SlideShare a Scribd company logo
1 of 69
Dunkin Donuts
My name
Institution
Course
Instructor
Date
Introduction
Consumer Reference
Feasibility Test
Market Scope
Testing and Customer Acceptance
Staffing
Roll Out Plan
CUSTOMER PREFERENCE
Market research and analysis
Competitor strategies
There is need to do market analysis so as to understand further
what the customers want. Without market research, products and
services offered will be null and void. Market research will also
help understand what kind of product the customer and it is not
being offered by competitors. It helps the business understand
the strategies of competitors. The business will find ways of
outperforming competitors based on what the customers prefer.
3
FEASIBILITY TEST
Costs of starting the business
Profit projections
It is important to perform a feasibility test so to find out how
much the business will cost. This the point that determines
whether it is worth investing in the business. This where a
forecast will be made to see projections. How long will it take
the business to realize profits.
4
MARKET SCOPE
Customers explore new brands
Implement new technologies
Make informed decisions
Undertaking market scope is to find the rational consumers who
are keen on trying to explore new brands in the market. This
phase helps in implementing new techniques of how to to do
business. It will assist the company in making informed
decisions hence reducing customer loss. It enables the company
to meet customer demands effectively. Satisfied customers will
ensure that the business keep growing.
5
CUSTOMER ACCEPTANCE
The ultimate goal for every study is to answer key questions and
provide up-to-date and reliable information to support the
client’s strategic business planning.
Pricing strategies
The best way for a business to penetrate the market is if the
customers accept the products and services that are being
offered by the business. Here the business will set prices that
are favorable to the customers. Not too high to push away
consumers and not too low to avoid making losses.
6
DUNKIN’S STAFFING
Employ qualified employees
Employees who share the visions of the business
Clearly state roles of each employee
Services will not perform themselves. A business needs
employees to attend to customers. A business needs qualified
employees who relate easily to customers and work faster to
meet the requests of customers. Good employees will the reason
customers keep coming to buy from the business. If the area is
full youths, the business needs youths who can easily
understand the demands of customers.
7
ROLL OUT
Identify your niche and make sure the uniqueness of your
product stands out.
Brand the product well in order to attract new customers as
well.
Perform a SWOT analysis and monitor your products’ life cycle.
After all factors have been considered and observed, it is time
to roll out the business. The best to win customers when the
business becomes operational is to brand the business. Unique
branding will draw customers away from competitors. The
business needs to do a SWOT analysis and monitor the lifecycle
of the products. The business needs to find a suitable location to
set up the business. This is where the business finds out if the
customers are satisfied with the services being offered.
8
Conclusion
offer unique services
Employ qualified employees
Meet the demands of customers
Employ reasonable prices
In conclusion, for a business to be a success the level of
attracting customers should be high. The business must employ
better strategies that will run competitors out of business. The
best strategies is offering unique products, reasonable prices on
products. Employees should be qualified and easily understand
the preferences of customers.
9
David Graeber, Bullshit Jobs: A Theory (2018) Chapter 3: Why
Do Those in
Bullshit Jobs Regularly Report Themselves Unhappy?
In this chapter, I’d like to start exploring some of the moral and
psychological
effects of being trapped inside a bullshit job.
In particular, I want to ask the obvious question: Why is this
even a problem? Or
to phrase it more precisely: Why does having a pointless job so
regularly cause
people to be miserable? On the face of it, it’s not obvious that it
should. After all,
we’re talking about people who are effectively being paid—
often very good money
—to do nothing. One might imagine that those being paid to do
nothing would
consider themselves fortunate, especially when they are more or
less left to
themselves. But while every now and then I did hear testimonies
from those who
said they couldn’t believe their luck in landing such a position,
the remarkable
thing is how very few of them there were.1 Many, in fact,
seemed perplexed by
their own reaction, unable to understand why their situation left
them feeling so
worthless or depressed. Indeed, the fact that there was no clear
explanation for
their feelings—no story they could tell themselves about the
nature of their
situation and what was wrong about it—often contributed to
their misery. At least
a galley slave knows that he’s oppressed. An office worker
forced to sit for seven
and a half hours a day pretending to type into a screen for $18
an hour, or a
junior member of a consultancy team forced to give the exact
same seminar on
innovation and creativity week in and week out for $50,000 a
year, is just
confused.
In an earlier book about debt, I wrote about the phenomenon of
“moral
confusion.” I took as my example the fact that throughout
human history, most
people seem to have agreed both that paying back one’s debts
was the essence of
morality and that moneylenders were evil. While the rise of
bullshit jobs is a
comparatively recent phenomenon, I think it creates a similar
moral
embarrassment. On the one hand, everyone is encouraged to
assume that human
beings will always tend to seek their best advantage, that is, to
find themselves a
situation where they can get the most benefit for the least
expenditure of time
and effort, and for the most part, we do assume this—especially
if we are talking
about such matters in the abstract. (“We can’t just give poor
people handouts!
Then they won’t have any incentive to look for work!”) On the
other hand, our
own experience, and those of the people we are closest to, tends
to contradict
these assumptions at many points. People almost never act and
react to
situations in quite the way our theories of human nature would
predict. The only
reasonable conclusion is that, at least in certain key essentials,
these theories
about human nature are wrong.
In this chapter, I don’t just want to ask why people are so
unhappy doing what
seems to them meaningless make-work, but to think more
deeply about what that
unhappiness can tell us about what people are and what they are
basically about.
Graeber, Bullshit Jobs: A Theory page !1
ABOUT ONE YOUNG MAN APPARENTLY HANDED A
SINECURE WHO
NONETHELESS FOUND HIMSELF UNABLE TO HANDLE
THE SITUATION
I will begin with a story. The following is the tale of a young
man named Eric,
whose first experience of the world of work was of a job that
proved absolutely,
even comically, pointless.
Eric: I’ve had many, many awful jobs, but the one that was
undoubtedly pure,
liquid bullshit was my first “professional job” postgraduation, a
dozen years ago. I
was the first in my family to attend university, and due to a
profound naïveté
about the purpose of higher education, I somehow expected that
it would open up
vistas of hitherto-unforeseen opportunity.
Instead, it offered graduate training schemes at
PricewaterhouseCoopers, KPMG,
etc. I preferred to sit on the dole for six months using my
graduate library
privileges to read French and Russian novels before the dole
forced me to attend
an interview which, sadly, led to a job.
That job involved working for a large design firm as its
“Interface Administrator.”
The Interface was a content management system—an intranet
with graphical
user interface, basically—designed to enable this company’s
work to be shared
across its seven offices around the UK.
Eric soon discovered that he was hired only because of a
communication problem
in the organization. In other words, he was a duct taper: the
entire computer
system was necessary only because the partners were unable to
pick up the phone
and coordinate with one another:
Eric: The firm was a partnership, with each office managed by
one partner. All of
them seem to have attended one of three private schools and the
same design
school (the Royal College of Art). Being unbelievably
competitive fortysomething
public schoolboys, they often tried to outcompete one another to
win bids, and on
more than one occasion, two different offices had found
themselves arriving at
the same client’s office to pitch work and having to hastily
combine their bids in
the parking lot of some dismal business park. The Interface was
designed to make
the company supercollaborative, across all of its offices, to
ensure that this (and
other myriad fuckups) didn’t happen again, and my job was to
help develop it,
run it, and sell it to the staff.
The problem was, it soon became apparent that Eric wasn’t even
really a duct
taper. He was a box ticker: one partner had insisted on the
project, and, rather 1
In earlier chapters, the author proposed categories of bullshit
jobs. A “duct taper” is someone assigned to 1
inadequately repair something that was poorly designed in the
first place, while a box ticker is someone
assigned to complete forms confirming that things that didn’t
need doing have been done. —GH
Graeber, Bullshit Jobs: A Theory page !2
than argue with him, the others pretended to agree. Then they
did everything in
their power to make sure it didn’t work.
Eric: I should have realized that this was one partner’s idea that
no one else
actually wanted to implement. Why else would they be paying a
twenty-one-year-
old history graduate with no IT experience to do this? They’d
bought the cheapest
software they could find, from a bunch of absolute crooks, so it
was buggy, prone
to crashing, and looked like a Windows 3.1 screen saver. The
entire workforce
was paranoid that it was designed to monitor their productivity,
record their
keystrokes, or flag that they were torrenting porn on the
company internet, and
so they wanted nothing to do with it. As I had absolutely no
background in coding
or software development, there was very little I could do to
improve the thing, so
I was basically tasked with selling and managing a badly
functioning, unwanted
turd. After a few months, I realized that there was very little for
me to do at all
most days, aside from answer a few queries from confused
designers wanting to
know how to upload a file, or search for someone’s email on the
address book.
The utter pointlessness of his situation soon led to subtle—and
then, increasingly
unsubtle—acts of rebellion:
Eric: I started arriving late and leaving early. I extended the
company policy of “a
pint on Friday lunchtime” into “pints every lunchtime.” I read
novels at my desk.
I went out for lunchtime walks that lasted three hours. I almost
perfected my
French reading ability, sitting with my shoes off with a copy of
Le Monde and a
Petit Robert. I tried to quit, and my boss offered me a £2,600
raise, which I
reluctantly accepted. They needed me precisely because I didn’t
have the skills to
implement something that they didn’t want to implement, and
they were willing
to pay to keep me. (Perhaps one could paraphrase Marx’s
Economic and
Philosophical Manuscripts of 1844 here: to forestall their fears
of alienation from
their own labor, they had to sacrifice me up to a greater
alienation from potential
human growth.)
As time went on, Eric became more and more flagrant in his
defiance, hoping he
could find something he could do that might actually cause him
to be fired. He
started showing up to work drunk and taking paid “business
trips” for
nonexistent meetings:
Eric: A colleague from the Edinburgh office, to whom I had
poured out my woes
when drunk at the annual general meeting, started to arrange
phony meetings
with me, once on a golf course near Gleneagles, me hacking at
the turf in
borrowed golf shoes two sizes too large. After getting away
with that, I started
arranging fictional meetings with people in the London office.
The firm would put
me up in a nicotine-coated room in the St. Athans in
Bloomsbury, and I would
meet old London friends for some good old-fashioned all-day
drinking in Soho
pubs, which often turned into all-night drinking in Shoreditch.
More than once, I
returned to my office the following Monday in last
Wednesday’s work shirt. I’d
long since stopped shaving, and by this point, my hair looked
like it was robbed
Graeber, Bullshit Jobs: A Theory page !3
from a Zeppelin roadie. I tried on two more occasions to quit,
but both times my
boss offered me more cash. By the end, I was being paid a
stupid sum for a job
that, at most, involved me answering the phone twice a day. I
eventually broke
down on the platform of Bristol Temple Meads train station one
late summer’s
afternoon. I’d always fancied seeing Bristol, and so I decided to
“visit” the Bristol
office to look at “user take-up.” I actually spent three days
taking MDMA at an
anarcho-syndicalist house party in St. Pauls, and the
dissociative comedown
made me realize how profoundly upsetting it was to live in a
state of utter
purposelessness.
After heroic efforts, Eric did finally manage to get himself
replaced:
Eric: Eventually, responding to pressure, my boss hired a junior
fresh out of a
computer science degree to see if some improvements could be
made to our
graphical user interface. On this kid’s first day at work, I wrote
him a list of what
needed to be done—and then immediately wrote my resignation
letter, which I
posted under my boss’s door when he took his next vacation,
surrendering my
last paycheck over the telephone in lieu of the statutory notice
period. I flew that
same week to Morocco to do very little in the coastal town of
Essaouira. When I
came back, I spent the next six months living in a squat,
growing my own
vegetables on three acres of land. I read your Strike! piece when
it first came out.
It might have been a revelation for some that capitalism creates
unnecessary jobs
in order for the wheels to merely keep on turning, but it wasn’t
to me.
The remarkable thing about this story is that many would
consider Eric’s a dream
job. He was being paid good money to do nothing. He was also
almost completely
unsupervised. He was given respect and every opportunity to
game the system.
Yet despite all that, it gradually destroyed him.
Why?
To a large degree, I think, this is really a story about social
class. Eric was a young
man from a working-class background—a child of factory
workers, no less—fresh
out of college and full of expectations, suddenly confronted
with a jolting
introduction to the “real world.” Reality, in this instance,
consisted of the fact that
(a) while middle-aged executives can be counted on to simply
assume that any
twentysomething white male will be at least something of a
computer whiz (even
if, as in this case, he had no computer training of any kind), and
(b) might even
grant someone like Eric a cushy situation if it suited their
momentary purposes,
(c) they basically saw him as something of a joke. Which his
job almost literally
was. His presence in the company was very close to a practical
joke some
designers were playing on one another.
Even more, what drove Eric crazy was the fact there was simply
no way he could
construe his job as serving any sort of purpose. He couldn’t
even tell himself he
was doing it to feed his family; he didn’t have one yet. Coming
from a background
where most people took pride in making, maintaining, and
fixing things, or
Graeber, Bullshit Jobs: A Theory page !4
anyway felt that was the sort of thing people should take pride
in, he had
assumed that going to university and moving into the
professional world would
mean doing the same sorts of thing on a grander, even more
meaningful, scale.
Instead, he ended up getting hired precisely for what he wasn’t
able to do. He
tried to just resign. They kept offering him more money. He
tried to get himself
fired. They wouldn’t fire him. He tried to rub their faces in it,
to make himself a
parody of what they seemed to think he was. It didn’t make the
slightest bit of
difference.
To get a sense of what was really happening here, let us imagine
a second history
major—we can refer to him as anti-Eric—a young man of a
professional
background but placed in exactly the same situation. How might
anti-Eric have
behaved differently? Well, likely as not, he would have played
along with the
charade. Instead of using phony business trips to practice forms
of self-
annihilation, anti-Eric would have used them to accumulate
social capital,
connections that would eventually allow him to move on to
better things. He
would have treated the job as a stepping-stone, and this very
project of
professional advancement would have given him a sense of
purpose. But such
attitudes and dispositions don’t come naturally. Children from
professional
backgrounds are taught to think like that from an early age.
Eric, who had not
been trained to act and think this way, couldn’t bring himself to
do it. As a result,
he ended up, for a time, at least, in a squat growing tomatoes.2
concerning the experience of falseness and purposelessness at
the core of bullshit
jobs, and the importance now felt of conveying the experience
of falseness and
purposelessness to youth
In a deeper way, Eric’s story brings together almost everything
that those with
bullshit jobs say is distressing about their situation. It’s not just
the
purposelessness— though certainly, it’s that. It’s also the
falseness. I’ve already
mentioned the indignation telemarketers feel when they are
forced to try to trick
or pressure people into doing something they think is against
their best interests.
This is a complicated feeling. We don’t even really have a name
for it. When we
think of scams, after all, we think of grifters, confidence artists;
they are easy to
see as romantic figures, rebels living by their wits, as well as
admirable because
they have achieved a certain form of mastery. This is why they
make acceptable
heroes in Hollywood movies. A confidence artist could easily
take delight in what
she’s doing. But being forced to scam someone is altogether
different. In such
circumstances, it’s hard not to feel you’re ultimately in the
same situation as the
person you’re scamming: you’re both being pressured and
manipulated by your
employer, only in your case, with the added indignity that
you’re also betraying
the trust of someone whose side you should be on. One might
imagine the
feelings sparked by most bullshit jobs would be very different.
After all, if the
employee is scamming anyone, it’s his employer, and he’s doing
it with his
employer’s full consent. But somehow, this is precisely what
many report to be so
disturbing about the situation. You don’t even have the
satisfaction of knowing
Graeber, Bullshit Jobs: A Theory page !5
you’re putting something over on someone. You’re not even
living your own lie.
Most of the time, you’re not even quite living somebody else’s
lie, either. Your job
is more like a boss’s unzippered fly that everyone can see but
also knows better
than to mention.
If anything, this appears to compound the sense of
purposelessness.
Perhaps anti-Eric would, indeed, have found a way to turn
around that
purposelessness and seen himself as in on the joke; perhaps if
he were a real go-
getter, he’d have used his administrative skills to effectively
take over the office;
but even children of the rich and powerful often find this
difficult to pull off. The
following testimony gives a sense of the moral confusion they
can often feel:
Rufus: I got the job because my dad was a Vice President at the
company. I was
charged with handling complaints. Given that it was (in name) a
biomedical
company, all returned product was considered a biohazard. So I
was able to
spend a lot of time in a room all by myself, with no supervision
and essentially no
work to do. The bulk of my memory of the job involves either
playing
Minesweeper or listening to podcasts.
I did spend hours poring over spreadsheets, tracking changes on
Word
documents, etc., but I guarantee you that I contributed nothing
to this company. I
spent every minute at the office wearing headphones. I paid
only the smallest
attention possible to the people around me and the “work” I was
assigned.
I hated every minute working there. In fact, more days than not,
I went home
early from work, took two- or three-hour lunch breaks, spent
hours “in the
bathroom” (wandering around), and nobody ever said a word. I
was compensated
for every minute.
Thinking back on it, it was kind of a dream job.
Retrospectively, Rufus understands that he got a ridiculously
sweet deal—he
seems rather baffled, actually, why he hated the job so much at
the time. But
surely he couldn’t have been entirely unaware of how his
coworkers must have
seen him: boss’s kid getting paid to goof off; feels he’s too
good to talk to them;
supervisors clearly informed “hands off.” It could hardly have
evoked warm
feelings.
Still, this story raises another question: If Rufus’s father didn’t
actually expect his
son to do the job, why did he insist he take it in the first place?
He could
presumably just as easily have given his son an allowance, or,
alternately,
assigned him a job that needed doing, coached him on his
duties, and taken some
minimal effort to make sure those tasks were actually carried
out. Instead, he
seems to have felt it was more important for Rufus to be able to
say he had a job
than to actually acquire work experience.
Graeber, Bullshit Jobs: A Theory page !6
That’s puzzling. It’s all the more puzzling because the father’s
attitude appears to
be extremely common. It wasn’t always so. There was once a
time when most
students in college whose parents could afford it, or who
qualified for
scholarships or assistance, received a stipend. It was considered
a good thing that
there might be a few years in a young man’s or woman’s life
where money was not
the primary motivation; where he or she could thus be free to
pursue other forms
of value: say, philosophy, poetry, athletics, sexual
experimentation, altered states
of consciousness, politics, or the history of Western art.
Nowadays it is
considered important they should work. However, it is not
considered important
they should work at anything useful. In fact, like Rufus they’re
barely expected to
work at all, just to show up and pretend to do so. A number of
students wrote just
to complain to me about this phenomenon. Here Patrick reflects
on his job as a
casual retail assistant in a student union convenience store:
Patrick: I didn’t actually need the job (I was getting by
financially without it), but
after some pressure from my family, I applied for it out of some
warped sense of
obligation to get experience in work to prepare me for whatever
lay ahead beyond
university. In reality, the job just took away time and energy
from other activities
I had been doing, like campaigning and activism, or reading for
pleasure, which I
think made me resent it even more.
The job was pretty standard for a student union convenience
store and involved
serving people on the till (could have easily been done by a
machine) with the
explicitly stated requirement, in my performance review after
my trial period,
that I “should be more positive and happy when serving
customers.” So not only
did they want me to do work that could have been performed by
a machine just as
effectively, they wanted me to pretend that I was enjoying that
state of affairs.
It was just about bearable if my shift was during lunchtime,
when it got really
busy, so time went by relatively quickly. Being on shift on a
Sunday afternoon
when nobody frequented the SU was just appalling. They had
this thing about us
not being able to just do nothing, even if the shop was empty.
So we couldn’t just
sit at the till and read a magazine. Instead, the manager made up
utterly
meaningless work for us to do, like going round the whole shop
and checking that
things were in date (even though we knew for a fact they were
because of the
turnover rate) or rearranging products on shelves in even more
pristine order
than they already were.
The very, very worst thing about the job was that it gave you so
much time to
think, because the work was so lacking in any intellectual
demand. So I just
thought so much about how bullshit my job was, how it could be
done by a
machine, how much I couldn’t wait for full communism, and
just endlessly
theorized the alternatives to a system where millions of human
beings have to do
that kind of work for their whole lives in order to survive. I
couldn’t stop thinking
about how miserable it made me.
Graeber, Bullshit Jobs: A Theory page !7
This is what happens, of course, when you first open the entire
world of social
and political possibility to a young mind by sending it to
college and then tell it to
stop thinking and tidy up already tidy shelves. Parents now feel
it is important
that young minds should have this experience. But what,
precisely, was Patrick
supposed to be learning through this exercise?
Here’s another example:
Brendan: I’m at a small college in Massachusetts training to be
a high school
history teacher. Recently I started work at the dining commons.
A coworker told me on my first day: “Half of this job is making
things look clean,
and the other half is looking busy.”
For the first couple of months, they had me “monitor” the back
room. I would
clean the buffet slider, restock the desserts, and wipe down
tables when people
left. It’s not a big room, so usually I could do all my tasks in
five minutes out of
every thirty. I ended up being able to get a lot of reading for my
coursework done.
However, sometimes one of the less understanding supervisors
would be
working. In that case, I would have to keep the corner of my eye
open at all times
in order to make sure they would always see me acting busy. I
have no idea why
the job description couldn’t just acknowledge that I wouldn’t
have much to do— if
I didn’t have to spend so much time and energy looking busy, I
could get my
reading and the table cleaning done quicker and more
efficiently.
But of course, efficiency is not the point. In fact, if we are
simply talking about
teaching students about efficient work habits, the best thing
would be to leave
them to their studies. Schoolwork is, after all, real work in
every sense except that
you don’t get paid for it (though if you’re receiving a
scholarship or an allowance,
you actually are getting paid for it). In fact, like almost all the
other activities
Patrick or Brendan might have been engaged in had they not
been obliged to take
on “real world” jobs, their classwork is actually more real than
the largely make-
work projects they ended up being forced to do. Schoolwork has
real content. One
must attend classes, do the readings, write exercises or papers,
and be judged on
the results. But in practical terms, this appears to be exactly
what makes
schoolwork appear inadequate to those authorities—parents,
teachers,
governments. administrators—who have all come to feel that
they must also teach
students about the real world. It’s too results-oriented. You can
study any way
you want to so long as you pass the test. A successful student
has to learn self-
discipline, but this is not the same as learning how to operate
under orders. Of
course, the same is true of most of the other projects and
activities students
might otherwise be engaged in: whether rehearsing for plays,
playing in a band,
political activism, or baking cookies or growing pot to sell to
fellow students. All
of which might be appropriate training for a society of self-
employed adults, or
even one made up primarily of the largely autonomous
professionals (doctors,
lawyers, architects, and so forth) that universities were once
designed to produce.
Graeber, Bullshit Jobs: A Theory page !8
It might even be appropriate to train young people for the
democratically
organized collectives that were the subject of Patrick’s reveries
about full
communism. But as Brendan points out, it is very much not
preparation for work
in today’s increasingly bullshitized workplace:
Brendan: A lot of these student work jobs have us doing some
sort of bullshit task
like scanning IDs, or monitoring empty rooms, or cleaning
already-clean tables.
Everyone is cool with it, because we get money while we study,
but otherwise
there’s absolutely no reason not to just give students the money
and automate or
eliminate the work.
I’m not altogether familiar with how the whole thing works, but
a lot of this work
is funded by the Feds and tied to our student loans. It’s part of a
whole federal
system designed to assign students a lot of debt—thereby
promising to coerce
them into labor in the future, as student debts are so hard to get
rid of—
accompanied by a bullshit education program designed to train
and prepare us
for our future bullshit jobs.
Brendan has a point, and I’ll be returning to his analysis in a
later chapter. Here,
though, I want to focus on what students forced into these
make-work jobs
actually learn from them—lessons that they do not learn from
more traditional
student occupations and pursuits such as studying for tests,
planning parties, and
so on. Even judging by Brendan’s and Patrick’s accounts (and I
could easily
reference many others), I think we can conclude that from these
jobs, students
learn at least five things:
1. how to operate under others’ direct supervision;
2. how to pretend to work even when nothing needs to done;
3. that one is not paid money to do things, however useful or
important, that one
actually enjoys;
4. that one is paid money to do things that are in no way useful
or important and
that one does not enjoy; and
5. that at least in jobs requiring interaction with the public,
even when one is
being paid to carry out tasks one does not enjoy, one also has to
pretend to be
enjoying it.
This is what Brendan meant by how make-work student
employment was a way
of “preparing and training” students for their future bullshit
jobs. He was
studying to be a high school history teacher—a meaningful job,
certainly, but, as
with almost all teaching positions in the United States, one
where the proportion
of hours spent teaching in class or preparing lessons has
declined, while the total
number of hours dedicated to administrative tasks has increased
dramatically.
This is what Brendan is suggesting: that it’s no coincidence that
the more jobs
requiring college degrees become suffused in bullshit, the more
pressure is put on
college students to learn about the real world by dedicating less
of their time to
self-organized goal-directed activity and more of it to tasks that
will prepare them
for the more mindless aspects of their future careers.
Graeber, Bullshit Jobs: A Theory page !9
WHY MANY OF OUR FUNDAMENTAL ASSUMPTIONS ON
HUMAN
MOTIVATION APPEAR TO BE INCORRECT
I do not think there is any thrill that can go through the human
heart like that felt by the inventor as he sees some creation of
the
brain unfolding to success . . . such emotions make a man forget
food, sleep, friends, love, everything.
—Nikola Tesla
If the argument of the previous section is correct, one could
perhaps conclude
that Eric’s problem was just that he hadn’t been sufficiently
prepared for the
pointlessness of the modern workplace. He had passed through
the old education
system—some traces of it are left—designed to prepare students
to actually do
things. This led to false expectations and an initial shock of
disillusionment that
he could not overcome.
Perhaps. But I don’t think that’s the full story. There is
something much deeper
going on here. Eric might have been unusually ill-prepared to
endure the
meaninglessness of his first job, but just about everyone does
see such
meaninglessness as something to be endured—despite the fact
that we are all
trained, in one way or another, to assume that human beings
should be perfectly
delighted to find themselves in his situation of being paid good
money not to
work.
Let us return to our initial problem. We may begin by asking
why we assume that
someone being paid to do nothing should consider himself
fortunate. What is the
basis of that theory of human nature from which this follows?
The obvious place
to look is at economic theory, which has turned this kind of
thought into a
science. According to classical economic theory, homo
oeconomicus, or
“economic man”—that is, the model human being that lies
behind every
prediction made by the discipline— is assumed to be motivated
above all by a
calculus of costs and benefits. All the mathematical equations
by which
economists bedazzle their clients, or the public, are founded on
one simple
assumption: that everyone, left to his own devices, will choose
the course of
action that provides the most of what he wants for the least
expenditure of
resources and effort. It is the simplicity of the formula that
makes the equations
possible: if one were to admit that humans have complicated
motivations, there
would be too many factors to take into account, it would be
impossible to
properly weight them, and predictions could not be made.
Therefore, while an
economist will say that while of course everyone is aware that
human beings are
not really selfish, calculating machines, assuming that they are
makes it possible
to explain a very large proportion of what humans do, and this
proportion—and
only this—is the subject matter of economic science.
Graeber, Bullshit Jobs: A Theory page !10
This is a reasonable statement as far as it goes. The problem is
there are many
domains of human life where the assumption clearly doesn’t
hold—and some of
them are precisely in the domain of what we like to call the
economy.
Graeber, Bullshit Jobs: A Theory page !11
Harry Frankfurt, On Bullshit (Princeton University Press 2005)
One of the most salient features of our culture is that there is so
much bullshit. Everyone
knows this. Each of us contributes his share. But we tend to
take the situation for
granted. Most people are rather confident of their ability to
recognize bullshit and to
avoid being taken in by it. So the phenomenon has not aroused
much deliberate
concern, nor attracted much sustained inquiry.
In consequence, we have no clear understanding of what bullshit
is, why there is so
much of it, or what functions it serves. And we lack a
conscientiously developed
appreciation of what it means to us. In other words, we have no
theory. I propose to
begin the development of a theoretical understanding of
bullshit, mainly by providing
some tentative and exploratory philosophical analysis. I shall
not consider the rhetorical
uses and misuses of bullshit. My aim is simply to give a rough
account of what bullshit is
and how it differs from what it is not—or (putting it somewhat
differently) to articulate,
more or less sketchily, the structure of its concept.
Any suggestion about what conditions are logically both
necessary and sufficient for the
constitution of bullshit is bound to be somewhat arbitrary. For
one thing, the expression
bullshit is often employed quite loosely—simply as a generic
term of abuse, with no very
specific literal meaning. For another, the phenomenon itself is
so vast and amorphous
that no crisp and perspicuous analysis of its concept can avoid
being procrustean.
Nonetheless it should be possible to say something helpful,
even though it is not likely to
be decisive. Even the most basic and preliminary questions
about bullshit remain, after
all, not only unanswered but unasked.
So far as I am aware, very little work has been done on this
subject. I have not
undertaken a survey of the literature, partly because I do not
know how to go about it.
To be sure, there is one quite obvious place to look—the Oxford
English Dictionary. The
OED has an entry for bullshit in the supplementary volumes,
and it also has entries for
various pertinent uses of the word bull and for some related
terms. I shall consider some
of these entries in due course. I have not consulted dictionaries
in languages other than
English, because I do not know the words for bullshit or bull in
any other language.
Another worthwhile source is the title essay in The Prevalence
of Humbug by Max
Black. I am uncertain just how close in meaning the word
humbug is to the word 1
bullshit. Of course, the words are not freely and fully
interchangeable; it is clear that
they are used differently. But the difference appears on the
whole to have more to do
with considerations of gentility, and certain other rhetorical
parameters, than with the
strictly literal modes of significance that concern me most. It is
more polite, as well as
less intense, to say “Humbug!” than to say “Bullshit!” For the
sake of this discussion, I
shall assume that there is no other important difference between
the two.
Max Black, The Prevalence of Humbug (Ithaca: Cornell
University Press, 1985).1
Frankfurt, On Bullshit, page !1
Black suggests a number of synonyms for humbug, including
the following: balderdash,
claptrap, hokum, drivel, buncombe, imposture, and quackery.
This list of quaint
equivalents is not very helpful. But Black also confronts the
problem of establishing the
nature of humbug more directly, and he offers the following
formal definition:
HUMBUG: deceptive misrepresentation, short of lying,
especially by
pretentious word or deed, of somebody’s own thoughts,
feelings, or
attitudes. 2
A very similar formulation might plausibly be offered as
enunciating the essential
characteristics of bullshit. As a preliminary to developing an
independent account of
those characteristics, I will comment on the various elements of
Black’s definition.
Deceptive misrepresentation: This may sound pleonastic. No
doubt what Black has in 3
mind is that humbug is necessarily designed or intended to
deceive, that its
misrepresentation is not merely inadvertent. In other words, it is
deliberate
misrepresentation. Now if, as a matter of conceptual necessity,
an intention to deceive is
an invariable feature of humbug, then the property of being
humbug depends at least in
part upon the perpetrator’s state of mind. It cannot be identical,
accordingly, with any
properties—either inherent or relational—belonging just to the
utterance by which the
humbug is perpetrated. In this respect, the property of being
humbug is similar to that
of being a lie, which is identical neither with the falsity nor
with any of the other
properties of the statement the liar makes, but which requires
that the liar makes his
statement in a certain state of mind—namely, with an intention
to deceive.
It is a further question whether there are any features essential
to humbug or to lying
that are not dependent upon the intentions and beliefs of the
person responsible for the
humbug or the lie, or whether it is, on the contrary, possible for
any utterance
whatsoever to be—given that the speaker is in a certain state of
mind—a vehicle of
humbug or of a lie. In some accounts of lying there is no lie
unless a false statement is
made; in others a person may be lying even if the statement he
makes is true, as long as
he himself believes that the statement is false and intends by
making it to deceive. What
about humbug and bullshit? May any utterance at all qualify as
humbug or bullshit,
given that (so to speak) the utterer’s heart is in the right place,
or must the utterance
have certain characteristics of its own as well?
Short of lying: It must be part of the point of saying that
humbug is “short of lying” that
while it has some of the distinguishing characteristics of lies,
there are others that it
lacks. But this cannot be the whole point. After all, every use of
language without
exception has some, but not all, of the characteristic features of
lies—if no other, then at
least the feature simply of being a use of language. Yet it would
surely be incorrect to
describe every use of language as short of lying. Black’s phrase
evokes the notion of
Ibid., p. 143.2
“Pleonasm” is a literary and linguistic term that means adding
an extra word to express a meaning that the other 3
words have already been expressed. Basically, what most
people call “being redundant.” —GH
Frankfurt, On Bullshit, page !2
some sort of continuum, on which lying occupies a certain
segment while humbug is
located exclusively at earlier points. What continuum could this
be, along which one
encounters humbug only before one encounters lying? Both
lying and humbug are
modes of misrepresentation. It is not at first glance apparent,
however, just how the
difference between these varieties of misrepresentation might be
construed as a
difference in degree.
Especially by pretentious word or deed: There are two points to
notice here. First, Black
identifies humbug not only as a category of speech but as a
category of action as well; it
may be accomplished either by words or by deeds. Second, his
use of the qualifier
“especially” indicates that Black does not regard
pretentiousness as an essential or
wholly indispensable characteristic of humbug. Undoubtedly,
much humbug is
pretentious. So far as concerns bullshit, moreover, “pretentious
bullshit” is close to
being a stock phrase. But I am inclined to think that when
bullshit is pretentious, this
happens because pretentiousness is its motive rather than a
constitutive element of its
essence. The fact that a person is behaving pretentiously is not,
it seems to me, part of
what is required to make his utterance an instance of bullshit. It
is often, to be sure,
what accounts for his making that utterance. However, it must
not be assumed that
bullshit always and necessarily has pretentiousness as its
motive.
Misrepresentation . . . of somebody’s own thoughts, feelings, or
attitudes: This provision
that the perpetrator of humbug is essentially misrepresenting
himself raises some very
central issues. To begin with, whenever a person deliberately
misrepresents anything, he
must inevitably be misrepresenting his own state of mind. It is
possible, of course, for a
person to misrepresent that alone—for instance, by pretending
to have a desire or a
feeling which he does not actually have. But suppose that a
person, whether by telling a
lie or in another way, misrepresents something else. Then he
necessarily misrepresents
at least two things. He misrepresents whatever he is talking
about—i.e., the state of
affairs that is the topic or referent of his discourse—and in
doing this he cannot avoid
misrepresenting his own mind as well. Thus someone who lies
about how much money
he has in his pocket both gives an account of the amount of
money in his pocket and
conveys that he believes this account. If the lie works, then its
victim is twice deceived,
having one false belief about what is in the liar’s pocket and
another false belief about
what is in the liar’s mind.
Now it is unlikely that Black wishes the referent of humbug to
be in every instance the
state of the speaker’s mind. There is no particular reason, after
all, why humbug may not
be about other things. Black probably means that humbug is not
designed primarily to
give its audience a false belief about whatever state of affairs
may be the topic, but that
its primary intention is rather to give its audience a false
impression concerning what is
going on in the mind of the speaker. Insofar as it is humbug, the
creation of this
impression is its main purpose and its point.
Understanding Black along these lines suggests a hypothesis to
account for his
characterization of humbug as “short of lying.” If I lie to you
about how much money I
have, then I do not thereby make an explicit assertion
concerning my beliefs. Therefore,
Frankfurt, On Bullshit, page !3
one might with some plausibility maintain that although in
telling the lie I certainly
misrepresent what is in my mind, this misrepresentation—as
distinct from my
misrepresentation of what is in my pocket—is not strictly
speaking a lie at all. For I do
not come right out with any statement whatever about what is in
my mind. Nor does the
statement I do affirm—e.g., “I have twenty dollars in my
pocket”—imply any statement
that attributes a belief to me. On the other hand, it is
unquestionable that in so
affirming, I provide you with a reasonable basis for making
certain judgments about
what I believe. In particular, I provide you with a reasonable
basis for supposing that I
believe I have twenty dollars in my pocket. Since this
supposition is by hypothesis false,
I do in telling the lie tend to deceive you concerning what is in
my mind even though I
do not actually tell a lie about that. In this light, it does not
seem unnatural or
inappropriate to regard me as misrepresenting my own beliefs in
a way that is “short of
lying.”
It is easy to think of familiar situations by which Black’s
account of humbug appears to
be unproblematically confirmed. Consider a Fourth of July
orator, who goes on
bombastically about “our great and blessed country, whose
Founding Fathers under
divine guidance created a new beginning for mankind.” This is
surely humbug. As
Black’s account suggests, the orator is not lying. He would be
lying only if it were his
intention to bring about in his audience beliefs that he himself
regards as false,
concerning such matters as whether our country is great,
whether it is blessed, whether
the Founders had divine guidance, and whether what they did
was in fact to create a new
beginning for mankind. But the orator does not really care what
his audience thinks
about the Founding Fathers, or about the role of the deity in our
country’s history, or the
like. At least, it is not an interest in what anyone thinks about
these matters that
motivates his speech.
It is clear that what makes Fourth of July oration humbug is not
fundamentally that the
speaker regards his statements as false. Rather, just as Black’s
account suggests, the
orator intends these statements to convey a certain impression
of himself. He is not
trying to deceive anyone concerning American history. What he
cares about is what
people think of him. He wants them to think of him as a patriot,
as someone who has
deep thoughts and feelings about the origins and the mission of
our country, who
appreciates the importance of religion, who is sensitive to the
greatness of our history,
whose pride in that history is combined with humility before
God, and so on.
Black’s account of humbug appears, then, to fit certain
paradigms quite snugly.
Nonetheless, I do not believe that it adequately or accurately
grasps the essential
character of bullshit. It is correct to say of bullshit, as he says
of humbug, both that it is
short of lying and that those who perpetrate it misrepresent
themselves in a certain way.
But Black’s account of these two features is significantly off
the mark. I shall next
attempt to develop, by considering some biographical material
pertaining to Ludwig
Frankfurt, On Bullshit, page !4
Wittgenstein, a preliminary but more accurately focused
appreciation of just what the 4
central characteristics of bullshit are.
Wittgenstein once said that the following bit of verse by
Longfellow could serve him as a
motto: 5
In the elder days of art
Builders wrought with greatest care
Each minute and unseen part,
For the Gods are everywhere.
The point of these lines is clear. In the old days, craftsmen did
not cut corners. They
worked carefully, and they took care with every aspect of their
work. Every part of the
product was considered, and each was designed and made to be
exactly as it should be.
These craftsmen did not relax their thoughtful self-discipline
even with respect to
features of their work that would ordinarily not be visible.
Although no one would notice
if those features were not quite right, the craftsmen would be
bothered by their
consciences. So nothing was swept under the rug. Or, one might
perhaps also say, there
was no bullshit.
It does seem fitting to construe carelessly made, shoddy goods
as in some way analogues
of bullshit. But in what way? Is the resemblance that bullshit
itself is invariably
produced in a careless or self-indulgent manner, that it is never
finely crafted, that in
the making of it there is never the meticulously attentive
concern with detail to which
Longfellow alludes? Is the bullshitter by his very nature a
mindless slob? Is his product
necessarily messy or unrefined? The word shit does, to be sure,
suggest this. Excrement
is not designed or crafted at all; it is merely emitted, or
dumped. It may have a more or
less coherent shape, or it may not, but it is in any case certainly
not wrought.
The notion of carefully wrought bullshit involves, then, a
certain inner strain.
Thoughtful attention to detail requires discipline and
objectivity. It entails accepting
standards and limitations that forbid the indulgence of impulse
or whim. It is this
selflessness that, in connection with bullshit, strikes us as
inapposite. But in fact it is not
out of the question at all. The realms of advertising and of
public relations, and the
nowadays closely related realm of politics, are replete with
instances of bullshit so
unmitigated that they can serve among the most indisputable
and classic paradigms of
the concept. And in these realms there are exquisitely
sophisticated craftsmen who—
with the help of advanced and demanding techniques of market
research, of public
Ludwig Wittgenstein (1889-1951) was a philosophy professor
in the English analytic tradition. He was born in 4
Austria but spent his professional life at Oxford, where he wrote
several highly influential works on the relation
between language and thought. He was famously serious and
passionate about philosophy. — GH
This is reported by Norman Malcolm, in his introduction to
Recollections of Wittgenstein, ed. R. Rhees (Oxford: 5
Oxford University Press, 1984), p. xiii.
Frankfurt, On Bullshit, page !5
opinion polling, of psychological testing, and so forth—dedicate
themselves tirelessly to
getting every word and image they produce exactly right.
Yet there is something more to be said about this. However
studiously and
conscientiously the bullshitter proceeds, it remains true that he
is also trying to get away
with something. There is surely in his work, as in the work of
the slovenly craftsman,
some kind of laxity that resists or eludes the demands of a
disinterested and austere
discipline. The pertinent mode of laxity cannot be equated,
evidently, with simple
carelessness or inattention to detail. I shall attempt in due
course to locate it more
correctly.
Wittgenstein devoted his philosophical energies largely to
identifying and combating
what he regarded as insidiously disruptive forms of “nonsense.”
He was apparently like
that in his personal life as well. This comes out in an anecdote
related by Fania Pascal,
who knew him in Cambridge in the 1930s:
I had my tonsils out and was in the Evelyn Nursing Home
feeling sorry for
myself. Wittgenstein called. I croaked: “I feel just like a dog
that has been
run over.” He was disgusted: “You don’t know what a dog that
has been
run over feels like.” 6
Now who knows what really happened? It seems extraordinary,
almost unbelievable,
that anyone could object seriously to what Pascal reports herself
as having said. That
characterization of her feelings—so innocently close to the
utterly commonplace “sick as
a dog”—is simply not provocative enough to arouse any
response as lively or intense as
disgust. If Pascal’s simile is offensive, then what figurative or
allusive uses of language
would not be?
So perhaps it did not really happen quite as Pascal says. Perhaps
Wittgenstein was
trying to make a small joke, and it misfired. He was only
pretending to bawl Pascal out,
just for the fun of a little hyperbole; and she got the tone and
the intention wrong. She
thought he was disgusted by her remark, when in fact he was
only trying to cheer her up
with some playfully exaggerated mock criticism or joshing. In
that case the incident is
not incredible or bizarre after all.
But if Pascal failed to recognize that Wittgenstein was only
teasing, then perhaps the
possibility that he was serious was at least not so far out of the
question. She knew him,
and she knew what to expect from him; she knew how he made
her feel. Her way of
understanding or of misunderstanding his remark was very
likely not altogether
discordant, then, with her sense of what he was like. We may
fairly suppose that even if
her account of the incident is not strictly true to the facts of
Wittgenstein’s intention, it
is sufficiently true to her idea of Wittgenstein to have made
sense to her. For the
purposes of this discussion, I shall accept Pascal’s report at face
value, supposing that
when it came to the use of allusive or figurative language,
Wittgenstein was indeed as
preposterous as she makes him out to be.
Fania Pascal, “Wittgenstein: A Personal Memoir,” in Rhees,
Recollections, pp. 28-29.6
Frankfurt, On Bullshit, page !6
Then just what is it that the Wittgenstein in her report considers
to be objectionable?
Let us assume that he is correct about the facts: that is, Pascal
really does not know how
run-over dogs feel. Even so, when she says what she does, she
is plainly not lying. She
would have been lying if, when she made her statement, she was
aware that she actually
felt quite good. For however little she knows about the lives of
dogs, it must certainly be
clear to Pascal that when dogs are run over they do not feel
good. So if she herself had in
fact been feeling good, it would have been a lie to assert that
she felt like a run-over dog.
Pascal’s Wittgenstein intends to accuse her not of lying but of
misrepresentation of
another sort. She characterizes her feeling as “the feeling of a
run-over dog.” She is not
really acquainted, however, with the feeling to which this
phrase refers. Of course, the
phrase is far from being complete nonsense to her; she is hardly
speaking gibberish.
What she says has an intelligible connotation, which she
certainly understands.
Moreover, she does know something about the quality of the
feeling to which the phrase
refers: she knows at least that it is an undesirable and
unenjoyable feeling, a bad feeling.
The trouble with her statement is that it purports to convey
something more than simply
that she feels bad. Her characterization of her feeling is too
specific; it is excessively
particular. Hers is not just any bad feeling but, according to her
account, the distinctive
kind of bad feeling that a dog has when it is run over. To the
Wittgenstein in Pascal’s
story, judging from his response, this is just bullshit.
Now assuming that Wittgenstein does indeed regard Pascal’s
characterization of how
she feels as an instance of bullshit, why does it strike him that
way? It does so, I believe,
because he perceives what Pascal says as being—roughly
speaking, for now—
unconnected to a concern with the truth. Her statement is not
germane to the enterprise
of describing reality. She does not even think she knows, except
in the vaguest way, how
a run-over dog feels. Her description of her own feeling is,
accordingly, something that
she is merely making up. She concocts it out of whole cloth; or,
if she got it from
someone else, she is repeating it quite mindlessly and without
any regard for how things
really are.
It is for this mindlessness that Pascal’s Wittgenstein chides her.
What disgusts him is
that Pascal is not even concerned whether her statement is
correct. There is every
likelihood, of course, that she says what she does only in a
somewhat clumsy effort to
speak colorfully, or to appear vivacious or good-humored; and
no doubt Wittgenstein’s
reaction—as she construes it—is absurdly intolerant. Be this as
it may, it seems clear
what that reaction is. He reacts as though he perceives her to be
speaking about her
feeling thoughtlessly, without conscientious attention to the
relevant facts. Her
statement is not “wrought with greatest care.” She makes it
without bothering to take
into account at all the question of its accuracy.
The point that troubles Wittgenstein is manifestly not that
Pascal has made a mistake in
her description of how she feels. Nor is it even that she has
made a careless mistake. Her
laxity, or her lack of care, is not a matter of having permitted an
error to slip into her
speech on account of some inadvertent or momentarily negligent
lapse in the attention
she was devoting to getting things right. The point is rather
that, so far as Wittgenstein
Frankfurt, On Bullshit, page !7
can see, Pascal offers a description of a certain state of affairs
without genuinely
submitting to the constraints which the endeavor to provide an
accurate representation
of reality imposes. Her fault is not that she fails to get things
right, but that she is not
even trying.
This is important to Wittgenstein because, whether justifiably or
not, he takes what she
says seriously, as a statement purporting to give an informative
description of the way
she feels. He construes her as engaged in an activity to which
the distinction between
what is true and what is false is crucial, and yet as taking no
interest in whether what
she says is true or false. It is in this sense that Pascal’s
statement is unconnected to a
concern with truth: she is not concerned with the truth-value of
what she says. That is
why she cannot be regarded as lying; for she does not presume
that she knows the truth,
and therefore she cannot be deliberately promulgating a
proposition that she presumes
to be false: Her statement is grounded neither in a belief that it
is true nor, as a lie must
be, in a belief that it is not true. It is just this lack of connection
to a concern with truth—
this indifference to how things really are—that I regard as of
the essence of bullshit.
Now I shall consider (quite selectively) certain items in the
Oxford English Dictionary
that are pertinent to clarifying the nature of bullshit. The OED
defines a bull session as
“an informal conversation or discussion, esp. of a group of
males.” Now as a definition,
this seems wrong. For one thing, the dictionary evidently
supposes that the use of the
term bull in bull session serves primarily just to indicate
gender. But even if it were true
that the participants in bull sessions are generally or typically
males, the assertion that a
bull session is essentially nothing more particular than an
informal discussion among
males would be as far off the mark as the parallel assertion that
a hen session is simply
an informal conversation among females. It is probably true that
the participants in hen
sessions must be females. Nonetheless the term hen session
conveys something more
specific than this concerning the particular kind of informal
conversation among
females to which hen sessions are characteristically devoted.
What is distinctive about
the sort of informal discussion among males that constitutes a
bull session is, it seems to
me, something like this: while the discussion may be intense
and significant, it is in a
certain respect not “for real.”
The characteristic topics of a bull session have to do with very
personal and emotion-
laden aspects of life—for instance, religion, politics, or sex.
People are generally
reluctant to speak altogether openly about these topics if they
expect that they might be
taken too seriously. What tends to go on in a bull session is that
the participants try out
various thoughts and attitudes in order to see how it feels to
hear themselves saying
such things and in order to discover how others respond,
without its being assumed that
they are committed to what they say: it is understood by
everyone in a bull session that
the statements people make do not necessarily reveal what they
really believe or how
they really feel. The main point is to make possible a high level
of candor and an
experimental or adventuresome approach to the subjects under
discussion. Therefore
provision is made for enjoying a certain irresponsibility, so that
people will be
encouraged to convey what is on their minds without too much
anxiety that they will be
held to it.
Frankfurt, On Bullshit, page !8
Each of the contributors to a bull session relies, in other words,
upon a general
recognition that what he expresses or says is not to be
understood as being what he
means wholeheartedly or believes unequivocally to be true. The
purpose of the
conversation is not to communicate beliefs. Accordingly, the
usual assumptions about
the connection between what people say and what they believe
are suspended. The
statements made in a bull session differ from bullshit in that
there is no pretense that
this connection is being sustained. They are like bullshit by
virtue of the fact that they
are in some degree unconstrained by a concern with truth. This
resemblance between
bull sessions and bullshit is suggested also by the term shooting
the bull, which refers to
the sort of conversation that characterizes bull sessions and in
which the term shooting
is very likely a cleaned-up rendition of shitting. The very term
bull session is, indeed,
quite probably a sanitized version of bullshit session.
A similar theme is discernible in a British usage of bull in
which, according to the OED,
the term refers to “unnecessary routine tasks or ceremonial;
excessive discipline or ‘spit-
and-polish’; = red-tape.” The dictionary provides the following
examples of this usage:
The Squadron . . . felt very bolshie about all that bull that was
flying
around the station (I. Gleed, Arise to Conquer vi. 51, 1942);
Them turning
out the guard for us, us marching past eyes right, all that sort of
bull (A.
Baron, Human Kind xxiv. 178, 1953); the drudgery and ‘bull’ in
an MP’s
life (Economist 8 Feb. 470/471, 1958).
Here the term bull evidently pertains to tasks that are pointless
in that they have
nothing much to do with the primary intent or justifying
purpose of the enterprise which
requires them. Spit-and polish and red tape do not genuinely
contribute, it is presumed,
to the “real” purposes of military personnel or government
officials, even though they
are imposed by agencies or agents that purport to be
conscientiously devoted to the
pursuit of those purposes. Thus the “unnecessary routine tasks
or ceremonial” that
constitute bull are disconnected from the legitimating motives
of the activity upon
which they intrude, just as the things people say in bull sessions
are disconnected from
their settled beliefs, and as bullshit is disconnected from a
concern with the truth.
The term bull is also employed, in a rather more widespread and
familiar usage, as a
somewhat less coarse equivalent of bullshit. In an entry for bull
as so used, the OED
suggests the following as definitive: “trivial, insincere, or
untruthful talk or writing;
nonsense.” Now it does not seem distinctive of bull either that it
must be deficient in
meaning or that it is necessarily unimportant; so “nonsense” and
“trivial,” even apart
from their vagueness, seem to be on the wrong track. The focus
of “insincere, or
untruthful” is better, but it needs to be sharpened. The entry at
hand also provides the 7
following two definitions:
1914 Dialect Notes IV. 162 Bull, talk which is not to the
purpose; ‘hot air’.
It may be noted that the inclusion of insincerity among its
essential conditions would imply that bull cannot be 7
produced inadvertently; for it hardly seems possible to be
inadvertently insincere.
Frankfurt, On Bullshit, page !9
1932 Times Lit. Supp. 8 Dec. 933/3 ‘Bull’ is the slang term for
a
combination of bluff, bravado, ‘hot air’, and what we used to
call in the
Army ‘Kidding the troops’.
“Not to the purpose” is appropriate, but it is both too broad in
scope and too vague. It
covers digressions and innocent irrelevancies, which are not
invariably instances of bull;
furthermore, saying that bull is not to the purpose leaves it
uncertain what purpose is
meant. The reference in both definitions to “hot air” is more
helpful.
When we characterize talk as hot air, we mean that what comes
out of the speaker’s
mouth is only that. It is mere vapor. His speech is empty,
without substance or content.
His use of language, accordingly, does not contribute to the
purpose it purports to serve.
No more information is communicated than if the speaker had
merely exhaled. There
are similarities between hot air and excrement, incidentally,
which make hot air seem an
especially suitable equivalent for bullshit. Just as hot air is
speech that has been emptied
of all informative content, so excrement is matter from which
everything nutritive has
been removed. Excrement may be regarded as the corpse of
nourishment, what remains
when the vital elements in food have been exhausted. In this
respect, excrement is a
representation of death that we ourselves produce and that,
indeed, we cannot help
producing in the very process of maintaining our lives. Perhaps
it is for making death so
intimate that we find excrement so repulsive. In any event, it
cannot serve the purposes
of sustenance, any more than hot air can serve those of
communication.
Now consider these lines from Pound’s Canto LXXIV, which
the OED cites in its entry
on bullshit as a verb:
Hey Snag wots in the bibl’?
Wot are the books ov the bible?
Name ’em, don’t bullshit ME. 8
This is a call for the facts. The person addressed is evidently
regarded as having in some
way claimed to know the Bible, or as having claimed to care
about it. The speaker
suspects that this is just empty talk, and demands that the claim
be supported with
facts. He will not accept a mere report; he insists upon seeing
the thing itself. In other
words, he is calling the bluff. The connection between bullshit
and bluff is affirmed
explicitly in the definition with which the lines by Pound are
associated:
Here is part of the context in which these lines occur: “Les
Albigeois, a problem of history, / and the fleet at Salamis 8
made with money lent by the state to the shipwrights / Tempus
tacendi, tempus loquendi. / Never inside the country
to raise the standard of living / but always abroad to increase
the profits of usurers, / dixit Lenin, / and gun sales lead
to more gun sales / they do not clutter the market for gunnery /
there is no saturation / Pisa, in the 23rd year of the
effort in sight of the tower / and Till was hung yesterday / for
murder and rape with trimmings plus Cholkis / plus
mythology, thought he was Zeus ram or another one / Hey Snag
wots in the bibl’? / Wot are the books ov the bible? /
Name ’em, don’t bullshit ME.”
Frankfurt, On Bullshit, page !10
As v. trans. and intr., to talk nonsense (to); . . . also, to bluff
one’s way
through (something) by talking nonsense.
It does seem that bullshitting involves a kind of bluff. It is
closer to bluffing, surely, than
to telling a lie. But what is implied concerning its nature by the
fact that it is more like
the former than it is like the latter? Just what is the relevant
difference here between a
bluff and a lie?
Lying and bluffing are both modes of misrepresentation or
deception. Now the concept
most central to the distinctive nature of a lie is that of falsity:
the liar is essentially
someone who deliberately promulgates a falsehood. Bluffing,
too, is typically devoted to
conveying something false. Unlike plain lying, however, it is
more especially a matter
not of falsity but of fakery. This is what accounts for its
nearness to bullshit. For the
essence of bullshit is not that it is false but that it is phony. In
order to appreciate this
distinction, one must recognize that a fake or a phony need not
be in any respect (apart
from authenticity itself) inferior to the real thing. What is not
genuine need not also be
defective in some other way. It may be, after all, an exact copy.
What is wrong with a
counterfeit is not what it is like, but how it was made. This
points to a similar and
fundamental aspect of the essential nature of bullshit: although
it is produced without
concern with the truth, it need not be false. The bullshitter is
faking things. But this does
not mean that he necessarily gets them wrong.
In Eric Ambler’s novel Dirty Story, a character named Arthur
Abdel Simpson recalls
advice that he received as a child from his father:
Although I was only seven when my father was killed, I still
remember him
very well and some of the things he used to say. . . . One of the
first things
he taught me was, “Never tell a lie when you can bullshit your
way
through.” 9
This presumes not only that there is an important difference
between lying and
bullshitting, but that the latter is preferable to the former. Now
the elder Simpson surely
did not consider bullshitting morally superior to lying. Nor is it
likely that he regarded
lies as invariably less effective than bullshit in accomplishing
the purposes for which
either of them might be employed. After all, an intelligently
crafted lie may do its work
with unqualified success. It may be that Simpson thought it
easier to get away with
bullshitting than with lying. Or perhaps he meant that, although
the risk of being caught
is about the same in each case, the consequences of being
caught are generally less
severe for the bullshitter than for the liar. In fact, people do
tend to be more tolerant of
bullshit than of lies, perhaps because we are less inclined to
take the former as a
personal affront. We may seek to distance ourselves from
bullshit, but we are more
E. Ambler, Dirty Story (1967), I. iii. 25. The citation is
provided in the same OED entry as the one that includes the 9
passage from Pound. The closeness of the relation between
bullshitting and bluffing is resonant, it seems to me, in the
parallelism of the idioms: “bullshit your way through” and
“bluff your way through.”
Frankfurt, On Bullshit, page !11
likely to turn away from it with an impatient or irritated shrug
than with the sense of
violation or outrage that lies often inspire. The problem of
understanding why our
attitude toward bullshit is generally more benign than our
attitude toward lying is an
important one, which I shall leave as an exercise for the reader.
The pertinent comparison is not, however, between telling a lie
and producing some
particular instance of bullshit. The elder Simpson identifies the
alternative to telling a lie
as “bullshitting one’s way through.” This involves not merely
producing one instance of
bullshit; it involves a program of producing bullshit to whatever
extent the
circumstances require. This is a key, perhaps, to his preference.
Telling a lie is an act
with a sharp focus. It is designed to insert a particular falsehood
at a specific point in a
set or system of beliefs, in order to avoid the consequences of
having that point occupied
by the truth. This requires a degree of craftsmanship, in which
the teller of the lie
submits to objective constraints imposed by what he takes to be
the truth. The liar is
inescapably concerned with truth-values. In order to invent a lie
at all, he must think he
knows what is true. And in order to invent an effective lie, he
must design his falsehood
under the guidance of that truth.
On the other hand, a person who undertakes to bullshit his way
through has much more
freedom. His focus is panoramic rather than particular. He does
not limit himself to
inserting a certain falsehood at a specific point, and thus he is
not constrained by the
truths surrounding that point or intersecting it. He is prepared,
so far as required, to
fake the context as well. This freedom from the constraints to
which the liar must
submit does not necessarily mean, of course, that his task is
easier than the task of the
liar. But the mode of creativity upon which it relies is less
analytical and less deliberative
than that which is mobilized in lying. It is more expansive and
independent, with more
spacious opportunities for improvisation, color, and imaginative
play. This is less a
matter of craft than of art. Hence the familiar notion of the
“bullshit artist.” My guess is
that the recommendation offered by Arthur Simpson’s father
reflects the fact that he
was more strongly drawn to this mode of creativity, regardless
of its relative merit or
effectiveness, than he was to the more austere and rigorous
demands of lying.
What bullshit essentially misrepresents is neither the state of
affairs to which it refers
nor the beliefs of the speaker concerning that state of affairs.
Those are what lies
misrepresent, by virtue of being false. Since bullshit need not
be false, it differs from lies
in its misrepresentational intent. The bullshitter may not
deceive us, or even intend to
do so, either about the facts or about what he takes the facts to
be. What he does
necessarily attempt to deceive us about is his enterprise. His
only indispensably
distinctive characteristic is that in a certain way he
misrepresents what he is up to.
This is the crux of the distinction between him and the liar.
Both he and the liar
represent themselves falsely as endeavoring to communicate the
truth. The success of
each depends upon deceiving us about that. But the fact about
himself that the liar hides
is that he is attempting to lead us away from a correct
apprehension of reality; we are
not to know that he wants us to believe something he supposes
to be false. The fact
about himself that the bullshitter hides, on the other hand, is
that the truth-values of his
Frankfurt, On Bullshit, page !12
statements are of no central interest to him; what we are not to
understand is that his
intention is neither to report the truth nor to conceal it. This
does not mean that his
speech is anarchically impulsive, but that the motive guiding
and controlling it is
unconcerned with how the things about which he speaks truly
are.
It is impossible for someone to lie unless he thinks he knows
the truth. Producing
bullshit requires no such conviction. A person who lies is
thereby responding to the
truth, and he is to that extent respectful of it. When an honest
man speaks, he says only
what he believes to be true; and for the liar, it is
correspondingly indispensable that he
considers his statements to be false. For the bullshitter,
however, all these bets are off:
he is neither on the side of the true nor on the side of the false.
His eye is not on the facts
at all, as the eyes of the honest man and of the liar are, except
insofar as they may be
pertinent to his interest in getting away with what he says. He
does not care whether the
things he says describe reality correctly. He just picks them out,
or makes them up, to
suit his purpose.
In his essay “Lying,” Saint Augustine distinguishes lies of eight
types, which he classifies
according to the characteristic intent or justification with which
a lie is told. Lies of
seven of these types are told only because they are supposed to
be indispensable means
to some end that is distinct from the sheer creation of false
beliefs. It is not their falsity
as such, in other words, that attracts the teller to them. Since
they are told only on
account of their supposed indispensability to a goal other than
deception itself, Saint
Augustine regards them as being told unwillingly: what the
person really wants is not to
tell the lie but to attain the goal. They are therefore not real
lies, in his view, and those
who tell them are not in the strictest sense liars. It is only the
remaining category that
contains what he identifies as “the lie which is told solely for
the pleasure of lying and
deceiving, that is, the real lie.” Lies in this category are not
told as means to any end 10
distinct from the propagation of falsehood. They are told simply
for their own sakes—
i.e., purely out of a love of deception:
There is a distinction between a person who tells a lie and a
liar. The
former is one who tells a lie unwillingly, while the liar loves to
lie and
passes his time in the joy of lying. . . . The latter takes delight
in lying,
rejoicing in the falsehood itself. 11
What Augustine calls “liars” and “real lies” are both rare and
extraordinary. Everyone
lies from time to time, but there are very few people to whom it
would often (or even
ever) occur to lie exclusively from a love of falsity or of
deception.
For most people, the fact that a statement is false constitutes in
itself a reason, however
weak and easily overridden, not to make the statement. For
Saint Augustine’s pure liar it
is, on the contrary, a reason in favor of making it. For the
bullshitter it is in itself neither
“Lying,” in Treatises on Various Subjects, in Fathers of the
Church, ed. R. J. Deferrari, vol. 16 (New York: Fathers of 10
the Church, 1952), p. 109. Saint Augustine maintains that
telling a lie of this type is a less serious sin than telling lies
in three of his categories and a more serious sin than telling lies
in the other four categories.
Ibid., p. 79.11
Frankfurt, On Bullshit, page !13
a reason in favor nor a reason against. Both in lying and in
telling the truth people are
guided by their beliefs concerning the way things are. These
guide them as they
endeavor either to describe the world correctly or to describe it
deceitfully. For this
reason, telling lies does not tend to unfit a person for telling the
truth in the same way
that bullshitting tends to. Through excessive indulgence in the
latter activity, which
involves making assertions without paying attention to anything
except what it suits one
to say, a person’s normal habit of attending to the ways things
are may become
attenuated or lost. Someone who lies and someone who tells the
truth are playing on
opposite sides, so to speak, in the same game. Each responds to
the facts as he
understands them, although the response of the one is guided by
the authority of the
truth, while the response of the other defies that authority and
refuses to meet its
demands. The bullshitter ignores these demands altogether. He
does not reject the
authority of the truth, as the liar does, and oppose himself to it.
He pays no attention to
it at all. By virtue of this, bullshit is a greater enemy of the
truth than lies are.
One who is concerned to report or to conceal the facts assumes
that there are indeed
facts that are in some way both determinate and knowable. His
interest in telling the
truth or in lying presupposes that there is a difference between
getting things wrong and
getting them right, and that it is at least occasionally possible to
tell the difference.
Someone who ceases to believe in the possibility of identifying
certain statements as true
and others as false can have only two alternatives. The first is
to desist both from efforts
to tell the truth and from efforts to deceive. This would mean
refraining from making
any assertion whatever about the facts. The second alternative is
to continue making
assertions that purport to describe the way things are, but that
cannot be anything
except bullshit.
Why is there so much bullshit? Of course it is impossible to be
sure that there is
relatively more of it nowadays than at other times. There is
more communication of all
kinds in our time than ever before, but the proportion that is
bullshit may not have
increased. Without assuming that the incidence of bullshit is
actually greater now, I will
mention a few considerations that help to account for the fact
that it is currently so
great.
Bullshit is unavoidable whenever circumstances require
someone to talk without
knowing what he is talking about. Thus the production of
bullshit is stimulated
whenever a person’s obligations or opportunities to speak about
some topic exceed his
knowledge of the facts that are relevant to that topic. This
discrepancy is common in
public life, where people are frequently impelled—whether by
their own propensities or
by the demands of others—to speak extensively about matters of
which they are to some
degree ignorant. Closely related instances arise from the
widespread conviction that it is
the responsibility of a citizen in a democracy to have opinions
about everything, or at
least everything that pertains to the conduct of his country’s
affairs. The lack of any
significant connection between a person’s opinions and his
apprehension of reality will
be even more severe, needless to say, for someone who believes
it his responsibility, as a
conscientious moral agent, to evaluate events and conditions in
all parts of the world.
Frankfurt, On Bullshit, page !14
The contemporary proliferation of bullshit also has deeper
sources, in various forms of
skepticism which deny that we can have any reliable access to
an objective reality, and
which therefore reject the possibility of knowing how things
truly are. These “antirealist”
doctrines undermine confidence in the value of disinterested
efforts to determine what
is true and what is false, and even in the intelligibility of the
notion of objective inquiry.
One response to this loss of confidence has been a retreat from
the discipline required
by dedication to the ideal of correctness to a quite different sort
of discipline, which is
imposed by pursuit of an alternative ideal of sincerity. Rather
than seeking primarily to
arrive at accurate representations of a common world, the
individual turns toward
trying to provide honest representations of himself. Convinced
that reality has no
inherent nature, which he might hope to identify as the truth
about things, he devotes
himself to being true to his own nature. It is as though he
decides that since it makes no
sense to try to be true to the facts, he must therefore try instead
to be true to himself.
But it is preposterous to imagine that we ourselves are
determinate, and hence
susceptible both to correct and to incorrect descriptions, while
supposing that the
ascription of determinacy to anything else has been exposed as
a mistake. As conscious
beings, we exist only in response to other things, and we cannot
know ourselves at all
without knowing them. Moreover, there is nothing in theory,
and certainly nothing in
experience, to support the extraordinary judgment that it is the
truth about himself that
is the easiest for a person to know. Facts about ourselves are
not peculiarly solid and
resistant to skeptical dissolution. Our natures are, indeed,
elusively insubstantial—
notoriously less stable and less inherent than the natures of
other things. And insofar as
this is the case, sincerity itself is bullshit.
Frankfurt, On Bullshit, page !15
Dunkin Donuts
My name
Institution
Course
Instructor
Date
Introduction
Consumer Reference
Feasibility Test
Market Scope
Testing and Customer Acceptance
Staffing
Roll Out Plan
CUSTOMER PREFERENCE
Market research and analysis
Competitor strategies
There is need to do market analysis so as to understand further
what the customers want. Without market research, products and
services offered will be null and void. Market research will also
help understand what kind of product the customer and it is not
being offered by competitors. It helps the business understand
the strategies of competitors. The business will find ways of
outperforming competitors based on what the customers prefer.
3
FEASIBILITY TEST
Costs of starting the business
Profit projections
It is important to perform a feasibility test so to find out how
much the business will cost. This the point that determines
whether it is worth investing in the business. This where a
forecast will be made to see projections. How long will it take
the business to realize profits.
4
MARKET SCOPE
Customers explore new brands
Implement new technologies
Make informed decisions
Undertaking market scope is to find the rational consumers who
are keen on trying to explore new brands in the market. This
phase helps in implementing new techniques of how to to do
business. It will assist the company in making informed
decisions hence reducing customer loss. It enables the company
to meet customer demands effectively. Satisfied customers will
ensure that the business keep growing.
5
CUSTOMER ACCEPTANCE
The ultimate goal for every study is to answer key questions and
provide up-to-date and reliable information to support the
client’s strategic business planning.
Pricing strategies
The best way for a business to penetrate the market is if the
customers accept the products and services that are being
offered by the business. Here the business will set prices that
are favorable to the customers. Not too high to push away
consumers and not too low to avoid making losses.
6
DUNKIN’S STAFFING
Employ qualified employees
Employees who share the visions of the business
Clearly state roles of each employee
Services will not perform themselves. A business needs
employees to attend to customers. A business needs qualified
employees who relate easily to customers and work faster to
meet the requests of customers. Good employees will the reason
customers keep coming to buy from the business. If the area is
full youths, the business needs youths who can easily
understand the demands of customers.
7
ROLL OUT
Identify your niche and make sure the uniqueness of your
product stands out.
Brand the product well in order to attract new customers as
well.
Perform a SWOT analysis and monitor your products’ life cycle.
After all factors have been considered and observed, it is time
to roll out the business. The best to win customers when the
business becomes operational is to brand the business. Unique
branding will draw customers away from competitors. The
business needs to do a SWOT analysis and monitor the lifecycle
of the products. The business needs to find a suitable location to
set up the business. This is where the business finds out if the
customers are satisfied with the services being offered.
8
Conclusion
offer unique services
Employ qualified employees
Meet the demands of customers
Employ reasonable prices
In conclusion, for a business to be a success the level of
attracting customers should be high. The business must employ
better strategies that will run competitors out of business. The
best strategies is offering unique products, reasonable prices on
products. Employees should be qualified and easily understand
the preferences of customers.
9

More Related Content

Similar to Dunkin DonutsMy nameInstitutionCourseInstructorDate.docx

CDI Founder Workshop Session 4 - Lean Startup Methodologies (Fall 2016)
CDI Founder Workshop Session 4 - Lean Startup Methodologies (Fall 2016)CDI Founder Workshop Session 4 - Lean Startup Methodologies (Fall 2016)
CDI Founder Workshop Session 4 - Lean Startup Methodologies (Fall 2016)
Collaboratory for Downtown Innovation
 
How Do I Get A Job With...
How Do I Get A Job With...How Do I Get A Job With...
How Do I Get A Job With...
Chuck Boyer
 
lightspeed-best-practices-for-hiring
lightspeed-best-practices-for-hiringlightspeed-best-practices-for-hiring
lightspeed-best-practices-for-hiring
Helen Morris
 
Rebounding from job loss
Rebounding from job lossRebounding from job loss
Rebounding from job loss
Chelse Benham
 

Similar to Dunkin DonutsMy nameInstitutionCourseInstructorDate.docx (20)

CDI Founder Workshop Session 4 - Lean Startup Methodologies (Fall 2016)
CDI Founder Workshop Session 4 - Lean Startup Methodologies (Fall 2016)CDI Founder Workshop Session 4 - Lean Startup Methodologies (Fall 2016)
CDI Founder Workshop Session 4 - Lean Startup Methodologies (Fall 2016)
 
English And Marketing
English And MarketingEnglish And Marketing
English And Marketing
 
How Do I Get A Job With...
How Do I Get A Job With...How Do I Get A Job With...
How Do I Get A Job With...
 
How Do I Get A Job With...
How Do I Get A Job With...How Do I Get A Job With...
How Do I Get A Job With...
 
lightspeed-best-practices-for-hiring
lightspeed-best-practices-for-hiringlightspeed-best-practices-for-hiring
lightspeed-best-practices-for-hiring
 
Corporates – the key to the promised land
Corporates – the key to the promised landCorporates – the key to the promised land
Corporates – the key to the promised land
 
Self Autobiography Essay Sample. Online assignment writing service.
Self Autobiography Essay Sample. Online assignment writing service.Self Autobiography Essay Sample. Online assignment writing service.
Self Autobiography Essay Sample. Online assignment writing service.
 
AIESEC Case Competition Pre-Work
AIESEC Case Competition Pre-WorkAIESEC Case Competition Pre-Work
AIESEC Case Competition Pre-Work
 
Writing For Money J Fleming
Writing For Money J FlemingWriting For Money J Fleming
Writing For Money J Fleming
 
The CEO As Brand
The CEO As BrandThe CEO As Brand
The CEO As Brand
 
10 truths
10 truths10 truths
10 truths
 
10 truths
10 truths10 truths
10 truths
 
10 truths
10 truths10 truths
10 truths
 
10 truths
10 truths10 truths
10 truths
 
The 7 must haves for a successful agency pitch
The 7 must haves for a successful agency pitchThe 7 must haves for a successful agency pitch
The 7 must haves for a successful agency pitch
 
Pigeonhole Yourself
Pigeonhole YourselfPigeonhole Yourself
Pigeonhole Yourself
 
Rebounding From Job Loss
Rebounding From Job LossRebounding From Job Loss
Rebounding From Job Loss
 
Rebounding from job loss
Rebounding from job lossRebounding from job loss
Rebounding from job loss
 
Golden potential for entrepreneurs from the start
Golden potential for entrepreneurs from the startGolden potential for entrepreneurs from the start
Golden potential for entrepreneurs from the start
 
Case-in-Point - Copy.pdf
Case-in-Point - Copy.pdfCase-in-Point - Copy.pdf
Case-in-Point - Copy.pdf
 

More from infantkimber

During this Module, you will be required to complete a Discussio.docx
During this Module, you will be required to complete a Discussio.docxDuring this Module, you will be required to complete a Discussio.docx
During this Module, you will be required to complete a Discussio.docx
infantkimber
 
During the two decades following WWII, significant political, social.docx
During the two decades following WWII, significant political, social.docxDuring the two decades following WWII, significant political, social.docx
During the two decades following WWII, significant political, social.docx
infantkimber
 
During the semester in which the student is enrolled in MUL2380, o.docx
During the semester in which the student is enrolled in MUL2380, o.docxDuring the semester in which the student is enrolled in MUL2380, o.docx
During the semester in which the student is enrolled in MUL2380, o.docx
infantkimber
 
During the late 1960s and early 1970s, cognitive psychology rese.docx
During the late 1960s and early 1970s, cognitive psychology rese.docxDuring the late 1960s and early 1970s, cognitive psychology rese.docx
During the late 1960s and early 1970s, cognitive psychology rese.docx
infantkimber
 
During the Renaissance and Baroque periods the type of patron divers.docx
During the Renaissance and Baroque periods the type of patron divers.docxDuring the Renaissance and Baroque periods the type of patron divers.docx
During the Renaissance and Baroque periods the type of patron divers.docx
infantkimber
 
During the quarter, you should keep a typed or handwritten journal r.docx
During the quarter, you should keep a typed or handwritten journal r.docxDuring the quarter, you should keep a typed or handwritten journal r.docx
During the quarter, you should keep a typed or handwritten journal r.docx
infantkimber
 

More from infantkimber (20)

During this time when the Internet provides essential communicat.docx
During this time when the Internet provides essential communicat.docxDuring this time when the Internet provides essential communicat.docx
During this time when the Internet provides essential communicat.docx
 
During this period, the Impressionists became very interested in Jap.docx
During this period, the Impressionists became very interested in Jap.docxDuring this period, the Impressionists became very interested in Jap.docx
During this period, the Impressionists became very interested in Jap.docx
 
During this Module, you will be required to complete a Discussio.docx
During this Module, you will be required to complete a Discussio.docxDuring this Module, you will be required to complete a Discussio.docx
During this Module, you will be required to complete a Discussio.docx
 
During this module, we review the concept of technology structures a.docx
During this module, we review the concept of technology structures a.docxDuring this module, we review the concept of technology structures a.docx
During this module, we review the concept of technology structures a.docx
 
During the two decades following WWII, significant political, social.docx
During the two decades following WWII, significant political, social.docxDuring the two decades following WWII, significant political, social.docx
During the two decades following WWII, significant political, social.docx
 
During the unprecedented times caused by the novel coronavirus d.docx
During the unprecedented times caused by the novel coronavirus d.docxDuring the unprecedented times caused by the novel coronavirus d.docx
During the unprecedented times caused by the novel coronavirus d.docx
 
During the time of the High Renaissance, culture and values varied d.docx
During the time of the High Renaissance, culture and values varied d.docxDuring the time of the High Renaissance, culture and values varied d.docx
During the time of the High Renaissance, culture and values varied d.docx
 
During the Reconstruction Era, the Southern states created many .docx
During the Reconstruction Era, the Southern states created many .docxDuring the Reconstruction Era, the Southern states created many .docx
During the Reconstruction Era, the Southern states created many .docx
 
During the semester in which the student is enrolled in MUL2380, o.docx
During the semester in which the student is enrolled in MUL2380, o.docxDuring the semester in which the student is enrolled in MUL2380, o.docx
During the semester in which the student is enrolled in MUL2380, o.docx
 
During the Reconstruction period, Congress became consumed with part.docx
During the Reconstruction period, Congress became consumed with part.docxDuring the Reconstruction period, Congress became consumed with part.docx
During the Reconstruction period, Congress became consumed with part.docx
 
During the late 1960s and early 1970s, cognitive psychology rese.docx
During the late 1960s and early 1970s, cognitive psychology rese.docxDuring the late 1960s and early 1970s, cognitive psychology rese.docx
During the late 1960s and early 1970s, cognitive psychology rese.docx
 
During the Renaissance and Baroque periods the type of patron divers.docx
During the Renaissance and Baroque periods the type of patron divers.docxDuring the Renaissance and Baroque periods the type of patron divers.docx
During the Renaissance and Baroque periods the type of patron divers.docx
 
During the Reagan Bush years there were many changes in America. P.docx
During the Reagan  Bush years there were many changes in America. P.docxDuring the Reagan  Bush years there were many changes in America. P.docx
During the Reagan Bush years there were many changes in America. P.docx
 
During the quarter, you should keep a typed or handwritten journal r.docx
During the quarter, you should keep a typed or handwritten journal r.docxDuring the quarter, you should keep a typed or handwritten journal r.docx
During the quarter, you should keep a typed or handwritten journal r.docx
 
During the quarter, Andronache Inc. collected $100 of cash from cust.docx
During the quarter, Andronache Inc. collected $100 of cash from cust.docxDuring the quarter, Andronache Inc. collected $100 of cash from cust.docx
During the quarter, Andronache Inc. collected $100 of cash from cust.docx
 
During the previous 30 years, the airline industry has experienced m.docx
During the previous 30 years, the airline industry has experienced m.docxDuring the previous 30 years, the airline industry has experienced m.docx
During the previous 30 years, the airline industry has experienced m.docx
 
During the previous weeks, you have developed your public speaki.docx
During the previous weeks, you have developed your public speaki.docxDuring the previous weeks, you have developed your public speaki.docx
During the previous weeks, you have developed your public speaki.docx
 
During the previous weeks, you have developed your public speaking s.docx
During the previous weeks, you have developed your public speaking s.docxDuring the previous weeks, you have developed your public speaking s.docx
During the previous weeks, you have developed your public speaking s.docx
 
During the last quarter of the century before 1900, a great movement.docx
During the last quarter of the century before 1900, a great movement.docxDuring the last quarter of the century before 1900, a great movement.docx
During the last quarter of the century before 1900, a great movement.docx
 
DueApr 25 by 11pmPoints50Submittinga file .docx
DueApr 25 by 11pmPoints50Submittinga file .docxDueApr 25 by 11pmPoints50Submittinga file .docx
DueApr 25 by 11pmPoints50Submittinga file .docx
 

Recently uploaded

Call Girls in Uttam Nagar (delhi) call me [🔝9953056974🔝] escort service 24X7
Call Girls in  Uttam Nagar (delhi) call me [🔝9953056974🔝] escort service 24X7Call Girls in  Uttam Nagar (delhi) call me [🔝9953056974🔝] escort service 24X7
Call Girls in Uttam Nagar (delhi) call me [🔝9953056974🔝] escort service 24X7
9953056974 Low Rate Call Girls In Saket, Delhi NCR
 

Recently uploaded (20)

This PowerPoint helps students to consider the concept of infinity.
This PowerPoint helps students to consider the concept of infinity.This PowerPoint helps students to consider the concept of infinity.
This PowerPoint helps students to consider the concept of infinity.
 
Jamworks pilot and AI at Jisc (20/03/2024)
Jamworks pilot and AI at Jisc (20/03/2024)Jamworks pilot and AI at Jisc (20/03/2024)
Jamworks pilot and AI at Jisc (20/03/2024)
 
Towards a code of practice for AI in AT.pptx
Towards a code of practice for AI in AT.pptxTowards a code of practice for AI in AT.pptx
Towards a code of practice for AI in AT.pptx
 
Understanding Accommodations and Modifications
Understanding  Accommodations and ModificationsUnderstanding  Accommodations and Modifications
Understanding Accommodations and Modifications
 
TỔNG ÔN TẬP THI VÀO LỚP 10 MÔN TIẾNG ANH NĂM HỌC 2023 - 2024 CÓ ĐÁP ÁN (NGỮ Â...
TỔNG ÔN TẬP THI VÀO LỚP 10 MÔN TIẾNG ANH NĂM HỌC 2023 - 2024 CÓ ĐÁP ÁN (NGỮ Â...TỔNG ÔN TẬP THI VÀO LỚP 10 MÔN TIẾNG ANH NĂM HỌC 2023 - 2024 CÓ ĐÁP ÁN (NGỮ Â...
TỔNG ÔN TẬP THI VÀO LỚP 10 MÔN TIẾNG ANH NĂM HỌC 2023 - 2024 CÓ ĐÁP ÁN (NGỮ Â...
 
80 ĐỀ THI THỬ TUYỂN SINH TIẾNG ANH VÀO 10 SỞ GD – ĐT THÀNH PHỐ HỒ CHÍ MINH NĂ...
80 ĐỀ THI THỬ TUYỂN SINH TIẾNG ANH VÀO 10 SỞ GD – ĐT THÀNH PHỐ HỒ CHÍ MINH NĂ...80 ĐỀ THI THỬ TUYỂN SINH TIẾNG ANH VÀO 10 SỞ GD – ĐT THÀNH PHỐ HỒ CHÍ MINH NĂ...
80 ĐỀ THI THỬ TUYỂN SINH TIẾNG ANH VÀO 10 SỞ GD – ĐT THÀNH PHỐ HỒ CHÍ MINH NĂ...
 
HMCS Max Bernays Pre-Deployment Brief (May 2024).pptx
HMCS Max Bernays Pre-Deployment Brief (May 2024).pptxHMCS Max Bernays Pre-Deployment Brief (May 2024).pptx
HMCS Max Bernays Pre-Deployment Brief (May 2024).pptx
 
Basic Civil Engineering first year Notes- Chapter 4 Building.pptx
Basic Civil Engineering first year Notes- Chapter 4 Building.pptxBasic Civil Engineering first year Notes- Chapter 4 Building.pptx
Basic Civil Engineering first year Notes- Chapter 4 Building.pptx
 
Sensory_Experience_and_Emotional_Resonance_in_Gabriel_Okaras_The_Piano_and_Th...
Sensory_Experience_and_Emotional_Resonance_in_Gabriel_Okaras_The_Piano_and_Th...Sensory_Experience_and_Emotional_Resonance_in_Gabriel_Okaras_The_Piano_and_Th...
Sensory_Experience_and_Emotional_Resonance_in_Gabriel_Okaras_The_Piano_and_Th...
 
Google Gemini An AI Revolution in Education.pptx
Google Gemini An AI Revolution in Education.pptxGoogle Gemini An AI Revolution in Education.pptx
Google Gemini An AI Revolution in Education.pptx
 
dusjagr & nano talk on open tools for agriculture research and learning
dusjagr & nano talk on open tools for agriculture research and learningdusjagr & nano talk on open tools for agriculture research and learning
dusjagr & nano talk on open tools for agriculture research and learning
 
Tatlong Kwento ni Lola basyang-1.pdf arts
Tatlong Kwento ni Lola basyang-1.pdf artsTatlong Kwento ni Lola basyang-1.pdf arts
Tatlong Kwento ni Lola basyang-1.pdf arts
 
Single or Multiple melodic lines structure
Single or Multiple melodic lines structureSingle or Multiple melodic lines structure
Single or Multiple melodic lines structure
 
Call Girls in Uttam Nagar (delhi) call me [🔝9953056974🔝] escort service 24X7
Call Girls in  Uttam Nagar (delhi) call me [🔝9953056974🔝] escort service 24X7Call Girls in  Uttam Nagar (delhi) call me [🔝9953056974🔝] escort service 24X7
Call Girls in Uttam Nagar (delhi) call me [🔝9953056974🔝] escort service 24X7
 
21st_Century_Skills_Framework_Final_Presentation_2.pptx
21st_Century_Skills_Framework_Final_Presentation_2.pptx21st_Century_Skills_Framework_Final_Presentation_2.pptx
21st_Century_Skills_Framework_Final_Presentation_2.pptx
 
Interdisciplinary_Insights_Data_Collection_Methods.pptx
Interdisciplinary_Insights_Data_Collection_Methods.pptxInterdisciplinary_Insights_Data_Collection_Methods.pptx
Interdisciplinary_Insights_Data_Collection_Methods.pptx
 
COMMUNICATING NEGATIVE NEWS - APPROACHES .pptx
COMMUNICATING NEGATIVE NEWS - APPROACHES .pptxCOMMUNICATING NEGATIVE NEWS - APPROACHES .pptx
COMMUNICATING NEGATIVE NEWS - APPROACHES .pptx
 
Simple, Complex, and Compound Sentences Exercises.pdf
Simple, Complex, and Compound Sentences Exercises.pdfSimple, Complex, and Compound Sentences Exercises.pdf
Simple, Complex, and Compound Sentences Exercises.pdf
 
Accessible Digital Futures project (20/03/2024)
Accessible Digital Futures project (20/03/2024)Accessible Digital Futures project (20/03/2024)
Accessible Digital Futures project (20/03/2024)
 
FSB Advising Checklist - Orientation 2024
FSB Advising Checklist - Orientation 2024FSB Advising Checklist - Orientation 2024
FSB Advising Checklist - Orientation 2024
 

Dunkin DonutsMy nameInstitutionCourseInstructorDate.docx

  • 1. Dunkin Donuts My name Institution Course Instructor Date Introduction Consumer Reference Feasibility Test Market Scope Testing and Customer Acceptance Staffing Roll Out Plan CUSTOMER PREFERENCE Market research and analysis Competitor strategies
  • 2. There is need to do market analysis so as to understand further what the customers want. Without market research, products and services offered will be null and void. Market research will also help understand what kind of product the customer and it is not being offered by competitors. It helps the business understand the strategies of competitors. The business will find ways of outperforming competitors based on what the customers prefer. 3 FEASIBILITY TEST Costs of starting the business Profit projections It is important to perform a feasibility test so to find out how much the business will cost. This the point that determines whether it is worth investing in the business. This where a forecast will be made to see projections. How long will it take the business to realize profits. 4 MARKET SCOPE Customers explore new brands Implement new technologies Make informed decisions Undertaking market scope is to find the rational consumers who are keen on trying to explore new brands in the market. This
  • 3. phase helps in implementing new techniques of how to to do business. It will assist the company in making informed decisions hence reducing customer loss. It enables the company to meet customer demands effectively. Satisfied customers will ensure that the business keep growing. 5 CUSTOMER ACCEPTANCE The ultimate goal for every study is to answer key questions and provide up-to-date and reliable information to support the client’s strategic business planning. Pricing strategies The best way for a business to penetrate the market is if the customers accept the products and services that are being offered by the business. Here the business will set prices that are favorable to the customers. Not too high to push away consumers and not too low to avoid making losses. 6 DUNKIN’S STAFFING Employ qualified employees Employees who share the visions of the business Clearly state roles of each employee Services will not perform themselves. A business needs employees to attend to customers. A business needs qualified
  • 4. employees who relate easily to customers and work faster to meet the requests of customers. Good employees will the reason customers keep coming to buy from the business. If the area is full youths, the business needs youths who can easily understand the demands of customers. 7 ROLL OUT Identify your niche and make sure the uniqueness of your product stands out. Brand the product well in order to attract new customers as well. Perform a SWOT analysis and monitor your products’ life cycle. After all factors have been considered and observed, it is time to roll out the business. The best to win customers when the business becomes operational is to brand the business. Unique branding will draw customers away from competitors. The business needs to do a SWOT analysis and monitor the lifecycle of the products. The business needs to find a suitable location to set up the business. This is where the business finds out if the customers are satisfied with the services being offered. 8 Conclusion offer unique services Employ qualified employees Meet the demands of customers Employ reasonable prices
  • 5. In conclusion, for a business to be a success the level of attracting customers should be high. The business must employ better strategies that will run competitors out of business. The best strategies is offering unique products, reasonable prices on products. Employees should be qualified and easily understand the preferences of customers. 9 David Graeber, Bullshit Jobs: A Theory (2018) Chapter 3: Why Do Those in Bullshit Jobs Regularly Report Themselves Unhappy? In this chapter, I’d like to start exploring some of the moral and psychological effects of being trapped inside a bullshit job. In particular, I want to ask the obvious question: Why is this even a problem? Or to phrase it more precisely: Why does having a pointless job so regularly cause people to be miserable? On the face of it, it’s not obvious that it should. After all, we’re talking about people who are effectively being paid— often very good money —to do nothing. One might imagine that those being paid to do nothing would consider themselves fortunate, especially when they are more or less left to themselves. But while every now and then I did hear testimonies
  • 6. from those who said they couldn’t believe their luck in landing such a position, the remarkable thing is how very few of them there were.1 Many, in fact, seemed perplexed by their own reaction, unable to understand why their situation left them feeling so worthless or depressed. Indeed, the fact that there was no clear explanation for their feelings—no story they could tell themselves about the nature of their situation and what was wrong about it—often contributed to their misery. At least a galley slave knows that he’s oppressed. An office worker forced to sit for seven and a half hours a day pretending to type into a screen for $18 an hour, or a junior member of a consultancy team forced to give the exact same seminar on innovation and creativity week in and week out for $50,000 a year, is just confused. In an earlier book about debt, I wrote about the phenomenon of “moral confusion.” I took as my example the fact that throughout human history, most people seem to have agreed both that paying back one’s debts was the essence of morality and that moneylenders were evil. While the rise of bullshit jobs is a comparatively recent phenomenon, I think it creates a similar moral embarrassment. On the one hand, everyone is encouraged to assume that human beings will always tend to seek their best advantage, that is, to
  • 7. find themselves a situation where they can get the most benefit for the least expenditure of time and effort, and for the most part, we do assume this—especially if we are talking about such matters in the abstract. (“We can’t just give poor people handouts! Then they won’t have any incentive to look for work!”) On the other hand, our own experience, and those of the people we are closest to, tends to contradict these assumptions at many points. People almost never act and react to situations in quite the way our theories of human nature would predict. The only reasonable conclusion is that, at least in certain key essentials, these theories about human nature are wrong. In this chapter, I don’t just want to ask why people are so unhappy doing what seems to them meaningless make-work, but to think more deeply about what that unhappiness can tell us about what people are and what they are basically about. Graeber, Bullshit Jobs: A Theory page !1 ABOUT ONE YOUNG MAN APPARENTLY HANDED A SINECURE WHO NONETHELESS FOUND HIMSELF UNABLE TO HANDLE THE SITUATION I will begin with a story. The following is the tale of a young
  • 8. man named Eric, whose first experience of the world of work was of a job that proved absolutely, even comically, pointless. Eric: I’ve had many, many awful jobs, but the one that was undoubtedly pure, liquid bullshit was my first “professional job” postgraduation, a dozen years ago. I was the first in my family to attend university, and due to a profound naïveté about the purpose of higher education, I somehow expected that it would open up vistas of hitherto-unforeseen opportunity. Instead, it offered graduate training schemes at PricewaterhouseCoopers, KPMG, etc. I preferred to sit on the dole for six months using my graduate library privileges to read French and Russian novels before the dole forced me to attend an interview which, sadly, led to a job. That job involved working for a large design firm as its “Interface Administrator.” The Interface was a content management system—an intranet with graphical user interface, basically—designed to enable this company’s work to be shared across its seven offices around the UK. Eric soon discovered that he was hired only because of a communication problem in the organization. In other words, he was a duct taper: the entire computer system was necessary only because the partners were unable to
  • 9. pick up the phone and coordinate with one another: Eric: The firm was a partnership, with each office managed by one partner. All of them seem to have attended one of three private schools and the same design school (the Royal College of Art). Being unbelievably competitive fortysomething public schoolboys, they often tried to outcompete one another to win bids, and on more than one occasion, two different offices had found themselves arriving at the same client’s office to pitch work and having to hastily combine their bids in the parking lot of some dismal business park. The Interface was designed to make the company supercollaborative, across all of its offices, to ensure that this (and other myriad fuckups) didn’t happen again, and my job was to help develop it, run it, and sell it to the staff. The problem was, it soon became apparent that Eric wasn’t even really a duct taper. He was a box ticker: one partner had insisted on the project, and, rather 1 In earlier chapters, the author proposed categories of bullshit jobs. A “duct taper” is someone assigned to 1 inadequately repair something that was poorly designed in the first place, while a box ticker is someone assigned to complete forms confirming that things that didn’t need doing have been done. —GH Graeber, Bullshit Jobs: A Theory page !2
  • 10. than argue with him, the others pretended to agree. Then they did everything in their power to make sure it didn’t work. Eric: I should have realized that this was one partner’s idea that no one else actually wanted to implement. Why else would they be paying a twenty-one-year- old history graduate with no IT experience to do this? They’d bought the cheapest software they could find, from a bunch of absolute crooks, so it was buggy, prone to crashing, and looked like a Windows 3.1 screen saver. The entire workforce was paranoid that it was designed to monitor their productivity, record their keystrokes, or flag that they were torrenting porn on the company internet, and so they wanted nothing to do with it. As I had absolutely no background in coding or software development, there was very little I could do to improve the thing, so I was basically tasked with selling and managing a badly functioning, unwanted turd. After a few months, I realized that there was very little for me to do at all most days, aside from answer a few queries from confused designers wanting to know how to upload a file, or search for someone’s email on the address book. The utter pointlessness of his situation soon led to subtle—and then, increasingly
  • 11. unsubtle—acts of rebellion: Eric: I started arriving late and leaving early. I extended the company policy of “a pint on Friday lunchtime” into “pints every lunchtime.” I read novels at my desk. I went out for lunchtime walks that lasted three hours. I almost perfected my French reading ability, sitting with my shoes off with a copy of Le Monde and a Petit Robert. I tried to quit, and my boss offered me a £2,600 raise, which I reluctantly accepted. They needed me precisely because I didn’t have the skills to implement something that they didn’t want to implement, and they were willing to pay to keep me. (Perhaps one could paraphrase Marx’s Economic and Philosophical Manuscripts of 1844 here: to forestall their fears of alienation from their own labor, they had to sacrifice me up to a greater alienation from potential human growth.) As time went on, Eric became more and more flagrant in his defiance, hoping he could find something he could do that might actually cause him to be fired. He started showing up to work drunk and taking paid “business trips” for nonexistent meetings: Eric: A colleague from the Edinburgh office, to whom I had poured out my woes when drunk at the annual general meeting, started to arrange phony meetings
  • 12. with me, once on a golf course near Gleneagles, me hacking at the turf in borrowed golf shoes two sizes too large. After getting away with that, I started arranging fictional meetings with people in the London office. The firm would put me up in a nicotine-coated room in the St. Athans in Bloomsbury, and I would meet old London friends for some good old-fashioned all-day drinking in Soho pubs, which often turned into all-night drinking in Shoreditch. More than once, I returned to my office the following Monday in last Wednesday’s work shirt. I’d long since stopped shaving, and by this point, my hair looked like it was robbed Graeber, Bullshit Jobs: A Theory page !3 from a Zeppelin roadie. I tried on two more occasions to quit, but both times my boss offered me more cash. By the end, I was being paid a stupid sum for a job that, at most, involved me answering the phone twice a day. I eventually broke down on the platform of Bristol Temple Meads train station one late summer’s afternoon. I’d always fancied seeing Bristol, and so I decided to “visit” the Bristol office to look at “user take-up.” I actually spent three days taking MDMA at an anarcho-syndicalist house party in St. Pauls, and the dissociative comedown made me realize how profoundly upsetting it was to live in a
  • 13. state of utter purposelessness. After heroic efforts, Eric did finally manage to get himself replaced: Eric: Eventually, responding to pressure, my boss hired a junior fresh out of a computer science degree to see if some improvements could be made to our graphical user interface. On this kid’s first day at work, I wrote him a list of what needed to be done—and then immediately wrote my resignation letter, which I posted under my boss’s door when he took his next vacation, surrendering my last paycheck over the telephone in lieu of the statutory notice period. I flew that same week to Morocco to do very little in the coastal town of Essaouira. When I came back, I spent the next six months living in a squat, growing my own vegetables on three acres of land. I read your Strike! piece when it first came out. It might have been a revelation for some that capitalism creates unnecessary jobs in order for the wheels to merely keep on turning, but it wasn’t to me. The remarkable thing about this story is that many would consider Eric’s a dream job. He was being paid good money to do nothing. He was also almost completely unsupervised. He was given respect and every opportunity to game the system. Yet despite all that, it gradually destroyed him.
  • 14. Why? To a large degree, I think, this is really a story about social class. Eric was a young man from a working-class background—a child of factory workers, no less—fresh out of college and full of expectations, suddenly confronted with a jolting introduction to the “real world.” Reality, in this instance, consisted of the fact that (a) while middle-aged executives can be counted on to simply assume that any twentysomething white male will be at least something of a computer whiz (even if, as in this case, he had no computer training of any kind), and (b) might even grant someone like Eric a cushy situation if it suited their momentary purposes, (c) they basically saw him as something of a joke. Which his job almost literally was. His presence in the company was very close to a practical joke some designers were playing on one another. Even more, what drove Eric crazy was the fact there was simply no way he could construe his job as serving any sort of purpose. He couldn’t even tell himself he was doing it to feed his family; he didn’t have one yet. Coming from a background where most people took pride in making, maintaining, and fixing things, or Graeber, Bullshit Jobs: A Theory page !4
  • 15. anyway felt that was the sort of thing people should take pride in, he had assumed that going to university and moving into the professional world would mean doing the same sorts of thing on a grander, even more meaningful, scale. Instead, he ended up getting hired precisely for what he wasn’t able to do. He tried to just resign. They kept offering him more money. He tried to get himself fired. They wouldn’t fire him. He tried to rub their faces in it, to make himself a parody of what they seemed to think he was. It didn’t make the slightest bit of difference. To get a sense of what was really happening here, let us imagine a second history major—we can refer to him as anti-Eric—a young man of a professional background but placed in exactly the same situation. How might anti-Eric have behaved differently? Well, likely as not, he would have played along with the charade. Instead of using phony business trips to practice forms of self- annihilation, anti-Eric would have used them to accumulate social capital, connections that would eventually allow him to move on to better things. He would have treated the job as a stepping-stone, and this very project of professional advancement would have given him a sense of purpose. But such
  • 16. attitudes and dispositions don’t come naturally. Children from professional backgrounds are taught to think like that from an early age. Eric, who had not been trained to act and think this way, couldn’t bring himself to do it. As a result, he ended up, for a time, at least, in a squat growing tomatoes.2 concerning the experience of falseness and purposelessness at the core of bullshit jobs, and the importance now felt of conveying the experience of falseness and purposelessness to youth In a deeper way, Eric’s story brings together almost everything that those with bullshit jobs say is distressing about their situation. It’s not just the purposelessness— though certainly, it’s that. It’s also the falseness. I’ve already mentioned the indignation telemarketers feel when they are forced to try to trick or pressure people into doing something they think is against their best interests. This is a complicated feeling. We don’t even really have a name for it. When we think of scams, after all, we think of grifters, confidence artists; they are easy to see as romantic figures, rebels living by their wits, as well as admirable because they have achieved a certain form of mastery. This is why they make acceptable heroes in Hollywood movies. A confidence artist could easily take delight in what she’s doing. But being forced to scam someone is altogether different. In such
  • 17. circumstances, it’s hard not to feel you’re ultimately in the same situation as the person you’re scamming: you’re both being pressured and manipulated by your employer, only in your case, with the added indignity that you’re also betraying the trust of someone whose side you should be on. One might imagine the feelings sparked by most bullshit jobs would be very different. After all, if the employee is scamming anyone, it’s his employer, and he’s doing it with his employer’s full consent. But somehow, this is precisely what many report to be so disturbing about the situation. You don’t even have the satisfaction of knowing Graeber, Bullshit Jobs: A Theory page !5 you’re putting something over on someone. You’re not even living your own lie. Most of the time, you’re not even quite living somebody else’s lie, either. Your job is more like a boss’s unzippered fly that everyone can see but also knows better than to mention. If anything, this appears to compound the sense of purposelessness. Perhaps anti-Eric would, indeed, have found a way to turn around that purposelessness and seen himself as in on the joke; perhaps if he were a real go-
  • 18. getter, he’d have used his administrative skills to effectively take over the office; but even children of the rich and powerful often find this difficult to pull off. The following testimony gives a sense of the moral confusion they can often feel: Rufus: I got the job because my dad was a Vice President at the company. I was charged with handling complaints. Given that it was (in name) a biomedical company, all returned product was considered a biohazard. So I was able to spend a lot of time in a room all by myself, with no supervision and essentially no work to do. The bulk of my memory of the job involves either playing Minesweeper or listening to podcasts. I did spend hours poring over spreadsheets, tracking changes on Word documents, etc., but I guarantee you that I contributed nothing to this company. I spent every minute at the office wearing headphones. I paid only the smallest attention possible to the people around me and the “work” I was assigned. I hated every minute working there. In fact, more days than not, I went home early from work, took two- or three-hour lunch breaks, spent hours “in the bathroom” (wandering around), and nobody ever said a word. I was compensated for every minute.
  • 19. Thinking back on it, it was kind of a dream job. Retrospectively, Rufus understands that he got a ridiculously sweet deal—he seems rather baffled, actually, why he hated the job so much at the time. But surely he couldn’t have been entirely unaware of how his coworkers must have seen him: boss’s kid getting paid to goof off; feels he’s too good to talk to them; supervisors clearly informed “hands off.” It could hardly have evoked warm feelings. Still, this story raises another question: If Rufus’s father didn’t actually expect his son to do the job, why did he insist he take it in the first place? He could presumably just as easily have given his son an allowance, or, alternately, assigned him a job that needed doing, coached him on his duties, and taken some minimal effort to make sure those tasks were actually carried out. Instead, he seems to have felt it was more important for Rufus to be able to say he had a job than to actually acquire work experience. Graeber, Bullshit Jobs: A Theory page !6 That’s puzzling. It’s all the more puzzling because the father’s attitude appears to be extremely common. It wasn’t always so. There was once a time when most students in college whose parents could afford it, or who
  • 20. qualified for scholarships or assistance, received a stipend. It was considered a good thing that there might be a few years in a young man’s or woman’s life where money was not the primary motivation; where he or she could thus be free to pursue other forms of value: say, philosophy, poetry, athletics, sexual experimentation, altered states of consciousness, politics, or the history of Western art. Nowadays it is considered important they should work. However, it is not considered important they should work at anything useful. In fact, like Rufus they’re barely expected to work at all, just to show up and pretend to do so. A number of students wrote just to complain to me about this phenomenon. Here Patrick reflects on his job as a casual retail assistant in a student union convenience store: Patrick: I didn’t actually need the job (I was getting by financially without it), but after some pressure from my family, I applied for it out of some warped sense of obligation to get experience in work to prepare me for whatever lay ahead beyond university. In reality, the job just took away time and energy from other activities I had been doing, like campaigning and activism, or reading for pleasure, which I think made me resent it even more. The job was pretty standard for a student union convenience store and involved serving people on the till (could have easily been done by a
  • 21. machine) with the explicitly stated requirement, in my performance review after my trial period, that I “should be more positive and happy when serving customers.” So not only did they want me to do work that could have been performed by a machine just as effectively, they wanted me to pretend that I was enjoying that state of affairs. It was just about bearable if my shift was during lunchtime, when it got really busy, so time went by relatively quickly. Being on shift on a Sunday afternoon when nobody frequented the SU was just appalling. They had this thing about us not being able to just do nothing, even if the shop was empty. So we couldn’t just sit at the till and read a magazine. Instead, the manager made up utterly meaningless work for us to do, like going round the whole shop and checking that things were in date (even though we knew for a fact they were because of the turnover rate) or rearranging products on shelves in even more pristine order than they already were. The very, very worst thing about the job was that it gave you so much time to think, because the work was so lacking in any intellectual demand. So I just thought so much about how bullshit my job was, how it could be done by a machine, how much I couldn’t wait for full communism, and just endlessly
  • 22. theorized the alternatives to a system where millions of human beings have to do that kind of work for their whole lives in order to survive. I couldn’t stop thinking about how miserable it made me. Graeber, Bullshit Jobs: A Theory page !7 This is what happens, of course, when you first open the entire world of social and political possibility to a young mind by sending it to college and then tell it to stop thinking and tidy up already tidy shelves. Parents now feel it is important that young minds should have this experience. But what, precisely, was Patrick supposed to be learning through this exercise? Here’s another example: Brendan: I’m at a small college in Massachusetts training to be a high school history teacher. Recently I started work at the dining commons. A coworker told me on my first day: “Half of this job is making things look clean, and the other half is looking busy.” For the first couple of months, they had me “monitor” the back room. I would clean the buffet slider, restock the desserts, and wipe down tables when people left. It’s not a big room, so usually I could do all my tasks in five minutes out of
  • 23. every thirty. I ended up being able to get a lot of reading for my coursework done. However, sometimes one of the less understanding supervisors would be working. In that case, I would have to keep the corner of my eye open at all times in order to make sure they would always see me acting busy. I have no idea why the job description couldn’t just acknowledge that I wouldn’t have much to do— if I didn’t have to spend so much time and energy looking busy, I could get my reading and the table cleaning done quicker and more efficiently. But of course, efficiency is not the point. In fact, if we are simply talking about teaching students about efficient work habits, the best thing would be to leave them to their studies. Schoolwork is, after all, real work in every sense except that you don’t get paid for it (though if you’re receiving a scholarship or an allowance, you actually are getting paid for it). In fact, like almost all the other activities Patrick or Brendan might have been engaged in had they not been obliged to take on “real world” jobs, their classwork is actually more real than the largely make- work projects they ended up being forced to do. Schoolwork has real content. One must attend classes, do the readings, write exercises or papers, and be judged on the results. But in practical terms, this appears to be exactly what makes
  • 24. schoolwork appear inadequate to those authorities—parents, teachers, governments. administrators—who have all come to feel that they must also teach students about the real world. It’s too results-oriented. You can study any way you want to so long as you pass the test. A successful student has to learn self- discipline, but this is not the same as learning how to operate under orders. Of course, the same is true of most of the other projects and activities students might otherwise be engaged in: whether rehearsing for plays, playing in a band, political activism, or baking cookies or growing pot to sell to fellow students. All of which might be appropriate training for a society of self- employed adults, or even one made up primarily of the largely autonomous professionals (doctors, lawyers, architects, and so forth) that universities were once designed to produce. Graeber, Bullshit Jobs: A Theory page !8 It might even be appropriate to train young people for the democratically organized collectives that were the subject of Patrick’s reveries about full communism. But as Brendan points out, it is very much not preparation for work in today’s increasingly bullshitized workplace: Brendan: A lot of these student work jobs have us doing some
  • 25. sort of bullshit task like scanning IDs, or monitoring empty rooms, or cleaning already-clean tables. Everyone is cool with it, because we get money while we study, but otherwise there’s absolutely no reason not to just give students the money and automate or eliminate the work. I’m not altogether familiar with how the whole thing works, but a lot of this work is funded by the Feds and tied to our student loans. It’s part of a whole federal system designed to assign students a lot of debt—thereby promising to coerce them into labor in the future, as student debts are so hard to get rid of— accompanied by a bullshit education program designed to train and prepare us for our future bullshit jobs. Brendan has a point, and I’ll be returning to his analysis in a later chapter. Here, though, I want to focus on what students forced into these make-work jobs actually learn from them—lessons that they do not learn from more traditional student occupations and pursuits such as studying for tests, planning parties, and so on. Even judging by Brendan’s and Patrick’s accounts (and I could easily reference many others), I think we can conclude that from these jobs, students learn at least five things: 1. how to operate under others’ direct supervision;
  • 26. 2. how to pretend to work even when nothing needs to done; 3. that one is not paid money to do things, however useful or important, that one actually enjoys; 4. that one is paid money to do things that are in no way useful or important and that one does not enjoy; and 5. that at least in jobs requiring interaction with the public, even when one is being paid to carry out tasks one does not enjoy, one also has to pretend to be enjoying it. This is what Brendan meant by how make-work student employment was a way of “preparing and training” students for their future bullshit jobs. He was studying to be a high school history teacher—a meaningful job, certainly, but, as with almost all teaching positions in the United States, one where the proportion of hours spent teaching in class or preparing lessons has declined, while the total number of hours dedicated to administrative tasks has increased dramatically. This is what Brendan is suggesting: that it’s no coincidence that the more jobs requiring college degrees become suffused in bullshit, the more pressure is put on college students to learn about the real world by dedicating less of their time to self-organized goal-directed activity and more of it to tasks that will prepare them for the more mindless aspects of their future careers. Graeber, Bullshit Jobs: A Theory page !9
  • 27. WHY MANY OF OUR FUNDAMENTAL ASSUMPTIONS ON HUMAN MOTIVATION APPEAR TO BE INCORRECT I do not think there is any thrill that can go through the human heart like that felt by the inventor as he sees some creation of the brain unfolding to success . . . such emotions make a man forget food, sleep, friends, love, everything. —Nikola Tesla If the argument of the previous section is correct, one could perhaps conclude that Eric’s problem was just that he hadn’t been sufficiently prepared for the pointlessness of the modern workplace. He had passed through the old education system—some traces of it are left—designed to prepare students to actually do things. This led to false expectations and an initial shock of disillusionment that he could not overcome. Perhaps. But I don’t think that’s the full story. There is something much deeper going on here. Eric might have been unusually ill-prepared to endure the meaninglessness of his first job, but just about everyone does see such meaninglessness as something to be endured—despite the fact that we are all trained, in one way or another, to assume that human beings
  • 28. should be perfectly delighted to find themselves in his situation of being paid good money not to work. Let us return to our initial problem. We may begin by asking why we assume that someone being paid to do nothing should consider himself fortunate. What is the basis of that theory of human nature from which this follows? The obvious place to look is at economic theory, which has turned this kind of thought into a science. According to classical economic theory, homo oeconomicus, or “economic man”—that is, the model human being that lies behind every prediction made by the discipline— is assumed to be motivated above all by a calculus of costs and benefits. All the mathematical equations by which economists bedazzle their clients, or the public, are founded on one simple assumption: that everyone, left to his own devices, will choose the course of action that provides the most of what he wants for the least expenditure of resources and effort. It is the simplicity of the formula that makes the equations possible: if one were to admit that humans have complicated motivations, there would be too many factors to take into account, it would be impossible to properly weight them, and predictions could not be made. Therefore, while an economist will say that while of course everyone is aware that
  • 29. human beings are not really selfish, calculating machines, assuming that they are makes it possible to explain a very large proportion of what humans do, and this proportion—and only this—is the subject matter of economic science. Graeber, Bullshit Jobs: A Theory page !10 This is a reasonable statement as far as it goes. The problem is there are many domains of human life where the assumption clearly doesn’t hold—and some of them are precisely in the domain of what we like to call the economy. Graeber, Bullshit Jobs: A Theory page !11 Harry Frankfurt, On Bullshit (Princeton University Press 2005) One of the most salient features of our culture is that there is so much bullshit. Everyone knows this. Each of us contributes his share. But we tend to take the situation for granted. Most people are rather confident of their ability to recognize bullshit and to avoid being taken in by it. So the phenomenon has not aroused much deliberate concern, nor attracted much sustained inquiry. In consequence, we have no clear understanding of what bullshit
  • 30. is, why there is so much of it, or what functions it serves. And we lack a conscientiously developed appreciation of what it means to us. In other words, we have no theory. I propose to begin the development of a theoretical understanding of bullshit, mainly by providing some tentative and exploratory philosophical analysis. I shall not consider the rhetorical uses and misuses of bullshit. My aim is simply to give a rough account of what bullshit is and how it differs from what it is not—or (putting it somewhat differently) to articulate, more or less sketchily, the structure of its concept. Any suggestion about what conditions are logically both necessary and sufficient for the constitution of bullshit is bound to be somewhat arbitrary. For one thing, the expression bullshit is often employed quite loosely—simply as a generic term of abuse, with no very specific literal meaning. For another, the phenomenon itself is so vast and amorphous that no crisp and perspicuous analysis of its concept can avoid being procrustean. Nonetheless it should be possible to say something helpful, even though it is not likely to be decisive. Even the most basic and preliminary questions about bullshit remain, after all, not only unanswered but unasked. So far as I am aware, very little work has been done on this subject. I have not undertaken a survey of the literature, partly because I do not know how to go about it. To be sure, there is one quite obvious place to look—the Oxford
  • 31. English Dictionary. The OED has an entry for bullshit in the supplementary volumes, and it also has entries for various pertinent uses of the word bull and for some related terms. I shall consider some of these entries in due course. I have not consulted dictionaries in languages other than English, because I do not know the words for bullshit or bull in any other language. Another worthwhile source is the title essay in The Prevalence of Humbug by Max Black. I am uncertain just how close in meaning the word humbug is to the word 1 bullshit. Of course, the words are not freely and fully interchangeable; it is clear that they are used differently. But the difference appears on the whole to have more to do with considerations of gentility, and certain other rhetorical parameters, than with the strictly literal modes of significance that concern me most. It is more polite, as well as less intense, to say “Humbug!” than to say “Bullshit!” For the sake of this discussion, I shall assume that there is no other important difference between the two. Max Black, The Prevalence of Humbug (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1985).1 Frankfurt, On Bullshit, page !1 Black suggests a number of synonyms for humbug, including the following: balderdash, claptrap, hokum, drivel, buncombe, imposture, and quackery.
  • 32. This list of quaint equivalents is not very helpful. But Black also confronts the problem of establishing the nature of humbug more directly, and he offers the following formal definition: HUMBUG: deceptive misrepresentation, short of lying, especially by pretentious word or deed, of somebody’s own thoughts, feelings, or attitudes. 2 A very similar formulation might plausibly be offered as enunciating the essential characteristics of bullshit. As a preliminary to developing an independent account of those characteristics, I will comment on the various elements of Black’s definition. Deceptive misrepresentation: This may sound pleonastic. No doubt what Black has in 3 mind is that humbug is necessarily designed or intended to deceive, that its misrepresentation is not merely inadvertent. In other words, it is deliberate misrepresentation. Now if, as a matter of conceptual necessity, an intention to deceive is an invariable feature of humbug, then the property of being humbug depends at least in part upon the perpetrator’s state of mind. It cannot be identical, accordingly, with any properties—either inherent or relational—belonging just to the utterance by which the humbug is perpetrated. In this respect, the property of being humbug is similar to that of being a lie, which is identical neither with the falsity nor
  • 33. with any of the other properties of the statement the liar makes, but which requires that the liar makes his statement in a certain state of mind—namely, with an intention to deceive. It is a further question whether there are any features essential to humbug or to lying that are not dependent upon the intentions and beliefs of the person responsible for the humbug or the lie, or whether it is, on the contrary, possible for any utterance whatsoever to be—given that the speaker is in a certain state of mind—a vehicle of humbug or of a lie. In some accounts of lying there is no lie unless a false statement is made; in others a person may be lying even if the statement he makes is true, as long as he himself believes that the statement is false and intends by making it to deceive. What about humbug and bullshit? May any utterance at all qualify as humbug or bullshit, given that (so to speak) the utterer’s heart is in the right place, or must the utterance have certain characteristics of its own as well? Short of lying: It must be part of the point of saying that humbug is “short of lying” that while it has some of the distinguishing characteristics of lies, there are others that it lacks. But this cannot be the whole point. After all, every use of language without exception has some, but not all, of the characteristic features of lies—if no other, then at least the feature simply of being a use of language. Yet it would surely be incorrect to
  • 34. describe every use of language as short of lying. Black’s phrase evokes the notion of Ibid., p. 143.2 “Pleonasm” is a literary and linguistic term that means adding an extra word to express a meaning that the other 3 words have already been expressed. Basically, what most people call “being redundant.” —GH Frankfurt, On Bullshit, page !2 some sort of continuum, on which lying occupies a certain segment while humbug is located exclusively at earlier points. What continuum could this be, along which one encounters humbug only before one encounters lying? Both lying and humbug are modes of misrepresentation. It is not at first glance apparent, however, just how the difference between these varieties of misrepresentation might be construed as a difference in degree. Especially by pretentious word or deed: There are two points to notice here. First, Black identifies humbug not only as a category of speech but as a category of action as well; it may be accomplished either by words or by deeds. Second, his use of the qualifier “especially” indicates that Black does not regard pretentiousness as an essential or wholly indispensable characteristic of humbug. Undoubtedly, much humbug is
  • 35. pretentious. So far as concerns bullshit, moreover, “pretentious bullshit” is close to being a stock phrase. But I am inclined to think that when bullshit is pretentious, this happens because pretentiousness is its motive rather than a constitutive element of its essence. The fact that a person is behaving pretentiously is not, it seems to me, part of what is required to make his utterance an instance of bullshit. It is often, to be sure, what accounts for his making that utterance. However, it must not be assumed that bullshit always and necessarily has pretentiousness as its motive. Misrepresentation . . . of somebody’s own thoughts, feelings, or attitudes: This provision that the perpetrator of humbug is essentially misrepresenting himself raises some very central issues. To begin with, whenever a person deliberately misrepresents anything, he must inevitably be misrepresenting his own state of mind. It is possible, of course, for a person to misrepresent that alone—for instance, by pretending to have a desire or a feeling which he does not actually have. But suppose that a person, whether by telling a lie or in another way, misrepresents something else. Then he necessarily misrepresents at least two things. He misrepresents whatever he is talking about—i.e., the state of affairs that is the topic or referent of his discourse—and in doing this he cannot avoid misrepresenting his own mind as well. Thus someone who lies about how much money he has in his pocket both gives an account of the amount of
  • 36. money in his pocket and conveys that he believes this account. If the lie works, then its victim is twice deceived, having one false belief about what is in the liar’s pocket and another false belief about what is in the liar’s mind. Now it is unlikely that Black wishes the referent of humbug to be in every instance the state of the speaker’s mind. There is no particular reason, after all, why humbug may not be about other things. Black probably means that humbug is not designed primarily to give its audience a false belief about whatever state of affairs may be the topic, but that its primary intention is rather to give its audience a false impression concerning what is going on in the mind of the speaker. Insofar as it is humbug, the creation of this impression is its main purpose and its point. Understanding Black along these lines suggests a hypothesis to account for his characterization of humbug as “short of lying.” If I lie to you about how much money I have, then I do not thereby make an explicit assertion concerning my beliefs. Therefore, Frankfurt, On Bullshit, page !3 one might with some plausibility maintain that although in telling the lie I certainly misrepresent what is in my mind, this misrepresentation—as distinct from my
  • 37. misrepresentation of what is in my pocket—is not strictly speaking a lie at all. For I do not come right out with any statement whatever about what is in my mind. Nor does the statement I do affirm—e.g., “I have twenty dollars in my pocket”—imply any statement that attributes a belief to me. On the other hand, it is unquestionable that in so affirming, I provide you with a reasonable basis for making certain judgments about what I believe. In particular, I provide you with a reasonable basis for supposing that I believe I have twenty dollars in my pocket. Since this supposition is by hypothesis false, I do in telling the lie tend to deceive you concerning what is in my mind even though I do not actually tell a lie about that. In this light, it does not seem unnatural or inappropriate to regard me as misrepresenting my own beliefs in a way that is “short of lying.” It is easy to think of familiar situations by which Black’s account of humbug appears to be unproblematically confirmed. Consider a Fourth of July orator, who goes on bombastically about “our great and blessed country, whose Founding Fathers under divine guidance created a new beginning for mankind.” This is surely humbug. As Black’s account suggests, the orator is not lying. He would be lying only if it were his intention to bring about in his audience beliefs that he himself regards as false, concerning such matters as whether our country is great, whether it is blessed, whether
  • 38. the Founders had divine guidance, and whether what they did was in fact to create a new beginning for mankind. But the orator does not really care what his audience thinks about the Founding Fathers, or about the role of the deity in our country’s history, or the like. At least, it is not an interest in what anyone thinks about these matters that motivates his speech. It is clear that what makes Fourth of July oration humbug is not fundamentally that the speaker regards his statements as false. Rather, just as Black’s account suggests, the orator intends these statements to convey a certain impression of himself. He is not trying to deceive anyone concerning American history. What he cares about is what people think of him. He wants them to think of him as a patriot, as someone who has deep thoughts and feelings about the origins and the mission of our country, who appreciates the importance of religion, who is sensitive to the greatness of our history, whose pride in that history is combined with humility before God, and so on. Black’s account of humbug appears, then, to fit certain paradigms quite snugly. Nonetheless, I do not believe that it adequately or accurately grasps the essential character of bullshit. It is correct to say of bullshit, as he says of humbug, both that it is short of lying and that those who perpetrate it misrepresent themselves in a certain way. But Black’s account of these two features is significantly off
  • 39. the mark. I shall next attempt to develop, by considering some biographical material pertaining to Ludwig Frankfurt, On Bullshit, page !4 Wittgenstein, a preliminary but more accurately focused appreciation of just what the 4 central characteristics of bullshit are. Wittgenstein once said that the following bit of verse by Longfellow could serve him as a motto: 5 In the elder days of art Builders wrought with greatest care Each minute and unseen part, For the Gods are everywhere. The point of these lines is clear. In the old days, craftsmen did not cut corners. They worked carefully, and they took care with every aspect of their work. Every part of the product was considered, and each was designed and made to be exactly as it should be. These craftsmen did not relax their thoughtful self-discipline even with respect to features of their work that would ordinarily not be visible. Although no one would notice if those features were not quite right, the craftsmen would be bothered by their
  • 40. consciences. So nothing was swept under the rug. Or, one might perhaps also say, there was no bullshit. It does seem fitting to construe carelessly made, shoddy goods as in some way analogues of bullshit. But in what way? Is the resemblance that bullshit itself is invariably produced in a careless or self-indulgent manner, that it is never finely crafted, that in the making of it there is never the meticulously attentive concern with detail to which Longfellow alludes? Is the bullshitter by his very nature a mindless slob? Is his product necessarily messy or unrefined? The word shit does, to be sure, suggest this. Excrement is not designed or crafted at all; it is merely emitted, or dumped. It may have a more or less coherent shape, or it may not, but it is in any case certainly not wrought. The notion of carefully wrought bullshit involves, then, a certain inner strain. Thoughtful attention to detail requires discipline and objectivity. It entails accepting standards and limitations that forbid the indulgence of impulse or whim. It is this selflessness that, in connection with bullshit, strikes us as inapposite. But in fact it is not out of the question at all. The realms of advertising and of public relations, and the nowadays closely related realm of politics, are replete with instances of bullshit so unmitigated that they can serve among the most indisputable and classic paradigms of the concept. And in these realms there are exquisitely
  • 41. sophisticated craftsmen who— with the help of advanced and demanding techniques of market research, of public Ludwig Wittgenstein (1889-1951) was a philosophy professor in the English analytic tradition. He was born in 4 Austria but spent his professional life at Oxford, where he wrote several highly influential works on the relation between language and thought. He was famously serious and passionate about philosophy. — GH This is reported by Norman Malcolm, in his introduction to Recollections of Wittgenstein, ed. R. Rhees (Oxford: 5 Oxford University Press, 1984), p. xiii. Frankfurt, On Bullshit, page !5 opinion polling, of psychological testing, and so forth—dedicate themselves tirelessly to getting every word and image they produce exactly right. Yet there is something more to be said about this. However studiously and conscientiously the bullshitter proceeds, it remains true that he is also trying to get away with something. There is surely in his work, as in the work of the slovenly craftsman, some kind of laxity that resists or eludes the demands of a disinterested and austere discipline. The pertinent mode of laxity cannot be equated, evidently, with simple carelessness or inattention to detail. I shall attempt in due course to locate it more correctly.
  • 42. Wittgenstein devoted his philosophical energies largely to identifying and combating what he regarded as insidiously disruptive forms of “nonsense.” He was apparently like that in his personal life as well. This comes out in an anecdote related by Fania Pascal, who knew him in Cambridge in the 1930s: I had my tonsils out and was in the Evelyn Nursing Home feeling sorry for myself. Wittgenstein called. I croaked: “I feel just like a dog that has been run over.” He was disgusted: “You don’t know what a dog that has been run over feels like.” 6 Now who knows what really happened? It seems extraordinary, almost unbelievable, that anyone could object seriously to what Pascal reports herself as having said. That characterization of her feelings—so innocently close to the utterly commonplace “sick as a dog”—is simply not provocative enough to arouse any response as lively or intense as disgust. If Pascal’s simile is offensive, then what figurative or allusive uses of language would not be? So perhaps it did not really happen quite as Pascal says. Perhaps Wittgenstein was trying to make a small joke, and it misfired. He was only pretending to bawl Pascal out, just for the fun of a little hyperbole; and she got the tone and the intention wrong. She thought he was disgusted by her remark, when in fact he was
  • 43. only trying to cheer her up with some playfully exaggerated mock criticism or joshing. In that case the incident is not incredible or bizarre after all. But if Pascal failed to recognize that Wittgenstein was only teasing, then perhaps the possibility that he was serious was at least not so far out of the question. She knew him, and she knew what to expect from him; she knew how he made her feel. Her way of understanding or of misunderstanding his remark was very likely not altogether discordant, then, with her sense of what he was like. We may fairly suppose that even if her account of the incident is not strictly true to the facts of Wittgenstein’s intention, it is sufficiently true to her idea of Wittgenstein to have made sense to her. For the purposes of this discussion, I shall accept Pascal’s report at face value, supposing that when it came to the use of allusive or figurative language, Wittgenstein was indeed as preposterous as she makes him out to be. Fania Pascal, “Wittgenstein: A Personal Memoir,” in Rhees, Recollections, pp. 28-29.6 Frankfurt, On Bullshit, page !6 Then just what is it that the Wittgenstein in her report considers to be objectionable? Let us assume that he is correct about the facts: that is, Pascal really does not know how
  • 44. run-over dogs feel. Even so, when she says what she does, she is plainly not lying. She would have been lying if, when she made her statement, she was aware that she actually felt quite good. For however little she knows about the lives of dogs, it must certainly be clear to Pascal that when dogs are run over they do not feel good. So if she herself had in fact been feeling good, it would have been a lie to assert that she felt like a run-over dog. Pascal’s Wittgenstein intends to accuse her not of lying but of misrepresentation of another sort. She characterizes her feeling as “the feeling of a run-over dog.” She is not really acquainted, however, with the feeling to which this phrase refers. Of course, the phrase is far from being complete nonsense to her; she is hardly speaking gibberish. What she says has an intelligible connotation, which she certainly understands. Moreover, she does know something about the quality of the feeling to which the phrase refers: she knows at least that it is an undesirable and unenjoyable feeling, a bad feeling. The trouble with her statement is that it purports to convey something more than simply that she feels bad. Her characterization of her feeling is too specific; it is excessively particular. Hers is not just any bad feeling but, according to her account, the distinctive kind of bad feeling that a dog has when it is run over. To the Wittgenstein in Pascal’s story, judging from his response, this is just bullshit. Now assuming that Wittgenstein does indeed regard Pascal’s
  • 45. characterization of how she feels as an instance of bullshit, why does it strike him that way? It does so, I believe, because he perceives what Pascal says as being—roughly speaking, for now— unconnected to a concern with the truth. Her statement is not germane to the enterprise of describing reality. She does not even think she knows, except in the vaguest way, how a run-over dog feels. Her description of her own feeling is, accordingly, something that she is merely making up. She concocts it out of whole cloth; or, if she got it from someone else, she is repeating it quite mindlessly and without any regard for how things really are. It is for this mindlessness that Pascal’s Wittgenstein chides her. What disgusts him is that Pascal is not even concerned whether her statement is correct. There is every likelihood, of course, that she says what she does only in a somewhat clumsy effort to speak colorfully, or to appear vivacious or good-humored; and no doubt Wittgenstein’s reaction—as she construes it—is absurdly intolerant. Be this as it may, it seems clear what that reaction is. He reacts as though he perceives her to be speaking about her feeling thoughtlessly, without conscientious attention to the relevant facts. Her statement is not “wrought with greatest care.” She makes it without bothering to take into account at all the question of its accuracy. The point that troubles Wittgenstein is manifestly not that
  • 46. Pascal has made a mistake in her description of how she feels. Nor is it even that she has made a careless mistake. Her laxity, or her lack of care, is not a matter of having permitted an error to slip into her speech on account of some inadvertent or momentarily negligent lapse in the attention she was devoting to getting things right. The point is rather that, so far as Wittgenstein Frankfurt, On Bullshit, page !7 can see, Pascal offers a description of a certain state of affairs without genuinely submitting to the constraints which the endeavor to provide an accurate representation of reality imposes. Her fault is not that she fails to get things right, but that she is not even trying. This is important to Wittgenstein because, whether justifiably or not, he takes what she says seriously, as a statement purporting to give an informative description of the way she feels. He construes her as engaged in an activity to which the distinction between what is true and what is false is crucial, and yet as taking no interest in whether what she says is true or false. It is in this sense that Pascal’s statement is unconnected to a concern with truth: she is not concerned with the truth-value of what she says. That is why she cannot be regarded as lying; for she does not presume that she knows the truth,
  • 47. and therefore she cannot be deliberately promulgating a proposition that she presumes to be false: Her statement is grounded neither in a belief that it is true nor, as a lie must be, in a belief that it is not true. It is just this lack of connection to a concern with truth— this indifference to how things really are—that I regard as of the essence of bullshit. Now I shall consider (quite selectively) certain items in the Oxford English Dictionary that are pertinent to clarifying the nature of bullshit. The OED defines a bull session as “an informal conversation or discussion, esp. of a group of males.” Now as a definition, this seems wrong. For one thing, the dictionary evidently supposes that the use of the term bull in bull session serves primarily just to indicate gender. But even if it were true that the participants in bull sessions are generally or typically males, the assertion that a bull session is essentially nothing more particular than an informal discussion among males would be as far off the mark as the parallel assertion that a hen session is simply an informal conversation among females. It is probably true that the participants in hen sessions must be females. Nonetheless the term hen session conveys something more specific than this concerning the particular kind of informal conversation among females to which hen sessions are characteristically devoted. What is distinctive about the sort of informal discussion among males that constitutes a bull session is, it seems to me, something like this: while the discussion may be intense
  • 48. and significant, it is in a certain respect not “for real.” The characteristic topics of a bull session have to do with very personal and emotion- laden aspects of life—for instance, religion, politics, or sex. People are generally reluctant to speak altogether openly about these topics if they expect that they might be taken too seriously. What tends to go on in a bull session is that the participants try out various thoughts and attitudes in order to see how it feels to hear themselves saying such things and in order to discover how others respond, without its being assumed that they are committed to what they say: it is understood by everyone in a bull session that the statements people make do not necessarily reveal what they really believe or how they really feel. The main point is to make possible a high level of candor and an experimental or adventuresome approach to the subjects under discussion. Therefore provision is made for enjoying a certain irresponsibility, so that people will be encouraged to convey what is on their minds without too much anxiety that they will be held to it. Frankfurt, On Bullshit, page !8 Each of the contributors to a bull session relies, in other words, upon a general recognition that what he expresses or says is not to be
  • 49. understood as being what he means wholeheartedly or believes unequivocally to be true. The purpose of the conversation is not to communicate beliefs. Accordingly, the usual assumptions about the connection between what people say and what they believe are suspended. The statements made in a bull session differ from bullshit in that there is no pretense that this connection is being sustained. They are like bullshit by virtue of the fact that they are in some degree unconstrained by a concern with truth. This resemblance between bull sessions and bullshit is suggested also by the term shooting the bull, which refers to the sort of conversation that characterizes bull sessions and in which the term shooting is very likely a cleaned-up rendition of shitting. The very term bull session is, indeed, quite probably a sanitized version of bullshit session. A similar theme is discernible in a British usage of bull in which, according to the OED, the term refers to “unnecessary routine tasks or ceremonial; excessive discipline or ‘spit- and-polish’; = red-tape.” The dictionary provides the following examples of this usage: The Squadron . . . felt very bolshie about all that bull that was flying around the station (I. Gleed, Arise to Conquer vi. 51, 1942); Them turning out the guard for us, us marching past eyes right, all that sort of bull (A. Baron, Human Kind xxiv. 178, 1953); the drudgery and ‘bull’ in an MP’s
  • 50. life (Economist 8 Feb. 470/471, 1958). Here the term bull evidently pertains to tasks that are pointless in that they have nothing much to do with the primary intent or justifying purpose of the enterprise which requires them. Spit-and polish and red tape do not genuinely contribute, it is presumed, to the “real” purposes of military personnel or government officials, even though they are imposed by agencies or agents that purport to be conscientiously devoted to the pursuit of those purposes. Thus the “unnecessary routine tasks or ceremonial” that constitute bull are disconnected from the legitimating motives of the activity upon which they intrude, just as the things people say in bull sessions are disconnected from their settled beliefs, and as bullshit is disconnected from a concern with the truth. The term bull is also employed, in a rather more widespread and familiar usage, as a somewhat less coarse equivalent of bullshit. In an entry for bull as so used, the OED suggests the following as definitive: “trivial, insincere, or untruthful talk or writing; nonsense.” Now it does not seem distinctive of bull either that it must be deficient in meaning or that it is necessarily unimportant; so “nonsense” and “trivial,” even apart from their vagueness, seem to be on the wrong track. The focus of “insincere, or untruthful” is better, but it needs to be sharpened. The entry at hand also provides the 7 following two definitions:
  • 51. 1914 Dialect Notes IV. 162 Bull, talk which is not to the purpose; ‘hot air’. It may be noted that the inclusion of insincerity among its essential conditions would imply that bull cannot be 7 produced inadvertently; for it hardly seems possible to be inadvertently insincere. Frankfurt, On Bullshit, page !9 1932 Times Lit. Supp. 8 Dec. 933/3 ‘Bull’ is the slang term for a combination of bluff, bravado, ‘hot air’, and what we used to call in the Army ‘Kidding the troops’. “Not to the purpose” is appropriate, but it is both too broad in scope and too vague. It covers digressions and innocent irrelevancies, which are not invariably instances of bull; furthermore, saying that bull is not to the purpose leaves it uncertain what purpose is meant. The reference in both definitions to “hot air” is more helpful. When we characterize talk as hot air, we mean that what comes out of the speaker’s mouth is only that. It is mere vapor. His speech is empty, without substance or content. His use of language, accordingly, does not contribute to the purpose it purports to serve. No more information is communicated than if the speaker had merely exhaled. There
  • 52. are similarities between hot air and excrement, incidentally, which make hot air seem an especially suitable equivalent for bullshit. Just as hot air is speech that has been emptied of all informative content, so excrement is matter from which everything nutritive has been removed. Excrement may be regarded as the corpse of nourishment, what remains when the vital elements in food have been exhausted. In this respect, excrement is a representation of death that we ourselves produce and that, indeed, we cannot help producing in the very process of maintaining our lives. Perhaps it is for making death so intimate that we find excrement so repulsive. In any event, it cannot serve the purposes of sustenance, any more than hot air can serve those of communication. Now consider these lines from Pound’s Canto LXXIV, which the OED cites in its entry on bullshit as a verb: Hey Snag wots in the bibl’? Wot are the books ov the bible? Name ’em, don’t bullshit ME. 8 This is a call for the facts. The person addressed is evidently regarded as having in some way claimed to know the Bible, or as having claimed to care about it. The speaker suspects that this is just empty talk, and demands that the claim be supported with facts. He will not accept a mere report; he insists upon seeing
  • 53. the thing itself. In other words, he is calling the bluff. The connection between bullshit and bluff is affirmed explicitly in the definition with which the lines by Pound are associated: Here is part of the context in which these lines occur: “Les Albigeois, a problem of history, / and the fleet at Salamis 8 made with money lent by the state to the shipwrights / Tempus tacendi, tempus loquendi. / Never inside the country to raise the standard of living / but always abroad to increase the profits of usurers, / dixit Lenin, / and gun sales lead to more gun sales / they do not clutter the market for gunnery / there is no saturation / Pisa, in the 23rd year of the effort in sight of the tower / and Till was hung yesterday / for murder and rape with trimmings plus Cholkis / plus mythology, thought he was Zeus ram or another one / Hey Snag wots in the bibl’? / Wot are the books ov the bible? / Name ’em, don’t bullshit ME.” Frankfurt, On Bullshit, page !10 As v. trans. and intr., to talk nonsense (to); . . . also, to bluff one’s way through (something) by talking nonsense. It does seem that bullshitting involves a kind of bluff. It is closer to bluffing, surely, than to telling a lie. But what is implied concerning its nature by the fact that it is more like the former than it is like the latter? Just what is the relevant difference here between a bluff and a lie?
  • 54. Lying and bluffing are both modes of misrepresentation or deception. Now the concept most central to the distinctive nature of a lie is that of falsity: the liar is essentially someone who deliberately promulgates a falsehood. Bluffing, too, is typically devoted to conveying something false. Unlike plain lying, however, it is more especially a matter not of falsity but of fakery. This is what accounts for its nearness to bullshit. For the essence of bullshit is not that it is false but that it is phony. In order to appreciate this distinction, one must recognize that a fake or a phony need not be in any respect (apart from authenticity itself) inferior to the real thing. What is not genuine need not also be defective in some other way. It may be, after all, an exact copy. What is wrong with a counterfeit is not what it is like, but how it was made. This points to a similar and fundamental aspect of the essential nature of bullshit: although it is produced without concern with the truth, it need not be false. The bullshitter is faking things. But this does not mean that he necessarily gets them wrong. In Eric Ambler’s novel Dirty Story, a character named Arthur Abdel Simpson recalls advice that he received as a child from his father: Although I was only seven when my father was killed, I still remember him very well and some of the things he used to say. . . . One of the first things he taught me was, “Never tell a lie when you can bullshit your way
  • 55. through.” 9 This presumes not only that there is an important difference between lying and bullshitting, but that the latter is preferable to the former. Now the elder Simpson surely did not consider bullshitting morally superior to lying. Nor is it likely that he regarded lies as invariably less effective than bullshit in accomplishing the purposes for which either of them might be employed. After all, an intelligently crafted lie may do its work with unqualified success. It may be that Simpson thought it easier to get away with bullshitting than with lying. Or perhaps he meant that, although the risk of being caught is about the same in each case, the consequences of being caught are generally less severe for the bullshitter than for the liar. In fact, people do tend to be more tolerant of bullshit than of lies, perhaps because we are less inclined to take the former as a personal affront. We may seek to distance ourselves from bullshit, but we are more E. Ambler, Dirty Story (1967), I. iii. 25. The citation is provided in the same OED entry as the one that includes the 9 passage from Pound. The closeness of the relation between bullshitting and bluffing is resonant, it seems to me, in the parallelism of the idioms: “bullshit your way through” and “bluff your way through.” Frankfurt, On Bullshit, page !11
  • 56. likely to turn away from it with an impatient or irritated shrug than with the sense of violation or outrage that lies often inspire. The problem of understanding why our attitude toward bullshit is generally more benign than our attitude toward lying is an important one, which I shall leave as an exercise for the reader. The pertinent comparison is not, however, between telling a lie and producing some particular instance of bullshit. The elder Simpson identifies the alternative to telling a lie as “bullshitting one’s way through.” This involves not merely producing one instance of bullshit; it involves a program of producing bullshit to whatever extent the circumstances require. This is a key, perhaps, to his preference. Telling a lie is an act with a sharp focus. It is designed to insert a particular falsehood at a specific point in a set or system of beliefs, in order to avoid the consequences of having that point occupied by the truth. This requires a degree of craftsmanship, in which the teller of the lie submits to objective constraints imposed by what he takes to be the truth. The liar is inescapably concerned with truth-values. In order to invent a lie at all, he must think he knows what is true. And in order to invent an effective lie, he must design his falsehood under the guidance of that truth. On the other hand, a person who undertakes to bullshit his way through has much more freedom. His focus is panoramic rather than particular. He does not limit himself to
  • 57. inserting a certain falsehood at a specific point, and thus he is not constrained by the truths surrounding that point or intersecting it. He is prepared, so far as required, to fake the context as well. This freedom from the constraints to which the liar must submit does not necessarily mean, of course, that his task is easier than the task of the liar. But the mode of creativity upon which it relies is less analytical and less deliberative than that which is mobilized in lying. It is more expansive and independent, with more spacious opportunities for improvisation, color, and imaginative play. This is less a matter of craft than of art. Hence the familiar notion of the “bullshit artist.” My guess is that the recommendation offered by Arthur Simpson’s father reflects the fact that he was more strongly drawn to this mode of creativity, regardless of its relative merit or effectiveness, than he was to the more austere and rigorous demands of lying. What bullshit essentially misrepresents is neither the state of affairs to which it refers nor the beliefs of the speaker concerning that state of affairs. Those are what lies misrepresent, by virtue of being false. Since bullshit need not be false, it differs from lies in its misrepresentational intent. The bullshitter may not deceive us, or even intend to do so, either about the facts or about what he takes the facts to be. What he does necessarily attempt to deceive us about is his enterprise. His only indispensably distinctive characteristic is that in a certain way he
  • 58. misrepresents what he is up to. This is the crux of the distinction between him and the liar. Both he and the liar represent themselves falsely as endeavoring to communicate the truth. The success of each depends upon deceiving us about that. But the fact about himself that the liar hides is that he is attempting to lead us away from a correct apprehension of reality; we are not to know that he wants us to believe something he supposes to be false. The fact about himself that the bullshitter hides, on the other hand, is that the truth-values of his Frankfurt, On Bullshit, page !12 statements are of no central interest to him; what we are not to understand is that his intention is neither to report the truth nor to conceal it. This does not mean that his speech is anarchically impulsive, but that the motive guiding and controlling it is unconcerned with how the things about which he speaks truly are. It is impossible for someone to lie unless he thinks he knows the truth. Producing bullshit requires no such conviction. A person who lies is thereby responding to the truth, and he is to that extent respectful of it. When an honest man speaks, he says only what he believes to be true; and for the liar, it is correspondingly indispensable that he
  • 59. considers his statements to be false. For the bullshitter, however, all these bets are off: he is neither on the side of the true nor on the side of the false. His eye is not on the facts at all, as the eyes of the honest man and of the liar are, except insofar as they may be pertinent to his interest in getting away with what he says. He does not care whether the things he says describe reality correctly. He just picks them out, or makes them up, to suit his purpose. In his essay “Lying,” Saint Augustine distinguishes lies of eight types, which he classifies according to the characteristic intent or justification with which a lie is told. Lies of seven of these types are told only because they are supposed to be indispensable means to some end that is distinct from the sheer creation of false beliefs. It is not their falsity as such, in other words, that attracts the teller to them. Since they are told only on account of their supposed indispensability to a goal other than deception itself, Saint Augustine regards them as being told unwillingly: what the person really wants is not to tell the lie but to attain the goal. They are therefore not real lies, in his view, and those who tell them are not in the strictest sense liars. It is only the remaining category that contains what he identifies as “the lie which is told solely for the pleasure of lying and deceiving, that is, the real lie.” Lies in this category are not told as means to any end 10 distinct from the propagation of falsehood. They are told simply for their own sakes—
  • 60. i.e., purely out of a love of deception: There is a distinction between a person who tells a lie and a liar. The former is one who tells a lie unwillingly, while the liar loves to lie and passes his time in the joy of lying. . . . The latter takes delight in lying, rejoicing in the falsehood itself. 11 What Augustine calls “liars” and “real lies” are both rare and extraordinary. Everyone lies from time to time, but there are very few people to whom it would often (or even ever) occur to lie exclusively from a love of falsity or of deception. For most people, the fact that a statement is false constitutes in itself a reason, however weak and easily overridden, not to make the statement. For Saint Augustine’s pure liar it is, on the contrary, a reason in favor of making it. For the bullshitter it is in itself neither “Lying,” in Treatises on Various Subjects, in Fathers of the Church, ed. R. J. Deferrari, vol. 16 (New York: Fathers of 10 the Church, 1952), p. 109. Saint Augustine maintains that telling a lie of this type is a less serious sin than telling lies in three of his categories and a more serious sin than telling lies in the other four categories. Ibid., p. 79.11 Frankfurt, On Bullshit, page !13
  • 61. a reason in favor nor a reason against. Both in lying and in telling the truth people are guided by their beliefs concerning the way things are. These guide them as they endeavor either to describe the world correctly or to describe it deceitfully. For this reason, telling lies does not tend to unfit a person for telling the truth in the same way that bullshitting tends to. Through excessive indulgence in the latter activity, which involves making assertions without paying attention to anything except what it suits one to say, a person’s normal habit of attending to the ways things are may become attenuated or lost. Someone who lies and someone who tells the truth are playing on opposite sides, so to speak, in the same game. Each responds to the facts as he understands them, although the response of the one is guided by the authority of the truth, while the response of the other defies that authority and refuses to meet its demands. The bullshitter ignores these demands altogether. He does not reject the authority of the truth, as the liar does, and oppose himself to it. He pays no attention to it at all. By virtue of this, bullshit is a greater enemy of the truth than lies are. One who is concerned to report or to conceal the facts assumes that there are indeed facts that are in some way both determinate and knowable. His interest in telling the truth or in lying presupposes that there is a difference between getting things wrong and
  • 62. getting them right, and that it is at least occasionally possible to tell the difference. Someone who ceases to believe in the possibility of identifying certain statements as true and others as false can have only two alternatives. The first is to desist both from efforts to tell the truth and from efforts to deceive. This would mean refraining from making any assertion whatever about the facts. The second alternative is to continue making assertions that purport to describe the way things are, but that cannot be anything except bullshit. Why is there so much bullshit? Of course it is impossible to be sure that there is relatively more of it nowadays than at other times. There is more communication of all kinds in our time than ever before, but the proportion that is bullshit may not have increased. Without assuming that the incidence of bullshit is actually greater now, I will mention a few considerations that help to account for the fact that it is currently so great. Bullshit is unavoidable whenever circumstances require someone to talk without knowing what he is talking about. Thus the production of bullshit is stimulated whenever a person’s obligations or opportunities to speak about some topic exceed his knowledge of the facts that are relevant to that topic. This discrepancy is common in public life, where people are frequently impelled—whether by their own propensities or
  • 63. by the demands of others—to speak extensively about matters of which they are to some degree ignorant. Closely related instances arise from the widespread conviction that it is the responsibility of a citizen in a democracy to have opinions about everything, or at least everything that pertains to the conduct of his country’s affairs. The lack of any significant connection between a person’s opinions and his apprehension of reality will be even more severe, needless to say, for someone who believes it his responsibility, as a conscientious moral agent, to evaluate events and conditions in all parts of the world. Frankfurt, On Bullshit, page !14 The contemporary proliferation of bullshit also has deeper sources, in various forms of skepticism which deny that we can have any reliable access to an objective reality, and which therefore reject the possibility of knowing how things truly are. These “antirealist” doctrines undermine confidence in the value of disinterested efforts to determine what is true and what is false, and even in the intelligibility of the notion of objective inquiry. One response to this loss of confidence has been a retreat from the discipline required by dedication to the ideal of correctness to a quite different sort of discipline, which is imposed by pursuit of an alternative ideal of sincerity. Rather than seeking primarily to arrive at accurate representations of a common world, the
  • 64. individual turns toward trying to provide honest representations of himself. Convinced that reality has no inherent nature, which he might hope to identify as the truth about things, he devotes himself to being true to his own nature. It is as though he decides that since it makes no sense to try to be true to the facts, he must therefore try instead to be true to himself. But it is preposterous to imagine that we ourselves are determinate, and hence susceptible both to correct and to incorrect descriptions, while supposing that the ascription of determinacy to anything else has been exposed as a mistake. As conscious beings, we exist only in response to other things, and we cannot know ourselves at all without knowing them. Moreover, there is nothing in theory, and certainly nothing in experience, to support the extraordinary judgment that it is the truth about himself that is the easiest for a person to know. Facts about ourselves are not peculiarly solid and resistant to skeptical dissolution. Our natures are, indeed, elusively insubstantial— notoriously less stable and less inherent than the natures of other things. And insofar as this is the case, sincerity itself is bullshit. Frankfurt, On Bullshit, page !15 Dunkin Donuts My name
  • 65. Institution Course Instructor Date Introduction Consumer Reference Feasibility Test Market Scope Testing and Customer Acceptance Staffing Roll Out Plan CUSTOMER PREFERENCE Market research and analysis Competitor strategies There is need to do market analysis so as to understand further what the customers want. Without market research, products and services offered will be null and void. Market research will also help understand what kind of product the customer and it is not being offered by competitors. It helps the business understand
  • 66. the strategies of competitors. The business will find ways of outperforming competitors based on what the customers prefer. 3 FEASIBILITY TEST Costs of starting the business Profit projections It is important to perform a feasibility test so to find out how much the business will cost. This the point that determines whether it is worth investing in the business. This where a forecast will be made to see projections. How long will it take the business to realize profits. 4 MARKET SCOPE Customers explore new brands Implement new technologies Make informed decisions Undertaking market scope is to find the rational consumers who are keen on trying to explore new brands in the market. This phase helps in implementing new techniques of how to to do business. It will assist the company in making informed decisions hence reducing customer loss. It enables the company to meet customer demands effectively. Satisfied customers will ensure that the business keep growing.
  • 67. 5 CUSTOMER ACCEPTANCE The ultimate goal for every study is to answer key questions and provide up-to-date and reliable information to support the client’s strategic business planning. Pricing strategies The best way for a business to penetrate the market is if the customers accept the products and services that are being offered by the business. Here the business will set prices that are favorable to the customers. Not too high to push away consumers and not too low to avoid making losses. 6 DUNKIN’S STAFFING Employ qualified employees Employees who share the visions of the business Clearly state roles of each employee Services will not perform themselves. A business needs employees to attend to customers. A business needs qualified employees who relate easily to customers and work faster to meet the requests of customers. Good employees will the reason customers keep coming to buy from the business. If the area is full youths, the business needs youths who can easily understand the demands of customers.
  • 68. 7 ROLL OUT Identify your niche and make sure the uniqueness of your product stands out. Brand the product well in order to attract new customers as well. Perform a SWOT analysis and monitor your products’ life cycle. After all factors have been considered and observed, it is time to roll out the business. The best to win customers when the business becomes operational is to brand the business. Unique branding will draw customers away from competitors. The business needs to do a SWOT analysis and monitor the lifecycle of the products. The business needs to find a suitable location to set up the business. This is where the business finds out if the customers are satisfied with the services being offered. 8 Conclusion offer unique services Employ qualified employees Meet the demands of customers Employ reasonable prices In conclusion, for a business to be a success the level of
  • 69. attracting customers should be high. The business must employ better strategies that will run competitors out of business. The best strategies is offering unique products, reasonable prices on products. Employees should be qualified and easily understand the preferences of customers. 9