalism are indeed
theoreti-
cally indefensible, politically pernicious, or both. This essay
explores the
senses in which human rights can (and cannot) be said to be
universal, the
senses in which they are (and are not) relative, and argues for
the “relative
universality” of internationally recognized human rights.
INTRodUcTIoN
This essay explores several different senses of “universal”
human rights. I also
consider, somewhat more briefly, several senses in which it
might be held
that human rights are “relative.” I defend what I call functional,
international
legal, and overlapping consensus universality. But I argue that
what I call
anthropological and ontological universality are empirically,
philosophically,
or politically indefensible. I also emphasize that universal
human rights,
properly understood, leave considerable space for national,
regional, cultural
particularity and other forms of diversity and relativity.
* Jack Donnelly is the Andrew Mellon Professor at the
Graduate School of International Stud-
ies, University of Denver.
The tone of this essay owes much to a long conversation with
Daniel Bell and Joseph
Chan in Japan nearly a decade ago. I thank them for the sort of
deep engagement of funda-
mental differences that represents one of the best and most
exhilarating features of intellectual
life. I also thank audiences at Yonsei University, Ritsumeikan
University, and Occidental
College, where earlier versions of this paper were presented,
and more than two decades
of students who have constantly pushed me to clarify, sharpen,
and properly modulate my
arguments.
Vol. 29282 HUMAN RIGHTS QUARTERLY
Cultural relativism has probably been the most discussed issue
in the
theory of human rights. Certainly that is true in this journal. I
have been an
active participant in these debates for a quarter century, arguing
for a form of
universalism that also allows substantial space for important
(second order)
claims of relativism.1 I continue to insist on what I call the
“relative univer-
sality” of human rights. Here, however, I give somewhat more
emphasis to
the limits of the universal.
In the 1980s, when vicious dictators regularly appealed to
culture to
justify their depredations, a heavy, perhaps even over-heavy,
emphasis on
universalism seemed not merely appropriate but essential.
Today, human
rights are backed by the world’s preponderant political,
economic, and
cultural powers and have become ideologically hegemonic in
international
society. Not only do few states today directly challenge
international hu-
man rights, a surprisingly small number even seriously contend
that large
portions of the Universal Declaration do not apply to them. An
account that
gives somewhat greater emphasis to the limits of universalism
thus seems
called for, especially now that American foreign policy
regularly appeals
to “universal” values in the pursuit of a global ideological war
that flouts
international legal norms.
1. coNcEpTUAL ANd SUbSTANTIVE UNIVERSALITY
We can begin by distinguishing the conceptual universality
implied by the
very idea of human rights from substantive universality, the
universality of
a particular conception or list of human rights. Human rights,
following the
manifest literal sense of the term, are ordinarily understood to
be the rights
that one has simply because one is human. As such, they are
equal rights,
because we either are or are not human beings, equally. Human
rights are
also inalienable rights, because being or not being human
usually is seen
as an inalterable fact of nature, not something that is either
earned or can
1. Jack Donnelly, Human Rights and Human Dignity: An
Analytic Critique of Non-West-
ern Human Rights Conceptions, 76 Am. Pol. Science Rev. 303–
16 (1982); Jack Donnelly,
Cultural Relativism and Universal Human Rights, 6 Hum. RtS.
Q. 400 (1984); JAck Don-
nelly, univeRSAl HumAn RigHtS in tHeoRy AnD PRActice
(Ithaca: Cornell Univ. Press, 1989);
Jack Donnelly, Traditional Values and Universal Human Rights:
Caste in India, in ASiAn
PeRSPectiveS on HumAn RigHtS (Claude E. Welch, Jr. &
Virginia A. Leary 1990); Jack Don-
nelly, Post-Cold War Reflections on International Human
Rights, 8 etHicS & int’l Aff. 97
(1994); Jack Donnelly, Conversing with Straw Men While
Ignoring Dictators: A Reply to
Roger Ames, 11 etHicS & int’l Aff. 207 (1997); Jack Donnelly,
Human Rights and Asian
Values: A Defense of “Western” Universalism, in tHe eASt
ASiAn cHAllenge foR HumAn RigHtS
(Joanne R. Bauer & Daniel A. Bell eds. 1999); JAck Donnelly,
univeRSAl HumAn RigHtS in
tHeoRy AnD PRActice (2d ed. Ithaca: Cornell Univ. Press,
2003); Rhoda E. Howard & Jack
Donnelly, Human Dignity, Human Rights and Political Regimes,
80 Am. Pol. Science Rev.
801 (1986).
2007 The Relative Universality of Human Rights 283
be lost. Human rights are thus “universal” rights in the sense
that they are
held “universally” by all human beings. Conceptual universality
is in effect
just another way of saying that human rights are, by definition,
equal and
inalienable.
Conceptual universality, however, establishes only that if there
are any
such rights, they are held equally/universally by all. It does not
show that
there are any such rights. Conceptually universal human rights
may be so
few in number or specified at such a high level of abstraction
that they are
of little practical consequence. And conceptual universality says
nothing
about the central question in most contemporary discussions of
universal-
ity, namely, whether the rights recognized in the Universal
Declaration of
Human Rights and the International Human Rights Covenants
are universal.
This is a substantive question. It will be our focus here.
2. UNIVERSAL poSSESSIoN NoT UNIVERSAL
ENfoRcEMENT
Defensible claims of universality, whether conceptual or
substantive, are
about the rights that we have as human beings. Whether
everyone, or even
anyone, enjoys these rights is another matter. In far too many
countries today
the state not only actively refuses to implement, but grossly and
systematically
violates, most internationally recognized human rights. And in
all countries,
significant violations of at least some human rights occur daily,
although
which rights are violated, and with what severity, varies
dramatically.
The global human rights regime relies on national
implementation of
internationally recognized human rights. Norm creation has
been interna-
tionalized. Enforcement of authoritative international human
rights norms,
however, is left almost entirely to sovereign states. The few and
limited
exceptions—most notably genocide, crimes against humanity,
certain war
crimes, and perhaps torture and arbitrary execution—only
underscore the
almost complete sovereign authority of states to implement
human rights in
their territories as they see fit.
Except in the European regional regime, supranational
supervisory bodies
are largely restricted to monitoring how states implement their
international
human rights obligations. Transnational human rights NGOs and
other
national and international advocates engage in largely
persuasive activity,
aimed at changing the human rights practices of states. Foreign
states are
free to raise human rights violations as an issue of concern but
have no
authority to implement or enforce human rights within another
state’s sov-
ereign jurisdiction. The implementation and enforcement of
universally held
human rights thus is extremely relative, largely a function of
where one has
the (good or bad) fortune to live.
Vol. 29284 HUMAN RIGHTS QUARTERLY
3. HISToRIcAL oR ANTHRopoLoGIcAL UNIVERSALITY2
Human rights are often held to be universal in the sense that
most societies
and cultures have practiced human rights throughout most of
their history.
“All societies cross-culturally and historically manifest
conceptions of human
rights.”3 This has generated a large body of literature on so-
called non-western
conceptions of human rights. “In almost all contemporary Arab
literature on
this subject [human rights], we find a listing of the basic rights
established
by modern conventions and declarations, and then a serious
attempt to trace
them back to Koranic texts.”4 “It is not often remembered that
traditional
African societies supported and practiced human rights.”5
“Protection of hu-
man rights is an integral part” of the traditions of Asian
societies.6 “All the
countries [of the Asian region] would agree that ‘human rights’
as a concept
existed in their tradition.”7 Even the Hindu caste system has
been described
as a “traditional, multidimensional view[s] of human rights.”8
Such claims to historical or anthropological universality
confuse values
such as justice, fairness, and humanity need with practices that
aim to re-
alize those values. Rights—entitlements that ground claims with
a special
force—are a particular kind of social practice. Human rights—
equal and
inalienable entitlements of all individuals that may be exercised
against
the state and society—are a distinctive way to seek to realize
social values
such as justice and human flourishing. There may be
considerable his-
torical/anthropological universality of values across time and
culture. No
society, civilization, or culture prior to the seventeenth century,
however,
2. This section draws directly from and summarizes Donnelly,
univeRSAl HumAn RigHtS in
tHeoRy AnD PRActice (2d ed.), supra note 1, at ch. 5.
3. Adamantia Pollis & Peter Schwab, Human Rights: A
Western Construct with Limited
Applicability, in HumAn RigHtS: cultuRAl AnD iDeologicAl
PeRSPectiveS 1, 15 (Adamantia
Pollis & Peter Schwab eds., 1979); compare Makau Mutua, The
Banjul Charter and
the African Cultural Fingerprint: An Evaluation of the Language
of Duties, 35 viRginA J.
int’l l. 339, at 358 (1995); David R. Penna & Patricia J.
Campbell, Human Rights and
Culture: Beyond Universality and Relativism, 19 tHiRD WoRlD
Q. 7, at 21 (1998).
4. Fouad Zakaria, Human Rights in the Arab World: The
Islamic Context, in PHiloSoPHicAl
founDAtionS of HumAn RigHtS 227, 228 (UNESCO ed., 1986).
5. Dunstan M. Wai, Human Rights in Sub-Saharan Africa, in
HumAn RigHtS: cultuRAl AnD
iDeologicAl PeRSPectiveS 115, 116 (Adamantia Pollis & Peter
Schwab eds., 1979).
6. Ibrahim Anwar, Special Address presented at the JUST
International Conference: Rethink-
ing Human Rights (7 Dec 1994) in HumAn WRongS 277 (1994).
7. Radhika Coomaraswamy, Human Rights Research and
Education: An Asian Perspective,
in inteRnAtionAl congReSS on tHe teAcHing of HumAn
RigHtS: WoRking DocumentS AnD Recom-
menDAtionS 224 (UNESCO ed., 1980).
8. Ralph Buultjens, Human Rights in Indian Political Culture,
in tHe moRAl imPeRAtiveS of
HumAn RigHtS: A WoRlD SuRvey 109, 113 (Kenneth W.
Thompson ed., 1980); compare
Yougindra Khushalani, Human Rights in Asia and Africa, 4
Hum. RtS. l. J. 403, 408
(1983); mAx l. StAckHouSe, cReeDS, Society, AnD HumAn
RigHtS: A StuDy in tHRee cultuReS
(1984).
2007 The Relative Universality of Human Rights 285
had a widely endorsed practice, or even vision, of equal and
inalienable
individual human rights.9
For example, Dunstan Wai argues that traditional African
beliefs and
institutions “sustained the ‘view that certain rights should be
upheld against
alleged necessities of state.’”10 This confuses human rights
with limited gov-
ernment.11 Government has been limited on a variety of
grounds other than
human rights, including divine commandment, legal rights, and
extralegal
checks such as a balance of power or the threat of popular
revolt.
“[T]he concept of human rights concerns the relationship
between the
individual and the state; it involves the status, claims, and
duties of the former
in the jurisdiction of the latter. As such, it is a subject as old as
politics.”12
Not all political relationships, however, are governed by,
related to, or even
consistent with, human rights. What the state owes those it rules
is indeed
a perennial question of politics. Human rights provide one
answer. Other
answers include divine right monarchy, the dictatorship of the
proletariat,
the principle of utility, aristocracy, theocracy, and democracy.
“[D]ifferent civilizations or societies have different conceptions
of hu-
man well-being. Hence, they have a different attitude toward
human rights
issues.”13 Even this is misleading. Other societies may have
(similar or differ-
ent) attitudes toward issues that we consider today to be matters
of human
rights. But without a widely understood concept of human rights
endorsed
or advocated by some important segment of that society, it is
hard to imagine
that they could have any attitude toward human rights. And it is
precisely
the idea of equal and inalienable rights that one has simply
because one
is a human being that was missing not only in traditional Asian,
African,
Islamic, but in traditional Western, societies as well.
9. For detailed support for this claim, see Donnelly,
univeRSAl HumAn RigHtS in tHeoRy AnD
PRActice (2d ed.), supra note 1, at ch. 5; RHoDA e. HoWARD,
HumAn RigHtS in commonWeAltH
AfRicA, at ch. 2(1986).
10. Wai, supra note 5, at 116.
11. Compare Asmarom Legesse, Human Rights in African
Political Culture, in tHe moRAl
imPeRAtiveS of HumAn RigHtS: A WoRlD SuRvey 123, 125–
27 (Kenneth W. Thompson ed.,
1980); Nana Kusi Appea Busia, Jr., The Status of Human Rights
in Pre-Colonial Africa:
Implications for Contemporary Practices, in AfRicA, HumAn
RigHtS, AnD tHe globAl SyStem:
tHe PoliticAl economy of HumAn RigHtS in A cHAnging
WoRlD 225, 231 (Eileen McCarthy-
Arnolds, David R. Penna, & Debra Joy Cruz Sobrepeña eds.,
1994); for non-African
examples, Abdul Aziz Said, Precept and Practice of Human
Rights in Islam, 1 univeRSAl
Hum. RtS. 63, 65 (1979); Raul Manglapus, Human Rights are
Not a Western Discovery,
4 WoRlDvieW (1978); Adamantia Pollis & Peter Schwab,
Introduction, in HumAn RigHtS:
cultuRAl AnD iDeologicAl PeRSPectiveS xiii, xiv (Adamantia
Pollis & Peter Schwab eds.,
1979).
12. Hung-Chao Tai, Human Rights in Taiwan: Convergence of
Two Political Cultures?, in
HumAn RigHtS in eASt ASiA: A cultuRAl PeRSPective 77, 79
(James C. Hsiung ed., 1985).
13. Manwoo Lee, North Korea and the Western Notion of
Human Rights, in HumAn RigHtS
in eASt ASiA: A cultuRAl PeRSPective 129, 131 (James C.
Hsiung ed., 1985).
Vol. 29286 HUMAN RIGHTS QUARTERLY
The ancient Greeks notoriously distinguished between Hellenes
and
barbarians, practiced slavery, denied basic rights to foreigners,
and (by our
standards) severely restricted the rights of even free adult
(male) citizens.
The idea that all human beings had equal and inalienable basic
rights was
equally foreign to Athens and Sparta, Plato and Aristotle,
Homer, Hesiod,
Aeschylus, Euripides, Aristophanes, and Thucydides. Much the
same is true
of ancient Rome, both as a republic and as an empire. In
medieval Europe,
where the spiritual egalitarianism and universality of
Christianity expressed
itself in deeply inegalitarian politics, the idea of equal legal and
political rights
for all human beings, had it been seriously contemplated, would
have been
seen as a moral abomination, a horrid transgression against
God’s order.
In the “pre-modern” world, both Western and non-Western
alike, the
duty of rulers to further the common good arose not from the
rights (entitle-
ments) of all human beings, or even all subjects, but from
divine command-
ment, natural law, tradition, or contingent political
arrangements. The people
could legitimately expect to benefit from the obligations of
their rulers to
rule justly. Neither in theory nor in practice, though, did they
have human
rights that could be exercised against unjust rulers. The reigning
ideas were
natural law and natural right (in the sense of righteousness or
rectitude) not
natural or human rights (in the sense of equal and inalienable
individual
entitlements).
Many arguments of anthropological universality are inspired by
an
admirable desire to show cultural sensitivity and respect. In fact
they do no
such thing. Rather, they misunderstand and misrepresent the
foundations
and functioning of the societies in question by anachronistically
imposing
an alien analytical framework.
I am not claiming that Islam, Confucianism, or traditional
African ideas
cannot support internationally recognized human rights. Quite
the contrary, I
argue below that in practice today they increasingly do support
human rights.
My point is simply that Islamic, Confucian, and African
societies did not in
fact develop significant bodies of human rights ideas or
practices prior to
the twentieth century. The next section offers an explanation for
this fact.
4. fUNcTIoNAL UNIVERSALITY
Natural or human rights ideas first developed in the modern
West. A full-
fledged natural rights theory is evident in John Locke’s Second
Treatise of
Government, published in 1689 in support of the so-called
Glorious Revolu-
tion. The American and French Revolutions first used such
ideas to construct
new political orders.14
14. JoHn locke, tWo tReAtiSe on goveRnment (London, W.
Wilson 1821) (1689).
2007 The Relative Universality of Human Rights 287
The social-structural “modernity” of these ideas and practices,
however,
not their cultural “Westernness,” deserves emphasis.15 Human
rights ideas
and practices arose not from any deep Western cultural roots
but from the
social, economic, and political transformations of modernity.
They thus have
relevance wherever those transformations have occurred,
irrespective of the
pre-existing culture of the place.
Nothing in classical or medieval culture specially predisposed
Europeans
to develop human rights ideas. Even early modern Europe, when
viewed
without the benefit of hindsight, seemed a particularly
unconducive cultural
milieu for human rights. No widely endorsed reading of
Christian scriptures
supported the idea of a broad set of equal and inalienable
individual rights
held by all Christians, let alone all human beings. Violent, often
brutal, in-
ternecine and international religious warfare was the norm. The
divine right
of kings was the reigning orthodoxy.
Nonetheless, in early modern Europe, ever more powerful and
pen-
etrating (capitalist) markets and (sovereign, bureaucratic) states
disrupted,
destroyed, or radically transformed “traditional” communities
and their
systems of mutual support and obligation. Rapidly expanding
numbers of
(relatively) separate families and individuals were thus left to
face a grow-
ing range of increasingly unbuffered economic and political
threats to their
interests and dignity. New “standard threats” to human dignity
provoked
new remedial responses.16
The absolutist state offered a society organized around a
monarchist hier-
archy justified by a state religion. The newly emergent
bourgeoisie envisioned
a society in which the claims of property balanced those of
birth. And as
“modernization” progressed, an ever widening range of
dispossessed groups
advanced claims for relief from injustices and disabilities. Such
demands
took many forms, including appeals to scripture, church,
morality, tradition,
justice, natural law, order, social utility, and national strength.
Claims of
equal and inalienable natural/human rights, however, became
increasingly
central. And the successes of some groups opened political
space for others
to advance similar claims for their equal rights.
The spread of modern markets and states has globalized the
same threats
to human dignity initially experienced in Europe. Human rights
represent
the most effective response yet devised to a wide range of
standard threats
to human dignity that market economies and bureaucratic states
have made
15. See Donnelly, univeRSAl HumAn RigHtS in tHeoRy AnD
PRActice (2d ed.), supra note 1, at ch.
4; compare Michael Goodhart, Origins and Universality in the
Human Rights Debate:
Cultural Essentialism and the Challenge of Globalization, 25
Hum. RtS. Q. 935 (2003).
ARvinD SHARmA, ARe HumAn RigHtS WeSteRn in oRigin? A
contRibution to tHe DiAlogue of
civilizAtionS(2006) extensively and critically explores the wide
variety of senses in which
human rights have been held to be “Western.”
16. HenRy SHue, bASic RigHtS: SubSiStence, Affluence, AnD
u.S. foReign Policy 29–34 (1980).
Vol. 29288 HUMAN RIGHTS QUARTERLY
nearly universal across the globe. Human rights today remain
the only proven
effective means to assure human dignity in societies dominated
by markets
and states. Although historically contingent and relative, this
functional
universality fully merits the label universal—for us, today.
Arguments that another state, society, or culture has developed
plausible
and effective alternative mechanisms for protecting or realizing
human dig-
nity in the contemporary world deserve serious attention.
Today, however,
such claims, when not advanced by repressive elites and their
supporters,
usually refer to an allegedly possible world that no one yet has
had the
good fortune to experience.
The functional universality of human rights depends on human
rights
providing attractive remedies for some of the most pressing
systemic threats
to human dignity. Human rights today do precisely that for a
growing number
of people of all cultures in all regions. Whatever our other
problems, we
all must deal with market economies and bureaucratic states.
Whatever our
other religious, moral, legal, and political resources, we all
need equal and
inalienable universal human rights to protect us from those
threats.
5. INTERNATIoNAL LEGAL UNIVERSALITY
If this argument is even close to correct, we ought to find
widespread active
endorsement of internationally recognized human rights. Such
endorsement
is evident in international human rights law, giving rise to what
I will call
international legal universality. The foundational international
legal instru-
ment is the Universal Declaration of Human Rights. The 1993
World Human
Rights Conference, in the first operative paragraph of the
Vienna Declaration
and Programme of Action, asserted that “the universal nature of
these rights
and freedoms is beyond question.”
Virtually all states accept the authority of the Universal
Declaration of
Human Rights. For the purposes of international relations,
human rights
today means, roughly, the rights in the Universal Declaration.
Those rights
have been further elaborated in a series of widely ratified
treaties. As of 6
December 2006, the six core international human rights treaties
(on civil and
political rights, economic, social, and cultural rights, racial
discrimination,
women, torture, and children) had an average 168 parties, which
represents
a truly impressive 86 percent ratification rate.17
Although this international legal universality operates in
significant mea-
sure at an elite interstate level, it has come to penetrate much
more deeply.
Movements for social justice and of political opposition have
increasingly
17. Ratification data is available at
http://www.ohchr.org/english/countries/ratification/index.
htm and http://www.ohchr.org/english/bodies/docs/status.pdf.
2007 The Relative Universality of Human Rights 289
adopted the language of human rights. Growing numbers of new
interna-
tional issues, ranging from migration, to global trade and
finance, to access
to pharmaceuticals are being framed as issues of human
rights.18
States that systematically violate internationally recognized
human
rights do not lose their legitimacy in international law. Except
in cases of
genocide, sovereignty still ultimately trumps human rights. But
protecting
internationally recognized human rights is increasingly seen as
a precondi-
tion of full political legitimacy. Consider Robert Mugabe’s
Zimbabwe. Even
China has adopted the language (although not too much of the
practice)
of internationally recognized human rights, seemingly as an
inescapable
precondition to its full recognition as a great power.
International legal universality, like functional universality, is
contingent
and relative. It depends on states deciding to treat the Universal
Declaration
and the Covenants as authoritative. Tomorrow, they may no
longer accept
or give as much weight to human rights. Today, however, they
clearly have
chosen, and continue to choose, human rights over competing
conceptions
of national and international political legitimacy.
6. oVERLAppING coNSENSUS UNIVERSALITY
International legal universality is incompletely but significantly
replicated at
the level of moral or political theory. John Rawls distinguishes
“comprehen-
sive religious, philosophical, or moral doctrines,” such as Islam,
Kantianism,
Confucianism, and Marxism, from “political conceptions of
justice,” which
address only the political structure of society, defined (as far as
possible) in-
dependent of any particular comprehensive doctrine.19
Adherents of different
comprehensive doctrines may be able to reach an “overlapping
consensus”
on a political conception of justice.20
Such a consensus is overlapping; partial rather than complete. It
is politi-
cal rather than moral or religious. Rawls developed the notion
to understand
how “there can be a stable and just society whose free and equal
citizens are
deeply divided by conflicting and even incommensurable
religious, philo-
sophical, and moral doctrines.”21 The idea, however, has
obvious extensions
to a culturally and politically diverse international society.22
18. AliSon bRySk, HumAn RigHtS AnD PRivAte WRongS:
conStRucting globAl civil Society (2005).
19. JoHn RAWlS, tHe lAW of PeoPleS xliii–xlv, 11–15, 174–
76 (1999); JoHn RAWlS, PoliticAl lib-
eRAliSm 31–33, 172–73 (1993).
20. RAWlS, PoliticAl libeRAliSm, supra note 19, at 133–72,
385–96.
21. Id. at 133.
22. RAWlS, tHe lAW of PeoPleS, supra note 19. Rawls’ own
extension involves both a wider
political conception of justice and a narrower list of
internationally recognized human
rights. The account offered here is Rawlsian in inspiration but
not that of John Rawls.
Vol. 29290 HUMAN RIGHTS QUARTERLY
Human rights can be grounded in a variety of comprehensive
doctrines.
For example, they can be seen as encoded in the natural law,
called for by
divine commandment, political means to further human good or
utility, or
institutions to produce virtuous citizens. Over the past few
decades more
and more adherents of a growing range of comprehensive
doctrines in all
regions of the world have come to endorse human rights—(but
only) as a
political conception of justice.23
It is important to remember that virtually all Western religious
and
philosophical doctrines through most of their history have either
rejected
or ignored human rights. Today, however, most adherents of
most Western
comprehensive doctrines endorse human rights. And if the
medieval Christian
world of crusades, serfdom, and hereditary aristocracy could
become today’s
world of liberal and social democratic welfare states, it is hard
to think of
a place where a similar transformation is inconceivable.
Consider claims that “Asian values” are incompatible with
internation-
ally recognized human rights.24 Asian values—like Western
values, African
values, and most other sets of values—can be, and have been,
understood
as incompatible with human rights. But they also can be and
have been
interpreted to support human rights, as they regularly are today
in Japan,
Taiwan, and South Korea. And political developments in a
growing number
of Asian countries suggest that ordinary people and even
governments are
increasingly viewing human rights as a contemporary political
expression of
their deepest ethical, cultural, and political values and
aspirations.25
23. Heiner Bielefeldt, “Western” versus “Islamic” Human
Rights Conceptions?: A Critique of
Cultural Essentialism in the Discussion on Human Rights, 28
Pol. tHeoRy 90 (2000) makes
a similar argument for overlapping consensus universality,
illustrated by a discussion
of recent trends in Islamic thinking on human rights. See also
Ashwani Kumar Peetush,
Cultural Diversity, Non-Western Communities, and Human
Rights, 34 PHiloSoPHicAl foRum
1 (2003), which deals with South Asian views. Vincanne
Adams, Suffering the Winds of
Lhasa: Politicized Bodies, Human Rights, Cultural Difference,
and Humanism in Tibet, 12
meD. AntHRoPology Q. 74 (1998) presents an account of the
suffering of Tibetan women
activists that stresses their instrumental adoption of human
rights ideas to grapple with
injustices and suffering that they understand in very different
terms. For a looser account
of cross-cultural consensus, see HumAn RigHtS in cRoSS-
cultuRAl PeRSPectiveS: A QueSt foR
conSenSuS (Abdullahi Ahmed An-Na’im ed. 1992).
24. AntHony J. lAngloiS, tHe PoliticS of JuStice AnD HumAn
RigHtS (2001) offers perhaps the
best overview. HumAn RigHtS AnD ASiAn vAlueS: conteSting
nAtionAl iDentitieS AnD cultuRAl
RePReSentAtionS in ASiA (Michael Jacobsen & Ole Bruun
eds., 2000); tHe eASt ASiAn cHAllenge
foR HumAn RigHtS, supra note 1, are good collections of
essays.
25. “Confucians can make sense of rights out of the resources
of their own tradition.” May
Sim, A Confucian Approach to Human Rights, 21 HiSt. PHil. Q.
337, 338 (2004). Compare
Joseph Chan, Moral Autonomy, Civil Liberties, and
Confucianism, 52 PHil. eASt & WeSt
281 (2002); Joseph Chan, Confucian Perspective on Human
Rights for Contemporary
China, in tHe eASt ASiAn cHAllenge foR HumAn RigHtS,
supra note 1. On Confucianism and
modern social and political practices, see confuciAniSm foR
tHe moDeRn WoRlD (Daniel A.
Bell & Hahm Chaibong eds., 2003).
2007 The Relative Universality of Human Rights 291
No culture or comprehensive doctrine is “by nature,” or in any
given or
fixed way, either compatible or incompatible with human rights.
Here we
circle back to the insight underlying (misformulated) arguments
of anthro-
pological universality. Whatever their past practice, nothing in
indigenous
African, Asian, or American cultures prevents them from
endorsing human
rights now. Cultures are immensely malleable, as are the
political expressions
of comprehensive doctrines. It is an empirical question whether
(any, some,
or most) members of a culture or exponents of a comprehensive
doctrine
support human rights as a political conception of justice.
All major civilizations have for long periods treated a
significant portion of
the human race as “outsiders” not entitled to guarantees that
could be taken
for granted by “insiders.” Few areas of the globe, for example,
have never
practiced and widely justified human bondage. All literate
civilizations have
for most of their histories assigned social roles, rights, and
duties primarily
on the basis of ascriptive characteristics such as birth, age, and
gender.
Today, however, the moral equality of all human beings is
strongly
endorsed by most leading comprehensive doctrines in all
regions of the
world. This convergence, both within and between civilizations,
provides the
foundation for a convergence on the rights of the Universal
Declaration. In
principle, a great variety of social practices other than human
rights might
provide the basis for realizing foundational egalitarian values.
In practice
human rights are rapidly becoming the preferred option. I will
call this
overlapping consensus universality.
7. VoLUNTARY oR coERcEd coNSENSUS?
Is the transnational consensus underlying international legal and
overlap-
ping consensus universality more voluntary or coerced? The
influence of the
United States and Western Europe should not be
underestimated. Example,
however, has been more powerful than advocacy and coercion
has typically
played less of a role than positive inducements such as closer
political or
economic relations or full participation in international society.
Human rights
dominate political discussions less because of pressure from
materially or
culturally dominant powers than because they respond to some
of the most
important social and political aspirations of individuals,
families, and groups
in most countries of the world.
States may be particularly vulnerable to external pressure and
thus
tempted or even compelled to offer purely formal endorsements
of interna-
tional norms advocated by leading powers.26 The assent of most
societies and
26. Even that seems to me not obviously correct. I read
hypocrisy more as evidence of the
substantive attractions of hypocritically endorsed norms.
Vol. 29292 HUMAN RIGHTS QUARTERLY
individuals, however, is largely voluntary. The consensus on the
Universal
Declaration, it seems to me, principally reflects its cross-
cultural substantive
attractions. People, when given a chance, usually (in the
contemporary world)
choose human rights, irrespective of region, religion, or culture.
Few “ordinary” citizens in any country have a particularly
sophisticated
sense of human rights. They respond instead to the general idea
that they and
their fellow citizens are entitled to equal treatment and certain
basic goods,
services, protections, and opportunities. I am in effect
suggesting that the
Universal Declaration presents a reasonable first approximation
of the list
that they would come up with, largely irrespective of culture,
after consid-
erable reflection. More precisely, there is little in the Universal
Declaration
that they would not (or could not be persuaded to) put there,
although we
might readily imagine a global constitutional convention today
coming up
with a somewhat different list.
The transnational consensus on the Universal Declaration arises
above
all from the largely voluntary decisions of people, states, and
other political
actors that human rights are essential to protecting their visions
of a life of
dignity. Therefore, we should talk more of the relative
universality of human
rights, rather than their relative universality.27
8. oNToLoGIcAL UNIVERSALITY
Overlapping consensus implies that human rights can, and in the
contem-
porary world do, have multiple and diverse “foundations.” A
single transh-
istorical foundation would provide what I will call ontological
universality.28
27. Laura Hebert in a private communication pointed out that I
previously described my
views as weak relativist or strong (but not radical) universalist,
but that in an earlier
version of this essay I used the label weak universalist. The
careful reader will note that
here I have avoided such formulations in favor of a notion of
relative universality that is
open to differing emphases. This reflects my growing
appreciation of the advantages of
approaching the continuum between relativism and universalism
less as an ideal type
account of all possible positions and more in terms of the
spectrum of views that hap-
pen to be prevalent among actively engaged participants in the
debate at a particular
time and place.
The actual spectrum of views actively engaged at any given
time and place is likely
to cover only a portion of the ideal type spectrum. My
arguments have always been
formulated primarily, although implicitly, with respect to the
former. Over the past
decade, much of the relativist end of the Cold War era spectrum
has disappeared from
mainstream discussions. Therefore, views such as my own that
once appeared near the
edge of the universalist end of the spectrum now appear more
moderately universalist. I
must also admit, though, that given this new political context I
have intentionally given
greater emphasis to the space available for diverse
implementations of universal human
rights norms. See Donnelly, Human Rights and Asian Values,
supra note 1; Section 13,
14 below.
28. For a recent attempt to defend ontological universality, see
WilliAm J. tAlbott, WHicH
RigHtS SHoulD be univeRSAl? 3–4 (2005).
2007 The Relative Universality of Human Rights 293
Although a single moral code may indeed be objectively correct
and valid at
all times in all places, at least three problems make ontological
universality
implausible and politically unappealing.
First, no matter how strenuously adherents of a particular
philosophy
or religion insist that (their) values are objectively valid, they
are unable to
persuade adherents of other religions or philosophies. This
failure to agree
leaves us in pretty much the same position as if there were no
objective
values at all. We are thrown back on arguments of functional,
international
legal, and overlapping consensus universality (understood now,
perhaps, as
imperfect reflections of a deeper ontological universality).
Second, all prominent comprehensive doctrines have for large
parts of
their history ignored or actively denied human rights. It is
improbable (al-
though conceivable) that an objectively correct doctrine has
been interpreted
incorrectly so widely. Thus it is unlikely that human rights in
general, and
the particular list in the Universal Declaration, are ontologically
universal.
At best, we might find that an ontologically universal
comprehensive doc-
trine has recently and contingently endorsed human rights as a
political
conception of justice.
Third, the ontological universality of human rights, coupled
with the
absence of anthropological universality, implies that virtually
all moral and
religious theories through most of their histories have been
objectively false
or immoral. This may indeed be correct. But before we embrace
such a
radical idea, I think we need much stronger arguments than are
currently
available to support the ontological universality of human
rights.
Overlapping consensus, rather than render human rights
groundless,
gives them multiple grounds. Whatever its analytical and
philosophical
virtues or shortcomings, this is of great practical utility. Those
who want
(or feel morally compelled) to make ontological claims can do
so with no
need to convince or compel others to accept this particular, or
even any,
foundation. Treating human rights as a Rawlsian political
conception of
justice thus allows us to address a wide range of issues of
political justice
and right while circumventing not merely inconclusive but often
pointlessly
divisive disputes over moral foundations.
9. cULTURAL RELATIVISM
Having considered a variety of possible senses of
“universality,” I now
want to turn, somewhat more briefly, to several different senses
of “relativ-
ity.” What makes (or is alleged to make) human rights relative?
Relative to
what? We have already seen that they are historically relative
and that, at
best, ontological universality remains a matter of debate. The
most common
argument for relativity appeals to culture.
Vol. 29294 HUMAN RIGHTS QUARTERLY
Cultural relativity is a fact: cultures differ, often dramatically,
across
time and space. Cultural relativism is a set of doctrines that
imbue cultural
relativity with prescriptive force. For our purposes we can
distinguish meth-
odological and substantive cultural relativism.29
Methodological cultural relativism was popular among mid-
twentieth
century anthropologists. They advocated a radically non-
judgmental analysis
of cultures in order to free anthropology from unconscious, and
often even
conscious, biases rooted in describing and judging other
societies according
to modern Western categories and values.30 Such arguments
lead directly to a
recognition of the historical or anthropological relativity of
human rights.
In discussions of human rights, however, cultural relativism
typically ap-
pears as a substantive normative doctrine that demands respect
for cultural
differences.31 The norms of the Universal Declaration are
presented as having
no normative force in the face of divergent cultural traditions.
Practice is to
be evaluated instead by the standards of the culture in question.
As the State-
ment on Human Rights of the American Anthropological
Association (AAA)
put it, “man is free only when he lives as his society defines
freedom.”32
Rhoda Howard-Hassmann has aptly described this position as
“cultural
absolutism”33. Culture provides absolute standards of
evaluation; whatever
a culture says is right is right (for those in that culture).34
Rather than ad-
dress the details of such claims, which usually involve
arguments that other
29. John J. Tilley, Cultural Relativism, 22 Hum. RtS. Q. 501
(2000) carefully reviews a number
of particular conceptions and cites much of the relevant
literature from anthropology.
Compare Alison Dundes Renteln, Relativism and the Search for
Human Rights, 90 Am.
AntHRoPologiSt 56 (1988).
30. melville J. HeRSkovitS, cultuRAl RelAtiviSm:
PeRSPectiveS in cultuRAl PluRAliSm (1972).
31. Even Renteln, Relativism and the Search for Human Rights,
supra note 29, at 56, who
claims to be advancing “a metaethical theory about the nature of
moral perceptions,” thus
making her position more like what I have called
methodological relativism, insists on
“the requirement that diversity be recognized” and the “urgent
need to adopt a broader
view of human rights that incorporates diverse concepts.”
Alison Dundes Renteln, The
Unanswered Challenge of Relativism and the Consequences for
Human Rights, 7 Hum.
RtS. Q. 514, at 540 (1985). Such substantive propositions
simply do not follow from
methodological relativism or any causal or descriptive account
of moral perceptions.
32. Exec. Comm., Am. Anthropological Ass’n, Statement on
Human Rights, 49 Am. AntHRo-
PologiSt 539, 543 (1947).
33. Rhoda E. Howard, Cultural Absolutism and the Nostalgia
for Community, 15 Hum. RtS.
Q. 315 (1993).
34. A variant on such arguments popular in the 1980s held that
each of the three “worlds”
of that era—Western/liberal, Soviet/socialist and Third World—
had its own distinctive
conception of human rights, rooted in its own shared historical
experience and conception
of social justice. See, e.g., Hector Gros Espiell, The Evolving
Concept of Human Rights:
Western, Socialist and Third World Approaches, in HumAn
RigHtS: tHiRty yeARS AfteR tHe
univeRSAl DeclARAtion (B. G. Ramcharan ed., 1979);
Adamantia Pollis, Liberal, Socialist,
and Third World Perspectives on Human Rights, in Toward a
Human Rights Framework
1 (Peter Schwab & Adamantia Pollis eds., 1982). This story was
often associated with
a claim that the West was focused on “first generation” civil
and political rights, the
socialist world on “second generation” economic, social, and
cultural rights, and the Third
2007 The Relative Universality of Human Rights 295
cultures give greater attention to duties than to rights and to
groups than to
individuals, I will focus on six very serious general problems
with substan-
tive or absolutist cultural relativism.
First, it risks reducing “right” to “traditional,” “good” to “old,”
and
“obligatory” to “habitual.” Few societies or individuals,
however, believe that
their values are binding simply or even primarily because they
happen to be
widely endorsed within their culture. Without very powerful
philosophical
arguments (which are not to be found in this cultural relativist
literature on
human rights) it would seem inappropriate to adopt a theory that
is incon-
sistent with the moral experience of almost all people—
especially in the
name of cultural sensitivity and diversity.
Second, the equation of indigenous cultural origins with moral
validity
is deeply problematic. The AAA statement insists that
“standards and val-
ues are relative to the culture from which they derive so that
any attempt
to formulate postulates that grow out of the beliefs or moral
codes of one
culture must to that extent detract from the applicability of any
Declaration
of Human Rights to mankind as a whole.”35 The idea that
simply because a
value or practice emerged in place A makes it, to that extent,
inapplicable
to B is, at best, a dubious philosophical claim that assumes the
impossibil-
ity of moral learning or adaptation except within (closed)
cultures. It also
dangerously assumes the moral infallibility of culture.
Third, intolerant, even genocidal, relativism is as defensible as
tolerant
relativism. If my culture’s values tell me that others are
inferior, there is
World on “third generation” solidarity rights. See Stephen P.
Marks, Emerging Human
Rights: A New Generation for the 1980s?, 33 RutgeRS l. Rev.
435 (1981); Karel Vasak,
Pour une troisième génération des droits de l’homme, in
StuDieS AnD eSSAyS on inteRnAtionAl
HumAnitARiAn lAW AnD ReD cRoSS PRinciPleS in HonouR
of JeAn Pictet 837 (Christophe Swinarski
ed., 1984); Karel Vasak, Les différentes catégories des droits de
l’homme, in leS Dimen-
SionS univeRSelleS DeS DRoitS De l’Homme. vol. i. (André
Lapeyre, François de Tinguy, & Karel
Vasak eds., 1991). micHeline R. iSHAy, tHe HiStoRy of
HumAn RigHtS: fRom Ancient timeS to tHe
globAlizAtion eRA (2004) presents a relatively sophisticated
post-Cold War version of this
argument. For a counter-argument, see J. Donnelly, Third
Generation Rights, in PeoPleS
AnD minoRitieS in inteRnAtionAl lAW 119 (Catherine
Brölmann, René Lefeber & Marjoleine
Zieck eds., 1993).
The three worlds story suggests that level of development
and political history impose
priorities on (groups of) states. Socialist and Third World
states, it was argued, could
not afford the “luxury” of civil and political rights, being
legitimately preoccupied with
establishing their national sovereignty and economic and social
development. While
usually acknowledging the long run desirability of civil and
political rights, they were
dismissed as (at best) a secondary priority, a distraction, or
even a serious impediment
to progress in countries struggling to achieve self-determination
and economic develop-
ment. The claim, though, that benevolent governments that
denied civil and political
rights could deliver development more rapidly and spread its
benefits more universally,
unfortunately found almost no support in the experience of
developmental dictator-
ships of the left and the right alike during the Cold War. Quite
the contrary, pursuing
economic and social rights without civil and political rights in
practice usually led to
poor performance in realizing both, particularly over the
medium and long run.
35. Exec. Comm., Am. Anthropological Ass’n, supra note 32,
at 542.
Vol. 29296 HUMAN RIGHTS QUARTERLY
no standard by which to challenge this. A multidimensional,
multicultural
conception of human rights requires appeal to principles
inconsistent with
normative cultural relativism.
Fourth, cultural relativist arguments usually either ignore
politics or
confuse it with culture. The often deeply coercive aspect to
culture is simply
ignored. As a result, such arguments regularly confuse what a
people has
been forced to tolerate with what it values.
Fifth, these arguments typically ignore the impact of states,
markets,
colonialism, the spread of human rights ideas, and various other
social
forces. The cultures described are idealized representations of a
past that, if
it ever existed, certainly does not exist today. For example,
Roger Ames, in
an essay entitled “Continuing the Conversation of Chinese
Human Rights,”
completely ignores the impact of half a century of communist
party rule, as
if it were irrelevant to discussing human rights in contemporary
China.36
Sixth, and most generally, the typical account of culture as
coherent,
homogenous, consensual, and static largely ignores cultural
contingency,
contestation, and change. Culture in fact is a repertoire of
deeply contested
symbols, practices, and meanings over and with which members
of a society
constantly struggle.37 Culture is not destiny—or, to the extent
that it is, that
is only because victorious elements in a particular society have
used their
power to make a particular, contingent destiny.
The fact of cultural relativity and the doctrine of
methodological cul-
tural relativism are important antidotes to misplaced
universalism. The fear
of (neo-)imperialism and the desire to demonstrate cultural
respect that lie
behind many cultural relativist arguments need to be taken
seriously. Norma-
tive cultural relativism, however, is a deeply problematic moral
theory that
offers a poor understanding of the relativity of human rights.
10. SELf-dETERMINATIoN ANd SoVEREIGNTY
Self-determination and sovereignty ground a tolerant relativism
based on the
mutual recognition of peoples/states in an international
community. Self-de-
termination, understood as an ethical principle, involves a claim
that a free
36. Roger T. Ames, Continuing the Conversation on Chinese
Human Rights, 11 etHicS & int’l
Aff. 177 (1997).
37. For excellent brief applications of this understanding of
culture to debates over human
rights, see Ann-Belinda S. Preis, Human Rights as Cultural
Practice: An Anthropological
Critique, 18 Hum. RtS. Q. 286 (1996); Andrew J. Nathan,
Universalism: A Particularistic
Account, in negotiAting cultuRe AnD HumAn RigHtS (Lynda S.
Bell, Andrew J. Nathan &
Ilan Peleg eds., 2001). Compare also Neil A. Engelhart, Rights
and Culture in the Asian
Values Argument: The Rise and Fall of Confucian Ethics in
Singapore, 22 Hum. RtS. Q.
548 (2000); Elizabeth M. Zechenter, In the Name of Culture:
Cultural Relativism and
the Abuse of the Individual, 53 J. AntHRoPologicAl ReS. 319
(1997).
2007 The Relative Universality of Human Rights 297
people is entitled to choose for itself its own way of life and its
own form
of government. The language of “democracy” is also often used.
Democratic
self-determination is a communal expression of the principles of
equality
and autonomy that lie at the heart of the idea of human rights.
Whether a particular practice is in fact the free choice of a free
people,
however, is an empirical question. And self-determination must
not be
confused with legal sovereignty. Legally sovereign states need
not satisfy
or reflect the ethical principle of self-determination. Too often,
repressive
regimes falsely claim to reflect the will of the people. Too
often, international
legal sovereignty shields regimes that violate both ethical self-
determination
and most internationally recognized human rights—which
brings us back
to the relative enjoyment of human rights, based largely on
where one
happens to live.
Often the result is a conflict between justice, represented by
human
rights and self-determination, and order, represented by
international legal
sovereignty. Non-intervention in the face of even systematic
human rights
violations dramatically decreases potentially violent conflicts
between states.
We can also see international legal sovereignty as an ethical
principle of
the society of states, a principle of mutual toleration and respect
for (state)
equality and autonomy. However we interpret it, though, legal
sovereignty
introduces a considerable element of relativity into the
enjoyment of inter-
nationally recognized human rights in the contemporary world.
11. poST-STRUcTURAL, poST-coLoNIAL, ANd cRITIcAL
ARGUMENTS
The growing hegemony of the idea of human rights since the
end of the Cold
War, combined with the rise of post-structural and post-colonial
perspectives,
has spawned a new stream of relativist, or perhaps more
accurately anti-
universalist, arguments. Although often similar to earlier
cultural relativist
arguments in both substance and motivation, they typically are
based on a
very different sort of anti-foundationalist ontology and
epistemology38 and
tend to be specially addressed to the context of globalization.
They seek
to challenge arrogant, neo-imperial arguments of universality,
and draw
attention to “the civilizationally asymmetrical power relations
embedded
in the international discourse,” in order to open or preserve
discursive and
practical space for autonomous action by marginalized groups
and peoples
across the globe.39
38. Critical Marxian perspectives, however, make similar
arguments from a foundationalist
perspective. See, e.g., tony evAnS, uS Hegemony AnD tHe
PRoJect of univeRSAl HumAn RigHtS
(1996); HumAn RigHtS fifty yeARS on: A ReAPPRAiSAl
(Tony Evans ed., 1998).
39. Anthony Woodiwiss, Human Rights and the Challenge of
Cosmopolitanism, 19 tHeoRy,
cultuRe & Society 139 (2002).
Vol. 29298 HUMAN RIGHTS QUARTERLY
Although some versions of such arguments are dismissively
critical,40
many are well modulated. “[T]he seduction of human rights
discourse has
been so great that it has, in fact, delayed the development of a
critique of
rights.”41 They claim that a lack of critical self-reflection has
made human
rights advocates “more part of a problem in today’s world than
part of the
solution.”42 There are “dark sides of virtue.”43 The
uncomfortable reality,
whatever the intentions of Western practitioners, too often is
“imperial
humanitarianism.”44
In these accounts, universality per se—and more particularly the
ten-
dency for universal claims to intellectually obscure and
politically repress
difference—is targeted more than universal human rights in
particular. Con-
versely, even many fairly radical post-structuralist and post-
colonial authors
reject normative cultural relativism in favor of a more
dialogical approach
to cross-cultural consensus that is not in the end dissimilar to
overlapping
consensus arguments discussed above.45 This, I believe, is a
reflection of a
growing sophistication in the discussion of relativity and
universality -on
both sides of the old divide.
12. JUSTIfYING pARTIcULARITY: UNIVERSAL RIGHTS,
NoT
IdENTIcAL pRAcTIcES
Over the past decade, most discussions have tried to move
beyond a dichoto-
mous presentation of the issue of universality. Most
sophisticated defenders
of both universality and relativity today recognize the dangers
of an extreme
40. For example, Makau Mutua writes of “the biased and
arrogant rhetoric and history of
the human rights enterprise,” which is simply the latest
expression of “the historical
continuum of the Eurocentric colonial project.” Makau Mutua,
Savages, Victims, and
Saviors: The Metaphor of Human Rights, 42 HARv. int’l l. J.
201, 202, 204 (2001). The
hegemony of international human rights norms, in this reading,
amounts to granting
Western culture “the prerogative of imperialism, the right to
define and impose on others
what it deems good for humanity.” Id. at 219.
41. Makau Wa Mutua, The Ideology of Human Rights, 36
viRginiA J. int’l l. 589, 591
(1996).
42. David Kennedy, The International Human Rights
Movement: Part of the Problem?, 15
HARvARD Hum. RtS. J. 101 (2002).
43. DAviD kenneDy, tHe DARk SiDeS of viRtue:
ReASSeSSing inteRnAtionAl HumAnitARiAniSm (2004).
44. Gil Gott, Imperial Humanitarianism: History of an Arrested
Dialectic, in moRAl imPeRiAliSm:
A cRiticAl AntHology 19 (Berta Esperanza Hernández-Truyol
ed., 2002); compare Susan
Koshy, From Cold War to Trade War: Neocolonialism and
Human Rights, 58 SociAl text
1 (1999); Pheng Cheah, Posit(ion)ing Human Rights in the
Current Global Conjuncture,
Public cultuRe 233–266 (1997). Michael Ignatieff, Human
Rights as Politics, Human
Rights as Idolotry, in HumAn RigHtS AS PoliticS AnD
iDolAtRy 3, 53 (Amy Gutmann ed., 2001)
expresses similar worries from within a very traditional Western
liberal perspective.
45. See, e.g., Bonaventura de Sousa Santos, Toward a
Multicultural Conception of Human
Rights, in moRAl imPeRiAliSm: A cRiticAl AntHology 39
(Berta Esperanza Hernández-Truyol
ed., 2002); Berta Esperanza Hernández-Truyol & Sharon
Elizabeth Rush, Culture, Na-
tionhood, and the Human Rights Ideal, 33 u. micH. J. l. RefoRm
233 (2000).
2007 The Relative Universality of Human Rights 299
commitment and acknowledge at least some attractions and
insights in the
positions of their critics and opponents.
At the relatively universalistic end of this spectrum, I have
defended
“relative universality.”46 Towards the relativist end, Richard
Wilson argues that
ideas of and struggles for human rights “are embedded in local
normative
orders and yet are caught within webs of power and meaning
which extend
beyond the local.”47 Near the center, Andrew Nathan uses the
language of
“tempered universalism.”48
This more flexible account of universality (and relativity)
makes a three-
tiered scheme for thinking about universality that I have long
advocated
particularly useful for thinking about what ought to be
universal, and what
relative, in the domain of “universal human rights.”49 Human
rights are
(relatively) universal at the level of the concept, broad
formulations such as
the claims in Articles 3 and 22 of the Universal Declaration that
“everyone
has the right to life, liberty and security of person” and “the
right to social
security.”50 Particular rights concepts, however, have multiple
defensible
conceptions. Any particular conception, in turn, will have many
defensible
implementations. At this level—for example, the design of
electoral sys-
tems to implement the right “to take part in the government of
his country,
directly or through freely chosen representatives”—relativity is
not merely
defensible but desirable.51
Functional and overlapping consensus universality lie primarily
at the
level of concepts. Most of the Universal Declaration lies at this
level as well.
Although international human rights treaties often embody
particular concep-
tions, and sometimes even particular forms of
implementation,52 they too
46. Towards this end of the spectrum, compare Fred Halliday,
Relativism and Universalism
in Human Rights: the Case of the Islamic Middle East, 43 Pol.
StuD. 152 (1995); Michael
J. Perry, Are Human Rights Universal? The Relativist Challenge
and Related Matters, 19
Hum. RtS. Q. 461 (1997); Charles R. Beitz, Human Rights as a
Common Concern, 95
Am. Pol. Science Rev. 269 (2001).
47. HumAn RigHtS, cultuRe & context: AntHRoPologicAl
PeRSPectiveS 23 (Richard Wilson ed.,
1997); compare Fred Dallmayr, “Asian Values” and Global
Human Rights, 52 PHil. eASt
& WeSt 173 (2002); Charles Taylor, Conditions of an Unforced
Consensus on Human
Rights, in tHe eASt ASiAn cHAllenge foR HumAn RigHtS,
supra note 1; Penna & Campbell,
supra note 3.
48. Nathan, supra note 37; compare Preis, supra note 37;
Declan O’Sullivan, Is the Declara-
tion of Human Rights Universal? 4 J. Hum. RtS. 25 (2000).
49. Donnelly, Cultural Relativism and Universal Human
Rights, supra note 1; Donnelly,
univeRSAl HumAn RigHtS in tHeoRy AnD PRActice (2d ed.),
supra note 1, §6.4.
50. Universal Declaration of Human Rights, adopted 10 Dec.
1948, G.A. Res. 217A (III),
U.N. GAOR, 3d Sess. (Resolutions, pt. 1), at 71, arts. 3, 22,
U.N. Doc. A/810 (1948),
reprinted in 43 Am. J. int’l l. 127 (Supp. 1949).
51. Id. art. 21.
52. For example, Article 14 of the Convention against Torture
specifies that:
Each State Party shall ensure in its legal system that the victim
of an act of torture obtains redress
and has an enforceable right to fair and adequate compensation,
including the means for as full
rehabilitation as possible. In the event of the death of the victim
as a result of an act of torture,
his dependants shall be entitled to compensation.
Vol. 29300 HUMAN RIGHTS QUARTERLY
permit a wide range of particular practices. Substantial second
order varia-
tion, by country, region, culture, or other grouping, is
completely consistent
with international legal and overlapping consensus universality.
Concepts set a range of plausible variations among conceptions,
which
in turn restrict the range of practices that can plausibly be
considered
implementations of a particular concept and conception. But
even some
deviations from authoritative international human rights norms
may be, all
things considered, (not il)legitimate.
Four criteria can help us to grapple seriously yet
sympathetically with
claims in support of such deviations. For reasons of space, I
simply stipulate
these criteria, although I doubt that they are deeply
controversial once we
have accepted some notion of relative universality.53
1) Important differences in threats are likely to justify
variations even at
the level of concepts. Although perhaps the strongest theoretical
justification
for even fairly substantial deviations from international human
rights norms,
such arguments rarely are empirically persuasive in the
contemporary world.
(Indigenous peoples may be the exception that proves the
rule.)54
2) Participants in the overlapping consensus deserve a
sympathetic
hearing when they present serious reasoned arguments
justifying limited
deviations from international norms. Disagreements over
“details” should
be approached differently from systematic deviations or
comprehensive at-
tacks. If the resulting set of human rights remains generally
consistent with
the structure and overarching values of the Universal
Declaration, we should
be relatively tolerant of particular deviations.
Convention Against Torture and Other Cruel, Inhuman or
Degrading Treatment or Pun-
ishment, adopted 10 Dec. 1984, G.A. Res. 39/46, U.N. GAOR,
39th Sess., Supp. No.
51, art. 14, U.N. Doc. A/39/51 (1985) (entered into force 26
June 1987), reprinted in
23 i.l.m. 1027 (1984), substantive changes noted in 24 i.l.m.
535 (1985).
53. I am implicitly speaking from the perspective of an
engaged participant in international
society. A different and more complex “subject position” may
be important “on the
ground” where ordinary people have more local and
particularistic understandings of
their values. I suspect that much of the “talking past each other”
in debates on cultural
relativism and human rights arises from taking arguments that
may be well formulated
for a particular setting, be it local or international, and applying
them directly in another
discursive setting, without the adjustments required to give
those arguments resonance
and persuasive force in that context. For example, in much of
rural China today, direct
appeals to internationally recognized human rights are unlikely
to be politically effica-
cious, and often will be positively counter-productive, either for
mobilizing peasants
or persuading local authorities. Those working directly to
improve the day to day life
of Chinese peasants needs to give central place to this fact. But
I would suggest that it
says more about the Chinese state and the enforced isolation
and systematic repression
of Chinese peasants than about “Asian values.”
54. Defensible categorical differences between “developed”
and “developing” countries, I
would argue, involve, at most, differing short-term priorities
among particular interna-
tionally recognized human rights, not major differences in the
list of rights appropriate
for individuals in such countries.
2007 The Relative Universality of Human Rights 301
3) Arguments claiming that a particular conception or
implementation
is, for cultural or historical reasons, deeply imbedded within or
of unusu-
ally great significance to some significant group in society
deserve, on their
face, sympathetic consideration. Even if we do not positively
value diversity,
the autonomous choices of free people should never be lightly
dismissed,
especially when they reflect well-established practices based on
deeply
held beliefs.
4) Tolerance for deviations should decrease as the level of
coercion
increases.
13. Two ILLUSTRATIoNS
Article 18 of the Universal Declaration reads, in its entirety,
“Everyone
has the right to freedom of thought, conscience and religion;
this right in-
cludes freedom to change his religion or belief, and freedom,
either alone or
in community with others and in public or private, to manifest
his religion
or belief in teaching, practice, worship and observance.”55
Most schools of
Islamic law and scholarship deny Muslims the right to change
their religion.
Is prohibition of apostasy by Muslims compatible with the
relative univer-
sality of Article 18? Reasonable people may reasonably
disagree, but I am
inclined to answer “Probably.”
The variation is at the level of conceptions—the limits of the
range
of application of the principle of freedom of religion—in a
context where
the overarching concept is strongly endorsed. Most Islamic
countries and
communities respect the right of adherents of other religions to
practice
their beliefs (within the ordinary constraints of public order).
Prohibition
of apostasy also has a deeply rooted doctrinal basis, supported
by a long
tradition of practice. I think, therefore, that we are compelled to
approach it
with a certain prima facie tolerance, particularly if it is a
relatively isolated
deviation from international norm.56
Persuasion certainly lies within a state’s margin of appreciation.
Freedom
of religion does not require religious neutrality—separation of
church and
state, as Americans typically put it—but only that people be
free to choose
and practice their religion. Furthermore, there is no guarantee
that the choice
55. Universal Declaration, supra note 50, art. 18.
56. Even where there is a broad pattern of systematic violations
of international human
rights norms, we often would do well not to focus too much on
the issue of apostasy,
which is likely to have a much stronger internal justification
than many other violations
of internationally recognized human rights. A better strategy, at
least where apostates do
not suffer severely, would be to work to improve broader human
rights practices, with
the aim of creating a situation where we would be “willing to
live with” at least some
forms of prohibition of apostasy.
Vol. 29302 HUMAN RIGHTS QUARTERLY
be without cost. A state thus might be justified in denying
certain benefits
to apostates, as long as those benefits are not guaranteed by
human rights.
(Protection against discrimination on the basis of religion is one
of the
foundational principles of international human rights norms.) It
may even
be (not im)permissible to impose modest disabilities on
apostates, again
as long as they do not violate the human rights of apostates,
who remain
human beings entitled to all of their human rights. And the state
is under
no obligation to protect apostates against social sanctions
imposed by their
families and communities that do not infringe human rights.
Executing apostates, however, certainly exceeds the bounds of
permis-
sible variation. Violently imposing a specific conception of
freedom of reli-
gion inappropriately denies basic personal autonomy. Whatever
the internal
justification, this so excessively infringes the existing
international legal and
overlapping consensus that it is not entitled to international
toleration—al-
though we should stress that the same constraints on the use of
force apply
to external actors, even before we take into account the
additional constraints
imposed by considerations of sovereignty and international
order.
Consider now Article 4(a) of the Racial Discrimination
Convention,
which requires parties to prohibit racial violence and incitement
to such
violence and to “declare an offence punishable by law all
dissemination
of ideas based on racial superiority or hatred.”57 Article 20(2)
of the Inter-
national Covenant on Civil and Political Rights similarly
requires that “any
advocacy of national, racial or religious hatred that constitutes
incitement
to discrimination, hostility or violence shall be prohibited by
law.”58 Such
requirements have been rejected in the United States, where free
speech
includes even “hate speech” that does not incite violence.
Here the issue is balancing two competing human rights, rather
than
a conflict between human rights and another value. Any
resolution will
require restricting the range of at least one of these rights.
Therefore, any
approach that plausibly protects the conceptual integrity of both
rights must
be described as controversial but defensible. American practice
with respect
to hate speech clearly falls into this category.
Because incitement to violence is legally prohibited, US
practice involves
only a narrow deviation from international norms, with respect
to one part
of a second order conception, in a context of general support for
the over-
arching concepts and conceptions. Furthermore, the deviation is
on behalf
of a strong implementation of another vitally important human
rights. And
57. International Convention on the Elimination of All Forms
of Racial Discrimination,
adopted 21 Dec. 1965, art. 4, ¶ a, 660 U.N.T.S. 195 (entered
into force 4 Jan. 1969),
reprinted in 5 I.L.M. 352 (1966).
58. International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights,
adopted 19 Dec. 1966, G.A. Res.
2200 (XXI), U.N. GAOR, 21st Sess., Supp. No. 16, art. 20(2),
U.N. Doc. A/6316 (1966),
999 U.N.T.S. 171 (entered into force 23 Mar. 1976).
2007 The Relative Universality of Human Rights 303
it is deeply rooted in legal history and constitutional theory. I
can imagine
few stronger cases for justifiable deviations from international
norms.
Targets of hate speech may indeed be harmed by that speech.
They re-
main, however, protected against violence. Conversely,
prohibiting speech
because of its content harms those whose speech is restricted. It
also ef-
fectively involves state imposition of a particular viewpoint,
which is prima
facie undesirable. Reasonable people may reasonably disagree
about which
harm is greatest. Toleration of the American refusal to prohibit
hate speech
thus seems demanded, even from those who sincerely and no
less reasonably
believe that prohibiting hate speech is the better course of
action. Americans,
however, need to be respectful of the mainstream practice and
be willing to
engage principled arguments to conform with international
norms.
These brief arguments are hardly conclusive, perhaps not even
correct.
(I am inclined to think that my argument on apostasy accepts
too great a
relativism.) I think, though, that they show that the (relative)
universality of
internationally recognized human rights does not require, or
even encour-
age, global homogenization or the sacrifice of (many) valued
local practices.
Certainly nothing in my account of relative universality implies,
let alone
justifies, cultural imperialism. Quite the contrary, (relatively)
universal human
rights protect people from imposed conceptions of the good life,
whether
those visions are imposed by local or foreign actors.
Human rights seek to allow human beings, individually and in
groups
that give meaning and value to their lives, to pursue their own
visions of
the good life. Such choices—so long as they are consistent with
comparable
rights for others and reflect a plausible vision of human
flourishing to which
we can imagine a free people freely assenting—deserve our
respect. In fact,
understanding human rights as a political conception of justice
supported by
an overlapping consensus requires us to allow human beings,
individually and
collectively, considerable space to shape (relatively) universal
rights to their
particular purposes—so long as they operate largely within the
constraints
at the level of concepts established by functional, international
legal, and
overlapping consensus universality.
14. UNIVERSALISM wITHoUT IMpERIALISM
My account has emphasized the “good” sides of universalism,
understood in
limited, relative terms. The political dangers of arguments of
anthropological
universality are modest, at least if one accepts functional and
international
legal universality. In arguing against ontological universality,
however, I
ignored the dangers of imperialist intolerance when such claims
move into
politics. This final section considers a few of the political
dangers posed by
excessive or “false” universalism, especially when a powerful
actor (mis)takes
its own interests for universal values.
Vol. 29304 HUMAN RIGHTS QUARTERLY
The legacy of colonialism demands that Westerners show
special cau-
tion and sensitivity when advancing arguments of universalism
in the face
of clashing cultural values. Westerners must also remember the
political,
economic, and cultural power that lies behind even their best
intentioned
activities. Anything that even hints of imposing Western values
is likely to
be met with understandable suspicion, even resistance. How
arguments of
universalism and arguments of relativism are advanced may
sometimes be
as important as the substance of those arguments.59
Care and caution, however, must not be confused with
inattention or
inaction. Our values, and international human rights norms, may
demand
that we act on them even in the absence of agreement by
others—at least
when that action does not involve force. Even strongly
sanctioned tradi-
tions may not deserve our toleration if they are unusually
objectionable.
Consider, for example, the deeply rooted tradition of anti-
Semitism in the
West or “untouchables” and bonded labor in India. Even if such
traditional
practices were not rejected by the governments in question, they
would not
deserve the tolerance, let alone the respect, of outsiders. When
rights-abu-
sive practices raise issues of great moral significance, tradition
and culture
are slight defense.
Consider violence against homosexuals. International human
rights law
does not prohibit discrimination on the basis of sexual
orientation. Sexual
orientation is not mentioned in the Universal Declaration or the
Covenants,
and arguments that it falls within the category of “other status”
in Article 2
of each of these documents are widely accepted, at least at the
level of law,
only in Europe and a few other countries. Nonetheless, everyone
is entitled
to security of the person. If the state refuses to protect some
people against
private violence, on the grounds that they are immoral, the state
violates
their basic human rights—which are held no less by the immoral
than the
moral.60 And the idea that the state should be permitted to
imprison or even
execute people solely on the basis of private voluntary acts
between consent-
ing adults, however much that behavior or “lifestyle” offends
community
conceptions of morality, is inconsistent with any plausible
conception of
personal autonomy and individual human rights.
I do not mean to minimize the dangers of cultural and political
arrogance,
especially when backed by great power. US foreign policy often
confuses
American interests with universal values. Many Americans do
seem to believe
that what’s good for the US is good for the world—and if not,
then “that’s
59. I probably would not object to readers who took this as
implicit acknowledgment of
certain shortcomings in some of my previous work on
relativism, although I suspect
that we might disagree about the range of applicability of such
criticisms.
60. For clarity, let me explicitly note that I am not endorsing
these judgments but simply
arguing that even if they are accepted they do not justify
violating human rights.
2007 The Relative Universality of Human Rights 305
their problem.” The dangers of such arrogant and abusive
“universalism”
are especially striking in international relations, where
normative disputes
that cannot be resolved by rational persuasion or appeal to
agreed upon
international norms tend to be settled by (political, economic,
and cultural)
power—of which United States today has more than anyone
else.
Faced with such undoubtedly perverse “unilateral
universalism,” even
some well meaning critics have been seduced by misguided
arguments for
the essential relativity of human rights. This, however, in effect
accepts the
American confusion of human rights with US foreign policy.
The proper rem-
edy for “false” universalism is defensible, relative universalism.
Functional,
overlapping consensus, and international legal universality, in
addition to
their analytical and substantive virtues, can be valuable
resources for resist-
ing many of the excesses of American foreign policy, and
perhaps even for
redirecting it into more humane channels.
Indirect support for such an argument is provided by the
preference of
the Bush administration for the language of democracy and
freedom rather
than human rights.61 For example, the introductions to the 2002
and 2006
national security statements use “freedom” twenty-five times,
“democracy”
six times, and “human rights” just once (and not at all in
2006).62 Part
of the reason would seem to be that human rights does have a
relatively
precise and well-settled meaning in contemporary international
relations.
“Democracy” is both narrower and more imprecisely defined,
especially
internationally.63 And “freedom” is a remarkably malleable
idea—“rich” or
“empty,” depending on your perspective—as a review of the
roster of the
“free world” in the 1970s indicates.
International legal and overlapping consensus universality can
provide
important protection against the arrogant “universalism” of the
powerful.
Without authoritative international standards, to what can the
United States
(or any other great power) be held accountable? If international
legal uni-
versality has no force, why shouldn’t the United States act on
its own (often
peculiar) understandings of human rights? Even the Bush
Administration’s
preference for “coalitions of the willing” provides indirect
testimony to the
attractions of the idea of overlapping consensus.
61. Compare Julie Mertus, The New U.S. Human Rights Policy:
A Radical Departure, 4 int’l
StuD. PeRSPectiveS 371 (2003).
62. See available at www.whitehouse.gov/nsc/nssall.html;
www.whitehouse.gov/nsc/nss/2006/
print/intro.html. The prefaces of the Clinton national security
statements of 1996, 1997,
and 1999, taken together, use “democracy” twenty-one times,
“human rights” seven times,
and “freedom” six. See available at
www.fas.org/spp/military/docops/national/1996stra.
htm; www.fas.org/man/docs/strategy97.htm;
www.dtic.mil/doctrine/jel/other_pubs/nssr99.
pdf.
63. Donnelly, univeRSAl HumAn RigHtS in tHeoRy AnD
PRActice (2d ed.), supra note 1, §11.3
Vol. 29306 HUMAN RIGHTS QUARTERLY
The contemporary virtues of (relative) universality are
especially great
because the ideological hegemony of human rights in the post-
Cold War
world is largely independent of American power. As Abu
Ghraib indicates,
international human rights norms may even provoke changes in
policy in
the midst of what is typically presented as a war. The
international and
national focus on Guantanamo—which on its face is odd, given
the tiny
percentage of the victims of the War on Terror who have
suffered in this bit
of American-occupied Cuba—underscores the power of widely
endorsed
international norms to change the terms of debate and transform
the mean-
ing of actions.
International legal universality is one of the great achievements
of the
international human rights movement, both intrinsically and
because it
has facilitated a deepening overlapping consensus. Even the
United States
participates, fitfully and incompletely, in these consensuses.
Not just the
Clinton administration but both Bush administrations as well
have regularly
raised human rights concerns in numerous bilateral
relationships, usually
with a central element of genuine concern. (The real problem
with American
foreign policy is less where it does raise human rights concerns
than where
it doesn’t, or where it allows them to be subordinated to other
concerns.)
And all of this matters, directly to tens or hundreds of
thousands of people,
and indirectly to many hundreds of millions, whose lives have
been made
better by internationally recognized human rights.
Human rights are not a panacea for the world’s problems. They
do,
however, fully deserve the prominence they have received in
recent years.
For the foreseeable future, human rights will remain a vital
element in
national, international, and transnational struggles for social
justice and
human dignity. And the relative universality of those rights is a
powerful
resource that can be used to help to build more just and humane
national
and international societies.
7
Human Rights
Abdullahi A. An-Na`im
Human rights is not commonly accepted as a field in sociology,
despite the clear
overlap in subject matter and possibilities of mutual conceptual
and method-
ological influence. In terms of the organization of this volume,
for example,
freedom from discrimination, as an overarching human rights
principle, has
obvious implications for fields in sociology ranging from
citizenship and
national identity to education, stratification and mobility, and
health policy.
Specific human rights, like freedom of speech and association,
are clearly rele-
vant to issues of political participation and labor. Gender,
sexuality, children,
and race are major themes among human rights scholars. The
relationship
between the state and civil society is central to the international
articulation
and national implementation of human rights in all societies
around the world,
and as such of interest to sociologists. Human rights
considerations are also
relevant to the mediation of competing claims to economic and
social justice,
identity, and communal autonomy, in global cross-cultural and
comparative
terms. These concerns join those of sociologists over such
issues as globalization
and postcolonial power relations, social movements,
development, accountabil-
ity of transnational corporations for labor relations, and
environmental con-
cerns.
To explore possibilities of collaboration and mutual influence
between
sociologists and human rights scholars, I begin with an
overview of the human
rights paradigm as the framework for the specification and
implementation of
rights through national politics and international relations.
Since many of the
main themes of human rights are commonly known in terms of
constitutional or
civil rights (subject to the crucial difference indicated later),
sociologists might
want to consider whether their familiarity with the working of
domestic
(national) civil rights could enable them to contribute to
mediating what I call
the paradox of international accountability for the domestic
practice of
sovereign states. Mediating that paradox also calls for some
understanding of the
debate over the universality and cultural/contextual relativity of
human rights,
discussed in the second section. In the third section of this
chapter, I discuss the
need for complementary legal and social science approaches to
the implementa-
tion of human rights as a framework for justice; and provide a
brief review of
some of the ways in which sociologists have addressed human
rights issues.
The Human Rights ParadigmThe Human Rights Paradigm
Human rights, in a generic sense, can be seen as a framework
for an adequate
response to the profound social concerns of persons and their
communities. This
primarily procedural sense of human rights is about creating and
maintaining
`̀ the space'' for individuals and groups to achieve justice,
personal security and
well-being, general political stability and economic
development, and so forth.
At the same time, however, human rights norms do have a
specific normative
content that reflects a certain understanding of what these
individual and soci-
etal objectives mean, and how they should be realized in
practice. In a substan-
tive sense, therefore, human rights have a clear ideological
orientation to what it
means to be human, and how social and political institutions
should work in
order to achieve certain ends. However, there is a tension
between these two
dimensions of human rights. To inspire and motivate people to
take them
seriously, human rights need to have significant and relevant
normative content
in each specific context.Yet this is likely to be resisted by
privileged and powerful
persons and groups in any society precisely because of the
potential to change
existing power relations. Aspects of this tension and its
implications will become
clearer after a brief explanation of what human rights are
commonly understood
to mean, and how they are supposed to work.
By the human rights paradigm I mean the idea that the
protection of certain
individual and collective/group rights, as discussed below, is a
matter of inter-
national concern, rather than the exclusive internal affair of
states. Paradox-
ically, as explained below, the same states control the processes
of determining
these rights at the international level, and applying them within
national jur-
isdictions. Moreover, what the so-called international
community may do about
a state that willfully and persistently disregards its international
obligations to
protect those rights is also subject to a complex interaction of
legal principles
and practical considerations. For instance, the notion of `̀
humanitarian inter-
vention'' to stop serious human rights violations within a
country (as claimed by
the NATO governments who intervened militarily in Kosovo in
1999 against the
government of Yugoslavia) involves balancing such factors as
human concern
about the suffering of the victims, the risks of action or inaction
for international
peace and security, and the political and economic interests of
the intervening
state(s), as well as the short-and long-term implications of
violating the sover-
eignty of that country.
Much of the normative, as well as the procedural, dimension of
human rights
is traditionally supposed to be provided for in national
constitutions and laws
Human Rights 87
for domestic application by the judicial and executive organs of
the state, as a
matter of national sovereignty. Earlier attempts by some states
acting collectively
to extend such regimes into the boundaries of another state
included interna-
tional efforts to end slavery and to protect minorities during the
nineteenth and
early twentieth centuries. But the real launch of the human
rights paradigm in
the generally accepted sense came about around the middle of
the twentieth
century. The horrific events of the Second World War prompted
strong agree-
ment by the mid-1940s on the need to effectively check the
serious failure of any
state to protect the rights of all persons and groups within its
territorial jurisdic-
tion (Steiner and Alston, 1996, p. 59). That was the first time
there has ever been
such a broad consensus about the need to reconcile respect for
the sovereignty of
a state with the protection of certain human rights as rights due
to every human
being by virtue of his or her humanity, without distinction on
such grounds as
race, sex, belief, language, or national origin.
But since the process of determining the nature and scope of
these rights, and
approaches to their international protection, was confined to
sovereign states
which were members of the United Nations (UN) in 1945, only
four African
states and eight Asian states were included. The rest of Africa
and Asia was
colonized at that time by the same European powers that were
proclaiming the
universality of human rights at the UN. Moreover, some basic
ambiguities in the
original concept continue to frustrate the prospects of its
practical application.
For example, these rights are proclaimed in general terms as
belonging to all
human beings, while their realization is strongly associated with
citizenship of a
specific country. Although some general principles of
international law still
apply to how a state may treat non-citizens who happen to be
within its territory,
the distinction between citizen and non-citizen is sometimes
difficult to justify
from a human rights point of view (Turner, 1993b, p. 495;
1997). To avoid these
complex issues in this brief overview, I refer to persons under
the jurisdiction of a
state, instead of identifying them as its citizens.
The consensus of the mid-1940s was strongly reflected in the
Charter of the
UN of 1945, which is the most authoritative document of the
present interna-
tional order. According to Article 1 of the Charter, `̀ The
Purposes of the United
Nations are . . . (3) To achieve international cooperation in
solving international
problems of an economic, social, cultural, or humanitarian
character, and in
promoting and encouraging respect for human rights and for
fundamental free-
doms for all without distinction as to race, sex, language, or
religion.'' While
emphasizing this basic obligation in other Articles, the UN
Charter left the task
of definition and implementation of `̀ human rights and
fundamental freedoms''
to subsequent developments.
That process began with the drafting and adoption of the
Universal Declara-
tion of Human Rights of 1948. But the Declaration is not
binding as such
because, according to the UN Charter, resolutions of the
General Assembly are
merely recommendations to member states of the organization.
The drafting and
adoption of detailed treaties, which are binding under
international law,
followed, to provide definitions of rights and their
implementation. Moreover,
some human rights norms can also be found in certain principles
of what is
88 Abdullahi Ahmed An-Na`im
known as customary international law, like the prohibition of
genocide, war
crimes, and crimes against humanity. These norms are binding
on all states,
regardless of their ratification of treaties on those matters.
Some human rights
scholars argue that certain aspects of the Universal Declaration
have become
binding as customary international law. For example, the
prohibition of torture
is generally accepted as binding on all states as a principle of
customary
international law, regardless of their ratification of the specific
treaties on the
subject.
The treaties setting the international `̀ legal'' standards of
human rights range
in scope from earlier Conventions on labor rights (1930),
genocide (1948), and
slavery (1956), to the broad 1966 International Covenants, one
on economic,
social and cultural rights, and the other on civil and political
rights. There is also
a growing number of specialized treaties, like the Conventions
for the Elimina-
tion of All Forms of Discrimination, on grounds of race (1965)
and gender
(1979), and the Convention on the Rights of the Child of 1989.
Similar stand-
ards appear in the regional documents of the European, Inter-
American, and
African systems (Steiner and Alston, 1996, p. 563). This legal
regime also
includes principles of humanitarian law regulating the conduct
of armed forces
in conflict situations, like the four Geneva Conventions of 1949,
and the 1951
Refugees Convention. Human rights standards have also been
elaborated
through several major international conferences. During the
1990s, for instance,
human rights principles and policies were elaborated in such
documents as the
Vienna Declaration and Programme of Action (1994) and the
Beijing Platform
for Action of the Fourth World Conference on Women (1995).
Human rights are
integral to the mandate of specialized intergovernmental
agencies like the Inter-
national Labor Organization (ILO), the World Health
Organization (WHO),
and the United Nation Development Programme (UNDP).
As the increasingly wide range of local, regional, and global
actors and
processes envisioned by this complex web of documents and
institutions clearly
shows, the development of an international legal framework
cannot mean that
the implementation of human rights be left to purely legal
approaches. The basic
idea of the human rights paradigm is now firmly established in
international
relations, as well as in the national politics of the vast majority
of countries
around the world, subject to differing assessment of its efficacy
or consistency of
its application. Nevertheless, the basic paradox remains: how to
achieve effect-
ive international supervision of domestic human rights
protection without
violating national sovereignty as the expression of the right to
self-determina-
tion, which is itself a collective human right under the first
Article of the 1966
Covenants.
From this perspective, I suggest, social science approaches
would be extremely
important for understanding the processes of legal articulation
and implementa-
tion of these rights as the proper and legitimate exercise of the
right to self-
determination, rather than its negation. Sociological analyses
are needed, for
example, for understanding the processes of social construction
of rights, whose
interests are served by those processes, and the role of civil
society and social
movements in generating the political will to adopt and
implement international
Human Rights 89
treaties protecting these rights. Such insights are essential for
mediating the
paradox of international protection of human rights through
respect for sover-
eignty, instead of its violation, as explained below.
It is true that, by ratifying treaties and subscribing to
international human
rights policy statements, states are indicating voluntary
acceptance of human
rights obligations as limitations on their national sovereignty.
But that notion
itself can be seen as entrenching, rather than diminishing, the
underlying para-
dox, because it is the state that decides when, how, and to what
extent to limit its
own sovereignty. First, the structure and content of any human
rights treaty are
negotiated and agreed among the delegates of states, before the
treaty is opened
for ratification. Second, and regardless of its publicly declared
position, no state
is legally bound until it formally ratifies the treaty according to
its own internal
constitutional and political process. Moreover, subject to the
requirements of the
international law of treaties, a state has the right not only to
enter `̀ reservations''
limiting the scope of its obligations under a treaty, but also to
repudiate a treaty
that it has previously ratified. Third, the state is also intended
to play a crucial
role in the interpretation and implementation within its territory
of the human
rights treaties it has ratified. Where national legislation is
required to incorpor-
ate international treaties into national law, as in the United
States and United
Kingdom, the domestic normative content of a treaty is
effectively determined by
the way it is expressed in legislative language, and interpreted
through the
judicial process, of the country (Steiner and Alston, 1996, p.
26). In other
words, domestic compliance with a state's international
obligations to protect
human rights can only be achieved by the official organs of the
same state.
Thus, while intended to ensure the protection of certain
minimum rights,
international protection is dependent on the active cooperation
of states in
limiting their freedom of action within their own domestic
jurisdiction. The
paradox of self-regulation by the state of its own behavior is, of
course, also
true of domestic constitutional and legal protection of rights.
The crucial differ-
ence, noted above, is that constitutional rights are the product
of internal
dynamics, whereas the human rights paradigm seeks to
influence domestic
situations in favor of upholding certain internationally
recognized standards.
In other words, the paradox is sharper for the human rights
paradigm because it
has to overcome internal opposition within the country in
question, without
having the power to impose its will on states which refuse to
comply. The need to
mediate this enduring paradox calls for a clear understanding of
the nature and
functioning of social and political forces and institutions within
each country,
and in its relations with other countries.
It is not helpful to simply call for formal limitations on state
sovereignty,
because that is neither practically feasible nor necessarily good
for the protection
of human rights in the long term. Formal limitations on
sovereignty are not
feasible because sovereignty is integral to the foundations of the
present inter-
national order, as entrenched in Article 2(7) of the UN Charter
and other
international documents, and fundamentally affirmed by
national constitutions
around the world. Since states are the principal actors at both
the international
and national levels, they are unlikely to relinquish their own
autonomy by
90 Abdullahi Ahmed An-Na`im
abandoning sovereignty or allowing other actors to achieve that
result. Even if
they were practically feasible, formal limitations might also be
counterproduc-
tive because sovereignty is the essential expression of the
fundamental collective
right to self-determination, as the practical vehicle of domestic
policy and the
necessary medium of international relations.
A more realistic and desirable approach, I suggest, is to seek to
diminish the
negative consequence of the paradox of self-regulation by
infusing the human
rights ethos into the fabric of the state itself and the global
context in which it
operates. In that way, the protection of human rights becomes
the outcome of
the free exercise of the right to self-determination, instead of
being seen as an
external imposition which violates that right. This paradigm
shift can best be
achieved by upholding the universality of human rights as, in
the words of the
Preamble to the Universal Declaration, `̀ the common standard
of achievement
for all peoples and all nations.'' Since external imposition will
probably be
resisted as a clear violation of sovereignty, while voluntary
compliance with
commonly agreed standards is likely to be seen as vindication
of sovereign
authority, the universality of human rights must reflect true
consensus around
the world. At a formal level, that is said to be achieved through
agreement
among states, as the representatives of their societies under
international law.
But according to the human rights paradigm itself, and as a
matter of practical
politics, international agreements are legitimate and sustainable
only to the
extent that they express the genuine consent of national
The Relative Universality of Internationally Recognized Human Rights
The Relative Universality of Internationally Recognized Human Rights
The Relative Universality of Internationally Recognized Human Rights
The Relative Universality of Internationally Recognized Human Rights
The Relative Universality of Internationally Recognized Human Rights
The Relative Universality of Internationally Recognized Human Rights
The Relative Universality of Internationally Recognized Human Rights
The Relative Universality of Internationally Recognized Human Rights
The Relative Universality of Internationally Recognized Human Rights
The Relative Universality of Internationally Recognized Human Rights
The Relative Universality of Internationally Recognized Human Rights
The Relative Universality of Internationally Recognized Human Rights
The Relative Universality of Internationally Recognized Human Rights
The Relative Universality of Internationally Recognized Human Rights
The Relative Universality of Internationally Recognized Human Rights
The Relative Universality of Internationally Recognized Human Rights
The Relative Universality of Internationally Recognized Human Rights
The Relative Universality of Internationally Recognized Human Rights
The Relative Universality of Internationally Recognized Human Rights
The Relative Universality of Internationally Recognized Human Rights
The Relative Universality of Internationally Recognized Human Rights

More Related Content

Similar to The Relative Universality of Internationally Recognized Human Rights

Based on Arendt’s analysis of human rights, do you think human rig.docx
Based on Arendt’s analysis of human rights, do you think human rig.docxBased on Arendt’s analysis of human rights, do you think human rig.docx
Based on Arendt’s analysis of human rights, do you think human rig.docxjasoninnes20
 
Human rights
Human rights Human rights
Human rights SJSurya6
 
Womens Rights as Human Rights Toward a Re-Vision of Human Ri.docx
Womens Rights as Human Rights Toward a Re-Vision of Human Ri.docxWomens Rights as Human Rights Toward a Re-Vision of Human Ri.docx
Womens Rights as Human Rights Toward a Re-Vision of Human Ri.docxlefrancoishazlett
 
The Human rights protection in the world
The Human rights protection in the worldThe Human rights protection in the world
The Human rights protection in the worldShwkatHossain1
 
Historical development
Historical developmentHistorical development
Historical developmentFahad Nakade
 
The Human Rights and their deficiencies book 6
The Human Rights and their deficiencies book 6The Human Rights and their deficiencies book 6
The Human Rights and their deficiencies book 6Miguel Cano
 
FC II NOTES FULL FLEX 5 LESSONS BBI.pptx
FC II NOTES FULL FLEX 5 LESSONS BBI.pptxFC II NOTES FULL FLEX 5 LESSONS BBI.pptx
FC II NOTES FULL FLEX 5 LESSONS BBI.pptxVidhiJAIN137470
 

Similar to The Relative Universality of Internationally Recognized Human Rights (13)

Based on Arendt’s analysis of human rights, do you think human rig.docx
Based on Arendt’s analysis of human rights, do you think human rig.docxBased on Arendt’s analysis of human rights, do you think human rig.docx
Based on Arendt’s analysis of human rights, do you think human rig.docx
 
Human rights
Human rights Human rights
Human rights
 
Human Rights (1) (1)
Human Rights (1) (1)Human Rights (1) (1)
Human Rights (1) (1)
 
Womens Rights as Human Rights Toward a Re-Vision of Human Ri.docx
Womens Rights as Human Rights Toward a Re-Vision of Human Ri.docxWomens Rights as Human Rights Toward a Re-Vision of Human Ri.docx
Womens Rights as Human Rights Toward a Re-Vision of Human Ri.docx
 
The Human rights protection in the world
The Human rights protection in the worldThe Human rights protection in the world
The Human rights protection in the world
 
Human rights
Human rightsHuman rights
Human rights
 
Historical development
Historical developmentHistorical development
Historical development
 
Human Rights Essay Writing
Human Rights Essay WritingHuman Rights Essay Writing
Human Rights Essay Writing
 
The Human Rights and their deficiencies book 6
The Human Rights and their deficiencies book 6The Human Rights and their deficiencies book 6
The Human Rights and their deficiencies book 6
 
FC II NOTES FULL FLEX 5 LESSONS BBI.pptx
FC II NOTES FULL FLEX 5 LESSONS BBI.pptxFC II NOTES FULL FLEX 5 LESSONS BBI.pptx
FC II NOTES FULL FLEX 5 LESSONS BBI.pptx
 
Essays On Human Rights
Essays On Human RightsEssays On Human Rights
Essays On Human Rights
 
Human rights in_india
Human rights in_indiaHuman rights in_india
Human rights in_india
 
Crisis in Cambodia
Crisis in CambodiaCrisis in Cambodia
Crisis in Cambodia
 

More from rhetttrevannion

Discuss three (3) ways that large organizations are increasingly eng.docx
Discuss three (3) ways that large organizations are increasingly eng.docxDiscuss three (3) ways that large organizations are increasingly eng.docx
Discuss three (3) ways that large organizations are increasingly eng.docxrhetttrevannion
 
Discuss this week’s objectives with your team sharing related rese.docx
Discuss this week’s objectives with your team sharing related rese.docxDiscuss this week’s objectives with your team sharing related rese.docx
Discuss this week’s objectives with your team sharing related rese.docxrhetttrevannion
 
Discuss theoretical considerations or assumptions relevant to yo.docx
Discuss theoretical considerations or assumptions relevant to yo.docxDiscuss theoretical considerations or assumptions relevant to yo.docx
Discuss theoretical considerations or assumptions relevant to yo.docxrhetttrevannion
 
Discuss theprinciple events of PROCESS AND THREAD used in both t.docx
Discuss theprinciple events of PROCESS AND THREAD used in both t.docxDiscuss theprinciple events of PROCESS AND THREAD used in both t.docx
Discuss theprinciple events of PROCESS AND THREAD used in both t.docxrhetttrevannion
 
Discuss the Windows Registry System Hive1) What information.docx
Discuss the Windows Registry System Hive1) What information.docxDiscuss the Windows Registry System Hive1) What information.docx
Discuss the Windows Registry System Hive1) What information.docxrhetttrevannion
 
Discuss the way the idea of heroism develops from Gilgamesh th.docx
Discuss the way the idea of heroism develops from Gilgamesh th.docxDiscuss the way the idea of heroism develops from Gilgamesh th.docx
Discuss the way the idea of heroism develops from Gilgamesh th.docxrhetttrevannion
 
Discuss the ways in which the history of the U.S. was presented in t.docx
Discuss the ways in which the history of the U.S. was presented in t.docxDiscuss the ways in which the history of the U.S. was presented in t.docx
Discuss the ways in which the history of the U.S. was presented in t.docxrhetttrevannion
 
Discuss the value of Lean Systems Engineering to systems develop.docx
Discuss the value of Lean Systems Engineering to systems develop.docxDiscuss the value of Lean Systems Engineering to systems develop.docx
Discuss the value of Lean Systems Engineering to systems develop.docxrhetttrevannion
 
discuss the various pathways interest groups use to influence politi.docx
discuss the various pathways interest groups use to influence politi.docxdiscuss the various pathways interest groups use to influence politi.docx
discuss the various pathways interest groups use to influence politi.docxrhetttrevannion
 
Discuss the various tools and techniques used by an HCO to incre.docx
Discuss the various tools and techniques used by an HCO to incre.docxDiscuss the various tools and techniques used by an HCO to incre.docx
Discuss the various tools and techniques used by an HCO to incre.docxrhetttrevannion
 
Discuss the various means by which slaves resisted the slave system..docx
Discuss the various means by which slaves resisted the slave system..docxDiscuss the various means by which slaves resisted the slave system..docx
Discuss the various means by which slaves resisted the slave system..docxrhetttrevannion
 
Discuss the typica l clinical presentation of the diagnosis , Hip Os.docx
Discuss the typica l clinical presentation of the diagnosis , Hip Os.docxDiscuss the typica l clinical presentation of the diagnosis , Hip Os.docx
Discuss the typica l clinical presentation of the diagnosis , Hip Os.docxrhetttrevannion
 
Discuss the types of resources, tools, and methods that are availabl.docx
Discuss the types of resources, tools, and methods that are availabl.docxDiscuss the types of resources, tools, and methods that are availabl.docx
Discuss the types of resources, tools, and methods that are availabl.docxrhetttrevannion
 
Discuss the types of items that should be examined in a firewall log.docx
Discuss the types of items that should be examined in a firewall log.docxDiscuss the types of items that should be examined in a firewall log.docx
Discuss the types of items that should be examined in a firewall log.docxrhetttrevannion
 
Discuss the types of property, providing an example of each an.docx
Discuss the types of property, providing an example of each an.docxDiscuss the types of property, providing an example of each an.docx
Discuss the types of property, providing an example of each an.docxrhetttrevannion
 
Discuss the type of personality it takes to become a police officer..docx
Discuss the type of personality it takes to become a police officer..docxDiscuss the type of personality it takes to become a police officer..docx
Discuss the type of personality it takes to become a police officer..docxrhetttrevannion
 
Discuss the two major sources of crime statistics for the United Sta.docx
Discuss the two major sources of crime statistics for the United Sta.docxDiscuss the two major sources of crime statistics for the United Sta.docx
Discuss the two major sources of crime statistics for the United Sta.docxrhetttrevannion
 
Discuss the two most prominent theories related to the stage of adul.docx
Discuss the two most prominent theories related to the stage of adul.docxDiscuss the two most prominent theories related to the stage of adul.docx
Discuss the two most prominent theories related to the stage of adul.docxrhetttrevannion
 
Discuss the two elements required for the consent defense. In ad.docx
Discuss the two elements required for the consent defense. In ad.docxDiscuss the two elements required for the consent defense. In ad.docx
Discuss the two elements required for the consent defense. In ad.docxrhetttrevannion
 
Discuss the Truth in Lending Act and what role it places in financia.docx
Discuss the Truth in Lending Act and what role it places in financia.docxDiscuss the Truth in Lending Act and what role it places in financia.docx
Discuss the Truth in Lending Act and what role it places in financia.docxrhetttrevannion
 

More from rhetttrevannion (20)

Discuss three (3) ways that large organizations are increasingly eng.docx
Discuss three (3) ways that large organizations are increasingly eng.docxDiscuss three (3) ways that large organizations are increasingly eng.docx
Discuss three (3) ways that large organizations are increasingly eng.docx
 
Discuss this week’s objectives with your team sharing related rese.docx
Discuss this week’s objectives with your team sharing related rese.docxDiscuss this week’s objectives with your team sharing related rese.docx
Discuss this week’s objectives with your team sharing related rese.docx
 
Discuss theoretical considerations or assumptions relevant to yo.docx
Discuss theoretical considerations or assumptions relevant to yo.docxDiscuss theoretical considerations or assumptions relevant to yo.docx
Discuss theoretical considerations or assumptions relevant to yo.docx
 
Discuss theprinciple events of PROCESS AND THREAD used in both t.docx
Discuss theprinciple events of PROCESS AND THREAD used in both t.docxDiscuss theprinciple events of PROCESS AND THREAD used in both t.docx
Discuss theprinciple events of PROCESS AND THREAD used in both t.docx
 
Discuss the Windows Registry System Hive1) What information.docx
Discuss the Windows Registry System Hive1) What information.docxDiscuss the Windows Registry System Hive1) What information.docx
Discuss the Windows Registry System Hive1) What information.docx
 
Discuss the way the idea of heroism develops from Gilgamesh th.docx
Discuss the way the idea of heroism develops from Gilgamesh th.docxDiscuss the way the idea of heroism develops from Gilgamesh th.docx
Discuss the way the idea of heroism develops from Gilgamesh th.docx
 
Discuss the ways in which the history of the U.S. was presented in t.docx
Discuss the ways in which the history of the U.S. was presented in t.docxDiscuss the ways in which the history of the U.S. was presented in t.docx
Discuss the ways in which the history of the U.S. was presented in t.docx
 
Discuss the value of Lean Systems Engineering to systems develop.docx
Discuss the value of Lean Systems Engineering to systems develop.docxDiscuss the value of Lean Systems Engineering to systems develop.docx
Discuss the value of Lean Systems Engineering to systems develop.docx
 
discuss the various pathways interest groups use to influence politi.docx
discuss the various pathways interest groups use to influence politi.docxdiscuss the various pathways interest groups use to influence politi.docx
discuss the various pathways interest groups use to influence politi.docx
 
Discuss the various tools and techniques used by an HCO to incre.docx
Discuss the various tools and techniques used by an HCO to incre.docxDiscuss the various tools and techniques used by an HCO to incre.docx
Discuss the various tools and techniques used by an HCO to incre.docx
 
Discuss the various means by which slaves resisted the slave system..docx
Discuss the various means by which slaves resisted the slave system..docxDiscuss the various means by which slaves resisted the slave system..docx
Discuss the various means by which slaves resisted the slave system..docx
 
Discuss the typica l clinical presentation of the diagnosis , Hip Os.docx
Discuss the typica l clinical presentation of the diagnosis , Hip Os.docxDiscuss the typica l clinical presentation of the diagnosis , Hip Os.docx
Discuss the typica l clinical presentation of the diagnosis , Hip Os.docx
 
Discuss the types of resources, tools, and methods that are availabl.docx
Discuss the types of resources, tools, and methods that are availabl.docxDiscuss the types of resources, tools, and methods that are availabl.docx
Discuss the types of resources, tools, and methods that are availabl.docx
 
Discuss the types of items that should be examined in a firewall log.docx
Discuss the types of items that should be examined in a firewall log.docxDiscuss the types of items that should be examined in a firewall log.docx
Discuss the types of items that should be examined in a firewall log.docx
 
Discuss the types of property, providing an example of each an.docx
Discuss the types of property, providing an example of each an.docxDiscuss the types of property, providing an example of each an.docx
Discuss the types of property, providing an example of each an.docx
 
Discuss the type of personality it takes to become a police officer..docx
Discuss the type of personality it takes to become a police officer..docxDiscuss the type of personality it takes to become a police officer..docx
Discuss the type of personality it takes to become a police officer..docx
 
Discuss the two major sources of crime statistics for the United Sta.docx
Discuss the two major sources of crime statistics for the United Sta.docxDiscuss the two major sources of crime statistics for the United Sta.docx
Discuss the two major sources of crime statistics for the United Sta.docx
 
Discuss the two most prominent theories related to the stage of adul.docx
Discuss the two most prominent theories related to the stage of adul.docxDiscuss the two most prominent theories related to the stage of adul.docx
Discuss the two most prominent theories related to the stage of adul.docx
 
Discuss the two elements required for the consent defense. In ad.docx
Discuss the two elements required for the consent defense. In ad.docxDiscuss the two elements required for the consent defense. In ad.docx
Discuss the two elements required for the consent defense. In ad.docx
 
Discuss the Truth in Lending Act and what role it places in financia.docx
Discuss the Truth in Lending Act and what role it places in financia.docxDiscuss the Truth in Lending Act and what role it places in financia.docx
Discuss the Truth in Lending Act and what role it places in financia.docx
 

Recently uploaded

Proudly South Africa powerpoint Thorisha.pptx
Proudly South Africa powerpoint Thorisha.pptxProudly South Africa powerpoint Thorisha.pptx
Proudly South Africa powerpoint Thorisha.pptxthorishapillay1
 
Paris 2024 Olympic Geographies - an activity
Paris 2024 Olympic Geographies - an activityParis 2024 Olympic Geographies - an activity
Paris 2024 Olympic Geographies - an activityGeoBlogs
 
The Most Excellent Way | 1 Corinthians 13
The Most Excellent Way | 1 Corinthians 13The Most Excellent Way | 1 Corinthians 13
The Most Excellent Way | 1 Corinthians 13Steve Thomason
 
Crayon Activity Handout For the Crayon A
Crayon Activity Handout For the Crayon ACrayon Activity Handout For the Crayon A
Crayon Activity Handout For the Crayon AUnboundStockton
 
call girls in Kamla Market (DELHI) 🔝 >༒9953330565🔝 genuine Escort Service 🔝✔️✔️
call girls in Kamla Market (DELHI) 🔝 >༒9953330565🔝 genuine Escort Service 🔝✔️✔️call girls in Kamla Market (DELHI) 🔝 >༒9953330565🔝 genuine Escort Service 🔝✔️✔️
call girls in Kamla Market (DELHI) 🔝 >༒9953330565🔝 genuine Escort Service 🔝✔️✔️9953056974 Low Rate Call Girls In Saket, Delhi NCR
 
Organic Name Reactions for the students and aspirants of Chemistry12th.pptx
Organic Name Reactions  for the students and aspirants of Chemistry12th.pptxOrganic Name Reactions  for the students and aspirants of Chemistry12th.pptx
Organic Name Reactions for the students and aspirants of Chemistry12th.pptxVS Mahajan Coaching Centre
 
How to Configure Email Server in Odoo 17
How to Configure Email Server in Odoo 17How to Configure Email Server in Odoo 17
How to Configure Email Server in Odoo 17Celine George
 
Employee wellbeing at the workplace.pptx
Employee wellbeing at the workplace.pptxEmployee wellbeing at the workplace.pptx
Employee wellbeing at the workplace.pptxNirmalaLoungPoorunde1
 
Biting mechanism of poisonous snakes.pdf
Biting mechanism of poisonous snakes.pdfBiting mechanism of poisonous snakes.pdf
Biting mechanism of poisonous snakes.pdfadityarao40181
 
Science lesson Moon for 4th quarter lesson
Science lesson Moon for 4th quarter lessonScience lesson Moon for 4th quarter lesson
Science lesson Moon for 4th quarter lessonJericReyAuditor
 
History Class XII Ch. 3 Kinship, Caste and Class (1).pptx
History Class XII Ch. 3 Kinship, Caste and Class (1).pptxHistory Class XII Ch. 3 Kinship, Caste and Class (1).pptx
History Class XII Ch. 3 Kinship, Caste and Class (1).pptxsocialsciencegdgrohi
 
Presiding Officer Training module 2024 lok sabha elections
Presiding Officer Training module 2024 lok sabha electionsPresiding Officer Training module 2024 lok sabha elections
Presiding Officer Training module 2024 lok sabha electionsanshu789521
 
Solving Puzzles Benefits Everyone (English).pptx
Solving Puzzles Benefits Everyone (English).pptxSolving Puzzles Benefits Everyone (English).pptx
Solving Puzzles Benefits Everyone (English).pptxOH TEIK BIN
 
18-04-UA_REPORT_MEDIALITERAСY_INDEX-DM_23-1-final-eng.pdf
18-04-UA_REPORT_MEDIALITERAСY_INDEX-DM_23-1-final-eng.pdf18-04-UA_REPORT_MEDIALITERAСY_INDEX-DM_23-1-final-eng.pdf
18-04-UA_REPORT_MEDIALITERAСY_INDEX-DM_23-1-final-eng.pdfssuser54595a
 
BASLIQ CURRENT LOOKBOOK LOOKBOOK(1) (1).pdf
BASLIQ CURRENT LOOKBOOK  LOOKBOOK(1) (1).pdfBASLIQ CURRENT LOOKBOOK  LOOKBOOK(1) (1).pdf
BASLIQ CURRENT LOOKBOOK LOOKBOOK(1) (1).pdfSoniaTolstoy
 
Pharmacognosy Flower 3. Compositae 2023.pdf
Pharmacognosy Flower 3. Compositae 2023.pdfPharmacognosy Flower 3. Compositae 2023.pdf
Pharmacognosy Flower 3. Compositae 2023.pdfMahmoud M. Sallam
 
Hybridoma Technology ( Production , Purification , and Application )
Hybridoma Technology  ( Production , Purification , and Application  ) Hybridoma Technology  ( Production , Purification , and Application  )
Hybridoma Technology ( Production , Purification , and Application ) Sakshi Ghasle
 
_Math 4-Q4 Week 5.pptx Steps in Collecting Data
_Math 4-Q4 Week 5.pptx Steps in Collecting Data_Math 4-Q4 Week 5.pptx Steps in Collecting Data
_Math 4-Q4 Week 5.pptx Steps in Collecting DataJhengPantaleon
 

Recently uploaded (20)

Proudly South Africa powerpoint Thorisha.pptx
Proudly South Africa powerpoint Thorisha.pptxProudly South Africa powerpoint Thorisha.pptx
Proudly South Africa powerpoint Thorisha.pptx
 
Paris 2024 Olympic Geographies - an activity
Paris 2024 Olympic Geographies - an activityParis 2024 Olympic Geographies - an activity
Paris 2024 Olympic Geographies - an activity
 
The Most Excellent Way | 1 Corinthians 13
The Most Excellent Way | 1 Corinthians 13The Most Excellent Way | 1 Corinthians 13
The Most Excellent Way | 1 Corinthians 13
 
Crayon Activity Handout For the Crayon A
Crayon Activity Handout For the Crayon ACrayon Activity Handout For the Crayon A
Crayon Activity Handout For the Crayon A
 
call girls in Kamla Market (DELHI) 🔝 >༒9953330565🔝 genuine Escort Service 🔝✔️✔️
call girls in Kamla Market (DELHI) 🔝 >༒9953330565🔝 genuine Escort Service 🔝✔️✔️call girls in Kamla Market (DELHI) 🔝 >༒9953330565🔝 genuine Escort Service 🔝✔️✔️
call girls in Kamla Market (DELHI) 🔝 >༒9953330565🔝 genuine Escort Service 🔝✔️✔️
 
Organic Name Reactions for the students and aspirants of Chemistry12th.pptx
Organic Name Reactions  for the students and aspirants of Chemistry12th.pptxOrganic Name Reactions  for the students and aspirants of Chemistry12th.pptx
Organic Name Reactions for the students and aspirants of Chemistry12th.pptx
 
How to Configure Email Server in Odoo 17
How to Configure Email Server in Odoo 17How to Configure Email Server in Odoo 17
How to Configure Email Server in Odoo 17
 
Employee wellbeing at the workplace.pptx
Employee wellbeing at the workplace.pptxEmployee wellbeing at the workplace.pptx
Employee wellbeing at the workplace.pptx
 
Biting mechanism of poisonous snakes.pdf
Biting mechanism of poisonous snakes.pdfBiting mechanism of poisonous snakes.pdf
Biting mechanism of poisonous snakes.pdf
 
Science lesson Moon for 4th quarter lesson
Science lesson Moon for 4th quarter lessonScience lesson Moon for 4th quarter lesson
Science lesson Moon for 4th quarter lesson
 
History Class XII Ch. 3 Kinship, Caste and Class (1).pptx
History Class XII Ch. 3 Kinship, Caste and Class (1).pptxHistory Class XII Ch. 3 Kinship, Caste and Class (1).pptx
History Class XII Ch. 3 Kinship, Caste and Class (1).pptx
 
Presiding Officer Training module 2024 lok sabha elections
Presiding Officer Training module 2024 lok sabha electionsPresiding Officer Training module 2024 lok sabha elections
Presiding Officer Training module 2024 lok sabha elections
 
Solving Puzzles Benefits Everyone (English).pptx
Solving Puzzles Benefits Everyone (English).pptxSolving Puzzles Benefits Everyone (English).pptx
Solving Puzzles Benefits Everyone (English).pptx
 
Model Call Girl in Tilak Nagar Delhi reach out to us at 🔝9953056974🔝
Model Call Girl in Tilak Nagar Delhi reach out to us at 🔝9953056974🔝Model Call Girl in Tilak Nagar Delhi reach out to us at 🔝9953056974🔝
Model Call Girl in Tilak Nagar Delhi reach out to us at 🔝9953056974🔝
 
18-04-UA_REPORT_MEDIALITERAСY_INDEX-DM_23-1-final-eng.pdf
18-04-UA_REPORT_MEDIALITERAСY_INDEX-DM_23-1-final-eng.pdf18-04-UA_REPORT_MEDIALITERAСY_INDEX-DM_23-1-final-eng.pdf
18-04-UA_REPORT_MEDIALITERAСY_INDEX-DM_23-1-final-eng.pdf
 
BASLIQ CURRENT LOOKBOOK LOOKBOOK(1) (1).pdf
BASLIQ CURRENT LOOKBOOK  LOOKBOOK(1) (1).pdfBASLIQ CURRENT LOOKBOOK  LOOKBOOK(1) (1).pdf
BASLIQ CURRENT LOOKBOOK LOOKBOOK(1) (1).pdf
 
Pharmacognosy Flower 3. Compositae 2023.pdf
Pharmacognosy Flower 3. Compositae 2023.pdfPharmacognosy Flower 3. Compositae 2023.pdf
Pharmacognosy Flower 3. Compositae 2023.pdf
 
Hybridoma Technology ( Production , Purification , and Application )
Hybridoma Technology  ( Production , Purification , and Application  ) Hybridoma Technology  ( Production , Purification , and Application  )
Hybridoma Technology ( Production , Purification , and Application )
 
TataKelola dan KamSiber Kecerdasan Buatan v022.pdf
TataKelola dan KamSiber Kecerdasan Buatan v022.pdfTataKelola dan KamSiber Kecerdasan Buatan v022.pdf
TataKelola dan KamSiber Kecerdasan Buatan v022.pdf
 
_Math 4-Q4 Week 5.pptx Steps in Collecting Data
_Math 4-Q4 Week 5.pptx Steps in Collecting Data_Math 4-Q4 Week 5.pptx Steps in Collecting Data
_Math 4-Q4 Week 5.pptx Steps in Collecting Data
 

The Relative Universality of Internationally Recognized Human Rights

  • 1. The Relative Universality of Human Rights Jack Donnelly Human Rights Quarterly, Volume 29, Number 2, May 2007, pp. 281-306 (Article) Published by Johns Hopkins University Press DOI: For additional information about this article Access provided by University of Washington @ Seattle (31 Jan 2018 00:24 GMT) https://doi.org/10.1353/hrq.2007.0016 https://muse.jhu.edu/article/215033 https://doi.org/10.1353/hrq.2007.0016 https://muse.jhu.edu/article/215033 HUMAN RIGHTS QUARTERLY Human Rights Quarterly 29 (2007) 281–306 © 2007 by The Johns Hopkins University Press The Relative Universality of Human Rights Jack Donnelly*
  • 2. AbSTRAcT Human rights as an international political project are closely tied to claims of universality. Attacks on the universality of human rights, however, are also widespread. And some versions of universalism are indeed theoreti- cally indefensible, politically pernicious, or both. This essay explores the senses in which human rights can (and cannot) be said to be universal, the senses in which they are (and are not) relative, and argues for the “relative universality” of internationally recognized human rights. INTRodUcTIoN This essay explores several different senses of “universal” human rights. I also consider, somewhat more briefly, several senses in which it might be held that human rights are “relative.” I defend what I call functional, international legal, and overlapping consensus universality. But I argue that what I call anthropological and ontological universality are empirically, philosophically, or politically indefensible. I also emphasize that universal human rights, properly understood, leave considerable space for national, regional, cultural particularity and other forms of diversity and relativity. * Jack Donnelly is the Andrew Mellon Professor at the Graduate School of International Stud-
  • 3. ies, University of Denver. The tone of this essay owes much to a long conversation with Daniel Bell and Joseph Chan in Japan nearly a decade ago. I thank them for the sort of deep engagement of funda- mental differences that represents one of the best and most exhilarating features of intellectual life. I also thank audiences at Yonsei University, Ritsumeikan University, and Occidental College, where earlier versions of this paper were presented, and more than two decades of students who have constantly pushed me to clarify, sharpen, and properly modulate my arguments. Vol. 29282 HUMAN RIGHTS QUARTERLY Cultural relativism has probably been the most discussed issue in the theory of human rights. Certainly that is true in this journal. I have been an active participant in these debates for a quarter century, arguing for a form of universalism that also allows substantial space for important (second order) claims of relativism.1 I continue to insist on what I call the “relative univer- sality” of human rights. Here, however, I give somewhat more emphasis to the limits of the universal. In the 1980s, when vicious dictators regularly appealed to culture to
  • 4. justify their depredations, a heavy, perhaps even over-heavy, emphasis on universalism seemed not merely appropriate but essential. Today, human rights are backed by the world’s preponderant political, economic, and cultural powers and have become ideologically hegemonic in international society. Not only do few states today directly challenge international hu- man rights, a surprisingly small number even seriously contend that large portions of the Universal Declaration do not apply to them. An account that gives somewhat greater emphasis to the limits of universalism thus seems called for, especially now that American foreign policy regularly appeals to “universal” values in the pursuit of a global ideological war that flouts international legal norms. 1. coNcEpTUAL ANd SUbSTANTIVE UNIVERSALITY We can begin by distinguishing the conceptual universality implied by the very idea of human rights from substantive universality, the universality of a particular conception or list of human rights. Human rights, following the manifest literal sense of the term, are ordinarily understood to be the rights that one has simply because one is human. As such, they are equal rights, because we either are or are not human beings, equally. Human rights are
  • 5. also inalienable rights, because being or not being human usually is seen as an inalterable fact of nature, not something that is either earned or can 1. Jack Donnelly, Human Rights and Human Dignity: An Analytic Critique of Non-West- ern Human Rights Conceptions, 76 Am. Pol. Science Rev. 303– 16 (1982); Jack Donnelly, Cultural Relativism and Universal Human Rights, 6 Hum. RtS. Q. 400 (1984); JAck Don- nelly, univeRSAl HumAn RigHtS in tHeoRy AnD PRActice (Ithaca: Cornell Univ. Press, 1989); Jack Donnelly, Traditional Values and Universal Human Rights: Caste in India, in ASiAn PeRSPectiveS on HumAn RigHtS (Claude E. Welch, Jr. & Virginia A. Leary 1990); Jack Don- nelly, Post-Cold War Reflections on International Human Rights, 8 etHicS & int’l Aff. 97 (1994); Jack Donnelly, Conversing with Straw Men While Ignoring Dictators: A Reply to Roger Ames, 11 etHicS & int’l Aff. 207 (1997); Jack Donnelly, Human Rights and Asian Values: A Defense of “Western” Universalism, in tHe eASt ASiAn cHAllenge foR HumAn RigHtS (Joanne R. Bauer & Daniel A. Bell eds. 1999); JAck Donnelly, univeRSAl HumAn RigHtS in tHeoRy AnD PRActice (2d ed. Ithaca: Cornell Univ. Press, 2003); Rhoda E. Howard & Jack Donnelly, Human Dignity, Human Rights and Political Regimes, 80 Am. Pol. Science Rev. 801 (1986). 2007 The Relative Universality of Human Rights 283
  • 6. be lost. Human rights are thus “universal” rights in the sense that they are held “universally” by all human beings. Conceptual universality is in effect just another way of saying that human rights are, by definition, equal and inalienable. Conceptual universality, however, establishes only that if there are any such rights, they are held equally/universally by all. It does not show that there are any such rights. Conceptually universal human rights may be so few in number or specified at such a high level of abstraction that they are of little practical consequence. And conceptual universality says nothing about the central question in most contemporary discussions of universal- ity, namely, whether the rights recognized in the Universal Declaration of Human Rights and the International Human Rights Covenants are universal. This is a substantive question. It will be our focus here. 2. UNIVERSAL poSSESSIoN NoT UNIVERSAL ENfoRcEMENT Defensible claims of universality, whether conceptual or substantive, are about the rights that we have as human beings. Whether everyone, or even anyone, enjoys these rights is another matter. In far too many countries today
  • 7. the state not only actively refuses to implement, but grossly and systematically violates, most internationally recognized human rights. And in all countries, significant violations of at least some human rights occur daily, although which rights are violated, and with what severity, varies dramatically. The global human rights regime relies on national implementation of internationally recognized human rights. Norm creation has been interna- tionalized. Enforcement of authoritative international human rights norms, however, is left almost entirely to sovereign states. The few and limited exceptions—most notably genocide, crimes against humanity, certain war crimes, and perhaps torture and arbitrary execution—only underscore the almost complete sovereign authority of states to implement human rights in their territories as they see fit. Except in the European regional regime, supranational supervisory bodies are largely restricted to monitoring how states implement their international human rights obligations. Transnational human rights NGOs and other national and international advocates engage in largely persuasive activity, aimed at changing the human rights practices of states. Foreign states are free to raise human rights violations as an issue of concern but
  • 8. have no authority to implement or enforce human rights within another state’s sov- ereign jurisdiction. The implementation and enforcement of universally held human rights thus is extremely relative, largely a function of where one has the (good or bad) fortune to live. Vol. 29284 HUMAN RIGHTS QUARTERLY 3. HISToRIcAL oR ANTHRopoLoGIcAL UNIVERSALITY2 Human rights are often held to be universal in the sense that most societies and cultures have practiced human rights throughout most of their history. “All societies cross-culturally and historically manifest conceptions of human rights.”3 This has generated a large body of literature on so- called non-western conceptions of human rights. “In almost all contemporary Arab literature on this subject [human rights], we find a listing of the basic rights established by modern conventions and declarations, and then a serious attempt to trace them back to Koranic texts.”4 “It is not often remembered that traditional African societies supported and practiced human rights.”5 “Protection of hu- man rights is an integral part” of the traditions of Asian societies.6 “All the countries [of the Asian region] would agree that ‘human rights’
  • 9. as a concept existed in their tradition.”7 Even the Hindu caste system has been described as a “traditional, multidimensional view[s] of human rights.”8 Such claims to historical or anthropological universality confuse values such as justice, fairness, and humanity need with practices that aim to re- alize those values. Rights—entitlements that ground claims with a special force—are a particular kind of social practice. Human rights— equal and inalienable entitlements of all individuals that may be exercised against the state and society—are a distinctive way to seek to realize social values such as justice and human flourishing. There may be considerable his- torical/anthropological universality of values across time and culture. No society, civilization, or culture prior to the seventeenth century, however, 2. This section draws directly from and summarizes Donnelly, univeRSAl HumAn RigHtS in tHeoRy AnD PRActice (2d ed.), supra note 1, at ch. 5. 3. Adamantia Pollis & Peter Schwab, Human Rights: A Western Construct with Limited Applicability, in HumAn RigHtS: cultuRAl AnD iDeologicAl PeRSPectiveS 1, 15 (Adamantia Pollis & Peter Schwab eds., 1979); compare Makau Mutua, The Banjul Charter and the African Cultural Fingerprint: An Evaluation of the Language of Duties, 35 viRginA J.
  • 10. int’l l. 339, at 358 (1995); David R. Penna & Patricia J. Campbell, Human Rights and Culture: Beyond Universality and Relativism, 19 tHiRD WoRlD Q. 7, at 21 (1998). 4. Fouad Zakaria, Human Rights in the Arab World: The Islamic Context, in PHiloSoPHicAl founDAtionS of HumAn RigHtS 227, 228 (UNESCO ed., 1986). 5. Dunstan M. Wai, Human Rights in Sub-Saharan Africa, in HumAn RigHtS: cultuRAl AnD iDeologicAl PeRSPectiveS 115, 116 (Adamantia Pollis & Peter Schwab eds., 1979). 6. Ibrahim Anwar, Special Address presented at the JUST International Conference: Rethink- ing Human Rights (7 Dec 1994) in HumAn WRongS 277 (1994). 7. Radhika Coomaraswamy, Human Rights Research and Education: An Asian Perspective, in inteRnAtionAl congReSS on tHe teAcHing of HumAn RigHtS: WoRking DocumentS AnD Recom- menDAtionS 224 (UNESCO ed., 1980). 8. Ralph Buultjens, Human Rights in Indian Political Culture, in tHe moRAl imPeRAtiveS of HumAn RigHtS: A WoRlD SuRvey 109, 113 (Kenneth W. Thompson ed., 1980); compare Yougindra Khushalani, Human Rights in Asia and Africa, 4 Hum. RtS. l. J. 403, 408 (1983); mAx l. StAckHouSe, cReeDS, Society, AnD HumAn RigHtS: A StuDy in tHRee cultuReS (1984).
  • 11. 2007 The Relative Universality of Human Rights 285 had a widely endorsed practice, or even vision, of equal and inalienable individual human rights.9 For example, Dunstan Wai argues that traditional African beliefs and institutions “sustained the ‘view that certain rights should be upheld against alleged necessities of state.’”10 This confuses human rights with limited gov- ernment.11 Government has been limited on a variety of grounds other than human rights, including divine commandment, legal rights, and extralegal checks such as a balance of power or the threat of popular revolt. “[T]he concept of human rights concerns the relationship between the individual and the state; it involves the status, claims, and duties of the former in the jurisdiction of the latter. As such, it is a subject as old as politics.”12 Not all political relationships, however, are governed by, related to, or even consistent with, human rights. What the state owes those it rules is indeed a perennial question of politics. Human rights provide one answer. Other answers include divine right monarchy, the dictatorship of the proletariat, the principle of utility, aristocracy, theocracy, and democracy. “[D]ifferent civilizations or societies have different conceptions
  • 12. of hu- man well-being. Hence, they have a different attitude toward human rights issues.”13 Even this is misleading. Other societies may have (similar or differ- ent) attitudes toward issues that we consider today to be matters of human rights. But without a widely understood concept of human rights endorsed or advocated by some important segment of that society, it is hard to imagine that they could have any attitude toward human rights. And it is precisely the idea of equal and inalienable rights that one has simply because one is a human being that was missing not only in traditional Asian, African, Islamic, but in traditional Western, societies as well. 9. For detailed support for this claim, see Donnelly, univeRSAl HumAn RigHtS in tHeoRy AnD PRActice (2d ed.), supra note 1, at ch. 5; RHoDA e. HoWARD, HumAn RigHtS in commonWeAltH AfRicA, at ch. 2(1986). 10. Wai, supra note 5, at 116. 11. Compare Asmarom Legesse, Human Rights in African Political Culture, in tHe moRAl imPeRAtiveS of HumAn RigHtS: A WoRlD SuRvey 123, 125– 27 (Kenneth W. Thompson ed., 1980); Nana Kusi Appea Busia, Jr., The Status of Human Rights in Pre-Colonial Africa: Implications for Contemporary Practices, in AfRicA, HumAn RigHtS, AnD tHe globAl SyStem: tHe PoliticAl economy of HumAn RigHtS in A cHAnging
  • 13. WoRlD 225, 231 (Eileen McCarthy- Arnolds, David R. Penna, & Debra Joy Cruz Sobrepeña eds., 1994); for non-African examples, Abdul Aziz Said, Precept and Practice of Human Rights in Islam, 1 univeRSAl Hum. RtS. 63, 65 (1979); Raul Manglapus, Human Rights are Not a Western Discovery, 4 WoRlDvieW (1978); Adamantia Pollis & Peter Schwab, Introduction, in HumAn RigHtS: cultuRAl AnD iDeologicAl PeRSPectiveS xiii, xiv (Adamantia Pollis & Peter Schwab eds., 1979). 12. Hung-Chao Tai, Human Rights in Taiwan: Convergence of Two Political Cultures?, in HumAn RigHtS in eASt ASiA: A cultuRAl PeRSPective 77, 79 (James C. Hsiung ed., 1985). 13. Manwoo Lee, North Korea and the Western Notion of Human Rights, in HumAn RigHtS in eASt ASiA: A cultuRAl PeRSPective 129, 131 (James C. Hsiung ed., 1985). Vol. 29286 HUMAN RIGHTS QUARTERLY The ancient Greeks notoriously distinguished between Hellenes and barbarians, practiced slavery, denied basic rights to foreigners, and (by our standards) severely restricted the rights of even free adult (male) citizens. The idea that all human beings had equal and inalienable basic rights was equally foreign to Athens and Sparta, Plato and Aristotle,
  • 14. Homer, Hesiod, Aeschylus, Euripides, Aristophanes, and Thucydides. Much the same is true of ancient Rome, both as a republic and as an empire. In medieval Europe, where the spiritual egalitarianism and universality of Christianity expressed itself in deeply inegalitarian politics, the idea of equal legal and political rights for all human beings, had it been seriously contemplated, would have been seen as a moral abomination, a horrid transgression against God’s order. In the “pre-modern” world, both Western and non-Western alike, the duty of rulers to further the common good arose not from the rights (entitle- ments) of all human beings, or even all subjects, but from divine command- ment, natural law, tradition, or contingent political arrangements. The people could legitimately expect to benefit from the obligations of their rulers to rule justly. Neither in theory nor in practice, though, did they have human rights that could be exercised against unjust rulers. The reigning ideas were natural law and natural right (in the sense of righteousness or rectitude) not natural or human rights (in the sense of equal and inalienable individual entitlements). Many arguments of anthropological universality are inspired by an
  • 15. admirable desire to show cultural sensitivity and respect. In fact they do no such thing. Rather, they misunderstand and misrepresent the foundations and functioning of the societies in question by anachronistically imposing an alien analytical framework. I am not claiming that Islam, Confucianism, or traditional African ideas cannot support internationally recognized human rights. Quite the contrary, I argue below that in practice today they increasingly do support human rights. My point is simply that Islamic, Confucian, and African societies did not in fact develop significant bodies of human rights ideas or practices prior to the twentieth century. The next section offers an explanation for this fact. 4. fUNcTIoNAL UNIVERSALITY Natural or human rights ideas first developed in the modern West. A full- fledged natural rights theory is evident in John Locke’s Second Treatise of Government, published in 1689 in support of the so-called Glorious Revolu- tion. The American and French Revolutions first used such ideas to construct new political orders.14 14. JoHn locke, tWo tReAtiSe on goveRnment (London, W. Wilson 1821) (1689).
  • 16. 2007 The Relative Universality of Human Rights 287 The social-structural “modernity” of these ideas and practices, however, not their cultural “Westernness,” deserves emphasis.15 Human rights ideas and practices arose not from any deep Western cultural roots but from the social, economic, and political transformations of modernity. They thus have relevance wherever those transformations have occurred, irrespective of the pre-existing culture of the place. Nothing in classical or medieval culture specially predisposed Europeans to develop human rights ideas. Even early modern Europe, when viewed without the benefit of hindsight, seemed a particularly unconducive cultural milieu for human rights. No widely endorsed reading of Christian scriptures supported the idea of a broad set of equal and inalienable individual rights held by all Christians, let alone all human beings. Violent, often brutal, in- ternecine and international religious warfare was the norm. The divine right of kings was the reigning orthodoxy. Nonetheless, in early modern Europe, ever more powerful and pen- etrating (capitalist) markets and (sovereign, bureaucratic) states disrupted,
  • 17. destroyed, or radically transformed “traditional” communities and their systems of mutual support and obligation. Rapidly expanding numbers of (relatively) separate families and individuals were thus left to face a grow- ing range of increasingly unbuffered economic and political threats to their interests and dignity. New “standard threats” to human dignity provoked new remedial responses.16 The absolutist state offered a society organized around a monarchist hier- archy justified by a state religion. The newly emergent bourgeoisie envisioned a society in which the claims of property balanced those of birth. And as “modernization” progressed, an ever widening range of dispossessed groups advanced claims for relief from injustices and disabilities. Such demands took many forms, including appeals to scripture, church, morality, tradition, justice, natural law, order, social utility, and national strength. Claims of equal and inalienable natural/human rights, however, became increasingly central. And the successes of some groups opened political space for others to advance similar claims for their equal rights. The spread of modern markets and states has globalized the same threats to human dignity initially experienced in Europe. Human rights represent
  • 18. the most effective response yet devised to a wide range of standard threats to human dignity that market economies and bureaucratic states have made 15. See Donnelly, univeRSAl HumAn RigHtS in tHeoRy AnD PRActice (2d ed.), supra note 1, at ch. 4; compare Michael Goodhart, Origins and Universality in the Human Rights Debate: Cultural Essentialism and the Challenge of Globalization, 25 Hum. RtS. Q. 935 (2003). ARvinD SHARmA, ARe HumAn RigHtS WeSteRn in oRigin? A contRibution to tHe DiAlogue of civilizAtionS(2006) extensively and critically explores the wide variety of senses in which human rights have been held to be “Western.” 16. HenRy SHue, bASic RigHtS: SubSiStence, Affluence, AnD u.S. foReign Policy 29–34 (1980). Vol. 29288 HUMAN RIGHTS QUARTERLY nearly universal across the globe. Human rights today remain the only proven effective means to assure human dignity in societies dominated by markets and states. Although historically contingent and relative, this functional universality fully merits the label universal—for us, today. Arguments that another state, society, or culture has developed plausible and effective alternative mechanisms for protecting or realizing human dig-
  • 19. nity in the contemporary world deserve serious attention. Today, however, such claims, when not advanced by repressive elites and their supporters, usually refer to an allegedly possible world that no one yet has had the good fortune to experience. The functional universality of human rights depends on human rights providing attractive remedies for some of the most pressing systemic threats to human dignity. Human rights today do precisely that for a growing number of people of all cultures in all regions. Whatever our other problems, we all must deal with market economies and bureaucratic states. Whatever our other religious, moral, legal, and political resources, we all need equal and inalienable universal human rights to protect us from those threats. 5. INTERNATIoNAL LEGAL UNIVERSALITY If this argument is even close to correct, we ought to find widespread active endorsement of internationally recognized human rights. Such endorsement is evident in international human rights law, giving rise to what I will call international legal universality. The foundational international legal instru- ment is the Universal Declaration of Human Rights. The 1993 World Human Rights Conference, in the first operative paragraph of the
  • 20. Vienna Declaration and Programme of Action, asserted that “the universal nature of these rights and freedoms is beyond question.” Virtually all states accept the authority of the Universal Declaration of Human Rights. For the purposes of international relations, human rights today means, roughly, the rights in the Universal Declaration. Those rights have been further elaborated in a series of widely ratified treaties. As of 6 December 2006, the six core international human rights treaties (on civil and political rights, economic, social, and cultural rights, racial discrimination, women, torture, and children) had an average 168 parties, which represents a truly impressive 86 percent ratification rate.17 Although this international legal universality operates in significant mea- sure at an elite interstate level, it has come to penetrate much more deeply. Movements for social justice and of political opposition have increasingly 17. Ratification data is available at http://www.ohchr.org/english/countries/ratification/index. htm and http://www.ohchr.org/english/bodies/docs/status.pdf. 2007 The Relative Universality of Human Rights 289
  • 21. adopted the language of human rights. Growing numbers of new interna- tional issues, ranging from migration, to global trade and finance, to access to pharmaceuticals are being framed as issues of human rights.18 States that systematically violate internationally recognized human rights do not lose their legitimacy in international law. Except in cases of genocide, sovereignty still ultimately trumps human rights. But protecting internationally recognized human rights is increasingly seen as a precondi- tion of full political legitimacy. Consider Robert Mugabe’s Zimbabwe. Even China has adopted the language (although not too much of the practice) of internationally recognized human rights, seemingly as an inescapable precondition to its full recognition as a great power. International legal universality, like functional universality, is contingent and relative. It depends on states deciding to treat the Universal Declaration and the Covenants as authoritative. Tomorrow, they may no longer accept or give as much weight to human rights. Today, however, they clearly have chosen, and continue to choose, human rights over competing conceptions of national and international political legitimacy. 6. oVERLAppING coNSENSUS UNIVERSALITY
  • 22. International legal universality is incompletely but significantly replicated at the level of moral or political theory. John Rawls distinguishes “comprehen- sive religious, philosophical, or moral doctrines,” such as Islam, Kantianism, Confucianism, and Marxism, from “political conceptions of justice,” which address only the political structure of society, defined (as far as possible) in- dependent of any particular comprehensive doctrine.19 Adherents of different comprehensive doctrines may be able to reach an “overlapping consensus” on a political conception of justice.20 Such a consensus is overlapping; partial rather than complete. It is politi- cal rather than moral or religious. Rawls developed the notion to understand how “there can be a stable and just society whose free and equal citizens are deeply divided by conflicting and even incommensurable religious, philo- sophical, and moral doctrines.”21 The idea, however, has obvious extensions to a culturally and politically diverse international society.22 18. AliSon bRySk, HumAn RigHtS AnD PRivAte WRongS: conStRucting globAl civil Society (2005). 19. JoHn RAWlS, tHe lAW of PeoPleS xliii–xlv, 11–15, 174– 76 (1999); JoHn RAWlS, PoliticAl lib- eRAliSm 31–33, 172–73 (1993). 20. RAWlS, PoliticAl libeRAliSm, supra note 19, at 133–72,
  • 23. 385–96. 21. Id. at 133. 22. RAWlS, tHe lAW of PeoPleS, supra note 19. Rawls’ own extension involves both a wider political conception of justice and a narrower list of internationally recognized human rights. The account offered here is Rawlsian in inspiration but not that of John Rawls. Vol. 29290 HUMAN RIGHTS QUARTERLY Human rights can be grounded in a variety of comprehensive doctrines. For example, they can be seen as encoded in the natural law, called for by divine commandment, political means to further human good or utility, or institutions to produce virtuous citizens. Over the past few decades more and more adherents of a growing range of comprehensive doctrines in all regions of the world have come to endorse human rights—(but only) as a political conception of justice.23 It is important to remember that virtually all Western religious and philosophical doctrines through most of their history have either rejected or ignored human rights. Today, however, most adherents of most Western comprehensive doctrines endorse human rights. And if the medieval Christian
  • 24. world of crusades, serfdom, and hereditary aristocracy could become today’s world of liberal and social democratic welfare states, it is hard to think of a place where a similar transformation is inconceivable. Consider claims that “Asian values” are incompatible with internation- ally recognized human rights.24 Asian values—like Western values, African values, and most other sets of values—can be, and have been, understood as incompatible with human rights. But they also can be and have been interpreted to support human rights, as they regularly are today in Japan, Taiwan, and South Korea. And political developments in a growing number of Asian countries suggest that ordinary people and even governments are increasingly viewing human rights as a contemporary political expression of their deepest ethical, cultural, and political values and aspirations.25 23. Heiner Bielefeldt, “Western” versus “Islamic” Human Rights Conceptions?: A Critique of Cultural Essentialism in the Discussion on Human Rights, 28 Pol. tHeoRy 90 (2000) makes a similar argument for overlapping consensus universality, illustrated by a discussion of recent trends in Islamic thinking on human rights. See also Ashwani Kumar Peetush, Cultural Diversity, Non-Western Communities, and Human Rights, 34 PHiloSoPHicAl foRum 1 (2003), which deals with South Asian views. Vincanne
  • 25. Adams, Suffering the Winds of Lhasa: Politicized Bodies, Human Rights, Cultural Difference, and Humanism in Tibet, 12 meD. AntHRoPology Q. 74 (1998) presents an account of the suffering of Tibetan women activists that stresses their instrumental adoption of human rights ideas to grapple with injustices and suffering that they understand in very different terms. For a looser account of cross-cultural consensus, see HumAn RigHtS in cRoSS- cultuRAl PeRSPectiveS: A QueSt foR conSenSuS (Abdullahi Ahmed An-Na’im ed. 1992). 24. AntHony J. lAngloiS, tHe PoliticS of JuStice AnD HumAn RigHtS (2001) offers perhaps the best overview. HumAn RigHtS AnD ASiAn vAlueS: conteSting nAtionAl iDentitieS AnD cultuRAl RePReSentAtionS in ASiA (Michael Jacobsen & Ole Bruun eds., 2000); tHe eASt ASiAn cHAllenge foR HumAn RigHtS, supra note 1, are good collections of essays. 25. “Confucians can make sense of rights out of the resources of their own tradition.” May Sim, A Confucian Approach to Human Rights, 21 HiSt. PHil. Q. 337, 338 (2004). Compare Joseph Chan, Moral Autonomy, Civil Liberties, and Confucianism, 52 PHil. eASt & WeSt 281 (2002); Joseph Chan, Confucian Perspective on Human Rights for Contemporary China, in tHe eASt ASiAn cHAllenge foR HumAn RigHtS, supra note 1. On Confucianism and modern social and political practices, see confuciAniSm foR tHe moDeRn WoRlD (Daniel A. Bell & Hahm Chaibong eds., 2003).
  • 26. 2007 The Relative Universality of Human Rights 291 No culture or comprehensive doctrine is “by nature,” or in any given or fixed way, either compatible or incompatible with human rights. Here we circle back to the insight underlying (misformulated) arguments of anthro- pological universality. Whatever their past practice, nothing in indigenous African, Asian, or American cultures prevents them from endorsing human rights now. Cultures are immensely malleable, as are the political expressions of comprehensive doctrines. It is an empirical question whether (any, some, or most) members of a culture or exponents of a comprehensive doctrine support human rights as a political conception of justice. All major civilizations have for long periods treated a significant portion of the human race as “outsiders” not entitled to guarantees that could be taken for granted by “insiders.” Few areas of the globe, for example, have never practiced and widely justified human bondage. All literate civilizations have for most of their histories assigned social roles, rights, and duties primarily on the basis of ascriptive characteristics such as birth, age, and gender. Today, however, the moral equality of all human beings is
  • 27. strongly endorsed by most leading comprehensive doctrines in all regions of the world. This convergence, both within and between civilizations, provides the foundation for a convergence on the rights of the Universal Declaration. In principle, a great variety of social practices other than human rights might provide the basis for realizing foundational egalitarian values. In practice human rights are rapidly becoming the preferred option. I will call this overlapping consensus universality. 7. VoLUNTARY oR coERcEd coNSENSUS? Is the transnational consensus underlying international legal and overlap- ping consensus universality more voluntary or coerced? The influence of the United States and Western Europe should not be underestimated. Example, however, has been more powerful than advocacy and coercion has typically played less of a role than positive inducements such as closer political or economic relations or full participation in international society. Human rights dominate political discussions less because of pressure from materially or culturally dominant powers than because they respond to some of the most important social and political aspirations of individuals, families, and groups in most countries of the world.
  • 28. States may be particularly vulnerable to external pressure and thus tempted or even compelled to offer purely formal endorsements of interna- tional norms advocated by leading powers.26 The assent of most societies and 26. Even that seems to me not obviously correct. I read hypocrisy more as evidence of the substantive attractions of hypocritically endorsed norms. Vol. 29292 HUMAN RIGHTS QUARTERLY individuals, however, is largely voluntary. The consensus on the Universal Declaration, it seems to me, principally reflects its cross- cultural substantive attractions. People, when given a chance, usually (in the contemporary world) choose human rights, irrespective of region, religion, or culture. Few “ordinary” citizens in any country have a particularly sophisticated sense of human rights. They respond instead to the general idea that they and their fellow citizens are entitled to equal treatment and certain basic goods, services, protections, and opportunities. I am in effect suggesting that the Universal Declaration presents a reasonable first approximation of the list that they would come up with, largely irrespective of culture, after consid-
  • 29. erable reflection. More precisely, there is little in the Universal Declaration that they would not (or could not be persuaded to) put there, although we might readily imagine a global constitutional convention today coming up with a somewhat different list. The transnational consensus on the Universal Declaration arises above all from the largely voluntary decisions of people, states, and other political actors that human rights are essential to protecting their visions of a life of dignity. Therefore, we should talk more of the relative universality of human rights, rather than their relative universality.27 8. oNToLoGIcAL UNIVERSALITY Overlapping consensus implies that human rights can, and in the contem- porary world do, have multiple and diverse “foundations.” A single transh- istorical foundation would provide what I will call ontological universality.28 27. Laura Hebert in a private communication pointed out that I previously described my views as weak relativist or strong (but not radical) universalist, but that in an earlier version of this essay I used the label weak universalist. The careful reader will note that here I have avoided such formulations in favor of a notion of relative universality that is open to differing emphases. This reflects my growing
  • 30. appreciation of the advantages of approaching the continuum between relativism and universalism less as an ideal type account of all possible positions and more in terms of the spectrum of views that hap- pen to be prevalent among actively engaged participants in the debate at a particular time and place. The actual spectrum of views actively engaged at any given time and place is likely to cover only a portion of the ideal type spectrum. My arguments have always been formulated primarily, although implicitly, with respect to the former. Over the past decade, much of the relativist end of the Cold War era spectrum has disappeared from mainstream discussions. Therefore, views such as my own that once appeared near the edge of the universalist end of the spectrum now appear more moderately universalist. I must also admit, though, that given this new political context I have intentionally given greater emphasis to the space available for diverse implementations of universal human rights norms. See Donnelly, Human Rights and Asian Values, supra note 1; Section 13, 14 below. 28. For a recent attempt to defend ontological universality, see WilliAm J. tAlbott, WHicH RigHtS SHoulD be univeRSAl? 3–4 (2005). 2007 The Relative Universality of Human Rights 293
  • 31. Although a single moral code may indeed be objectively correct and valid at all times in all places, at least three problems make ontological universality implausible and politically unappealing. First, no matter how strenuously adherents of a particular philosophy or religion insist that (their) values are objectively valid, they are unable to persuade adherents of other religions or philosophies. This failure to agree leaves us in pretty much the same position as if there were no objective values at all. We are thrown back on arguments of functional, international legal, and overlapping consensus universality (understood now, perhaps, as imperfect reflections of a deeper ontological universality). Second, all prominent comprehensive doctrines have for large parts of their history ignored or actively denied human rights. It is improbable (al- though conceivable) that an objectively correct doctrine has been interpreted incorrectly so widely. Thus it is unlikely that human rights in general, and the particular list in the Universal Declaration, are ontologically universal. At best, we might find that an ontologically universal comprehensive doc- trine has recently and contingently endorsed human rights as a political conception of justice.
  • 32. Third, the ontological universality of human rights, coupled with the absence of anthropological universality, implies that virtually all moral and religious theories through most of their histories have been objectively false or immoral. This may indeed be correct. But before we embrace such a radical idea, I think we need much stronger arguments than are currently available to support the ontological universality of human rights. Overlapping consensus, rather than render human rights groundless, gives them multiple grounds. Whatever its analytical and philosophical virtues or shortcomings, this is of great practical utility. Those who want (or feel morally compelled) to make ontological claims can do so with no need to convince or compel others to accept this particular, or even any, foundation. Treating human rights as a Rawlsian political conception of justice thus allows us to address a wide range of issues of political justice and right while circumventing not merely inconclusive but often pointlessly divisive disputes over moral foundations. 9. cULTURAL RELATIVISM Having considered a variety of possible senses of “universality,” I now
  • 33. want to turn, somewhat more briefly, to several different senses of “relativ- ity.” What makes (or is alleged to make) human rights relative? Relative to what? We have already seen that they are historically relative and that, at best, ontological universality remains a matter of debate. The most common argument for relativity appeals to culture. Vol. 29294 HUMAN RIGHTS QUARTERLY Cultural relativity is a fact: cultures differ, often dramatically, across time and space. Cultural relativism is a set of doctrines that imbue cultural relativity with prescriptive force. For our purposes we can distinguish meth- odological and substantive cultural relativism.29 Methodological cultural relativism was popular among mid- twentieth century anthropologists. They advocated a radically non- judgmental analysis of cultures in order to free anthropology from unconscious, and often even conscious, biases rooted in describing and judging other societies according to modern Western categories and values.30 Such arguments lead directly to a recognition of the historical or anthropological relativity of human rights. In discussions of human rights, however, cultural relativism
  • 34. typically ap- pears as a substantive normative doctrine that demands respect for cultural differences.31 The norms of the Universal Declaration are presented as having no normative force in the face of divergent cultural traditions. Practice is to be evaluated instead by the standards of the culture in question. As the State- ment on Human Rights of the American Anthropological Association (AAA) put it, “man is free only when he lives as his society defines freedom.”32 Rhoda Howard-Hassmann has aptly described this position as “cultural absolutism”33. Culture provides absolute standards of evaluation; whatever a culture says is right is right (for those in that culture).34 Rather than ad- dress the details of such claims, which usually involve arguments that other 29. John J. Tilley, Cultural Relativism, 22 Hum. RtS. Q. 501 (2000) carefully reviews a number of particular conceptions and cites much of the relevant literature from anthropology. Compare Alison Dundes Renteln, Relativism and the Search for Human Rights, 90 Am. AntHRoPologiSt 56 (1988). 30. melville J. HeRSkovitS, cultuRAl RelAtiviSm: PeRSPectiveS in cultuRAl PluRAliSm (1972). 31. Even Renteln, Relativism and the Search for Human Rights, supra note 29, at 56, who
  • 35. claims to be advancing “a metaethical theory about the nature of moral perceptions,” thus making her position more like what I have called methodological relativism, insists on “the requirement that diversity be recognized” and the “urgent need to adopt a broader view of human rights that incorporates diverse concepts.” Alison Dundes Renteln, The Unanswered Challenge of Relativism and the Consequences for Human Rights, 7 Hum. RtS. Q. 514, at 540 (1985). Such substantive propositions simply do not follow from methodological relativism or any causal or descriptive account of moral perceptions. 32. Exec. Comm., Am. Anthropological Ass’n, Statement on Human Rights, 49 Am. AntHRo- PologiSt 539, 543 (1947). 33. Rhoda E. Howard, Cultural Absolutism and the Nostalgia for Community, 15 Hum. RtS. Q. 315 (1993). 34. A variant on such arguments popular in the 1980s held that each of the three “worlds” of that era—Western/liberal, Soviet/socialist and Third World— had its own distinctive conception of human rights, rooted in its own shared historical experience and conception of social justice. See, e.g., Hector Gros Espiell, The Evolving Concept of Human Rights: Western, Socialist and Third World Approaches, in HumAn RigHtS: tHiRty yeARS AfteR tHe univeRSAl DeclARAtion (B. G. Ramcharan ed., 1979); Adamantia Pollis, Liberal, Socialist, and Third World Perspectives on Human Rights, in Toward a
  • 36. Human Rights Framework 1 (Peter Schwab & Adamantia Pollis eds., 1982). This story was often associated with a claim that the West was focused on “first generation” civil and political rights, the socialist world on “second generation” economic, social, and cultural rights, and the Third 2007 The Relative Universality of Human Rights 295 cultures give greater attention to duties than to rights and to groups than to individuals, I will focus on six very serious general problems with substan- tive or absolutist cultural relativism. First, it risks reducing “right” to “traditional,” “good” to “old,” and “obligatory” to “habitual.” Few societies or individuals, however, believe that their values are binding simply or even primarily because they happen to be widely endorsed within their culture. Without very powerful philosophical arguments (which are not to be found in this cultural relativist literature on human rights) it would seem inappropriate to adopt a theory that is incon- sistent with the moral experience of almost all people— especially in the name of cultural sensitivity and diversity. Second, the equation of indigenous cultural origins with moral validity
  • 37. is deeply problematic. The AAA statement insists that “standards and val- ues are relative to the culture from which they derive so that any attempt to formulate postulates that grow out of the beliefs or moral codes of one culture must to that extent detract from the applicability of any Declaration of Human Rights to mankind as a whole.”35 The idea that simply because a value or practice emerged in place A makes it, to that extent, inapplicable to B is, at best, a dubious philosophical claim that assumes the impossibil- ity of moral learning or adaptation except within (closed) cultures. It also dangerously assumes the moral infallibility of culture. Third, intolerant, even genocidal, relativism is as defensible as tolerant relativism. If my culture’s values tell me that others are inferior, there is World on “third generation” solidarity rights. See Stephen P. Marks, Emerging Human Rights: A New Generation for the 1980s?, 33 RutgeRS l. Rev. 435 (1981); Karel Vasak, Pour une troisième génération des droits de l’homme, in StuDieS AnD eSSAyS on inteRnAtionAl HumAnitARiAn lAW AnD ReD cRoSS PRinciPleS in HonouR of JeAn Pictet 837 (Christophe Swinarski ed., 1984); Karel Vasak, Les différentes catégories des droits de l’homme, in leS Dimen- SionS univeRSelleS DeS DRoitS De l’Homme. vol. i. (André Lapeyre, François de Tinguy, & Karel Vasak eds., 1991). micHeline R. iSHAy, tHe HiStoRy of
  • 38. HumAn RigHtS: fRom Ancient timeS to tHe globAlizAtion eRA (2004) presents a relatively sophisticated post-Cold War version of this argument. For a counter-argument, see J. Donnelly, Third Generation Rights, in PeoPleS AnD minoRitieS in inteRnAtionAl lAW 119 (Catherine Brölmann, René Lefeber & Marjoleine Zieck eds., 1993). The three worlds story suggests that level of development and political history impose priorities on (groups of) states. Socialist and Third World states, it was argued, could not afford the “luxury” of civil and political rights, being legitimately preoccupied with establishing their national sovereignty and economic and social development. While usually acknowledging the long run desirability of civil and political rights, they were dismissed as (at best) a secondary priority, a distraction, or even a serious impediment to progress in countries struggling to achieve self-determination and economic develop- ment. The claim, though, that benevolent governments that denied civil and political rights could deliver development more rapidly and spread its benefits more universally, unfortunately found almost no support in the experience of developmental dictator- ships of the left and the right alike during the Cold War. Quite the contrary, pursuing economic and social rights without civil and political rights in practice usually led to poor performance in realizing both, particularly over the medium and long run.
  • 39. 35. Exec. Comm., Am. Anthropological Ass’n, supra note 32, at 542. Vol. 29296 HUMAN RIGHTS QUARTERLY no standard by which to challenge this. A multidimensional, multicultural conception of human rights requires appeal to principles inconsistent with normative cultural relativism. Fourth, cultural relativist arguments usually either ignore politics or confuse it with culture. The often deeply coercive aspect to culture is simply ignored. As a result, such arguments regularly confuse what a people has been forced to tolerate with what it values. Fifth, these arguments typically ignore the impact of states, markets, colonialism, the spread of human rights ideas, and various other social forces. The cultures described are idealized representations of a past that, if it ever existed, certainly does not exist today. For example, Roger Ames, in an essay entitled “Continuing the Conversation of Chinese Human Rights,” completely ignores the impact of half a century of communist party rule, as if it were irrelevant to discussing human rights in contemporary China.36
  • 40. Sixth, and most generally, the typical account of culture as coherent, homogenous, consensual, and static largely ignores cultural contingency, contestation, and change. Culture in fact is a repertoire of deeply contested symbols, practices, and meanings over and with which members of a society constantly struggle.37 Culture is not destiny—or, to the extent that it is, that is only because victorious elements in a particular society have used their power to make a particular, contingent destiny. The fact of cultural relativity and the doctrine of methodological cul- tural relativism are important antidotes to misplaced universalism. The fear of (neo-)imperialism and the desire to demonstrate cultural respect that lie behind many cultural relativist arguments need to be taken seriously. Norma- tive cultural relativism, however, is a deeply problematic moral theory that offers a poor understanding of the relativity of human rights. 10. SELf-dETERMINATIoN ANd SoVEREIGNTY Self-determination and sovereignty ground a tolerant relativism based on the mutual recognition of peoples/states in an international community. Self-de- termination, understood as an ethical principle, involves a claim that a free 36. Roger T. Ames, Continuing the Conversation on Chinese
  • 41. Human Rights, 11 etHicS & int’l Aff. 177 (1997). 37. For excellent brief applications of this understanding of culture to debates over human rights, see Ann-Belinda S. Preis, Human Rights as Cultural Practice: An Anthropological Critique, 18 Hum. RtS. Q. 286 (1996); Andrew J. Nathan, Universalism: A Particularistic Account, in negotiAting cultuRe AnD HumAn RigHtS (Lynda S. Bell, Andrew J. Nathan & Ilan Peleg eds., 2001). Compare also Neil A. Engelhart, Rights and Culture in the Asian Values Argument: The Rise and Fall of Confucian Ethics in Singapore, 22 Hum. RtS. Q. 548 (2000); Elizabeth M. Zechenter, In the Name of Culture: Cultural Relativism and the Abuse of the Individual, 53 J. AntHRoPologicAl ReS. 319 (1997). 2007 The Relative Universality of Human Rights 297 people is entitled to choose for itself its own way of life and its own form of government. The language of “democracy” is also often used. Democratic self-determination is a communal expression of the principles of equality and autonomy that lie at the heart of the idea of human rights. Whether a particular practice is in fact the free choice of a free people, however, is an empirical question. And self-determination must not be
  • 42. confused with legal sovereignty. Legally sovereign states need not satisfy or reflect the ethical principle of self-determination. Too often, repressive regimes falsely claim to reflect the will of the people. Too often, international legal sovereignty shields regimes that violate both ethical self- determination and most internationally recognized human rights—which brings us back to the relative enjoyment of human rights, based largely on where one happens to live. Often the result is a conflict between justice, represented by human rights and self-determination, and order, represented by international legal sovereignty. Non-intervention in the face of even systematic human rights violations dramatically decreases potentially violent conflicts between states. We can also see international legal sovereignty as an ethical principle of the society of states, a principle of mutual toleration and respect for (state) equality and autonomy. However we interpret it, though, legal sovereignty introduces a considerable element of relativity into the enjoyment of inter- nationally recognized human rights in the contemporary world. 11. poST-STRUcTURAL, poST-coLoNIAL, ANd cRITIcAL ARGUMENTS The growing hegemony of the idea of human rights since the
  • 43. end of the Cold War, combined with the rise of post-structural and post-colonial perspectives, has spawned a new stream of relativist, or perhaps more accurately anti- universalist, arguments. Although often similar to earlier cultural relativist arguments in both substance and motivation, they typically are based on a very different sort of anti-foundationalist ontology and epistemology38 and tend to be specially addressed to the context of globalization. They seek to challenge arrogant, neo-imperial arguments of universality, and draw attention to “the civilizationally asymmetrical power relations embedded in the international discourse,” in order to open or preserve discursive and practical space for autonomous action by marginalized groups and peoples across the globe.39 38. Critical Marxian perspectives, however, make similar arguments from a foundationalist perspective. See, e.g., tony evAnS, uS Hegemony AnD tHe PRoJect of univeRSAl HumAn RigHtS (1996); HumAn RigHtS fifty yeARS on: A ReAPPRAiSAl (Tony Evans ed., 1998). 39. Anthony Woodiwiss, Human Rights and the Challenge of Cosmopolitanism, 19 tHeoRy, cultuRe & Society 139 (2002).
  • 44. Vol. 29298 HUMAN RIGHTS QUARTERLY Although some versions of such arguments are dismissively critical,40 many are well modulated. “[T]he seduction of human rights discourse has been so great that it has, in fact, delayed the development of a critique of rights.”41 They claim that a lack of critical self-reflection has made human rights advocates “more part of a problem in today’s world than part of the solution.”42 There are “dark sides of virtue.”43 The uncomfortable reality, whatever the intentions of Western practitioners, too often is “imperial humanitarianism.”44 In these accounts, universality per se—and more particularly the ten- dency for universal claims to intellectually obscure and politically repress difference—is targeted more than universal human rights in particular. Con- versely, even many fairly radical post-structuralist and post- colonial authors reject normative cultural relativism in favor of a more dialogical approach to cross-cultural consensus that is not in the end dissimilar to overlapping consensus arguments discussed above.45 This, I believe, is a reflection of a growing sophistication in the discussion of relativity and universality -on both sides of the old divide.
  • 45. 12. JUSTIfYING pARTIcULARITY: UNIVERSAL RIGHTS, NoT IdENTIcAL pRAcTIcES Over the past decade, most discussions have tried to move beyond a dichoto- mous presentation of the issue of universality. Most sophisticated defenders of both universality and relativity today recognize the dangers of an extreme 40. For example, Makau Mutua writes of “the biased and arrogant rhetoric and history of the human rights enterprise,” which is simply the latest expression of “the historical continuum of the Eurocentric colonial project.” Makau Mutua, Savages, Victims, and Saviors: The Metaphor of Human Rights, 42 HARv. int’l l. J. 201, 202, 204 (2001). The hegemony of international human rights norms, in this reading, amounts to granting Western culture “the prerogative of imperialism, the right to define and impose on others what it deems good for humanity.” Id. at 219. 41. Makau Wa Mutua, The Ideology of Human Rights, 36 viRginiA J. int’l l. 589, 591 (1996). 42. David Kennedy, The International Human Rights Movement: Part of the Problem?, 15 HARvARD Hum. RtS. J. 101 (2002). 43. DAviD kenneDy, tHe DARk SiDeS of viRtue: ReASSeSSing inteRnAtionAl HumAnitARiAniSm (2004). 44. Gil Gott, Imperial Humanitarianism: History of an Arrested
  • 46. Dialectic, in moRAl imPeRiAliSm: A cRiticAl AntHology 19 (Berta Esperanza Hernández-Truyol ed., 2002); compare Susan Koshy, From Cold War to Trade War: Neocolonialism and Human Rights, 58 SociAl text 1 (1999); Pheng Cheah, Posit(ion)ing Human Rights in the Current Global Conjuncture, Public cultuRe 233–266 (1997). Michael Ignatieff, Human Rights as Politics, Human Rights as Idolotry, in HumAn RigHtS AS PoliticS AnD iDolAtRy 3, 53 (Amy Gutmann ed., 2001) expresses similar worries from within a very traditional Western liberal perspective. 45. See, e.g., Bonaventura de Sousa Santos, Toward a Multicultural Conception of Human Rights, in moRAl imPeRiAliSm: A cRiticAl AntHology 39 (Berta Esperanza Hernández-Truyol ed., 2002); Berta Esperanza Hernández-Truyol & Sharon Elizabeth Rush, Culture, Na- tionhood, and the Human Rights Ideal, 33 u. micH. J. l. RefoRm 233 (2000). 2007 The Relative Universality of Human Rights 299 commitment and acknowledge at least some attractions and insights in the positions of their critics and opponents. At the relatively universalistic end of this spectrum, I have defended “relative universality.”46 Towards the relativist end, Richard Wilson argues that
  • 47. ideas of and struggles for human rights “are embedded in local normative orders and yet are caught within webs of power and meaning which extend beyond the local.”47 Near the center, Andrew Nathan uses the language of “tempered universalism.”48 This more flexible account of universality (and relativity) makes a three- tiered scheme for thinking about universality that I have long advocated particularly useful for thinking about what ought to be universal, and what relative, in the domain of “universal human rights.”49 Human rights are (relatively) universal at the level of the concept, broad formulations such as the claims in Articles 3 and 22 of the Universal Declaration that “everyone has the right to life, liberty and security of person” and “the right to social security.”50 Particular rights concepts, however, have multiple defensible conceptions. Any particular conception, in turn, will have many defensible implementations. At this level—for example, the design of electoral sys- tems to implement the right “to take part in the government of his country, directly or through freely chosen representatives”—relativity is not merely defensible but desirable.51 Functional and overlapping consensus universality lie primarily at the
  • 48. level of concepts. Most of the Universal Declaration lies at this level as well. Although international human rights treaties often embody particular concep- tions, and sometimes even particular forms of implementation,52 they too 46. Towards this end of the spectrum, compare Fred Halliday, Relativism and Universalism in Human Rights: the Case of the Islamic Middle East, 43 Pol. StuD. 152 (1995); Michael J. Perry, Are Human Rights Universal? The Relativist Challenge and Related Matters, 19 Hum. RtS. Q. 461 (1997); Charles R. Beitz, Human Rights as a Common Concern, 95 Am. Pol. Science Rev. 269 (2001). 47. HumAn RigHtS, cultuRe & context: AntHRoPologicAl PeRSPectiveS 23 (Richard Wilson ed., 1997); compare Fred Dallmayr, “Asian Values” and Global Human Rights, 52 PHil. eASt & WeSt 173 (2002); Charles Taylor, Conditions of an Unforced Consensus on Human Rights, in tHe eASt ASiAn cHAllenge foR HumAn RigHtS, supra note 1; Penna & Campbell, supra note 3. 48. Nathan, supra note 37; compare Preis, supra note 37; Declan O’Sullivan, Is the Declara- tion of Human Rights Universal? 4 J. Hum. RtS. 25 (2000). 49. Donnelly, Cultural Relativism and Universal Human Rights, supra note 1; Donnelly, univeRSAl HumAn RigHtS in tHeoRy AnD PRActice (2d ed.), supra note 1, §6.4.
  • 49. 50. Universal Declaration of Human Rights, adopted 10 Dec. 1948, G.A. Res. 217A (III), U.N. GAOR, 3d Sess. (Resolutions, pt. 1), at 71, arts. 3, 22, U.N. Doc. A/810 (1948), reprinted in 43 Am. J. int’l l. 127 (Supp. 1949). 51. Id. art. 21. 52. For example, Article 14 of the Convention against Torture specifies that: Each State Party shall ensure in its legal system that the victim of an act of torture obtains redress and has an enforceable right to fair and adequate compensation, including the means for as full rehabilitation as possible. In the event of the death of the victim as a result of an act of torture, his dependants shall be entitled to compensation. Vol. 29300 HUMAN RIGHTS QUARTERLY permit a wide range of particular practices. Substantial second order varia- tion, by country, region, culture, or other grouping, is completely consistent with international legal and overlapping consensus universality. Concepts set a range of plausible variations among conceptions, which in turn restrict the range of practices that can plausibly be considered implementations of a particular concept and conception. But even some deviations from authoritative international human rights norms may be, all
  • 50. things considered, (not il)legitimate. Four criteria can help us to grapple seriously yet sympathetically with claims in support of such deviations. For reasons of space, I simply stipulate these criteria, although I doubt that they are deeply controversial once we have accepted some notion of relative universality.53 1) Important differences in threats are likely to justify variations even at the level of concepts. Although perhaps the strongest theoretical justification for even fairly substantial deviations from international human rights norms, such arguments rarely are empirically persuasive in the contemporary world. (Indigenous peoples may be the exception that proves the rule.)54 2) Participants in the overlapping consensus deserve a sympathetic hearing when they present serious reasoned arguments justifying limited deviations from international norms. Disagreements over “details” should be approached differently from systematic deviations or comprehensive at- tacks. If the resulting set of human rights remains generally consistent with the structure and overarching values of the Universal Declaration, we should be relatively tolerant of particular deviations. Convention Against Torture and Other Cruel, Inhuman or
  • 51. Degrading Treatment or Pun- ishment, adopted 10 Dec. 1984, G.A. Res. 39/46, U.N. GAOR, 39th Sess., Supp. No. 51, art. 14, U.N. Doc. A/39/51 (1985) (entered into force 26 June 1987), reprinted in 23 i.l.m. 1027 (1984), substantive changes noted in 24 i.l.m. 535 (1985). 53. I am implicitly speaking from the perspective of an engaged participant in international society. A different and more complex “subject position” may be important “on the ground” where ordinary people have more local and particularistic understandings of their values. I suspect that much of the “talking past each other” in debates on cultural relativism and human rights arises from taking arguments that may be well formulated for a particular setting, be it local or international, and applying them directly in another discursive setting, without the adjustments required to give those arguments resonance and persuasive force in that context. For example, in much of rural China today, direct appeals to internationally recognized human rights are unlikely to be politically effica- cious, and often will be positively counter-productive, either for mobilizing peasants or persuading local authorities. Those working directly to improve the day to day life of Chinese peasants needs to give central place to this fact. But I would suggest that it says more about the Chinese state and the enforced isolation and systematic repression of Chinese peasants than about “Asian values.”
  • 52. 54. Defensible categorical differences between “developed” and “developing” countries, I would argue, involve, at most, differing short-term priorities among particular interna- tionally recognized human rights, not major differences in the list of rights appropriate for individuals in such countries. 2007 The Relative Universality of Human Rights 301 3) Arguments claiming that a particular conception or implementation is, for cultural or historical reasons, deeply imbedded within or of unusu- ally great significance to some significant group in society deserve, on their face, sympathetic consideration. Even if we do not positively value diversity, the autonomous choices of free people should never be lightly dismissed, especially when they reflect well-established practices based on deeply held beliefs. 4) Tolerance for deviations should decrease as the level of coercion increases. 13. Two ILLUSTRATIoNS Article 18 of the Universal Declaration reads, in its entirety, “Everyone has the right to freedom of thought, conscience and religion; this right in-
  • 53. cludes freedom to change his religion or belief, and freedom, either alone or in community with others and in public or private, to manifest his religion or belief in teaching, practice, worship and observance.”55 Most schools of Islamic law and scholarship deny Muslims the right to change their religion. Is prohibition of apostasy by Muslims compatible with the relative univer- sality of Article 18? Reasonable people may reasonably disagree, but I am inclined to answer “Probably.” The variation is at the level of conceptions—the limits of the range of application of the principle of freedom of religion—in a context where the overarching concept is strongly endorsed. Most Islamic countries and communities respect the right of adherents of other religions to practice their beliefs (within the ordinary constraints of public order). Prohibition of apostasy also has a deeply rooted doctrinal basis, supported by a long tradition of practice. I think, therefore, that we are compelled to approach it with a certain prima facie tolerance, particularly if it is a relatively isolated deviation from international norm.56 Persuasion certainly lies within a state’s margin of appreciation. Freedom of religion does not require religious neutrality—separation of church and
  • 54. state, as Americans typically put it—but only that people be free to choose and practice their religion. Furthermore, there is no guarantee that the choice 55. Universal Declaration, supra note 50, art. 18. 56. Even where there is a broad pattern of systematic violations of international human rights norms, we often would do well not to focus too much on the issue of apostasy, which is likely to have a much stronger internal justification than many other violations of internationally recognized human rights. A better strategy, at least where apostates do not suffer severely, would be to work to improve broader human rights practices, with the aim of creating a situation where we would be “willing to live with” at least some forms of prohibition of apostasy. Vol. 29302 HUMAN RIGHTS QUARTERLY be without cost. A state thus might be justified in denying certain benefits to apostates, as long as those benefits are not guaranteed by human rights. (Protection against discrimination on the basis of religion is one of the foundational principles of international human rights norms.) It may even be (not im)permissible to impose modest disabilities on apostates, again as long as they do not violate the human rights of apostates,
  • 55. who remain human beings entitled to all of their human rights. And the state is under no obligation to protect apostates against social sanctions imposed by their families and communities that do not infringe human rights. Executing apostates, however, certainly exceeds the bounds of permis- sible variation. Violently imposing a specific conception of freedom of reli- gion inappropriately denies basic personal autonomy. Whatever the internal justification, this so excessively infringes the existing international legal and overlapping consensus that it is not entitled to international toleration—al- though we should stress that the same constraints on the use of force apply to external actors, even before we take into account the additional constraints imposed by considerations of sovereignty and international order. Consider now Article 4(a) of the Racial Discrimination Convention, which requires parties to prohibit racial violence and incitement to such violence and to “declare an offence punishable by law all dissemination of ideas based on racial superiority or hatred.”57 Article 20(2) of the Inter- national Covenant on Civil and Political Rights similarly requires that “any advocacy of national, racial or religious hatred that constitutes incitement
  • 56. to discrimination, hostility or violence shall be prohibited by law.”58 Such requirements have been rejected in the United States, where free speech includes even “hate speech” that does not incite violence. Here the issue is balancing two competing human rights, rather than a conflict between human rights and another value. Any resolution will require restricting the range of at least one of these rights. Therefore, any approach that plausibly protects the conceptual integrity of both rights must be described as controversial but defensible. American practice with respect to hate speech clearly falls into this category. Because incitement to violence is legally prohibited, US practice involves only a narrow deviation from international norms, with respect to one part of a second order conception, in a context of general support for the over- arching concepts and conceptions. Furthermore, the deviation is on behalf of a strong implementation of another vitally important human rights. And 57. International Convention on the Elimination of All Forms of Racial Discrimination, adopted 21 Dec. 1965, art. 4, ¶ a, 660 U.N.T.S. 195 (entered into force 4 Jan. 1969), reprinted in 5 I.L.M. 352 (1966). 58. International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights,
  • 57. adopted 19 Dec. 1966, G.A. Res. 2200 (XXI), U.N. GAOR, 21st Sess., Supp. No. 16, art. 20(2), U.N. Doc. A/6316 (1966), 999 U.N.T.S. 171 (entered into force 23 Mar. 1976). 2007 The Relative Universality of Human Rights 303 it is deeply rooted in legal history and constitutional theory. I can imagine few stronger cases for justifiable deviations from international norms. Targets of hate speech may indeed be harmed by that speech. They re- main, however, protected against violence. Conversely, prohibiting speech because of its content harms those whose speech is restricted. It also ef- fectively involves state imposition of a particular viewpoint, which is prima facie undesirable. Reasonable people may reasonably disagree about which harm is greatest. Toleration of the American refusal to prohibit hate speech thus seems demanded, even from those who sincerely and no less reasonably believe that prohibiting hate speech is the better course of action. Americans, however, need to be respectful of the mainstream practice and be willing to engage principled arguments to conform with international norms. These brief arguments are hardly conclusive, perhaps not even
  • 58. correct. (I am inclined to think that my argument on apostasy accepts too great a relativism.) I think, though, that they show that the (relative) universality of internationally recognized human rights does not require, or even encour- age, global homogenization or the sacrifice of (many) valued local practices. Certainly nothing in my account of relative universality implies, let alone justifies, cultural imperialism. Quite the contrary, (relatively) universal human rights protect people from imposed conceptions of the good life, whether those visions are imposed by local or foreign actors. Human rights seek to allow human beings, individually and in groups that give meaning and value to their lives, to pursue their own visions of the good life. Such choices—so long as they are consistent with comparable rights for others and reflect a plausible vision of human flourishing to which we can imagine a free people freely assenting—deserve our respect. In fact, understanding human rights as a political conception of justice supported by an overlapping consensus requires us to allow human beings, individually and collectively, considerable space to shape (relatively) universal rights to their particular purposes—so long as they operate largely within the constraints at the level of concepts established by functional, international
  • 59. legal, and overlapping consensus universality. 14. UNIVERSALISM wITHoUT IMpERIALISM My account has emphasized the “good” sides of universalism, understood in limited, relative terms. The political dangers of arguments of anthropological universality are modest, at least if one accepts functional and international legal universality. In arguing against ontological universality, however, I ignored the dangers of imperialist intolerance when such claims move into politics. This final section considers a few of the political dangers posed by excessive or “false” universalism, especially when a powerful actor (mis)takes its own interests for universal values. Vol. 29304 HUMAN RIGHTS QUARTERLY The legacy of colonialism demands that Westerners show special cau- tion and sensitivity when advancing arguments of universalism in the face of clashing cultural values. Westerners must also remember the political, economic, and cultural power that lies behind even their best intentioned activities. Anything that even hints of imposing Western values is likely to be met with understandable suspicion, even resistance. How
  • 60. arguments of universalism and arguments of relativism are advanced may sometimes be as important as the substance of those arguments.59 Care and caution, however, must not be confused with inattention or inaction. Our values, and international human rights norms, may demand that we act on them even in the absence of agreement by others—at least when that action does not involve force. Even strongly sanctioned tradi- tions may not deserve our toleration if they are unusually objectionable. Consider, for example, the deeply rooted tradition of anti- Semitism in the West or “untouchables” and bonded labor in India. Even if such traditional practices were not rejected by the governments in question, they would not deserve the tolerance, let alone the respect, of outsiders. When rights-abu- sive practices raise issues of great moral significance, tradition and culture are slight defense. Consider violence against homosexuals. International human rights law does not prohibit discrimination on the basis of sexual orientation. Sexual orientation is not mentioned in the Universal Declaration or the Covenants, and arguments that it falls within the category of “other status” in Article 2 of each of these documents are widely accepted, at least at the
  • 61. level of law, only in Europe and a few other countries. Nonetheless, everyone is entitled to security of the person. If the state refuses to protect some people against private violence, on the grounds that they are immoral, the state violates their basic human rights—which are held no less by the immoral than the moral.60 And the idea that the state should be permitted to imprison or even execute people solely on the basis of private voluntary acts between consent- ing adults, however much that behavior or “lifestyle” offends community conceptions of morality, is inconsistent with any plausible conception of personal autonomy and individual human rights. I do not mean to minimize the dangers of cultural and political arrogance, especially when backed by great power. US foreign policy often confuses American interests with universal values. Many Americans do seem to believe that what’s good for the US is good for the world—and if not, then “that’s 59. I probably would not object to readers who took this as implicit acknowledgment of certain shortcomings in some of my previous work on relativism, although I suspect that we might disagree about the range of applicability of such criticisms. 60. For clarity, let me explicitly note that I am not endorsing
  • 62. these judgments but simply arguing that even if they are accepted they do not justify violating human rights. 2007 The Relative Universality of Human Rights 305 their problem.” The dangers of such arrogant and abusive “universalism” are especially striking in international relations, where normative disputes that cannot be resolved by rational persuasion or appeal to agreed upon international norms tend to be settled by (political, economic, and cultural) power—of which United States today has more than anyone else. Faced with such undoubtedly perverse “unilateral universalism,” even some well meaning critics have been seduced by misguided arguments for the essential relativity of human rights. This, however, in effect accepts the American confusion of human rights with US foreign policy. The proper rem- edy for “false” universalism is defensible, relative universalism. Functional, overlapping consensus, and international legal universality, in addition to their analytical and substantive virtues, can be valuable resources for resist- ing many of the excesses of American foreign policy, and perhaps even for redirecting it into more humane channels.
  • 63. Indirect support for such an argument is provided by the preference of the Bush administration for the language of democracy and freedom rather than human rights.61 For example, the introductions to the 2002 and 2006 national security statements use “freedom” twenty-five times, “democracy” six times, and “human rights” just once (and not at all in 2006).62 Part of the reason would seem to be that human rights does have a relatively precise and well-settled meaning in contemporary international relations. “Democracy” is both narrower and more imprecisely defined, especially internationally.63 And “freedom” is a remarkably malleable idea—“rich” or “empty,” depending on your perspective—as a review of the roster of the “free world” in the 1970s indicates. International legal and overlapping consensus universality can provide important protection against the arrogant “universalism” of the powerful. Without authoritative international standards, to what can the United States (or any other great power) be held accountable? If international legal uni- versality has no force, why shouldn’t the United States act on its own (often peculiar) understandings of human rights? Even the Bush Administration’s preference for “coalitions of the willing” provides indirect
  • 64. testimony to the attractions of the idea of overlapping consensus. 61. Compare Julie Mertus, The New U.S. Human Rights Policy: A Radical Departure, 4 int’l StuD. PeRSPectiveS 371 (2003). 62. See available at www.whitehouse.gov/nsc/nssall.html; www.whitehouse.gov/nsc/nss/2006/ print/intro.html. The prefaces of the Clinton national security statements of 1996, 1997, and 1999, taken together, use “democracy” twenty-one times, “human rights” seven times, and “freedom” six. See available at www.fas.org/spp/military/docops/national/1996stra. htm; www.fas.org/man/docs/strategy97.htm; www.dtic.mil/doctrine/jel/other_pubs/nssr99. pdf. 63. Donnelly, univeRSAl HumAn RigHtS in tHeoRy AnD PRActice (2d ed.), supra note 1, §11.3 Vol. 29306 HUMAN RIGHTS QUARTERLY The contemporary virtues of (relative) universality are especially great because the ideological hegemony of human rights in the post- Cold War world is largely independent of American power. As Abu Ghraib indicates, international human rights norms may even provoke changes in policy in the midst of what is typically presented as a war. The international and
  • 65. national focus on Guantanamo—which on its face is odd, given the tiny percentage of the victims of the War on Terror who have suffered in this bit of American-occupied Cuba—underscores the power of widely endorsed international norms to change the terms of debate and transform the mean- ing of actions. International legal universality is one of the great achievements of the international human rights movement, both intrinsically and because it has facilitated a deepening overlapping consensus. Even the United States participates, fitfully and incompletely, in these consensuses. Not just the Clinton administration but both Bush administrations as well have regularly raised human rights concerns in numerous bilateral relationships, usually with a central element of genuine concern. (The real problem with American foreign policy is less where it does raise human rights concerns than where it doesn’t, or where it allows them to be subordinated to other concerns.) And all of this matters, directly to tens or hundreds of thousands of people, and indirectly to many hundreds of millions, whose lives have been made better by internationally recognized human rights. Human rights are not a panacea for the world’s problems. They do,
  • 66. however, fully deserve the prominence they have received in recent years. For the foreseeable future, human rights will remain a vital element in national, international, and transnational struggles for social justice and human dignity. And the relative universality of those rights is a powerful resource that can be used to help to build more just and humane national and international societies. 7 Human Rights Abdullahi A. An-Na`im Human rights is not commonly accepted as a field in sociology, despite the clear overlap in subject matter and possibilities of mutual conceptual and method- ological influence. In terms of the organization of this volume, for example, freedom from discrimination, as an overarching human rights principle, has obvious implications for fields in sociology ranging from citizenship and national identity to education, stratification and mobility, and health policy. Specific human rights, like freedom of speech and association, are clearly rele- vant to issues of political participation and labor. Gender, sexuality, children,
  • 67. and race are major themes among human rights scholars. The relationship between the state and civil society is central to the international articulation and national implementation of human rights in all societies around the world, and as such of interest to sociologists. Human rights considerations are also relevant to the mediation of competing claims to economic and social justice, identity, and communal autonomy, in global cross-cultural and comparative terms. These concerns join those of sociologists over such issues as globalization and postcolonial power relations, social movements, development, accountabil- ity of transnational corporations for labor relations, and environmental con- cerns. To explore possibilities of collaboration and mutual influence between sociologists and human rights scholars, I begin with an overview of the human rights paradigm as the framework for the specification and implementation of rights through national politics and international relations. Since many of the main themes of human rights are commonly known in terms of constitutional or civil rights (subject to the crucial difference indicated later), sociologists might want to consider whether their familiarity with the working of domestic (national) civil rights could enable them to contribute to mediating what I call
  • 68. the paradox of international accountability for the domestic practice of sovereign states. Mediating that paradox also calls for some understanding of the debate over the universality and cultural/contextual relativity of human rights, discussed in the second section. In the third section of this chapter, I discuss the need for complementary legal and social science approaches to the implementa- tion of human rights as a framework for justice; and provide a brief review of some of the ways in which sociologists have addressed human rights issues. The Human Rights ParadigmThe Human Rights Paradigm Human rights, in a generic sense, can be seen as a framework for an adequate response to the profound social concerns of persons and their communities. This primarily procedural sense of human rights is about creating and maintaining `̀ the space'' for individuals and groups to achieve justice, personal security and well-being, general political stability and economic development, and so forth. At the same time, however, human rights norms do have a specific normative content that reflects a certain understanding of what these individual and soci- etal objectives mean, and how they should be realized in practice. In a substan-
  • 69. tive sense, therefore, human rights have a clear ideological orientation to what it means to be human, and how social and political institutions should work in order to achieve certain ends. However, there is a tension between these two dimensions of human rights. To inspire and motivate people to take them seriously, human rights need to have significant and relevant normative content in each specific context.Yet this is likely to be resisted by privileged and powerful persons and groups in any society precisely because of the potential to change existing power relations. Aspects of this tension and its implications will become clearer after a brief explanation of what human rights are commonly understood to mean, and how they are supposed to work. By the human rights paradigm I mean the idea that the protection of certain individual and collective/group rights, as discussed below, is a matter of inter- national concern, rather than the exclusive internal affair of states. Paradox- ically, as explained below, the same states control the processes of determining these rights at the international level, and applying them within national jur- isdictions. Moreover, what the so-called international community may do about a state that willfully and persistently disregards its international obligations to protect those rights is also subject to a complex interaction of legal principles
  • 70. and practical considerations. For instance, the notion of `̀ humanitarian inter- vention'' to stop serious human rights violations within a country (as claimed by the NATO governments who intervened militarily in Kosovo in 1999 against the government of Yugoslavia) involves balancing such factors as human concern about the suffering of the victims, the risks of action or inaction for international peace and security, and the political and economic interests of the intervening state(s), as well as the short-and long-term implications of violating the sover- eignty of that country. Much of the normative, as well as the procedural, dimension of human rights is traditionally supposed to be provided for in national constitutions and laws Human Rights 87 for domestic application by the judicial and executive organs of the state, as a matter of national sovereignty. Earlier attempts by some states acting collectively to extend such regimes into the boundaries of another state included interna- tional efforts to end slavery and to protect minorities during the nineteenth and early twentieth centuries. But the real launch of the human rights paradigm in the generally accepted sense came about around the middle of
  • 71. the twentieth century. The horrific events of the Second World War prompted strong agree- ment by the mid-1940s on the need to effectively check the serious failure of any state to protect the rights of all persons and groups within its territorial jurisdic- tion (Steiner and Alston, 1996, p. 59). That was the first time there has ever been such a broad consensus about the need to reconcile respect for the sovereignty of a state with the protection of certain human rights as rights due to every human being by virtue of his or her humanity, without distinction on such grounds as race, sex, belief, language, or national origin. But since the process of determining the nature and scope of these rights, and approaches to their international protection, was confined to sovereign states which were members of the United Nations (UN) in 1945, only four African states and eight Asian states were included. The rest of Africa and Asia was colonized at that time by the same European powers that were proclaiming the universality of human rights at the UN. Moreover, some basic ambiguities in the original concept continue to frustrate the prospects of its practical application. For example, these rights are proclaimed in general terms as belonging to all human beings, while their realization is strongly associated with citizenship of a specific country. Although some general principles of
  • 72. international law still apply to how a state may treat non-citizens who happen to be within its territory, the distinction between citizen and non-citizen is sometimes difficult to justify from a human rights point of view (Turner, 1993b, p. 495; 1997). To avoid these complex issues in this brief overview, I refer to persons under the jurisdiction of a state, instead of identifying them as its citizens. The consensus of the mid-1940s was strongly reflected in the Charter of the UN of 1945, which is the most authoritative document of the present interna- tional order. According to Article 1 of the Charter, `̀ The Purposes of the United Nations are . . . (3) To achieve international cooperation in solving international problems of an economic, social, cultural, or humanitarian character, and in promoting and encouraging respect for human rights and for fundamental free- doms for all without distinction as to race, sex, language, or religion.'' While emphasizing this basic obligation in other Articles, the UN Charter left the task of definition and implementation of `̀ human rights and fundamental freedoms'' to subsequent developments. That process began with the drafting and adoption of the Universal Declara- tion of Human Rights of 1948. But the Declaration is not binding as such because, according to the UN Charter, resolutions of the
  • 73. General Assembly are merely recommendations to member states of the organization. The drafting and adoption of detailed treaties, which are binding under international law, followed, to provide definitions of rights and their implementation. Moreover, some human rights norms can also be found in certain principles of what is 88 Abdullahi Ahmed An-Na`im known as customary international law, like the prohibition of genocide, war crimes, and crimes against humanity. These norms are binding on all states, regardless of their ratification of treaties on those matters. Some human rights scholars argue that certain aspects of the Universal Declaration have become binding as customary international law. For example, the prohibition of torture is generally accepted as binding on all states as a principle of customary international law, regardless of their ratification of the specific treaties on the subject. The treaties setting the international `̀ legal'' standards of human rights range in scope from earlier Conventions on labor rights (1930), genocide (1948), and slavery (1956), to the broad 1966 International Covenants, one on economic,
  • 74. social and cultural rights, and the other on civil and political rights. There is also a growing number of specialized treaties, like the Conventions for the Elimina- tion of All Forms of Discrimination, on grounds of race (1965) and gender (1979), and the Convention on the Rights of the Child of 1989. Similar stand- ards appear in the regional documents of the European, Inter- American, and African systems (Steiner and Alston, 1996, p. 563). This legal regime also includes principles of humanitarian law regulating the conduct of armed forces in conflict situations, like the four Geneva Conventions of 1949, and the 1951 Refugees Convention. Human rights standards have also been elaborated through several major international conferences. During the 1990s, for instance, human rights principles and policies were elaborated in such documents as the Vienna Declaration and Programme of Action (1994) and the Beijing Platform for Action of the Fourth World Conference on Women (1995). Human rights are integral to the mandate of specialized intergovernmental agencies like the Inter- national Labor Organization (ILO), the World Health Organization (WHO), and the United Nation Development Programme (UNDP). As the increasingly wide range of local, regional, and global actors and processes envisioned by this complex web of documents and institutions clearly
  • 75. shows, the development of an international legal framework cannot mean that the implementation of human rights be left to purely legal approaches. The basic idea of the human rights paradigm is now firmly established in international relations, as well as in the national politics of the vast majority of countries around the world, subject to differing assessment of its efficacy or consistency of its application. Nevertheless, the basic paradox remains: how to achieve effect- ive international supervision of domestic human rights protection without violating national sovereignty as the expression of the right to self-determina- tion, which is itself a collective human right under the first Article of the 1966 Covenants. From this perspective, I suggest, social science approaches would be extremely important for understanding the processes of legal articulation and implementa- tion of these rights as the proper and legitimate exercise of the right to self- determination, rather than its negation. Sociological analyses are needed, for example, for understanding the processes of social construction of rights, whose interests are served by those processes, and the role of civil society and social movements in generating the political will to adopt and implement international Human Rights 89
  • 76. treaties protecting these rights. Such insights are essential for mediating the paradox of international protection of human rights through respect for sover- eignty, instead of its violation, as explained below. It is true that, by ratifying treaties and subscribing to international human rights policy statements, states are indicating voluntary acceptance of human rights obligations as limitations on their national sovereignty. But that notion itself can be seen as entrenching, rather than diminishing, the underlying para- dox, because it is the state that decides when, how, and to what extent to limit its own sovereignty. First, the structure and content of any human rights treaty are negotiated and agreed among the delegates of states, before the treaty is opened for ratification. Second, and regardless of its publicly declared position, no state is legally bound until it formally ratifies the treaty according to its own internal constitutional and political process. Moreover, subject to the requirements of the international law of treaties, a state has the right not only to enter `̀ reservations'' limiting the scope of its obligations under a treaty, but also to repudiate a treaty that it has previously ratified. Third, the state is also intended to play a crucial role in the interpretation and implementation within its territory
  • 77. of the human rights treaties it has ratified. Where national legislation is required to incorpor- ate international treaties into national law, as in the United States and United Kingdom, the domestic normative content of a treaty is effectively determined by the way it is expressed in legislative language, and interpreted through the judicial process, of the country (Steiner and Alston, 1996, p. 26). In other words, domestic compliance with a state's international obligations to protect human rights can only be achieved by the official organs of the same state. Thus, while intended to ensure the protection of certain minimum rights, international protection is dependent on the active cooperation of states in limiting their freedom of action within their own domestic jurisdiction. The paradox of self-regulation by the state of its own behavior is, of course, also true of domestic constitutional and legal protection of rights. The crucial differ- ence, noted above, is that constitutional rights are the product of internal dynamics, whereas the human rights paradigm seeks to influence domestic situations in favor of upholding certain internationally recognized standards. In other words, the paradox is sharper for the human rights paradigm because it has to overcome internal opposition within the country in question, without
  • 78. having the power to impose its will on states which refuse to comply. The need to mediate this enduring paradox calls for a clear understanding of the nature and functioning of social and political forces and institutions within each country, and in its relations with other countries. It is not helpful to simply call for formal limitations on state sovereignty, because that is neither practically feasible nor necessarily good for the protection of human rights in the long term. Formal limitations on sovereignty are not feasible because sovereignty is integral to the foundations of the present inter- national order, as entrenched in Article 2(7) of the UN Charter and other international documents, and fundamentally affirmed by national constitutions around the world. Since states are the principal actors at both the international and national levels, they are unlikely to relinquish their own autonomy by 90 Abdullahi Ahmed An-Na`im abandoning sovereignty or allowing other actors to achieve that result. Even if they were practically feasible, formal limitations might also be counterproduc- tive because sovereignty is the essential expression of the fundamental collective right to self-determination, as the practical vehicle of domestic
  • 79. policy and the necessary medium of international relations. A more realistic and desirable approach, I suggest, is to seek to diminish the negative consequence of the paradox of self-regulation by infusing the human rights ethos into the fabric of the state itself and the global context in which it operates. In that way, the protection of human rights becomes the outcome of the free exercise of the right to self-determination, instead of being seen as an external imposition which violates that right. This paradigm shift can best be achieved by upholding the universality of human rights as, in the words of the Preamble to the Universal Declaration, `̀ the common standard of achievement for all peoples and all nations.'' Since external imposition will probably be resisted as a clear violation of sovereignty, while voluntary compliance with commonly agreed standards is likely to be seen as vindication of sovereign authority, the universality of human rights must reflect true consensus around the world. At a formal level, that is said to be achieved through agreement among states, as the representatives of their societies under international law. But according to the human rights paradigm itself, and as a matter of practical politics, international agreements are legitimate and sustainable only to the extent that they express the genuine consent of national