SlideShare a Scribd company logo
1 of 11
Download to read offline
Invalidating the Claim that it is Unhelpful to refer to
Violence by State Actors as Terrorism
James Peters 14905640
11/4/2014
Invalidating the Claim that it is Unhelpful to refer to Violence by
State Actors as Terrorism
When considering whether or not to classify violence inflicted by states/state agents
that causes destruction whilst instilling fear on a targeted –or wider– audience as “terrorism”,
there are several factors that need to be taken into account. Firstly, as a collective unit
endowed with the mandate to protect its members, can a state illegitimately use its monopoly
on the use of force? Secondly, if there is a limit on the use of force as jus in bello prescribes,
then when is the line crossed by which a state’s actions can be labeled “terroristic”? This then
begs the question of agency versus intent of action and requires this to be juxtaposed against
an accepted definition (or at least a concrete definition for the purpose of this analysis) of
terrorism. Once these three factors have been analyzed and it is determined that there is a
possible category of state violence outside the realm of acceptable use of force, the question
remains should the violence be labeled as state committed terrorism, and if not, then how
should it be claimed? As will be shown, this violence is not existentially different than
terroristic acts committed by non-state organizations and terror groups, thus invalidating
claims that there should be a distinction in applying a terrorist label to actions committed by
states. However as will be shown through the usage of historical examples, the near universal
usage of this kind of force by a wide variety of states in the twentieth century and in our
contemporary world raises the questions, if state powers, great or not, engage in terroristic
activity, then does it fall into yet another acceptable use of state power and are states
normatively wrong for their use of terroristic force?
To answer these questions, one must briefly consider the scope of the theory of
statecraft in justifying state use of force. While it is generally accepted that states have a right
to legitimately use force,1
there is disagreement among political philosophers and theorists as
to how much force can be considered a legitimate use of force. A realist like Kenneth Waltz
would argue that because the international system is dominated by anarchy2
, a state needs to
use enough force to maintain a balance of power in the international system.3
And if strong
state coercion is used, then that is what the state needs to do to maintain its place in the
international order.
1
Waltz (p. 103, 1979)
2
ibid
3
Waltz (p. 117, 1979
If one took the nature of the political as far as Carl Schmitt does, there would be no
violence that falls outside the usage of legitimate state force. As violence equals the ultimate
expression of political action,4
and the state is the “one political community”5
upon which the
friend-enemy distinction is defined, it is state action that defines the community. By engaging
in state violence, a state is expressing the extreme of the friend-enemy distinction6
. Even
when that violence is expressed against an internal faction of the state, it reveals that a
politically polarizing domestic friend-enemy distinction has been created within the state
itself, thus the creation of a new antagonistic political group to the mother state.7
While Schmitt does represent an extreme of the legitimate use of force, it can be
observed through his text that he starts with the same pessimistic view of human nature as
other classical realists by name.8
It can then be argued that his argument is an extreme
evolution of the realist narrative. His focus on state power throughout The Concept of the
Political as being defined and justified by the Political9
fully manifests the realist focus on
state power being central to political authority and the use of violence as being always
justified when used by the state to maintain its authority.
While it would be easy to write off the question of expressible state terrorism here as
being a nonsensical question, the problem of focusing solely on the state’s right to use force
overlooks the factor of scope mentioned in the piece State Terrorism: Issues of Concept and
Measurement. Scope looks beyond whether the state has the right to use force. The scholarly
focus on scope evaluates the nature of a state’s activity and the level of harm inflicted upon
the intended victims and audience.10
Is the nature of the state action proportionate to the
threat to the acting state’s security or interests?
That question of scope can be measured against Just War Theory –jus ad bellum and
jus in bello— and international agreements like the Geneva Convention. If a state has unjustly
used force before all options have been exhausted, if the violence is not sanctioned by a
legitimate authority (the UNSC)11
, if it is not being used in an instance of self-defense (if the
state action is “pre-emptive”), and if it is being fought by the normatively “wrong” intentions,
4
Schmitt (p.33, 2007)
5
Schmitt (p. 45, 2007)
6
Schmitt (p. 33, 2007)
7
Schmitt (p. 32, 2007)
8
Schmitt (p. 61, 2007)
9
The friend-enemy distinction
10
Mitchell, et al. (p. 14, 1986)
11
(UN Charter, Article 7)
then it is in violation of jus ad bellum and is therefore overstepping the post-WWII
international systems accepted jus cogens on the use of force.12
Additionally, if the state’s
actions violate the principles of discrimination13
or proportionality,14
then the scope of
violence can be measured as being a step further from traditional state usage of force and
more akin to the violence of politically motivated non-state actors.15
Hand in hand with jus in bello, is the intensity principle in measuring the qualification
of state violence as terroristic in nature or not.16
Intensity expands beyond scope to include
the ‘frequency of occurrence’17
of violence against a target group. And as is argued by
Blakeley in Contemporary State Terrorism: Theory and Practice, it is not the victims of the
immediate violence that help to create a qualitative distinction between the void of simple
state repression and state sponsored terrorism, but it is the fear of the compliant observers
within the state –the target audience that matters when assessing the frequency of
occurrence.18
If a climate of fear already exists, then a state does not need to commit repeated
offenses in order to ensure order and compliance via terror tactics.
But what is a terror tactic? To paraphrase the definition of terrorism given by the
authors of the Mitchell piece, it can be detailed as a violent action by Actor A against Victim
B with the intention of striking fear in Target C to the extent that Actor A is able to influence
compliance, change or neutrality from Target C.19
One key element in discerning terror
violence from the standard state monopoly on force would be the intent with which the state
wields the force that is used. Meaning, ‘there must be an…element…affecting the behavior
of a target group.’20
As discussed in the Blakeley piece21
, it can be terroristic if it steps
beyond the rules of war outlined in Geneva Convention III (treatment of prisoners of war)22
and IV (treatment of civilians).23
12
(Ferraro, n.d.)
13
Only military targets should be targeted (ibid.)
14
Force should be limited in scope to only what is necessary to end the state of conflict (ibid.)
15
Blakeley (p. 13, 2009)
16
Mitchell, et al. (p. 14, 1986)
17
Ibid.
18
Blakeley (p. 14, 2009)
19
Mitchell, et al. (p. 5, 1986)
20
Mitchell, et al. (p.4, 1986)
21
Blakeley (p. 19, 2009)
22
(Gen. III., 1949)
23
(Gen. IV., 1949
One such example of a terror tactic expanding to a larger audience would be the
Prague Spring. Because the USSR so effectively crushed the rebellion of Prime Minister
Dubcek, a definite message with a terrorizing effect was sent to the other members of the
Warsaw Pact that dissidence would not be tolerated and would be swiftly and violently
ended. This same effect can also be seen at a national level in the example of the
effectiveness of the Stasi in East Germany (DDR). By using the Political Terror Scale of
Mitchell et al., the DDR could easy qualify in their lowest levels (D or E) in terms of
promoting domestic terror at a near national level; ‘murders, disappearances, and torture are a
common part of life…terror affects primarily those who interest themselves in…ideas.’24
This would lend to the thought that terrorism is not necessarily about the agent (non-
state actors as propagated by western media) but rather, it is about the action itself. When
classifying an action as a terroristic action, one must look at its qualitative distinctions. While
most scholars and legal codes will differ in their exact wordings of what terrorism is, they all
hold central themes25
: a violent act, intention to cause coercion of a wider audience, with the
threat of a possible future action of equal scale.26
Blakeley rightly claims that an act labeled
as an act of state terrorism must be consistent with the label used to declare acts committed
by non-state actors as terroristic.27
Therefore the focus of terrorism studies should focus away
from agency to observing the act itself.
This need to focus on the intended outcome of the action when it is committed is
especially stressed by Blakeley throughout her piece. This stands in direct contrast to the
state-centric pre-9/11 narrative that, ‘governmental violence could be so classified [as a
terrorist act].’28
But as she points out, it is nevertheless important to not exclude states from a
group that can be responsible for terrorist actions29
. In fact, because of the social and political
structure created by a state, it is in a far better position than many non-state terrorist
organizations in upholding ‘a pre-existing climate of fear.’30
As there are no major qualitative
differences between state sponsored terrorism and terrorism committed by non-state actors, is
it possible to look briefly at a range of historical examples and organize states into “good”
24
Mitchell, et al. (p. 21, 1986)
25
Blakeley (p. 12, 2009)
26
Chomsky (p. 13, 1991)
27
Blakeley (p. 12, 2009)
28
Becker (p. 91, 2006)
29
(Blakeley, 2009)
30
Blakeley (p. 15, 2009)
states that comply with jus cogens regarding the non-use of terrorism and “evil” states that
are complacent or active proponents of state sponsored terrorism.
To evaluate if such categorization can exist, the five permanent members of the
UNSC, as the five primary states charged with upholding international order and law in the
post-WWII system,31
will be judged on historical examples tested by the determined
definition of terrorism.32
As noted by Blakeley,33
there is no codified international law
officially condemning state terrorism, thus, defining it. Therefore we will use the tested
historical examples to determine if an un-codified jus cogens has been established in
contradicition to standing international law of the United Nations.
As one of five permanent Security Council members, it goes without saying that
Russia (and the USSR before 1992) has been an overt sponsor of state terrorism. Moving
beyond its four and a half decades of sponsoring mercenary client states in the Warsaw Pact
(the Deutsches Demokratic Republik was mentioned above and is one such example or
terroristic states sponsored by the USSR),34
it becomes overtly clear that the USSR itself was
a “terrorist state” in its reaction to the Hungarian Uprising in 1956.35
While the act itself can
be claimed by a realist like Waltz to be within the acceptable use of state power to maintain
the balance of power between the USSR and the Anglo-American led alliance in Western
Europe, when we look at the intentions of the invasion following the revolt, we can then
classify it as a terrorist act.
A major state actor used force against a dissident faction that opposed its power or
influence. The action was done with the intent of compelling a return of Hungarian obedience
to the Soviet model of governance. The swift reaction created an atmosphere of extreme
terror both in Hungary against further revolution and surely inspired fear in other potential
separatist/autonomy movements throughout the Eastern Bloc. This proved to instill a period
of unquestioned soviet control until the Prague Spring just over ten years later.
31
(United Nations Security Council, n.d.)
32
Summed by Blakeley, the definition used in the test cases will be ‘State terrorism involves the deliberate
targeting of individuals that the state has a duty to protect to invoke terror in a wider audience [and this can
be expanded to an international scale by adding a clause that states can sponsor similar violence in a third
state with the intent on coercing that state, its institutions and/or segments of its population to change its
behavior]’ (ibid)
33
(ibid)
34
Similar to the US “employment of mercenary states” Chomsky (p. 15, 1991)
35
(Encyclopaedia Britannica, Hungary)
China too has quite prominently used terror tactics to force its populace into
compliance. Most prominently, the communist government’s brutal reaction to the protesters
at Tiananmen Square showcased a situation in which Actor A (the Chinese government) used
force against Victim B (the student protesters) to enforce continued compliance of the general
populace.36
The brutal crackdown by the government sent a message to the people of China
that the one-party system was to stay in China and that it would not accept any challenge to
that notion.
Likewise, the US has quite infamously used terroristic activities at home to dissuade
convergence from the official party line of the government. The most overt example of the
use of terror in the US would be the McCarthyism era and the Red Scare. The black list of the
House Committee on Un-American Activates stood in complete contrast to the liberal ideal
of free thought and free speech. By its use of the black list and closed door court cases, the
US government successfully created an environment of extreme terror during this period. It
targeted many high profile people throughout the entertainment industry and, like the reaches
of the Stasi, reached down to the average citizen. By prosecuting “communists” on largely
fabricated charges, the fearful frenzy created by “McCarthyism” proved an effective usage of
domestic state-sanctioned terrorism that coerced people into compliance with the government
narrative.
Domestic terrorism has also been used by the two remaining undiscussed UN Security
Council Members: the United Kingdom and France. The British fought fire with fire in North
Ireland. By not openly condemning and properly punishing police officers and members of
the armed forces who used torture as a means to extract information regarding “terrorist
activities” from Catholics during the Northern Ireland conflict,37
the British state condones
the action as a means to an end. This end harms the citizens of Northern Ireland that the
United Kingdom was mandated to protect, thus resulting in a case of state terrorism.38
As
Blakeley argues, state agency is present and an act is terroristic and not criminal if the ruling
government does not prosecute the offending agents of the state to the fullest extent of the
law.39
36
(BBC, 2005)
37
(Cobain, 2010)
38
Blakeley (p. 19, 2009)
39
Blakeley (p. 21, 2009)
The French too have used torture and kidnapping as a means of domestic control
during their attempted annexation of Algeria.40
The years 1956 and 57 were particularly
violent in the state violence propagated against the separatist groups that wanted Algeria to
become independent instead of a part of France.41
The authorization of the use of torture,
kidnappings and execution by officers as high as generals implicate the French in the usage
of state terrorism to regain control of Algeria.42
As discussed in the Blakeley piece, any use
of state force or violence that goes beyond the bounds of war laid out by the Geneva
Convention is a use of force that wanders into the category of state terrorism.43
As Algeria
was a region under French Colonial control, France had responsibility to the citizens beyond
the French settlers of Algeria to protect them. It violated this mandate by the use of extreme
force and terrorist tactics to wrestle military control over the country as its colonial empire
dissolved.
While these are five examples that hold an important political and historical relevance
to the five permanent members of the UNSC, they are a mere drop in the bucket when we
look at the long list of terroristic acts committed by these states. To name off five more quick
examples we could include Russian sponsored terrorism in Eastern Ukraine today, the
terroristic tactics employed by Mao during the Great Leap Forward and the Cultural
Revolution a couple years later, America’s global network of client mercenary states44
and
global network of terror camps like Guantanamo Bay and those in Eastern Europe, the
terroristic tactics used by the British in their attempts to retain imperialist control over India,
and the French application of terroristic methods used in Algeria in their final attempts to
retain control over Vietnam. And this list clearly does not include the endless abuses of
medium and small states against their citizens that would qualify as terroristic: the
disappearance of Argentinian and Chilean citizens during the cold war,45
South Africa’s use
of terrorist tactics to uphold its Apartheid regime, and Iranian support for terrorist
organizations like Hamas.
40
(Thull & Arens, 2001)
41
(Encyclopaedia Britannica, Algerian War)
42
(Martin, 2013)
43
Blakeley (p. 20, 2009)
44
Chomsky (p. 15, 1991)
45
Blakeley (p. 22, 1991)
While this clashes with the normative values of international laws articulated via the
Geneva Convention and the UN Declaration of Human Rights,46
it would seem that state
actors great and small employ the use of terroristic tactics, thus forming a new jus cogens,
and this would seem to validate the claim that a different term should be applied to force used
by state actors or agents of states that engage in violent activities that escape the bounds of
codified use of force. However, this claim is invalid. Along with soft law created by terrorism
scholars and the codified international law, states should be held accountable for the use of
terrorist violence. It is the responsibility of citizens in industrial liberalized republics and the
rest of the world to governments to officially adopt treaties that condemn the use of state
practiced terrorism.
46
(Human Rights, 1948)
Bibliography
Anon., 1948. The Universal Declaration of Human Rights. [Online]
Available at: http://www.un.org/en/documents/udhr/history.shtml
[Accessed 4 November 2014].
Anon., 1949. Convention (III) relative to the Treatment of Prisoners of War. [Online]
Available at: https://www.icrc.org/applic/ihl/ihl.nsf/INTRO/375?OpenDocument
[Accessed 3 November 2014].
Anon., 1949. Convention (IV) relative to the Protection of Civilian Persons. [Online]
Available at: https://www.icrc.org/applic/ihl/ihl.nsf/INTRO/380?OpenDocument
[Accessed 3 November 2014].
Anon., 2005. 1989: Massacre in Tiananmen Square. [Online]
Available at:
http://news.bbc.co.uk/onthisday/hi/dates/stories/june/4/newsid_2496000/2496277.stm
[Accessed 2 November 2014].
Anon., n.d.. Algerian War. [Online]
Available at: http://www.britannica.com/EBchecked/topic/15078/Algerian-War
[Accessed 3 November 2014].
Anon., n.d.. Hungarian Revolution. [Online]
Available at: http://www.britannica.com/EBchecked/topic/276709/Hungarian-Revolution
[Accessed 2 November 2014].
Anon., n.d.. United Nations Security Council. [Online]
Available at: http://www.un.org/en/sc/
[Accessed 2 November 2014].
Becker, T., 2006. Terrorism and the State Rethinking Rules of State Responsibility. Portland: Hart
Publishing.
Blakeley, R., 2009. State Terrorism in the Social Sciences: Theories, Methods and Concepts. In: R.
Jackson, E. Murphy & S. Poynting, eds. Contemporary State Terrorism: Theory and Practice.
unknown: Routledge Ltd, pp. 12-27.
Chomsky, N., 1991 . International Terrorism: Image and Reality. In: A. Goerge, ed. Western State
Terrorism. Padstow: Polity Press, pp. 12-38.
Cobain, I., 2010. Hundreds of Northern Ireland 'terrorists' allege police torture. [Online]
Available at: http://www.theguardian.com/uk/2010/oct/11/northern-ireland-terrorists-
miscarriages-justice
[Accessed 2 November 2014].
Ferraro, V., n.d.. Principles of the Just War. [Online]
Available at: https://www.mtholyoke.edu/acad/intrel/pol116/justwar.htm
[Accessed 1 November 2014].
Martin, D., 2013. Paul Aussaresses, 95, Who Tortured Algerians, Dies. [Online]
Available at: http://www.nytimes.com/2013/12/05/world/europe/paul-aussaresses-95-dies-
confessed-to-torture.html?_r=0
[Accessed 2 November 2014].
Mitchell, C., Stohl, M., Carleton, D. & Lopez, G. A., 1986. State Terrorism: Issues of Concept and
Measurement. In: M. Stohl & G. A. Lopez, eds. Government Violence and Repression: An Agenda for
Research. Westport(Connecticut): Greenwood Press, Inc, pp. 1-25.
Schmitt, C., 2007. The Concept of the Political. Chicago(Il): University of Chicago.
Thull, F. & Arens, M., 2001. Torture in the Algerian war (1954-62). [Online]
Available at: http://www.wsws.org/en/articles/2001/04/alg-a09.html
[Accessed 3 November 2014].
Waltz, K., 1979. Theory of International Politics. 1st ed. s.l.:McGraw-Hill.

More Related Content

What's hot

Federalist Papers No 26, Restraining Legislative Authority Regarding Defense
Federalist Papers No 26, Restraining Legislative Authority Regarding DefenseFederalist Papers No 26, Restraining Legislative Authority Regarding Defense
Federalist Papers No 26, Restraining Legislative Authority Regarding DefenseChuck Thompson
 
"A Visceral Response to GUN CONTROL is not the Answer" by Frank Ricci, Gary C...
"A Visceral Response to GUN CONTROL is not the Answer" by Frank Ricci, Gary C..."A Visceral Response to GUN CONTROL is not the Answer" by Frank Ricci, Gary C...
"A Visceral Response to GUN CONTROL is not the Answer" by Frank Ricci, Gary C...Conceal & Carry Network
 
Coercive-Diplomacy
Coercive-DiplomacyCoercive-Diplomacy
Coercive-DiplomacyJames Peters
 
Arendtian Perspective of the State and Sovereignty Nexus: A Contemporary Inte...
Arendtian Perspective of the State and Sovereignty Nexus: A Contemporary Inte...Arendtian Perspective of the State and Sovereignty Nexus: A Contemporary Inte...
Arendtian Perspective of the State and Sovereignty Nexus: A Contemporary Inte...AJHSSR Journal
 
How to Reverse the Tide of War. A Global People’s Movement. Say No to Nuclear...
How to Reverse the Tide of War. A Global People’s Movement. Say No to Nuclear...How to Reverse the Tide of War. A Global People’s Movement. Say No to Nuclear...
How to Reverse the Tide of War. A Global People’s Movement. Say No to Nuclear...Chris Helweg
 
Coercive diplomacy, 26 11-2012 22h38
Coercive diplomacy, 26 11-2012 22h38Coercive diplomacy, 26 11-2012 22h38
Coercive diplomacy, 26 11-2012 22h38Paulina Méndez
 
Federalist 10
Federalist 10Federalist 10
Federalist 10dficker
 
Tabakian Pols 7 Fall/Spring 2014 Power 4
Tabakian Pols 7 Fall/Spring 2014 Power 4Tabakian Pols 7 Fall/Spring 2014 Power 4
Tabakian Pols 7 Fall/Spring 2014 Power 4John Paul Tabakian
 
Realist theories of global politics
Realist theories of global politicsRealist theories of global politics
Realist theories of global politicsbentogo
 
Fivefold typography of conflict
Fivefold typography of conflictFivefold typography of conflict
Fivefold typography of conflictbentogo
 
Capstone Final_Ian Malis-1
Capstone Final_Ian Malis-1Capstone Final_Ian Malis-1
Capstone Final_Ian Malis-1Ian Malis
 
Why Civil Resistance Works
Why Civil Resistance WorksWhy Civil Resistance Works
Why Civil Resistance WorksMiqui Mel
 
Justifying war
Justifying warJustifying war
Justifying warandeedalal
 
Cv pc+rb2005analysis
Cv pc+rb2005analysisCv pc+rb2005analysis
Cv pc+rb2005analysiskrishna G
 

What's hot (20)

Federalist Papers No 26, Restraining Legislative Authority Regarding Defense
Federalist Papers No 26, Restraining Legislative Authority Regarding DefenseFederalist Papers No 26, Restraining Legislative Authority Regarding Defense
Federalist Papers No 26, Restraining Legislative Authority Regarding Defense
 
final draft
final draftfinal draft
final draft
 
"A Visceral Response to GUN CONTROL is not the Answer" by Frank Ricci, Gary C...
"A Visceral Response to GUN CONTROL is not the Answer" by Frank Ricci, Gary C..."A Visceral Response to GUN CONTROL is not the Answer" by Frank Ricci, Gary C...
"A Visceral Response to GUN CONTROL is not the Answer" by Frank Ricci, Gary C...
 
Fed 45
Fed 45Fed 45
Fed 45
 
Coercive-Diplomacy
Coercive-DiplomacyCoercive-Diplomacy
Coercive-Diplomacy
 
Arendtian Perspective of the State and Sovereignty Nexus: A Contemporary Inte...
Arendtian Perspective of the State and Sovereignty Nexus: A Contemporary Inte...Arendtian Perspective of the State and Sovereignty Nexus: A Contemporary Inte...
Arendtian Perspective of the State and Sovereignty Nexus: A Contemporary Inte...
 
How to Reverse the Tide of War. A Global People’s Movement. Say No to Nuclear...
How to Reverse the Tide of War. A Global People’s Movement. Say No to Nuclear...How to Reverse the Tide of War. A Global People’s Movement. Say No to Nuclear...
How to Reverse the Tide of War. A Global People’s Movement. Say No to Nuclear...
 
Theories of I.R-2
Theories of I.R-2Theories of I.R-2
Theories of I.R-2
 
Coercive diplomacy, 26 11-2012 22h38
Coercive diplomacy, 26 11-2012 22h38Coercive diplomacy, 26 11-2012 22h38
Coercive diplomacy, 26 11-2012 22h38
 
Coercive diplomacy
Coercive diplomacyCoercive diplomacy
Coercive diplomacy
 
Federalist 10
Federalist 10Federalist 10
Federalist 10
 
Tabakian Pols 7 Fall/Spring 2014 Power 4
Tabakian Pols 7 Fall/Spring 2014 Power 4Tabakian Pols 7 Fall/Spring 2014 Power 4
Tabakian Pols 7 Fall/Spring 2014 Power 4
 
Realist theories of global politics
Realist theories of global politicsRealist theories of global politics
Realist theories of global politics
 
Fivefold typography of conflict
Fivefold typography of conflictFivefold typography of conflict
Fivefold typography of conflict
 
GaultGWKWgCdr
GaultGWKWgCdrGaultGWKWgCdr
GaultGWKWgCdr
 
Capstone Final_Ian Malis-1
Capstone Final_Ian Malis-1Capstone Final_Ian Malis-1
Capstone Final_Ian Malis-1
 
Why Civil Resistance Works
Why Civil Resistance WorksWhy Civil Resistance Works
Why Civil Resistance Works
 
Boston Bombings
Boston BombingsBoston Bombings
Boston Bombings
 
Justifying war
Justifying warJustifying war
Justifying war
 
Cv pc+rb2005analysis
Cv pc+rb2005analysisCv pc+rb2005analysis
Cv pc+rb2005analysis
 

Similar to Invalidating the Claim that it is Unhelpful to refer to Violence by State Actors as Terrorism

[2012 12-04 3] - terrorism definition and type
[2012 12-04 3] - terrorism definition and type[2012 12-04 3] - terrorism definition and type
[2012 12-04 3] - terrorism definition and typeCarlos Oliveira
 
Attempts To Define Terrorism Terrorist Or Freedom Fighter
Attempts To Define Terrorism  Terrorist Or Freedom FighterAttempts To Define Terrorism  Terrorist Or Freedom Fighter
Attempts To Define Terrorism Terrorist Or Freedom FighterDustin Pytko
 
Bringing the State Back InEdited byPETER B. EVANS,Br.docx
Bringing the State Back InEdited byPETER B. EVANS,Br.docxBringing the State Back InEdited byPETER B. EVANS,Br.docx
Bringing the State Back InEdited byPETER B. EVANS,Br.docxAASTHA76
 
War Making and State Making as Organized Crime .docx
     War Making and State Making as Organized Crime .docx     War Making and State Making as Organized Crime .docx
War Making and State Making as Organized Crime .docxhallettfaustina
 
A COSMOPOLITANISM OF FEAR THE GLOBAL SIGNIFICANCE OF TERRORISM AFTER THE 9 1...
A COSMOPOLITANISM OF FEAR  THE GLOBAL SIGNIFICANCE OF TERRORISM AFTER THE 9 1...A COSMOPOLITANISM OF FEAR  THE GLOBAL SIGNIFICANCE OF TERRORISM AFTER THE 9 1...
A COSMOPOLITANISM OF FEAR THE GLOBAL SIGNIFICANCE OF TERRORISM AFTER THE 9 1...Whitney Anderson
 
Tactical Adoption of Terrorism by Islamic Insurgency
Tactical Adoption of Terrorism by Islamic InsurgencyTactical Adoption of Terrorism by Islamic Insurgency
Tactical Adoption of Terrorism by Islamic InsurgencyPatrick Thomas Cannon
 
Negotiations with Terrorist Organizations for the Release of Abductees: Betwe...
Negotiations with Terrorist Organizations for the Release of Abductees: Betwe...Negotiations with Terrorist Organizations for the Release of Abductees: Betwe...
Negotiations with Terrorist Organizations for the Release of Abductees: Betwe...Przegląd Politologiczny
 
Military Interventions for Humanitarian Purposes
Military Interventions for Humanitarian PurposesMilitary Interventions for Humanitarian Purposes
Military Interventions for Humanitarian PurposesSilvia Perino Vaiga
 
Online Assignment
Online AssignmentOnline Assignment
Online AssignmentArun Murali
 
Each response is 250 words eachResponse 1Mearsheimer’s orig.docx
Each response is 250 words eachResponse 1Mearsheimer’s orig.docxEach response is 250 words eachResponse 1Mearsheimer’s orig.docx
Each response is 250 words eachResponse 1Mearsheimer’s orig.docxjoellemurphey
 
Chapter 9International RelationsChapter Objectives1. Explain.docx
Chapter 9International RelationsChapter Objectives1. Explain.docxChapter 9International RelationsChapter Objectives1. Explain.docx
Chapter 9International RelationsChapter Objectives1. Explain.docxtiffanyd4
 
Chapter 9International RelationsChapter Objectives1. Explain.docx
Chapter 9International RelationsChapter Objectives1. Explain.docxChapter 9International RelationsChapter Objectives1. Explain.docx
Chapter 9International RelationsChapter Objectives1. Explain.docxmccormicknadine86
 
independent graduate study
independent graduate studyindependent graduate study
independent graduate studyJames Daza
 

Similar to Invalidating the Claim that it is Unhelpful to refer to Violence by State Actors as Terrorism (17)

[2012 12-04 3] - terrorism definition and type
[2012 12-04 3] - terrorism definition and type[2012 12-04 3] - terrorism definition and type
[2012 12-04 3] - terrorism definition and type
 
Terrorism
TerrorismTerrorism
Terrorism
 
Essay On Terrorism In World
Essay On Terrorism In WorldEssay On Terrorism In World
Essay On Terrorism In World
 
Attempts To Define Terrorism Terrorist Or Freedom Fighter
Attempts To Define Terrorism  Terrorist Or Freedom FighterAttempts To Define Terrorism  Terrorist Or Freedom Fighter
Attempts To Define Terrorism Terrorist Or Freedom Fighter
 
Bringing the State Back InEdited byPETER B. EVANS,Br.docx
Bringing the State Back InEdited byPETER B. EVANS,Br.docxBringing the State Back InEdited byPETER B. EVANS,Br.docx
Bringing the State Back InEdited byPETER B. EVANS,Br.docx
 
War Making and State Making as Organized Crime .docx
     War Making and State Making as Organized Crime .docx     War Making and State Making as Organized Crime .docx
War Making and State Making as Organized Crime .docx
 
Terrorism
TerrorismTerrorism
Terrorism
 
A COSMOPOLITANISM OF FEAR THE GLOBAL SIGNIFICANCE OF TERRORISM AFTER THE 9 1...
A COSMOPOLITANISM OF FEAR  THE GLOBAL SIGNIFICANCE OF TERRORISM AFTER THE 9 1...A COSMOPOLITANISM OF FEAR  THE GLOBAL SIGNIFICANCE OF TERRORISM AFTER THE 9 1...
A COSMOPOLITANISM OF FEAR THE GLOBAL SIGNIFICANCE OF TERRORISM AFTER THE 9 1...
 
Tactical Adoption of Terrorism by Islamic Insurgency
Tactical Adoption of Terrorism by Islamic InsurgencyTactical Adoption of Terrorism by Islamic Insurgency
Tactical Adoption of Terrorism by Islamic Insurgency
 
Negotiations with Terrorist Organizations for the Release of Abductees: Betwe...
Negotiations with Terrorist Organizations for the Release of Abductees: Betwe...Negotiations with Terrorist Organizations for the Release of Abductees: Betwe...
Negotiations with Terrorist Organizations for the Release of Abductees: Betwe...
 
Military Interventions for Humanitarian Purposes
Military Interventions for Humanitarian PurposesMilitary Interventions for Humanitarian Purposes
Military Interventions for Humanitarian Purposes
 
Online Assignment
Online AssignmentOnline Assignment
Online Assignment
 
Each response is 250 words eachResponse 1Mearsheimer’s orig.docx
Each response is 250 words eachResponse 1Mearsheimer’s orig.docxEach response is 250 words eachResponse 1Mearsheimer’s orig.docx
Each response is 250 words eachResponse 1Mearsheimer’s orig.docx
 
Chapter 9International RelationsChapter Objectives1. Explain.docx
Chapter 9International RelationsChapter Objectives1. Explain.docxChapter 9International RelationsChapter Objectives1. Explain.docx
Chapter 9International RelationsChapter Objectives1. Explain.docx
 
Chapter 9International RelationsChapter Objectives1. Explain.docx
Chapter 9International RelationsChapter Objectives1. Explain.docxChapter 9International RelationsChapter Objectives1. Explain.docx
Chapter 9International RelationsChapter Objectives1. Explain.docx
 
Are Suspect Terrorists Legitimate Targets of ‘Signature’ Drone Strikes_ Chall...
Are Suspect Terrorists Legitimate Targets of ‘Signature’ Drone Strikes_ Chall...Are Suspect Terrorists Legitimate Targets of ‘Signature’ Drone Strikes_ Chall...
Are Suspect Terrorists Legitimate Targets of ‘Signature’ Drone Strikes_ Chall...
 
independent graduate study
independent graduate studyindependent graduate study
independent graduate study
 

Invalidating the Claim that it is Unhelpful to refer to Violence by State Actors as Terrorism

  • 1. Invalidating the Claim that it is Unhelpful to refer to Violence by State Actors as Terrorism James Peters 14905640 11/4/2014
  • 2. Invalidating the Claim that it is Unhelpful to refer to Violence by State Actors as Terrorism When considering whether or not to classify violence inflicted by states/state agents that causes destruction whilst instilling fear on a targeted –or wider– audience as “terrorism”, there are several factors that need to be taken into account. Firstly, as a collective unit endowed with the mandate to protect its members, can a state illegitimately use its monopoly on the use of force? Secondly, if there is a limit on the use of force as jus in bello prescribes, then when is the line crossed by which a state’s actions can be labeled “terroristic”? This then begs the question of agency versus intent of action and requires this to be juxtaposed against an accepted definition (or at least a concrete definition for the purpose of this analysis) of terrorism. Once these three factors have been analyzed and it is determined that there is a possible category of state violence outside the realm of acceptable use of force, the question remains should the violence be labeled as state committed terrorism, and if not, then how should it be claimed? As will be shown, this violence is not existentially different than terroristic acts committed by non-state organizations and terror groups, thus invalidating claims that there should be a distinction in applying a terrorist label to actions committed by states. However as will be shown through the usage of historical examples, the near universal usage of this kind of force by a wide variety of states in the twentieth century and in our contemporary world raises the questions, if state powers, great or not, engage in terroristic activity, then does it fall into yet another acceptable use of state power and are states normatively wrong for their use of terroristic force? To answer these questions, one must briefly consider the scope of the theory of statecraft in justifying state use of force. While it is generally accepted that states have a right to legitimately use force,1 there is disagreement among political philosophers and theorists as to how much force can be considered a legitimate use of force. A realist like Kenneth Waltz would argue that because the international system is dominated by anarchy2 , a state needs to use enough force to maintain a balance of power in the international system.3 And if strong state coercion is used, then that is what the state needs to do to maintain its place in the international order. 1 Waltz (p. 103, 1979) 2 ibid 3 Waltz (p. 117, 1979
  • 3. If one took the nature of the political as far as Carl Schmitt does, there would be no violence that falls outside the usage of legitimate state force. As violence equals the ultimate expression of political action,4 and the state is the “one political community”5 upon which the friend-enemy distinction is defined, it is state action that defines the community. By engaging in state violence, a state is expressing the extreme of the friend-enemy distinction6 . Even when that violence is expressed against an internal faction of the state, it reveals that a politically polarizing domestic friend-enemy distinction has been created within the state itself, thus the creation of a new antagonistic political group to the mother state.7 While Schmitt does represent an extreme of the legitimate use of force, it can be observed through his text that he starts with the same pessimistic view of human nature as other classical realists by name.8 It can then be argued that his argument is an extreme evolution of the realist narrative. His focus on state power throughout The Concept of the Political as being defined and justified by the Political9 fully manifests the realist focus on state power being central to political authority and the use of violence as being always justified when used by the state to maintain its authority. While it would be easy to write off the question of expressible state terrorism here as being a nonsensical question, the problem of focusing solely on the state’s right to use force overlooks the factor of scope mentioned in the piece State Terrorism: Issues of Concept and Measurement. Scope looks beyond whether the state has the right to use force. The scholarly focus on scope evaluates the nature of a state’s activity and the level of harm inflicted upon the intended victims and audience.10 Is the nature of the state action proportionate to the threat to the acting state’s security or interests? That question of scope can be measured against Just War Theory –jus ad bellum and jus in bello— and international agreements like the Geneva Convention. If a state has unjustly used force before all options have been exhausted, if the violence is not sanctioned by a legitimate authority (the UNSC)11 , if it is not being used in an instance of self-defense (if the state action is “pre-emptive”), and if it is being fought by the normatively “wrong” intentions, 4 Schmitt (p.33, 2007) 5 Schmitt (p. 45, 2007) 6 Schmitt (p. 33, 2007) 7 Schmitt (p. 32, 2007) 8 Schmitt (p. 61, 2007) 9 The friend-enemy distinction 10 Mitchell, et al. (p. 14, 1986) 11 (UN Charter, Article 7)
  • 4. then it is in violation of jus ad bellum and is therefore overstepping the post-WWII international systems accepted jus cogens on the use of force.12 Additionally, if the state’s actions violate the principles of discrimination13 or proportionality,14 then the scope of violence can be measured as being a step further from traditional state usage of force and more akin to the violence of politically motivated non-state actors.15 Hand in hand with jus in bello, is the intensity principle in measuring the qualification of state violence as terroristic in nature or not.16 Intensity expands beyond scope to include the ‘frequency of occurrence’17 of violence against a target group. And as is argued by Blakeley in Contemporary State Terrorism: Theory and Practice, it is not the victims of the immediate violence that help to create a qualitative distinction between the void of simple state repression and state sponsored terrorism, but it is the fear of the compliant observers within the state –the target audience that matters when assessing the frequency of occurrence.18 If a climate of fear already exists, then a state does not need to commit repeated offenses in order to ensure order and compliance via terror tactics. But what is a terror tactic? To paraphrase the definition of terrorism given by the authors of the Mitchell piece, it can be detailed as a violent action by Actor A against Victim B with the intention of striking fear in Target C to the extent that Actor A is able to influence compliance, change or neutrality from Target C.19 One key element in discerning terror violence from the standard state monopoly on force would be the intent with which the state wields the force that is used. Meaning, ‘there must be an…element…affecting the behavior of a target group.’20 As discussed in the Blakeley piece21 , it can be terroristic if it steps beyond the rules of war outlined in Geneva Convention III (treatment of prisoners of war)22 and IV (treatment of civilians).23 12 (Ferraro, n.d.) 13 Only military targets should be targeted (ibid.) 14 Force should be limited in scope to only what is necessary to end the state of conflict (ibid.) 15 Blakeley (p. 13, 2009) 16 Mitchell, et al. (p. 14, 1986) 17 Ibid. 18 Blakeley (p. 14, 2009) 19 Mitchell, et al. (p. 5, 1986) 20 Mitchell, et al. (p.4, 1986) 21 Blakeley (p. 19, 2009) 22 (Gen. III., 1949) 23 (Gen. IV., 1949
  • 5. One such example of a terror tactic expanding to a larger audience would be the Prague Spring. Because the USSR so effectively crushed the rebellion of Prime Minister Dubcek, a definite message with a terrorizing effect was sent to the other members of the Warsaw Pact that dissidence would not be tolerated and would be swiftly and violently ended. This same effect can also be seen at a national level in the example of the effectiveness of the Stasi in East Germany (DDR). By using the Political Terror Scale of Mitchell et al., the DDR could easy qualify in their lowest levels (D or E) in terms of promoting domestic terror at a near national level; ‘murders, disappearances, and torture are a common part of life…terror affects primarily those who interest themselves in…ideas.’24 This would lend to the thought that terrorism is not necessarily about the agent (non- state actors as propagated by western media) but rather, it is about the action itself. When classifying an action as a terroristic action, one must look at its qualitative distinctions. While most scholars and legal codes will differ in their exact wordings of what terrorism is, they all hold central themes25 : a violent act, intention to cause coercion of a wider audience, with the threat of a possible future action of equal scale.26 Blakeley rightly claims that an act labeled as an act of state terrorism must be consistent with the label used to declare acts committed by non-state actors as terroristic.27 Therefore the focus of terrorism studies should focus away from agency to observing the act itself. This need to focus on the intended outcome of the action when it is committed is especially stressed by Blakeley throughout her piece. This stands in direct contrast to the state-centric pre-9/11 narrative that, ‘governmental violence could be so classified [as a terrorist act].’28 But as she points out, it is nevertheless important to not exclude states from a group that can be responsible for terrorist actions29 . In fact, because of the social and political structure created by a state, it is in a far better position than many non-state terrorist organizations in upholding ‘a pre-existing climate of fear.’30 As there are no major qualitative differences between state sponsored terrorism and terrorism committed by non-state actors, is it possible to look briefly at a range of historical examples and organize states into “good” 24 Mitchell, et al. (p. 21, 1986) 25 Blakeley (p. 12, 2009) 26 Chomsky (p. 13, 1991) 27 Blakeley (p. 12, 2009) 28 Becker (p. 91, 2006) 29 (Blakeley, 2009) 30 Blakeley (p. 15, 2009)
  • 6. states that comply with jus cogens regarding the non-use of terrorism and “evil” states that are complacent or active proponents of state sponsored terrorism. To evaluate if such categorization can exist, the five permanent members of the UNSC, as the five primary states charged with upholding international order and law in the post-WWII system,31 will be judged on historical examples tested by the determined definition of terrorism.32 As noted by Blakeley,33 there is no codified international law officially condemning state terrorism, thus, defining it. Therefore we will use the tested historical examples to determine if an un-codified jus cogens has been established in contradicition to standing international law of the United Nations. As one of five permanent Security Council members, it goes without saying that Russia (and the USSR before 1992) has been an overt sponsor of state terrorism. Moving beyond its four and a half decades of sponsoring mercenary client states in the Warsaw Pact (the Deutsches Demokratic Republik was mentioned above and is one such example or terroristic states sponsored by the USSR),34 it becomes overtly clear that the USSR itself was a “terrorist state” in its reaction to the Hungarian Uprising in 1956.35 While the act itself can be claimed by a realist like Waltz to be within the acceptable use of state power to maintain the balance of power between the USSR and the Anglo-American led alliance in Western Europe, when we look at the intentions of the invasion following the revolt, we can then classify it as a terrorist act. A major state actor used force against a dissident faction that opposed its power or influence. The action was done with the intent of compelling a return of Hungarian obedience to the Soviet model of governance. The swift reaction created an atmosphere of extreme terror both in Hungary against further revolution and surely inspired fear in other potential separatist/autonomy movements throughout the Eastern Bloc. This proved to instill a period of unquestioned soviet control until the Prague Spring just over ten years later. 31 (United Nations Security Council, n.d.) 32 Summed by Blakeley, the definition used in the test cases will be ‘State terrorism involves the deliberate targeting of individuals that the state has a duty to protect to invoke terror in a wider audience [and this can be expanded to an international scale by adding a clause that states can sponsor similar violence in a third state with the intent on coercing that state, its institutions and/or segments of its population to change its behavior]’ (ibid) 33 (ibid) 34 Similar to the US “employment of mercenary states” Chomsky (p. 15, 1991) 35 (Encyclopaedia Britannica, Hungary)
  • 7. China too has quite prominently used terror tactics to force its populace into compliance. Most prominently, the communist government’s brutal reaction to the protesters at Tiananmen Square showcased a situation in which Actor A (the Chinese government) used force against Victim B (the student protesters) to enforce continued compliance of the general populace.36 The brutal crackdown by the government sent a message to the people of China that the one-party system was to stay in China and that it would not accept any challenge to that notion. Likewise, the US has quite infamously used terroristic activities at home to dissuade convergence from the official party line of the government. The most overt example of the use of terror in the US would be the McCarthyism era and the Red Scare. The black list of the House Committee on Un-American Activates stood in complete contrast to the liberal ideal of free thought and free speech. By its use of the black list and closed door court cases, the US government successfully created an environment of extreme terror during this period. It targeted many high profile people throughout the entertainment industry and, like the reaches of the Stasi, reached down to the average citizen. By prosecuting “communists” on largely fabricated charges, the fearful frenzy created by “McCarthyism” proved an effective usage of domestic state-sanctioned terrorism that coerced people into compliance with the government narrative. Domestic terrorism has also been used by the two remaining undiscussed UN Security Council Members: the United Kingdom and France. The British fought fire with fire in North Ireland. By not openly condemning and properly punishing police officers and members of the armed forces who used torture as a means to extract information regarding “terrorist activities” from Catholics during the Northern Ireland conflict,37 the British state condones the action as a means to an end. This end harms the citizens of Northern Ireland that the United Kingdom was mandated to protect, thus resulting in a case of state terrorism.38 As Blakeley argues, state agency is present and an act is terroristic and not criminal if the ruling government does not prosecute the offending agents of the state to the fullest extent of the law.39 36 (BBC, 2005) 37 (Cobain, 2010) 38 Blakeley (p. 19, 2009) 39 Blakeley (p. 21, 2009)
  • 8. The French too have used torture and kidnapping as a means of domestic control during their attempted annexation of Algeria.40 The years 1956 and 57 were particularly violent in the state violence propagated against the separatist groups that wanted Algeria to become independent instead of a part of France.41 The authorization of the use of torture, kidnappings and execution by officers as high as generals implicate the French in the usage of state terrorism to regain control of Algeria.42 As discussed in the Blakeley piece, any use of state force or violence that goes beyond the bounds of war laid out by the Geneva Convention is a use of force that wanders into the category of state terrorism.43 As Algeria was a region under French Colonial control, France had responsibility to the citizens beyond the French settlers of Algeria to protect them. It violated this mandate by the use of extreme force and terrorist tactics to wrestle military control over the country as its colonial empire dissolved. While these are five examples that hold an important political and historical relevance to the five permanent members of the UNSC, they are a mere drop in the bucket when we look at the long list of terroristic acts committed by these states. To name off five more quick examples we could include Russian sponsored terrorism in Eastern Ukraine today, the terroristic tactics employed by Mao during the Great Leap Forward and the Cultural Revolution a couple years later, America’s global network of client mercenary states44 and global network of terror camps like Guantanamo Bay and those in Eastern Europe, the terroristic tactics used by the British in their attempts to retain imperialist control over India, and the French application of terroristic methods used in Algeria in their final attempts to retain control over Vietnam. And this list clearly does not include the endless abuses of medium and small states against their citizens that would qualify as terroristic: the disappearance of Argentinian and Chilean citizens during the cold war,45 South Africa’s use of terrorist tactics to uphold its Apartheid regime, and Iranian support for terrorist organizations like Hamas. 40 (Thull & Arens, 2001) 41 (Encyclopaedia Britannica, Algerian War) 42 (Martin, 2013) 43 Blakeley (p. 20, 2009) 44 Chomsky (p. 15, 1991) 45 Blakeley (p. 22, 1991)
  • 9. While this clashes with the normative values of international laws articulated via the Geneva Convention and the UN Declaration of Human Rights,46 it would seem that state actors great and small employ the use of terroristic tactics, thus forming a new jus cogens, and this would seem to validate the claim that a different term should be applied to force used by state actors or agents of states that engage in violent activities that escape the bounds of codified use of force. However, this claim is invalid. Along with soft law created by terrorism scholars and the codified international law, states should be held accountable for the use of terrorist violence. It is the responsibility of citizens in industrial liberalized republics and the rest of the world to governments to officially adopt treaties that condemn the use of state practiced terrorism. 46 (Human Rights, 1948)
  • 10. Bibliography Anon., 1948. The Universal Declaration of Human Rights. [Online] Available at: http://www.un.org/en/documents/udhr/history.shtml [Accessed 4 November 2014]. Anon., 1949. Convention (III) relative to the Treatment of Prisoners of War. [Online] Available at: https://www.icrc.org/applic/ihl/ihl.nsf/INTRO/375?OpenDocument [Accessed 3 November 2014]. Anon., 1949. Convention (IV) relative to the Protection of Civilian Persons. [Online] Available at: https://www.icrc.org/applic/ihl/ihl.nsf/INTRO/380?OpenDocument [Accessed 3 November 2014]. Anon., 2005. 1989: Massacre in Tiananmen Square. [Online] Available at: http://news.bbc.co.uk/onthisday/hi/dates/stories/june/4/newsid_2496000/2496277.stm [Accessed 2 November 2014]. Anon., n.d.. Algerian War. [Online] Available at: http://www.britannica.com/EBchecked/topic/15078/Algerian-War [Accessed 3 November 2014]. Anon., n.d.. Hungarian Revolution. [Online] Available at: http://www.britannica.com/EBchecked/topic/276709/Hungarian-Revolution [Accessed 2 November 2014]. Anon., n.d.. United Nations Security Council. [Online] Available at: http://www.un.org/en/sc/ [Accessed 2 November 2014]. Becker, T., 2006. Terrorism and the State Rethinking Rules of State Responsibility. Portland: Hart Publishing. Blakeley, R., 2009. State Terrorism in the Social Sciences: Theories, Methods and Concepts. In: R. Jackson, E. Murphy & S. Poynting, eds. Contemporary State Terrorism: Theory and Practice. unknown: Routledge Ltd, pp. 12-27. Chomsky, N., 1991 . International Terrorism: Image and Reality. In: A. Goerge, ed. Western State Terrorism. Padstow: Polity Press, pp. 12-38. Cobain, I., 2010. Hundreds of Northern Ireland 'terrorists' allege police torture. [Online] Available at: http://www.theguardian.com/uk/2010/oct/11/northern-ireland-terrorists- miscarriages-justice [Accessed 2 November 2014]. Ferraro, V., n.d.. Principles of the Just War. [Online] Available at: https://www.mtholyoke.edu/acad/intrel/pol116/justwar.htm [Accessed 1 November 2014].
  • 11. Martin, D., 2013. Paul Aussaresses, 95, Who Tortured Algerians, Dies. [Online] Available at: http://www.nytimes.com/2013/12/05/world/europe/paul-aussaresses-95-dies- confessed-to-torture.html?_r=0 [Accessed 2 November 2014]. Mitchell, C., Stohl, M., Carleton, D. & Lopez, G. A., 1986. State Terrorism: Issues of Concept and Measurement. In: M. Stohl & G. A. Lopez, eds. Government Violence and Repression: An Agenda for Research. Westport(Connecticut): Greenwood Press, Inc, pp. 1-25. Schmitt, C., 2007. The Concept of the Political. Chicago(Il): University of Chicago. Thull, F. & Arens, M., 2001. Torture in the Algerian war (1954-62). [Online] Available at: http://www.wsws.org/en/articles/2001/04/alg-a09.html [Accessed 3 November 2014]. Waltz, K., 1979. Theory of International Politics. 1st ed. s.l.:McGraw-Hill.