SlideShare a Scribd company logo
1 of 34
Download to read offline
Intermediate
microeconomics:
Lecture 2
Risk and Expected
utility
Risk attitude
Application to
insurance market
Intermediate microeconomics: Lecture 2
March 7, 2013
Intermediate
microeconomics:
Lecture 2
Risk and Expected
utility
Risk attitude
Application to
insurance market
Risk
◮ Many economic choice is risky in the sense that the
outcome is not certain.
◮ Project choice
◮ Investment decision
◮ Occupational choice
◮ Marriage decision
Intermediate
microeconomics:
Lecture 2
Risk and Expected
utility
Risk attitude
Application to
insurance market
Risky choice as lottery
◮ A decision problem under risk can be interpreted as a
choice of “lotteries”.
◮ Project choice
◮ If the future economic condition is good, your project
yields $1000
◮ If it is bad, your project yields $0.
◮ If the probability of having a good economy is 20%, it is
a lottery such that $1000 with 20% and $0 with 80%
Intermediate
microeconomics:
Lecture 2
Risk and Expected
utility
Risk attitude
Application to
insurance market
Notation
◮ If the probability of having a good economy is 20%, it is
a lottery such that $1000 with 20% and $0 with 80%
◮ Formally, the above lottery can be written as
L = (x1,x2;p1,p2) = (1000,0;0.2,0.8)
Intermediate
microeconomics:
Lecture 2
Risk and Expected
utility
Risk attitude
Application to
insurance market
Example
◮ Which is your favorite lottery?
◮ L1 = (10,10;0.5,0.5)
◮ L2 = (0,20;0.5,0.5)
◮ L3 = (5,10;0.2,08)
Intermediate
microeconomics:
Lecture 2
Risk and Expected
utility
Risk attitude
Application to
insurance market
Preference over lotteries
◮ As Lecture 1, define a preference over lotteries, e.g.,
L1 ≻ L2 ≻ L3.
◮ If your taste is transitive and complete, it is rational
preference.
◮ Then, you have a utility function U(L) that represents
your taste for lotteries.
◮ However, you might want more intuitive and useful
representation.
Intermediate
microeconomics:
Lecture 2
Risk and Expected
utility
Risk attitude
Application to
insurance market
Expected value
◮ If it is a lottery, how about the average or expected
value?
◮ That is,
U(L) = p(x1)x1 +p(x2)x2
◮ More generally, if there are N possible outcomes,
U(L) = ∑
n
p(xn)xn
Intermediate
microeconomics:
Lecture 2
Risk and Expected
utility
Risk attitude
Application to
insurance market
Problem
◮ Note that if L1 = (10,10;0.5,0.5) and
L2 = (0,20;0.5,0.5), then U(L1) = U(L2) if U is the
expected value.
◮ Thus, unless you find L1 and L2 indifferent, this is not
right way to represent your preference.
◮ In other words, the expected value cannot reflect your
attitude toward risk.
Intermediate
microeconomics:
Lecture 2
Risk and Expected
utility
Risk attitude
Application to
insurance market
Expected utility
◮ There is an alternative way.
◮ Expected utility theory represents your preference with
the following form
U(L) = p(x1)u(x1)+p(x2)u(x2)
◮ More generally, if there are many possible outcomes
U(L) = ∑
n
p(xn)u(xn)
Intermediate
microeconomics:
Lecture 2
Risk and Expected
utility
Risk attitude
Application to
insurance market
Example
◮ Suppose you cast a dice. If your get x ∈ {1,2,..,6}, you
receives $x.
◮ The expected utility is
EU(x) =
1
6
[u(1)+u(2)+u(3)+u(4)+u(5)+u(6)]
◮ For example, if u(x) =
√
x, then EU(x) = 1.805303682
Intermediate
microeconomics:
Lecture 2
Risk and Expected
utility
Risk attitude
Application to
insurance market
When does EU exist?
◮ We learn that a preference can be represented by a
utility if and only if the preference is rational.
◮ When can a preference over lotteries be represented by
an expected utility?
◮ In other words, what is the condition that guarantees
existence of u(x) such that
L′
L′′
if and only if
∑
n
pL′ (xn)u(xn) ≥ ∑
n
pL′′ (xn)u(xn)
Intermediate
microeconomics:
Lecture 2
Risk and Expected
utility
Risk attitude
Application to
insurance market
Continuity
Definition
A preference over lotteries satisfies continuity assumption if,
for any lotteries L′,L′′,L′′′ such that L′ L′′ L′′′, there
exists α ∈ (0,1) such that αL′ +(1−α)L′′′ ∼ L′′
◮ Roughly put, a small change of a probability can make a
small change in your preference.
Intermediate
microeconomics:
Lecture 2
Risk and Expected
utility
Risk attitude
Application to
insurance market
Independence
Definition
A preference over lotteries satisfies independence
assumption if, for any lotteries L′,L′′,L′′′ such that L′ L′′,
αL′ +(1−α)L′′′ αL′′ +(1−α)L′′′ for any α ∈ (0,1].
◮ Roughly put, if you expand two lotteries with a common
lottery, it should not affect preference over the two
lotteries.
Intermediate
microeconomics:
Lecture 2
Risk and Expected
utility
Risk attitude
Application to
insurance market
The condition
◮ The following result is known.
Proposition
There exists an expected utility that represents a preference
over lotteries if and only if the preference is rational and
satisfies the continuity and independence assumptions.
Intermediate
microeconomics:
Lecture 2
Risk and Expected
utility
Risk attitude
Application to
insurance market
Risk attitude
◮ The expected value cannot capture a risk attitude.
◮ If L1 = (10,10;0.5,0.5) and L2 = (0,20;0.5,0.5), then
what can we say about U(L1) vs. U(L2) if U is the
expected utility?
◮ Can the expected utility capture a risk attitude?
Intermediate
microeconomics:
Lecture 2
Risk and Expected
utility
Risk attitude
Application to
insurance market
Risk aversion
◮ Suppose u(x) = xα (other functional form can be also
possible)
◮ Suppose you prefer L1 to L2, that is, you are risk
averse.
◮ Then choose α ∈ (0,1), say 1/2
◮ Then,
1
2101/2 + 1
2101/2 = 101/2 = 3.162 > 1
2201/2 = 2.236.
◮ So α < 1 represents that you are risk averse.
Intermediate
microeconomics:
Lecture 2
Risk and Expected
utility
Risk attitude
Application to
insurance market
Risk aversion and concavity
◮ If u(x) is strictly concave, then the agent is always risk
averse.
◮ u(x) = ln(x)
◮ u(x) =
√
x
Intermediate
microeconomics:
Lecture 2
Risk and Expected
utility
Risk attitude
Application to
insurance market
Risk loving
◮ Suppose you prefer L2 to L1, that is, you are a risk
lover.
◮ Then choose α > 1 in your xα.
◮ Then, 1
2102 + 1
2102 = 102 = 100 < 1
2202 = 200.
◮ So α > 1 represents that you are a risk lover.
Intermediate
microeconomics:
Lecture 2
Risk and Expected
utility
Risk attitude
Application to
insurance market
Risk loving and convexity
◮ If u(x) is strictly convex, then the agent is always risk
averse.
◮ u(x) = x3
◮ u(x) = ex
Intermediate
microeconomics:
Lecture 2
Risk and Expected
utility
Risk attitude
Application to
insurance market
Risk neutrality
◮ If α = 1, then the expected utility becomes the
expected value.
◮ 1
210+ 1
210 = 10 = 1
220.
◮ That is, L1 and L2 are indifferent.
◮ So α = 1 means that you are risk neutral.
Intermediate
microeconomics:
Lecture 2
Risk and Expected
utility
Risk attitude
Application to
insurance market
Risk neutrality and linearity
◮ if u(x) is linear, then the agent is always risk averse.
◮ u(x) = 4x
◮ u(x) = 0.3x
Intermediate
microeconomics:
Lecture 2
Risk and Expected
utility
Risk attitude
Application to
insurance market
Certainty equivalent
◮ L = (x,y;p,1−p)
◮ Consider z such that u(z) = pu(x)+(1−p)u(y)
◮ That is, you are indifferent between certain z dollar and
lottery L.
◮ Then, z is called certainty equivalent of L
◮ If you are risk averse, z < px +(1−p)y.
◮ If you are risk neutral, z = px +(1−p)y.
Intermediate
microeconomics:
Lecture 2
Risk and Expected
utility
Risk attitude
Application to
insurance market
Risk premium
◮ Risk premium of L is an extra money that can be paid
to compensate the risk of L.
◮ Formally, we can define risk premium as
px +(1−p)y −z.
◮ Note that if the agent is risk neutral z = px +(1−p)y
and thus, the risk premium is always 0.
Intermediate
microeconomics:
Lecture 2
Risk and Expected
utility
Risk attitude
Application to
insurance market
Example
◮ L = (10,60;0.5,0.5) and u(x) = 100x − x2
2
◮ pu(x)+(1−p)u(y) = 1
2(1000−50)+ 1
2 (6000−1800) =
2625
Intermediate
microeconomics:
Lecture 2
Risk and Expected
utility
Risk attitude
Application to
insurance market
Example
◮ Certainty equivalence z solves u(z) = 2625 or
0 = z2
−200z +5250
◮ The certainty equivalent is
z =
200−
√
40000−21000
2
≈ 31
◮ Risk premium is
1
2
10+
1
2
60−31 = 4
Intermediate
microeconomics:
Lecture 2
Risk and Expected
utility
Risk attitude
Application to
insurance market
Insurance
◮ Consider the following simple insurance market.
◮ Suppose that the probability of having an accident is
known as p.
◮ The accident could make your income from 100 to 0.
◮ Insurance guarantees you to have 100 all the time as
long as you pay $q.
Intermediate
microeconomics:
Lecture 2
Risk and Expected
utility
Risk attitude
Application to
insurance market
Expected utility
◮ So with the insurance, your utility is
U(100−q)
.
◮ On the other hand, without the insurance, your
expected utility is
(1−p)U(100)+pU(0)
.
Intermediate
microeconomics:
Lecture 2
Risk and Expected
utility
Risk attitude
Application to
insurance market
Buyer’s problem
◮ You buy the insurance if your utility from buying is
higher than your expected utility from facing
uncertainty.
◮ That is,
(1−p)U(100)+pU(0) ≤ U(100−q)
Intermediate
microeconomics:
Lecture 2
Risk and Expected
utility
Risk attitude
Application to
insurance market
Seller’s problem
◮ The insurance company has to make sure that
◮ she can sell the product (Sale’s condition)
◮ the profit is not negative (Profitability condition)
Intermediate
microeconomics:
Lecture 2
Risk and Expected
utility
Risk attitude
Application to
insurance market
Sale’s condition
◮ Recall the certainty equivalent of L = (0,100;p,1−p) is
z such that
U(z) = (1−p)U(100)+pU(0)
◮ Then, the consumer prefers to buy the insurance as long
as 100−q ≥ z or
q ≤ 100−z
◮ Thus, the insurance company has to choose q so that it
satisfies the above condition to sell the insurance.
Intermediate
microeconomics:
Lecture 2
Risk and Expected
utility
Risk attitude
Application to
insurance market
Profitability condition
◮ The insurance company gets q but they have to pay
100 with probability p. Thus, their expected profit
given q is q −100p.
◮ Thus, q has to be q ≥ 100p to keep her profit
non-negative.
Intermediate
microeconomics:
Lecture 2
Risk and Expected
utility
Risk attitude
Application to
insurance market
Trading condition
◮ The trade occurs if and only if the sale’s condition and
the profitability condition are both satisfied.
◮ In other words, q has to be
100−z ≥ q ≥ 100p
Intermediate
microeconomics:
Lecture 2
Risk and Expected
utility
Risk attitude
Application to
insurance market
Risk neutral buyer
◮ If you are risk neutral, z = (1−p)100. Then,
100−z = 100p
◮ Thus, q = 100p is the only value that satisfies the
trading condition
100−z ≥ q ≥ 100p
◮ Then, the expected profit is always 0.
Intermediate
microeconomics:
Lecture 2
Risk and Expected
utility
Risk attitude
Application to
insurance market
Risk aversion
◮ Recall that if you are risk averse, z < (1−p)100. Then,
100−z > 100p
◮ Thus, by choosing q such that
100−z > q > 100p,
the company earns a positive profit and the consumer
buys the insurance.

More Related Content

Viewers also liked

Study ties use of dialysis catheters to greater infection risk in patients
Study ties use of dialysis catheters to greater infection risk in patientsStudy ties use of dialysis catheters to greater infection risk in patients
Study ties use of dialysis catheters to greater infection risk in patientsdialysisinjuryhelpline
 
Posimat presentation cosmetics aropak rus
Posimat presentation   cosmetics aropak rusPosimat presentation   cosmetics aropak rus
Posimat presentation cosmetics aropak rusaropak
 
Fanartikel Robbie Williams
Fanartikel Robbie WilliamsFanartikel Robbie Williams
Fanartikel Robbie WilliamsInes Zacherl
 
Eval question 1 version 2
Eval question 1 version 2Eval question 1 version 2
Eval question 1 version 2jESSicaN6
 
The Art of Readable Code - DongPV
The Art of Readable Code - DongPVThe Art of Readable Code - DongPV
The Art of Readable Code - DongPVĐông Đô
 
Mengapa orang mentaati hukum
Mengapa orang mentaati hukumMengapa orang mentaati hukum
Mengapa orang mentaati hukumNovita Ekasari
 
Lucrare
LucrareLucrare
Lucraredanagb
 
Analisis leverage
Analisis leverageAnalisis leverage
Analisis leverageSere Wax's
 
TDD (Test Driven Development)
TDD (Test Driven Development)TDD (Test Driven Development)
TDD (Test Driven Development)Đông Đô
 
Factores de riesgo fisicos
Factores de riesgo fisicosFactores de riesgo fisicos
Factores de riesgo fisicosJuan Pablo
 

Viewers also liked (15)

Study ties use of dialysis catheters to greater infection risk in patients
Study ties use of dialysis catheters to greater infection risk in patientsStudy ties use of dialysis catheters to greater infection risk in patients
Study ties use of dialysis catheters to greater infection risk in patients
 
Posimat presentation cosmetics aropak rus
Posimat presentation   cosmetics aropak rusPosimat presentation   cosmetics aropak rus
Posimat presentation cosmetics aropak rus
 
Fanartikel Robbie Williams
Fanartikel Robbie WilliamsFanartikel Robbie Williams
Fanartikel Robbie Williams
 
Eval question 1 version 2
Eval question 1 version 2Eval question 1 version 2
Eval question 1 version 2
 
Infotmatica 2
Infotmatica 2Infotmatica 2
Infotmatica 2
 
Pair programing
Pair programingPair programing
Pair programing
 
The Art of Readable Code - DongPV
The Art of Readable Code - DongPVThe Art of Readable Code - DongPV
The Art of Readable Code - DongPV
 
Mengapa orang mentaati hukum
Mengapa orang mentaati hukumMengapa orang mentaati hukum
Mengapa orang mentaati hukum
 
Lucrare
LucrareLucrare
Lucrare
 
13 geologictime
13 geologictime13 geologictime
13 geologictime
 
Obesity Project
Obesity ProjectObesity Project
Obesity Project
 
Analisis leverage
Analisis leverageAnalisis leverage
Analisis leverage
 
Latest CV of Gangadhar
Latest CV of GangadharLatest CV of Gangadhar
Latest CV of Gangadhar
 
TDD (Test Driven Development)
TDD (Test Driven Development)TDD (Test Driven Development)
TDD (Test Driven Development)
 
Factores de riesgo fisicos
Factores de riesgo fisicosFactores de riesgo fisicos
Factores de riesgo fisicos
 

Similar to Lecture 2

Business CycleDenecia Brown, Shawna Baumert, Firas Far.docx
Business CycleDenecia Brown, Shawna Baumert, Firas Far.docxBusiness CycleDenecia Brown, Shawna Baumert, Firas Far.docx
Business CycleDenecia Brown, Shawna Baumert, Firas Far.docxhumphrieskalyn
 
ECON 417 Economics of UncertaintyContentsI Expected U.docx
ECON 417 Economics of UncertaintyContentsI Expected U.docxECON 417 Economics of UncertaintyContentsI Expected U.docx
ECON 417 Economics of UncertaintyContentsI Expected U.docxjack60216
 
Microeconomics Uncertainty
Microeconomics UncertaintyMicroeconomics Uncertainty
Microeconomics UncertaintyRakesh Mehta
 
Criticism on Li's Copula Approach
Criticism on Li's Copula ApproachCriticism on Li's Copula Approach
Criticism on Li's Copula ApproachOleguer Sagarra
 
UNCERTAINITY AND CONSUMER BEHAVIOUR PPT.pptx
UNCERTAINITY AND CONSUMER BEHAVIOUR PPT.pptxUNCERTAINITY AND CONSUMER BEHAVIOUR PPT.pptx
UNCERTAINITY AND CONSUMER BEHAVIOUR PPT.pptxAroutselvamChanemoug1
 
lecture_9_uncertainty.pdf
lecture_9_uncertainty.pdflecture_9_uncertainty.pdf
lecture_9_uncertainty.pdfMUHAMMADAKANJI1
 
Risk and Risk Aversion FM
Risk and Risk Aversion FMRisk and Risk Aversion FM
Risk and Risk Aversion FMFellowBuddy.com
 
Principles of Actuarial Science Chapter 1
Principles of Actuarial Science Chapter 1Principles of Actuarial Science Chapter 1
Principles of Actuarial Science Chapter 1ssuser8226b2
 
Sensitivity &amp; Scenario Analysis
Sensitivity &amp; Scenario AnalysisSensitivity &amp; Scenario Analysis
Sensitivity &amp; Scenario AnalysisDr. Rana Singh
 
the basic tools of finance ch 14.pptx
the basic tools of finance ch 14.pptxthe basic tools of finance ch 14.pptx
the basic tools of finance ch 14.pptxChusmanAhmed2
 
CABT SHS Statistics & Probability - Expected Value and Variance of Discrete P...
CABT SHS Statistics & Probability - Expected Value and Variance of Discrete P...CABT SHS Statistics & Probability - Expected Value and Variance of Discrete P...
CABT SHS Statistics & Probability - Expected Value and Variance of Discrete P...Gilbert Joseph Abueg
 
Financial Regulation Lecture 9Based on notes by Marlena El.docx
Financial Regulation Lecture 9Based on notes by Marlena El.docxFinancial Regulation Lecture 9Based on notes by Marlena El.docx
Financial Regulation Lecture 9Based on notes by Marlena El.docxericn8
 
Cramton2014a Risk Theory (slides).pdf
Cramton2014a Risk Theory (slides).pdfCramton2014a Risk Theory (slides).pdf
Cramton2014a Risk Theory (slides).pdfYumiHosen
 
Chapter 3. Arbitrage (asset) pricing theoryNeil Wallace.docx
Chapter 3. Arbitrage (asset) pricing theoryNeil Wallace.docxChapter 3. Arbitrage (asset) pricing theoryNeil Wallace.docx
Chapter 3. Arbitrage (asset) pricing theoryNeil Wallace.docxchristinemaritza
 

Similar to Lecture 2 (20)

Risk
RiskRisk
Risk
 
Business CycleDenecia Brown, Shawna Baumert, Firas Far.docx
Business CycleDenecia Brown, Shawna Baumert, Firas Far.docxBusiness CycleDenecia Brown, Shawna Baumert, Firas Far.docx
Business CycleDenecia Brown, Shawna Baumert, Firas Far.docx
 
ECON 417 Economics of UncertaintyContentsI Expected U.docx
ECON 417 Economics of UncertaintyContentsI Expected U.docxECON 417 Economics of UncertaintyContentsI Expected U.docx
ECON 417 Economics of UncertaintyContentsI Expected U.docx
 
Microeconomics Uncertainty
Microeconomics UncertaintyMicroeconomics Uncertainty
Microeconomics Uncertainty
 
Criticism on Li's Copula Approach
Criticism on Li's Copula ApproachCriticism on Li's Copula Approach
Criticism on Li's Copula Approach
 
Prospect Theory.pptx
Prospect Theory.pptxProspect Theory.pptx
Prospect Theory.pptx
 
UNCERTAINITY AND CONSUMER BEHAVIOUR PPT.pptx
UNCERTAINITY AND CONSUMER BEHAVIOUR PPT.pptxUNCERTAINITY AND CONSUMER BEHAVIOUR PPT.pptx
UNCERTAINITY AND CONSUMER BEHAVIOUR PPT.pptx
 
Statergy mgmt
Statergy mgmtStatergy mgmt
Statergy mgmt
 
lecture_9_uncertainty.pdf
lecture_9_uncertainty.pdflecture_9_uncertainty.pdf
lecture_9_uncertainty.pdf
 
Microeconomic Theory Homework Help
Microeconomic Theory Homework HelpMicroeconomic Theory Homework Help
Microeconomic Theory Homework Help
 
Risk and Risk Aversion FM
Risk and Risk Aversion FMRisk and Risk Aversion FM
Risk and Risk Aversion FM
 
Robust Optimal Reinsurance and Investment Problem with p-Thinning Dependent a...
Robust Optimal Reinsurance and Investment Problem with p-Thinning Dependent a...Robust Optimal Reinsurance and Investment Problem with p-Thinning Dependent a...
Robust Optimal Reinsurance and Investment Problem with p-Thinning Dependent a...
 
Principles of Actuarial Science Chapter 1
Principles of Actuarial Science Chapter 1Principles of Actuarial Science Chapter 1
Principles of Actuarial Science Chapter 1
 
Sensitivity &amp; Scenario Analysis
Sensitivity &amp; Scenario AnalysisSensitivity &amp; Scenario Analysis
Sensitivity &amp; Scenario Analysis
 
the basic tools of finance ch 14.pptx
the basic tools of finance ch 14.pptxthe basic tools of finance ch 14.pptx
the basic tools of finance ch 14.pptx
 
CABT SHS Statistics & Probability - Expected Value and Variance of Discrete P...
CABT SHS Statistics & Probability - Expected Value and Variance of Discrete P...CABT SHS Statistics & Probability - Expected Value and Variance of Discrete P...
CABT SHS Statistics & Probability - Expected Value and Variance of Discrete P...
 
Financial Regulation Lecture 9Based on notes by Marlena El.docx
Financial Regulation Lecture 9Based on notes by Marlena El.docxFinancial Regulation Lecture 9Based on notes by Marlena El.docx
Financial Regulation Lecture 9Based on notes by Marlena El.docx
 
Cramton2014a Risk Theory (slides).pdf
Cramton2014a Risk Theory (slides).pdfCramton2014a Risk Theory (slides).pdf
Cramton2014a Risk Theory (slides).pdf
 
Chapter 3. Arbitrage (asset) pricing theoryNeil Wallace.docx
Chapter 3. Arbitrage (asset) pricing theoryNeil Wallace.docxChapter 3. Arbitrage (asset) pricing theoryNeil Wallace.docx
Chapter 3. Arbitrage (asset) pricing theoryNeil Wallace.docx
 
Risk
RiskRisk
Risk
 

Lecture 2

  • 1. Intermediate microeconomics: Lecture 2 Risk and Expected utility Risk attitude Application to insurance market Intermediate microeconomics: Lecture 2 March 7, 2013
  • 2. Intermediate microeconomics: Lecture 2 Risk and Expected utility Risk attitude Application to insurance market Risk ◮ Many economic choice is risky in the sense that the outcome is not certain. ◮ Project choice ◮ Investment decision ◮ Occupational choice ◮ Marriage decision
  • 3. Intermediate microeconomics: Lecture 2 Risk and Expected utility Risk attitude Application to insurance market Risky choice as lottery ◮ A decision problem under risk can be interpreted as a choice of “lotteries”. ◮ Project choice ◮ If the future economic condition is good, your project yields $1000 ◮ If it is bad, your project yields $0. ◮ If the probability of having a good economy is 20%, it is a lottery such that $1000 with 20% and $0 with 80%
  • 4. Intermediate microeconomics: Lecture 2 Risk and Expected utility Risk attitude Application to insurance market Notation ◮ If the probability of having a good economy is 20%, it is a lottery such that $1000 with 20% and $0 with 80% ◮ Formally, the above lottery can be written as L = (x1,x2;p1,p2) = (1000,0;0.2,0.8)
  • 5. Intermediate microeconomics: Lecture 2 Risk and Expected utility Risk attitude Application to insurance market Example ◮ Which is your favorite lottery? ◮ L1 = (10,10;0.5,0.5) ◮ L2 = (0,20;0.5,0.5) ◮ L3 = (5,10;0.2,08)
  • 6. Intermediate microeconomics: Lecture 2 Risk and Expected utility Risk attitude Application to insurance market Preference over lotteries ◮ As Lecture 1, define a preference over lotteries, e.g., L1 ≻ L2 ≻ L3. ◮ If your taste is transitive and complete, it is rational preference. ◮ Then, you have a utility function U(L) that represents your taste for lotteries. ◮ However, you might want more intuitive and useful representation.
  • 7. Intermediate microeconomics: Lecture 2 Risk and Expected utility Risk attitude Application to insurance market Expected value ◮ If it is a lottery, how about the average or expected value? ◮ That is, U(L) = p(x1)x1 +p(x2)x2 ◮ More generally, if there are N possible outcomes, U(L) = ∑ n p(xn)xn
  • 8. Intermediate microeconomics: Lecture 2 Risk and Expected utility Risk attitude Application to insurance market Problem ◮ Note that if L1 = (10,10;0.5,0.5) and L2 = (0,20;0.5,0.5), then U(L1) = U(L2) if U is the expected value. ◮ Thus, unless you find L1 and L2 indifferent, this is not right way to represent your preference. ◮ In other words, the expected value cannot reflect your attitude toward risk.
  • 9. Intermediate microeconomics: Lecture 2 Risk and Expected utility Risk attitude Application to insurance market Expected utility ◮ There is an alternative way. ◮ Expected utility theory represents your preference with the following form U(L) = p(x1)u(x1)+p(x2)u(x2) ◮ More generally, if there are many possible outcomes U(L) = ∑ n p(xn)u(xn)
  • 10. Intermediate microeconomics: Lecture 2 Risk and Expected utility Risk attitude Application to insurance market Example ◮ Suppose you cast a dice. If your get x ∈ {1,2,..,6}, you receives $x. ◮ The expected utility is EU(x) = 1 6 [u(1)+u(2)+u(3)+u(4)+u(5)+u(6)] ◮ For example, if u(x) = √ x, then EU(x) = 1.805303682
  • 11. Intermediate microeconomics: Lecture 2 Risk and Expected utility Risk attitude Application to insurance market When does EU exist? ◮ We learn that a preference can be represented by a utility if and only if the preference is rational. ◮ When can a preference over lotteries be represented by an expected utility? ◮ In other words, what is the condition that guarantees existence of u(x) such that L′ L′′ if and only if ∑ n pL′ (xn)u(xn) ≥ ∑ n pL′′ (xn)u(xn)
  • 12. Intermediate microeconomics: Lecture 2 Risk and Expected utility Risk attitude Application to insurance market Continuity Definition A preference over lotteries satisfies continuity assumption if, for any lotteries L′,L′′,L′′′ such that L′ L′′ L′′′, there exists α ∈ (0,1) such that αL′ +(1−α)L′′′ ∼ L′′ ◮ Roughly put, a small change of a probability can make a small change in your preference.
  • 13. Intermediate microeconomics: Lecture 2 Risk and Expected utility Risk attitude Application to insurance market Independence Definition A preference over lotteries satisfies independence assumption if, for any lotteries L′,L′′,L′′′ such that L′ L′′, αL′ +(1−α)L′′′ αL′′ +(1−α)L′′′ for any α ∈ (0,1]. ◮ Roughly put, if you expand two lotteries with a common lottery, it should not affect preference over the two lotteries.
  • 14. Intermediate microeconomics: Lecture 2 Risk and Expected utility Risk attitude Application to insurance market The condition ◮ The following result is known. Proposition There exists an expected utility that represents a preference over lotteries if and only if the preference is rational and satisfies the continuity and independence assumptions.
  • 15. Intermediate microeconomics: Lecture 2 Risk and Expected utility Risk attitude Application to insurance market Risk attitude ◮ The expected value cannot capture a risk attitude. ◮ If L1 = (10,10;0.5,0.5) and L2 = (0,20;0.5,0.5), then what can we say about U(L1) vs. U(L2) if U is the expected utility? ◮ Can the expected utility capture a risk attitude?
  • 16. Intermediate microeconomics: Lecture 2 Risk and Expected utility Risk attitude Application to insurance market Risk aversion ◮ Suppose u(x) = xα (other functional form can be also possible) ◮ Suppose you prefer L1 to L2, that is, you are risk averse. ◮ Then choose α ∈ (0,1), say 1/2 ◮ Then, 1 2101/2 + 1 2101/2 = 101/2 = 3.162 > 1 2201/2 = 2.236. ◮ So α < 1 represents that you are risk averse.
  • 17. Intermediate microeconomics: Lecture 2 Risk and Expected utility Risk attitude Application to insurance market Risk aversion and concavity ◮ If u(x) is strictly concave, then the agent is always risk averse. ◮ u(x) = ln(x) ◮ u(x) = √ x
  • 18. Intermediate microeconomics: Lecture 2 Risk and Expected utility Risk attitude Application to insurance market Risk loving ◮ Suppose you prefer L2 to L1, that is, you are a risk lover. ◮ Then choose α > 1 in your xα. ◮ Then, 1 2102 + 1 2102 = 102 = 100 < 1 2202 = 200. ◮ So α > 1 represents that you are a risk lover.
  • 19. Intermediate microeconomics: Lecture 2 Risk and Expected utility Risk attitude Application to insurance market Risk loving and convexity ◮ If u(x) is strictly convex, then the agent is always risk averse. ◮ u(x) = x3 ◮ u(x) = ex
  • 20. Intermediate microeconomics: Lecture 2 Risk and Expected utility Risk attitude Application to insurance market Risk neutrality ◮ If α = 1, then the expected utility becomes the expected value. ◮ 1 210+ 1 210 = 10 = 1 220. ◮ That is, L1 and L2 are indifferent. ◮ So α = 1 means that you are risk neutral.
  • 21. Intermediate microeconomics: Lecture 2 Risk and Expected utility Risk attitude Application to insurance market Risk neutrality and linearity ◮ if u(x) is linear, then the agent is always risk averse. ◮ u(x) = 4x ◮ u(x) = 0.3x
  • 22. Intermediate microeconomics: Lecture 2 Risk and Expected utility Risk attitude Application to insurance market Certainty equivalent ◮ L = (x,y;p,1−p) ◮ Consider z such that u(z) = pu(x)+(1−p)u(y) ◮ That is, you are indifferent between certain z dollar and lottery L. ◮ Then, z is called certainty equivalent of L ◮ If you are risk averse, z < px +(1−p)y. ◮ If you are risk neutral, z = px +(1−p)y.
  • 23. Intermediate microeconomics: Lecture 2 Risk and Expected utility Risk attitude Application to insurance market Risk premium ◮ Risk premium of L is an extra money that can be paid to compensate the risk of L. ◮ Formally, we can define risk premium as px +(1−p)y −z. ◮ Note that if the agent is risk neutral z = px +(1−p)y and thus, the risk premium is always 0.
  • 24. Intermediate microeconomics: Lecture 2 Risk and Expected utility Risk attitude Application to insurance market Example ◮ L = (10,60;0.5,0.5) and u(x) = 100x − x2 2 ◮ pu(x)+(1−p)u(y) = 1 2(1000−50)+ 1 2 (6000−1800) = 2625
  • 25. Intermediate microeconomics: Lecture 2 Risk and Expected utility Risk attitude Application to insurance market Example ◮ Certainty equivalence z solves u(z) = 2625 or 0 = z2 −200z +5250 ◮ The certainty equivalent is z = 200− √ 40000−21000 2 ≈ 31 ◮ Risk premium is 1 2 10+ 1 2 60−31 = 4
  • 26. Intermediate microeconomics: Lecture 2 Risk and Expected utility Risk attitude Application to insurance market Insurance ◮ Consider the following simple insurance market. ◮ Suppose that the probability of having an accident is known as p. ◮ The accident could make your income from 100 to 0. ◮ Insurance guarantees you to have 100 all the time as long as you pay $q.
  • 27. Intermediate microeconomics: Lecture 2 Risk and Expected utility Risk attitude Application to insurance market Expected utility ◮ So with the insurance, your utility is U(100−q) . ◮ On the other hand, without the insurance, your expected utility is (1−p)U(100)+pU(0) .
  • 28. Intermediate microeconomics: Lecture 2 Risk and Expected utility Risk attitude Application to insurance market Buyer’s problem ◮ You buy the insurance if your utility from buying is higher than your expected utility from facing uncertainty. ◮ That is, (1−p)U(100)+pU(0) ≤ U(100−q)
  • 29. Intermediate microeconomics: Lecture 2 Risk and Expected utility Risk attitude Application to insurance market Seller’s problem ◮ The insurance company has to make sure that ◮ she can sell the product (Sale’s condition) ◮ the profit is not negative (Profitability condition)
  • 30. Intermediate microeconomics: Lecture 2 Risk and Expected utility Risk attitude Application to insurance market Sale’s condition ◮ Recall the certainty equivalent of L = (0,100;p,1−p) is z such that U(z) = (1−p)U(100)+pU(0) ◮ Then, the consumer prefers to buy the insurance as long as 100−q ≥ z or q ≤ 100−z ◮ Thus, the insurance company has to choose q so that it satisfies the above condition to sell the insurance.
  • 31. Intermediate microeconomics: Lecture 2 Risk and Expected utility Risk attitude Application to insurance market Profitability condition ◮ The insurance company gets q but they have to pay 100 with probability p. Thus, their expected profit given q is q −100p. ◮ Thus, q has to be q ≥ 100p to keep her profit non-negative.
  • 32. Intermediate microeconomics: Lecture 2 Risk and Expected utility Risk attitude Application to insurance market Trading condition ◮ The trade occurs if and only if the sale’s condition and the profitability condition are both satisfied. ◮ In other words, q has to be 100−z ≥ q ≥ 100p
  • 33. Intermediate microeconomics: Lecture 2 Risk and Expected utility Risk attitude Application to insurance market Risk neutral buyer ◮ If you are risk neutral, z = (1−p)100. Then, 100−z = 100p ◮ Thus, q = 100p is the only value that satisfies the trading condition 100−z ≥ q ≥ 100p ◮ Then, the expected profit is always 0.
  • 34. Intermediate microeconomics: Lecture 2 Risk and Expected utility Risk attitude Application to insurance market Risk aversion ◮ Recall that if you are risk averse, z < (1−p)100. Then, 100−z > 100p ◮ Thus, by choosing q such that 100−z > q > 100p, the company earns a positive profit and the consumer buys the insurance.