SlideShare a Scribd company logo
1 of 613
C H A P T E R
±
±
±
±
±
±
±
±
±
±
±
±
±
±
±
±
±
±
±
±
±
±
±
±
±
±
±
±
±
±
±
±
±
±
2 IS IT ALL RELATIVE?
Noting that what one society deems morally wrong, another
deems right, ethical
relativists conclude that morals are like manners or style of
dress. The ancient
Greek historian Herodotus, quoting the poet Pindar, long ago
announced the rela-
tivist principle when he said, “Custom is king.”
Ethical relativism became popular in the nineteenth century
when European
social scientists traveled the world and discovered a
bewildering variety of moral
norms and practices. Anthropologists like Ruth Benedict and
sociologists like Wil-
liam Graham Sumner embraced ethical relativism and gave it
the cachet of science.
Ethical relativism is a tempting doctrine because it appeals to
our desire to be
tolerant of other societies. However, it has not found much
favor among profes-
sional philosophers, who point out that while tolerance is a
virtue, indifference
to suffering is a vice. Several of the philosophers and moralists
included in this
chapter—Loretta M. Kopelman, Louis Pojman, R. M. MacIver,
and Martin Luther
King, Jr.—believe that while much morality is indeed a matter
of local custom,
some objectively valid moral principles apply to everyone. For
them, tolerance
ends when a practice or custom violates a universal human
right. Lawrence
Lengbeyer tries to work out a compromise between relativism
and absolutism.
Recently a number of anthropologists have joined philosophers
and theologians
in rejecting relativism. They challenge the idea that social
scientists must always be
neutral bystanders. Carolyn Fluehr-Lobban struggles with the
problem of whether
to condemn or to refrain from condemning the societies she
studies. In the end she
finds herself unable to retain the neutral “scientific” stance.
Thomas Nagel argues
that the Golden Rule in its negative form—not to do unto others
what you would
not have them do unto you—provides an objective
nonrelativistic basis for
morality.
Finally, when a relativist like Benedict or Sumner points to the
diversity of vil-
lages, and thus of norms, those who believe in universal moral
standards can point
to the newly emerging “global village.” Universal ethical
principles are already fully
76
©
C
en
ga
ge
L
ea
rn
in
g.
A
ll
rig
ht
s r
es
er
ve
d.
N
o
di
st
rib
ut
io
n
al
lo
w
ed
w
ith
ou
t e
xp
re
ss
a
ut
ho
riz
at
io
n.
codified for the “global village” in such documents as the
United Nations Declara-
tion of Human Rights, the United Nations Declaration of the
Rights of Children,
and the United Nations Declaration of the Rights of Women.
These declarations
firmly assert that all people, regardless of cultural background,
regardless of gender
or social status, should enjoy certain basic moral rights. While
it is certainly true
that the United Nations declarations are not universally
enforced, their very exis-
tence suggests there may be far more moral consensus in the
world than the relati-
vists allow.
IS IT ALL RELATIVE? 77
©
C
en
ga
ge
L
ea
rn
in
g.
A
ll
rig
ht
s r
es
er
ve
d.
N
o
di
st
rib
ut
io
n
al
lo
w
ed
w
ith
ou
t e
xp
re
ss
a
ut
ho
riz
at
io
n.
Morality As Custom
Herodotus
Herodotus (c. 485–425 B.C.) was the first Western historian.
Much of
what we know about the ancient world in and around Greece
derives
from him.
Following is one of the fragments of text by Herodotus
available to us
today. Although brief, it clearly shows that Herodotus may well
be the
first thinker in Western intellectual history to espouse a version
of what
today we call ethical relativism.
If anyone, no matter who, were given the opportunity of
choosing from amongst
all the nations in the world the set of beliefs which he thought
best, he would
inevitably, after careful consideration of their relative merits,
choose that of his
own country. Everyone without exception believes his own
native customs, and
the religion he was brought up in, to be the best; and that being
so, it is unlikely
that anyone but a madman would mock at such things. There is
abundant evi-
dence that this is the universal feeling about the ancient
customs of one’s country.
One might recall, in particular, an anecdote of Darius. When he
was king of
Persia, he summoned the Greeks who happened to be present at
his court, and
asked them what they would take to eat the dead bodies of their
fathers. They
replied that they would not do it for any money in the world.
Later, in the pres-
ence of the Greeks, and through an interpreter, so that they
could understand
what was said, he asked some Indians, of the tribe called
Callatiae, who do in
fact eat their parents’ dead bodies, what they would take to burn
them. They
uttered a cry of horror and forbade him to mention such a
dreadful thing. One
can see by this what custom can do, and Pindar, in my opinion,
was right when
he called it “king of all.”
STUDY QUESTIONS
1. Herodotus says that people prefer the customs of their own
country over those of all
other countries. That may have been true in his day. Is it true in
ours?
2. Herodotus’s example of what the ancient Greeks and Indians
did with the bodies of
their dead parents clearly shows that cultures have different
customs. But does that
make the case for ethical relativism? Though the two societies
did it in very different
ways, both seem to be engaged in honoring their deceased
parents.
MORALITY AS CUSTOM From Herodotus’s The Histories,
translated by Aubrey de Sélincourt, revised by
A. R. Burn (Penguin Classics 1954, revised edition 1972),
copyright © the Estate of Aubrey de
Sélincourt, 1954, copyright © A. R. Burn, 1972.
78
©
C
en
ga
ge
L
ea
rn
in
g.
A
ll
rig
ht
s r
es
er
ve
d.
N
o
di
st
rib
ut
io
n
al
lo
w
ed
w
ith
ou
t e
xp
re
ss
a
ut
ho
riz
at
io
n.
A Defense of Moral Relativism
Ruth Benedict
Ruth Benedict (1887–1948) was one of America’s foremost
anthropolo-
gists. Her Patterns of Culture (1935) is considered a classic of
comparative
anthropology.
Morality, says Ruth Benedict, is a convenient term for socially
approved
customs (that is, mores). What one society approves may be
disgraceful
and unacceptable to another. Moral rules, like rules of etiquette
or styles
of dress, vary from society to society. Morality is culturally
relative. Values
are shaped by culture. As Benedict points out, trances are
highly regarded
in India, so in India many people have trances. Some ancient
societies
praised homosexual love, so there homosexuality was a norm.
Where
material possessions are highly valued, people amass property.
“Most indi-
viduals are plastic to the moulding force of the society into
which they are
born.”
Modern social anthropology has become more and more a study
of the varieties
and common elements of cultural environment and the
consequences of these in
human behavior. For such a study of diverse social orders
primitive peoples fortu-
nately provide a laboratory not yet entirely vitiated by the
spread of a standardized
worldwide civilization. Dyaks and Hopis, Fijians and Yakuts are
significant for psy-
chological and sociological study because only among these
simpler peoples has
there been sufficient isolation to give opportunity for the
development of localized
social forms. In the higher cultures the standardization of
custom and belief over a
couple of continents has given a false sense of the inevitability
of the particular
forms that have gained currency, and we need to turn to a wider
survey in order
to check the conclusions we hastily base upon this near-
universality of familiar cus-
toms. Most of the simpler cultures did not gain the wide
currency of the one which,
out of our experience, we identify with human nature, but this
was for various his-
torical reasons, and certainly not for any that gives us as its
carriers a monopoly of
social good or of social sanity. Modern civilization, from this
point of view,
becomes not a necessary pinnacle of human achievement but
one entry in a long
series of possible adjustments.
These adjustments, whether they are in mannerisms like the
ways of showing
anger, or joy, or grief in any society, or in major human drives
like those of sex,
prove to be far more variable than experience in any one culture
would suggest. In
certain fields, such as that of religion or of formal marriage
arrangements, these
A DEFENSE OF MORAL RELATIVISM From “Anthropology
and the Abnormal” by Ruth Benedict, in The
Journal of General Psychology 10 (1934): 59–82. Reprinted
with permission of the Helen Dwight
Reid Educational Foundation. Published by Heldref
Publications, 1319 Eighteenth St., N.W.,
Washington, DC, 20036-1802. Copyright © 1934.
RUTH BENEDICT: A DEFENSE OF MORAL RELATIVISM 79
©
C
en
ga
ge
L
ea
rn
in
g.
A
ll
rig
ht
s r
es
er
ve
d.
N
o
di
st
rib
ut
io
n
al
lo
w
ed
w
ith
ou
t e
xp
re
ss
a
ut
ho
riz
at
io
n.
wide limits of variability are well known and can be fairly
described. In others it is
not yet possible to give a generalized account, but that does not
absolve us of the
task of indicating the significance of the work that has been
done and of the pro-
blems that have arisen.
One of these problems relates to the customary modern normal-
abnormal cate-
gories and our conclusions regarding them. In how far are such
categories culturally
determined, or in how far can we with assurance regard them as
absolute? In how
far can we regard inability to function socially as diagnostic of
abnormality, or in
how far is it necessary to regard this as a function of the
culture?
As a matter of fact, one of the most striking facts that emerge
from a study of
widely varying cultures is the ease with which our abnormals
function in other cul-
tures. It does not matter what kind of “abnormality” we choose
for illustration,
those which indicate extreme instability, or those which are
more in the nature of
character traits like sadism or delusions of grandeur or of
persecution, there are
well-described cultures in which these abnormals function at
ease and with honor,
and apparently without danger or difficulty to the society.
The most notorious of these is trance and catalepsy. Even a very
mild mystic is
aberrant in our culture. But most peoples have regarded even
extreme psychic man-
ifestations not only as normal and desirable, but even as
characteristic of highly val-
ued and gifted individuals. This was true even in our own
cultural background in
that period when Catholicism made the ecstatic experience the
mark of sainthood.
It is hard for us, born and brought up in a culture that makes no
use of the experi-
ence, to realize how important a role it may play and how many
individuals are
capable of it, once it has been given an honorable place in any
society.…
Cataleptic and trance phenomena are, of course, only one
illustration of the
fact that those whom we regard as abnormals may function
adequately in other cul-
tures. Many of our culturally discarded traits are selected for
elaboration in differ-
ent societies. Homosexuality is an excellent example, for in this
case our attention is
not constantly diverted, as in the consideration of trance, to the
interruption of rou-
tine activity which it implies. Homosexuality poses the problem
very simply. A ten-
dency toward this trait in our culture exposes an individual to
all the conflicts to
which all aberrants are always exposed, and we tend to identify
the consequences
of this conflict with homosexuality. But these consequences are
obviously local
and cultural. Homosexuals in many societies are not
incompetent, but they may
be such if the culture asks adjustments of them that would strain
any man’s vitality.
Wherever homosexuality has been given an honorable place in
any society, those to
whom it is congenial have filled adequately the honorable roles
society assigns to
them. Plato’s Republic is, of course, the most convincing
statement of such a read-
ing of homosexuality. It is presented as one of the major means
to the good life, and
it was generally so regarded in Greece at that time.
The cultural attitude toward homosexuals has not always been
on such a high
ethical plane, but it has been very varied. Among many
American Indian tribes
there exists the institution of the berdache, as the French called
them. These men-
women were men who at puberty or thereafter took the dress
and the occupations
of women. Sometimes they married other men and lived with
them. Sometimes they
were men with no inversion, persons of weak sexual endowment
who chose this
rôle to avoid the jeers of the women. The berdaches were never
regarded as of
80 I S IT ALL RELATIVE?
©
C
en
ga
ge
L
ea
rn
in
g.
A
ll
rig
ht
s r
es
er
ve
d.
N
o
di
st
rib
ut
io
n
al
lo
w
ed
w
ith
ou
t e
xp
re
ss
a
ut
ho
riz
at
io
n.
first-rate super-natural power, as similar men-women were in
Siberia, but rather as
leaders in women’s occupations, good healers in certain
diseases, or, among certain
tribes, as the genial organizers of social affairs. In any case,
they were socially
placed. They were not left exposed to the conflicts that visit the
deviant who is
excluded from participation in the recognized patterns of his
society.
The most spectacular illustrations of the extent to which
normality may be cul-
turally defined are those cultures where an abnormality of our
culture is the corner-
stone of their social structure. It is not possible to do justice to
these possibilities in
a short discussion. A recent study of an island of northwest
Melanesia by Fortune
describes a society built upon traits which we regard as beyond
the border of para-
noia. In this tribe the exogamic groups look upon each other as
prime manipulators
of black magic, so that one marries always into an enemy group
which remains for
life one’s deadly and unappeasable foes. They look upon a good
garden crop as a
confession of theft, for everyone is engaged in making magic to
induce into his gar-
den the productiveness of his neighbors’; therefore no secrecy
in the island is so rig-
idly insisted upon as the secrecy of a man’s harvesting of his
yams. Their polite
phrase at the acceptance of a gift is, “And if you now poison
me, how shall I
repay you this present?” Their preoccupation with poisoning is
constant; no
woman ever leaves her cooking pot for a moment untended.
Even the great affinal
economic exchanges that are characteristic of this Melanesian
culture area are quite
altered in Dobu since they are incompatible with this fear and
distrust that pervades
the culture. They go farther and people the whole world outside
their own quarters
with such malignant spirits that all-night feasts and ceremonials
simply do not
occur here. They have even rigorous religiously enforced
customs that forbid the
sharing of seed even in one family group. Anyone else’s food is
deadly poison to
you, so that communality of stores is out of the question. For
some months before
harvest the whole society is on the verge of starvation, but if
one falls to the temp-
tation and eats up one’s seed yams, one is an outcast and a
beachcomber for life.
There is no coming back. It involves, as a matter of course,
divorce and the break-
ing of all social ties.
Now in this society where no one may work with another and no
one may
share with another, Fortune describes the individual who was
regarded by all his
fellows as crazy. He was not one of those who periodically ran
amok and, beside
himself and frothing at the mouth, fell with a knife upon anyone
he could reach.
Such behavior they did not regard as putting anyone outside the
pale. They did
not even put the individuals who were known to be liable to
these attacks under
any kind of control. They merely fled when they saw the attack
coming on and
kept out of the way. “He would be all right tomorrow.” But
there was one man
of sunny, kindly disposition who liked work and liked to be
helpful. The compul-
sion was too strong for him to repress it in favor of the opposite
tendencies of his
culture. Men and women never spoke of him without laughing;
he was silly and
simple and definitely crazy. Nevertheless, to the ethnologist
used to a culture that
has, in Christianity, made his type the model of all virtue, he
seemed a pleasant
fellow.…
… Among the Kwakiutl it did not matter whether a relative had
died in bed of
disease, or by the hand of an enemy, in either case death was an
affront to be wiped
out by the death of another person. The fact that one had been
caused to mourn
RUTH BENEDICT: A DEFENSE OF MORAL RELATIVISM 81
©
C
en
ga
ge
L
ea
rn
in
g.
A
ll
rig
ht
s r
es
er
ve
d.
N
o
di
st
rib
ut
io
n
al
lo
w
ed
w
ith
ou
t e
xp
re
ss
a
ut
ho
riz
at
io
n.
was proof that one had been put upon. A chief’s sister and her
daughter had gone
up to Victoria, and either because they drank bad whiskey or
because their boat
capsized they never came back. The chief called together his
warriors. “Now I ask
you, tribes, who shall wail? Shall I do it or shall another?” The
spokesman
answered, of course, “Not you, Chief. Let some other of the
tribes.” Immediately
they set up the war pole to announce their intention of wiping
out the injury, and
gathered a war party. They set out, and found seven men and
two children asleep
and killed them. “Then they felt good when they arrived at
Sebaa in the evening.”
The point which is of interest to us is that in our society those
who on that
occasion would feel good when they arrived at Sebaa that
evening would be the
definitely abnormal. There would be some, even in our society,
but it is not a rec-
ognized and approved mood under the circumstances. On the
Northwest Coast
those are favored and fortunate to whom that mood under those
circumstances is
congenial, and those to whom it is repugnant are unlucky. This
latter minority can
register in their own culture only by doing violence to their
congenial responses and
acquiring others that are difficult for them. The person, for
instance, who, like a
Plains Indian whose wife has been taken from him, is too proud
to fight, can deal
with the Northwest Coast civilization only by ignoring its
strongest bents. If he can-
not achieve it, he is the deviant in that culture, their instance of
abnormality.
This head-hunting that takes place on the Northwest Coast after
a death is no
matter of blood revenge or of organized vengeance. There is no
effort to tie up the
subsequent killing with any responsibility on the part of the
victim for the death of
the person who is being mourned. A chief whose son has died
goes visiting wher-
ever his fancy dictates, and he says to his host, “My prince has
died today, and you
go with him.” Then he kills him. In this, according to their
interpretation, he acts
nobly because he has not been downed. He has thrust back in
return. The whole
procedure is meaningless without the fundamental paranoid
reading of bereave-
ment. Death, like all the other untoward accidents of existence,
confounds man’s
pride and can only be handled in the category of insults.
Behavior honored upon the Northwest Coast is one which is
recognized as
abnormal in our civilization, and yet it is sufficiently close to
the attitudes of our
own culture to be intelligible to us and to have a definite
vocabulary with which
we may discuss it. The megalomaniac paranoid trend is a
definite danger in our
society. It is encouraged by some of our major preoccupations,
and it confronts us
with a choice of two possible attitudes. One is to brand it as
abnormal and repre-
hensible, and is the attitude we have chosen in our civilization.
The other is to make
it an essential attribute of ideal man, and this is the solution in
the culture of the
Northwest Coast.
These illustrations, which it has been possible to indicate only
in the briefest
manner, force upon us the fact that normality is culturally
defined. An adult shaped
to the drives and standards of either of these cultures, if he were
transported into
our civilization, would fall into our categories of abnormality.
He would be faced
with the psychic dilemmas of the socially unavailable. In his
own culture, however,
he is the pillar of society, the end result of socially inculcated
mores, and the prob-
lem of personal instability in his case simply does not arise.
No one civilization can possibly utilize in its mores the whole
potential range of
human behavior. Just as there are great numbers of possible
phonetic articulations,
82 I S IT ALL RELATIVE?
©
C
en
ga
ge
L
ea
rn
in
g.
A
ll
rig
ht
s r
es
er
ve
d.
N
o
di
st
rib
ut
io
n
al
lo
w
ed
w
ith
ou
t e
xp
re
ss
a
ut
ho
riz
at
io
n.
and the possibility of language depends on a selection and
standardization of a few
of these in order that speech communication may be possible at
all, so the possibil-
ity of organized behavior of every sort, from the fashions of
local dress and houses
to the dicta of a people’s ethics and religion, depends upon a
similar selection
among the possible behavior traits. In the field of recognized
economic obligations
or sex tabus this selection is as non-rational and subconscious a
process as it is in
the field of phonetics. It is a process which goes on in the group
for long periods of
time and is historically conditioned by innumerable accidents of
isolation or of con-
tact of peoples. In any comprehensive study of psychology, the
selection that differ-
ent cultures have made in the course of history within the great
circumference of
potential behavior is of great significance.
Every society, beginning with some slight inclination in one
direction or
another, carries its preference farther and farther, integrating
itself more and more
completely upon its chosen basis, and discarding those types of
behavior that are
uncongenial. Most of those organizations of personality that
seem to us most
uncontrovertibly abnormal have been used by different
civilizations in the very
foundations of their institutional life. Conversely the most
valued traits of normal
individuals have been looked on in differently organized
cultures as aberrant. Nor-
mality, in short, within a very wide range, is culturally defined.
It is primarily a
term for the socially elaborated segment of human behavior in
any culture; and
abnormality, a term for the segment that that particular
civilization does not use.
The very eyes with which we see the problem are conditioned
by the long tradi-
tional habits of our own society.
It is a point that has been made more often in relation to ethics
than in relation
to psychiatry. We do not any longer make the mistake of
deriving the morality of
our locality and decade directly from the inevitable constitution
of human nature.
We do not elevate it to the dignity of a first principle. We
recognize that morality
differs in every society, and is a convenient term for socially
approved habits. Man-
kind has always preferred to say, “It is morally good,” rather
than “It is habitual,”
and the fact of this preference is matter enough for a critical
science of ethics. But
historically the two phrases are synonymous.
The concept of the normal is properly a variant of the concept
of the good. It is
that which society has approved. A normal action is one which
falls well within the
limits of expected behavior for a particular society. Its
variability among different
peoples is essentially a function of the variability of the
behavior patterns that dif-
ferent societies have created for themselves, and can never be
wholly divorced from
a consideration of culturally institutionalized types of behavior.
Each culture is a more or less elaborate working-out of the
potentialities of the
segment it has chosen. In so far as a civilization is well
integrated and consistent
within itself, it will tend to carry farther and farther, according
to its nature, its ini-
tial impulse toward a particular type of action, and from the
point of view of any
other culture those elaborations will include more and more
extreme and aberrant
traits.
Each of these traits, in proportion as it reinforces the chosen
behavior patterns
of that culture, is for that culture normal. Those individuals to
whom it is congenial
either congenitally, or as the result of childhood sets, are
accorded prestige in that
culture, and are not visited with the social contempt or
disapproval which their
RUTH BENEDICT: A DEFENSE OF MORAL RELATIVISM 83
©
C
en
ga
ge
L
ea
rn
in
g.
A
ll
rig
ht
s r
es
er
ve
d.
N
o
di
st
rib
ut
io
n
al
lo
w
ed
w
ith
ou
t e
xp
re
ss
a
ut
ho
riz
at
io
n.
traits would call down upon them in a society that was
differently organized. On
the other hand, those individuals whose characteristics are not
congenial to the
selected type of human behavior in that community are the
deviants, no matter
how valued their personality traits may be in a contrasted
civilization.
The Dobuan who is not easily susceptible to fear of treachery,
who enjoys work
and likes to be helpful, is their neurotic and regarded as silly.
On the Northwest
Coast the person who finds it difficult to read life in terms of an
insult contest will
be the person upon whom fall all the difficulties of the
culturally unprovided for.
The person who does not find it easy to humiliate a neighbor,
nor to see humilia-
tion in his own experience, who is genial and loving, may, of
course, find some
unstandardized way of achieving satisfactions in his society, but
not in the major
patterned responses that his culture requires of him. If he is
born to play an impor-
tant rôle in a family with many hereditary privileges, he can
succeed only by doing
violence to his whole personality. If he does not succeed, he has
betrayed his cul-
ture; that is, he is abnormal.
I have spoken of individuals as having sets toward certain types
of behavior,
and of these sets as running sometimes counter to the types of
behavior which are
institutionalized in the culture to which they belong. From all
that we know of con-
trasting cultures it seems clear that differences of temperament
occur in every soci-
ety. The matter has never been made the subject of
investigation, but from the
available material it would appear that these temperament types
are very likely of
universal recurrence. That is, there is an ascertainable range of
human behavior that
is found wherever a sufficiently large series of individuals is
observed. But the pro-
portion in which behavior types stand to one another in
different societies is not
universal. The vast majority of the individuals in any group are
shaped to the fash-
ion of that culture. In other words, most individuals are plastic
to the moulding
force of the society into which they are born. In a society that
values trance, as in
India, they will have supernormal experience. In a society that
institutionalizes
homosexuality, they will be homosexual. In a society that sets
the gathering of pos-
sessions as the chief human objective, they will amass property.
The deviants, what-
ever the type of behavior the culture has institutionalized, will
remain few in
number, and there seems no more difficulty in moulding that
vast malleable major-
ity to the “normality” of what we consider an aberrant trait,
such as delusions of
reference, than to the normality of such accepted behavior
patterns as acquisitive-
ness. The small proportion of the number of the deviants in any
culture is not a
function of the sure instinct with which that society has built
itself upon the funda-
mental sanities, but of the universal fact that, happily, the
majority of mankind
quite readily take any shape that is presented to them.…
STUDY QUESTIONS
1. Do you think that the fact of cultural diversity is itself an
argument for ethical relativ-
ism? Explain.
2. If Benedict’s defense of ethical relativism is correct, then the
correct way to resolve a
personal dilemma might be to take a survey or poll to see what
the majority in your
society think is right. If the majority favor capital punishment
and oppose abortion,
for example, then capital punishment is right and abortion is
wrong. Can you defend
Benedict against this odd consequence? Explain.
84 I S IT ALL RELATIVE?
©
C
en
ga
ge
L
ea
rn
in
g.
A
ll
rig
ht
s r
es
er
ve
d.
N
o
di
st
rib
ut
io
n
al
lo
w
ed
w
ith
ou
t e
xp
re
ss
a
ut
ho
riz
at
io
n.
3. Do you think that certain types of behavior (for example,
executing children or beating
animals to death) are wrong wherever they occur, despite
attitudes prevailing in the
societies that practice them? If you believe that such acts are
universally wrong, what
makes them wrong?
4. How might Benedict account for notions of moral
enlightenment and moral progress?
A Defense of Cultural Relativism
William Graham Sumner
William Graham Sumner (1840–1910) was a sociologist, an
economist,
and a proponent of Darwinism. His books include What Social
Classes
Owe to Each Other (1883) and Folkways (1906).
William Graham Sumner claims that his ethical relativism is
derived from
having observed other societies. According to Sumner, the
“folkways”—
that is, the customs, mores, and traditions of each society—are
so
ingrained in its members that they naturally come to think of
them as
objectively “right” and “good.” We may build elaborate
philosophical
and legal doctrines around these concepts, but it is the folkways
that deter-
mine their true meaning.
There is a right way to catch game, to win a wife, to make one’s
self appear, to cure
disease, to honor ghosts, to treat comrades or strangers, to
behave when a child is
born, on the warpath, in council, and so on in all cases which
can arise. The ways
are defined on the negative side, that is, by taboos. The “right”
way is the way
which the ancestors used and which has been handed down. The
tradition is its
own warrant. It is not held subject to verification by experience.
The notion of
right is in the folkways. It is not outside of them, of
independent origin, and
brought to them to test them. In the folkways, whatever is, is
right. This is because
they are traditional, and therefore contain in themselves the
authority of the ances-
tral ghosts. When we come to the folkways we are at the end of
our analysis. The
notion of right and ought is the same in regard to all the
folkways.…
The morality of a group at a time is the sum of the taboos and
prescriptions in
the folkways by which right conduct is defined. Therefore
morals can never be intu-
itive. They are historical, institutional, and empirical. World
philosophy, life policy,
right, rights, and morality are all products of the folkways.
They are reflections
on, and generalizations from, the experience of pleasure and
pain which is won
in efforts to carry on the struggle for existence under actual life
conditions.
A DEFENSE OF CULTURAL RELATIVISM From Folkways by
William Graham Sumner.
WILLIAM GRAHAM SUMNER: A DEFENSE OF CULTURAL
RELATIVISM 85
©
C
en
ga
ge
L
ea
rn
in
g.
A
ll
rig
ht
s r
es
er
ve
d.
N
o
di
st
rib
ut
io
n
al
lo
w
ed
w
ith
ou
t e
xp
re
ss
a
ut
ho
riz
at
io
n.
The generalizations are very crude and vague in their germinal
forms. They are all
embodied in folklore, and all our philosophy and science have
been developed out
of them.
Mores Are a Directive Force
Of course the view which has been stated is antagonistic to the
view that philoso-
phy and ethics furnish creative and determining forces in
society and history. That
view comes down to us from the Greek philosophy and it has
now prevailed so
long that all current discussion conforms to it. Philosophy and
ethics are pursued
as independent disciplines, and the results are brought to the
science of society and
to statesmanship and legislation as authoritative dicta. We also
have Völkerpsycho-
logie, Sozialpolitik, and other intermediate forms which show
the struggle of meta-
physics to retain control of the science of society. The “historic
sense,” the
Zeitgeist, and other terms of similar import are partial
recognitions of the mores
and their importance in the science of society. We shall see
below that philosophy
and ethics are products of the folkways. They are taken out of
the mores, but are
never original and creative; they are secondary and derived.
They often interfere in
the second stage of the sequence—act, thought, act. Then they
produce harm, but
some ground is furnished for the claim that they are creative or
at least regulative.
In fact, the real process in great bodies of men is not one of
deduction from any
great principle of philosophy or ethics. It is one of minute
efforts to live well
under existing conditions, which efforts are repeated
indefinitely by great numbers,
getting strength from habit and from the fellowship of united
action. The resultant
folkways become coercive. All are forced to conform, and the
folkways dominate
the societal life. Then they seem true and right, and arise into
mores as the norm
of welfare. Thence are produced faiths, ideas, doctrines,
religions, and philosophies,
according to the stage of civilization and the fashions of
reflection and
generalization.
What Is Goodness or Badness of the Mores?
It is most important to notice that, for the people of a time and
place, their own
mores are always good, or rather that for them there can be no
question of the
goodness or badness of their mores. The reason is because the
standards of good
and right are in the mores. If the life conditions change, the
traditional folkways
may produce pain and loss, or fail to produce the same good as
formerly. Then
the loss of comfort and ease brings doubt into the judgment of
welfare (causing
doubt of the pleasure of the gods, or of war power, or of
health), and thus dis-
turbs the unconscious philosophy of the mores. Then a later
time will pass judg-
ment on the mores. Another society may also pass judgment on
the mores. In our
literary and historical study of the mores we want to get from
them their educa-
tional value, which consists in the stimulus or warning as to
what is, in its effects,
societally good or bad. This may lead us to reject or neglect a
phenomenon like
infanticide, slavery, or witchcraft, as an old “abuse” and “evil,”
or to pass by
the crusades as a folly which cannot recur. Such a course would
be a great error.
Everything in the mores of a time and place must be regarded as
justified with
86 I S IT ALL RELATIVE?
©
C
en
ga
ge
L
ea
rn
in
g.
A
ll
rig
ht
s r
es
er
ve
d.
N
o
di
st
rib
ut
io
n
al
lo
w
ed
w
ith
ou
t e
xp
re
ss
a
ut
ho
riz
at
io
n.
regard to that time and place. “Good” mores are those which are
well adapted to
the situation. “Bad” mores are those which are not so adapted.
The mores are not
so stereotyped and changeless as might appear, because they are
forever moving
towards more complete adaptation to conditions and interests,
and also towards
more complete adjustment to each other. People in mass have
never made or kept
up a custom in order to hurt their own interests. They have
made innumerable
errors as to what their interests were and how to satisfy them,
but they have
always aimed to serve their interests as well as they could. This
gives the stand-
point for the student of the mores. All things in them come
before him on the
same plane. They all bring instruction and warning. They all
have the same rela-
tion to power and welfare. The mistakes in them are component
parts of them.
We do not study them in order to approve some of them and
condemn others.
They are all equally worthy of attention from the fact that they
existed and were
used. The chief object of study in them is their adjustment to
interests, their rela-
tion to welfare, and their coordination in a harmonious system
of life policy. For
the men of the time there are no “bad” mores. What is
traditional and current
is the standard of what ought to be. The masses never raise any
question about
such things. If a few raise doubts and questions, this proves that
the folkways
have already begun to lose firmness and the regulative element
in the mores has
begun to lose authority. This indicates that the folkways are on
their way to a
new adjustment. The extreme of folly, wickedness, and
absurdity in the mores is
witch persecutions, but the best men in the seventeenth century
had no doubt that
witches existed, and that they ought to be burned. The religion,
statecraft, juris-
prudence, philosophy, and social system of that age all
contributed to maintain
that belief. It was rather a culmination than a contradiction of
the current faiths
and convictions, just as the dogma that all men are equal and
that one ought to
have as much political power in the state as another was the
culmination of the
political dogmatism and social philosophy of the nineteenth
century. Hence our
judgments of the good or evil consequences of folkways are to
be kept separate
from our study of the historical phenomena of them, and of their
strength and
the reasons for it. The judgments have their place in plans and
doctrines for the
future, not in a retrospect.
The Mores Have the Authority of Facts
The mores come down to us from the past. Each individual is
born into them as
he is born into the atmosphere, and he does not reflect on them,
or criticize them
any more than a baby analyzes the atmosphere before he begins
to breathe it.
Each one is subjected to the influence of the mores, and formed
by them, before
he is capable of reasoning about them. It may be objected that
nowadays, at least,
we criticize all traditions, and accept none just because they are
handed down to
us. If we take up cases of things which are still entirely or
almost entirely in the
mores, we shall see that this is not so. There are sects of free-
lovers amongst us
who want to discuss pair marriage. They are not simply people
of evil life. They
invite us to discuss rationally our inherited customs and ideas as
to marriage,
which, they say, are by no means so excellent and elevated as
we believe. They
WILLIAM GRAHAM SUMNER: A DEFENSE OF CULTURAL
RELATIVISM 87
©
C
en
ga
ge
L
ea
rn
in
g.
A
ll
rig
ht
s r
es
er
ve
d.
N
o
di
st
rib
ut
io
n
al
lo
w
ed
w
ith
ou
t e
xp
re
ss
a
ut
ho
riz
at
io
n.
have never won any serious attention. Some others want to
argue in favor of
polygamy on grounds of expediency. They fail to obtain a
hearing. Others want
to discuss property. In spite of some literary activity on their
part, no discussion
of property, bequest, and inheritance has ever been opened.
Property and mar-
riage are in the mores. Nothing can ever change them but the
unconscious and
imperceptible movement of the mores. Religion was originally a
matter of the
mores. It became a societal institution and a function of the
state. It has now to
a great extent been put back into the mores. Since laws with
penalties to enforce
religious creeds or practices have gone out of use any one may
think and act as he
pleases about religion. Therefore, it is not now “good form” to
attack religion.
Infidel publications are now tabooed by the mores, and are more
effectually
repressed than ever before. They produce no controversy.
Democracy is in our
American mores. It is a product of our physical and economic
conditions. It is
impossible to discuss or criticize it. It is glorified for
popularity, and is a subject
of dithyrambic rhetoric. No one treats it with complete candor
and sincerity. No
one dares to analyze it as he would aristocracy or autocracy. He
would get no
hearing and would only incur abuse. The thing to be noticed in
all these cases is
that the masses oppose a deaf ear to every argument against the
mores. It is only
insofar as things have been transferred from the mores into laws
and positive
institutions that there is discussion about them or rationalizing
upon them. The
mores contain the norm by which, if we should discuss the
mores, we should
have to judge the mores. We learn the mores as unconsciously
as we learn to
walk and eat and breathe. The masses never learn how we walk,
and eat, and
breathe, and they never know any reason why the mores are
what they are. The
justification of them is that when we wake to consciousness of
life we find them
facts which already hold us in the bonds of tradition, custom,
and habit. The
mores contain embodied in them notions, doctrines, and
maxims, but they are
facts. They are in the present tense. They have nothing to do
with what ought to
be, will be, may be, or once was, if it is not now.
Mores and Morals; Social Code
For everyone the mores give the notion of what ought to be.
This includes the
notion of what ought to be done, for all should cooperate to
bring to pass, in the
order of life, what ought to be. All notions of propriety,
decency, chastity, polite-
ness, order, duty, right, rights, discipline, respect, reverence,
cooperation, and fel-
lowship, especially all things in regard to which good and ill
depend entirely on
the point at which the line is drawn, are in the mores. The mores
can make things
seem right and good to one group or one age which to another
seem antagonistic to
every instinct of human nature. The thirteenth century bred in
every heart such a
sentiment in regard to heretics that inquisitors had no more
misgivings in their pro-
ceedings than men would have now if they should attempt to
exterminate rattle-
snakes. The sixteenth century gave to all such notions about
witches that witch
persecutors thought they were waging war on enemies of God
and man. Of course
the inquisitors and witch persecutors constantly developed the
notions of heretics
and witches. They exaggerated the notions and then gave them
back again to the
88 I S IT ALL RELATIVE?
©
C
en
ga
ge
L
ea
rn
in
g.
A
ll
rig
ht
s r
es
er
ve
d.
N
o
di
st
rib
ut
io
n
al
lo
w
ed
w
ith
ou
t e
xp
re
ss
a
ut
ho
riz
at
io
n.
mores, in their expanded form, to inflame the hearts of men
with terror and hate
and to become, in the next stage, so much more fantastic and
ferocious motives.
Such is the reaction between the mores and the acts of the living
generation. The
world philosophy of the age is never anything but the reflection
on the mental hori-
zon, which is formed out of the mores, of the ruling ideas which
are in the mores
themselves. It is from a failure to recognize the to and fro in
this reaction that the
current notion arises that mores are produced by doctrines. The
“morals” of an age
are never anything but the consonance between what is done and
what the mores of
the age require. The whole revolves on itself, in the relation of
the specific to the
general, within the horizon formed by the mores. Every attempt
to win an outside
standpoint from which to reduce the whole to an absolute
philosophy of truth and
right, based on an unalterable principle, is a delusion. New
elements are brought in
only by new conquests of nature through science and art. The
new conquests
change the conditions of life and the interests of the members of
the society. Then
the mores change by adaptation to new conditions and interests.
The philosophy
and ethics then follow to account for and justify the changes in
the mores; often,
also, to claim that they have caused the changes. They never do
anything but
draw new lines of bearing between the parts of the mores and
the horizon of
thought within which they are enclosed, and which is a
deduction from the mores.
The horizon is widened by more knowledge, but for one age it is
just as much a
generalization from the mores as for another. It is always
unreal. It is only a prod-
uct of thought. The ethical philosophers select points on this
horizon from which to
take their bearings, and they think that they have won some
authority for their sys-
tems when they travel back again from the generalization to the
specific custom out
of which it was deduced. The cases of the inquisitors and witch
persecutors who
toiled arduously and continually for their chosen ends, for little
or no reward,
show us the relation between mores on the one side and
philosophy, ethics, and
religion on the other.
STUDY QUESTIONS
1. Sumner says, “For the people of a time and place, their own
mores are always good,
or rather … for them there can be no question of the goodness
or badness of their
mores.” Explain his position. Has Sumner overlooked the
possibility that a people
could wonder whether their own mores are correct? Or does
Sumner deny this is
possible?
2. Sumner says that we often pass judgment on mores of the
past or on mores of other
people in the present. For example, we now think that
infanticide and slavery were
wrong. Why does Sumner believe that such moralizing is
inappropriate?
3. Sumner believes that mores change when scientific
discoveries or technological inven-
tions change the conditions of life. Why is it only practical
inventions that change
mores, and not moral insights?
4. What is the Zeitgeist? How is the concept relevant to
Sumner’s theory?
5. Sumner denies that mores are ever produced by doctrines.
Does this mean that the
moral doctrines of philosophers like Aristotle, Kant, or Mill
have no influence on what
counts as moral? Explain.
WILLIAM GRAHAM SUMNER: A DEFENSE OF CULTURAL
RELATIVISM 89
©
C
en
ga
ge
L
ea
rn
in
g.
A
ll
rig
ht
s r
es
er
ve
d.
N
o
di
st
rib
ut
io
n
al
lo
w
ed
w
ith
ou
t e
xp
re
ss
a
ut
ho
riz
at
io
n.
Cultural Relativism and Universal Rights
Carolyn Fluehr-Lobban
Carolyn Fluehr-Lobban (b. 1945) is a professor of anthropology
at Rhode
Island College, where she is director of the general education
program. She
has written a number of works on Islamic culture and practice,
including
Modern Egypt and Its Heritage (1990), Islamic Society in
Practice (1994),
and Race and Racism: An Introduction (2006).
Carolyn Fluehr-Lobban is an anthropologist who objects to the
widespread
acceptance of ethical relativism by her peers. She points out
that in 1947,
when the idea of an international declaration of universal human
rights
was first being discussed, anthropologists, who were mainly
ethical relati-
vists, declined to participate. Fluehr-Lobban says that this
laissez-faire pos-
ture must change: “the time has come” for anthropologists to
take a stand
on key human-rights issues. This will entail morally judging
and condemn-
ing some of the societies they study. In particular, Fluehr-
Lobban con-
demns the mores that in many cultures contribute to the
exploitation and
degradation of women. Fluehr-Lobban advocates active
measures to get
social change: “We cannot just be bystanders.”
Cultural relativism, long a key concept in anthropology, asserts
that since each cul-
ture has its own values and practices, anthropologists should not
make value judg-
ments about cultural differences. As a result, anthropological
pedagogy has stressed
that the study of customs and norms should be value-free, and
that the appropriate
role of the anthropologist is that of observer and recorder.
Today, however, this view is being challenged by critics inside
and outside the
discipline, especially those who want anthropologists to take a
stand on key
human-rights issues. I agree that the time has come for
anthropologists to become
more actively engaged in safeguarding the rights of people
whose lives and cultures
they study.
Historically, anthropology as a discipline has declined to
participate in the dia-
logue that produced international conventions regarding human
rights. For exam-
ple, in 1947, when the executive board of the American
Anthropological
Association withdrew from discussions that led to the
“Universal Declaration of
Human Rights,” it did so in the belief that no such declaration
would be applicable
to all human beings. But the world and anthropology have
changed. Because their
research involves extended interaction with people at the
grassroots, anthropolo-
gists are in a unique position to lend knowledge and expertise to
the international
debate regarding human rights.
CULTURAL RELATIVISM AND UNIVERSAL RIGHTS Used
by permission of the author.
90 I S IT ALL RELATIVE?
©
C
en
ga
ge
L
ea
rn
in
g.
A
ll
rig
ht
s r
es
er
ve
d.
N
o
di
st
rib
ut
io
n
al
lo
w
ed
w
ith
ou
t e
xp
re
ss
a
ut
ho
riz
at
io
n.
Doing so does not represent a complete break with the traditions
of our field.
After all, in the past, anthropologists did not hesitate to speak
out against such rep-
rehensible practices as Nazi genocide and South African
apartheid. And they have
testified in U.S. courts against government rules that impinge
on the religious tradi-
tions or sacred lands of Native Americans, decrying government
policies that treat
groups of people unjustly.
However, other practices that violate individual rights or
oppress particular
groups have not been denounced. Anthropologists generally
have not spoken
out, for example, against the practice in many cultures of
female circumcision,
which critics call a mutilation of women. They have been
unwilling to pass
judgment on such forms of culturally based homicide as the
killing of infants
or the aged. Some have withheld judgment on acts of communal
violence, such
as clashes between Hindus and Muslims in India or Tutsis and
Hutus in
Rwanda, perhaps because the animosities between those groups
are of long
standing.
Moreover, as a practical matter, organized anthropology’s
refusal to participate
in drafting the 1947 human-rights declaration has meant that
anthropologists have
not had much of a role in drafting later human-rights
statements, such as the United
Nations’ “Convention on the Elimination of All Forms of
Discrimination Against
Women,” approved in 1979. In many international forums
discussing women’s
rights, participants have specifically rejected using cultural
relativism as a barrier
to improving women’s lives.
The issue of violence against women throws the perils of
cultural relativism into
stark relief. Following the lead of human-rights advocates, a
growing number of
anthropologists and others are coming to recognize that
violence against women
should be acknowledged as a violation of a basic human right to
be free from
harm. They believe that such violence cannot be excused or
justified on cultural
grounds.
Let me refer to my own experience. For nearly 25 years, I have
conducted
research in the Sudan, one of the African countries where the
practice of female cir-
cumcision is widespread, affecting the vast majority of females
in the northern
Sudan. Chronic infections are a common result, and sexual
intercourse and child-
birth are rendered difficult and painful. However, cultural
ideology in the Sudan
holds that an uncircumcised woman is not respectable, and few
families would
risk their daughter’s chances of marrying by not having her
circumcised. British
colonial officials outlawed the practice in 1946, but this served
only to make it sur-
reptitious and thus more dangerous. Women found it harder to
get treatment for
mistakes or for side effects of the illegal surgery.
For a long time I felt trapped between, on one side, my
anthropologist’s under-
standing of the custom and of the sensitivities about it among
the people with
whom I was working, and, on the other, the largely feminist
campaign in the West
to eradicate what critics see as a “barbaric” custom. To ally
myself with Western
feminists and condemn female circumcision seemed to me to be
a betrayal of the
value system and culture of the Sudan, which I had come to
understand. But as
I was asked over the years to comment on female circumcision
because of my
expertise in the Sudan, I came to realize how deeply I felt that
the practice was
harmful and wrong.
CAROLYN FLUEHR-LOBBAN: CULTURAL RELATIVISM
AND UNIVERSAL RIGHTS 91
©
C
en
ga
ge
L
ea
rn
in
g.
A
ll
rig
ht
s r
es
er
ve
d.
N
o
di
st
rib
ut
io
n
al
lo
w
ed
w
ith
ou
t e
xp
re
ss
a
ut
ho
riz
at
io
n.
In 1993, female circumcision was one of the practices deemed
harmful by
delegates at the international Human Rights Conference in
Vienna. During their dis-
cussions, they came to view circumcision as a violation of the
rights of children as
well as of the women who suffer its consequences throughout
life. Those discussions
made me realize that there was a moral agenda larger than
myself, larger than West-
ern culture or the culture of the northern Sudan or my
discipline. I decided to join
colleagues from other disciplines and cultures in speaking out
against the practice.
Some cultures are beginning to change, although cause and
effect are difficult
to determine. Women’s associations in the Ivory Coast are
calling for an end to
female circumcision. In Egypt, the Cairo Institute for Human
Rights has reported
the first publicly acknowledged marriage of an uncircumcised
woman. In the United
States, a Nigerian woman recently was granted asylum on the
ground that her
returning to her country would result in the forcible
circumcision of her daughter,
which was deemed a violation of the girl’s human rights.
To be sure, it is not easy to achieve consensus concerning the
point at which
cultural practices cross the line and become violations of human
rights. But it is
important that scholars and human-rights activists discuss the
issue. Some examples
of when the line is crossed may be clearer than others. The
action of a Japanese
wife who feels honor-bound to commit suicide because of the
shame of her
husband’s infidelity can be explained and perhaps justified by
the traditional code
of honor in Japanese society. However, when she decides to
take the lives of her
children as well, she is committing murder, which may be easier
to condemn than
suicide.
What about “honor” killings of sisters and daughters accused of
sexual miscon-
duct in some Middle Eastern and Mediterranean societies? Some
anthropologists
have explained this practice in culturally relativist terms, saying
that severe disrup-
tions of the moral order occur when sexual impropriety is
alleged or takes place. To
restore the social equilibrium and avoid feuds, the local culture
requires the shed-
ding of blood to wash away the shame of sexual dishonor. The
practice of honor
killings, which victimizes mainly women, has been defended in
some local courts
as less serious than premeditated murder, because it stems from
longstanding cul-
tural traditions. While some judges have agreed, anthropologists
should see a differ-
ent picture: a pattern of cultural discrimination against women.
As the issue of domestic violence shows, we need to explore the
ways that we
balance individual and cultural rights. The “right” of a man to
discipline, slap, hit,
or beat his wife (and often, by extension, his children) is widely
recognized across
many cultures in which male dominance is an accepted fact of
life. Indeed, the issue
of domestic violence has only recently been added to the
international human-rights
agenda, with the addition of women’s rights to the list of basic
human rights at the
Vienna conference.
The fact that domestic violence is being openly discussed and
challenged in
some societies (the United States is among the leaders) helps to
encourage dialogue
in societies in which domestic violence has been a taboo
subject. This dialogue is
relatively new, and no clear principles have emerged. But
anthropologists could
inform and enrich the discussion, using their knowledge of
family and community
life in different cultures.
92 I S IT ALL RELATIVE?
©
C
en
ga
ge
L
ea
rn
in
g.
A
ll
rig
ht
s r
es
er
ve
d.
N
o
di
st
rib
ut
io
n
al
lo
w
ed
w
ith
ou
t e
xp
re
ss
a
ut
ho
riz
at
io
n.
Cases of genocide may allow the clearest insight into where the
line between
local culture and universal morality lies. Many anthropologists
have urged the
Brazilian and Venezuelan governments to stop gold miners from
slaughtering the
Yanomami people, who are battling the encroachment of miners
on their rain for-
ests. Other practices that harm individuals or categories of
people (such as the
elderly, women, and enslaved or formerly enslaved people) may
not represent geno-
cide per se, and thus may present somewhat harder questions
about the morality of
traditional practices. We need to focus on the harm done,
however, and not on the
scale of the abuse. We need to be sensitive to cultural
differences but not allow
them to override widely recognized human rights.
The exchange of ideas across cultures is already fostering a
growing acceptance
of the universal nature of some human rights, regardless of
cultural differences. The
right of individuals to be free from harm or the threat of harm,
and the right of
cultural minorities to exist freely within states, are just two
examples of rights that
are beginning to be universally recognized—although not
universally applied.
Fortunately, organized anthropology is beginning to change its
attitude toward
cultural relativism and human rights. The theme of the 1994
convention of the
American Anthropological Association was human rights. At the
sessions organized
around the topic, many anthropologists said they no longer were
absolutely com-
mitted to cultural relativism. The association has responded to
the changing attitude
among its members by forming a Commission for Human
Rights, charged with
developing a specifically anthropological perspective on those
rights, and with chal-
lenging violations and promoting education about them.
Nevertheless, many anthropologists continue to express strong
support for cul-
tural relativism. One of the most contentious issues arises from
the fundamental
question: What authority do we Westerners have to impose our
own concept of
universal rights on the rest of humanity? It is true that Western
ideas of human
rights have so far dominated international discourse. On the
other hand, the cul-
tural relativists’ argument is often used by repressive
governments to deflect interna-
tional criticism of their abuse of their citizens. At the very
least, anthropologists
need to condemn such misuse of cultural relativism, even if it
means that they may
be denied permission to do research in the country in question.
Personally, I would go further: I believe that we should not let
the concept of
relativism stop us from using national and international forums
to examine ways
to protect the lives and dignity of people in every culture.
Because of our involve-
ment in local societies, anthropologists could provide early
warnings of abuses—for
example, by reporting data to international human-rights
organizations, and by
joining the dialogue at international conferences. When there is
a choice between
defending human rights and defending cultural relativism,
anthropologists should
choose to protect and promote human rights. We cannot just be
bystanders.
STUDY QUESTIONS
1. What prompted Fluehr-Lobban to pass moral judgment on the
societies she was
studying? How does she justify this to herself as an
anthropologist who is sensitive
to the feelings of the people she is judging?
2. Now that she is no longer merely standing by as an observer,
what role does
Fluehr-Lobban see herself playing?
CAROLYN FLUEHR-LOBBAN: CULTURAL RELATIVISM
AND UNIVERSAL RIGHTS 93
©
C
en
ga
ge
L
ea
rn
in
g.
A
ll
rig
ht
s r
es
er
ve
d.
N
o
di
st
rib
ut
io
n
al
lo
w
ed
w
ith
ou
t e
xp
re
ss
a
ut
ho
riz
at
io
n.
3. How, in the opinion of Fluehr-Lobban, is “cultural
relativism” being misused by some
anthropologists?
4. Give an example of what Fluehr-Lobban considers to be an
abusive practice in a soci-
ety, and state what human right it violates. How might an
outsider go about getting the
abusive practice changed?
Female Circumcision/Genital Mutilation
and Ethical Relativism
Loretta M. Kopelman
Loretta Kopelman (b. 1938) is professor emeritus at East
Carolina Univer-
sity. She specializes in bioethics and has written more than 140
articles and
edited several books on the topic.
Some relativists claim that “an action is right if it is approved
in a person’s
culture and wrong if it is disapproved.” By this reasoning, no
culture has
the moral authority to criticize the practices of other cultures;
each society
determines for itself what is right and wrong. Kopelman
opposes this the-
ory and points out that it can be used to justify horrific
practices like
apartheid, genocide, and war—and female genital mutilation
(FGM). She
rejects the relativist view on the grounds that moral judgments,
like medi-
cal or scientific findings, can be evaluated for consistency and
empirical
accuracy. Those who defend FGM, for example, often justify it
by claiming
it is a religious imperative and is essential to women’s health.
In fact, it is
not required by the Koran, and it is manifestly bad for women’s
health.
Most cultures, says Kopelman, share similar basic moral values
and goals,
such as the alleviation of suffering and the promotion of
personal well-
being. They are also responsive to logic and rules of evidence.
These com-
mon goals give her hope that we can engage in meaningful
intercultural
discussions about right and wrong.
In northern Africa and southern Arabia many girls undergo
ritual surgery involving
removal of parts of their external genitalia; the surgery is often
accompanied by cer-
emonies intended to honor and welcome the girls into their
communities. About
80 million living women have had this surgery, and an
additional 4 or 5 million
girls undergo it each year. Usually performed between infancy
and puberty, these
Loretta M. Kopelman, “Female Circumcision/Genital Mutilation
and Ethical Relativism,” Second
Opinion 20, no. 2 (October 1994): 55–71. Reprinted by
permission of the Park Ridge Center.
94 I S IT ALL RELATIVE?
©
C
en
ga
ge
L
ea
rn
in
g.
A
ll
rig
ht
s r
es
er
ve
d.
N
o
di
st
rib
ut
io
n
al
lo
w
ed
w
ith
ou
t e
xp
re
ss
a
ut
ho
riz
at
io
n.
ancient practices are supposed to promote chastity, religion,
group identity, cleanli-
ness, health, family values, and marriage goals. This tradition is
prevalent and
deeply embedded in many countries, including Ethiopia, the
Sudan, Somalia, Sierra
Leone, Kenya, Tanzania, Central African Republic, Chad,
Gambia, Liberia, Mali,
Senegal, Eritrea, Ivory Coast, Upper Volta, Mauritania, Nigeria,
Mozambique,
Botswana, Lesotho, and Egypt. Modified versions of the
surgeries are also
performed in Southern Yemen and Musqat-Oman. Tragically,
the usual ways of
performing these surgeries deny women sexual orgasms, cause
significant morbidity
or mortality among women and children, and strain the
overburdened health care
systems in these developing countries. Some refer to these
practices as female cir-
cumcision, but those wishing to stop them increasingly use the
description female
genital mutilation.
Impassioned cultural clashes erupt when people from societies
practicing female
circumcision/genital mutilation settle in other parts of the world
and bring these
rites with them. It is practiced, for example, by Muslim groups
in the Philippines,
Malaysia, Pakistan, Indonesia, Europe, and North America.
Parents may use tradi-
tional practitioners or seek medical facilities to reduce the
morbidity or mortality of
this genital surgery. Some doctors and nurses perform the
procedures for large fees
or because they are concerned about the unhygienic techniques
that traditional
practitioners may use. In the United Kingdom, where about
2,000 girls undergo
the surgery annually, it is classified as child abuse. Other
countries have also classi-
fied it as child abuse, including Canada and France….
Many international agencies like UNICEF, the International
Federation of
Gynecology and Obstetrics, and the World Health Organization
(WHO) openly
condemn and try to stop the practices of female genital
mutilation. Such national
groups as the American Medical Association … have also
denounced these rituals.
Women’s groups from around the world protest these practices
and the lack of
notice they receive….
Most women in cultures practicing female circumcision/genital
mutilation,
when interviewed by investigators from their culture, state that
they do not believe
that such practices deprive them of anything important. They do
not think that
women can have orgasms or that sex can be directly pleasing to
women but assume
that their pleasure comes only from knowing they contribute to
their husbands’
enjoyment. Some critics argue that women who hold such
beliefs cannot be under-
stood to be making an informed choice; they thus condemn this
custom as a form
of oppression….
International discussion, criticisms, and condemnation of
female circumcision/
genital mutilation help activists who struggle to change these
rites that are thor-
oughly entrenched in their own cultures. Not surprisingly,
people who want to con-
tinue these practices resent such criticisms, seeing them as
assaults upon their deeply
embedded and popular cultural traditions.
Underlying intercultural disputes is often a basic moral
controversy: Does
praise or criticism from outside a culture or society have any
moral authority within
it? That is, do the moral judgments from one culture have any
relevance to judg-
ments about what is right or wrong within another culture?
According to some ver-
sions of ethical relativism, to say that something is right means
that it is approved
of in the speaker’s culture; to say that something is wrong
means that it is
LORETTA M. KOPELMAN: FEMALE
CIRCUMCISION/GENITAL MUTILATION 95
©
C
en
ga
ge
L
ea
rn
in
g.
A
ll
rig
ht
s r
es
er
ve
d.
N
o
di
st
rib
ut
io
n
al
lo
w
ed
w
ith
ou
t e
xp
re
ss
a
ut
ho
riz
at
io
n.
disapproved. If this is correct, there is no rational basis for
establishing across
cultures that one set of culturally established moral values is
right and the other
wrong. The right action is one that is approved by the person’s
society or culture,
and the wrong action is one that is disapproved by the person’s
society or culture;
there are moral truths, but they are determined by the norms of
the society. On this
view, then, the cultural approval of female circumcision/genital
mutilation means
that the practice is right; disapproval means that it is wrong.
In contrast to such versions of ethical relativism, other
traditions hold that to
say something is morally right means that the claim can be
defended with reasons
in a certain way. Saying that something is approved (such as
slavery) does not settle
whether it is right, because something can be wrong even when
it is approved by
most people in a culture. Moral judgments do not describe what
is approved but
prescribe what ought to be approved; if worthy of being called
moral or ethical
judgments, they must be defensible with reasons that are
consistent and empirically
defensible. As we shall find, advocates of the practice of female
circumcision/genital
mutilation do not say, “We approve of these rituals, and that is
the end of the
matter.” Rather, they try to defend the practice as useful in
promoting many impor-
tant goals. In fact, however, the practice is inconsistent with
important goals and
values of the cultures in which it is practiced. We find that we
can evaluate some
of the reasons given for performing these rituals and that
despite our cultural differ-
ences about what to value and how to act, we share many
methods of discovery,
evaluation, and explanation. These enable us sometimes
correctly to judge other
cultures, and they us. Moral judgments can be evaluated at least
in terms of their
consistency and their relation to stable evidence, like medical or
scientific findings.
By this means certain moral claims can be challenged, even
where we have different
cultural values, and the practice of female circumcision/genital
mutilation shown to
be wrong. Thus, both intercultural and intracultural discussions,
criticisms, and
condemnation of female genital mutilation as well as support
for activists seeking
to stop the practice can have moral authority, or so I argue.
After considering some of the health hazards of female
circumcision/genital
mutilation, I review the version of ethical relativism that denies
moral authority to
cross-cultural moral judgments. By examining the cultural
reasons used to justify
female circumcision/genital mutilation, I want to show that
many aspects of this
discussion are open to cross-cultural evaluation and
understanding and hence that
this version of ethical relativism fails. After discussing some
anticipated objections,
I conclude that these relativists have a heavy burden of proof to
show why we
cannot make intercultural judgments that have moral force
concerning female geni-
tal mutilation, just as we do concerning such things as
oppression, intolerance,
exploitation, waste, aggression, and torture or imprisonment of
dissidents.
Types of Surgery and Their Health Consequences
Female circumcision/genital mutilation takes three forms. Type
1 circumcision
involves pricking or removing the clitoral hood, or prepuce.
This is the least muti-
lating type and should not preclude sexual orgasms in later life,
unlike other forms.
When this surgery is performed on infants and small children,
however, it may be
difficult to avoid removal of additional tissue, because infants’
genitalia are small,
96 I S IT ALL RELATIVE?
©
C
en
ga
ge
L
ea
rn
in
g.
A
ll
rig
ht
s r
es
er
ve
d.
N
o
di
st
rib
ut
io
n
al
lo
w
ed
w
ith
ou
t e
xp
re
ss
a
ut
ho
riz
at
io
n.
and the tools commonly used are pins, scissors, razors, and
knives. In the southern
Arabian countries of Southern Yemen and Musqat-Oman, Type
1 circumcision is
commonly practiced. In African countries, however, Type 1
circumcision is often
not regarded as a genuine circumcision. Only about 3 percent of
the women in
one east African survey had this type of circumcision, and none
in another where
all the women surveyed had been circumcised.
Type 2, or intermediary, circumcision involves removal of the
clitoris and
most or all of the labia minora. In Type 3 circumcision, or
infibulation, the cli-
toris, labia minora, and parts of the labia majora are removed.
The gaping
wound to the vulva is stitched tightly closed, leaving a tiny
opening so that the
woman can pass urine and menstrual flow. (Type 3 is also
known as Pharaonic
circumcision, suggesting that it has been done since the time of
the pharaohs.)
In some African countries most young girls between infancy and
10 years of age
have Type 3 circumcision. Traditional practitioners often use
sharpened or hot
stones, razors, or knives, frequently without anesthesia or
antibiotics. In many
communities thorns are used to stitch the wound closed, and a
twig is inserted to
keep an opening. The girl’s legs may be bound for a month or
more while the scar
heals….
Almost all girls experience immediate pain following the
surgery. El Dareer
found other immediate consequences, including bleeding,
infection, and shock
correlating with the type of circumcision. The published studies
by investigators
from the regions where these rituals are practiced uniformly
find that women
expressed similar complaints and had similar complications
from female circumci-
sion/genital mutilation: at the site of the surgery, scarring can
make penetration
difficult and intercourse painful; cysts may form, requiring
surgical repairs; a vari-
ety of menstrual problems arise if the opening left is too small
to allow adequate
drainage; fistulas or tears in the bowel or urinary tract are
common, causing
incontinence, which in turn leads to social as well as medical
problems;
maternal-fetal complications and prolonged and obstructed labor
are also well-
established consequences. El Dareer writes, “The result almost
invariably causes
immediate and long-term medical complications, especially at
childbirth. Consum-
mation of marriage is always a difficult experience for both
partners, and marital
problems often result. Psychological disturbances in girls due to
circumcision are
not uncommon.” The operation can also be fatal because of
shock, tetanus, and
septicemia….
Ethical Relativism
Female circumcision/genital mutilation serves as a test case for
some versions of eth-
ical relativism because the practice has widespread approval
within the cultures
where it is practiced and widespread disapproval outside those
cultures. Relativism,
however, means different things to different “academic
cultures.” Indeed one of the
most striking things about the term relativism is that it is used
in so many different
ways, spanning the banal to the highly controversial. In the
Encyclopedia of Philos-
ophy, Richard D. Brandt writes, “Contemporary philosophers
generally apply the
term [ethical relativism] to some position they disagree with or
consider absurd, sel-
dom to their own views; social scientists, however, often
classify themselves as
LORETTA M. KOPELMAN: FEMALE
CIRCUMCISION/GENITAL MUTILATION 97
©
C
en
ga
ge
L
ea
rn
in
g.
A
ll
rig
ht
s r
es
er
ve
d.
N
o
di
st
rib
ut
io
n
al
lo
w
ed
w
ith
ou
t e
xp
re
ss
a
ut
ho
riz
at
io
n.
relativists.” Philosophers and those in religious studies often
distinguish two ways
to understand relativism: one is controversial, and the other is
not. The noncontro-
versial, descriptive version, often called descriptive relativism,
is the view that peo-
ple from different cultures do act differently and have distinct
norms. Social
scientists often work as descriptive relativists: they try to
understand cultural differ-
ences and look for any underlying similarities. Those studying
or criticizing female
circumcision/genital mutilation, of course, recognize that we do
act differently and
have different values. But descriptions about how or in what
way we are different
do not entail statements about how we ought to act.
The controversial position, called ethical relativism, is that an
action is right if
it is approved in a person’s culture and wrong if it is
disapproved. Another version
of this controversial view is that to say something is right
means it has cultural
approval; to say something is wrong means it has cultural
disapproval. According
to this view, which some call cultural relativism, there is no
way to evaluate moral
claims across cultures; positions taken by international groups
like the World
Health Organization merely express a cluster of particular
societal opinions and
have no moral standing in other cultures. On this view it is
incoherent to claim
that something is wrong in a culture yet approved, or right yet
disapproved; people
can express moral judgments about things done in their own or
other cultures, but
they are expressing only their cultural point of view, not one
that has moral author-
ity in another culture….
I would begin by observing that we seem to share methods of
discovery,
evaluation, negotiation, and explanation that can be used to help
assess moral judg-
ments. For example, we agree how to evaluate methods and
research in science,
engineering, and medicine, and on how to translate, debate,
deliberate, criticize,
negotiate, and use technology. To do these things, however, we
must first have
agreed to some extent on how to distinguish good and bad
methods and research
in science, engineering, and medicine, and what constitutes a
good or bad transla-
tion, debate, deliberation, criticism, negotiation, or use of
technology. These shared
methods can be used to help evaluate moral judgments from one
culture to another
in a way that sometimes has moral authority. An example of a
belief that could be
evaluated by stable medical evidence is the assertion by people
in some regions that
the infant’s “death could result if, during delivery, the baby’s
head touches the
clitoris.” In addition, some moral claims can be evaluated in
terms of their coher-
ence. It seems incompatible to promote maternal-fetal health as
a good and also to
advocate avoidable practices known to cause serious perinatal
and neonatal
infections.
We need not rank values similarly with people in another
culture, or our own,
to have coherent discussions about their consistency,
consequences, or factual pre-
suppositions. That is, even if some moral or ethical (I use these
terms interchange-
ably) judgments express unique cultural norms, they may still
be morally evaluated
by another culture on the basis of their logical consistency and
their coherence with
stable and cross-culturally accepted empirical information. In
addition, we seem to
share some moral values, goals, and judgments such as those
about the evils of
unnecessary suffering and lost opportunities, the need for food
and shelter, the
duty to help children, and the goods of promoting public health
and personal
well-being. Let us consider therefore, the reasons given by men
and women
98 I S IT ALL RELATIVE?
©
C
en
ga
ge
L
ea
rn
in
g.
A
ll
rig
ht
s r
es
er
ve
d.
N
o
di
st
rib
ut
io
n
al
lo
w
ed
w
ith
ou
t e
xp
re
ss
a
ut
ho
riz
at
io
n.
who practice female circumcision/genital mutilation in their
communities. The
information presented herein is based upon studies done by
investigators who
come from these cultures, some of whom had this ritual surgery
as children (El
Dareer is one such investigator). We can examine whether these
reasons allow peo-
ple from other cultures any way of entering the debate based
upon such considera-
tions as consistency or stable medical findings.
Reasons Given for Female Circumcision/Genital Mutilation
According to four independent series of studies conducted by
investigators from
countries where female circumcision is widely practiced, the
primary reasons given
for performing this ritual surgery are that it (1) meets a
religious requirement, (2)
preserves group identity, (3) helps to maintain cleanliness and
health, (4) preserves
virginity and family honor and prevents immorality, and (5)
furthers marriage goals
including greater sexual pleasure for men.
El Dareer conducted her studies in the Sudan, Dr. Olayinka
Koso-Thomas in
and around Sierra Leone, and Raquiya Haji Dualeh Abdalla and
Daphne Williams
Ntiri in Somalia. They argue that the reasons for continuing this
practice in their
respective countries float on a sea of false beliefs, beliefs that
thrive because of a
lack of education and open discussion about reproduction and
sexuality. Insofar
as intercultural methods for evaluating factual and logical
statements exist, people
from other cultures should at least be able to understand these
inconsistencies or
mistaken factual beliefs and use them as a basis for making
some judgments having
intercultural moral authority.
First, according to these studies the main reason given for
performing female
circumcision/genital mutilation is that it is regarded as a
religious requirement.
Most of the people practicing this ritual are Muslims, but it is
not a practice
required by the Koran. El Dareer writes: “Circumcision of
women is not explicitly
enjoined in the Koran, but there are two implicit sayings of the
Prophet
Mohammed: ‘Circumcision is an ordinance in men and an
embellishment in
women’ and, reportedly Mohammed said to Om Attiya, a woman
who circumcised
girls in El Medina, ‘Do not go deep. It is more illuminating to
the face and more
enjoyable to the husband.’ Another version says, ‘Reduce but do
not destroy. This
is enjoyable to the woman and preferable to the man.’ But there
is nothing in the
Koran to suggest that the Prophet commanded that women be
circumcised. He
advised that it was important to both sexes that very little
should be taken.” Female
circumcision/genital mutilation, moreover, is not practiced in
the spiritual center of
Islam, Saudi Arabia. Another reason for questioning this as a
Muslim practice is
that clitoridectomy and infibulation predate Islam, going back
to the time of the
pharaohs….
Second, many argue that the practice helps to preserve group
identity. When
Christian colonialists in Kenya introduced laws opposing the
practice of female cir-
cumcision in the 1930s, African leader Kenyatta expressed a
view still popular
today: “This operation is still regarded as the very essence of an
institution which
has enormous educational, social, moral and religious
implications, quite apart
from the operation itself. For the present, it is impossible for a
member of the
[Kikuyu] tribe to imagine an initiation without clitoridectomy
the abolition of
LORETTA M. KOPELMAN: FEMALE
CIRCUMCISION/GENITAL MUTILATION 99
©
C
en
ga
ge
L
ea
rn
in
g.
A
ll
rig
ht
s r
es
er
ve
d.
N
o
di
st
rib
ut
io
n
al
lo
w
ed
w
ith
ou
t e
xp
re
ss
a
ut
ho
riz
at
io
n.
IRUA [the ritual operation] will destroy the tribal symbol which
identifies the age
group and prevent the Kikuyu from perpetuating that spirit of
collectivism and
national solidarity which they have been able to maintain from
time immemorial.”
In addition, the practice is of social and economic importance to
older women who
are paid for performing the rituals….
Drs. Koso-Thomas, El Dareer, and Abdalla agree that people in
these countries
support female circumcision as a good practice, but only
because they do not
understand that it is a leading cause of sickness or even death
for girls, mothers,
and infants, and a major cause of infertility, infection, and
maternal-fetal and mari-
tal complications. They conclude that these facts are not
confronted because these
societies do not speak openly of such matters. Abdalla writes,
“There is no longer
any reason, given the present state of progress in science, to
tolerate confusion and
ignorance about reproduction and women’s sexuality.” Female
circumcision/genital
mutilation is intended to honor women as male circumcision
honors men, and
members of cultures where the surgery is practiced are shocked
by the analogy of
clitoridectomy to removal of the penis….
Third, the belief that the practice advances health and hygiene
is incompatible
with stable data from surveys done in these cultures, where
female circumcision/
genital mutilation has been linked to mortality or morbidity
such as shock, infertil-
ity, infections, incontinence, maternal-fetal complications, and
protracted labor….
Fourth, investigators found that circumcision is thought
necessary in these
cultures to preserve virginity and family honor and to prevent
immorality. Type 3
circumcision is used to keep women from having sexual
intercourse before marriage
and conceiving illegitimate children. In addition, many believe
that Types 2 and 3
circumcision must be done because uncircumcised women have
excessive and
uncontrollable sexual drives. El Dareer, however, believes that
this view is not con-
sistently held—that women in the Sudan are respected and that
Sudanese men
would be shocked to apply this sometimes-held cultural view to
members of their
own families. This reason also seems incompatible with the
general view, which
investigators found was held by both men and women in these
cultures, that sex
cannot be pleasant for women. In addition, female
circumcision/genital mutilation
offers no foolproof way to promote chastity and can even lead
to promiscuity
because it does not diminish desire or libido even where it
makes orgasms impossi-
ble. Some women continually seek experiences with new sexual
partners because
they are left unsatisfied in their sexual encounters. Moreover,
some pretend to be
virgins by getting stitched up tightly again….
Fifth, interviewers found that people practicing female
circumcision/genital
mutilation believe that it furthers marriage goals, including
greater sexual pleasure
for men. To survive economically, women in these cultures
must marry, and they
will not be acceptable marriage partners unless they have
undergone this ritual
surgery. It is a curse, for example, to say that someone is the
child of an uncir-
cumcised woman. The widely held belief that infibulation
enhances women’s
beauty and men’s sexual pleasure makes it difficult for women
who wish to marry
to resist this practice. Some men from these cultures, however,
report that they
enjoy sex more with uncircumcised women. Furthermore,
female circumcision/
genital mutilation is inconsistent with the established goals of
some of these cultures
because it is a leading cause of disability and contributes to the
high mortality rate
100 I S IT ALL RELATIVE?
©
C
en
ga
ge
L
ea
rn
in
g.
A
ll
rig
ht
s r
es
er
ve
d.
N
o
di
st
rib
ut
io
n
al
lo
w
ed
w
ith
ou
t e
xp
re
ss
a
ut
ho
riz
at
io
n.
among mothers, fetuses, and children. Far from promoting the
goals of marriage, it
causes difficulty in consummating marriage, infertility,
prolonged and obstructed
labor, and morbidity and mortality.
Criticisms of Ethical Relativism
Examination of the debate concerning female circumcision
suggests several conclu-
sions about the extent to which people from outside a culture
can understand or
contribute to moral debates within it in a way that has moral
force. First, the fact
that a culture’s moral and religious views are often intertwined
with beliefs that are
open to rational and empirical evaluation can be a basis of
cross-cultural examina-
tion and intercultural moral criticism. Beliefs that the practice
enhances fertility and
promotes health, that women cannot have orgasms, and that
allowing the baby’s
head to touch the clitoris during delivery causes death to the
baby are incompatible
with stable medical data. Thus an opening is allowed for
genuine cross-cultural dis-
cussion or criticism of the practice.
Some claims about female circumcision/genital mutilation,
however, are not
as easily open to cross-cultural understanding. For example,
cultures practicing
the Type 3 surgery, infibulation, believe that it makes women
more beautiful.
For those who are not from these cultures, this belief is difficult
to understand,
especially when surveys show that many women in these
cultures, when inter-
viewed, attribute to infibulation their keloid scars, urine
retention, pelvic infec-
tions, puerperal sepsis, and obstetrical problems. Koso-Thomas
writes: “None of
the reasons put forward in favor of circumcision have any real
scientific or logical
basis. It is surprising that aesthetics and the maintenance of
cleanliness are
advanced as grounds for female circumcision. The scars could
hardly be thought
of as contributing to beauty. The hardened scar and stump
usually seen where the
clitoris should be, or in the case of the infibulated vulva, taut
skin with an ugly
long scar down the middle, present a horrifying picture.” Thus
not everyone in
these cultures believes that these rituals enhance beauty; some
find such claims dif-
ficult to understand.
Second, the debate over female circumcision/genital mutilation
illustrates
another difficulty for defenders of this version of ethical
relativism concerning the
problem of differentiating cultures. People who brought the
practice of female cir-
cumcision/genital mutilation with them when they moved to
another nation still
claim to be a distinct cultural group. Some who moved to
Britain, for example,
resent the interference in their culture represented by laws that
condemn the prac-
tice as child abuse. If ethical relativists are to appeal to cultural
approval in making
the final determination of what is good or bad, right or wrong,
they must tell us
how to distinguish one culture from another.
How exactly do we count or separate cultures? A society is not
a nation-state,
because some social groups have distinctive identities within
nations. If we do not
define societies as nations, however, how do we distinguish
among cultural groups,
for example, well enough to say that an action is child abuse in
one culture but not
in another? Subcultures in nations typically overlap and have
many variations. Even
if we could count cultural groups well enough to say exactly
how to distinguish one
culture from another, how and when would this be relevant?
How big or old or
LORETTA M. KOPELMAN: FEMALE
CIRCUMCISION/GENITAL MUTILATION 101
©
C
en
ga
ge
L
ea
rn
in
g.
A
ll
rig
ht
s r
es
er
ve
d.
N
o
di
st
rib
ut
io
n
al
lo
w
ed
w
ith
ou
t e
xp
re
ss
a
ut
ho
riz
at
io
n.
vital must a culture, subculture, group, or cult be in order to be
recognized as a
society whose moral distinctions are self-contained and self-
justifying?
A related problem is that there can be passionate disagreement,
ambivalence, or
rapid changes within a culture or group over what is approved
or disapproved.
According to ethical relativism, where there is significant
disagreement within a cul-
ture there is no way to determine what is right or wrong. But
what disagreement is
significant?
Third, despite some clear disagreement such as that over the
rightness of female
circumcision/genital mutilation, people from different parts of
the world share com-
mon goals like the desirability of promoting people’s health,
happiness, opportu-
nities, and cooperation, and the wisdom of stopping war,
pollution, oppression,
torture, and exploitation. These common goals make us a world
community, and
using shared methods of reasoning and evaluation, we can
discuss how they are
understood or how well they are implemented in different parts
of our world com-
munity. We can use these shared goals to assess whether female
circumcision/genital
mutilation is more like respect or oppression, more like
enhancement or diminish-
ment of opportunities, or more like pleasure or torture. Another
way to express this
is to say that we should recognize universal human rights or be
respectful of each
other as persons capable of reasoned discourse.
Fourth, this version of ethical relativism, if consistently held,
leads to the abhor-
rent conclusion that we cannot make intercultural judgments
with moral force
about societies that start wars, practice torture, or exploit and
oppress other
groups; as long as these activities are approved in the society
that does them, they
are allegedly right. Yet the world community believed that it
was making a cross-
cultural judgment with moral force when it criticized the
Communist Chinese gov-
ernment for crushing a pro-democracy student protest rally, the
South Africans for
upholding apartheid, the Soviets for using psychiatry to
suppress dissent, and the
Bosnian Serbs for carrying out the siege of Sarajevo.
And the judgment was expressed without anyone’s ascertaining
whether the
respective actions had wide-spread approval in those countries.
In each case, repre-
sentatives from the criticized society usually said something
like, “You don’t
understand why this is morally justified in our culture even if it
would not be
in your society.” If ethical relativism were convincing, these
responses ought to be
as well.
Relativists who want to defend sound social cross-cultural and
moral judg-
ments about the value of freedom and human rights in other
cultures seem to have
two choices. On the one hand, if they agree that some cross-
cultural norms have
moral authority, they should also agree that some intercultural
judgments about
female circumcision/genital mutilation may have moral
authority. Some relativists
take this route …, thereby abandoning the version of ethical
relativism being criti-
cized herein. On the other hand, if they defend this version of
ethical relativism yet
make cross-cultural moral judgments about the importance of
values like tolerance,
group benefit, and the survival of cultures, they will have to
admit to an inconsis-
tency in their arguments. For example, anthropologist Scheper-
Hughes… advocates
tolerance of other cultural value systems; she fails to see that
she is saying that tol-
erance between cultures is right and that this is a cross-cultural
moral judgment
using a moral norm (tolerance). Similarly, relativists who say it
is wrong to
102 I S IT ALL RELATIVE?
©
C
en
ga
ge
L
ea
rn
in
g.
A
ll
rig
ht
s r
es
er
ve
d.
N
o
di
st
rib
ut
io
n
al
lo
w
ed
w
ith
ou
t e
xp
re
ss
a
ut
ho
riz
at
io
n.
eliminate rituals that give meaning to other cultures are also
inconsistent in making
a judgment that presumes to have genuine cross-cultural moral
authority.
The burden of proof, then, is upon defenders of this version of
ethical relativ-
ism to show why we cannot do something we think we
sometimes do very well,
namely, engage in intercultural moral discussion, cooperation,
or criticism and
give support to people whose welfare or rights are in jeopardy
in other cultures. In
addition, defenders of ethical relativism need to explain how we
can justify the
actions of international professional societies that take moral
stands in adopting
policy. For example, international groups may take moral stands
that advocate
fighting pandemics, stopping wars, halting oppression,
promoting health education,
or eliminating poverty, and they seem to have moral authority in
some cases. Some
might respond that our professional groups are themselves
cultures of a sort. But
this response raises the already discussed problem of how to
individuate a culture
or society.
Objections
Some standard rejoinders are made to criticism of relativism,
but they leave
untouched the arguments against the particular version of
ethical relativism dis-
cussed herein. First, some defenders argue that cross-cultural
moral judgments per-
petuate the evils of absolutism, cultural dogmatism, or cultural
imperialism. People
rarely admit to such transgressions, often enlisting medicine,
religion, science, or the
“pure light of reason” to arrive at an allegedly impartial,
disinterested, and justified
conclusion that they should “enlighten” and “educate” the
“natives,” “savages,” or
“infidels.” Anthropologist Scheper-Hughes writes, “I don’t
‘like’ the idea of clitori-
dectomy any better than any other woman I know. But I like
even less the western
‘voices of reason’ [imposing their views].” Scheper-Hughes and
others suggest that,
in arguing that we can make moral judgments across cultures,
we are thereby
claiming a particular culture knows best and has the right to
impose its allegedly
superior knowledge on other cultures.
Claiming that we can sometimes judge another culture in a way
that has moral
force, however, does not entail that one culture is always right,
that absolutism is
legitimate, or that we can impose our beliefs on others.
Relativists sometimes
respond that even if this is not a strict logical consequence, it is
a practical result.
Sherwin writes, “Many social scientists have endorsed versions
of relativism pre-
cisely out of their sense that the alternative promotes cultural
dominance. They
may be making a philosophical error in drawing that conclusion,
but I do not
think that they are making an empirical one.”…
The version of ethical relativism we have been considering,
however, does
not avoid cultural imperialism. To say that an act is right, on
this view, means
that it has cultural approval, including acts of war, oppression,
enslavement,
aggression, exploitation, racism, or torture. On this view, the
disapproval of
other cultures is irrelevant in determining whether these acts are
right or wrong;
accordingly, the disapproval of people in other cultures, even
victims of war,
oppression, enslavement, aggression, exploitation, racism, or
torture, does not
count in deciding what is right or wrong except in their own
culture. This view
thus leads to abhorrent conclusions. It entails not only the
affirmation that
LORETTA M. KOPELMAN: FEMALE
CIRCUMCISION/GENITAL MUTILATION 103
©
C
en
ga
ge
L
ea
rn
in
g.
A
ll
rig
ht
s r
es
er
ve
d.
N
o
di
st
rib
ut
io
n
al
lo
w
ed
w
ith
ou
t e
xp
re
ss
a
ut
ho
riz
at
io
n.
female circumcision/genital mutilation is right in cultures where
it is approved
but the affirmation that anything with wide social approval is
right, including
slavery, war, discrimination, oppression, racism, and torture. If
defenders of the
version of ethical relativism criticized herein are consistent,
they will dismiss any
objections by people in other cultures as merely an expression
of their own cul-
tural preferences, having no moral standing whatsoever in the
society that is
engaging in the acts in question.
Defenders of ethical relativism must explain why we should
adopt a view lead-
ing to such abhorrent conclusions. They may respond that
cultures sometimes over-
lap and hence that the victims’ protests within or between
cultures ought to count.
But this response raises two further difficulties for defenders of
ethical relativism.
First, it is inconsistent if it means that the views of people in
other cultures have
moral standing and oppressors ought to consider the views of
victims. Such judg-
ments are inconsistent with this version of ethical relativism
because they are
cross-cultural judgments with moral authority. The second
difficulty with this
defense, also discussed above, is that it raises the problem of
how we differentiate
a culture or society.
Second, some defenders of ethical relativism argue that we
cannot know
enough about another culture to make any cross-cultural moral
judgments. We can-
not really understand another society well enough to criticize it,
they claim, because
our feelings, concepts, or ways of reasoning are too different;
our so-called ordinary
moral views about what is permissible are determined by our
upbringing and envir-
onments to such a degree that they cannot be transferred to
other cultures. There
are two ways to understand this objection. The first is that
nothing counts as
understanding another culture except being raised in it. If that is
what is meant,
then the objection is valid in a trivial way. But it does not
address the important
issue of whether we can comprehend well enough to make
relevant moral distinc-
tions or engage in critical ethical discussions about the
universal human right to be
free of oppression.
The second, and nontrivial, way to understand this objection is
that we cannot
understand another society well enough to justify claiming to
know what is right or
wrong in that society or even to raise moral questions about
what enhances or
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx
C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx

More Related Content

Similar to C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx

Morality Essay Topics.pdf
Morality Essay Topics.pdfMorality Essay Topics.pdf
Morality Essay Topics.pdfAlicia Galindo
 
Liu Lingzhi LiuEAD IIPaul Hufker September 16th Universa.docx
Liu Lingzhi LiuEAD IIPaul Hufker September 16th Universa.docxLiu Lingzhi LiuEAD IIPaul Hufker September 16th Universa.docx
Liu Lingzhi LiuEAD IIPaul Hufker September 16th Universa.docxcroysierkathey
 
Respect For Life Essay. 005 Essays On Respect Essay Example Adoption Thatsnotus
Respect For Life Essay. 005 Essays On Respect Essay Example Adoption  ThatsnotusRespect For Life Essay. 005 Essays On Respect Essay Example Adoption  Thatsnotus
Respect For Life Essay. 005 Essays On Respect Essay Example Adoption ThatsnotusBeth Retzlaff
 
Sujay Religion in the twenty-first century and beyond FINAL FINAL FINAL.pdf
Sujay Religion in the twenty-first century and beyond FINAL FINAL FINAL.pdfSujay Religion in the twenty-first century and beyond FINAL FINAL FINAL.pdf
Sujay Religion in the twenty-first century and beyond FINAL FINAL FINAL.pdfSujay Rao Mandavilli
 
American History Essay Questions. US History Essay / Essays / History, Cultur...
American History Essay Questions. US History Essay / Essays / History, Cultur...American History Essay Questions. US History Essay / Essays / History, Cultur...
American History Essay Questions. US History Essay / Essays / History, Cultur...Amanda Stephens
 
Junior Thesis - Submitted for Publishing___
Junior Thesis - Submitted for Publishing___Junior Thesis - Submitted for Publishing___
Junior Thesis - Submitted for Publishing___Alex Amari
 
Week 9 Cultural Relativism.pptx
Week 9 Cultural Relativism.pptxWeek 9 Cultural Relativism.pptx
Week 9 Cultural Relativism.pptxArvinCruz19
 
CHARLES W. CHESNUTT LIBRARY ELECTRONIC RESERVE COLLECTI.docx
CHARLES W. CHESNUTT LIBRARY  ELECTRONIC RESERVE COLLECTI.docxCHARLES W. CHESNUTT LIBRARY  ELECTRONIC RESERVE COLLECTI.docx
CHARLES W. CHESNUTT LIBRARY ELECTRONIC RESERVE COLLECTI.docxbissacr
 
Cosmology Similar to a culture but emphasizes howwhat count.docx
Cosmology Similar to a culture but emphasizes howwhat count.docxCosmology Similar to a culture but emphasizes howwhat count.docx
Cosmology Similar to a culture but emphasizes howwhat count.docxfaithxdunce63732
 
Democracy Essay. Democracy and Development - Free Essay Example PapersOwl.com
Democracy Essay. Democracy and Development - Free Essay Example  PapersOwl.comDemocracy Essay. Democracy and Development - Free Essay Example  PapersOwl.com
Democracy Essay. Democracy and Development - Free Essay Example PapersOwl.comKimberly Balentine
 
Religion in Conservation and Management: A Durkheimian View
Religion in Conservation and Management: A Durkheimian ViewReligion in Conservation and Management: A Durkheimian View
Religion in Conservation and Management: A Durkheimian Viewliasuprapti
 

Similar to C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx (12)

Morality Essay Topics.pdf
Morality Essay Topics.pdfMorality Essay Topics.pdf
Morality Essay Topics.pdf
 
Liu Lingzhi LiuEAD IIPaul Hufker September 16th Universa.docx
Liu Lingzhi LiuEAD IIPaul Hufker September 16th Universa.docxLiu Lingzhi LiuEAD IIPaul Hufker September 16th Universa.docx
Liu Lingzhi LiuEAD IIPaul Hufker September 16th Universa.docx
 
lesson 1 UCSP.pptx
lesson 1 UCSP.pptxlesson 1 UCSP.pptx
lesson 1 UCSP.pptx
 
Respect For Life Essay. 005 Essays On Respect Essay Example Adoption Thatsnotus
Respect For Life Essay. 005 Essays On Respect Essay Example Adoption  ThatsnotusRespect For Life Essay. 005 Essays On Respect Essay Example Adoption  Thatsnotus
Respect For Life Essay. 005 Essays On Respect Essay Example Adoption Thatsnotus
 
Sujay Religion in the twenty-first century and beyond FINAL FINAL FINAL.pdf
Sujay Religion in the twenty-first century and beyond FINAL FINAL FINAL.pdfSujay Religion in the twenty-first century and beyond FINAL FINAL FINAL.pdf
Sujay Religion in the twenty-first century and beyond FINAL FINAL FINAL.pdf
 
American History Essay Questions. US History Essay / Essays / History, Cultur...
American History Essay Questions. US History Essay / Essays / History, Cultur...American History Essay Questions. US History Essay / Essays / History, Cultur...
American History Essay Questions. US History Essay / Essays / History, Cultur...
 
Junior Thesis - Submitted for Publishing___
Junior Thesis - Submitted for Publishing___Junior Thesis - Submitted for Publishing___
Junior Thesis - Submitted for Publishing___
 
Week 9 Cultural Relativism.pptx
Week 9 Cultural Relativism.pptxWeek 9 Cultural Relativism.pptx
Week 9 Cultural Relativism.pptx
 
CHARLES W. CHESNUTT LIBRARY ELECTRONIC RESERVE COLLECTI.docx
CHARLES W. CHESNUTT LIBRARY  ELECTRONIC RESERVE COLLECTI.docxCHARLES W. CHESNUTT LIBRARY  ELECTRONIC RESERVE COLLECTI.docx
CHARLES W. CHESNUTT LIBRARY ELECTRONIC RESERVE COLLECTI.docx
 
Cosmology Similar to a culture but emphasizes howwhat count.docx
Cosmology Similar to a culture but emphasizes howwhat count.docxCosmology Similar to a culture but emphasizes howwhat count.docx
Cosmology Similar to a culture but emphasizes howwhat count.docx
 
Democracy Essay. Democracy and Development - Free Essay Example PapersOwl.com
Democracy Essay. Democracy and Development - Free Essay Example  PapersOwl.comDemocracy Essay. Democracy and Development - Free Essay Example  PapersOwl.com
Democracy Essay. Democracy and Development - Free Essay Example PapersOwl.com
 
Religion in Conservation and Management: A Durkheimian View
Religion in Conservation and Management: A Durkheimian ViewReligion in Conservation and Management: A Durkheimian View
Religion in Conservation and Management: A Durkheimian View
 

More from clairbycraft

Calculus Quiz 2 (Derivatives)Covers Units 9-13. This is a 10 quest.docx
Calculus Quiz 2 (Derivatives)Covers Units 9-13. This is a 10 quest.docxCalculus Quiz 2 (Derivatives)Covers Units 9-13. This is a 10 quest.docx
Calculus Quiz 2 (Derivatives)Covers Units 9-13. This is a 10 quest.docxclairbycraft
 
Calculus IDirections (10 pts. each) Answer each of the followin.docx
Calculus IDirections (10 pts. each) Answer each of the followin.docxCalculus IDirections (10 pts. each) Answer each of the followin.docx
Calculus IDirections (10 pts. each) Answer each of the followin.docxclairbycraft
 
Cadence Publishes Comprehensive Book onMixed-Signal Method.docx
Cadence Publishes Comprehensive Book onMixed-Signal Method.docxCadence Publishes Comprehensive Book onMixed-Signal Method.docx
Cadence Publishes Comprehensive Book onMixed-Signal Method.docxclairbycraft
 
Calculate the energy in the form of heat (in kJ) required to change .docx
Calculate the energy in the form of heat (in kJ) required to change .docxCalculate the energy in the form of heat (in kJ) required to change .docx
Calculate the energy in the form of heat (in kJ) required to change .docxclairbycraft
 
CAHIIM Competencies Assessed Subdomain VI.D. Human Resources Ma.docx
CAHIIM Competencies Assessed Subdomain VI.D. Human Resources Ma.docxCAHIIM Competencies Assessed Subdomain VI.D. Human Resources Ma.docx
CAHIIM Competencies Assessed Subdomain VI.D. Human Resources Ma.docxclairbycraft
 
C8-1 CASE STUDY 8 CARLSON COMPANIES STORAGE SOLUT.docx
C8-1 CASE STUDY 8    CARLSON COMPANIES STORAGE SOLUT.docxC8-1 CASE STUDY 8    CARLSON COMPANIES STORAGE SOLUT.docx
C8-1 CASE STUDY 8 CARLSON COMPANIES STORAGE SOLUT.docxclairbycraft
 
Caffeine intake in children in the United States and 10-ytre.docx
Caffeine intake in children in the United States and 10-ytre.docxCaffeine intake in children in the United States and 10-ytre.docx
Caffeine intake in children in the United States and 10-ytre.docxclairbycraft
 
Cabbage patch hip dance move, The running man hip hop dance move, th.docx
Cabbage patch hip dance move, The running man hip hop dance move, th.docxCabbage patch hip dance move, The running man hip hop dance move, th.docx
Cabbage patch hip dance move, The running man hip hop dance move, th.docxclairbycraft
 
CA4Leading TeamsAre we a teamHi, my name is Jenny .docx
CA4Leading TeamsAre we a teamHi, my name is Jenny .docxCA4Leading TeamsAre we a teamHi, my name is Jenny .docx
CA4Leading TeamsAre we a teamHi, my name is Jenny .docxclairbycraft
 
C7-1 CASE STUDY 7 DATA CENTER CONSOLIDATION AT GUARDI.docx
C7-1 CASE STUDY 7  DATA CENTER CONSOLIDATION AT GUARDI.docxC7-1 CASE STUDY 7  DATA CENTER CONSOLIDATION AT GUARDI.docx
C7-1 CASE STUDY 7 DATA CENTER CONSOLIDATION AT GUARDI.docxclairbycraft
 
C9-1 CASE STUDY 9 ST. LUKES HEALTH CARE SYSTEM Hospitals have been .docx
C9-1 CASE STUDY 9 ST. LUKES HEALTH CARE SYSTEM Hospitals have been .docxC9-1 CASE STUDY 9 ST. LUKES HEALTH CARE SYSTEM Hospitals have been .docx
C9-1 CASE STUDY 9 ST. LUKES HEALTH CARE SYSTEM Hospitals have been .docxclairbycraft
 
C9-1 CASE STUDY 9 ST. LUKES HEALTH CARE SYSTEM .docx
C9-1 CASE STUDY 9   ST. LUKES HEALTH CARE SYSTEM .docxC9-1 CASE STUDY 9   ST. LUKES HEALTH CARE SYSTEM .docx
C9-1 CASE STUDY 9 ST. LUKES HEALTH CARE SYSTEM .docxclairbycraft
 
C361 TASK 22C361 TASK 22C361 Task 2WGUEv.docx
C361 TASK 22C361 TASK 22C361 Task 2WGUEv.docxC361 TASK 22C361 TASK 22C361 Task 2WGUEv.docx
C361 TASK 22C361 TASK 22C361 Task 2WGUEv.docxclairbycraft
 
C6-1 CASE STUDY 6 CHEVRON’S INFRASTRUCTURE EVOLUT.docx
C6-1 CASE STUDY 6 CHEVRON’S INFRASTRUCTURE  EVOLUT.docxC6-1 CASE STUDY 6 CHEVRON’S INFRASTRUCTURE  EVOLUT.docx
C6-1 CASE STUDY 6 CHEVRON’S INFRASTRUCTURE EVOLUT.docxclairbycraft
 
C125C126 FORMAL LAB REPORTFORMAL LAB REPORT, GeneralA f.docx
C125C126 FORMAL LAB REPORTFORMAL LAB REPORT, GeneralA f.docxC125C126 FORMAL LAB REPORTFORMAL LAB REPORT, GeneralA f.docx
C125C126 FORMAL LAB REPORTFORMAL LAB REPORT, GeneralA f.docxclairbycraft
 
C10-1 CASE STUDY 10 CHOICE HOTELS INTERNATIONAL .docx
C10-1 CASE STUDY 10     CHOICE HOTELS INTERNATIONAL .docxC10-1 CASE STUDY 10     CHOICE HOTELS INTERNATIONAL .docx
C10-1 CASE STUDY 10 CHOICE HOTELS INTERNATIONAL .docxclairbycraft
 
C11-1 CASE STUDY 11 CLOUD COMPUTING (IN)SECURITY .docx
C11-1 CASE STUDY 11   CLOUD COMPUTING (IN)SECURITY .docxC11-1 CASE STUDY 11   CLOUD COMPUTING (IN)SECURITY .docx
C11-1 CASE STUDY 11 CLOUD COMPUTING (IN)SECURITY .docxclairbycraft
 
C1-1 CASE STUDY 1 UNIFIED COMMUNICATIONS AT BOEING .docx
C1-1 CASE STUDY 1  UNIFIED COMMUNICATIONS AT BOEING .docxC1-1 CASE STUDY 1  UNIFIED COMMUNICATIONS AT BOEING .docx
C1-1 CASE STUDY 1 UNIFIED COMMUNICATIONS AT BOEING .docxclairbycraft
 
C09 07222011 101525 Page 88IT leader who had just been.docx
C09 07222011 101525 Page 88IT leader who had just been.docxC09 07222011 101525 Page 88IT leader who had just been.docx
C09 07222011 101525 Page 88IT leader who had just been.docxclairbycraft
 
C053GXML 10192012 214425 Page 131cC H A P T E R.docx
C053GXML 10192012 214425 Page 131cC H A P T E R.docxC053GXML 10192012 214425 Page 131cC H A P T E R.docx
C053GXML 10192012 214425 Page 131cC H A P T E R.docxclairbycraft
 

More from clairbycraft (20)

Calculus Quiz 2 (Derivatives)Covers Units 9-13. This is a 10 quest.docx
Calculus Quiz 2 (Derivatives)Covers Units 9-13. This is a 10 quest.docxCalculus Quiz 2 (Derivatives)Covers Units 9-13. This is a 10 quest.docx
Calculus Quiz 2 (Derivatives)Covers Units 9-13. This is a 10 quest.docx
 
Calculus IDirections (10 pts. each) Answer each of the followin.docx
Calculus IDirections (10 pts. each) Answer each of the followin.docxCalculus IDirections (10 pts. each) Answer each of the followin.docx
Calculus IDirections (10 pts. each) Answer each of the followin.docx
 
Cadence Publishes Comprehensive Book onMixed-Signal Method.docx
Cadence Publishes Comprehensive Book onMixed-Signal Method.docxCadence Publishes Comprehensive Book onMixed-Signal Method.docx
Cadence Publishes Comprehensive Book onMixed-Signal Method.docx
 
Calculate the energy in the form of heat (in kJ) required to change .docx
Calculate the energy in the form of heat (in kJ) required to change .docxCalculate the energy in the form of heat (in kJ) required to change .docx
Calculate the energy in the form of heat (in kJ) required to change .docx
 
CAHIIM Competencies Assessed Subdomain VI.D. Human Resources Ma.docx
CAHIIM Competencies Assessed Subdomain VI.D. Human Resources Ma.docxCAHIIM Competencies Assessed Subdomain VI.D. Human Resources Ma.docx
CAHIIM Competencies Assessed Subdomain VI.D. Human Resources Ma.docx
 
C8-1 CASE STUDY 8 CARLSON COMPANIES STORAGE SOLUT.docx
C8-1 CASE STUDY 8    CARLSON COMPANIES STORAGE SOLUT.docxC8-1 CASE STUDY 8    CARLSON COMPANIES STORAGE SOLUT.docx
C8-1 CASE STUDY 8 CARLSON COMPANIES STORAGE SOLUT.docx
 
Caffeine intake in children in the United States and 10-ytre.docx
Caffeine intake in children in the United States and 10-ytre.docxCaffeine intake in children in the United States and 10-ytre.docx
Caffeine intake in children in the United States and 10-ytre.docx
 
Cabbage patch hip dance move, The running man hip hop dance move, th.docx
Cabbage patch hip dance move, The running man hip hop dance move, th.docxCabbage patch hip dance move, The running man hip hop dance move, th.docx
Cabbage patch hip dance move, The running man hip hop dance move, th.docx
 
CA4Leading TeamsAre we a teamHi, my name is Jenny .docx
CA4Leading TeamsAre we a teamHi, my name is Jenny .docxCA4Leading TeamsAre we a teamHi, my name is Jenny .docx
CA4Leading TeamsAre we a teamHi, my name is Jenny .docx
 
C7-1 CASE STUDY 7 DATA CENTER CONSOLIDATION AT GUARDI.docx
C7-1 CASE STUDY 7  DATA CENTER CONSOLIDATION AT GUARDI.docxC7-1 CASE STUDY 7  DATA CENTER CONSOLIDATION AT GUARDI.docx
C7-1 CASE STUDY 7 DATA CENTER CONSOLIDATION AT GUARDI.docx
 
C9-1 CASE STUDY 9 ST. LUKES HEALTH CARE SYSTEM Hospitals have been .docx
C9-1 CASE STUDY 9 ST. LUKES HEALTH CARE SYSTEM Hospitals have been .docxC9-1 CASE STUDY 9 ST. LUKES HEALTH CARE SYSTEM Hospitals have been .docx
C9-1 CASE STUDY 9 ST. LUKES HEALTH CARE SYSTEM Hospitals have been .docx
 
C9-1 CASE STUDY 9 ST. LUKES HEALTH CARE SYSTEM .docx
C9-1 CASE STUDY 9   ST. LUKES HEALTH CARE SYSTEM .docxC9-1 CASE STUDY 9   ST. LUKES HEALTH CARE SYSTEM .docx
C9-1 CASE STUDY 9 ST. LUKES HEALTH CARE SYSTEM .docx
 
C361 TASK 22C361 TASK 22C361 Task 2WGUEv.docx
C361 TASK 22C361 TASK 22C361 Task 2WGUEv.docxC361 TASK 22C361 TASK 22C361 Task 2WGUEv.docx
C361 TASK 22C361 TASK 22C361 Task 2WGUEv.docx
 
C6-1 CASE STUDY 6 CHEVRON’S INFRASTRUCTURE EVOLUT.docx
C6-1 CASE STUDY 6 CHEVRON’S INFRASTRUCTURE  EVOLUT.docxC6-1 CASE STUDY 6 CHEVRON’S INFRASTRUCTURE  EVOLUT.docx
C6-1 CASE STUDY 6 CHEVRON’S INFRASTRUCTURE EVOLUT.docx
 
C125C126 FORMAL LAB REPORTFORMAL LAB REPORT, GeneralA f.docx
C125C126 FORMAL LAB REPORTFORMAL LAB REPORT, GeneralA f.docxC125C126 FORMAL LAB REPORTFORMAL LAB REPORT, GeneralA f.docx
C125C126 FORMAL LAB REPORTFORMAL LAB REPORT, GeneralA f.docx
 
C10-1 CASE STUDY 10 CHOICE HOTELS INTERNATIONAL .docx
C10-1 CASE STUDY 10     CHOICE HOTELS INTERNATIONAL .docxC10-1 CASE STUDY 10     CHOICE HOTELS INTERNATIONAL .docx
C10-1 CASE STUDY 10 CHOICE HOTELS INTERNATIONAL .docx
 
C11-1 CASE STUDY 11 CLOUD COMPUTING (IN)SECURITY .docx
C11-1 CASE STUDY 11   CLOUD COMPUTING (IN)SECURITY .docxC11-1 CASE STUDY 11   CLOUD COMPUTING (IN)SECURITY .docx
C11-1 CASE STUDY 11 CLOUD COMPUTING (IN)SECURITY .docx
 
C1-1 CASE STUDY 1 UNIFIED COMMUNICATIONS AT BOEING .docx
C1-1 CASE STUDY 1  UNIFIED COMMUNICATIONS AT BOEING .docxC1-1 CASE STUDY 1  UNIFIED COMMUNICATIONS AT BOEING .docx
C1-1 CASE STUDY 1 UNIFIED COMMUNICATIONS AT BOEING .docx
 
C09 07222011 101525 Page 88IT leader who had just been.docx
C09 07222011 101525 Page 88IT leader who had just been.docxC09 07222011 101525 Page 88IT leader who had just been.docx
C09 07222011 101525 Page 88IT leader who had just been.docx
 
C053GXML 10192012 214425 Page 131cC H A P T E R.docx
C053GXML 10192012 214425 Page 131cC H A P T E R.docxC053GXML 10192012 214425 Page 131cC H A P T E R.docx
C053GXML 10192012 214425 Page 131cC H A P T E R.docx
 

Recently uploaded

Accessible Digital Futures project (20/03/2024)
Accessible Digital Futures project (20/03/2024)Accessible Digital Futures project (20/03/2024)
Accessible Digital Futures project (20/03/2024)Jisc
 
How to setup Pycharm environment for Odoo 17.pptx
How to setup Pycharm environment for Odoo 17.pptxHow to setup Pycharm environment for Odoo 17.pptx
How to setup Pycharm environment for Odoo 17.pptxCeline George
 
HMCS Vancouver Pre-Deployment Brief - May 2024 (Web Version).pptx
HMCS Vancouver Pre-Deployment Brief - May 2024 (Web Version).pptxHMCS Vancouver Pre-Deployment Brief - May 2024 (Web Version).pptx
HMCS Vancouver Pre-Deployment Brief - May 2024 (Web Version).pptxmarlenawright1
 
How to Add New Custom Addons Path in Odoo 17
How to Add New Custom Addons Path in Odoo 17How to Add New Custom Addons Path in Odoo 17
How to Add New Custom Addons Path in Odoo 17Celine George
 
80 ĐỀ THI THỬ TUYỂN SINH TIẾNG ANH VÀO 10 SỞ GD – ĐT THÀNH PHỐ HỒ CHÍ MINH NĂ...
80 ĐỀ THI THỬ TUYỂN SINH TIẾNG ANH VÀO 10 SỞ GD – ĐT THÀNH PHỐ HỒ CHÍ MINH NĂ...80 ĐỀ THI THỬ TUYỂN SINH TIẾNG ANH VÀO 10 SỞ GD – ĐT THÀNH PHỐ HỒ CHÍ MINH NĂ...
80 ĐỀ THI THỬ TUYỂN SINH TIẾNG ANH VÀO 10 SỞ GD – ĐT THÀNH PHỐ HỒ CHÍ MINH NĂ...Nguyen Thanh Tu Collection
 
Understanding Accommodations and Modifications
Understanding  Accommodations and ModificationsUnderstanding  Accommodations and Modifications
Understanding Accommodations and ModificationsMJDuyan
 
Plant propagation: Sexual and Asexual propapagation.pptx
Plant propagation: Sexual and Asexual propapagation.pptxPlant propagation: Sexual and Asexual propapagation.pptx
Plant propagation: Sexual and Asexual propapagation.pptxUmeshTimilsina1
 
This PowerPoint helps students to consider the concept of infinity.
This PowerPoint helps students to consider the concept of infinity.This PowerPoint helps students to consider the concept of infinity.
This PowerPoint helps students to consider the concept of infinity.christianmathematics
 
Salient Features of India constitution especially power and functions
Salient Features of India constitution especially power and functionsSalient Features of India constitution especially power and functions
Salient Features of India constitution especially power and functionsKarakKing
 
Kodo Millet PPT made by Ghanshyam bairwa college of Agriculture kumher bhara...
Kodo Millet  PPT made by Ghanshyam bairwa college of Agriculture kumher bhara...Kodo Millet  PPT made by Ghanshyam bairwa college of Agriculture kumher bhara...
Kodo Millet PPT made by Ghanshyam bairwa college of Agriculture kumher bhara...pradhanghanshyam7136
 
SOC 101 Demonstration of Learning Presentation
SOC 101 Demonstration of Learning PresentationSOC 101 Demonstration of Learning Presentation
SOC 101 Demonstration of Learning Presentationcamerronhm
 
On_Translating_a_Tamil_Poem_by_A_K_Ramanujan.pptx
On_Translating_a_Tamil_Poem_by_A_K_Ramanujan.pptxOn_Translating_a_Tamil_Poem_by_A_K_Ramanujan.pptx
On_Translating_a_Tamil_Poem_by_A_K_Ramanujan.pptxPooja Bhuva
 
21st_Century_Skills_Framework_Final_Presentation_2.pptx
21st_Century_Skills_Framework_Final_Presentation_2.pptx21st_Century_Skills_Framework_Final_Presentation_2.pptx
21st_Century_Skills_Framework_Final_Presentation_2.pptxJoelynRubio1
 
Philosophy of china and it's charactistics
Philosophy of china and it's charactisticsPhilosophy of china and it's charactistics
Philosophy of china and it's charactisticshameyhk98
 
Tatlong Kwento ni Lola basyang-1.pdf arts
Tatlong Kwento ni Lola basyang-1.pdf artsTatlong Kwento ni Lola basyang-1.pdf arts
Tatlong Kwento ni Lola basyang-1.pdf artsNbelano25
 
Python Notes for mca i year students osmania university.docx
Python Notes for mca i year students osmania university.docxPython Notes for mca i year students osmania university.docx
Python Notes for mca i year students osmania university.docxRamakrishna Reddy Bijjam
 
Jual Obat Aborsi Hongkong ( Asli No.1 ) 085657271886 Obat Penggugur Kandungan...
Jual Obat Aborsi Hongkong ( Asli No.1 ) 085657271886 Obat Penggugur Kandungan...Jual Obat Aborsi Hongkong ( Asli No.1 ) 085657271886 Obat Penggugur Kandungan...
Jual Obat Aborsi Hongkong ( Asli No.1 ) 085657271886 Obat Penggugur Kandungan...ZurliaSoop
 
COMMUNICATING NEGATIVE NEWS - APPROACHES .pptx
COMMUNICATING NEGATIVE NEWS - APPROACHES .pptxCOMMUNICATING NEGATIVE NEWS - APPROACHES .pptx
COMMUNICATING NEGATIVE NEWS - APPROACHES .pptxannathomasp01
 
Interdisciplinary_Insights_Data_Collection_Methods.pptx
Interdisciplinary_Insights_Data_Collection_Methods.pptxInterdisciplinary_Insights_Data_Collection_Methods.pptx
Interdisciplinary_Insights_Data_Collection_Methods.pptxPooja Bhuva
 

Recently uploaded (20)

Accessible Digital Futures project (20/03/2024)
Accessible Digital Futures project (20/03/2024)Accessible Digital Futures project (20/03/2024)
Accessible Digital Futures project (20/03/2024)
 
How to setup Pycharm environment for Odoo 17.pptx
How to setup Pycharm environment for Odoo 17.pptxHow to setup Pycharm environment for Odoo 17.pptx
How to setup Pycharm environment for Odoo 17.pptx
 
HMCS Vancouver Pre-Deployment Brief - May 2024 (Web Version).pptx
HMCS Vancouver Pre-Deployment Brief - May 2024 (Web Version).pptxHMCS Vancouver Pre-Deployment Brief - May 2024 (Web Version).pptx
HMCS Vancouver Pre-Deployment Brief - May 2024 (Web Version).pptx
 
How to Add New Custom Addons Path in Odoo 17
How to Add New Custom Addons Path in Odoo 17How to Add New Custom Addons Path in Odoo 17
How to Add New Custom Addons Path in Odoo 17
 
80 ĐỀ THI THỬ TUYỂN SINH TIẾNG ANH VÀO 10 SỞ GD – ĐT THÀNH PHỐ HỒ CHÍ MINH NĂ...
80 ĐỀ THI THỬ TUYỂN SINH TIẾNG ANH VÀO 10 SỞ GD – ĐT THÀNH PHỐ HỒ CHÍ MINH NĂ...80 ĐỀ THI THỬ TUYỂN SINH TIẾNG ANH VÀO 10 SỞ GD – ĐT THÀNH PHỐ HỒ CHÍ MINH NĂ...
80 ĐỀ THI THỬ TUYỂN SINH TIẾNG ANH VÀO 10 SỞ GD – ĐT THÀNH PHỐ HỒ CHÍ MINH NĂ...
 
Understanding Accommodations and Modifications
Understanding  Accommodations and ModificationsUnderstanding  Accommodations and Modifications
Understanding Accommodations and Modifications
 
Mehran University Newsletter Vol-X, Issue-I, 2024
Mehran University Newsletter Vol-X, Issue-I, 2024Mehran University Newsletter Vol-X, Issue-I, 2024
Mehran University Newsletter Vol-X, Issue-I, 2024
 
Plant propagation: Sexual and Asexual propapagation.pptx
Plant propagation: Sexual and Asexual propapagation.pptxPlant propagation: Sexual and Asexual propapagation.pptx
Plant propagation: Sexual and Asexual propapagation.pptx
 
This PowerPoint helps students to consider the concept of infinity.
This PowerPoint helps students to consider the concept of infinity.This PowerPoint helps students to consider the concept of infinity.
This PowerPoint helps students to consider the concept of infinity.
 
Salient Features of India constitution especially power and functions
Salient Features of India constitution especially power and functionsSalient Features of India constitution especially power and functions
Salient Features of India constitution especially power and functions
 
Kodo Millet PPT made by Ghanshyam bairwa college of Agriculture kumher bhara...
Kodo Millet  PPT made by Ghanshyam bairwa college of Agriculture kumher bhara...Kodo Millet  PPT made by Ghanshyam bairwa college of Agriculture kumher bhara...
Kodo Millet PPT made by Ghanshyam bairwa college of Agriculture kumher bhara...
 
SOC 101 Demonstration of Learning Presentation
SOC 101 Demonstration of Learning PresentationSOC 101 Demonstration of Learning Presentation
SOC 101 Demonstration of Learning Presentation
 
On_Translating_a_Tamil_Poem_by_A_K_Ramanujan.pptx
On_Translating_a_Tamil_Poem_by_A_K_Ramanujan.pptxOn_Translating_a_Tamil_Poem_by_A_K_Ramanujan.pptx
On_Translating_a_Tamil_Poem_by_A_K_Ramanujan.pptx
 
21st_Century_Skills_Framework_Final_Presentation_2.pptx
21st_Century_Skills_Framework_Final_Presentation_2.pptx21st_Century_Skills_Framework_Final_Presentation_2.pptx
21st_Century_Skills_Framework_Final_Presentation_2.pptx
 
Philosophy of china and it's charactistics
Philosophy of china and it's charactisticsPhilosophy of china and it's charactistics
Philosophy of china and it's charactistics
 
Tatlong Kwento ni Lola basyang-1.pdf arts
Tatlong Kwento ni Lola basyang-1.pdf artsTatlong Kwento ni Lola basyang-1.pdf arts
Tatlong Kwento ni Lola basyang-1.pdf arts
 
Python Notes for mca i year students osmania university.docx
Python Notes for mca i year students osmania university.docxPython Notes for mca i year students osmania university.docx
Python Notes for mca i year students osmania university.docx
 
Jual Obat Aborsi Hongkong ( Asli No.1 ) 085657271886 Obat Penggugur Kandungan...
Jual Obat Aborsi Hongkong ( Asli No.1 ) 085657271886 Obat Penggugur Kandungan...Jual Obat Aborsi Hongkong ( Asli No.1 ) 085657271886 Obat Penggugur Kandungan...
Jual Obat Aborsi Hongkong ( Asli No.1 ) 085657271886 Obat Penggugur Kandungan...
 
COMMUNICATING NEGATIVE NEWS - APPROACHES .pptx
COMMUNICATING NEGATIVE NEWS - APPROACHES .pptxCOMMUNICATING NEGATIVE NEWS - APPROACHES .pptx
COMMUNICATING NEGATIVE NEWS - APPROACHES .pptx
 
Interdisciplinary_Insights_Data_Collection_Methods.pptx
Interdisciplinary_Insights_Data_Collection_Methods.pptxInterdisciplinary_Insights_Data_Collection_Methods.pptx
Interdisciplinary_Insights_Data_Collection_Methods.pptx
 

C H A P T E R±±±±±±±±±±±±±±±.docx

  • 1. C H A P T E R ± ± ± ± ± ± ± ± ± ± ± ± ± ± ± ± ± ± ± ± ± ± ± ± ± ± ± ± ± ±
  • 2. ± ± ± ± 2 IS IT ALL RELATIVE? Noting that what one society deems morally wrong, another deems right, ethical relativists conclude that morals are like manners or style of dress. The ancient Greek historian Herodotus, quoting the poet Pindar, long ago announced the rela- tivist principle when he said, “Custom is king.” Ethical relativism became popular in the nineteenth century when European social scientists traveled the world and discovered a bewildering variety of moral norms and practices. Anthropologists like Ruth Benedict and sociologists like Wil- liam Graham Sumner embraced ethical relativism and gave it the cachet of science. Ethical relativism is a tempting doctrine because it appeals to our desire to be tolerant of other societies. However, it has not found much favor among profes- sional philosophers, who point out that while tolerance is a virtue, indifference to suffering is a vice. Several of the philosophers and moralists included in this chapter—Loretta M. Kopelman, Louis Pojman, R. M. MacIver, and Martin Luther King, Jr.—believe that while much morality is indeed a matter of local custom,
  • 3. some objectively valid moral principles apply to everyone. For them, tolerance ends when a practice or custom violates a universal human right. Lawrence Lengbeyer tries to work out a compromise between relativism and absolutism. Recently a number of anthropologists have joined philosophers and theologians in rejecting relativism. They challenge the idea that social scientists must always be neutral bystanders. Carolyn Fluehr-Lobban struggles with the problem of whether to condemn or to refrain from condemning the societies she studies. In the end she finds herself unable to retain the neutral “scientific” stance. Thomas Nagel argues that the Golden Rule in its negative form—not to do unto others what you would not have them do unto you—provides an objective nonrelativistic basis for morality. Finally, when a relativist like Benedict or Sumner points to the diversity of vil- lages, and thus of norms, those who believe in universal moral standards can point to the newly emerging “global village.” Universal ethical principles are already fully 76 © C en
  • 5. al lo w ed w ith ou t e xp re ss a ut ho riz at io n. codified for the “global village” in such documents as the United Nations Declara- tion of Human Rights, the United Nations Declaration of the Rights of Children, and the United Nations Declaration of the Rights of Women. These declarations
  • 6. firmly assert that all people, regardless of cultural background, regardless of gender or social status, should enjoy certain basic moral rights. While it is certainly true that the United Nations declarations are not universally enforced, their very exis- tence suggests there may be far more moral consensus in the world than the relati- vists allow. IS IT ALL RELATIVE? 77 © C en ga ge L ea rn in g. A ll rig ht s r es
  • 8. ho riz at io n. Morality As Custom Herodotus Herodotus (c. 485–425 B.C.) was the first Western historian. Much of what we know about the ancient world in and around Greece derives from him. Following is one of the fragments of text by Herodotus available to us today. Although brief, it clearly shows that Herodotus may well be the first thinker in Western intellectual history to espouse a version of what today we call ethical relativism. If anyone, no matter who, were given the opportunity of choosing from amongst all the nations in the world the set of beliefs which he thought best, he would inevitably, after careful consideration of their relative merits, choose that of his own country. Everyone without exception believes his own native customs, and
  • 9. the religion he was brought up in, to be the best; and that being so, it is unlikely that anyone but a madman would mock at such things. There is abundant evi- dence that this is the universal feeling about the ancient customs of one’s country. One might recall, in particular, an anecdote of Darius. When he was king of Persia, he summoned the Greeks who happened to be present at his court, and asked them what they would take to eat the dead bodies of their fathers. They replied that they would not do it for any money in the world. Later, in the pres- ence of the Greeks, and through an interpreter, so that they could understand what was said, he asked some Indians, of the tribe called Callatiae, who do in fact eat their parents’ dead bodies, what they would take to burn them. They uttered a cry of horror and forbade him to mention such a dreadful thing. One can see by this what custom can do, and Pindar, in my opinion, was right when he called it “king of all.” STUDY QUESTIONS 1. Herodotus says that people prefer the customs of their own country over those of all other countries. That may have been true in his day. Is it true in ours? 2. Herodotus’s example of what the ancient Greeks and Indians did with the bodies of their dead parents clearly shows that cultures have different
  • 10. customs. But does that make the case for ethical relativism? Though the two societies did it in very different ways, both seem to be engaged in honoring their deceased parents. MORALITY AS CUSTOM From Herodotus’s The Histories, translated by Aubrey de Sélincourt, revised by A. R. Burn (Penguin Classics 1954, revised edition 1972), copyright © the Estate of Aubrey de Sélincourt, 1954, copyright © A. R. Burn, 1972. 78 © C en ga ge L ea rn in g. A ll rig ht s r
  • 12. ut ho riz at io n. A Defense of Moral Relativism Ruth Benedict Ruth Benedict (1887–1948) was one of America’s foremost anthropolo- gists. Her Patterns of Culture (1935) is considered a classic of comparative anthropology. Morality, says Ruth Benedict, is a convenient term for socially approved customs (that is, mores). What one society approves may be disgraceful and unacceptable to another. Moral rules, like rules of etiquette or styles of dress, vary from society to society. Morality is culturally relative. Values are shaped by culture. As Benedict points out, trances are highly regarded in India, so in India many people have trances. Some ancient societies praised homosexual love, so there homosexuality was a norm. Where
  • 13. material possessions are highly valued, people amass property. “Most indi- viduals are plastic to the moulding force of the society into which they are born.” Modern social anthropology has become more and more a study of the varieties and common elements of cultural environment and the consequences of these in human behavior. For such a study of diverse social orders primitive peoples fortu- nately provide a laboratory not yet entirely vitiated by the spread of a standardized worldwide civilization. Dyaks and Hopis, Fijians and Yakuts are significant for psy- chological and sociological study because only among these simpler peoples has there been sufficient isolation to give opportunity for the development of localized social forms. In the higher cultures the standardization of custom and belief over a couple of continents has given a false sense of the inevitability of the particular forms that have gained currency, and we need to turn to a wider survey in order to check the conclusions we hastily base upon this near- universality of familiar cus- toms. Most of the simpler cultures did not gain the wide currency of the one which, out of our experience, we identify with human nature, but this was for various his- torical reasons, and certainly not for any that gives us as its carriers a monopoly of social good or of social sanity. Modern civilization, from this point of view,
  • 14. becomes not a necessary pinnacle of human achievement but one entry in a long series of possible adjustments. These adjustments, whether they are in mannerisms like the ways of showing anger, or joy, or grief in any society, or in major human drives like those of sex, prove to be far more variable than experience in any one culture would suggest. In certain fields, such as that of religion or of formal marriage arrangements, these A DEFENSE OF MORAL RELATIVISM From “Anthropology and the Abnormal” by Ruth Benedict, in The Journal of General Psychology 10 (1934): 59–82. Reprinted with permission of the Helen Dwight Reid Educational Foundation. Published by Heldref Publications, 1319 Eighteenth St., N.W., Washington, DC, 20036-1802. Copyright © 1934. RUTH BENEDICT: A DEFENSE OF MORAL RELATIVISM 79 © C en ga ge L ea rn in
  • 16. ou t e xp re ss a ut ho riz at io n. wide limits of variability are well known and can be fairly described. In others it is not yet possible to give a generalized account, but that does not absolve us of the task of indicating the significance of the work that has been done and of the pro- blems that have arisen. One of these problems relates to the customary modern normal- abnormal cate- gories and our conclusions regarding them. In how far are such categories culturally determined, or in how far can we with assurance regard them as absolute? In how far can we regard inability to function socially as diagnostic of
  • 17. abnormality, or in how far is it necessary to regard this as a function of the culture? As a matter of fact, one of the most striking facts that emerge from a study of widely varying cultures is the ease with which our abnormals function in other cul- tures. It does not matter what kind of “abnormality” we choose for illustration, those which indicate extreme instability, or those which are more in the nature of character traits like sadism or delusions of grandeur or of persecution, there are well-described cultures in which these abnormals function at ease and with honor, and apparently without danger or difficulty to the society. The most notorious of these is trance and catalepsy. Even a very mild mystic is aberrant in our culture. But most peoples have regarded even extreme psychic man- ifestations not only as normal and desirable, but even as characteristic of highly val- ued and gifted individuals. This was true even in our own cultural background in that period when Catholicism made the ecstatic experience the mark of sainthood. It is hard for us, born and brought up in a culture that makes no use of the experi- ence, to realize how important a role it may play and how many individuals are capable of it, once it has been given an honorable place in any society.… Cataleptic and trance phenomena are, of course, only one
  • 18. illustration of the fact that those whom we regard as abnormals may function adequately in other cul- tures. Many of our culturally discarded traits are selected for elaboration in differ- ent societies. Homosexuality is an excellent example, for in this case our attention is not constantly diverted, as in the consideration of trance, to the interruption of rou- tine activity which it implies. Homosexuality poses the problem very simply. A ten- dency toward this trait in our culture exposes an individual to all the conflicts to which all aberrants are always exposed, and we tend to identify the consequences of this conflict with homosexuality. But these consequences are obviously local and cultural. Homosexuals in many societies are not incompetent, but they may be such if the culture asks adjustments of them that would strain any man’s vitality. Wherever homosexuality has been given an honorable place in any society, those to whom it is congenial have filled adequately the honorable roles society assigns to them. Plato’s Republic is, of course, the most convincing statement of such a read- ing of homosexuality. It is presented as one of the major means to the good life, and it was generally so regarded in Greece at that time. The cultural attitude toward homosexuals has not always been on such a high ethical plane, but it has been very varied. Among many American Indian tribes there exists the institution of the berdache, as the French called
  • 19. them. These men- women were men who at puberty or thereafter took the dress and the occupations of women. Sometimes they married other men and lived with them. Sometimes they were men with no inversion, persons of weak sexual endowment who chose this rôle to avoid the jeers of the women. The berdaches were never regarded as of 80 I S IT ALL RELATIVE? © C en ga ge L ea rn in g. A ll rig ht s r es
  • 21. ho riz at io n. first-rate super-natural power, as similar men-women were in Siberia, but rather as leaders in women’s occupations, good healers in certain diseases, or, among certain tribes, as the genial organizers of social affairs. In any case, they were socially placed. They were not left exposed to the conflicts that visit the deviant who is excluded from participation in the recognized patterns of his society. The most spectacular illustrations of the extent to which normality may be cul- turally defined are those cultures where an abnormality of our culture is the corner- stone of their social structure. It is not possible to do justice to these possibilities in a short discussion. A recent study of an island of northwest Melanesia by Fortune describes a society built upon traits which we regard as beyond the border of para- noia. In this tribe the exogamic groups look upon each other as prime manipulators of black magic, so that one marries always into an enemy group which remains for life one’s deadly and unappeasable foes. They look upon a good
  • 22. garden crop as a confession of theft, for everyone is engaged in making magic to induce into his gar- den the productiveness of his neighbors’; therefore no secrecy in the island is so rig- idly insisted upon as the secrecy of a man’s harvesting of his yams. Their polite phrase at the acceptance of a gift is, “And if you now poison me, how shall I repay you this present?” Their preoccupation with poisoning is constant; no woman ever leaves her cooking pot for a moment untended. Even the great affinal economic exchanges that are characteristic of this Melanesian culture area are quite altered in Dobu since they are incompatible with this fear and distrust that pervades the culture. They go farther and people the whole world outside their own quarters with such malignant spirits that all-night feasts and ceremonials simply do not occur here. They have even rigorous religiously enforced customs that forbid the sharing of seed even in one family group. Anyone else’s food is deadly poison to you, so that communality of stores is out of the question. For some months before harvest the whole society is on the verge of starvation, but if one falls to the temp- tation and eats up one’s seed yams, one is an outcast and a beachcomber for life. There is no coming back. It involves, as a matter of course, divorce and the break- ing of all social ties. Now in this society where no one may work with another and no
  • 23. one may share with another, Fortune describes the individual who was regarded by all his fellows as crazy. He was not one of those who periodically ran amok and, beside himself and frothing at the mouth, fell with a knife upon anyone he could reach. Such behavior they did not regard as putting anyone outside the pale. They did not even put the individuals who were known to be liable to these attacks under any kind of control. They merely fled when they saw the attack coming on and kept out of the way. “He would be all right tomorrow.” But there was one man of sunny, kindly disposition who liked work and liked to be helpful. The compul- sion was too strong for him to repress it in favor of the opposite tendencies of his culture. Men and women never spoke of him without laughing; he was silly and simple and definitely crazy. Nevertheless, to the ethnologist used to a culture that has, in Christianity, made his type the model of all virtue, he seemed a pleasant fellow.… … Among the Kwakiutl it did not matter whether a relative had died in bed of disease, or by the hand of an enemy, in either case death was an affront to be wiped out by the death of another person. The fact that one had been caused to mourn RUTH BENEDICT: A DEFENSE OF MORAL RELATIVISM 81
  • 25. ut io n al lo w ed w ith ou t e xp re ss a ut ho riz at io n. was proof that one had been put upon. A chief’s sister and her daughter had gone
  • 26. up to Victoria, and either because they drank bad whiskey or because their boat capsized they never came back. The chief called together his warriors. “Now I ask you, tribes, who shall wail? Shall I do it or shall another?” The spokesman answered, of course, “Not you, Chief. Let some other of the tribes.” Immediately they set up the war pole to announce their intention of wiping out the injury, and gathered a war party. They set out, and found seven men and two children asleep and killed them. “Then they felt good when they arrived at Sebaa in the evening.” The point which is of interest to us is that in our society those who on that occasion would feel good when they arrived at Sebaa that evening would be the definitely abnormal. There would be some, even in our society, but it is not a rec- ognized and approved mood under the circumstances. On the Northwest Coast those are favored and fortunate to whom that mood under those circumstances is congenial, and those to whom it is repugnant are unlucky. This latter minority can register in their own culture only by doing violence to their congenial responses and acquiring others that are difficult for them. The person, for instance, who, like a Plains Indian whose wife has been taken from him, is too proud to fight, can deal with the Northwest Coast civilization only by ignoring its strongest bents. If he can- not achieve it, he is the deviant in that culture, their instance of
  • 27. abnormality. This head-hunting that takes place on the Northwest Coast after a death is no matter of blood revenge or of organized vengeance. There is no effort to tie up the subsequent killing with any responsibility on the part of the victim for the death of the person who is being mourned. A chief whose son has died goes visiting wher- ever his fancy dictates, and he says to his host, “My prince has died today, and you go with him.” Then he kills him. In this, according to their interpretation, he acts nobly because he has not been downed. He has thrust back in return. The whole procedure is meaningless without the fundamental paranoid reading of bereave- ment. Death, like all the other untoward accidents of existence, confounds man’s pride and can only be handled in the category of insults. Behavior honored upon the Northwest Coast is one which is recognized as abnormal in our civilization, and yet it is sufficiently close to the attitudes of our own culture to be intelligible to us and to have a definite vocabulary with which we may discuss it. The megalomaniac paranoid trend is a definite danger in our society. It is encouraged by some of our major preoccupations, and it confronts us with a choice of two possible attitudes. One is to brand it as abnormal and repre- hensible, and is the attitude we have chosen in our civilization. The other is to make
  • 28. it an essential attribute of ideal man, and this is the solution in the culture of the Northwest Coast. These illustrations, which it has been possible to indicate only in the briefest manner, force upon us the fact that normality is culturally defined. An adult shaped to the drives and standards of either of these cultures, if he were transported into our civilization, would fall into our categories of abnormality. He would be faced with the psychic dilemmas of the socially unavailable. In his own culture, however, he is the pillar of society, the end result of socially inculcated mores, and the prob- lem of personal instability in his case simply does not arise. No one civilization can possibly utilize in its mores the whole potential range of human behavior. Just as there are great numbers of possible phonetic articulations, 82 I S IT ALL RELATIVE? © C en ga ge L ea rn
  • 30. ith ou t e xp re ss a ut ho riz at io n. and the possibility of language depends on a selection and standardization of a few of these in order that speech communication may be possible at all, so the possibil- ity of organized behavior of every sort, from the fashions of local dress and houses to the dicta of a people’s ethics and religion, depends upon a similar selection among the possible behavior traits. In the field of recognized economic obligations or sex tabus this selection is as non-rational and subconscious a process as it is in the field of phonetics. It is a process which goes on in the group
  • 31. for long periods of time and is historically conditioned by innumerable accidents of isolation or of con- tact of peoples. In any comprehensive study of psychology, the selection that differ- ent cultures have made in the course of history within the great circumference of potential behavior is of great significance. Every society, beginning with some slight inclination in one direction or another, carries its preference farther and farther, integrating itself more and more completely upon its chosen basis, and discarding those types of behavior that are uncongenial. Most of those organizations of personality that seem to us most uncontrovertibly abnormal have been used by different civilizations in the very foundations of their institutional life. Conversely the most valued traits of normal individuals have been looked on in differently organized cultures as aberrant. Nor- mality, in short, within a very wide range, is culturally defined. It is primarily a term for the socially elaborated segment of human behavior in any culture; and abnormality, a term for the segment that that particular civilization does not use. The very eyes with which we see the problem are conditioned by the long tradi- tional habits of our own society. It is a point that has been made more often in relation to ethics than in relation to psychiatry. We do not any longer make the mistake of
  • 32. deriving the morality of our locality and decade directly from the inevitable constitution of human nature. We do not elevate it to the dignity of a first principle. We recognize that morality differs in every society, and is a convenient term for socially approved habits. Man- kind has always preferred to say, “It is morally good,” rather than “It is habitual,” and the fact of this preference is matter enough for a critical science of ethics. But historically the two phrases are synonymous. The concept of the normal is properly a variant of the concept of the good. It is that which society has approved. A normal action is one which falls well within the limits of expected behavior for a particular society. Its variability among different peoples is essentially a function of the variability of the behavior patterns that dif- ferent societies have created for themselves, and can never be wholly divorced from a consideration of culturally institutionalized types of behavior. Each culture is a more or less elaborate working-out of the potentialities of the segment it has chosen. In so far as a civilization is well integrated and consistent within itself, it will tend to carry farther and farther, according to its nature, its ini- tial impulse toward a particular type of action, and from the point of view of any other culture those elaborations will include more and more extreme and aberrant traits.
  • 33. Each of these traits, in proportion as it reinforces the chosen behavior patterns of that culture, is for that culture normal. Those individuals to whom it is congenial either congenitally, or as the result of childhood sets, are accorded prestige in that culture, and are not visited with the social contempt or disapproval which their RUTH BENEDICT: A DEFENSE OF MORAL RELATIVISM 83 © C en ga ge L ea rn in g. A ll rig ht s r es
  • 35. ho riz at io n. traits would call down upon them in a society that was differently organized. On the other hand, those individuals whose characteristics are not congenial to the selected type of human behavior in that community are the deviants, no matter how valued their personality traits may be in a contrasted civilization. The Dobuan who is not easily susceptible to fear of treachery, who enjoys work and likes to be helpful, is their neurotic and regarded as silly. On the Northwest Coast the person who finds it difficult to read life in terms of an insult contest will be the person upon whom fall all the difficulties of the culturally unprovided for. The person who does not find it easy to humiliate a neighbor, nor to see humilia- tion in his own experience, who is genial and loving, may, of course, find some unstandardized way of achieving satisfactions in his society, but not in the major patterned responses that his culture requires of him. If he is born to play an impor- tant rôle in a family with many hereditary privileges, he can
  • 36. succeed only by doing violence to his whole personality. If he does not succeed, he has betrayed his cul- ture; that is, he is abnormal. I have spoken of individuals as having sets toward certain types of behavior, and of these sets as running sometimes counter to the types of behavior which are institutionalized in the culture to which they belong. From all that we know of con- trasting cultures it seems clear that differences of temperament occur in every soci- ety. The matter has never been made the subject of investigation, but from the available material it would appear that these temperament types are very likely of universal recurrence. That is, there is an ascertainable range of human behavior that is found wherever a sufficiently large series of individuals is observed. But the pro- portion in which behavior types stand to one another in different societies is not universal. The vast majority of the individuals in any group are shaped to the fash- ion of that culture. In other words, most individuals are plastic to the moulding force of the society into which they are born. In a society that values trance, as in India, they will have supernormal experience. In a society that institutionalizes homosexuality, they will be homosexual. In a society that sets the gathering of pos- sessions as the chief human objective, they will amass property. The deviants, what- ever the type of behavior the culture has institutionalized, will
  • 37. remain few in number, and there seems no more difficulty in moulding that vast malleable major- ity to the “normality” of what we consider an aberrant trait, such as delusions of reference, than to the normality of such accepted behavior patterns as acquisitive- ness. The small proportion of the number of the deviants in any culture is not a function of the sure instinct with which that society has built itself upon the funda- mental sanities, but of the universal fact that, happily, the majority of mankind quite readily take any shape that is presented to them.… STUDY QUESTIONS 1. Do you think that the fact of cultural diversity is itself an argument for ethical relativ- ism? Explain. 2. If Benedict’s defense of ethical relativism is correct, then the correct way to resolve a personal dilemma might be to take a survey or poll to see what the majority in your society think is right. If the majority favor capital punishment and oppose abortion, for example, then capital punishment is right and abortion is wrong. Can you defend Benedict against this odd consequence? Explain. 84 I S IT ALL RELATIVE? © C
  • 39. n al lo w ed w ith ou t e xp re ss a ut ho riz at io n. 3. Do you think that certain types of behavior (for example, executing children or beating animals to death) are wrong wherever they occur, despite attitudes prevailing in the societies that practice them? If you believe that such acts are
  • 40. universally wrong, what makes them wrong? 4. How might Benedict account for notions of moral enlightenment and moral progress? A Defense of Cultural Relativism William Graham Sumner William Graham Sumner (1840–1910) was a sociologist, an economist, and a proponent of Darwinism. His books include What Social Classes Owe to Each Other (1883) and Folkways (1906). William Graham Sumner claims that his ethical relativism is derived from having observed other societies. According to Sumner, the “folkways”— that is, the customs, mores, and traditions of each society—are so ingrained in its members that they naturally come to think of them as objectively “right” and “good.” We may build elaborate philosophical and legal doctrines around these concepts, but it is the folkways that deter- mine their true meaning. There is a right way to catch game, to win a wife, to make one’s self appear, to cure disease, to honor ghosts, to treat comrades or strangers, to behave when a child is born, on the warpath, in council, and so on in all cases which can arise. The ways
  • 41. are defined on the negative side, that is, by taboos. The “right” way is the way which the ancestors used and which has been handed down. The tradition is its own warrant. It is not held subject to verification by experience. The notion of right is in the folkways. It is not outside of them, of independent origin, and brought to them to test them. In the folkways, whatever is, is right. This is because they are traditional, and therefore contain in themselves the authority of the ances- tral ghosts. When we come to the folkways we are at the end of our analysis. The notion of right and ought is the same in regard to all the folkways.… The morality of a group at a time is the sum of the taboos and prescriptions in the folkways by which right conduct is defined. Therefore morals can never be intu- itive. They are historical, institutional, and empirical. World philosophy, life policy, right, rights, and morality are all products of the folkways. They are reflections on, and generalizations from, the experience of pleasure and pain which is won in efforts to carry on the struggle for existence under actual life conditions. A DEFENSE OF CULTURAL RELATIVISM From Folkways by William Graham Sumner. WILLIAM GRAHAM SUMNER: A DEFENSE OF CULTURAL RELATIVISM 85
  • 43. ut io n al lo w ed w ith ou t e xp re ss a ut ho riz at io n. The generalizations are very crude and vague in their germinal forms. They are all
  • 44. embodied in folklore, and all our philosophy and science have been developed out of them. Mores Are a Directive Force Of course the view which has been stated is antagonistic to the view that philoso- phy and ethics furnish creative and determining forces in society and history. That view comes down to us from the Greek philosophy and it has now prevailed so long that all current discussion conforms to it. Philosophy and ethics are pursued as independent disciplines, and the results are brought to the science of society and to statesmanship and legislation as authoritative dicta. We also have Völkerpsycho- logie, Sozialpolitik, and other intermediate forms which show the struggle of meta- physics to retain control of the science of society. The “historic sense,” the Zeitgeist, and other terms of similar import are partial recognitions of the mores and their importance in the science of society. We shall see below that philosophy and ethics are products of the folkways. They are taken out of the mores, but are never original and creative; they are secondary and derived. They often interfere in the second stage of the sequence—act, thought, act. Then they produce harm, but some ground is furnished for the claim that they are creative or at least regulative. In fact, the real process in great bodies of men is not one of deduction from any
  • 45. great principle of philosophy or ethics. It is one of minute efforts to live well under existing conditions, which efforts are repeated indefinitely by great numbers, getting strength from habit and from the fellowship of united action. The resultant folkways become coercive. All are forced to conform, and the folkways dominate the societal life. Then they seem true and right, and arise into mores as the norm of welfare. Thence are produced faiths, ideas, doctrines, religions, and philosophies, according to the stage of civilization and the fashions of reflection and generalization. What Is Goodness or Badness of the Mores? It is most important to notice that, for the people of a time and place, their own mores are always good, or rather that for them there can be no question of the goodness or badness of their mores. The reason is because the standards of good and right are in the mores. If the life conditions change, the traditional folkways may produce pain and loss, or fail to produce the same good as formerly. Then the loss of comfort and ease brings doubt into the judgment of welfare (causing doubt of the pleasure of the gods, or of war power, or of health), and thus dis- turbs the unconscious philosophy of the mores. Then a later time will pass judg- ment on the mores. Another society may also pass judgment on the mores. In our
  • 46. literary and historical study of the mores we want to get from them their educa- tional value, which consists in the stimulus or warning as to what is, in its effects, societally good or bad. This may lead us to reject or neglect a phenomenon like infanticide, slavery, or witchcraft, as an old “abuse” and “evil,” or to pass by the crusades as a folly which cannot recur. Such a course would be a great error. Everything in the mores of a time and place must be regarded as justified with 86 I S IT ALL RELATIVE? © C en ga ge L ea rn in g. A ll rig ht
  • 48. a ut ho riz at io n. regard to that time and place. “Good” mores are those which are well adapted to the situation. “Bad” mores are those which are not so adapted. The mores are not so stereotyped and changeless as might appear, because they are forever moving towards more complete adaptation to conditions and interests, and also towards more complete adjustment to each other. People in mass have never made or kept up a custom in order to hurt their own interests. They have made innumerable errors as to what their interests were and how to satisfy them, but they have always aimed to serve their interests as well as they could. This gives the stand- point for the student of the mores. All things in them come before him on the same plane. They all bring instruction and warning. They all have the same rela- tion to power and welfare. The mistakes in them are component parts of them. We do not study them in order to approve some of them and
  • 49. condemn others. They are all equally worthy of attention from the fact that they existed and were used. The chief object of study in them is their adjustment to interests, their rela- tion to welfare, and their coordination in a harmonious system of life policy. For the men of the time there are no “bad” mores. What is traditional and current is the standard of what ought to be. The masses never raise any question about such things. If a few raise doubts and questions, this proves that the folkways have already begun to lose firmness and the regulative element in the mores has begun to lose authority. This indicates that the folkways are on their way to a new adjustment. The extreme of folly, wickedness, and absurdity in the mores is witch persecutions, but the best men in the seventeenth century had no doubt that witches existed, and that they ought to be burned. The religion, statecraft, juris- prudence, philosophy, and social system of that age all contributed to maintain that belief. It was rather a culmination than a contradiction of the current faiths and convictions, just as the dogma that all men are equal and that one ought to have as much political power in the state as another was the culmination of the political dogmatism and social philosophy of the nineteenth century. Hence our judgments of the good or evil consequences of folkways are to be kept separate from our study of the historical phenomena of them, and of their
  • 50. strength and the reasons for it. The judgments have their place in plans and doctrines for the future, not in a retrospect. The Mores Have the Authority of Facts The mores come down to us from the past. Each individual is born into them as he is born into the atmosphere, and he does not reflect on them, or criticize them any more than a baby analyzes the atmosphere before he begins to breathe it. Each one is subjected to the influence of the mores, and formed by them, before he is capable of reasoning about them. It may be objected that nowadays, at least, we criticize all traditions, and accept none just because they are handed down to us. If we take up cases of things which are still entirely or almost entirely in the mores, we shall see that this is not so. There are sects of free- lovers amongst us who want to discuss pair marriage. They are not simply people of evil life. They invite us to discuss rationally our inherited customs and ideas as to marriage, which, they say, are by no means so excellent and elevated as we believe. They WILLIAM GRAHAM SUMNER: A DEFENSE OF CULTURAL RELATIVISM 87 © C
  • 52. n al lo w ed w ith ou t e xp re ss a ut ho riz at io n. have never won any serious attention. Some others want to argue in favor of polygamy on grounds of expediency. They fail to obtain a hearing. Others want to discuss property. In spite of some literary activity on their
  • 53. part, no discussion of property, bequest, and inheritance has ever been opened. Property and mar- riage are in the mores. Nothing can ever change them but the unconscious and imperceptible movement of the mores. Religion was originally a matter of the mores. It became a societal institution and a function of the state. It has now to a great extent been put back into the mores. Since laws with penalties to enforce religious creeds or practices have gone out of use any one may think and act as he pleases about religion. Therefore, it is not now “good form” to attack religion. Infidel publications are now tabooed by the mores, and are more effectually repressed than ever before. They produce no controversy. Democracy is in our American mores. It is a product of our physical and economic conditions. It is impossible to discuss or criticize it. It is glorified for popularity, and is a subject of dithyrambic rhetoric. No one treats it with complete candor and sincerity. No one dares to analyze it as he would aristocracy or autocracy. He would get no hearing and would only incur abuse. The thing to be noticed in all these cases is that the masses oppose a deaf ear to every argument against the mores. It is only insofar as things have been transferred from the mores into laws and positive institutions that there is discussion about them or rationalizing upon them. The mores contain the norm by which, if we should discuss the
  • 54. mores, we should have to judge the mores. We learn the mores as unconsciously as we learn to walk and eat and breathe. The masses never learn how we walk, and eat, and breathe, and they never know any reason why the mores are what they are. The justification of them is that when we wake to consciousness of life we find them facts which already hold us in the bonds of tradition, custom, and habit. The mores contain embodied in them notions, doctrines, and maxims, but they are facts. They are in the present tense. They have nothing to do with what ought to be, will be, may be, or once was, if it is not now. Mores and Morals; Social Code For everyone the mores give the notion of what ought to be. This includes the notion of what ought to be done, for all should cooperate to bring to pass, in the order of life, what ought to be. All notions of propriety, decency, chastity, polite- ness, order, duty, right, rights, discipline, respect, reverence, cooperation, and fel- lowship, especially all things in regard to which good and ill depend entirely on the point at which the line is drawn, are in the mores. The mores can make things seem right and good to one group or one age which to another seem antagonistic to every instinct of human nature. The thirteenth century bred in every heart such a sentiment in regard to heretics that inquisitors had no more
  • 55. misgivings in their pro- ceedings than men would have now if they should attempt to exterminate rattle- snakes. The sixteenth century gave to all such notions about witches that witch persecutors thought they were waging war on enemies of God and man. Of course the inquisitors and witch persecutors constantly developed the notions of heretics and witches. They exaggerated the notions and then gave them back again to the 88 I S IT ALL RELATIVE? © C en ga ge L ea rn in g. A ll rig ht s r
  • 57. ut ho riz at io n. mores, in their expanded form, to inflame the hearts of men with terror and hate and to become, in the next stage, so much more fantastic and ferocious motives. Such is the reaction between the mores and the acts of the living generation. The world philosophy of the age is never anything but the reflection on the mental hori- zon, which is formed out of the mores, of the ruling ideas which are in the mores themselves. It is from a failure to recognize the to and fro in this reaction that the current notion arises that mores are produced by doctrines. The “morals” of an age are never anything but the consonance between what is done and what the mores of the age require. The whole revolves on itself, in the relation of the specific to the general, within the horizon formed by the mores. Every attempt to win an outside standpoint from which to reduce the whole to an absolute philosophy of truth and right, based on an unalterable principle, is a delusion. New elements are brought in
  • 58. only by new conquests of nature through science and art. The new conquests change the conditions of life and the interests of the members of the society. Then the mores change by adaptation to new conditions and interests. The philosophy and ethics then follow to account for and justify the changes in the mores; often, also, to claim that they have caused the changes. They never do anything but draw new lines of bearing between the parts of the mores and the horizon of thought within which they are enclosed, and which is a deduction from the mores. The horizon is widened by more knowledge, but for one age it is just as much a generalization from the mores as for another. It is always unreal. It is only a prod- uct of thought. The ethical philosophers select points on this horizon from which to take their bearings, and they think that they have won some authority for their sys- tems when they travel back again from the generalization to the specific custom out of which it was deduced. The cases of the inquisitors and witch persecutors who toiled arduously and continually for their chosen ends, for little or no reward, show us the relation between mores on the one side and philosophy, ethics, and religion on the other. STUDY QUESTIONS 1. Sumner says, “For the people of a time and place, their own mores are always good,
  • 59. or rather … for them there can be no question of the goodness or badness of their mores.” Explain his position. Has Sumner overlooked the possibility that a people could wonder whether their own mores are correct? Or does Sumner deny this is possible? 2. Sumner says that we often pass judgment on mores of the past or on mores of other people in the present. For example, we now think that infanticide and slavery were wrong. Why does Sumner believe that such moralizing is inappropriate? 3. Sumner believes that mores change when scientific discoveries or technological inven- tions change the conditions of life. Why is it only practical inventions that change mores, and not moral insights? 4. What is the Zeitgeist? How is the concept relevant to Sumner’s theory? 5. Sumner denies that mores are ever produced by doctrines. Does this mean that the moral doctrines of philosophers like Aristotle, Kant, or Mill have no influence on what counts as moral? Explain. WILLIAM GRAHAM SUMNER: A DEFENSE OF CULTURAL RELATIVISM 89 © C
  • 61. n al lo w ed w ith ou t e xp re ss a ut ho riz at io n. Cultural Relativism and Universal Rights Carolyn Fluehr-Lobban Carolyn Fluehr-Lobban (b. 1945) is a professor of anthropology
  • 62. at Rhode Island College, where she is director of the general education program. She has written a number of works on Islamic culture and practice, including Modern Egypt and Its Heritage (1990), Islamic Society in Practice (1994), and Race and Racism: An Introduction (2006). Carolyn Fluehr-Lobban is an anthropologist who objects to the widespread acceptance of ethical relativism by her peers. She points out that in 1947, when the idea of an international declaration of universal human rights was first being discussed, anthropologists, who were mainly ethical relati- vists, declined to participate. Fluehr-Lobban says that this laissez-faire pos- ture must change: “the time has come” for anthropologists to take a stand on key human-rights issues. This will entail morally judging and condemn- ing some of the societies they study. In particular, Fluehr- Lobban con- demns the mores that in many cultures contribute to the exploitation and degradation of women. Fluehr-Lobban advocates active measures to get social change: “We cannot just be bystanders.” Cultural relativism, long a key concept in anthropology, asserts that since each cul- ture has its own values and practices, anthropologists should not make value judg- ments about cultural differences. As a result, anthropological
  • 63. pedagogy has stressed that the study of customs and norms should be value-free, and that the appropriate role of the anthropologist is that of observer and recorder. Today, however, this view is being challenged by critics inside and outside the discipline, especially those who want anthropologists to take a stand on key human-rights issues. I agree that the time has come for anthropologists to become more actively engaged in safeguarding the rights of people whose lives and cultures they study. Historically, anthropology as a discipline has declined to participate in the dia- logue that produced international conventions regarding human rights. For exam- ple, in 1947, when the executive board of the American Anthropological Association withdrew from discussions that led to the “Universal Declaration of Human Rights,” it did so in the belief that no such declaration would be applicable to all human beings. But the world and anthropology have changed. Because their research involves extended interaction with people at the grassroots, anthropolo- gists are in a unique position to lend knowledge and expertise to the international debate regarding human rights. CULTURAL RELATIVISM AND UNIVERSAL RIGHTS Used by permission of the author.
  • 64. 90 I S IT ALL RELATIVE? © C en ga ge L ea rn in g. A ll rig ht s r es er ve d. N o di st
  • 66. Doing so does not represent a complete break with the traditions of our field. After all, in the past, anthropologists did not hesitate to speak out against such rep- rehensible practices as Nazi genocide and South African apartheid. And they have testified in U.S. courts against government rules that impinge on the religious tradi- tions or sacred lands of Native Americans, decrying government policies that treat groups of people unjustly. However, other practices that violate individual rights or oppress particular groups have not been denounced. Anthropologists generally have not spoken out, for example, against the practice in many cultures of female circumcision, which critics call a mutilation of women. They have been unwilling to pass judgment on such forms of culturally based homicide as the killing of infants or the aged. Some have withheld judgment on acts of communal violence, such as clashes between Hindus and Muslims in India or Tutsis and Hutus in Rwanda, perhaps because the animosities between those groups are of long standing. Moreover, as a practical matter, organized anthropology’s refusal to participate in drafting the 1947 human-rights declaration has meant that anthropologists have not had much of a role in drafting later human-rights statements, such as the United
  • 67. Nations’ “Convention on the Elimination of All Forms of Discrimination Against Women,” approved in 1979. In many international forums discussing women’s rights, participants have specifically rejected using cultural relativism as a barrier to improving women’s lives. The issue of violence against women throws the perils of cultural relativism into stark relief. Following the lead of human-rights advocates, a growing number of anthropologists and others are coming to recognize that violence against women should be acknowledged as a violation of a basic human right to be free from harm. They believe that such violence cannot be excused or justified on cultural grounds. Let me refer to my own experience. For nearly 25 years, I have conducted research in the Sudan, one of the African countries where the practice of female cir- cumcision is widespread, affecting the vast majority of females in the northern Sudan. Chronic infections are a common result, and sexual intercourse and child- birth are rendered difficult and painful. However, cultural ideology in the Sudan holds that an uncircumcised woman is not respectable, and few families would risk their daughter’s chances of marrying by not having her circumcised. British colonial officials outlawed the practice in 1946, but this served only to make it sur-
  • 68. reptitious and thus more dangerous. Women found it harder to get treatment for mistakes or for side effects of the illegal surgery. For a long time I felt trapped between, on one side, my anthropologist’s under- standing of the custom and of the sensitivities about it among the people with whom I was working, and, on the other, the largely feminist campaign in the West to eradicate what critics see as a “barbaric” custom. To ally myself with Western feminists and condemn female circumcision seemed to me to be a betrayal of the value system and culture of the Sudan, which I had come to understand. But as I was asked over the years to comment on female circumcision because of my expertise in the Sudan, I came to realize how deeply I felt that the practice was harmful and wrong. CAROLYN FLUEHR-LOBBAN: CULTURAL RELATIVISM AND UNIVERSAL RIGHTS 91 © C en ga ge L ea rn
  • 70. ith ou t e xp re ss a ut ho riz at io n. In 1993, female circumcision was one of the practices deemed harmful by delegates at the international Human Rights Conference in Vienna. During their dis- cussions, they came to view circumcision as a violation of the rights of children as well as of the women who suffer its consequences throughout life. Those discussions made me realize that there was a moral agenda larger than myself, larger than West- ern culture or the culture of the northern Sudan or my discipline. I decided to join colleagues from other disciplines and cultures in speaking out
  • 71. against the practice. Some cultures are beginning to change, although cause and effect are difficult to determine. Women’s associations in the Ivory Coast are calling for an end to female circumcision. In Egypt, the Cairo Institute for Human Rights has reported the first publicly acknowledged marriage of an uncircumcised woman. In the United States, a Nigerian woman recently was granted asylum on the ground that her returning to her country would result in the forcible circumcision of her daughter, which was deemed a violation of the girl’s human rights. To be sure, it is not easy to achieve consensus concerning the point at which cultural practices cross the line and become violations of human rights. But it is important that scholars and human-rights activists discuss the issue. Some examples of when the line is crossed may be clearer than others. The action of a Japanese wife who feels honor-bound to commit suicide because of the shame of her husband’s infidelity can be explained and perhaps justified by the traditional code of honor in Japanese society. However, when she decides to take the lives of her children as well, she is committing murder, which may be easier to condemn than suicide. What about “honor” killings of sisters and daughters accused of sexual miscon-
  • 72. duct in some Middle Eastern and Mediterranean societies? Some anthropologists have explained this practice in culturally relativist terms, saying that severe disrup- tions of the moral order occur when sexual impropriety is alleged or takes place. To restore the social equilibrium and avoid feuds, the local culture requires the shed- ding of blood to wash away the shame of sexual dishonor. The practice of honor killings, which victimizes mainly women, has been defended in some local courts as less serious than premeditated murder, because it stems from longstanding cul- tural traditions. While some judges have agreed, anthropologists should see a differ- ent picture: a pattern of cultural discrimination against women. As the issue of domestic violence shows, we need to explore the ways that we balance individual and cultural rights. The “right” of a man to discipline, slap, hit, or beat his wife (and often, by extension, his children) is widely recognized across many cultures in which male dominance is an accepted fact of life. Indeed, the issue of domestic violence has only recently been added to the international human-rights agenda, with the addition of women’s rights to the list of basic human rights at the Vienna conference. The fact that domestic violence is being openly discussed and challenged in some societies (the United States is among the leaders) helps to encourage dialogue
  • 73. in societies in which domestic violence has been a taboo subject. This dialogue is relatively new, and no clear principles have emerged. But anthropologists could inform and enrich the discussion, using their knowledge of family and community life in different cultures. 92 I S IT ALL RELATIVE? © C en ga ge L ea rn in g. A ll rig ht s r es er ve
  • 75. at io n. Cases of genocide may allow the clearest insight into where the line between local culture and universal morality lies. Many anthropologists have urged the Brazilian and Venezuelan governments to stop gold miners from slaughtering the Yanomami people, who are battling the encroachment of miners on their rain for- ests. Other practices that harm individuals or categories of people (such as the elderly, women, and enslaved or formerly enslaved people) may not represent geno- cide per se, and thus may present somewhat harder questions about the morality of traditional practices. We need to focus on the harm done, however, and not on the scale of the abuse. We need to be sensitive to cultural differences but not allow them to override widely recognized human rights. The exchange of ideas across cultures is already fostering a growing acceptance of the universal nature of some human rights, regardless of cultural differences. The right of individuals to be free from harm or the threat of harm, and the right of cultural minorities to exist freely within states, are just two examples of rights that
  • 76. are beginning to be universally recognized—although not universally applied. Fortunately, organized anthropology is beginning to change its attitude toward cultural relativism and human rights. The theme of the 1994 convention of the American Anthropological Association was human rights. At the sessions organized around the topic, many anthropologists said they no longer were absolutely com- mitted to cultural relativism. The association has responded to the changing attitude among its members by forming a Commission for Human Rights, charged with developing a specifically anthropological perspective on those rights, and with chal- lenging violations and promoting education about them. Nevertheless, many anthropologists continue to express strong support for cul- tural relativism. One of the most contentious issues arises from the fundamental question: What authority do we Westerners have to impose our own concept of universal rights on the rest of humanity? It is true that Western ideas of human rights have so far dominated international discourse. On the other hand, the cul- tural relativists’ argument is often used by repressive governments to deflect interna- tional criticism of their abuse of their citizens. At the very least, anthropologists need to condemn such misuse of cultural relativism, even if it means that they may be denied permission to do research in the country in question.
  • 77. Personally, I would go further: I believe that we should not let the concept of relativism stop us from using national and international forums to examine ways to protect the lives and dignity of people in every culture. Because of our involve- ment in local societies, anthropologists could provide early warnings of abuses—for example, by reporting data to international human-rights organizations, and by joining the dialogue at international conferences. When there is a choice between defending human rights and defending cultural relativism, anthropologists should choose to protect and promote human rights. We cannot just be bystanders. STUDY QUESTIONS 1. What prompted Fluehr-Lobban to pass moral judgment on the societies she was studying? How does she justify this to herself as an anthropologist who is sensitive to the feelings of the people she is judging? 2. Now that she is no longer merely standing by as an observer, what role does Fluehr-Lobban see herself playing? CAROLYN FLUEHR-LOBBAN: CULTURAL RELATIVISM AND UNIVERSAL RIGHTS 93 © C
  • 79. n al lo w ed w ith ou t e xp re ss a ut ho riz at io n. 3. How, in the opinion of Fluehr-Lobban, is “cultural relativism” being misused by some anthropologists? 4. Give an example of what Fluehr-Lobban considers to be an
  • 80. abusive practice in a soci- ety, and state what human right it violates. How might an outsider go about getting the abusive practice changed? Female Circumcision/Genital Mutilation and Ethical Relativism Loretta M. Kopelman Loretta Kopelman (b. 1938) is professor emeritus at East Carolina Univer- sity. She specializes in bioethics and has written more than 140 articles and edited several books on the topic. Some relativists claim that “an action is right if it is approved in a person’s culture and wrong if it is disapproved.” By this reasoning, no culture has the moral authority to criticize the practices of other cultures; each society determines for itself what is right and wrong. Kopelman opposes this the- ory and points out that it can be used to justify horrific practices like apartheid, genocide, and war—and female genital mutilation (FGM). She rejects the relativist view on the grounds that moral judgments, like medi- cal or scientific findings, can be evaluated for consistency and empirical accuracy. Those who defend FGM, for example, often justify it by claiming it is a religious imperative and is essential to women’s health. In fact, it is
  • 81. not required by the Koran, and it is manifestly bad for women’s health. Most cultures, says Kopelman, share similar basic moral values and goals, such as the alleviation of suffering and the promotion of personal well- being. They are also responsive to logic and rules of evidence. These com- mon goals give her hope that we can engage in meaningful intercultural discussions about right and wrong. In northern Africa and southern Arabia many girls undergo ritual surgery involving removal of parts of their external genitalia; the surgery is often accompanied by cer- emonies intended to honor and welcome the girls into their communities. About 80 million living women have had this surgery, and an additional 4 or 5 million girls undergo it each year. Usually performed between infancy and puberty, these Loretta M. Kopelman, “Female Circumcision/Genital Mutilation and Ethical Relativism,” Second Opinion 20, no. 2 (October 1994): 55–71. Reprinted by permission of the Park Ridge Center. 94 I S IT ALL RELATIVE? © C en ga
  • 83. lo w ed w ith ou t e xp re ss a ut ho riz at io n. ancient practices are supposed to promote chastity, religion, group identity, cleanli- ness, health, family values, and marriage goals. This tradition is prevalent and deeply embedded in many countries, including Ethiopia, the Sudan, Somalia, Sierra Leone, Kenya, Tanzania, Central African Republic, Chad, Gambia, Liberia, Mali,
  • 84. Senegal, Eritrea, Ivory Coast, Upper Volta, Mauritania, Nigeria, Mozambique, Botswana, Lesotho, and Egypt. Modified versions of the surgeries are also performed in Southern Yemen and Musqat-Oman. Tragically, the usual ways of performing these surgeries deny women sexual orgasms, cause significant morbidity or mortality among women and children, and strain the overburdened health care systems in these developing countries. Some refer to these practices as female cir- cumcision, but those wishing to stop them increasingly use the description female genital mutilation. Impassioned cultural clashes erupt when people from societies practicing female circumcision/genital mutilation settle in other parts of the world and bring these rites with them. It is practiced, for example, by Muslim groups in the Philippines, Malaysia, Pakistan, Indonesia, Europe, and North America. Parents may use tradi- tional practitioners or seek medical facilities to reduce the morbidity or mortality of this genital surgery. Some doctors and nurses perform the procedures for large fees or because they are concerned about the unhygienic techniques that traditional practitioners may use. In the United Kingdom, where about 2,000 girls undergo the surgery annually, it is classified as child abuse. Other countries have also classi- fied it as child abuse, including Canada and France….
  • 85. Many international agencies like UNICEF, the International Federation of Gynecology and Obstetrics, and the World Health Organization (WHO) openly condemn and try to stop the practices of female genital mutilation. Such national groups as the American Medical Association … have also denounced these rituals. Women’s groups from around the world protest these practices and the lack of notice they receive…. Most women in cultures practicing female circumcision/genital mutilation, when interviewed by investigators from their culture, state that they do not believe that such practices deprive them of anything important. They do not think that women can have orgasms or that sex can be directly pleasing to women but assume that their pleasure comes only from knowing they contribute to their husbands’ enjoyment. Some critics argue that women who hold such beliefs cannot be under- stood to be making an informed choice; they thus condemn this custom as a form of oppression…. International discussion, criticisms, and condemnation of female circumcision/ genital mutilation help activists who struggle to change these rites that are thor- oughly entrenched in their own cultures. Not surprisingly, people who want to con- tinue these practices resent such criticisms, seeing them as assaults upon their deeply
  • 86. embedded and popular cultural traditions. Underlying intercultural disputes is often a basic moral controversy: Does praise or criticism from outside a culture or society have any moral authority within it? That is, do the moral judgments from one culture have any relevance to judg- ments about what is right or wrong within another culture? According to some ver- sions of ethical relativism, to say that something is right means that it is approved of in the speaker’s culture; to say that something is wrong means that it is LORETTA M. KOPELMAN: FEMALE CIRCUMCISION/GENITAL MUTILATION 95 © C en ga ge L ea rn in g. A ll
  • 88. re ss a ut ho riz at io n. disapproved. If this is correct, there is no rational basis for establishing across cultures that one set of culturally established moral values is right and the other wrong. The right action is one that is approved by the person’s society or culture, and the wrong action is one that is disapproved by the person’s society or culture; there are moral truths, but they are determined by the norms of the society. On this view, then, the cultural approval of female circumcision/genital mutilation means that the practice is right; disapproval means that it is wrong. In contrast to such versions of ethical relativism, other traditions hold that to say something is morally right means that the claim can be defended with reasons in a certain way. Saying that something is approved (such as slavery) does not settle
  • 89. whether it is right, because something can be wrong even when it is approved by most people in a culture. Moral judgments do not describe what is approved but prescribe what ought to be approved; if worthy of being called moral or ethical judgments, they must be defensible with reasons that are consistent and empirically defensible. As we shall find, advocates of the practice of female circumcision/genital mutilation do not say, “We approve of these rituals, and that is the end of the matter.” Rather, they try to defend the practice as useful in promoting many impor- tant goals. In fact, however, the practice is inconsistent with important goals and values of the cultures in which it is practiced. We find that we can evaluate some of the reasons given for performing these rituals and that despite our cultural differ- ences about what to value and how to act, we share many methods of discovery, evaluation, and explanation. These enable us sometimes correctly to judge other cultures, and they us. Moral judgments can be evaluated at least in terms of their consistency and their relation to stable evidence, like medical or scientific findings. By this means certain moral claims can be challenged, even where we have different cultural values, and the practice of female circumcision/genital mutilation shown to be wrong. Thus, both intercultural and intracultural discussions, criticisms, and condemnation of female genital mutilation as well as support for activists seeking
  • 90. to stop the practice can have moral authority, or so I argue. After considering some of the health hazards of female circumcision/genital mutilation, I review the version of ethical relativism that denies moral authority to cross-cultural moral judgments. By examining the cultural reasons used to justify female circumcision/genital mutilation, I want to show that many aspects of this discussion are open to cross-cultural evaluation and understanding and hence that this version of ethical relativism fails. After discussing some anticipated objections, I conclude that these relativists have a heavy burden of proof to show why we cannot make intercultural judgments that have moral force concerning female geni- tal mutilation, just as we do concerning such things as oppression, intolerance, exploitation, waste, aggression, and torture or imprisonment of dissidents. Types of Surgery and Their Health Consequences Female circumcision/genital mutilation takes three forms. Type 1 circumcision involves pricking or removing the clitoral hood, or prepuce. This is the least muti- lating type and should not preclude sexual orgasms in later life, unlike other forms. When this surgery is performed on infants and small children, however, it may be difficult to avoid removal of additional tissue, because infants’ genitalia are small,
  • 91. 96 I S IT ALL RELATIVE? © C en ga ge L ea rn in g. A ll rig ht s r es er ve d. N o di st
  • 93. and the tools commonly used are pins, scissors, razors, and knives. In the southern Arabian countries of Southern Yemen and Musqat-Oman, Type 1 circumcision is commonly practiced. In African countries, however, Type 1 circumcision is often not regarded as a genuine circumcision. Only about 3 percent of the women in one east African survey had this type of circumcision, and none in another where all the women surveyed had been circumcised. Type 2, or intermediary, circumcision involves removal of the clitoris and most or all of the labia minora. In Type 3 circumcision, or infibulation, the cli- toris, labia minora, and parts of the labia majora are removed. The gaping wound to the vulva is stitched tightly closed, leaving a tiny opening so that the woman can pass urine and menstrual flow. (Type 3 is also known as Pharaonic circumcision, suggesting that it has been done since the time of the pharaohs.) In some African countries most young girls between infancy and 10 years of age have Type 3 circumcision. Traditional practitioners often use sharpened or hot stones, razors, or knives, frequently without anesthesia or antibiotics. In many communities thorns are used to stitch the wound closed, and a twig is inserted to keep an opening. The girl’s legs may be bound for a month or more while the scar heals….
  • 94. Almost all girls experience immediate pain following the surgery. El Dareer found other immediate consequences, including bleeding, infection, and shock correlating with the type of circumcision. The published studies by investigators from the regions where these rituals are practiced uniformly find that women expressed similar complaints and had similar complications from female circumci- sion/genital mutilation: at the site of the surgery, scarring can make penetration difficult and intercourse painful; cysts may form, requiring surgical repairs; a vari- ety of menstrual problems arise if the opening left is too small to allow adequate drainage; fistulas or tears in the bowel or urinary tract are common, causing incontinence, which in turn leads to social as well as medical problems; maternal-fetal complications and prolonged and obstructed labor are also well- established consequences. El Dareer writes, “The result almost invariably causes immediate and long-term medical complications, especially at childbirth. Consum- mation of marriage is always a difficult experience for both partners, and marital problems often result. Psychological disturbances in girls due to circumcision are not uncommon.” The operation can also be fatal because of shock, tetanus, and septicemia…. Ethical Relativism
  • 95. Female circumcision/genital mutilation serves as a test case for some versions of eth- ical relativism because the practice has widespread approval within the cultures where it is practiced and widespread disapproval outside those cultures. Relativism, however, means different things to different “academic cultures.” Indeed one of the most striking things about the term relativism is that it is used in so many different ways, spanning the banal to the highly controversial. In the Encyclopedia of Philos- ophy, Richard D. Brandt writes, “Contemporary philosophers generally apply the term [ethical relativism] to some position they disagree with or consider absurd, sel- dom to their own views; social scientists, however, often classify themselves as LORETTA M. KOPELMAN: FEMALE CIRCUMCISION/GENITAL MUTILATION 97 © C en ga ge L ea rn in g.
  • 97. t e xp re ss a ut ho riz at io n. relativists.” Philosophers and those in religious studies often distinguish two ways to understand relativism: one is controversial, and the other is not. The noncontro- versial, descriptive version, often called descriptive relativism, is the view that peo- ple from different cultures do act differently and have distinct norms. Social scientists often work as descriptive relativists: they try to understand cultural differ- ences and look for any underlying similarities. Those studying or criticizing female circumcision/genital mutilation, of course, recognize that we do act differently and have different values. But descriptions about how or in what way we are different
  • 98. do not entail statements about how we ought to act. The controversial position, called ethical relativism, is that an action is right if it is approved in a person’s culture and wrong if it is disapproved. Another version of this controversial view is that to say something is right means it has cultural approval; to say something is wrong means it has cultural disapproval. According to this view, which some call cultural relativism, there is no way to evaluate moral claims across cultures; positions taken by international groups like the World Health Organization merely express a cluster of particular societal opinions and have no moral standing in other cultures. On this view it is incoherent to claim that something is wrong in a culture yet approved, or right yet disapproved; people can express moral judgments about things done in their own or other cultures, but they are expressing only their cultural point of view, not one that has moral author- ity in another culture…. I would begin by observing that we seem to share methods of discovery, evaluation, negotiation, and explanation that can be used to help assess moral judg- ments. For example, we agree how to evaluate methods and research in science, engineering, and medicine, and on how to translate, debate, deliberate, criticize, negotiate, and use technology. To do these things, however, we must first have
  • 99. agreed to some extent on how to distinguish good and bad methods and research in science, engineering, and medicine, and what constitutes a good or bad transla- tion, debate, deliberation, criticism, negotiation, or use of technology. These shared methods can be used to help evaluate moral judgments from one culture to another in a way that sometimes has moral authority. An example of a belief that could be evaluated by stable medical evidence is the assertion by people in some regions that the infant’s “death could result if, during delivery, the baby’s head touches the clitoris.” In addition, some moral claims can be evaluated in terms of their coher- ence. It seems incompatible to promote maternal-fetal health as a good and also to advocate avoidable practices known to cause serious perinatal and neonatal infections. We need not rank values similarly with people in another culture, or our own, to have coherent discussions about their consistency, consequences, or factual pre- suppositions. That is, even if some moral or ethical (I use these terms interchange- ably) judgments express unique cultural norms, they may still be morally evaluated by another culture on the basis of their logical consistency and their coherence with stable and cross-culturally accepted empirical information. In addition, we seem to share some moral values, goals, and judgments such as those about the evils of
  • 100. unnecessary suffering and lost opportunities, the need for food and shelter, the duty to help children, and the goods of promoting public health and personal well-being. Let us consider therefore, the reasons given by men and women 98 I S IT ALL RELATIVE? © C en ga ge L ea rn in g. A ll rig ht s r es er ve
  • 102. at io n. who practice female circumcision/genital mutilation in their communities. The information presented herein is based upon studies done by investigators who come from these cultures, some of whom had this ritual surgery as children (El Dareer is one such investigator). We can examine whether these reasons allow peo- ple from other cultures any way of entering the debate based upon such considera- tions as consistency or stable medical findings. Reasons Given for Female Circumcision/Genital Mutilation According to four independent series of studies conducted by investigators from countries where female circumcision is widely practiced, the primary reasons given for performing this ritual surgery are that it (1) meets a religious requirement, (2) preserves group identity, (3) helps to maintain cleanliness and health, (4) preserves virginity and family honor and prevents immorality, and (5) furthers marriage goals including greater sexual pleasure for men. El Dareer conducted her studies in the Sudan, Dr. Olayinka Koso-Thomas in and around Sierra Leone, and Raquiya Haji Dualeh Abdalla and
  • 103. Daphne Williams Ntiri in Somalia. They argue that the reasons for continuing this practice in their respective countries float on a sea of false beliefs, beliefs that thrive because of a lack of education and open discussion about reproduction and sexuality. Insofar as intercultural methods for evaluating factual and logical statements exist, people from other cultures should at least be able to understand these inconsistencies or mistaken factual beliefs and use them as a basis for making some judgments having intercultural moral authority. First, according to these studies the main reason given for performing female circumcision/genital mutilation is that it is regarded as a religious requirement. Most of the people practicing this ritual are Muslims, but it is not a practice required by the Koran. El Dareer writes: “Circumcision of women is not explicitly enjoined in the Koran, but there are two implicit sayings of the Prophet Mohammed: ‘Circumcision is an ordinance in men and an embellishment in women’ and, reportedly Mohammed said to Om Attiya, a woman who circumcised girls in El Medina, ‘Do not go deep. It is more illuminating to the face and more enjoyable to the husband.’ Another version says, ‘Reduce but do not destroy. This is enjoyable to the woman and preferable to the man.’ But there is nothing in the Koran to suggest that the Prophet commanded that women be
  • 104. circumcised. He advised that it was important to both sexes that very little should be taken.” Female circumcision/genital mutilation, moreover, is not practiced in the spiritual center of Islam, Saudi Arabia. Another reason for questioning this as a Muslim practice is that clitoridectomy and infibulation predate Islam, going back to the time of the pharaohs…. Second, many argue that the practice helps to preserve group identity. When Christian colonialists in Kenya introduced laws opposing the practice of female cir- cumcision in the 1930s, African leader Kenyatta expressed a view still popular today: “This operation is still regarded as the very essence of an institution which has enormous educational, social, moral and religious implications, quite apart from the operation itself. For the present, it is impossible for a member of the [Kikuyu] tribe to imagine an initiation without clitoridectomy the abolition of LORETTA M. KOPELMAN: FEMALE CIRCUMCISION/GENITAL MUTILATION 99 © C en ga ge
  • 106. w ed w ith ou t e xp re ss a ut ho riz at io n. IRUA [the ritual operation] will destroy the tribal symbol which identifies the age group and prevent the Kikuyu from perpetuating that spirit of collectivism and national solidarity which they have been able to maintain from time immemorial.” In addition, the practice is of social and economic importance to older women who are paid for performing the rituals….
  • 107. Drs. Koso-Thomas, El Dareer, and Abdalla agree that people in these countries support female circumcision as a good practice, but only because they do not understand that it is a leading cause of sickness or even death for girls, mothers, and infants, and a major cause of infertility, infection, and maternal-fetal and mari- tal complications. They conclude that these facts are not confronted because these societies do not speak openly of such matters. Abdalla writes, “There is no longer any reason, given the present state of progress in science, to tolerate confusion and ignorance about reproduction and women’s sexuality.” Female circumcision/genital mutilation is intended to honor women as male circumcision honors men, and members of cultures where the surgery is practiced are shocked by the analogy of clitoridectomy to removal of the penis…. Third, the belief that the practice advances health and hygiene is incompatible with stable data from surveys done in these cultures, where female circumcision/ genital mutilation has been linked to mortality or morbidity such as shock, infertil- ity, infections, incontinence, maternal-fetal complications, and protracted labor…. Fourth, investigators found that circumcision is thought necessary in these cultures to preserve virginity and family honor and to prevent immorality. Type 3
  • 108. circumcision is used to keep women from having sexual intercourse before marriage and conceiving illegitimate children. In addition, many believe that Types 2 and 3 circumcision must be done because uncircumcised women have excessive and uncontrollable sexual drives. El Dareer, however, believes that this view is not con- sistently held—that women in the Sudan are respected and that Sudanese men would be shocked to apply this sometimes-held cultural view to members of their own families. This reason also seems incompatible with the general view, which investigators found was held by both men and women in these cultures, that sex cannot be pleasant for women. In addition, female circumcision/genital mutilation offers no foolproof way to promote chastity and can even lead to promiscuity because it does not diminish desire or libido even where it makes orgasms impossi- ble. Some women continually seek experiences with new sexual partners because they are left unsatisfied in their sexual encounters. Moreover, some pretend to be virgins by getting stitched up tightly again…. Fifth, interviewers found that people practicing female circumcision/genital mutilation believe that it furthers marriage goals, including greater sexual pleasure for men. To survive economically, women in these cultures must marry, and they will not be acceptable marriage partners unless they have undergone this ritual
  • 109. surgery. It is a curse, for example, to say that someone is the child of an uncir- cumcised woman. The widely held belief that infibulation enhances women’s beauty and men’s sexual pleasure makes it difficult for women who wish to marry to resist this practice. Some men from these cultures, however, report that they enjoy sex more with uncircumcised women. Furthermore, female circumcision/ genital mutilation is inconsistent with the established goals of some of these cultures because it is a leading cause of disability and contributes to the high mortality rate 100 I S IT ALL RELATIVE? © C en ga ge L ea rn in g. A ll rig
  • 111. ss a ut ho riz at io n. among mothers, fetuses, and children. Far from promoting the goals of marriage, it causes difficulty in consummating marriage, infertility, prolonged and obstructed labor, and morbidity and mortality. Criticisms of Ethical Relativism Examination of the debate concerning female circumcision suggests several conclu- sions about the extent to which people from outside a culture can understand or contribute to moral debates within it in a way that has moral force. First, the fact that a culture’s moral and religious views are often intertwined with beliefs that are open to rational and empirical evaluation can be a basis of cross-cultural examina- tion and intercultural moral criticism. Beliefs that the practice enhances fertility and promotes health, that women cannot have orgasms, and that
  • 112. allowing the baby’s head to touch the clitoris during delivery causes death to the baby are incompatible with stable medical data. Thus an opening is allowed for genuine cross-cultural dis- cussion or criticism of the practice. Some claims about female circumcision/genital mutilation, however, are not as easily open to cross-cultural understanding. For example, cultures practicing the Type 3 surgery, infibulation, believe that it makes women more beautiful. For those who are not from these cultures, this belief is difficult to understand, especially when surveys show that many women in these cultures, when inter- viewed, attribute to infibulation their keloid scars, urine retention, pelvic infec- tions, puerperal sepsis, and obstetrical problems. Koso-Thomas writes: “None of the reasons put forward in favor of circumcision have any real scientific or logical basis. It is surprising that aesthetics and the maintenance of cleanliness are advanced as grounds for female circumcision. The scars could hardly be thought of as contributing to beauty. The hardened scar and stump usually seen where the clitoris should be, or in the case of the infibulated vulva, taut skin with an ugly long scar down the middle, present a horrifying picture.” Thus not everyone in these cultures believes that these rituals enhance beauty; some find such claims dif- ficult to understand.
  • 113. Second, the debate over female circumcision/genital mutilation illustrates another difficulty for defenders of this version of ethical relativism concerning the problem of differentiating cultures. People who brought the practice of female cir- cumcision/genital mutilation with them when they moved to another nation still claim to be a distinct cultural group. Some who moved to Britain, for example, resent the interference in their culture represented by laws that condemn the prac- tice as child abuse. If ethical relativists are to appeal to cultural approval in making the final determination of what is good or bad, right or wrong, they must tell us how to distinguish one culture from another. How exactly do we count or separate cultures? A society is not a nation-state, because some social groups have distinctive identities within nations. If we do not define societies as nations, however, how do we distinguish among cultural groups, for example, well enough to say that an action is child abuse in one culture but not in another? Subcultures in nations typically overlap and have many variations. Even if we could count cultural groups well enough to say exactly how to distinguish one culture from another, how and when would this be relevant? How big or old or LORETTA M. KOPELMAN: FEMALE CIRCUMCISION/GENITAL MUTILATION 101
  • 115. ut io n al lo w ed w ith ou t e xp re ss a ut ho riz at io n. vital must a culture, subculture, group, or cult be in order to be
  • 116. recognized as a society whose moral distinctions are self-contained and self- justifying? A related problem is that there can be passionate disagreement, ambivalence, or rapid changes within a culture or group over what is approved or disapproved. According to ethical relativism, where there is significant disagreement within a cul- ture there is no way to determine what is right or wrong. But what disagreement is significant? Third, despite some clear disagreement such as that over the rightness of female circumcision/genital mutilation, people from different parts of the world share com- mon goals like the desirability of promoting people’s health, happiness, opportu- nities, and cooperation, and the wisdom of stopping war, pollution, oppression, torture, and exploitation. These common goals make us a world community, and using shared methods of reasoning and evaluation, we can discuss how they are understood or how well they are implemented in different parts of our world com- munity. We can use these shared goals to assess whether female circumcision/genital mutilation is more like respect or oppression, more like enhancement or diminish- ment of opportunities, or more like pleasure or torture. Another way to express this is to say that we should recognize universal human rights or be respectful of each
  • 117. other as persons capable of reasoned discourse. Fourth, this version of ethical relativism, if consistently held, leads to the abhor- rent conclusion that we cannot make intercultural judgments with moral force about societies that start wars, practice torture, or exploit and oppress other groups; as long as these activities are approved in the society that does them, they are allegedly right. Yet the world community believed that it was making a cross- cultural judgment with moral force when it criticized the Communist Chinese gov- ernment for crushing a pro-democracy student protest rally, the South Africans for upholding apartheid, the Soviets for using psychiatry to suppress dissent, and the Bosnian Serbs for carrying out the siege of Sarajevo. And the judgment was expressed without anyone’s ascertaining whether the respective actions had wide-spread approval in those countries. In each case, repre- sentatives from the criticized society usually said something like, “You don’t understand why this is morally justified in our culture even if it would not be in your society.” If ethical relativism were convincing, these responses ought to be as well. Relativists who want to defend sound social cross-cultural and moral judg- ments about the value of freedom and human rights in other cultures seem to have
  • 118. two choices. On the one hand, if they agree that some cross- cultural norms have moral authority, they should also agree that some intercultural judgments about female circumcision/genital mutilation may have moral authority. Some relativists take this route …, thereby abandoning the version of ethical relativism being criti- cized herein. On the other hand, if they defend this version of ethical relativism yet make cross-cultural moral judgments about the importance of values like tolerance, group benefit, and the survival of cultures, they will have to admit to an inconsis- tency in their arguments. For example, anthropologist Scheper- Hughes… advocates tolerance of other cultural value systems; she fails to see that she is saying that tol- erance between cultures is right and that this is a cross-cultural moral judgment using a moral norm (tolerance). Similarly, relativists who say it is wrong to 102 I S IT ALL RELATIVE? © C en ga ge L ea rn
  • 120. ith ou t e xp re ss a ut ho riz at io n. eliminate rituals that give meaning to other cultures are also inconsistent in making a judgment that presumes to have genuine cross-cultural moral authority. The burden of proof, then, is upon defenders of this version of ethical relativ- ism to show why we cannot do something we think we sometimes do very well, namely, engage in intercultural moral discussion, cooperation, or criticism and give support to people whose welfare or rights are in jeopardy in other cultures. In
  • 121. addition, defenders of ethical relativism need to explain how we can justify the actions of international professional societies that take moral stands in adopting policy. For example, international groups may take moral stands that advocate fighting pandemics, stopping wars, halting oppression, promoting health education, or eliminating poverty, and they seem to have moral authority in some cases. Some might respond that our professional groups are themselves cultures of a sort. But this response raises the already discussed problem of how to individuate a culture or society. Objections Some standard rejoinders are made to criticism of relativism, but they leave untouched the arguments against the particular version of ethical relativism dis- cussed herein. First, some defenders argue that cross-cultural moral judgments per- petuate the evils of absolutism, cultural dogmatism, or cultural imperialism. People rarely admit to such transgressions, often enlisting medicine, religion, science, or the “pure light of reason” to arrive at an allegedly impartial, disinterested, and justified conclusion that they should “enlighten” and “educate” the “natives,” “savages,” or “infidels.” Anthropologist Scheper-Hughes writes, “I don’t ‘like’ the idea of clitori- dectomy any better than any other woman I know. But I like even less the western
  • 122. ‘voices of reason’ [imposing their views].” Scheper-Hughes and others suggest that, in arguing that we can make moral judgments across cultures, we are thereby claiming a particular culture knows best and has the right to impose its allegedly superior knowledge on other cultures. Claiming that we can sometimes judge another culture in a way that has moral force, however, does not entail that one culture is always right, that absolutism is legitimate, or that we can impose our beliefs on others. Relativists sometimes respond that even if this is not a strict logical consequence, it is a practical result. Sherwin writes, “Many social scientists have endorsed versions of relativism pre- cisely out of their sense that the alternative promotes cultural dominance. They may be making a philosophical error in drawing that conclusion, but I do not think that they are making an empirical one.”… The version of ethical relativism we have been considering, however, does not avoid cultural imperialism. To say that an act is right, on this view, means that it has cultural approval, including acts of war, oppression, enslavement, aggression, exploitation, racism, or torture. On this view, the disapproval of other cultures is irrelevant in determining whether these acts are right or wrong; accordingly, the disapproval of people in other cultures, even victims of war,
  • 123. oppression, enslavement, aggression, exploitation, racism, or torture, does not count in deciding what is right or wrong except in their own culture. This view thus leads to abhorrent conclusions. It entails not only the affirmation that LORETTA M. KOPELMAN: FEMALE CIRCUMCISION/GENITAL MUTILATION 103 © C en ga ge L ea rn in g. A ll rig ht s r es er ve
  • 125. at io n. female circumcision/genital mutilation is right in cultures where it is approved but the affirmation that anything with wide social approval is right, including slavery, war, discrimination, oppression, racism, and torture. If defenders of the version of ethical relativism criticized herein are consistent, they will dismiss any objections by people in other cultures as merely an expression of their own cul- tural preferences, having no moral standing whatsoever in the society that is engaging in the acts in question. Defenders of ethical relativism must explain why we should adopt a view lead- ing to such abhorrent conclusions. They may respond that cultures sometimes over- lap and hence that the victims’ protests within or between cultures ought to count. But this response raises two further difficulties for defenders of ethical relativism. First, it is inconsistent if it means that the views of people in other cultures have moral standing and oppressors ought to consider the views of victims. Such judg- ments are inconsistent with this version of ethical relativism because they are
  • 126. cross-cultural judgments with moral authority. The second difficulty with this defense, also discussed above, is that it raises the problem of how we differentiate a culture or society. Second, some defenders of ethical relativism argue that we cannot know enough about another culture to make any cross-cultural moral judgments. We can- not really understand another society well enough to criticize it, they claim, because our feelings, concepts, or ways of reasoning are too different; our so-called ordinary moral views about what is permissible are determined by our upbringing and envir- onments to such a degree that they cannot be transferred to other cultures. There are two ways to understand this objection. The first is that nothing counts as understanding another culture except being raised in it. If that is what is meant, then the objection is valid in a trivial way. But it does not address the important issue of whether we can comprehend well enough to make relevant moral distinc- tions or engage in critical ethical discussions about the universal human right to be free of oppression. The second, and nontrivial, way to understand this objection is that we cannot understand another society well enough to justify claiming to know what is right or wrong in that society or even to raise moral questions about what enhances or