SlideShare a Scribd company logo
1 of 47
THE ANTICHRIST
by Friedrich Nietzsche
Published 1895
translation by H.L. Mencken
Published 1920
PREFACE
This book belongs to the most rare of men. Perhaps not one of
them is yet alive. It is possible that they may be among those
who understand my "Zarathustra": how could I confound myself
with those who are now sprouting ears?--First the day after
tomorrow must come for me. Some men are born posthumously.
The conditions under which any one understands me, and
necessarily understands me--I know them only too well. Even to
endure my seriousness, my passion, he must carry intellectual
integrity to the verge of hardness. He must be accustomed to
living on mountain tops--and to looking upon the wretched
gabble of politics and nationalism as beneath him. He must have
become indifferent; he must never ask of the truth whether it
brings profit to him or a fatality to him... He must have an
inclination, born of strength, for questions that no one has the
courage for; the courage for the forbidden; predestination for
the labyrinth. The experience of seven solitudes. New ears for
new music. New eyes for what is most distant. A new
conscience for truths that have hitherto remained unheard. And
the will to economize in the grand manner--to hold together his
strength, his enthusiasm...Reverence for self; love of self;
absolute freedom of self.....
Very well, then! of that sort only are my readers, my true
readers, my readers foreordained: of what account are the rest?-
-The rest are merely humanity.--One must make one's self
superior to humanity, in power, in loftiness of soul,--in
contempt.
FRIEDRICH W. NIETZSCHE.
1.
--Let us look each other in the face. We are Hyperboreans--we
know well enough how remote our place is. "Neither by land
nor by water will you find the road to the Hyperboreans": even
Pindar1,in his day, knew that much about us. Beyond the North,
beyond the ice, beyond death--our life, our happiness...We have
discovered that happiness; we know the way; we got our
knowledge of it from thousands of years in the labyrinth. Who
else has found it?--The man of today?--"I don't know either the
way out or the way in; I am whatever doesn't know either the
way out or the way in"--so sighs the man of today...This is the
sort of modernity that made us ill,--we sickened on lazy peace,
cowardly compromise, the whole virtuous dirtiness of the
modern Yea and Nay. This tolerance and largeur of the heart
that "forgives" everything because it "understands" everything
is a sirocco to us. Rather live amid the ice than among modern
virtues and other such south-winds! . . . We were brave enough;
we spared neither ourselves nor others; but we were a long time
finding out where to direct our courage. We grew dismal; they
called us fatalists. Our fate--it was the fulness, the tension, the
storing up of powers. We thirsted for the lightnings and great
deeds; we kept as far as possible from the happiness of the
weakling, from "resignation" . . . There was thunder in our air;
nature, as we embodied it, became overcast--for we had not yet
found the way. The formula of our happiness: a Yea, a Nay, a
straight line, a goal...
2.
What is good?--Whatever augments the feeling of power, the
will to power, power itself, in man.
What is evil?--Whatever springs from weakness.
What is happiness?--The feeling that power increases--
thatresistance is overcome.
Not contentment, but more power; not peace at any price, but
war; not virtue, but efficiency (virtue in the Renaissance sense,
virtu, virtue free of moral acid).
The weak and the botched shall perish: first principle of our
charity. And one should help them to it.
What is more harmful than any vice?--Practical sympathy for
the botched and the weak--Christianity...
3.
The problem that I set here is not what shall replace mankind in
the order of living creatures (--man is an end--): but what type
of man must be bred, must be willed, as being the most
valuable, the most worthy of life, the most secure guarantee of
the future.
This more valuable type has appeared often enough in the past:
but always as a happy accident, as an exception, never as
deliberately willed. Very often it has been precisely the most
feared; hitherto it has been almost the terror of terrors ;--and
out of that terror the contrary type has been willed, cultivated
and attained: the domestic animal, the herd animal, the sick
brute-man--the Christian. . .
4.
Mankind surely does not represent an evolution toward a better
or stronger or higher level, as progress is now understood. This
"progress" is merely a modern idea, which is to say, a false
idea. The European of today, in his essential worth, falls far
below the European of the Renaissance; the process of evolution
does not necessarily mean elevation, enhancement,
strengthening.
True enough, it succeeds in isolated and individual cases in
various parts of the earth and under the most widely different
cultures, and in these cases a higher type certainly manifests
itself; something which, compared to mankind in the mass,
appears as a sort of superman. Such happy strokes of high
success have always been possible, and will remain possible,
perhaps, for all time to come. Even whole races, tribes and
nations may occasionally represent such lucky accidents.
5.
We should not deck out and embellish Christianity: it has waged
a war to the death against this higher type of man, it has put all
the deepest instincts of this type under its ban, it has developed
its concept of evil, of the Evil One himself, out of these
instincts--the strong man as the typical reprobate, the "outcast
among men." Christianity has taken the part of all the weak, the
low, the botched; it has made an ideal out of antagonism to all
the self-preservative instincts of sound life; it has corrupted
even the faculties of those natures that are intellectually most
vigorous, by representing the highest intellectual values as
sinful, as misleading, as full of temptation. The most lamentable
example: the corruption of Pascal, who believed that his
intellect had been destroyed by original sin, whereas it was
actually destroyed by Christianity!--
6.
It is a painful and tragic spectacle that rises before me: I have
drawn back the curtain from the rottenness of man. This word,
in my mouth, is at least free from one suspicion: that it involves
a moral accusation against humanity. It is used--and I wish to
emphasize the fact again--without any moral significance: and
this is so far true that the rottenness I speak of is most apparent
to me precisely in those quarters where there has been most
aspiration, hitherto, toward "virtue" and "godliness." As you
probably surmise, I understand rottenness in the sense of
decadence: my argument is that all the values on which mankind
now fixes its highest aspirations are decadence-values.
I call an animal, a species, an individual corrupt, when it loses
its instincts, when it chooses, when it prefers, what is injurious
to it. A history of the "higher feelings," the "ideals of
humanity"--and it is possible that I'll have to write it--would
almost explain why man is so degenerate. Life itself appears to
me as an instinct for growth, for survival, for the accumulation
of forces, for power: whenever the will to power fails there is
disaster. My contention is that all the highest values of
humanity have been emptied of this will--that the values of
decadence, of nihilism, now prevail under the holiest names.
7.
Christianity is called the religion of pity.-- Pity stands in
opposition to all the tonic passions that augment the energy of
the feeling of aliveness: it is a depressant. A man loses power
when he pities. Through pity that drain upon strength which
suffering works is multiplied a thousandfold. Suffering is made
contagious by pity; under certain circumstances it may lead to a
total sacrifice of life and living energy--a loss out of all
proportion to the magnitude of the cause (--the case of the death
of the Nazarene). This is the first view of it; there is, however,
a still more important one. If one measures the effects of pity by
the gravity of the reactions it sets up, its character as a menace
to life appears in a much clearer light. Pity thwarts the whole
law of evolution, which is the law of natural selection. It
preserves whatever is ripe for destruction; it fights on the side
of those disinherited and condemned by life; by maintaining life
in so many of the botched of all kinds, it gives life itself a
gloomy and dubious aspect. Mankind has ventured to call pity a
virtue (--in every superior moral system it appears as a
weakness--); going still further, it has been called the virtue, the
source and foundation of all other virtues--but let us always
bear in mind that this was from the standpoint of a philosophy
that was nihilistic, and upon whose shield the denial of life was
inscribed. Schopenhauer was right in this: that by means of pity
life is denied, and made worthy of denial--pity is the technic of
nihilism. Let me repeat: this depressing and contagious instinct
stands against all those instincts which work for the
preservation and enhancement of life: in the role of protector of
the miserable, it is a prime agent in the promotion of
decadence--pity persuades to extinction....Of course, one
doesn't say "extinction": one says "the other world," or "God,"
or "the true life," or Nirvana, salvation, blessedness.... This
innocent rhetoric, from the realm of religious-ethical
balderdash, appears a good deal less innocent when one reflects
upon the tendency that it conceals beneath sublime words: the
tendency to destroy life. Schopenhauer was hostile to life: that
is why pity appeared to him as a virtue. . . . Aristotle, as every
one knows, saw in pity a sickly and dangerous state of mind, the
remedy for which was an occasional purgative: he regarded
tragedy as that purgative. The instinct of life should prompt us
to seek some means of puncturing any such pathological and
dangerous accumulation of pity as that appearing in
Schopenhauer's case (and also, alack, in that of our whole
literary decadence, from St. Petersburg to Paris, from Tolstoi to
Wagner), that it may burst and be discharged. . . Nothing is
more unhealthy, amid all our unhealthy modernism, than
Christian pity. To be the doctors here, to be unmerciful here, to
wield the knife here--all this is our business, all this is our sort
of humanity, by this sign we are philosophers, we Hyperboreans
!--
8.
It is necessary to say just whom we regard as our antagonists:
theologians and all who have any theological blood in their
veins--this is our whole philosophy. . . . One must have faced
that menace at close hand, better still, one must have had
experience of it directly and almost succumbed to it, to realize
that it is not to be taken lightly (--the alleged free-thinking of
our naturalists and physiologists seems to me to be a joke--they
have no passion about such things; they have not suffered--).
This poisoning goes a great deal further than most people think:
I find the arrogant habit of the theologian among all who regard
themselves as "idealists"--among all who, by virtue of a higher
point of departure, claim a right to rise above reality, and to
look upon it with suspicion. . . The idealist, like the
ecclesiastic, carries all sorts of lofty concepts in his hand (--and
not only in his hand!); he launches them with benevolent
contempt against "understanding," "the senses," "honor," "good
living," "science"; he sees such things as beneath him, as
pernicious and seductive forces, on which "the soul" soars as a
pure thing-in-itself--as if humility, chastity, poverty, in a word,
holiness, had not already done much more damage to life than
all imaginable horrors and vices. . . The pure soul is a pure lie. .
. So long as the priest, that professional denier, calumniator and
poisoner of life, is accepted as a higher variety of man, there
can be no answer to the question, What is truth? Truth has
already been stood on its head when the obvious attorney of
mere emptiness is mistaken for its representative.
9.
Upon this theological instinct I make war: I find the tracks of it
everywhere. Whoever has theological blood in his veins is
shifty and dishonourable in all things. The pathetic thing that
grows out of this condition is called faith: in other words,
closing one's eyes upon one's self once for all, to avoid
suffering the sight of incurable falsehood. People erect a
concept of morality, of virtue, of holiness upon this false view
of all things; they ground good conscience upon faulty vision;
they argue that no other sort of vision has value any more, once
they have made theirs sacrosanct with the names of "God,"
"salvation" and "eternity." I unearth this theological instinct in
all directions: it is the most widespread and the most
subterranean form of falsehood to be found on earth. Whatever
a theologian regards as true must be false: there you have
almost a criterion of truth. His profound instinct of self-
preservation stands against truth ever coming into honour in any
way, or even getting stated. Wherever the influence of
theologians is felt there is a transvaluation of values, and the
concepts "true" and "false" are forced to change places: what
ever is most damaging to life is there called "true," and
whatever exalts it, intensifies it, approves it, justifies it and
makes it triumphant is there called "false."... When theologians,
working through the "consciences" of princes (or of peoples--),
stretch out their hands for power, there is never any doubt as to
the fundamental issue: the will to make an end, the nihilistic
will exerts that power...
10.
Among Germans I am immediately understood when I say that
theological blood is the ruin of philosophy. The Protestant
pastor is the grandfather of German philosophy; Protestantism
itself is its peccatum originale. Definition of Protestantism:
hemiplegic paralysis of Christianity--and of reason. ... One need
only utter the words "Tubingen School" to get an understanding
of what German philosophy is at bottom--a very artful form of
theology. . . The Suabians are the best liars in Germany; they
lie innocently. . . . Why all the rejoicing over the appearance of
Kant that went through the learned world of Germany, three-
fourths of which is made up of the sons of preachers and
teachers--why the German conviction still echoing, that with
Kant came a change for the better? The theological instinct of
German scholars made them see clearly just what had become
possible again. . . . A backstairs leading to the old ideal stood
open; the concept of the "true world," the concept of morality as
the essence of the world (--the two most vicious errors that ever
existed!), were once more, thanks to a subtle and wily
scepticism, if not actually demonstrable, then at least no longer
refutable... Reason, the prerogative of reason, does not go so
far. . . Out of reality there had been made "appearance"; an
absolutely false world, that of being, had been turned into
reality. . . . The success of Kant is merely a theological success;
he was, like Luther and Leibnitz, but one more impediment to
German integrity, already far from steady.--
11.
A word now against Kant as a moralist. A virtue must be our
invention; it must spring out of our personal need and defence.
In every other case it is a source of danger. That which does not
belong to our life menaces it; a virtue which has its roots in
mere respect for the concept of "virtue," as Kant would have it,
is pernicious. "Virtue," "duty," "good for its own sake,"
goodness grounded upon impersonality or a notion of universal
validity--these are all chimeras, and in them one finds only an
expression of the decay, the last collapse of life, the Chinese
spirit of Konigsberg. Quite the contrary is demanded by the
most profound laws of self-preservation and of growth: to wit,
that every man find hisown virtue, his own categorical
imperative. A nation goes to pieces when it confounds its duty
with the general concept of duty. Nothing works a more
complete and penetrating disaster than every "impersonal" duty,
every sacrifice before the Moloch of abstraction.--To think that
no one has thought of Kant's categorical imperative as
dangerous to life!...The theological instinct alone took it under
protection !--An action prompted by the life-instinct proves that
it is a right action by the amount of pleasure that goes with it:
and yet that Nihilist, with his bowels of Christian dogmatism,
regarded pleasure as an objection . . . What destroys a man more
quickly than to work, think and feel without inner necessity,
without any deep personal desire, without pleasure--as a mere
automaton of duty? That is the recipe for decadence, and no less
for idiocy. . . Kant became an idiot.--And such a man was the
contemporary of Goethe! This calamitous spinner of cobwebs
passed for the German philosopher--still passes today! . . . I
forbid myself to say what I think of the Germans. . . . Didn't
Kant see in the French Revolution the transformation of the
state from the inorganic form to the organic? Didn't he ask
himself if there was a single event that could be explained save
on the assumption of a moral faculty in man, so that on the
basis of it, "the tendency of mankind toward the good" could be
explained, once and for all time? Kant's answer: "That is
revolution." Instinct at fault in everything and anything, instinct
as a revolt against nature, German decadence as a philosophy--
that is Kant!----
12.
I put aside a few sceptics, the types of decency in the history of
philosophy: the rest haven't the slightest conception of
intellectual integrity. They behave like women, all these great
enthusiasts and prodigies--they regard "beautiful feelings" as
arguments, the "heaving breast" as the bellows of divine
inspiration, conviction as the criterion of truth. In the end, with
"German" innocence, Kant tried to give a scientific flavour to
this form of corruption, this dearth of intellectual conscience,
by calling it "practical reason." He deliberately invented a
variety of reasons for use on occasions when it was desirable
not to trouble with reason--that is, when morality, when the
sublime command "thou shalt," was heard. When one recalls the
fact that, among all peoples, the philosopher is no more than a
development from the old type of priest, this inheritance from
the priest, this fraud upon self, ceases to be remarkable. When a
man feels that he has a divine mission, say to lift up, to save or
to liberate mankind--when a man feels the divine spark in his
heart and believes that he is the mouthpiece of supernatural
imperatives--when such a mission in. flames him, it is only
natural that he should stand beyond all merely reasonable
standards of judgment. He feels that he is himself sanctified by
this mission, that he is himself a type of a higher order! . . .
What has a priest to do with philosophy! He stands far above
it!--And hitherto the priest has ruled!--Hehas determined the
meaning of "true" and "not true"!
13.
Let us not under-estimate this fact: that we ourselves, we free
spirits, are already a "transvaluation of all values," a visualized
declaration of war and victory against all the old concepts of
"true" and "not true." The most valuable intuitions are the last
to be attained; the most valuable of all are those which
determine methods. All the methods, all the principles of the
scientific spirit of today, were the targets for thousands of years
of the most profound contempt; if a man inclined to them he
was excluded from the society of "decent" people--he passed as
"an enemy of God," as a scoffer at the truth, as one "possessed."
As a man of science, he belonged to the Chandala2... We have
had the whole pathetic stupidity of mankind against us--their
every notion of what the truth ought to be, of what the service
of the truth ought to be--their every "thou shalt" was launched
against us. . . . Our objectives, our methods, our quiet, cautious,
distrustful manner--all appeared to them as absolutely
discreditable and contemptible.--Looking back, one may almost
ask one's self with reason if it was not actually an aesthetic
sense that kept men blind so long: what they demanded of the
truth was picturesque effectiveness, and of the learned a strong
appeal to their senses. It was our modesty that stood out longest
against their taste...How well they guessed that, these turkey-
cocks of God!
14.
We have unlearned something. We have be come more modest
in every way. We no longer derive man from the "spirit," from
the "god-head"; we have dropped him back among the beasts.
We regard him as the strongest of the beasts because he is the
craftiest; one of the results thereof is his intellectuality. On the
other hand, we guard ourselves against a conceit which would
assert itself even here: that man is the great second thought in
the process of organic evolution. He is, in truth, anything but
the crown of creation: beside him stand many other animals, all
at similar stages of development... And even when we say that
we say a bit too much, for man, relatively speaking, is the most
botched of all the animals and the sickliest, and he has
wandered the most dangerously from his instincts--though for
all that, to be sure, he remains the most interesting!--As regards
the lower animals, it was Descartes who first had the really
admirable daring to describe them as machina; the whole of our
physiology is directed toward proving the truth of this doctrine.
Moreover, it is illogical to set man apart, as Descartes did: what
we know of man today is limited precisely by the extent to
which we have regarded him, too, as a machine. Formerly we
accorded to man, as his inheritance from some higher order of
beings, what was called "free will"; now we have taken even
this will from him, for the term no longer describes anything
that we can understand. The old word "will" now connotes only
a sort of result, an individual reaction, that follows inevitably
upon a series of partly discordant and partly harmonious
stimuli--the will no longer "acts," or "moves." . . . Formerly it
was thought that man's consciousness, his "spirit," offered
evidence of his high origin, his divinity. That he might be
perfected, he was advised, tortoise-like, to draw his senses in,
to have no traffic with earthly things, to shuffle off his mortal
coil--then only the important part of him, the "pure spirit,"
would remain. Here again we have thought out the thing better:
to us consciousness, or "the spirit," appears as a symptom of a
relative imperfection of the organism, as an experiment, a
groping, a misunderstanding, as an affliction which uses up
nervous force unnecessarily--we deny that anything can be done
perfectly so long as it is done consciously. The "pure spirit" is a
piece of pure stupidity: take away the nervous system and the
senses, the so-called "mortal shell," and the rest is
miscalculation--thatis all!...
15.
Under Christianity neither morality nor religion has any point of
contact with actuality. It offers purely imaginary causes ("God"
"soul," "ego," "spirit," "free will"--or even "unfree"), and
purely imaginary effects ("sin" "salvation" "grace,"
"punishment," "forgiveness of sins"). Intercourse between
imaginarybeings ("God," "spirits," "souls"); an imaginarynatural
history (anthropocentric; a total denial of the concept of natural
causes); an imaginary psychology (misunderstandings of self,
misinterpretations of agreeable or disagreeable general feelings-
-for example, of the states of the nervus sympathicus with the
help of the sign-language of religio-ethical balderdash--,
"repentance," "pangs of conscience," "temptation by the devil,"
"the presence of God"); an imaginaryteleology (the "kingdom of
God," "the last judgment," "eternal life").--This purely fictitious
world, greatly to its disadvantage, is to be differentiated from
the world of dreams; the later at least reflects reality, whereas
the former falsifies it, cheapens it and denies it. Once the
concept of "nature" had been opposed to the concept of "God,"
the word "natural" necessarily took on the meaning of
"abominable"--the whole of that fictitious world has its sources
in hatred of the natural (--the real!--), and is no more than
evidence of a profound uneasiness in the presence of reality. . .
. This explains everything. Who alone has any reason for living
his way out of reality? The man who suffers under it. But to
suffer from reality one must be a botched reality. . . . The
preponderance of pains over pleasures is the cause of this
fictitious morality and religion: but such a preponderance also
supplies the formula for decadence...
16.
A criticism of the Christian concept of God leads inevitably to
the same conclusion.--A nation that still believes in itself holds
fast to its own god. In him it does honour to the conditions
which enable it to survive, to its virtues--it projects its joy in
itself, its feeling of power, into a being to whom one may offer
thanks. He who is rich will give of his riches; a proud people
need a god to whom they can make sacrifices. . . Religion,
within these limits, is a form of gratitude. A man is grateful for
his own existence: to that end he needs a god.--Such a god must
be able to work both benefits and injuries; he must be able to
play either friend or foe--he is wondered at for the good he does
as well as for the evil he does. But the castration, against all
nature, of such a god, making him a god of goodness alone,
would be contrary to human inclination. Mankind has just as
much need for an evil god as for a good god; it doesn't have to
thank mere tolerance and humanitarianism for its own existence.
. . . What would be the value of a god who knew nothing of
anger, revenge, envy, scorn, cunning, violence? who had
perhaps never experienced the rapturous ardeurs of victory and
of destruction? No one would understand such a god: why
should any one want him?--True enough, when a nation is on
the downward path, when it feels its belief in its own future, its
hope of freedom slipping from it, when it begins to see
submission as a first necessity and the virtues of submission as
measures of self-preservation, then it must overhaul its god. He
then becomes a hypocrite, timorous and demure; he counsels
"peace of soul," hate-no-more, leniency, "love" of friend and
foe. He moralizes endlessly; he creeps into every private virtue;
he becomes the god of every man; he becomes a private citizen,
a cosmopolitan. . . Formerly he represented a people, the
strength of a people, everything aggressive and thirsty for
power in the soul of a people; now he is simply the good
god...The truth is that there is no other alternative for gods:
either they are the will to power--in which case they are
national gods--or incapacity for power--in which case they have
to be good.
17.
Wherever the will to power begins to decline, in whatever form,
there is always an accompanying decline physiologically, a
decadence. The divinity of this decadence, shorn of its
masculine virtues and passions, is converted perforce into a god
of the physiologically degraded, of the weak. Of course, they do
not call themselves the weak; they call themselves "the good." .
. . No hint is needed to indicate the moments in history at which
the dualistic fiction of a good and an evil god first became
possible. The same instinct which prompts the inferior to reduce
their own god to "goodness-in-itself" also prompts them to
eliminate all good qualities from the god of their superiors; they
make revenge on their masters by making a devil of the latter's
god.--The good god, and the devil like him--both are abortions
of decadence.--How can we be so tolerant of the naïveté of
Christian theologians as to join in their doctrine that the
evolution of the concept of god from "the god of Israel," the
god of a people, to the Christian god, the essence of all
goodness, is to be described as progress?--But even Renan does
this. As if Renan had a right to be naïve! The contrary actually
stares one in the face. When everything necessary to ascending
life; when all that is strong, courageous, masterful and proud
has been eliminated from the concept of a god; when he has
sunk step by step to the level of a staff for the weary, a sheet-
anchor for the drowning; when he be comes the poor man's god,
the sinner's god, the invalid's god par excellence, and the
attribute of "saviour" or "redeemer" remains as the one essential
attribute of divinity--just what is the significance of such a
metamorphosis? what does such a reduction of the godhead
imply?--To be sure, the "kingdom of God" has thus grown
larger. Formerly he had only his own people, his "chosen"
people. But since then he has gone wandering, like his people
themselves, into foreign parts; he has given up settling down
quietly anywhere; finally he has come to feel at home
everywhere, and is the great cosmopolitan--until now he has the
"great majority" on his side, and half the earth. But this god of
the "great majority," this democrat among gods, has not become
a proud heathen god: on the contrary, he remains a Jew, he
remains a god in a corner, a god of all the dark nooks and
crevices, of all the noisesome quarters of the world! . . His
earthly kingdom, now as always, is a kingdom of the
underworld, a souterrain kingdom, a ghetto kingdom. . . And he
himself is so pale, so weak, so decadent . . . Even the palest of
the pale are able to master him--messieurs the metaphysicians,
those albinos of the intellect. They spun their webs around him
for so long that finally he was hypnotized, and began to spin
himself, and became another metaphysician. Thereafter he
resumed once more his old business of spinning the world out of
his inmost being sub specie Spinozae; thereafter he be came
ever thinner and paler--became the "ideal," became "pure
spirit," became "the absolute," became "the thing-in-itself." . . .
The collapse of a god: he became a "thing-in-itself."
18.
The Christian concept of a god--the god as the patron of the
sick, the god as a spinner of cobwebs, the god as a spirit--is one
of the most corrupt concepts that has ever been set up in the
world: it probably touches low-water mark in the ebbing
evolution of the god-type. God degenerated into the
contradiction of life. Instead of being its transfiguration and
eternal Yea! In him war is declared on life, on nature, on the
will to live! God becomes the formula for every slander upon
the "here and now," and for every lie about the "beyond"! In
him nothingness is deified, and the will to nothingness is made
holy! . . .
19.
The fact that the strong races of northern Europe did not
repudiate this Christian god does little credit to their gift for
religion--and not much more to their taste. They ought to have
been able to make an end of such a moribund and worn-out
product of the decadence. A curse lies upon them because they
were not equal to it; they made illness, decrepitude and
contradiction a part of their instincts--and since then they have
not managed to create any more gods. Two thousand years have
come and gone--and not a single new god! Instead, there still
exists, and as if by some intrinsic right,--as if he were the
ultimatum and maximum of the power to create gods, of the
creator spiritus in mankind--this pitiful god of Christian
monotono-theism! This hybrid image of decay, conjured up out
of emptiness, contradiction and vain imagining, in which all the
instincts of decadence, all the cowardices and wearinesses of
the soul find their sanction!--
20.
In my condemnation of Christianity I surely hope I do no
injustice to a related religion with an even larger number of
believers: I allude to Buddhism. Both are to be reckoned among
the nihilistic religions--they are both decadence religions--but
they are separated from each other in a very remarkable way.
For the fact that he is able to compare them at all the critic of
Christianity is indebted to the scholars of India.--Buddhism is a
hundred times as realistic as Christianity--it is part of its living
heritage that it is able to face problems objectively and coolly;
it is the product of long centuries of philosophical speculation.
The concept, "god," was already disposed of before it appeared.
Buddhism is the only genuinely positive religion to be
encountered in history, and this applies even to its epistemology
(which is a strict phenomenalism) --It does not speak of a
"struggle with sin," but, yielding to reality, of the "struggle
with suffering." Sharply differentiating itself from Christianity,
it puts the self-deception that lies in moral concepts be hind it;
it is, in my phrase,beyond good and evil.--The two
physiological facts upon which it grounds itself and upon which
it bestows its chief attention are: first, an excessive
sensitiveness to sensation, which manifests itself as a refined
susceptibility to pain, and secondly, an extraordinary
spirituality, a too protracted concern with concepts and logical
procedures, under the influence of which the instinct of
personality has yielded to a notion of the "impersonal." (--Both
of these states will be familiar to a few of my readers, the
objectivists, by experience, as they are to me). These
physiological states produced a depression, and Buddha tried to
combat it by hygienic measures. Against it he prescribed a life
in the open, a life of travel; moderation in eating and a careful
selection of foods; caution in the use of intoxicants; the same
caution in arousing any of the passions that foster a bilious
habit and heat the blood; finally, no worry, either on one's own
account or on account of others. He encourages ideas that make
for either quiet contentment or good cheer--he finds means to
combat ideas of other sorts. He understands good, the state of
goodness, as something which promotes health. Prayer is not
included, and neither is asceticism. There is no categorical
imperative nor any disciplines, even within the walls of a
monastery (--it is always possible to leave--). These things
would have been simply means of increasing the excessive
sensitiveness above mentioned. For the same reason he does not
advocate any conflict with unbelievers; his teaching is
antagonistic to nothing so much as to revenge, aversion,
ressentiment (--"enmity never brings an end to enmity": the
moving refrain of all Buddhism. . .) And in all this he was right,
for it is precisely these passions which, in view of his main
regiminal purpose, are unhealthful. The mental fatigue that he
observes, already plainly displayed in too much "objectivity"
(that is, in the individual's loss of interest in himself, in loss of
balance and of "egoism"), he combats by strong efforts to lead
even the spiritual interests back to the ego. In Buddha's
teaching egoism is a duty. The "one thing needful," the question
"how can you be delivered from suffering," regulates and
determines the whole spiritual diet. (--Perhaps one will here
recall that Athenian who also declared war upon pure
"scientificality," to wit, Socrates, who also elevated egoism to
the estate of a morality) .
21.
The things necessary to Buddhism are a very mild climate,
customs of great gentleness and liberality, and no militarism;
moreover, it must get its start among the higher and better
educated classes. Cheerfulness, quiet and the absence of desire
are the chief desiderata, and they are attained. Buddhism is not
a religion in which perfection is merely an object of aspiration:
perfection is actually normal.--Under Christianity the instincts
of the subjugated and the oppressed come to the fore: it is only
those who are at the bottom who seek their salvation in it. Here
the prevailing pastime, the favourite remedy for boredom is the
discussion of sin, self-criticism, the inquisition of conscience;
here the emotion produced by power (called "God") is pumped
up (by prayer); here the highest good is regarded as
unattainable, as a gift, as "grace." Here, too, open dealing is
lacking; concealment and the darkened room are Christian. Here
body is despised and hygiene is denounced as sensual; the
church even ranges itself against cleanliness (--the first
Christian order after the banishment of the Moors closed the
public baths, of which there were 270 in Cordova alone) .
Christian, too; is a certain cruelty toward one's self and toward
others; hatred of unbelievers; the will to persecute. Sombre and
disquieting ideas are in the foreground; the most esteemed
states of mind, bearing the most respectable names are
epileptoid; the diet is so regulated as to engender morbid
symptoms and over-stimulate the nerves. Christian, again, is all
deadly enmity to the rulers of the earth, to the "aristocratic"--
along with a sort of secret rivalry with them (--one resigns one's
"body" to them--one wantsonly one's "soul" . . . ). And
Christian is all hatred of the intellect, of pride, of courage of
freedom, of intellectual libertinage; Christian is all hatred of the
senses, of joy in the senses, of joy in general . . .
22.
When Christianity departed from its native soil, that of the
lowest orders, the underworld of the ancient world, and began
seeking power among barbarian peoples, it no longer had to deal
with exhausted men, but with men still inwardly savage and
capable of self torture--in brief, strong men, but bungled men.
Here, unlike in the case of the Buddhists, the cause of
discontent with self, suffering through self, is not merely a
general sensitiveness and susceptibility to pain, but, on the
contrary, an inordinate thirst for inflicting pain on others, a
tendency to obtain subjective satisfaction in hostile deeds and
ideas. Christianity had to embrace barbaric concepts and
valuations in order to obtain mastery over barbarians: of such
sort, for example, are the sacrifices of the first-born, the
drinking of blood as a sacrament, the disdain of the intellect and
of culture; torture in all its forms, whether bodily or not; the
whole pomp of the cult. Buddhism is a religion for peoples in a
further state of development, for races that have become kind,
gentle and over-spiritualized (--Europe is not yet ripe for it--):
it is a summons 'that takes them back to peace and cheerfulness,
to a careful rationing of the spirit, to a certain hardening of the
body. Christianity aims at mastering beasts of prey; its modus
operandi is to make them ill--to make feeble is the Christian
recipe for taming, for "civilizing." Buddhism is a religion for
the closing, over-wearied stages of civilization. Christianity
appears before civilization has so much as begun--under certain
circumstances it lays the very foundations thereof.
23.
Buddhism, I repeat, is a hundred times more austere, more
honest, more objective. It no longer has to justify its pains, its
susceptibility to suffering, by interpreting these things in terms
of sin--it simply says, as it simply thinks, "I suffer." To the
barbarian, however, suffering in itself is scarcely
understandable: what he needs, first of all, is an explanation as
to why he suffers. (His mere instinct prompts him to deny his
suffering altogether, or to endure it in silence.) Here the word
"devil" was a blessing: man had to have an omnipotent and
terrible enemy--there was no need to be ashamed of suffering at
the hands of such an enemy.
--At the bottom of Christianity there are several subtleties that
belong to the Orient. In the first place, it knows that it is of
very little consequence whether a thing be true or not, so long
as it is believed to be true. Truth and faith: here we have two
wholly distinct worlds of ideas, almost two diametrically
opposite worlds--the road to the one and the road to the other
lie miles apart. To understand that fact thoroughly--this is
almost enough, in the Orient, to make one a sage. The Brahmins
knew it, Plato knew it, every student of the esoteric knows it.
When, for example, a man gets any pleasure out of the notion
that he has been saved from sin, it is not necessary for him to be
actually sinful, but merely to feel sinful. But when faith is thus
exalted above everything else, it necessarily follows that
reason, knowledge and patient inquiry have to be discredited:
the road to the truth becomes a forbidden road.--Hope, in its
stronger forms, is a great deal more powerful stimulans to life
than any sort of realized joy can ever be. Man must be sustained
in suffering by a hope so high that no conflict with actuality can
dash it--so high, indeed, that no fulfillment can satisfy it: a
hope reaching out beyond this world. (Precisely because of this
power that hope has of making the suffering hold out, the
Greeks regarded it as the evil of evils, as the most malign of
evils; it remained behind at the source of all evil.)3--In order
that love may be possible, God must become a person; in order
that the lower instincts may take a hand in the matter God must
be young. To satisfy the ardor of the woman a beautiful saint
must appear on the scene, and to satisfy that of the men there
must be a virgin. These things are necessary if Christianity is to
assume lordship over a soil on which some aphrodisiacal or
Adonis cult has already established a notion as to what a cult
ought to be. To insist upon chastity greatly strengthens the
vehemence and subjectivity of the religious instinct--it makes
the cult warmer, more enthusiastic, more soulful.--Love is the
state in which man sees things most decidedly as they are not.
The force of illusion reaches its highest here, and so does the
capacity for sweetening, for transfiguring. When a man is in
love he endures more than at any other time; he submits to
anything. The problem was to devise a religion which would
allow one to love: by this means the worst that life has to offer
is overcome--it is scarcely even noticed.--So much for the three
Christian virtues: faith, hope and charity: I call them the three
Christian ingenuities.--Buddhism is in too late a stage of
development, too full of positivism, to be shrewd in any such
way.--
24.
Here I barely touch upon the problem of the origin of
Christianity. The first thing necessary to its solution is this: that
Christianity is to be understood only by examining the soil from
which it sprung--it is not a reaction against Jewish instincts; it
is their inevitable product; it is simply one more step in the
awe-inspiring logic of the Jews. In the words of the Saviour,
"salvation is of the Jews." 4--The second thing to remember is
this: that the psychological type of the Galilean is still to be
recognized, but it was only in its most degenerate form (which
is at once maimed and overladen with foreign features) that it
could serve in the manner in which it has been used: as a type
of the Saviour of mankind.
--The Jews are the most remarkable people in the history of the
world, for when they were confronted with the question, to be
or not to be, they chose, with perfectly unearthly deliberation,
to be at anyprice: this price involved a radical falsification of
all nature, of all naturalness, of all reality, of the whole inner
world, as well as of the outer. They put themselves against all
those conditions under which, hitherto, a people had been able
to live, or had even been permitted to live; out of themselves
they evolved an idea which stood in direct opposition to natural
conditions--one by one they distorted religion, civilization,
morality, history and psychology until each became a
contradiction of its natural significance. We meet with the same
phenomenon later on, in an incalculably exaggerated form, but
only as a copy: the Christian church, put beside the "people of
God," shows a complete lack of any claim to originality.
Precisely for this reason the Jews are the most fateful people in
the history of the world: their influence has so falsified the
reasoning of mankind in this matter that today the Christian can
cherish anti-Semitism without realizing that it is no more than
the final consequence of Judaism.
In my "Genealogy of Morals" I give the first psychological
explanation of the concepts underlying those two antithetical
things, a noble morality and a ressentiment morality, the second
of which is a mere product of the denial of the former. The
Judaeo-Christian moral system belongs to the second division,
and in every detail. In order to be able to say Nay to everything
representing an ascending evolution of life--that is, to well-
being, to power, to beauty, to self-approval--the instincts of
ressentiment, here become downright genius, had to invent an
other world in which the acceptance of life appeared as the most
evil and abominable thing imaginable. Psychologically, the
Jews are a people gifted with the very strongest vitality, so
much so that when they found themselves facing impossible
conditions of life they chose voluntarily, and with a profound
talent for self-preservation, the side of all those instincts which
make for decadence--not as if mastered by them, but as if
detecting in them a power by which "the world" could be defied.
The Jews are the very opposite of decadents: they have simply
been forced into appearing in that guise, and with a degree of
skill approaching the non plus ultra of histrionic genius they
have managed to put themselves at the head of all decadent
movements (--for example, the Christianity of Paul--), and so
make of them something stronger than any party frankly saying
Yes to life. To the sort of men who reach out for power under
Judaism and Christianity,--that is to say, to the priestly class-
decadence is no more than a means to an end. Men of this sort
have a vital interest in making mankind sick, and in confusing
the values of "good" and "bad," "true" and "false" in a manner
that is not only dangerous to life, but also slanders it.
Nicomachean Ethics
Book 1, Chapter 1
EVERY art and every inquiry, and similarly every action and
pursuit, is thought to aim at some good; and for this reason the
good has rightly been declared to be that at which all things
aim. But a certain difference is found among ends; some are
activities, others are products apart from the activities that
produce them. Where there are ends apart from the actions, it is
the nature of the products to be better than the activities. Now,
as there are many actions, arts, and sciences, their ends also are
many; the end of the medical art is health, that of shipbuilding a
vessel, that of strategy victory, that of economics wealth. But
where such arts fall under a single capacity -- as bridle-making
and the other arts concerned with the equipment of horses fall
under the art of riding, and this and every military action under
strategy, in the same way other arts fall under yet others -- in
all of these the ends of the master arts are to be preferred to all
the subordinate ends; for it is for the sake of the former that the
latter are pursued. It makes no difference whether the activities
themselves are the ends of the actions, or something else apart
from the activities, as in the case of the sciences just
mentioned.
Book 1, Chapter 2
If, then, there is some end of the things we do, which we desire
for its own sake (everything else being desired for the sake of
this), and if we do not choose everything for the sake of
something else (for at that rate the process would go on to
infinity, so that our desire would be empty and vain), clearly
this must be the good and the chief good. Will not the
knowledge of it, then, have a great influence on life? Shall we
not, like archers who have a mark to aim at, be more likely to
hit upon what is right? If so, we must try, in outline at least, to
determine what it is, and of which of the sciences or capacities
it is the object. It would seem to belong to the most
authoritative art and that which is most truly the master art. And
politics appears to be of this nature; for it is this that ordains
which of the sciences should be studied in a state, and which
each class of citizens should learn and up to what point they
should learn them; and we see even the most highly esteemed of
capacities to fall under this, e.g. strategy, economics, rhetoric;
now, since politics uses the rest of the sciences, and since,
again, it legislates as to what we are to do and what we are to
abstain from, the end of this science must include those of the
others, so that this end must be the good for man. For even if
the end is the same for a single man and for a state, that of the
state seems at all events something greater and more complete
whether to attain or to preserve; though it is worth while to
attain the end merely for one man, it is finer and more godlike
to attain it for a nation or for city-states. These, then, are the
ends at which our inquiry aims, since it is political science, in
one sense of that term.
Book 1, Chapter 3
Our discussion will be adequate if it has as much clearness as
the subject-matter admits of, for precision is not to be sought
for alike in all discussions, any more than in all the products of
the crafts. Now fine and just actions, which political science
investigates, admit of much variety and fluctuation of opinion,
so that they may be thought to exist only by convention, and not
by nature. And goods also give rise to a similar fluctuation
because they bring harm to many people; for before now men
have been undone by reason of their wealth, and others by
reason of their courage. We must be content, then, in speaking
of such subjects and with such premisses to indicate the truth
roughly and in outline, and in speaking about things which are
only for the most part true and with premisses of the same kind
to reach conclusions that are no better. In the same spirit,
therefore, should each type of statement be received; for it is
the mark of an educated man to look for precision in each class
of things just so far as the nature of the subject admits; it is
evidently equally foolish to accept probable reasoning from a
mathematician and to demand from a rhetorician scientific
proofs.
Now each man judges well the things he knows, and of these he
is a good judge. And so the man who has been educated in a
subject is a good judge of that subject, and the man who has
received an all-round education is a good judge in general.
Hence a young man is not a proper hearer of lectures on
political science; for he is inexperienced in the actions that
occur in life, but its discussions start from these and are about
these; and, further, since he tends to follow his passions, his
study will be vain and unprofitable, because the end aimed at is
not knowledge but action. And it makes no difference whether
he is young in years or youthful in character; the defect does
not depend on time, but on his living, and pursuing each
successive object, as passion directs. For to such persons, as to
the incontinent, knowledge brings no profit; but to those who
desire and act in accordance with a rational principle knowledge
about such matters will be of great benefit.
These remarks about the student, the sort of treatment to be
expected, and the purpose of the inquiry, may be taken as our
preface.
Book 1, Chapter 4
Let us resume our inquiry and state, in view of the fact that all
knowledge and every pursuit aims at some good, what it is that
we say political science aims at and what is the highest of all
goods achievable by action. Verbally there is very general
agreement; for both the general run of men and people of
superior refinement say that it is happiness, and identify living
well and doing well with being happy; but with regard to what
happiness is they differ, and the many do not give the same
account as the wise. For the former think it is some plain and
obvious thing, like pleasure, wealth, or honour; they differ,
however, from one another -- and often even the same man
identifies it with different things, with health when he is ill,
with wealth when he is poor; but, conscious of their ignorance,
they admire those who proclaim some great ideal that is above
their comprehension. Now some thought that apart from these
many goods there is another which is self-subsistent and causes
the goodness of all these as well. To examine all the opinions
that have been held were perhaps somewhat fruitless; enough to
examine those that are most prevalent or that seem to be
arguable.
Let us not fail to notice, however, that there is a difference
between arguments from and those to the first principles. For
Plato, too, was right in raising this question and asking, as he
used to do, 'are we on the way from or to the first principles?'
There is a difference, as there is in a race-course between the
course from the judges to the turning-point and the way back.
For, while we must begin with what is known, things are objects
of knowledge in two senses -- some to us, some without
qualification. Presumably, then, we must begin with things
known to us. Hence any one who is to listen intelligently to
lectures about what is noble and just, and generally, about the
subjects of political science must have been brought up in good
habits. For the fact is the starting-point, and if this is
sufficiently plain to him, he will not at the start need the reason
as well; and the man who has been well brought up has or can
easily get starting points. And as for him who neither has nor
can get them, let him hear the words of Hesiod:
Far best is he who knows all things himself;
Good, he that hearkens when men counsel right;
But he who neither knows, nor lays to heart
Another's wisdom, is a useless wight.
Book 1, Chapter 5
Let us, however, resume our discussion from the point at which
we digressed. To judge from the lives that men lead, most men,
and men of the most vulgar type, seem (not without some
ground) to identify the good, or happiness, with pleasure; which
is the reason why they love the life of enjoyment. For there are,
we may say, three prominent types of life -- that just mentioned,
the political, and thirdly the contemplative life. Now the mass
of mankind are evidently quite slavish in their tastes, preferring
a life suitable to beasts, but they get some ground for their view
from the fact that many of those in high places share the tastes
of Sardanapallus. A consideration of the prominent types of life
shows that people of superior refinement and of active
disposition identify happiness with honour; for this is, roughly
speaking, the end of the political life. But it seems too
superficial to be what we are looking for, since it is thought to
depend on those who bestow honour rather than on him who
receives it, but the good we divine to be something proper to a
man and not easily taken from him. Further, men seem to pursue
honour in order that they may be assured of their goodness; at
least it is by men of practical wisdom that they seek to be
honoured, and among those who know them, and on the ground
of their virtue; clearly, then, according to them, at any rate,
virtue is better. And perhaps one might even suppose this to be,
rather than honour, the end of the political life. But even this
appears somewhat incomplete; for possession of virtue seems
actually compatible with being asleep, or with lifelong
inactivity, and, further, with the greatest sufferings and
misfortunes; but a man who was living so no one would call
happy, unless he were maintaining a thesis at all costs. But
enough of this; for the subject has been sufficiently treated even
in the current discussions. Third comes the contemplative life,
which we shall consider later.
The life of money-making is one undertaken under compulsion,
and wealth is evidently not the good we are seeking; for it is
merely useful and for the sake of something else. And so one
might rather take the aforenamed objects to be ends; for they
are loved for themselves. But it is evident that not even these
are ends; yet many arguments have been thrown away in support
of them. Let us leave this subject, then.
Book 1, Chapter 6
We had perhaps better consider the universal good and discuss
thoroughly what is meant by it, although such an inquiry is
made an uphill one by the fact that the Forms have been
introduced by friends of our own. Yet it would perhaps be
thought to be better, indeed to be our duty, for the sake of
maintaining the truth even to destroy what touches us closely,
especially as we are philosophers or lovers of wisdom; for,
while both are dear, piety requires us to honour truth above our
friends.
The men who introduced this doctrine did not posit Ideas of
classes within which they recognized priority and posteriority
(which is the reason why they did not maintain the existence of
an Idea embracing all numbers); but the term 'good' is used both
in the category of substance and in that of quality and in that of
relation, and that which is per se, i.e. substance, is prior in
nature to the relative (for the latter is like an off shoot and
accident of being); so that there could not be a common Idea set
over all these goods. Further, since 'good' has as many senses as
'being' (for it is predicated both in the category of substance, as
of God and of reason, and in quality, i.e. of the virtues, and in
quantity, i.e. of that which is moderate, and in relation, i.e. of
the useful, and in time, i.e. of the right opportunity, and in
place, i.e. of the right locality and the like), clearly it cannot be
something universally present in all cases and single; for then it
could not have been predicated in all the categories but in one
only. Further, since of the things answering to one Idea there is
one science, there would have been one science of all the goods;
but as it is there are many sciences even of the things that fall
under one category, e.g. of opportunity, for opportunity in war
is studied by strategics and in disease by medicine, and the
moderate in food is studied by medicine and in exercise by the
science of gymnastics. And one might ask the question, what in
the world they mean by 'a thing itself', is (as is the case) in 'man
himself' and in a particular man the account of man is one and
the same. For in so far as they are man, they will in no respect
differ; and if this is so, neither will 'good itself' and particular
goods, in so far as they are good. But again it will not be good
any the more for being eternal, since that which lasts long is no
whiter than that which perishes in a day. The Pythagoreans
seem to give a more plausible account of the good, when they
place the one in the column of goods; and it is they that
Speusippus seems to have followed.
But let us discuss these matters elsewhere; an objection to what
we have said, however, may be discerned in the fact that the
Platonists have not been speaking about all goods, and that the
goods that are pursued and loved for themselves are called good
by reference to a single Form, while those which tend to
produce or to preserve these somehow or to prevent their
contraries are called so by reference to these, and in a
secondary sense. Clearly, then, goods must be spoken of in two
ways, and some must be good in themselves, the others by
reason of these. Let us separate, then, things good in themselves
from things useful, and consider whether the former are called
good by reference to a single Idea. What sort of goods would
one call good in themselves? Is it those that are pursued even
when isolated from others, such as intelligence, sight, and
certain pleasures and honours? Certainly, if we pursue these
also for the sake of something else, yet one would place them
among things good in themselves. Or is nothing other than the
Idea of good good in itself? In that case the Form will be empty.
But if the things we have named are also things good in
themselves, the account of the good will have to appear as
something identical in them all, as that of whiteness is identical
in snow and in white lead. But of honour, wisdom, and pleasure,
just in respect of their goodness, the accounts are distinct and
diverse. The good, therefore, is not some common element
answering to one Idea.
But what then do we mean by the good? It is surely not like the
things that only chance to have the same name. Are goods one,
then, by being derived from one good or by all contributing to
one good, or are they rather one by analogy? Certainly as sight
is in the body, so is reason in the soul, and so on in other cases.
But perhaps these subjects had better be dismissed for the
present; for perfect precision about them would be more
appropriate to another branch of philosophy. And similarly with
regard to the Idea; even if there is some one good which is
universally predicable of goods or is capable of separate and
independent existence, clearly it could not be achieved or
attained by man; but we are now seeking something attainable.
Perhaps, however, some one might think it worth while to
recognize this with a view to the goods that are attainable and
achievable; for having this as a sort of pattern we shall know
better the goods that are good for us, and if we know them shall
attain them. This argument has some plausibility, but seems to
clash with the procedure of the sciences; for all of these, though
they aim at some good and seek to supply the deficiency of it,
leave on one side the knowledge of the good. Yet that all the
exponents of the arts should be ignorant of, and should not even
seek, so great an aid is not probable. It is hard, too, to see how
a weaver or a carpenter will be benefited in regard to his own
craft by knowing this 'good itself', or how the man who has
viewed the Idea itself will be a better doctor or general thereby.
For a doctor seems not even to study health in this way, but the
health of man, or perhaps rather the health of a particular man;
it is individuals that he is healing. But enough of these topics.
Book 1, Chapter 7
Let us again return to the good we are seeking, and ask what it
can be. It seems different in different actions and arts; it is
different in medicine, in strategy, and in the other arts likewise.
What then is the good of each? Surely that for whose sake
everything else is done. In medicine this is health, in strategy
victory, in architecture a house, in any other sphere something
else, and in every action and pursuit the end; for it is for the
sake of this that all men do whatever else they do. Therefore, if
there is an end for all that we do, this will be the good
achievable by action, and if there are more than one, these will
be the goods achievable by action.
So the argument has by a different course reached the same
point; but we must try to state this even more clearly. Since
there are evidently more than one end, and we choose some of
these (e.g. wealth, flutes, and in general instruments) for the
sake of something else, clearly not all ends are final ends; but
the chief good is evidently something final. Therefore, if there
is only one final end, this will be what we are seeking, and if
there are more than one, the most final of these will be what we
are seeking. Now we call that which is in itself worthy of
pursuit more final than that which is worthy of pursuit for the
sake of something else, and that which is never desirable for the
sake of something else more final than the things that are
desirable both in themselves and for the sake of that other thing,
and therefore we call final without qualification that which is
always desirable in itself and never for the sake of something
else.
Now such a thing happiness, above all else, is held to be; for
this we choose always for self and never for the sake of
something else, but honour, pleasure, reason, and every virtue
we choose indeed for themselves (for if nothing resulted from
them we should still choose each of them), but we choose them
also for the sake of happiness, judging that by means of them
we shall be happy. Happiness, on the other hand, no one
chooses for the sake of these, nor, in general, for anything other
than itself.
From the point of view of self-sufficiency the same result seems
to follow; for the final good is thought to be self-sufficient.
Now by self-sufficient we do not mean that which is sufficient
for a man by himself, for one who lives a solitary life, but also
for parents, children, wife, and in general for his friends and
fellow citizens, since man is born for citizenship. But some
limit must be set to this; for if we extend our requirement to
ancestors and descendants and friends' friends we are in for an
infinite series. Let us examine this question, however, on
another occasion; the self-sufficient we now define as that
which when isolated makes life desirable and lacking in
nothing; and such we think happiness to be; and further we
think it most desirable of all things, without being counted as
one good thing among others -- if it were so counted it would
clearly be made more desirable by the addition of even the least
of goods; for that which is added becomes an excess of goods,
and of goods the greater is always more desirable. Happiness,
then, is something final and self-sufficient, and is the end of
action.
Presumably, however, to say that happiness is the chief good
seems a platitude, and a clearer account of what it is still
desired. This might perhaps be given, if we could first ascertain
the function of man. For just as for a flute-player, a sculptor, or
an artist, and, in general, for all things that have a function or
activity, the good and the 'well' is thought to reside in the
function, so would it seem to be for man, if he has a function.
Have the carpenter, then, and the tanner certain functions or
activities, and has man none? Is he born without a function? Or
as eye, hand, foot, and in general each of the parts evidently has
a function, may one lay it down that man similarly has a
function apart from all these? What then can this be? Life seems
to be common even to plants, but we are seeking what is
peculiar to man. Let us exclude, therefore, the life of nutrition
and growth. Next there would be a life of perception, but it also
seems to be common even to the horse, the ox, and every
animal. There remains, then, an active life of the element that
has a rational principle; of this, one part has such a principle in
the sense of being obedient to one, the other in the sense of
possessing one and exercising thought. And, as 'life of the
rational element' also has two meanings, we must state that life
in the sense of activity is what we mean; for this seems to be
the more proper sense of the term. Now if the function of man is
an activity of soul which follows or implies a rational principle,
and if we say 'so-and-so-and 'a good so-and-so' have a function
which is the same in kind, e.g. a lyre, and a good lyre-player,
and so without qualification in all cases, eminence in respect of
goodness being idded to the name of the function (for the
function of a lyre-player is to play the lyre, and that of a good
lyre-player is to do so well): if this is the case, and we state the
function of man to be a certain kind of life, and this to be an
activity or actions of the soul implying a rational principle, and
the function of a good man to be the good and noble
performance of these, and if any action is well performed when
it is performed in accordance with the appropriate excellence: if
this is the case, human good turns out to be activity of soul in
accordance with virtue, and if there are more than one virtue, in
accordance with the best and most complete.
But we must add 'in a complete life.' For one swallow does not
make a summer, nor does one day; and so too one day, or a
short time, does not make a man blessed and happy.
Let this serve as an outline of the good; for we must presumably
first sketch it roughly, and then later fill in the details. But it
would seem that any one is capable of carrying on and
articulating what has once been well outlined, and that time is a
good discoverer or partner in such a work; to which facts the
advances of the arts are due; for any one can add what is
lacking. And we must also remember what has been said before,
and not look for precision in all things alike, but in each class
of things such precision as accords with the subject-matter, and
so much as is appropriate to the inquiry. For a carpenter and a
geometer investigate the right angle in different ways; the
former does so in so far as the right angle is useful for his work,
while the latter inquires what it is or what sort of thing it is; for
he is a spectator of the truth. We must act in the same way,
then, in all other matters as well, that our main task may not be
subordinated to minor questions. Nor must we demand the cause
in all matters alike; it is enough in some cases that the fact be
well established, as in the case of the first principles; the fact is
the primary thing or first principle. Now of first principles we
see some by induction, some by perception, some by a certain
habituation, and others too in other ways. But each set of
principles we must try to investigate in the natural way, and we
must take pains to state them definitely, since they have a great
influence on what follows. For the beginning is thought to be
more than half of the whole, and many of the questions we ask
are cleared up by it.
Book 1, Chapter 8
We must consider it, however, in the light not only of our
conclusion and our premisses, but also of what is commonly
said about it; for with a true view all the data harmonize, but
with a false one the facts soon clash. Now goods have been
divided into three classes, and some are described as external,
others as relating to soul or to body; we call those that relate to
soul most properly and truly goods, and psychical actions and
activities we class as relating to soul. Therefore our account
must be sound, at least according to this view, which is an old
one and agreed on by philosophers. It is correct also in that we
identify the end with certain actions and activities; for thus it
falls among goods of the soul and not among external goods.
Another belief which harmonizes with our account is that the
happy man lives well and does well; for we have practically
defined happiness as a sort of good life and good action. The
characteristics that are looked for in happiness seem also, all of
them, to belong to what we have defined happiness as being.
For some identify happiness with virtue, some with practical
wisdom, others with a kind of philosophic wisdom, others with
these, or one of these, accompanied by pleasure or not without
pleasure; while others include also external prosperity. Now
some of these views have been held by many men and men of
old, others by a few eminent persons; and it is not probable that
either of these should be entirely mistaken, but rather that they
should be right in at least some one respect or even in most
respects.
With those who identify happiness with virtue or some one
virtue our account is in harmony; for to virtue belongs virtuous
activity. But it makes, perhaps, no small difference whether we
place the chief good in possession or in use, in state of mind or
in activity. For the state of mind may exist without producing
any good result, as in a man who is asleep or in some other way
quite inactive, but the activity cannot; for one who has the
activity will of necessity be acting, and acting well. And as in
the Olympic Games it is not the most beautiful and the strongest
that are crowned but those who compete (for it is some of these
that are victorious), so those who act win, and rightly win, the
noble and good things in life.
Their life is also in itself pleasant. For pleasure is a state of
soul, and to each man that which he is said to be a lover of is
pleasant; e.g. not only is a horse pleasant to the lover of horses,
and a spectacle to the lover of sights, but also in the same way
just acts are pleasant to the lover of justice and in general
virtuous acts to the lover of virtue. Now for most men their
pleasures are in conflict with one another because these are not
by nature pleasant, but the lovers of what is noble find pleasant
the things that are by nature pleasant; and virtuous actions are
such, so that these are pleasant for such men as well as in their
own nature. Their life, therefore, has no further need of pleasure
as a sort of adventitious charm, but has its pleasure in itself.
For, besides what we have said, the man who does not rejoice in
noble actions is not even good; since no one would call a man
just who did not enjoy acting justly, nor any man liberal who
did not enjoy liberal actions; and similarly in all other cases. If
this is so, virtuous actions must be in themselves pleasant. But
they are also good and noble, and have each of these attributes
in the highest degree, since the good man judges well about
these attributes; his judgement is such as we have described.
Happiness then is the best, noblest, and most pleasant thing in
the world, and these attributes are not severed as in the
inscription at Delos --
Most noble is that which is justest, and best is health;
But pleasantest is it to win what we love.
For all these properties belong to the best activities; and these,
or one -- the best -- of these, we identify with happiness.
Yet evidently, as we said, it needs the external goods as well;
for it is impossible, or not easy, to do noble acts without the
proper equipment. In many actions we use friends and riches
and political power as instruments; and there are some things
the lack of which takes the lustre from happiness, as good birth,
goodly children, beauty; for the man who is very ugly in
appearance or ill-born or solitary and childless is not very likely
to be happy, and perhaps a man would be still less likely if he
had thoroughly bad children or friends or had lost good children
or friends by death. As we said, then, happiness seems to need
this sort of prosperity in addition; for which reason some
identify happiness with good fortune, though others identify it
with virtue.
Book 1, Chapter 9
For this reason also the question is asked, whether happiness is
to be acquired by learning or by habituation or some other sort
of training, or comes in virtue of some divine providence or
again by chance. Now if there is any gift of the gods to men, it
is reasonable that happiness should be god-given, and most
surely god-given of all human things inasmuch as it is the best.
But this question would perhaps be more appropriate to another
inquiry; happiness seems, however, even if it is not god-sent but
comes as a result of virtue and some process of learning or
training, to be among the most godlike things; for that which is
the prize and end of virtue seems to be the best thing in the
world, and something godlike and blessed.
It will also on this view be very generally shared; for all who
are not maimed as regards their potentiality for virtue may win
it by a certain kind of study and care. But if it is better to be
happy thus than by chance, it is reasonable that the facts should
be so, since everything that depends on the action of nature is
by nature as good as it can be, and similarly everything that
depends on art or any rational cause, and especially if it
depends on the best of all causes. To entrust to chance what is
greatest and most noble would be a very defective arrangement.
The answer to the question we are asking is plain also from the
definition of happiness; for it has been said to be a virtuous
activity of soul, of a certain kind. Of the remaining goods, some
must necessarily pre-exist as conditions of happiness, and
others are naturally co-operative and useful as instruments. And
this will be found to agree with what we said at the outset; for
we stated the end of political science to be the best end, and
political science spends most of its pains on making the citizens
to be of a certain character, viz. good and capable of noble acts.
It is natural, then, that we call neither ox nor horse nor any
other of the animals happy; for none of them is capable of
sharing in such activity. For this reason also a boy is not happy;
for he is not yet capable of such acts, owing to his age; and
boys who are called happy are being congratulated by reason of
the hopes we have for them. For there is required, as we said,
not only complete virtue but also a complete life, since many
changes occur in life, and all manner of chances, and the most
prosperous may fall into great misfortunes in old age, as is told
of Priam in the Trojan Cycle; and one who has experienced such
chances and has ended wretchedly no one calls happy.
Book 1, Chapter 10
Must no one at all, then, be called happy while he lives; must
we, as Solon says, see the end? Even if we are to lay down this
doctrine, is it also the case that a man is happy when he is dead?
Or is not this quite absurd, especially for us who say that
happiness is an activity? But if we do not call the dead man
happy, and if Solon does not mean this, but that one can then
safely call a man blessed as being at last beyond evils and
misfortunes, this also affords matter for discussion; for both
evil and good are thought to exist for a dead man, as much as
for one who is alive but not aware of them; e.g. honours and
dishonours and the good or bad fortunes of children and in
general of descendants. And this also presents a problem; for
though a man has lived happily up to old age and has had a
death worthy of his life, many reverses may befall his
descendants -- some of them may be good and attain the life
they deserve, while with others the opposite may be the case;
and clearly too the degrees of relationship between them and
their ancestors may vary indefinitely. It would be odd, then, if
the dead man were to share in these changes and become at one
time happy, at another wretched; while it would also be odd if
the fortunes of the descendants did not for some time have some
effect on the happiness of their ancestors.
But we must return to our first difficulty; for perhaps by a
consideration of it our present problem might be solved. Now if
we must see the end and only then call a man happy, not as
being happy but as having been so before, surely this is a
paradox, that when he is happy the attribute that belongs to him
is not to be truly predicated of him because we do not wish to
call living men happy, on account of the changes that may
befall them, and because we have assumed happiness to be
something permanent and by no means easily changed, while a
single man may suffer many turns of fortune's wheel. For
clearly if we were to keep pace with his fortunes, we should
often call the same man happy and again wretched, making the
happy man out to be chameleon and insecurely based. Or is this
keeping pace with his fortunes quite wrong? Success or failure
in life does not depend on these, but human life, as we said,
needs these as mere additions, while virtuous activities or their
opposites are what constitute happiness or the reverse.
The question we have now discussed confirms our definition.
For no function of man has so much permanence as virtuous
activities (these are thought to be more durable even than
knowledge of the sciences), and of these themselves the most
valuable are more durable because those who are happy spend
their life most readily and most continuously in these; for this
seems to be the reason why we do not forget them. The attribute
in question, then, will belong to the happy man, and he will be
happy throughout his life; for always, or by preference to
everything else, he will be engaged in virtuous action and
contemplation, and he will bear the chances of life most nobly
and altogether decorously, if he is 'truly good' and 'foursquare
beyond reproach'.
Now many events happen by chance, and events differing in
importance; small pieces of good fortune or of its opposite
clearly do not weigh down the scales of life one way or the
other, but a multitude of great events if they turn out well will
make life happier (for not only are they themselves such as to
add beauty to life, but the way a man deals with them may be
noble and good), while if they turn out ill they crush and maim
happiness; for they both bring pain with them and hinder many
activities. Yet even in these nobility shines through, when a
man bears with resignation many great misfortunes, not through
insensibility to pain but through nobility and greatness of soul.
If activities are, as we said, what gives life its character, no
happy man can become miserable; for he will never do the acts
that are hateful and mean. For the man who is truly good and
wise, we think, bears all the chances life becomingly and
always makes the best of circumstances, as a good general
makes the best military use of the army at his command and a
good shoemaker makes the best shoes out of the hides that are
given him; and so with all other craftsmen. And if this is the
case, the happy man can never become miserable; though he
will not reach blessedness, if he meet with fortunes like those of
Priam.
Nor, again, is he many-coloured and changeable; for neither
will he be moved from his happy state easily or by any ordinary
misadventures, but only by many great ones, nor, if he has had
many great misadventures, will he recover his happiness in a
short time, but if at all, only in a long and complete one in
which he has attained many splendid successes.
When then should we not say that he is happy who is active in
accordance with complete virtue and is sufficiently equipped
with external goods, not for some chance period but throughout
a complete life? Or must we add 'and who is destined to live
thus and die as befits his life'? Certainly the future is obscure to
us, while happiness, we claim, is an end and something in every
way final. If so, we shall call happy those among living men in
whom these conditions are, and are to be, fulfilled -- but happy
men. So much for these questions.
Book 1, Chapter 11
That the fortunes of descendants and of all a man's friends
should not affect his happiness at all seems a very unfriendly
doctrine, and one opposed to the opinions men hold; but since
the events that happen are numerous and admit of all sorts of
difference, and some come more near to us and others less so, it
seems a long -- nay, an infinite -- task to discuss each in detail;
a general outline will perhaps suffice. If, then, as some of a
man's own misadventures have a certain weight and influence
on life while others are, as it were, lighter, so too there are
differences among the misadventures of our friends taken as a
whole, and it makes a difference whether the various suffering
befall the living or the dead (much more even than whether
lawless and terrible deeds are presupposed in a tragedy or done
on the stage), this difference also must be taken into account; or
rather, perhaps, the fact that doubt is felt whether the dead
share in any good or evil. For it seems, from these
considerations, that even if anything whether good or evil
penetrates to them, it must be something weak and negligible,
either in itself or for them, or if not, at least it must be such in
degree and kind as not to make happy those who are not happy
nor to take away their blessedness from those who are. The
good or bad fortunes of friends, then, seem to have some effects
on the dead, but effects of such a kind and degree as neither to
make the happy unhappy nor to produce any other change of the
kind.
Book 1, Chapter 12
These questions having been definitely answered, let us
consider whether happiness is among the things that are praised
or rather among the things that are prized; for clearly it is not to
be placed among potentialities. Everything that is praised seems
to be praised because it is of a certain kind and is related
somehow to something else; for we praise the just or brave man
and in general both the good man and virtue itself because of
the actions and functions involved, and we praise the strong
man, the good runner, and so on, because he is of a certain kind
and is related in a certain way to something good and important.
This is clear also from the praises of the gods; for it seems
absurd that the gods should be referred to our standard, but this
is done because praise involves a reference, to something else.
But if if praise is for things such as we have described, clearly
what applies to the best things is not praise, but something
greater and better, as is indeed obvious; for what we do to the
gods and the most godlike of men is to call them blessed and
happy. And so too with good things; no one praises happiness as
he does justice, but rather calls it blessed, as being something
more divine and better.
Eudoxus also seems to have been right in his method of
advocating the supremacy of pleasure; he thought that the fact
that, though a good, it is not praised indicated it to be better
than the things that are praised, and that this is what God and
the good are; for by reference to these all other things are
judged. Praise is appropriate to virtue, for as a result of virtue
men tend to do noble deeds, but encomia are bestowed on acts,
whether of the body or of the soul. But perhaps nicety in these
matters is more proper to those who have made a study of
encomia; to us it is clear from what has been said that happiness
is among the things that are prized and perfect. It seems to be so
also from the fact that it is a first principle; for it is for the sake
of this that we all do all that we do, and the first principle and
cause of goods is, we claim, something prized and divine.
Book 1, Chapter 13
Since happiness is an activity of soul in accordance with perfect
virtue, we must consider the nature of virtue; for perhaps we
shall thus see better the nature of happiness. The true student of
politics, too, is thought to have studied virtue above all things;
for he wishes to make his fellow citizens good and obedient to
the laws. As an example of this we have the lawgivers of the
Cretans and the Spartans, and any others of the kind that there
may have been. And if this inquiry belongs to political science,
clearly the pursuit of it will be in accordance with our original
plan. But clearly the virtue we must study is human virtue; for
the good we were seeking was human good and the happiness
human happiness. By human virtue we mean not that of the
body but that of the soul; and happiness also we call an activity
of soul. But if this is so, clearly the student of politics must
know somehow the facts about soul, as the man who is to heal
the eyes or the body as a whole must know about the eyes or the
body; and all the more since politics is more prized and better
than medicine; but even among doctors the best educated spend
much labour on acquiring knowledge of the body. The student
of politics, then, must study the soul, and must study it with
these objects in view, and do so just to the extent which is
sufficient for the questions we are discussing; for further
precision is perhaps something more laborious than our
purposes require.
Some things are said about it, adequately enough, even in the
discussions outside our school, and we must use these; e.g. that
one element in the soul is irrational and one has a rational
principle. Whether these are separated as the parts of the body
or of anything divisible are, or are distinct by definition but by
nature inseparable, like convex and concave in the
circumference of a circle, does not affect the present question.
Of the irrational element one division seems to be widely
distributed, and vegetative in its nature, I mean that which
causes nutrition and growth; for it is this kind of power of the
soul that one must assign to all nurslings and to embryos, and
this same power to fullgrown creatures; this is more reasonable
than to assign some different power to them. Now the
excellence of this seems to be common to all species and not
specifically human; for this part or faculty seems to function
most in sleep, while goodness and badness are least manifest in
sleep (whence comes the saying that the happy are not better off
than the wretched for half their lives; and this happens naturally
enough, since sleep is an inactivity of the soul in that respect in
which it is called good or bad), unless perhaps to a small extent
some of the movements actually penetrate to the soul, and in
this respect the dreams of good men are better than those of
ordinary people. Enough of this subject, however; let us leave
the nutritive faculty alone, since it has by its nature no share in
human excellence.
There seems to be also another irrational element in the soul --
one which in a sense, however, shares in a rational principle.
For we praise the rational principle of the continent man and of
the incontinent, and the part of their soul that has such a
principle, since it urges them aright and towards the best
objects; but there is found in them also another element
naturally opposed to the rational principle, which fights against
and resists that principle. For exactly as paralysed limbs when
we intend to move them to the right turn on the contrary to the
left, so is it with the soul; the impulses of incontinent people
move in contrary directions. But while in the body we see that
which moves astray, in the soul we do not. No doubt, however,
we must none the less suppose that in the soul too there is
something contrary to the rational principle, resisting and
opposing it. In what sense it is distinct from the other elements
does not concern us. Now even this seems to have a share in a
rational principle, as we said; at any rate in the continent man it
obeys the rational principle and presumably in the temperate
and brave man it is still more obedient; for in him it speaks, on
all matters, with the same voice as the rational principle.
Therefore the irrational element also appears to be two-fold. For
the vegetative element in no way shares in a rational principle,
but the appetitive and in general the desiring element in a sense
shares in it, in so far as it listens to and obeys it; this is the
sense in which we speak of 'taking account' of one's father or
one's friends, not that in which we speak of 'accounting for a
mathematical property. That the irrational element is in some
sense persuaded by a rational principle is indicated also by the
giving of advice and by all reproof and exhortation. And if this
element also must be said to have a rational principle, that
which has a rational principle (as well as that which has not)
will be twofold, one subdivision having it in the strict sense and
in itself, and the other having a tendency to obey as one does
one's father.
Virtue too is distinguished into kinds in accordance with this
difference; for we say that some of the virtues are intellectual
and others moral, philosophic wisdom and understanding and
practical wisdom being intellectual, liberality and temperance
moral. For in speaking about a man's character we do not say
that he is wise or has understanding but that he is good-
tempered or temperate; yet we praise the wise man also with
respect to his state of mind; and of states of mind we call those
which merit praise virtues.
Next BookContents

More Related Content

Similar to THE ANTICHRIST BY NIETZSCHE

Jesus was victorious
Jesus was victoriousJesus was victorious
Jesus was victoriousGLENN PEASE
 
Discourse on Colonialism Aimé Césaire Translated b.docx
Discourse on Colonialism  Aimé Césaire  Translated b.docxDiscourse on Colonialism  Aimé Césaire  Translated b.docx
Discourse on Colonialism Aimé Césaire Translated b.docxlynettearnold46882
 
G Existentialism Introduction.ppt
G Existentialism Introduction.pptG Existentialism Introduction.ppt
G Existentialism Introduction.pptJojamesGaddi1
 
Jesus was concerned that none be lost
Jesus was concerned that none be lostJesus was concerned that none be lost
Jesus was concerned that none be lostGLENN PEASE
 
The Grail Message - Volume 1, Lecture 4 - Morality
The Grail Message - Volume 1, Lecture 4 - Morality The Grail Message - Volume 1, Lecture 4 - Morality
The Grail Message - Volume 1, Lecture 4 - Morality The Grail Movement
 
23692564 rollo-may-tthe-courage-to-create
23692564 rollo-may-tthe-courage-to-create23692564 rollo-may-tthe-courage-to-create
23692564 rollo-may-tthe-courage-to-createnoogle1996
 
Hidden Messages Revealed Charles Darwin'
Hidden Messages Revealed Charles Darwin'Hidden Messages Revealed Charles Darwin'
Hidden Messages Revealed Charles Darwin'Steven Camilleri
 
6.2 My GuiltMy Guiltby Maya AngelouMy guilt is slavery’s .docx
6.2 My GuiltMy Guiltby Maya AngelouMy guilt is slavery’s .docx6.2 My GuiltMy Guiltby Maya AngelouMy guilt is slavery’s .docx
6.2 My GuiltMy Guiltby Maya AngelouMy guilt is slavery’s .docxblondellchancy
 
What We Have to Lose Theodore Dalrymple Whenever we le.docx
What We Have to Lose Theodore Dalrymple Whenever we le.docxWhat We Have to Lose Theodore Dalrymple Whenever we le.docx
What We Have to Lose Theodore Dalrymple Whenever we le.docxmecklenburgstrelitzh
 
Narrative of the Life ofFrederick Douglass, An America.docx
Narrative of the Life ofFrederick Douglass, An America.docxNarrative of the Life ofFrederick Douglass, An America.docx
Narrative of the Life ofFrederick Douglass, An America.docxvannagoforth
 
Jesus was truth and freedom
Jesus was truth and freedomJesus was truth and freedom
Jesus was truth and freedomGLENN PEASE
 
Slave and Master Morality
Slave and Master Morality Slave and Master Morality
Slave and Master Morality KevinLimsky
 
Scapegoat theory & Christianity
Scapegoat theory & ChristianityScapegoat theory & Christianity
Scapegoat theory & Christianitypindleton
 
Illustrations, humor, poetry and quotations vol 6
Illustrations, humor, poetry and quotations vol 6Illustrations, humor, poetry and quotations vol 6
Illustrations, humor, poetry and quotations vol 6GLENN PEASE
 
Turn of the Century Intellectual Trends.ppt
Turn of the Century Intellectual Trends.pptTurn of the Century Intellectual Trends.ppt
Turn of the Century Intellectual Trends.pptHamzaHasan43
 

Similar to THE ANTICHRIST BY NIETZSCHE (20)

Jesus was victorious
Jesus was victoriousJesus was victorious
Jesus was victorious
 
Discourse on Colonialism Aimé Césaire Translated b.docx
Discourse on Colonialism  Aimé Césaire  Translated b.docxDiscourse on Colonialism  Aimé Césaire  Translated b.docx
Discourse on Colonialism Aimé Césaire Translated b.docx
 
G Existentialism Introduction.ppt
G Existentialism Introduction.pptG Existentialism Introduction.ppt
G Existentialism Introduction.ppt
 
Jesus was concerned that none be lost
Jesus was concerned that none be lostJesus was concerned that none be lost
Jesus was concerned that none be lost
 
Frederick Douglass
Frederick DouglassFrederick Douglass
Frederick Douglass
 
Iowa 2 historical
Iowa 2 historicalIowa 2 historical
Iowa 2 historical
 
The Grail Message - Volume 1, Lecture 4 - Morality
The Grail Message - Volume 1, Lecture 4 - Morality The Grail Message - Volume 1, Lecture 4 - Morality
The Grail Message - Volume 1, Lecture 4 - Morality
 
23692564 rollo-may-tthe-courage-to-create
23692564 rollo-may-tthe-courage-to-create23692564 rollo-may-tthe-courage-to-create
23692564 rollo-may-tthe-courage-to-create
 
Hidden Messages Revealed Charles Darwin'
Hidden Messages Revealed Charles Darwin'Hidden Messages Revealed Charles Darwin'
Hidden Messages Revealed Charles Darwin'
 
6.2 My GuiltMy Guiltby Maya AngelouMy guilt is slavery’s .docx
6.2 My GuiltMy Guiltby Maya AngelouMy guilt is slavery’s .docx6.2 My GuiltMy Guiltby Maya AngelouMy guilt is slavery’s .docx
6.2 My GuiltMy Guiltby Maya AngelouMy guilt is slavery’s .docx
 
What We Have to Lose Theodore Dalrymple Whenever we le.docx
What We Have to Lose Theodore Dalrymple Whenever we le.docxWhat We Have to Lose Theodore Dalrymple Whenever we le.docx
What We Have to Lose Theodore Dalrymple Whenever we le.docx
 
Narrative of the Life ofFrederick Douglass, An America.docx
Narrative of the Life ofFrederick Douglass, An America.docxNarrative of the Life ofFrederick Douglass, An America.docx
Narrative of the Life ofFrederick Douglass, An America.docx
 
Jesus was truth and freedom
Jesus was truth and freedomJesus was truth and freedom
Jesus was truth and freedom
 
Slave and Master Morality
Slave and Master Morality Slave and Master Morality
Slave and Master Morality
 
Horror6
Horror6Horror6
Horror6
 
From self reliance
From self relianceFrom self reliance
From self reliance
 
From self reliance
From self relianceFrom self reliance
From self reliance
 
Scapegoat theory & Christianity
Scapegoat theory & ChristianityScapegoat theory & Christianity
Scapegoat theory & Christianity
 
Illustrations, humor, poetry and quotations vol 6
Illustrations, humor, poetry and quotations vol 6Illustrations, humor, poetry and quotations vol 6
Illustrations, humor, poetry and quotations vol 6
 
Turn of the Century Intellectual Trends.ppt
Turn of the Century Intellectual Trends.pptTurn of the Century Intellectual Trends.ppt
Turn of the Century Intellectual Trends.ppt
 

More from mehek4

Accident Up Ahead!Listen to this text being read aloud by a hu.docx
Accident Up Ahead!Listen to this text being read aloud by a hu.docxAccident Up Ahead!Listen to this text being read aloud by a hu.docx
Accident Up Ahead!Listen to this text being read aloud by a hu.docxmehek4
 
Access the annual report provided in Course Materials to complete .docx
Access the annual report provided in Course Materials to complete .docxAccess the annual report provided in Course Materials to complete .docx
Access the annual report provided in Course Materials to complete .docxmehek4
 
Access the Internet to acquire a copy of the most recent annual re.docx
Access the Internet to acquire a copy of the most recent annual re.docxAccess the Internet to acquire a copy of the most recent annual re.docx
Access the Internet to acquire a copy of the most recent annual re.docxmehek4
 
Acc 290 Final Exam MCQs) Which financial statement is used to de.docx
Acc 290 Final Exam MCQs) Which financial statement is used to de.docxAcc 290 Final Exam MCQs) Which financial statement is used to de.docx
Acc 290 Final Exam MCQs) Which financial statement is used to de.docxmehek4
 
AC2760Week 2 Assignment.docx
AC2760Week 2 Assignment.docxAC2760Week 2 Assignment.docx
AC2760Week 2 Assignment.docxmehek4
 
AC1220 Lab 5.1IntroductionJake determines that owning the .docx
AC1220 Lab 5.1IntroductionJake determines that owning the .docxAC1220 Lab 5.1IntroductionJake determines that owning the .docx
AC1220 Lab 5.1IntroductionJake determines that owning the .docxmehek4
 
Abstract(Provide the main generalizable statement resulting .docx
Abstract(Provide the main generalizable statement resulting .docxAbstract(Provide the main generalizable statement resulting .docx
Abstract(Provide the main generalizable statement resulting .docxmehek4
 
Abusive relationships are at the core of the Coetzee novel, whether .docx
Abusive relationships are at the core of the Coetzee novel, whether .docxAbusive relationships are at the core of the Coetzee novel, whether .docx
Abusive relationships are at the core of the Coetzee novel, whether .docxmehek4
 
Abraham, J., Sick, B., Anderson, J., Berg, A., Dehmer, C., & Tufano,.docx
Abraham, J., Sick, B., Anderson, J., Berg, A., Dehmer, C., & Tufano,.docxAbraham, J., Sick, B., Anderson, J., Berg, A., Dehmer, C., & Tufano,.docx
Abraham, J., Sick, B., Anderson, J., Berg, A., Dehmer, C., & Tufano,.docxmehek4
 
Abraham, J., Sick, B., Anderson, J., Berg, A., Dehmer, C., & Tufan.docx
Abraham, J., Sick, B., Anderson, J., Berg, A., Dehmer, C., & Tufan.docxAbraham, J., Sick, B., Anderson, J., Berg, A., Dehmer, C., & Tufan.docx
Abraham, J., Sick, B., Anderson, J., Berg, A., Dehmer, C., & Tufan.docxmehek4
 
A.Da la correcta conjugación para cada oración.(Give the corre.docx
A.Da la correcta conjugación para cada oración.(Give the corre.docxA.Da la correcta conjugación para cada oración.(Give the corre.docx
A.Da la correcta conjugación para cada oración.(Give the corre.docxmehek4
 
Abraham Lincoln is considered by many historians to be the greatest .docx
Abraham Lincoln is considered by many historians to be the greatest .docxAbraham Lincoln is considered by many historians to be the greatest .docx
Abraham Lincoln is considered by many historians to be the greatest .docxmehek4
 
About half of the paid lobbyists in Washington are former government.docx
About half of the paid lobbyists in Washington are former government.docxAbout half of the paid lobbyists in Washington are former government.docx
About half of the paid lobbyists in Washington are former government.docxmehek4
 
ABC sells 400 shares of its $23 par common stock for $27. The entry .docx
ABC sells 400 shares of its $23 par common stock for $27. The entry .docxABC sells 400 shares of its $23 par common stock for $27. The entry .docx
ABC sells 400 shares of its $23 par common stock for $27. The entry .docxmehek4
 
ABC company is increasing its equity by selling additional shares to.docx
ABC company is increasing its equity by selling additional shares to.docxABC company is increasing its equity by selling additional shares to.docx
ABC company is increasing its equity by selling additional shares to.docxmehek4
 
A.The unification of previously fractious and divided Arab tribes.docx
A.The unification of previously fractious and divided Arab tribes.docxA.The unification of previously fractious and divided Arab tribes.docx
A.The unification of previously fractious and divided Arab tribes.docxmehek4
 
A.Escribe la forma correcta del verbo en españolNosotros siem.docx
A.Escribe la forma correcta del verbo en españolNosotros siem.docxA.Escribe la forma correcta del verbo en españolNosotros siem.docx
A.Escribe la forma correcta del verbo en españolNosotros siem.docxmehek4
 
A.Both countries fought for independence from Great Britain, b.docx
A.Both countries fought for independence from Great Britain, b.docxA.Both countries fought for independence from Great Britain, b.docx
A.Both countries fought for independence from Great Britain, b.docxmehek4
 
a.A patent purchased from J. Miller on January 1, 2010, for a ca.docx
a.A patent purchased from J. Miller on January 1, 2010, for a ca.docxa.A patent purchased from J. Miller on January 1, 2010, for a ca.docx
a.A patent purchased from J. Miller on January 1, 2010, for a ca.docxmehek4
 
A.) Imagine that astronomers have discovered intelligent life in a n.docx
A.) Imagine that astronomers have discovered intelligent life in a n.docxA.) Imagine that astronomers have discovered intelligent life in a n.docx
A.) Imagine that astronomers have discovered intelligent life in a n.docxmehek4
 

More from mehek4 (20)

Accident Up Ahead!Listen to this text being read aloud by a hu.docx
Accident Up Ahead!Listen to this text being read aloud by a hu.docxAccident Up Ahead!Listen to this text being read aloud by a hu.docx
Accident Up Ahead!Listen to this text being read aloud by a hu.docx
 
Access the annual report provided in Course Materials to complete .docx
Access the annual report provided in Course Materials to complete .docxAccess the annual report provided in Course Materials to complete .docx
Access the annual report provided in Course Materials to complete .docx
 
Access the Internet to acquire a copy of the most recent annual re.docx
Access the Internet to acquire a copy of the most recent annual re.docxAccess the Internet to acquire a copy of the most recent annual re.docx
Access the Internet to acquire a copy of the most recent annual re.docx
 
Acc 290 Final Exam MCQs) Which financial statement is used to de.docx
Acc 290 Final Exam MCQs) Which financial statement is used to de.docxAcc 290 Final Exam MCQs) Which financial statement is used to de.docx
Acc 290 Final Exam MCQs) Which financial statement is used to de.docx
 
AC2760Week 2 Assignment.docx
AC2760Week 2 Assignment.docxAC2760Week 2 Assignment.docx
AC2760Week 2 Assignment.docx
 
AC1220 Lab 5.1IntroductionJake determines that owning the .docx
AC1220 Lab 5.1IntroductionJake determines that owning the .docxAC1220 Lab 5.1IntroductionJake determines that owning the .docx
AC1220 Lab 5.1IntroductionJake determines that owning the .docx
 
Abstract(Provide the main generalizable statement resulting .docx
Abstract(Provide the main generalizable statement resulting .docxAbstract(Provide the main generalizable statement resulting .docx
Abstract(Provide the main generalizable statement resulting .docx
 
Abusive relationships are at the core of the Coetzee novel, whether .docx
Abusive relationships are at the core of the Coetzee novel, whether .docxAbusive relationships are at the core of the Coetzee novel, whether .docx
Abusive relationships are at the core of the Coetzee novel, whether .docx
 
Abraham, J., Sick, B., Anderson, J., Berg, A., Dehmer, C., & Tufano,.docx
Abraham, J., Sick, B., Anderson, J., Berg, A., Dehmer, C., & Tufano,.docxAbraham, J., Sick, B., Anderson, J., Berg, A., Dehmer, C., & Tufano,.docx
Abraham, J., Sick, B., Anderson, J., Berg, A., Dehmer, C., & Tufano,.docx
 
Abraham, J., Sick, B., Anderson, J., Berg, A., Dehmer, C., & Tufan.docx
Abraham, J., Sick, B., Anderson, J., Berg, A., Dehmer, C., & Tufan.docxAbraham, J., Sick, B., Anderson, J., Berg, A., Dehmer, C., & Tufan.docx
Abraham, J., Sick, B., Anderson, J., Berg, A., Dehmer, C., & Tufan.docx
 
A.Da la correcta conjugación para cada oración.(Give the corre.docx
A.Da la correcta conjugación para cada oración.(Give the corre.docxA.Da la correcta conjugación para cada oración.(Give the corre.docx
A.Da la correcta conjugación para cada oración.(Give the corre.docx
 
Abraham Lincoln is considered by many historians to be the greatest .docx
Abraham Lincoln is considered by many historians to be the greatest .docxAbraham Lincoln is considered by many historians to be the greatest .docx
Abraham Lincoln is considered by many historians to be the greatest .docx
 
About half of the paid lobbyists in Washington are former government.docx
About half of the paid lobbyists in Washington are former government.docxAbout half of the paid lobbyists in Washington are former government.docx
About half of the paid lobbyists in Washington are former government.docx
 
ABC sells 400 shares of its $23 par common stock for $27. The entry .docx
ABC sells 400 shares of its $23 par common stock for $27. The entry .docxABC sells 400 shares of its $23 par common stock for $27. The entry .docx
ABC sells 400 shares of its $23 par common stock for $27. The entry .docx
 
ABC company is increasing its equity by selling additional shares to.docx
ABC company is increasing its equity by selling additional shares to.docxABC company is increasing its equity by selling additional shares to.docx
ABC company is increasing its equity by selling additional shares to.docx
 
A.The unification of previously fractious and divided Arab tribes.docx
A.The unification of previously fractious and divided Arab tribes.docxA.The unification of previously fractious and divided Arab tribes.docx
A.The unification of previously fractious and divided Arab tribes.docx
 
A.Escribe la forma correcta del verbo en españolNosotros siem.docx
A.Escribe la forma correcta del verbo en españolNosotros siem.docxA.Escribe la forma correcta del verbo en españolNosotros siem.docx
A.Escribe la forma correcta del verbo en españolNosotros siem.docx
 
A.Both countries fought for independence from Great Britain, b.docx
A.Both countries fought for independence from Great Britain, b.docxA.Both countries fought for independence from Great Britain, b.docx
A.Both countries fought for independence from Great Britain, b.docx
 
a.A patent purchased from J. Miller on January 1, 2010, for a ca.docx
a.A patent purchased from J. Miller on January 1, 2010, for a ca.docxa.A patent purchased from J. Miller on January 1, 2010, for a ca.docx
a.A patent purchased from J. Miller on January 1, 2010, for a ca.docx
 
A.) Imagine that astronomers have discovered intelligent life in a n.docx
A.) Imagine that astronomers have discovered intelligent life in a n.docxA.) Imagine that astronomers have discovered intelligent life in a n.docx
A.) Imagine that astronomers have discovered intelligent life in a n.docx
 

Recently uploaded

Blooming Together_ Growing a Community Garden Worksheet.docx
Blooming Together_ Growing a Community Garden Worksheet.docxBlooming Together_ Growing a Community Garden Worksheet.docx
Blooming Together_ Growing a Community Garden Worksheet.docxUnboundStockton
 
Gas measurement O2,Co2,& ph) 04/2024.pptx
Gas measurement O2,Co2,& ph) 04/2024.pptxGas measurement O2,Co2,& ph) 04/2024.pptx
Gas measurement O2,Co2,& ph) 04/2024.pptxDr.Ibrahim Hassaan
 
Earth Day Presentation wow hello nice great
Earth Day Presentation wow hello nice greatEarth Day Presentation wow hello nice great
Earth Day Presentation wow hello nice greatYousafMalik24
 
Capitol Tech U Doctoral Presentation - April 2024.pptx
Capitol Tech U Doctoral Presentation - April 2024.pptxCapitol Tech U Doctoral Presentation - April 2024.pptx
Capitol Tech U Doctoral Presentation - April 2024.pptxCapitolTechU
 
MICROBIOLOGY biochemical test detailed.pptx
MICROBIOLOGY biochemical test detailed.pptxMICROBIOLOGY biochemical test detailed.pptx
MICROBIOLOGY biochemical test detailed.pptxabhijeetpadhi001
 
Like-prefer-love -hate+verb+ing & silent letters & citizenship text.pdf
Like-prefer-love -hate+verb+ing & silent letters & citizenship text.pdfLike-prefer-love -hate+verb+ing & silent letters & citizenship text.pdf
Like-prefer-love -hate+verb+ing & silent letters & citizenship text.pdfMr Bounab Samir
 
Hierarchy of management that covers different levels of management
Hierarchy of management that covers different levels of managementHierarchy of management that covers different levels of management
Hierarchy of management that covers different levels of managementmkooblal
 
MARGINALIZATION (Different learners in Marginalized Group
MARGINALIZATION (Different learners in Marginalized GroupMARGINALIZATION (Different learners in Marginalized Group
MARGINALIZATION (Different learners in Marginalized GroupJonathanParaisoCruz
 
CELL CYCLE Division Science 8 quarter IV.pptx
CELL CYCLE Division Science 8 quarter IV.pptxCELL CYCLE Division Science 8 quarter IV.pptx
CELL CYCLE Division Science 8 quarter IV.pptxJiesonDelaCerna
 
Types of Journalistic Writing Grade 8.pptx
Types of Journalistic Writing Grade 8.pptxTypes of Journalistic Writing Grade 8.pptx
Types of Journalistic Writing Grade 8.pptxEyham Joco
 
Difference Between Search & Browse Methods in Odoo 17
Difference Between Search & Browse Methods in Odoo 17Difference Between Search & Browse Methods in Odoo 17
Difference Between Search & Browse Methods in Odoo 17Celine George
 
Employee wellbeing at the workplace.pptx
Employee wellbeing at the workplace.pptxEmployee wellbeing at the workplace.pptx
Employee wellbeing at the workplace.pptxNirmalaLoungPoorunde1
 
How to Configure Email Server in Odoo 17
How to Configure Email Server in Odoo 17How to Configure Email Server in Odoo 17
How to Configure Email Server in Odoo 17Celine George
 
Painted Grey Ware.pptx, PGW Culture of India
Painted Grey Ware.pptx, PGW Culture of IndiaPainted Grey Ware.pptx, PGW Culture of India
Painted Grey Ware.pptx, PGW Culture of IndiaVirag Sontakke
 
Historical philosophical, theoretical, and legal foundations of special and i...
Historical philosophical, theoretical, and legal foundations of special and i...Historical philosophical, theoretical, and legal foundations of special and i...
Historical philosophical, theoretical, and legal foundations of special and i...jaredbarbolino94
 
ECONOMIC CONTEXT - PAPER 1 Q3: NEWSPAPERS.pptx
ECONOMIC CONTEXT - PAPER 1 Q3: NEWSPAPERS.pptxECONOMIC CONTEXT - PAPER 1 Q3: NEWSPAPERS.pptx
ECONOMIC CONTEXT - PAPER 1 Q3: NEWSPAPERS.pptxiammrhaywood
 
ENGLISH 7_Q4_LESSON 2_ Employing a Variety of Strategies for Effective Interp...
ENGLISH 7_Q4_LESSON 2_ Employing a Variety of Strategies for Effective Interp...ENGLISH 7_Q4_LESSON 2_ Employing a Variety of Strategies for Effective Interp...
ENGLISH 7_Q4_LESSON 2_ Employing a Variety of Strategies for Effective Interp...JhezDiaz1
 

Recently uploaded (20)

Blooming Together_ Growing a Community Garden Worksheet.docx
Blooming Together_ Growing a Community Garden Worksheet.docxBlooming Together_ Growing a Community Garden Worksheet.docx
Blooming Together_ Growing a Community Garden Worksheet.docx
 
Gas measurement O2,Co2,& ph) 04/2024.pptx
Gas measurement O2,Co2,& ph) 04/2024.pptxGas measurement O2,Co2,& ph) 04/2024.pptx
Gas measurement O2,Co2,& ph) 04/2024.pptx
 
Earth Day Presentation wow hello nice great
Earth Day Presentation wow hello nice greatEarth Day Presentation wow hello nice great
Earth Day Presentation wow hello nice great
 
Capitol Tech U Doctoral Presentation - April 2024.pptx
Capitol Tech U Doctoral Presentation - April 2024.pptxCapitol Tech U Doctoral Presentation - April 2024.pptx
Capitol Tech U Doctoral Presentation - April 2024.pptx
 
Model Call Girl in Tilak Nagar Delhi reach out to us at 🔝9953056974🔝
Model Call Girl in Tilak Nagar Delhi reach out to us at 🔝9953056974🔝Model Call Girl in Tilak Nagar Delhi reach out to us at 🔝9953056974🔝
Model Call Girl in Tilak Nagar Delhi reach out to us at 🔝9953056974🔝
 
MICROBIOLOGY biochemical test detailed.pptx
MICROBIOLOGY biochemical test detailed.pptxMICROBIOLOGY biochemical test detailed.pptx
MICROBIOLOGY biochemical test detailed.pptx
 
Like-prefer-love -hate+verb+ing & silent letters & citizenship text.pdf
Like-prefer-love -hate+verb+ing & silent letters & citizenship text.pdfLike-prefer-love -hate+verb+ing & silent letters & citizenship text.pdf
Like-prefer-love -hate+verb+ing & silent letters & citizenship text.pdf
 
9953330565 Low Rate Call Girls In Rohini Delhi NCR
9953330565 Low Rate Call Girls In Rohini  Delhi NCR9953330565 Low Rate Call Girls In Rohini  Delhi NCR
9953330565 Low Rate Call Girls In Rohini Delhi NCR
 
Hierarchy of management that covers different levels of management
Hierarchy of management that covers different levels of managementHierarchy of management that covers different levels of management
Hierarchy of management that covers different levels of management
 
MARGINALIZATION (Different learners in Marginalized Group
MARGINALIZATION (Different learners in Marginalized GroupMARGINALIZATION (Different learners in Marginalized Group
MARGINALIZATION (Different learners in Marginalized Group
 
CELL CYCLE Division Science 8 quarter IV.pptx
CELL CYCLE Division Science 8 quarter IV.pptxCELL CYCLE Division Science 8 quarter IV.pptx
CELL CYCLE Division Science 8 quarter IV.pptx
 
Types of Journalistic Writing Grade 8.pptx
Types of Journalistic Writing Grade 8.pptxTypes of Journalistic Writing Grade 8.pptx
Types of Journalistic Writing Grade 8.pptx
 
Difference Between Search & Browse Methods in Odoo 17
Difference Between Search & Browse Methods in Odoo 17Difference Between Search & Browse Methods in Odoo 17
Difference Between Search & Browse Methods in Odoo 17
 
Employee wellbeing at the workplace.pptx
Employee wellbeing at the workplace.pptxEmployee wellbeing at the workplace.pptx
Employee wellbeing at the workplace.pptx
 
How to Configure Email Server in Odoo 17
How to Configure Email Server in Odoo 17How to Configure Email Server in Odoo 17
How to Configure Email Server in Odoo 17
 
Painted Grey Ware.pptx, PGW Culture of India
Painted Grey Ware.pptx, PGW Culture of IndiaPainted Grey Ware.pptx, PGW Culture of India
Painted Grey Ware.pptx, PGW Culture of India
 
Historical philosophical, theoretical, and legal foundations of special and i...
Historical philosophical, theoretical, and legal foundations of special and i...Historical philosophical, theoretical, and legal foundations of special and i...
Historical philosophical, theoretical, and legal foundations of special and i...
 
ECONOMIC CONTEXT - PAPER 1 Q3: NEWSPAPERS.pptx
ECONOMIC CONTEXT - PAPER 1 Q3: NEWSPAPERS.pptxECONOMIC CONTEXT - PAPER 1 Q3: NEWSPAPERS.pptx
ECONOMIC CONTEXT - PAPER 1 Q3: NEWSPAPERS.pptx
 
OS-operating systems- ch04 (Threads) ...
OS-operating systems- ch04 (Threads) ...OS-operating systems- ch04 (Threads) ...
OS-operating systems- ch04 (Threads) ...
 
ENGLISH 7_Q4_LESSON 2_ Employing a Variety of Strategies for Effective Interp...
ENGLISH 7_Q4_LESSON 2_ Employing a Variety of Strategies for Effective Interp...ENGLISH 7_Q4_LESSON 2_ Employing a Variety of Strategies for Effective Interp...
ENGLISH 7_Q4_LESSON 2_ Employing a Variety of Strategies for Effective Interp...
 

THE ANTICHRIST BY NIETZSCHE

  • 1. THE ANTICHRIST by Friedrich Nietzsche Published 1895 translation by H.L. Mencken Published 1920 PREFACE This book belongs to the most rare of men. Perhaps not one of them is yet alive. It is possible that they may be among those who understand my "Zarathustra": how could I confound myself with those who are now sprouting ears?--First the day after tomorrow must come for me. Some men are born posthumously. The conditions under which any one understands me, and necessarily understands me--I know them only too well. Even to endure my seriousness, my passion, he must carry intellectual integrity to the verge of hardness. He must be accustomed to living on mountain tops--and to looking upon the wretched gabble of politics and nationalism as beneath him. He must have become indifferent; he must never ask of the truth whether it brings profit to him or a fatality to him... He must have an inclination, born of strength, for questions that no one has the courage for; the courage for the forbidden; predestination for the labyrinth. The experience of seven solitudes. New ears for new music. New eyes for what is most distant. A new conscience for truths that have hitherto remained unheard. And the will to economize in the grand manner--to hold together his
  • 2. strength, his enthusiasm...Reverence for self; love of self; absolute freedom of self..... Very well, then! of that sort only are my readers, my true readers, my readers foreordained: of what account are the rest?- -The rest are merely humanity.--One must make one's self superior to humanity, in power, in loftiness of soul,--in contempt. FRIEDRICH W. NIETZSCHE. 1. --Let us look each other in the face. We are Hyperboreans--we know well enough how remote our place is. "Neither by land nor by water will you find the road to the Hyperboreans": even Pindar1,in his day, knew that much about us. Beyond the North, beyond the ice, beyond death--our life, our happiness...We have discovered that happiness; we know the way; we got our knowledge of it from thousands of years in the labyrinth. Who else has found it?--The man of today?--"I don't know either the way out or the way in; I am whatever doesn't know either the way out or the way in"--so sighs the man of today...This is the sort of modernity that made us ill,--we sickened on lazy peace, cowardly compromise, the whole virtuous dirtiness of the modern Yea and Nay. This tolerance and largeur of the heart that "forgives" everything because it "understands" everything is a sirocco to us. Rather live amid the ice than among modern virtues and other such south-winds! . . . We were brave enough; we spared neither ourselves nor others; but we were a long time finding out where to direct our courage. We grew dismal; they called us fatalists. Our fate--it was the fulness, the tension, the storing up of powers. We thirsted for the lightnings and great deeds; we kept as far as possible from the happiness of the weakling, from "resignation" . . . There was thunder in our air; nature, as we embodied it, became overcast--for we had not yet found the way. The formula of our happiness: a Yea, a Nay, a
  • 3. straight line, a goal... 2. What is good?--Whatever augments the feeling of power, the will to power, power itself, in man. What is evil?--Whatever springs from weakness. What is happiness?--The feeling that power increases-- thatresistance is overcome. Not contentment, but more power; not peace at any price, but war; not virtue, but efficiency (virtue in the Renaissance sense, virtu, virtue free of moral acid). The weak and the botched shall perish: first principle of our charity. And one should help them to it. What is more harmful than any vice?--Practical sympathy for the botched and the weak--Christianity... 3. The problem that I set here is not what shall replace mankind in the order of living creatures (--man is an end--): but what type of man must be bred, must be willed, as being the most valuable, the most worthy of life, the most secure guarantee of the future. This more valuable type has appeared often enough in the past: but always as a happy accident, as an exception, never as deliberately willed. Very often it has been precisely the most feared; hitherto it has been almost the terror of terrors ;--and out of that terror the contrary type has been willed, cultivated and attained: the domestic animal, the herd animal, the sick brute-man--the Christian. . . 4. Mankind surely does not represent an evolution toward a better
  • 4. or stronger or higher level, as progress is now understood. This "progress" is merely a modern idea, which is to say, a false idea. The European of today, in his essential worth, falls far below the European of the Renaissance; the process of evolution does not necessarily mean elevation, enhancement, strengthening. True enough, it succeeds in isolated and individual cases in various parts of the earth and under the most widely different cultures, and in these cases a higher type certainly manifests itself; something which, compared to mankind in the mass, appears as a sort of superman. Such happy strokes of high success have always been possible, and will remain possible, perhaps, for all time to come. Even whole races, tribes and nations may occasionally represent such lucky accidents. 5. We should not deck out and embellish Christianity: it has waged a war to the death against this higher type of man, it has put all the deepest instincts of this type under its ban, it has developed its concept of evil, of the Evil One himself, out of these instincts--the strong man as the typical reprobate, the "outcast among men." Christianity has taken the part of all the weak, the low, the botched; it has made an ideal out of antagonism to all the self-preservative instincts of sound life; it has corrupted even the faculties of those natures that are intellectually most vigorous, by representing the highest intellectual values as sinful, as misleading, as full of temptation. The most lamentable example: the corruption of Pascal, who believed that his intellect had been destroyed by original sin, whereas it was actually destroyed by Christianity!-- 6. It is a painful and tragic spectacle that rises before me: I have
  • 5. drawn back the curtain from the rottenness of man. This word, in my mouth, is at least free from one suspicion: that it involves a moral accusation against humanity. It is used--and I wish to emphasize the fact again--without any moral significance: and this is so far true that the rottenness I speak of is most apparent to me precisely in those quarters where there has been most aspiration, hitherto, toward "virtue" and "godliness." As you probably surmise, I understand rottenness in the sense of decadence: my argument is that all the values on which mankind now fixes its highest aspirations are decadence-values. I call an animal, a species, an individual corrupt, when it loses its instincts, when it chooses, when it prefers, what is injurious to it. A history of the "higher feelings," the "ideals of humanity"--and it is possible that I'll have to write it--would almost explain why man is so degenerate. Life itself appears to me as an instinct for growth, for survival, for the accumulation of forces, for power: whenever the will to power fails there is disaster. My contention is that all the highest values of humanity have been emptied of this will--that the values of decadence, of nihilism, now prevail under the holiest names. 7. Christianity is called the religion of pity.-- Pity stands in opposition to all the tonic passions that augment the energy of the feeling of aliveness: it is a depressant. A man loses power when he pities. Through pity that drain upon strength which suffering works is multiplied a thousandfold. Suffering is made contagious by pity; under certain circumstances it may lead to a total sacrifice of life and living energy--a loss out of all proportion to the magnitude of the cause (--the case of the death of the Nazarene). This is the first view of it; there is, however, a still more important one. If one measures the effects of pity by the gravity of the reactions it sets up, its character as a menace to life appears in a much clearer light. Pity thwarts the whole
  • 6. law of evolution, which is the law of natural selection. It preserves whatever is ripe for destruction; it fights on the side of those disinherited and condemned by life; by maintaining life in so many of the botched of all kinds, it gives life itself a gloomy and dubious aspect. Mankind has ventured to call pity a virtue (--in every superior moral system it appears as a weakness--); going still further, it has been called the virtue, the source and foundation of all other virtues--but let us always bear in mind that this was from the standpoint of a philosophy that was nihilistic, and upon whose shield the denial of life was inscribed. Schopenhauer was right in this: that by means of pity life is denied, and made worthy of denial--pity is the technic of nihilism. Let me repeat: this depressing and contagious instinct stands against all those instincts which work for the preservation and enhancement of life: in the role of protector of the miserable, it is a prime agent in the promotion of decadence--pity persuades to extinction....Of course, one doesn't say "extinction": one says "the other world," or "God," or "the true life," or Nirvana, salvation, blessedness.... This innocent rhetoric, from the realm of religious-ethical balderdash, appears a good deal less innocent when one reflects upon the tendency that it conceals beneath sublime words: the tendency to destroy life. Schopenhauer was hostile to life: that is why pity appeared to him as a virtue. . . . Aristotle, as every one knows, saw in pity a sickly and dangerous state of mind, the remedy for which was an occasional purgative: he regarded tragedy as that purgative. The instinct of life should prompt us to seek some means of puncturing any such pathological and dangerous accumulation of pity as that appearing in Schopenhauer's case (and also, alack, in that of our whole literary decadence, from St. Petersburg to Paris, from Tolstoi to Wagner), that it may burst and be discharged. . . Nothing is more unhealthy, amid all our unhealthy modernism, than Christian pity. To be the doctors here, to be unmerciful here, to wield the knife here--all this is our business, all this is our sort of humanity, by this sign we are philosophers, we Hyperboreans
  • 7. !-- 8. It is necessary to say just whom we regard as our antagonists: theologians and all who have any theological blood in their veins--this is our whole philosophy. . . . One must have faced that menace at close hand, better still, one must have had experience of it directly and almost succumbed to it, to realize that it is not to be taken lightly (--the alleged free-thinking of our naturalists and physiologists seems to me to be a joke--they have no passion about such things; they have not suffered--). This poisoning goes a great deal further than most people think: I find the arrogant habit of the theologian among all who regard themselves as "idealists"--among all who, by virtue of a higher point of departure, claim a right to rise above reality, and to look upon it with suspicion. . . The idealist, like the ecclesiastic, carries all sorts of lofty concepts in his hand (--and not only in his hand!); he launches them with benevolent contempt against "understanding," "the senses," "honor," "good living," "science"; he sees such things as beneath him, as pernicious and seductive forces, on which "the soul" soars as a pure thing-in-itself--as if humility, chastity, poverty, in a word, holiness, had not already done much more damage to life than all imaginable horrors and vices. . . The pure soul is a pure lie. . . So long as the priest, that professional denier, calumniator and poisoner of life, is accepted as a higher variety of man, there can be no answer to the question, What is truth? Truth has already been stood on its head when the obvious attorney of mere emptiness is mistaken for its representative. 9. Upon this theological instinct I make war: I find the tracks of it everywhere. Whoever has theological blood in his veins is shifty and dishonourable in all things. The pathetic thing that
  • 8. grows out of this condition is called faith: in other words, closing one's eyes upon one's self once for all, to avoid suffering the sight of incurable falsehood. People erect a concept of morality, of virtue, of holiness upon this false view of all things; they ground good conscience upon faulty vision; they argue that no other sort of vision has value any more, once they have made theirs sacrosanct with the names of "God," "salvation" and "eternity." I unearth this theological instinct in all directions: it is the most widespread and the most subterranean form of falsehood to be found on earth. Whatever a theologian regards as true must be false: there you have almost a criterion of truth. His profound instinct of self- preservation stands against truth ever coming into honour in any way, or even getting stated. Wherever the influence of theologians is felt there is a transvaluation of values, and the concepts "true" and "false" are forced to change places: what ever is most damaging to life is there called "true," and whatever exalts it, intensifies it, approves it, justifies it and makes it triumphant is there called "false."... When theologians, working through the "consciences" of princes (or of peoples--), stretch out their hands for power, there is never any doubt as to the fundamental issue: the will to make an end, the nihilistic will exerts that power... 10. Among Germans I am immediately understood when I say that theological blood is the ruin of philosophy. The Protestant pastor is the grandfather of German philosophy; Protestantism itself is its peccatum originale. Definition of Protestantism: hemiplegic paralysis of Christianity--and of reason. ... One need only utter the words "Tubingen School" to get an understanding of what German philosophy is at bottom--a very artful form of theology. . . The Suabians are the best liars in Germany; they lie innocently. . . . Why all the rejoicing over the appearance of Kant that went through the learned world of Germany, three-
  • 9. fourths of which is made up of the sons of preachers and teachers--why the German conviction still echoing, that with Kant came a change for the better? The theological instinct of German scholars made them see clearly just what had become possible again. . . . A backstairs leading to the old ideal stood open; the concept of the "true world," the concept of morality as the essence of the world (--the two most vicious errors that ever existed!), were once more, thanks to a subtle and wily scepticism, if not actually demonstrable, then at least no longer refutable... Reason, the prerogative of reason, does not go so far. . . Out of reality there had been made "appearance"; an absolutely false world, that of being, had been turned into reality. . . . The success of Kant is merely a theological success; he was, like Luther and Leibnitz, but one more impediment to German integrity, already far from steady.-- 11. A word now against Kant as a moralist. A virtue must be our invention; it must spring out of our personal need and defence. In every other case it is a source of danger. That which does not belong to our life menaces it; a virtue which has its roots in mere respect for the concept of "virtue," as Kant would have it, is pernicious. "Virtue," "duty," "good for its own sake," goodness grounded upon impersonality or a notion of universal validity--these are all chimeras, and in them one finds only an expression of the decay, the last collapse of life, the Chinese spirit of Konigsberg. Quite the contrary is demanded by the most profound laws of self-preservation and of growth: to wit, that every man find hisown virtue, his own categorical imperative. A nation goes to pieces when it confounds its duty with the general concept of duty. Nothing works a more complete and penetrating disaster than every "impersonal" duty, every sacrifice before the Moloch of abstraction.--To think that no one has thought of Kant's categorical imperative as dangerous to life!...The theological instinct alone took it under
  • 10. protection !--An action prompted by the life-instinct proves that it is a right action by the amount of pleasure that goes with it: and yet that Nihilist, with his bowels of Christian dogmatism, regarded pleasure as an objection . . . What destroys a man more quickly than to work, think and feel without inner necessity, without any deep personal desire, without pleasure--as a mere automaton of duty? That is the recipe for decadence, and no less for idiocy. . . Kant became an idiot.--And such a man was the contemporary of Goethe! This calamitous spinner of cobwebs passed for the German philosopher--still passes today! . . . I forbid myself to say what I think of the Germans. . . . Didn't Kant see in the French Revolution the transformation of the state from the inorganic form to the organic? Didn't he ask himself if there was a single event that could be explained save on the assumption of a moral faculty in man, so that on the basis of it, "the tendency of mankind toward the good" could be explained, once and for all time? Kant's answer: "That is revolution." Instinct at fault in everything and anything, instinct as a revolt against nature, German decadence as a philosophy-- that is Kant!---- 12. I put aside a few sceptics, the types of decency in the history of philosophy: the rest haven't the slightest conception of intellectual integrity. They behave like women, all these great enthusiasts and prodigies--they regard "beautiful feelings" as arguments, the "heaving breast" as the bellows of divine inspiration, conviction as the criterion of truth. In the end, with "German" innocence, Kant tried to give a scientific flavour to this form of corruption, this dearth of intellectual conscience, by calling it "practical reason." He deliberately invented a variety of reasons for use on occasions when it was desirable not to trouble with reason--that is, when morality, when the sublime command "thou shalt," was heard. When one recalls the fact that, among all peoples, the philosopher is no more than a development from the old type of priest, this inheritance from
  • 11. the priest, this fraud upon self, ceases to be remarkable. When a man feels that he has a divine mission, say to lift up, to save or to liberate mankind--when a man feels the divine spark in his heart and believes that he is the mouthpiece of supernatural imperatives--when such a mission in. flames him, it is only natural that he should stand beyond all merely reasonable standards of judgment. He feels that he is himself sanctified by this mission, that he is himself a type of a higher order! . . . What has a priest to do with philosophy! He stands far above it!--And hitherto the priest has ruled!--Hehas determined the meaning of "true" and "not true"! 13. Let us not under-estimate this fact: that we ourselves, we free spirits, are already a "transvaluation of all values," a visualized declaration of war and victory against all the old concepts of "true" and "not true." The most valuable intuitions are the last to be attained; the most valuable of all are those which determine methods. All the methods, all the principles of the scientific spirit of today, were the targets for thousands of years of the most profound contempt; if a man inclined to them he was excluded from the society of "decent" people--he passed as "an enemy of God," as a scoffer at the truth, as one "possessed." As a man of science, he belonged to the Chandala2... We have had the whole pathetic stupidity of mankind against us--their every notion of what the truth ought to be, of what the service of the truth ought to be--their every "thou shalt" was launched against us. . . . Our objectives, our methods, our quiet, cautious, distrustful manner--all appeared to them as absolutely discreditable and contemptible.--Looking back, one may almost ask one's self with reason if it was not actually an aesthetic sense that kept men blind so long: what they demanded of the truth was picturesque effectiveness, and of the learned a strong appeal to their senses. It was our modesty that stood out longest against their taste...How well they guessed that, these turkey-
  • 12. cocks of God! 14. We have unlearned something. We have be come more modest in every way. We no longer derive man from the "spirit," from the "god-head"; we have dropped him back among the beasts. We regard him as the strongest of the beasts because he is the craftiest; one of the results thereof is his intellectuality. On the other hand, we guard ourselves against a conceit which would assert itself even here: that man is the great second thought in the process of organic evolution. He is, in truth, anything but the crown of creation: beside him stand many other animals, all at similar stages of development... And even when we say that we say a bit too much, for man, relatively speaking, is the most botched of all the animals and the sickliest, and he has wandered the most dangerously from his instincts--though for all that, to be sure, he remains the most interesting!--As regards the lower animals, it was Descartes who first had the really admirable daring to describe them as machina; the whole of our physiology is directed toward proving the truth of this doctrine. Moreover, it is illogical to set man apart, as Descartes did: what we know of man today is limited precisely by the extent to which we have regarded him, too, as a machine. Formerly we accorded to man, as his inheritance from some higher order of beings, what was called "free will"; now we have taken even this will from him, for the term no longer describes anything that we can understand. The old word "will" now connotes only a sort of result, an individual reaction, that follows inevitably upon a series of partly discordant and partly harmonious stimuli--the will no longer "acts," or "moves." . . . Formerly it was thought that man's consciousness, his "spirit," offered evidence of his high origin, his divinity. That he might be perfected, he was advised, tortoise-like, to draw his senses in, to have no traffic with earthly things, to shuffle off his mortal coil--then only the important part of him, the "pure spirit,"
  • 13. would remain. Here again we have thought out the thing better: to us consciousness, or "the spirit," appears as a symptom of a relative imperfection of the organism, as an experiment, a groping, a misunderstanding, as an affliction which uses up nervous force unnecessarily--we deny that anything can be done perfectly so long as it is done consciously. The "pure spirit" is a piece of pure stupidity: take away the nervous system and the senses, the so-called "mortal shell," and the rest is miscalculation--thatis all!... 15. Under Christianity neither morality nor religion has any point of contact with actuality. It offers purely imaginary causes ("God" "soul," "ego," "spirit," "free will"--or even "unfree"), and purely imaginary effects ("sin" "salvation" "grace," "punishment," "forgiveness of sins"). Intercourse between imaginarybeings ("God," "spirits," "souls"); an imaginarynatural history (anthropocentric; a total denial of the concept of natural causes); an imaginary psychology (misunderstandings of self, misinterpretations of agreeable or disagreeable general feelings- -for example, of the states of the nervus sympathicus with the help of the sign-language of religio-ethical balderdash--, "repentance," "pangs of conscience," "temptation by the devil," "the presence of God"); an imaginaryteleology (the "kingdom of God," "the last judgment," "eternal life").--This purely fictitious world, greatly to its disadvantage, is to be differentiated from the world of dreams; the later at least reflects reality, whereas the former falsifies it, cheapens it and denies it. Once the concept of "nature" had been opposed to the concept of "God," the word "natural" necessarily took on the meaning of "abominable"--the whole of that fictitious world has its sources in hatred of the natural (--the real!--), and is no more than evidence of a profound uneasiness in the presence of reality. . . . This explains everything. Who alone has any reason for living his way out of reality? The man who suffers under it. But to
  • 14. suffer from reality one must be a botched reality. . . . The preponderance of pains over pleasures is the cause of this fictitious morality and religion: but such a preponderance also supplies the formula for decadence... 16. A criticism of the Christian concept of God leads inevitably to the same conclusion.--A nation that still believes in itself holds fast to its own god. In him it does honour to the conditions which enable it to survive, to its virtues--it projects its joy in itself, its feeling of power, into a being to whom one may offer thanks. He who is rich will give of his riches; a proud people need a god to whom they can make sacrifices. . . Religion, within these limits, is a form of gratitude. A man is grateful for his own existence: to that end he needs a god.--Such a god must be able to work both benefits and injuries; he must be able to play either friend or foe--he is wondered at for the good he does as well as for the evil he does. But the castration, against all nature, of such a god, making him a god of goodness alone, would be contrary to human inclination. Mankind has just as much need for an evil god as for a good god; it doesn't have to thank mere tolerance and humanitarianism for its own existence. . . . What would be the value of a god who knew nothing of anger, revenge, envy, scorn, cunning, violence? who had perhaps never experienced the rapturous ardeurs of victory and of destruction? No one would understand such a god: why should any one want him?--True enough, when a nation is on the downward path, when it feels its belief in its own future, its hope of freedom slipping from it, when it begins to see submission as a first necessity and the virtues of submission as measures of self-preservation, then it must overhaul its god. He then becomes a hypocrite, timorous and demure; he counsels "peace of soul," hate-no-more, leniency, "love" of friend and foe. He moralizes endlessly; he creeps into every private virtue; he becomes the god of every man; he becomes a private citizen,
  • 15. a cosmopolitan. . . Formerly he represented a people, the strength of a people, everything aggressive and thirsty for power in the soul of a people; now he is simply the good god...The truth is that there is no other alternative for gods: either they are the will to power--in which case they are national gods--or incapacity for power--in which case they have to be good. 17. Wherever the will to power begins to decline, in whatever form, there is always an accompanying decline physiologically, a decadence. The divinity of this decadence, shorn of its masculine virtues and passions, is converted perforce into a god of the physiologically degraded, of the weak. Of course, they do not call themselves the weak; they call themselves "the good." . . . No hint is needed to indicate the moments in history at which the dualistic fiction of a good and an evil god first became possible. The same instinct which prompts the inferior to reduce their own god to "goodness-in-itself" also prompts them to eliminate all good qualities from the god of their superiors; they make revenge on their masters by making a devil of the latter's god.--The good god, and the devil like him--both are abortions of decadence.--How can we be so tolerant of the naïveté of Christian theologians as to join in their doctrine that the evolution of the concept of god from "the god of Israel," the god of a people, to the Christian god, the essence of all goodness, is to be described as progress?--But even Renan does this. As if Renan had a right to be naïve! The contrary actually stares one in the face. When everything necessary to ascending life; when all that is strong, courageous, masterful and proud has been eliminated from the concept of a god; when he has sunk step by step to the level of a staff for the weary, a sheet- anchor for the drowning; when he be comes the poor man's god, the sinner's god, the invalid's god par excellence, and the attribute of "saviour" or "redeemer" remains as the one essential
  • 16. attribute of divinity--just what is the significance of such a metamorphosis? what does such a reduction of the godhead imply?--To be sure, the "kingdom of God" has thus grown larger. Formerly he had only his own people, his "chosen" people. But since then he has gone wandering, like his people themselves, into foreign parts; he has given up settling down quietly anywhere; finally he has come to feel at home everywhere, and is the great cosmopolitan--until now he has the "great majority" on his side, and half the earth. But this god of the "great majority," this democrat among gods, has not become a proud heathen god: on the contrary, he remains a Jew, he remains a god in a corner, a god of all the dark nooks and crevices, of all the noisesome quarters of the world! . . His earthly kingdom, now as always, is a kingdom of the underworld, a souterrain kingdom, a ghetto kingdom. . . And he himself is so pale, so weak, so decadent . . . Even the palest of the pale are able to master him--messieurs the metaphysicians, those albinos of the intellect. They spun their webs around him for so long that finally he was hypnotized, and began to spin himself, and became another metaphysician. Thereafter he resumed once more his old business of spinning the world out of his inmost being sub specie Spinozae; thereafter he be came ever thinner and paler--became the "ideal," became "pure spirit," became "the absolute," became "the thing-in-itself." . . . The collapse of a god: he became a "thing-in-itself." 18. The Christian concept of a god--the god as the patron of the sick, the god as a spinner of cobwebs, the god as a spirit--is one of the most corrupt concepts that has ever been set up in the world: it probably touches low-water mark in the ebbing evolution of the god-type. God degenerated into the contradiction of life. Instead of being its transfiguration and eternal Yea! In him war is declared on life, on nature, on the will to live! God becomes the formula for every slander upon
  • 17. the "here and now," and for every lie about the "beyond"! In him nothingness is deified, and the will to nothingness is made holy! . . . 19. The fact that the strong races of northern Europe did not repudiate this Christian god does little credit to their gift for religion--and not much more to their taste. They ought to have been able to make an end of such a moribund and worn-out product of the decadence. A curse lies upon them because they were not equal to it; they made illness, decrepitude and contradiction a part of their instincts--and since then they have not managed to create any more gods. Two thousand years have come and gone--and not a single new god! Instead, there still exists, and as if by some intrinsic right,--as if he were the ultimatum and maximum of the power to create gods, of the creator spiritus in mankind--this pitiful god of Christian monotono-theism! This hybrid image of decay, conjured up out of emptiness, contradiction and vain imagining, in which all the instincts of decadence, all the cowardices and wearinesses of the soul find their sanction!-- 20. In my condemnation of Christianity I surely hope I do no injustice to a related religion with an even larger number of believers: I allude to Buddhism. Both are to be reckoned among the nihilistic religions--they are both decadence religions--but they are separated from each other in a very remarkable way. For the fact that he is able to compare them at all the critic of Christianity is indebted to the scholars of India.--Buddhism is a hundred times as realistic as Christianity--it is part of its living heritage that it is able to face problems objectively and coolly; it is the product of long centuries of philosophical speculation. The concept, "god," was already disposed of before it appeared.
  • 18. Buddhism is the only genuinely positive religion to be encountered in history, and this applies even to its epistemology (which is a strict phenomenalism) --It does not speak of a "struggle with sin," but, yielding to reality, of the "struggle with suffering." Sharply differentiating itself from Christianity, it puts the self-deception that lies in moral concepts be hind it; it is, in my phrase,beyond good and evil.--The two physiological facts upon which it grounds itself and upon which it bestows its chief attention are: first, an excessive sensitiveness to sensation, which manifests itself as a refined susceptibility to pain, and secondly, an extraordinary spirituality, a too protracted concern with concepts and logical procedures, under the influence of which the instinct of personality has yielded to a notion of the "impersonal." (--Both of these states will be familiar to a few of my readers, the objectivists, by experience, as they are to me). These physiological states produced a depression, and Buddha tried to combat it by hygienic measures. Against it he prescribed a life in the open, a life of travel; moderation in eating and a careful selection of foods; caution in the use of intoxicants; the same caution in arousing any of the passions that foster a bilious habit and heat the blood; finally, no worry, either on one's own account or on account of others. He encourages ideas that make for either quiet contentment or good cheer--he finds means to combat ideas of other sorts. He understands good, the state of goodness, as something which promotes health. Prayer is not included, and neither is asceticism. There is no categorical imperative nor any disciplines, even within the walls of a monastery (--it is always possible to leave--). These things would have been simply means of increasing the excessive sensitiveness above mentioned. For the same reason he does not advocate any conflict with unbelievers; his teaching is antagonistic to nothing so much as to revenge, aversion, ressentiment (--"enmity never brings an end to enmity": the moving refrain of all Buddhism. . .) And in all this he was right, for it is precisely these passions which, in view of his main
  • 19. regiminal purpose, are unhealthful. The mental fatigue that he observes, already plainly displayed in too much "objectivity" (that is, in the individual's loss of interest in himself, in loss of balance and of "egoism"), he combats by strong efforts to lead even the spiritual interests back to the ego. In Buddha's teaching egoism is a duty. The "one thing needful," the question "how can you be delivered from suffering," regulates and determines the whole spiritual diet. (--Perhaps one will here recall that Athenian who also declared war upon pure "scientificality," to wit, Socrates, who also elevated egoism to the estate of a morality) . 21. The things necessary to Buddhism are a very mild climate, customs of great gentleness and liberality, and no militarism; moreover, it must get its start among the higher and better educated classes. Cheerfulness, quiet and the absence of desire are the chief desiderata, and they are attained. Buddhism is not a religion in which perfection is merely an object of aspiration: perfection is actually normal.--Under Christianity the instincts of the subjugated and the oppressed come to the fore: it is only those who are at the bottom who seek their salvation in it. Here the prevailing pastime, the favourite remedy for boredom is the discussion of sin, self-criticism, the inquisition of conscience; here the emotion produced by power (called "God") is pumped up (by prayer); here the highest good is regarded as unattainable, as a gift, as "grace." Here, too, open dealing is lacking; concealment and the darkened room are Christian. Here body is despised and hygiene is denounced as sensual; the church even ranges itself against cleanliness (--the first Christian order after the banishment of the Moors closed the public baths, of which there were 270 in Cordova alone) . Christian, too; is a certain cruelty toward one's self and toward others; hatred of unbelievers; the will to persecute. Sombre and disquieting ideas are in the foreground; the most esteemed
  • 20. states of mind, bearing the most respectable names are epileptoid; the diet is so regulated as to engender morbid symptoms and over-stimulate the nerves. Christian, again, is all deadly enmity to the rulers of the earth, to the "aristocratic"-- along with a sort of secret rivalry with them (--one resigns one's "body" to them--one wantsonly one's "soul" . . . ). And Christian is all hatred of the intellect, of pride, of courage of freedom, of intellectual libertinage; Christian is all hatred of the senses, of joy in the senses, of joy in general . . . 22. When Christianity departed from its native soil, that of the lowest orders, the underworld of the ancient world, and began seeking power among barbarian peoples, it no longer had to deal with exhausted men, but with men still inwardly savage and capable of self torture--in brief, strong men, but bungled men. Here, unlike in the case of the Buddhists, the cause of discontent with self, suffering through self, is not merely a general sensitiveness and susceptibility to pain, but, on the contrary, an inordinate thirst for inflicting pain on others, a tendency to obtain subjective satisfaction in hostile deeds and ideas. Christianity had to embrace barbaric concepts and valuations in order to obtain mastery over barbarians: of such sort, for example, are the sacrifices of the first-born, the drinking of blood as a sacrament, the disdain of the intellect and of culture; torture in all its forms, whether bodily or not; the whole pomp of the cult. Buddhism is a religion for peoples in a further state of development, for races that have become kind, gentle and over-spiritualized (--Europe is not yet ripe for it--): it is a summons 'that takes them back to peace and cheerfulness, to a careful rationing of the spirit, to a certain hardening of the body. Christianity aims at mastering beasts of prey; its modus operandi is to make them ill--to make feeble is the Christian recipe for taming, for "civilizing." Buddhism is a religion for the closing, over-wearied stages of civilization. Christianity
  • 21. appears before civilization has so much as begun--under certain circumstances it lays the very foundations thereof. 23. Buddhism, I repeat, is a hundred times more austere, more honest, more objective. It no longer has to justify its pains, its susceptibility to suffering, by interpreting these things in terms of sin--it simply says, as it simply thinks, "I suffer." To the barbarian, however, suffering in itself is scarcely understandable: what he needs, first of all, is an explanation as to why he suffers. (His mere instinct prompts him to deny his suffering altogether, or to endure it in silence.) Here the word "devil" was a blessing: man had to have an omnipotent and terrible enemy--there was no need to be ashamed of suffering at the hands of such an enemy. --At the bottom of Christianity there are several subtleties that belong to the Orient. In the first place, it knows that it is of very little consequence whether a thing be true or not, so long as it is believed to be true. Truth and faith: here we have two wholly distinct worlds of ideas, almost two diametrically opposite worlds--the road to the one and the road to the other lie miles apart. To understand that fact thoroughly--this is almost enough, in the Orient, to make one a sage. The Brahmins knew it, Plato knew it, every student of the esoteric knows it. When, for example, a man gets any pleasure out of the notion that he has been saved from sin, it is not necessary for him to be actually sinful, but merely to feel sinful. But when faith is thus exalted above everything else, it necessarily follows that reason, knowledge and patient inquiry have to be discredited: the road to the truth becomes a forbidden road.--Hope, in its stronger forms, is a great deal more powerful stimulans to life than any sort of realized joy can ever be. Man must be sustained in suffering by a hope so high that no conflict with actuality can dash it--so high, indeed, that no fulfillment can satisfy it: a
  • 22. hope reaching out beyond this world. (Precisely because of this power that hope has of making the suffering hold out, the Greeks regarded it as the evil of evils, as the most malign of evils; it remained behind at the source of all evil.)3--In order that love may be possible, God must become a person; in order that the lower instincts may take a hand in the matter God must be young. To satisfy the ardor of the woman a beautiful saint must appear on the scene, and to satisfy that of the men there must be a virgin. These things are necessary if Christianity is to assume lordship over a soil on which some aphrodisiacal or Adonis cult has already established a notion as to what a cult ought to be. To insist upon chastity greatly strengthens the vehemence and subjectivity of the religious instinct--it makes the cult warmer, more enthusiastic, more soulful.--Love is the state in which man sees things most decidedly as they are not. The force of illusion reaches its highest here, and so does the capacity for sweetening, for transfiguring. When a man is in love he endures more than at any other time; he submits to anything. The problem was to devise a religion which would allow one to love: by this means the worst that life has to offer is overcome--it is scarcely even noticed.--So much for the three Christian virtues: faith, hope and charity: I call them the three Christian ingenuities.--Buddhism is in too late a stage of development, too full of positivism, to be shrewd in any such way.-- 24. Here I barely touch upon the problem of the origin of Christianity. The first thing necessary to its solution is this: that Christianity is to be understood only by examining the soil from which it sprung--it is not a reaction against Jewish instincts; it is their inevitable product; it is simply one more step in the awe-inspiring logic of the Jews. In the words of the Saviour, "salvation is of the Jews." 4--The second thing to remember is this: that the psychological type of the Galilean is still to be
  • 23. recognized, but it was only in its most degenerate form (which is at once maimed and overladen with foreign features) that it could serve in the manner in which it has been used: as a type of the Saviour of mankind. --The Jews are the most remarkable people in the history of the world, for when they were confronted with the question, to be or not to be, they chose, with perfectly unearthly deliberation, to be at anyprice: this price involved a radical falsification of all nature, of all naturalness, of all reality, of the whole inner world, as well as of the outer. They put themselves against all those conditions under which, hitherto, a people had been able to live, or had even been permitted to live; out of themselves they evolved an idea which stood in direct opposition to natural conditions--one by one they distorted religion, civilization, morality, history and psychology until each became a contradiction of its natural significance. We meet with the same phenomenon later on, in an incalculably exaggerated form, but only as a copy: the Christian church, put beside the "people of God," shows a complete lack of any claim to originality. Precisely for this reason the Jews are the most fateful people in the history of the world: their influence has so falsified the reasoning of mankind in this matter that today the Christian can cherish anti-Semitism without realizing that it is no more than the final consequence of Judaism. In my "Genealogy of Morals" I give the first psychological explanation of the concepts underlying those two antithetical things, a noble morality and a ressentiment morality, the second of which is a mere product of the denial of the former. The Judaeo-Christian moral system belongs to the second division, and in every detail. In order to be able to say Nay to everything representing an ascending evolution of life--that is, to well- being, to power, to beauty, to self-approval--the instincts of ressentiment, here become downright genius, had to invent an other world in which the acceptance of life appeared as the most evil and abominable thing imaginable. Psychologically, the
  • 24. Jews are a people gifted with the very strongest vitality, so much so that when they found themselves facing impossible conditions of life they chose voluntarily, and with a profound talent for self-preservation, the side of all those instincts which make for decadence--not as if mastered by them, but as if detecting in them a power by which "the world" could be defied. The Jews are the very opposite of decadents: they have simply been forced into appearing in that guise, and with a degree of skill approaching the non plus ultra of histrionic genius they have managed to put themselves at the head of all decadent movements (--for example, the Christianity of Paul--), and so make of them something stronger than any party frankly saying Yes to life. To the sort of men who reach out for power under Judaism and Christianity,--that is to say, to the priestly class- decadence is no more than a means to an end. Men of this sort have a vital interest in making mankind sick, and in confusing the values of "good" and "bad," "true" and "false" in a manner that is not only dangerous to life, but also slanders it. Nicomachean Ethics Book 1, Chapter 1 EVERY art and every inquiry, and similarly every action and pursuit, is thought to aim at some good; and for this reason the good has rightly been declared to be that at which all things aim. But a certain difference is found among ends; some are activities, others are products apart from the activities that produce them. Where there are ends apart from the actions, it is the nature of the products to be better than the activities. Now, as there are many actions, arts, and sciences, their ends also are many; the end of the medical art is health, that of shipbuilding a vessel, that of strategy victory, that of economics wealth. But where such arts fall under a single capacity -- as bridle-making and the other arts concerned with the equipment of horses fall under the art of riding, and this and every military action under strategy, in the same way other arts fall under yet others -- in
  • 25. all of these the ends of the master arts are to be preferred to all the subordinate ends; for it is for the sake of the former that the latter are pursued. It makes no difference whether the activities themselves are the ends of the actions, or something else apart from the activities, as in the case of the sciences just mentioned. Book 1, Chapter 2 If, then, there is some end of the things we do, which we desire for its own sake (everything else being desired for the sake of this), and if we do not choose everything for the sake of something else (for at that rate the process would go on to infinity, so that our desire would be empty and vain), clearly this must be the good and the chief good. Will not the knowledge of it, then, have a great influence on life? Shall we not, like archers who have a mark to aim at, be more likely to hit upon what is right? If so, we must try, in outline at least, to determine what it is, and of which of the sciences or capacities it is the object. It would seem to belong to the most authoritative art and that which is most truly the master art. And politics appears to be of this nature; for it is this that ordains which of the sciences should be studied in a state, and which each class of citizens should learn and up to what point they should learn them; and we see even the most highly esteemed of capacities to fall under this, e.g. strategy, economics, rhetoric; now, since politics uses the rest of the sciences, and since, again, it legislates as to what we are to do and what we are to abstain from, the end of this science must include those of the others, so that this end must be the good for man. For even if the end is the same for a single man and for a state, that of the state seems at all events something greater and more complete whether to attain or to preserve; though it is worth while to attain the end merely for one man, it is finer and more godlike to attain it for a nation or for city-states. These, then, are the ends at which our inquiry aims, since it is political science, in
  • 26. one sense of that term. Book 1, Chapter 3 Our discussion will be adequate if it has as much clearness as the subject-matter admits of, for precision is not to be sought for alike in all discussions, any more than in all the products of the crafts. Now fine and just actions, which political science investigates, admit of much variety and fluctuation of opinion, so that they may be thought to exist only by convention, and not by nature. And goods also give rise to a similar fluctuation because they bring harm to many people; for before now men have been undone by reason of their wealth, and others by reason of their courage. We must be content, then, in speaking of such subjects and with such premisses to indicate the truth roughly and in outline, and in speaking about things which are only for the most part true and with premisses of the same kind to reach conclusions that are no better. In the same spirit, therefore, should each type of statement be received; for it is the mark of an educated man to look for precision in each class of things just so far as the nature of the subject admits; it is evidently equally foolish to accept probable reasoning from a mathematician and to demand from a rhetorician scientific proofs. Now each man judges well the things he knows, and of these he is a good judge. And so the man who has been educated in a subject is a good judge of that subject, and the man who has received an all-round education is a good judge in general. Hence a young man is not a proper hearer of lectures on political science; for he is inexperienced in the actions that occur in life, but its discussions start from these and are about these; and, further, since he tends to follow his passions, his study will be vain and unprofitable, because the end aimed at is not knowledge but action. And it makes no difference whether he is young in years or youthful in character; the defect does
  • 27. not depend on time, but on his living, and pursuing each successive object, as passion directs. For to such persons, as to the incontinent, knowledge brings no profit; but to those who desire and act in accordance with a rational principle knowledge about such matters will be of great benefit. These remarks about the student, the sort of treatment to be expected, and the purpose of the inquiry, may be taken as our preface. Book 1, Chapter 4 Let us resume our inquiry and state, in view of the fact that all knowledge and every pursuit aims at some good, what it is that we say political science aims at and what is the highest of all goods achievable by action. Verbally there is very general agreement; for both the general run of men and people of superior refinement say that it is happiness, and identify living well and doing well with being happy; but with regard to what happiness is they differ, and the many do not give the same account as the wise. For the former think it is some plain and obvious thing, like pleasure, wealth, or honour; they differ, however, from one another -- and often even the same man identifies it with different things, with health when he is ill, with wealth when he is poor; but, conscious of their ignorance, they admire those who proclaim some great ideal that is above their comprehension. Now some thought that apart from these many goods there is another which is self-subsistent and causes the goodness of all these as well. To examine all the opinions that have been held were perhaps somewhat fruitless; enough to examine those that are most prevalent or that seem to be arguable. Let us not fail to notice, however, that there is a difference between arguments from and those to the first principles. For Plato, too, was right in raising this question and asking, as he
  • 28. used to do, 'are we on the way from or to the first principles?' There is a difference, as there is in a race-course between the course from the judges to the turning-point and the way back. For, while we must begin with what is known, things are objects of knowledge in two senses -- some to us, some without qualification. Presumably, then, we must begin with things known to us. Hence any one who is to listen intelligently to lectures about what is noble and just, and generally, about the subjects of political science must have been brought up in good habits. For the fact is the starting-point, and if this is sufficiently plain to him, he will not at the start need the reason as well; and the man who has been well brought up has or can easily get starting points. And as for him who neither has nor can get them, let him hear the words of Hesiod: Far best is he who knows all things himself; Good, he that hearkens when men counsel right; But he who neither knows, nor lays to heart Another's wisdom, is a useless wight. Book 1, Chapter 5 Let us, however, resume our discussion from the point at which we digressed. To judge from the lives that men lead, most men, and men of the most vulgar type, seem (not without some ground) to identify the good, or happiness, with pleasure; which is the reason why they love the life of enjoyment. For there are, we may say, three prominent types of life -- that just mentioned, the political, and thirdly the contemplative life. Now the mass of mankind are evidently quite slavish in their tastes, preferring a life suitable to beasts, but they get some ground for their view from the fact that many of those in high places share the tastes of Sardanapallus. A consideration of the prominent types of life shows that people of superior refinement and of active disposition identify happiness with honour; for this is, roughly speaking, the end of the political life. But it seems too
  • 29. superficial to be what we are looking for, since it is thought to depend on those who bestow honour rather than on him who receives it, but the good we divine to be something proper to a man and not easily taken from him. Further, men seem to pursue honour in order that they may be assured of their goodness; at least it is by men of practical wisdom that they seek to be honoured, and among those who know them, and on the ground of their virtue; clearly, then, according to them, at any rate, virtue is better. And perhaps one might even suppose this to be, rather than honour, the end of the political life. But even this appears somewhat incomplete; for possession of virtue seems actually compatible with being asleep, or with lifelong inactivity, and, further, with the greatest sufferings and misfortunes; but a man who was living so no one would call happy, unless he were maintaining a thesis at all costs. But enough of this; for the subject has been sufficiently treated even in the current discussions. Third comes the contemplative life, which we shall consider later. The life of money-making is one undertaken under compulsion, and wealth is evidently not the good we are seeking; for it is merely useful and for the sake of something else. And so one might rather take the aforenamed objects to be ends; for they are loved for themselves. But it is evident that not even these are ends; yet many arguments have been thrown away in support of them. Let us leave this subject, then. Book 1, Chapter 6 We had perhaps better consider the universal good and discuss thoroughly what is meant by it, although such an inquiry is made an uphill one by the fact that the Forms have been introduced by friends of our own. Yet it would perhaps be thought to be better, indeed to be our duty, for the sake of maintaining the truth even to destroy what touches us closely, especially as we are philosophers or lovers of wisdom; for,
  • 30. while both are dear, piety requires us to honour truth above our friends. The men who introduced this doctrine did not posit Ideas of classes within which they recognized priority and posteriority (which is the reason why they did not maintain the existence of an Idea embracing all numbers); but the term 'good' is used both in the category of substance and in that of quality and in that of relation, and that which is per se, i.e. substance, is prior in nature to the relative (for the latter is like an off shoot and accident of being); so that there could not be a common Idea set over all these goods. Further, since 'good' has as many senses as 'being' (for it is predicated both in the category of substance, as of God and of reason, and in quality, i.e. of the virtues, and in quantity, i.e. of that which is moderate, and in relation, i.e. of the useful, and in time, i.e. of the right opportunity, and in place, i.e. of the right locality and the like), clearly it cannot be something universally present in all cases and single; for then it could not have been predicated in all the categories but in one only. Further, since of the things answering to one Idea there is one science, there would have been one science of all the goods; but as it is there are many sciences even of the things that fall under one category, e.g. of opportunity, for opportunity in war is studied by strategics and in disease by medicine, and the moderate in food is studied by medicine and in exercise by the science of gymnastics. And one might ask the question, what in the world they mean by 'a thing itself', is (as is the case) in 'man himself' and in a particular man the account of man is one and the same. For in so far as they are man, they will in no respect differ; and if this is so, neither will 'good itself' and particular goods, in so far as they are good. But again it will not be good any the more for being eternal, since that which lasts long is no whiter than that which perishes in a day. The Pythagoreans seem to give a more plausible account of the good, when they place the one in the column of goods; and it is they that Speusippus seems to have followed.
  • 31. But let us discuss these matters elsewhere; an objection to what we have said, however, may be discerned in the fact that the Platonists have not been speaking about all goods, and that the goods that are pursued and loved for themselves are called good by reference to a single Form, while those which tend to produce or to preserve these somehow or to prevent their contraries are called so by reference to these, and in a secondary sense. Clearly, then, goods must be spoken of in two ways, and some must be good in themselves, the others by reason of these. Let us separate, then, things good in themselves from things useful, and consider whether the former are called good by reference to a single Idea. What sort of goods would one call good in themselves? Is it those that are pursued even when isolated from others, such as intelligence, sight, and certain pleasures and honours? Certainly, if we pursue these also for the sake of something else, yet one would place them among things good in themselves. Or is nothing other than the Idea of good good in itself? In that case the Form will be empty. But if the things we have named are also things good in themselves, the account of the good will have to appear as something identical in them all, as that of whiteness is identical in snow and in white lead. But of honour, wisdom, and pleasure, just in respect of their goodness, the accounts are distinct and diverse. The good, therefore, is not some common element answering to one Idea. But what then do we mean by the good? It is surely not like the things that only chance to have the same name. Are goods one, then, by being derived from one good or by all contributing to one good, or are they rather one by analogy? Certainly as sight is in the body, so is reason in the soul, and so on in other cases. But perhaps these subjects had better be dismissed for the present; for perfect precision about them would be more appropriate to another branch of philosophy. And similarly with regard to the Idea; even if there is some one good which is
  • 32. universally predicable of goods or is capable of separate and independent existence, clearly it could not be achieved or attained by man; but we are now seeking something attainable. Perhaps, however, some one might think it worth while to recognize this with a view to the goods that are attainable and achievable; for having this as a sort of pattern we shall know better the goods that are good for us, and if we know them shall attain them. This argument has some plausibility, but seems to clash with the procedure of the sciences; for all of these, though they aim at some good and seek to supply the deficiency of it, leave on one side the knowledge of the good. Yet that all the exponents of the arts should be ignorant of, and should not even seek, so great an aid is not probable. It is hard, too, to see how a weaver or a carpenter will be benefited in regard to his own craft by knowing this 'good itself', or how the man who has viewed the Idea itself will be a better doctor or general thereby. For a doctor seems not even to study health in this way, but the health of man, or perhaps rather the health of a particular man; it is individuals that he is healing. But enough of these topics. Book 1, Chapter 7 Let us again return to the good we are seeking, and ask what it can be. It seems different in different actions and arts; it is different in medicine, in strategy, and in the other arts likewise. What then is the good of each? Surely that for whose sake everything else is done. In medicine this is health, in strategy victory, in architecture a house, in any other sphere something else, and in every action and pursuit the end; for it is for the sake of this that all men do whatever else they do. Therefore, if there is an end for all that we do, this will be the good achievable by action, and if there are more than one, these will be the goods achievable by action. So the argument has by a different course reached the same point; but we must try to state this even more clearly. Since
  • 33. there are evidently more than one end, and we choose some of these (e.g. wealth, flutes, and in general instruments) for the sake of something else, clearly not all ends are final ends; but the chief good is evidently something final. Therefore, if there is only one final end, this will be what we are seeking, and if there are more than one, the most final of these will be what we are seeking. Now we call that which is in itself worthy of pursuit more final than that which is worthy of pursuit for the sake of something else, and that which is never desirable for the sake of something else more final than the things that are desirable both in themselves and for the sake of that other thing, and therefore we call final without qualification that which is always desirable in itself and never for the sake of something else. Now such a thing happiness, above all else, is held to be; for this we choose always for self and never for the sake of something else, but honour, pleasure, reason, and every virtue we choose indeed for themselves (for if nothing resulted from them we should still choose each of them), but we choose them also for the sake of happiness, judging that by means of them we shall be happy. Happiness, on the other hand, no one chooses for the sake of these, nor, in general, for anything other than itself. From the point of view of self-sufficiency the same result seems to follow; for the final good is thought to be self-sufficient. Now by self-sufficient we do not mean that which is sufficient for a man by himself, for one who lives a solitary life, but also for parents, children, wife, and in general for his friends and fellow citizens, since man is born for citizenship. But some limit must be set to this; for if we extend our requirement to ancestors and descendants and friends' friends we are in for an infinite series. Let us examine this question, however, on another occasion; the self-sufficient we now define as that which when isolated makes life desirable and lacking in
  • 34. nothing; and such we think happiness to be; and further we think it most desirable of all things, without being counted as one good thing among others -- if it were so counted it would clearly be made more desirable by the addition of even the least of goods; for that which is added becomes an excess of goods, and of goods the greater is always more desirable. Happiness, then, is something final and self-sufficient, and is the end of action. Presumably, however, to say that happiness is the chief good seems a platitude, and a clearer account of what it is still desired. This might perhaps be given, if we could first ascertain the function of man. For just as for a flute-player, a sculptor, or an artist, and, in general, for all things that have a function or activity, the good and the 'well' is thought to reside in the function, so would it seem to be for man, if he has a function. Have the carpenter, then, and the tanner certain functions or activities, and has man none? Is he born without a function? Or as eye, hand, foot, and in general each of the parts evidently has a function, may one lay it down that man similarly has a function apart from all these? What then can this be? Life seems to be common even to plants, but we are seeking what is peculiar to man. Let us exclude, therefore, the life of nutrition and growth. Next there would be a life of perception, but it also seems to be common even to the horse, the ox, and every animal. There remains, then, an active life of the element that has a rational principle; of this, one part has such a principle in the sense of being obedient to one, the other in the sense of possessing one and exercising thought. And, as 'life of the rational element' also has two meanings, we must state that life in the sense of activity is what we mean; for this seems to be the more proper sense of the term. Now if the function of man is an activity of soul which follows or implies a rational principle, and if we say 'so-and-so-and 'a good so-and-so' have a function which is the same in kind, e.g. a lyre, and a good lyre-player, and so without qualification in all cases, eminence in respect of
  • 35. goodness being idded to the name of the function (for the function of a lyre-player is to play the lyre, and that of a good lyre-player is to do so well): if this is the case, and we state the function of man to be a certain kind of life, and this to be an activity or actions of the soul implying a rational principle, and the function of a good man to be the good and noble performance of these, and if any action is well performed when it is performed in accordance with the appropriate excellence: if this is the case, human good turns out to be activity of soul in accordance with virtue, and if there are more than one virtue, in accordance with the best and most complete. But we must add 'in a complete life.' For one swallow does not make a summer, nor does one day; and so too one day, or a short time, does not make a man blessed and happy. Let this serve as an outline of the good; for we must presumably first sketch it roughly, and then later fill in the details. But it would seem that any one is capable of carrying on and articulating what has once been well outlined, and that time is a good discoverer or partner in such a work; to which facts the advances of the arts are due; for any one can add what is lacking. And we must also remember what has been said before, and not look for precision in all things alike, but in each class of things such precision as accords with the subject-matter, and so much as is appropriate to the inquiry. For a carpenter and a geometer investigate the right angle in different ways; the former does so in so far as the right angle is useful for his work, while the latter inquires what it is or what sort of thing it is; for he is a spectator of the truth. We must act in the same way, then, in all other matters as well, that our main task may not be subordinated to minor questions. Nor must we demand the cause in all matters alike; it is enough in some cases that the fact be well established, as in the case of the first principles; the fact is the primary thing or first principle. Now of first principles we see some by induction, some by perception, some by a certain
  • 36. habituation, and others too in other ways. But each set of principles we must try to investigate in the natural way, and we must take pains to state them definitely, since they have a great influence on what follows. For the beginning is thought to be more than half of the whole, and many of the questions we ask are cleared up by it. Book 1, Chapter 8 We must consider it, however, in the light not only of our conclusion and our premisses, but also of what is commonly said about it; for with a true view all the data harmonize, but with a false one the facts soon clash. Now goods have been divided into three classes, and some are described as external, others as relating to soul or to body; we call those that relate to soul most properly and truly goods, and psychical actions and activities we class as relating to soul. Therefore our account must be sound, at least according to this view, which is an old one and agreed on by philosophers. It is correct also in that we identify the end with certain actions and activities; for thus it falls among goods of the soul and not among external goods. Another belief which harmonizes with our account is that the happy man lives well and does well; for we have practically defined happiness as a sort of good life and good action. The characteristics that are looked for in happiness seem also, all of them, to belong to what we have defined happiness as being. For some identify happiness with virtue, some with practical wisdom, others with a kind of philosophic wisdom, others with these, or one of these, accompanied by pleasure or not without pleasure; while others include also external prosperity. Now some of these views have been held by many men and men of old, others by a few eminent persons; and it is not probable that either of these should be entirely mistaken, but rather that they should be right in at least some one respect or even in most respects.
  • 37. With those who identify happiness with virtue or some one virtue our account is in harmony; for to virtue belongs virtuous activity. But it makes, perhaps, no small difference whether we place the chief good in possession or in use, in state of mind or in activity. For the state of mind may exist without producing any good result, as in a man who is asleep or in some other way quite inactive, but the activity cannot; for one who has the activity will of necessity be acting, and acting well. And as in the Olympic Games it is not the most beautiful and the strongest that are crowned but those who compete (for it is some of these that are victorious), so those who act win, and rightly win, the noble and good things in life. Their life is also in itself pleasant. For pleasure is a state of soul, and to each man that which he is said to be a lover of is pleasant; e.g. not only is a horse pleasant to the lover of horses, and a spectacle to the lover of sights, but also in the same way just acts are pleasant to the lover of justice and in general virtuous acts to the lover of virtue. Now for most men their pleasures are in conflict with one another because these are not by nature pleasant, but the lovers of what is noble find pleasant the things that are by nature pleasant; and virtuous actions are such, so that these are pleasant for such men as well as in their own nature. Their life, therefore, has no further need of pleasure as a sort of adventitious charm, but has its pleasure in itself. For, besides what we have said, the man who does not rejoice in noble actions is not even good; since no one would call a man just who did not enjoy acting justly, nor any man liberal who did not enjoy liberal actions; and similarly in all other cases. If this is so, virtuous actions must be in themselves pleasant. But they are also good and noble, and have each of these attributes in the highest degree, since the good man judges well about these attributes; his judgement is such as we have described. Happiness then is the best, noblest, and most pleasant thing in the world, and these attributes are not severed as in the inscription at Delos --
  • 38. Most noble is that which is justest, and best is health; But pleasantest is it to win what we love. For all these properties belong to the best activities; and these, or one -- the best -- of these, we identify with happiness. Yet evidently, as we said, it needs the external goods as well; for it is impossible, or not easy, to do noble acts without the proper equipment. In many actions we use friends and riches and political power as instruments; and there are some things the lack of which takes the lustre from happiness, as good birth, goodly children, beauty; for the man who is very ugly in appearance or ill-born or solitary and childless is not very likely to be happy, and perhaps a man would be still less likely if he had thoroughly bad children or friends or had lost good children or friends by death. As we said, then, happiness seems to need this sort of prosperity in addition; for which reason some identify happiness with good fortune, though others identify it with virtue. Book 1, Chapter 9 For this reason also the question is asked, whether happiness is to be acquired by learning or by habituation or some other sort of training, or comes in virtue of some divine providence or again by chance. Now if there is any gift of the gods to men, it is reasonable that happiness should be god-given, and most surely god-given of all human things inasmuch as it is the best. But this question would perhaps be more appropriate to another inquiry; happiness seems, however, even if it is not god-sent but comes as a result of virtue and some process of learning or training, to be among the most godlike things; for that which is the prize and end of virtue seems to be the best thing in the world, and something godlike and blessed.
  • 39. It will also on this view be very generally shared; for all who are not maimed as regards their potentiality for virtue may win it by a certain kind of study and care. But if it is better to be happy thus than by chance, it is reasonable that the facts should be so, since everything that depends on the action of nature is by nature as good as it can be, and similarly everything that depends on art or any rational cause, and especially if it depends on the best of all causes. To entrust to chance what is greatest and most noble would be a very defective arrangement. The answer to the question we are asking is plain also from the definition of happiness; for it has been said to be a virtuous activity of soul, of a certain kind. Of the remaining goods, some must necessarily pre-exist as conditions of happiness, and others are naturally co-operative and useful as instruments. And this will be found to agree with what we said at the outset; for we stated the end of political science to be the best end, and political science spends most of its pains on making the citizens to be of a certain character, viz. good and capable of noble acts. It is natural, then, that we call neither ox nor horse nor any other of the animals happy; for none of them is capable of sharing in such activity. For this reason also a boy is not happy; for he is not yet capable of such acts, owing to his age; and boys who are called happy are being congratulated by reason of the hopes we have for them. For there is required, as we said, not only complete virtue but also a complete life, since many changes occur in life, and all manner of chances, and the most prosperous may fall into great misfortunes in old age, as is told of Priam in the Trojan Cycle; and one who has experienced such chances and has ended wretchedly no one calls happy. Book 1, Chapter 10 Must no one at all, then, be called happy while he lives; must we, as Solon says, see the end? Even if we are to lay down this
  • 40. doctrine, is it also the case that a man is happy when he is dead? Or is not this quite absurd, especially for us who say that happiness is an activity? But if we do not call the dead man happy, and if Solon does not mean this, but that one can then safely call a man blessed as being at last beyond evils and misfortunes, this also affords matter for discussion; for both evil and good are thought to exist for a dead man, as much as for one who is alive but not aware of them; e.g. honours and dishonours and the good or bad fortunes of children and in general of descendants. And this also presents a problem; for though a man has lived happily up to old age and has had a death worthy of his life, many reverses may befall his descendants -- some of them may be good and attain the life they deserve, while with others the opposite may be the case; and clearly too the degrees of relationship between them and their ancestors may vary indefinitely. It would be odd, then, if the dead man were to share in these changes and become at one time happy, at another wretched; while it would also be odd if the fortunes of the descendants did not for some time have some effect on the happiness of their ancestors. But we must return to our first difficulty; for perhaps by a consideration of it our present problem might be solved. Now if we must see the end and only then call a man happy, not as being happy but as having been so before, surely this is a paradox, that when he is happy the attribute that belongs to him is not to be truly predicated of him because we do not wish to call living men happy, on account of the changes that may befall them, and because we have assumed happiness to be something permanent and by no means easily changed, while a single man may suffer many turns of fortune's wheel. For clearly if we were to keep pace with his fortunes, we should often call the same man happy and again wretched, making the happy man out to be chameleon and insecurely based. Or is this keeping pace with his fortunes quite wrong? Success or failure in life does not depend on these, but human life, as we said,
  • 41. needs these as mere additions, while virtuous activities or their opposites are what constitute happiness or the reverse. The question we have now discussed confirms our definition. For no function of man has so much permanence as virtuous activities (these are thought to be more durable even than knowledge of the sciences), and of these themselves the most valuable are more durable because those who are happy spend their life most readily and most continuously in these; for this seems to be the reason why we do not forget them. The attribute in question, then, will belong to the happy man, and he will be happy throughout his life; for always, or by preference to everything else, he will be engaged in virtuous action and contemplation, and he will bear the chances of life most nobly and altogether decorously, if he is 'truly good' and 'foursquare beyond reproach'. Now many events happen by chance, and events differing in importance; small pieces of good fortune or of its opposite clearly do not weigh down the scales of life one way or the other, but a multitude of great events if they turn out well will make life happier (for not only are they themselves such as to add beauty to life, but the way a man deals with them may be noble and good), while if they turn out ill they crush and maim happiness; for they both bring pain with them and hinder many activities. Yet even in these nobility shines through, when a man bears with resignation many great misfortunes, not through insensibility to pain but through nobility and greatness of soul. If activities are, as we said, what gives life its character, no happy man can become miserable; for he will never do the acts that are hateful and mean. For the man who is truly good and wise, we think, bears all the chances life becomingly and always makes the best of circumstances, as a good general makes the best military use of the army at his command and a good shoemaker makes the best shoes out of the hides that are
  • 42. given him; and so with all other craftsmen. And if this is the case, the happy man can never become miserable; though he will not reach blessedness, if he meet with fortunes like those of Priam. Nor, again, is he many-coloured and changeable; for neither will he be moved from his happy state easily or by any ordinary misadventures, but only by many great ones, nor, if he has had many great misadventures, will he recover his happiness in a short time, but if at all, only in a long and complete one in which he has attained many splendid successes. When then should we not say that he is happy who is active in accordance with complete virtue and is sufficiently equipped with external goods, not for some chance period but throughout a complete life? Or must we add 'and who is destined to live thus and die as befits his life'? Certainly the future is obscure to us, while happiness, we claim, is an end and something in every way final. If so, we shall call happy those among living men in whom these conditions are, and are to be, fulfilled -- but happy men. So much for these questions. Book 1, Chapter 11 That the fortunes of descendants and of all a man's friends should not affect his happiness at all seems a very unfriendly doctrine, and one opposed to the opinions men hold; but since the events that happen are numerous and admit of all sorts of difference, and some come more near to us and others less so, it seems a long -- nay, an infinite -- task to discuss each in detail; a general outline will perhaps suffice. If, then, as some of a man's own misadventures have a certain weight and influence on life while others are, as it were, lighter, so too there are differences among the misadventures of our friends taken as a whole, and it makes a difference whether the various suffering befall the living or the dead (much more even than whether
  • 43. lawless and terrible deeds are presupposed in a tragedy or done on the stage), this difference also must be taken into account; or rather, perhaps, the fact that doubt is felt whether the dead share in any good or evil. For it seems, from these considerations, that even if anything whether good or evil penetrates to them, it must be something weak and negligible, either in itself or for them, or if not, at least it must be such in degree and kind as not to make happy those who are not happy nor to take away their blessedness from those who are. The good or bad fortunes of friends, then, seem to have some effects on the dead, but effects of such a kind and degree as neither to make the happy unhappy nor to produce any other change of the kind. Book 1, Chapter 12 These questions having been definitely answered, let us consider whether happiness is among the things that are praised or rather among the things that are prized; for clearly it is not to be placed among potentialities. Everything that is praised seems to be praised because it is of a certain kind and is related somehow to something else; for we praise the just or brave man and in general both the good man and virtue itself because of the actions and functions involved, and we praise the strong man, the good runner, and so on, because he is of a certain kind and is related in a certain way to something good and important. This is clear also from the praises of the gods; for it seems absurd that the gods should be referred to our standard, but this is done because praise involves a reference, to something else. But if if praise is for things such as we have described, clearly what applies to the best things is not praise, but something greater and better, as is indeed obvious; for what we do to the gods and the most godlike of men is to call them blessed and happy. And so too with good things; no one praises happiness as he does justice, but rather calls it blessed, as being something more divine and better.
  • 44. Eudoxus also seems to have been right in his method of advocating the supremacy of pleasure; he thought that the fact that, though a good, it is not praised indicated it to be better than the things that are praised, and that this is what God and the good are; for by reference to these all other things are judged. Praise is appropriate to virtue, for as a result of virtue men tend to do noble deeds, but encomia are bestowed on acts, whether of the body or of the soul. But perhaps nicety in these matters is more proper to those who have made a study of encomia; to us it is clear from what has been said that happiness is among the things that are prized and perfect. It seems to be so also from the fact that it is a first principle; for it is for the sake of this that we all do all that we do, and the first principle and cause of goods is, we claim, something prized and divine. Book 1, Chapter 13 Since happiness is an activity of soul in accordance with perfect virtue, we must consider the nature of virtue; for perhaps we shall thus see better the nature of happiness. The true student of politics, too, is thought to have studied virtue above all things; for he wishes to make his fellow citizens good and obedient to the laws. As an example of this we have the lawgivers of the Cretans and the Spartans, and any others of the kind that there may have been. And if this inquiry belongs to political science, clearly the pursuit of it will be in accordance with our original plan. But clearly the virtue we must study is human virtue; for the good we were seeking was human good and the happiness human happiness. By human virtue we mean not that of the body but that of the soul; and happiness also we call an activity of soul. But if this is so, clearly the student of politics must know somehow the facts about soul, as the man who is to heal the eyes or the body as a whole must know about the eyes or the body; and all the more since politics is more prized and better than medicine; but even among doctors the best educated spend
  • 45. much labour on acquiring knowledge of the body. The student of politics, then, must study the soul, and must study it with these objects in view, and do so just to the extent which is sufficient for the questions we are discussing; for further precision is perhaps something more laborious than our purposes require. Some things are said about it, adequately enough, even in the discussions outside our school, and we must use these; e.g. that one element in the soul is irrational and one has a rational principle. Whether these are separated as the parts of the body or of anything divisible are, or are distinct by definition but by nature inseparable, like convex and concave in the circumference of a circle, does not affect the present question. Of the irrational element one division seems to be widely distributed, and vegetative in its nature, I mean that which causes nutrition and growth; for it is this kind of power of the soul that one must assign to all nurslings and to embryos, and this same power to fullgrown creatures; this is more reasonable than to assign some different power to them. Now the excellence of this seems to be common to all species and not specifically human; for this part or faculty seems to function most in sleep, while goodness and badness are least manifest in sleep (whence comes the saying that the happy are not better off than the wretched for half their lives; and this happens naturally enough, since sleep is an inactivity of the soul in that respect in which it is called good or bad), unless perhaps to a small extent some of the movements actually penetrate to the soul, and in this respect the dreams of good men are better than those of ordinary people. Enough of this subject, however; let us leave the nutritive faculty alone, since it has by its nature no share in human excellence. There seems to be also another irrational element in the soul -- one which in a sense, however, shares in a rational principle.
  • 46. For we praise the rational principle of the continent man and of the incontinent, and the part of their soul that has such a principle, since it urges them aright and towards the best objects; but there is found in them also another element naturally opposed to the rational principle, which fights against and resists that principle. For exactly as paralysed limbs when we intend to move them to the right turn on the contrary to the left, so is it with the soul; the impulses of incontinent people move in contrary directions. But while in the body we see that which moves astray, in the soul we do not. No doubt, however, we must none the less suppose that in the soul too there is something contrary to the rational principle, resisting and opposing it. In what sense it is distinct from the other elements does not concern us. Now even this seems to have a share in a rational principle, as we said; at any rate in the continent man it obeys the rational principle and presumably in the temperate and brave man it is still more obedient; for in him it speaks, on all matters, with the same voice as the rational principle. Therefore the irrational element also appears to be two-fold. For the vegetative element in no way shares in a rational principle, but the appetitive and in general the desiring element in a sense shares in it, in so far as it listens to and obeys it; this is the sense in which we speak of 'taking account' of one's father or one's friends, not that in which we speak of 'accounting for a mathematical property. That the irrational element is in some sense persuaded by a rational principle is indicated also by the giving of advice and by all reproof and exhortation. And if this element also must be said to have a rational principle, that which has a rational principle (as well as that which has not) will be twofold, one subdivision having it in the strict sense and in itself, and the other having a tendency to obey as one does one's father. Virtue too is distinguished into kinds in accordance with this difference; for we say that some of the virtues are intellectual
  • 47. and others moral, philosophic wisdom and understanding and practical wisdom being intellectual, liberality and temperance moral. For in speaking about a man's character we do not say that he is wise or has understanding but that he is good- tempered or temperate; yet we praise the wise man also with respect to his state of mind; and of states of mind we call those which merit praise virtues. Next BookContents