SlideShare a Scribd company logo
1 of 12
TOPIC
IDEA OF FREEDOM IN KANT
PSDA
Submitted by:
DISHA YADAV
ENROLLMENT NO:-364177O3821
SUBJECT:- POLITICAL SCIENCE I
SEMESTER:-SECOND
SECTION:-2-C
Submitted To:
DR. GARIMA MAHESHWARI
Vivekananda School of Law and Legal Studies
VIVEKANANDA INSTITUTE OF PROFESSIONAL STUDIES
Pitampura, Delhi-110034 202
IDEA OF FREEDOM IN KANTact
ABSTRACT
Kant wants to show that freedom is possible in the face of natural
necessity. Transcendental idealism is his solution, which locates
freedom outside of nature. I accept that this makes freedom possible, but
object that it precludes the recognition of other rational agents. In
making this case, I trace some of the history of Kant’s thoughts on
freedom. In several of his earlier works, he argues that we are aware of
our own activity. He later abandons this approach, as he worries that any
awareness of our activity involves access to the noumenal, and thereby
conflicts with the epistemic limits of transcendental idealism. In its
place, from the second Critique onwards, Kant argues that we are
conscious of the moral law, which tells me that I ought to do something,
thus revealing that I can. This is the only proof of freedom consistent
with transcendental idealism, but I argue that such an exclusively first-
personal approach precludes the (third-personal) recognition of other
rational agents. I conclude that transcendental idealism thus fails to
provide an adequate account of freedom. In its place, I sketch an
alternative picture of how freedom is possible, one that locates freedom
within, rather than outside of nature.
Freedom lies at the heart of Kant’s system. He thinks that transcendental
idealism makes it possible. There are a variety of well-known objections
to this approach, but in this paper I want to draw attention to an
overlooked one.1
I accept that transcendental idealism makes freedom
possible, but argue that it precludes the recognition of other rational
agents. This is not a sceptical worry. I have no problem with accepting
that we can – and do – recognise other rational agents, but I think that
Kant’s set-up does not allow for this.2
In making this case, I highlight
the importance of the third-person for Kant’s moral philosophy. In
doing so, I depart from a recent emphasis on the first-personal nature of
Kant’s moral philosophy. Without the third-person, Kant’s approach is
hopeless, or so I shall argue.
I begin with a basic question: how do we know that we are rational
agents? For a while, Kant’s answer was that we are conscious of our
agency. He then came to worry that this conflicted with the epistemic
limits of transcendental idealism, as it involves some sort of awareness
of our noumenal self, and so changed his answer. From the
second Critique onwards, Kant argues that we are conscious of an
unconditional obligation – the moral law – which tells us that we ought
to do something, thus revealing that we can.4
Jeanine Grenberg (2013)
has recently offered an excellent defence of this later approach, where
she insists that the moral phenomenology in question is exclusively
first-personal – the experience of the moral law reveals my freedom
to me. I agree with Grenberg that this is Kant’s considered position, and
also that it is the only proof of freedom consistent with the epistemic
limits of transcendental idealism. I depart from Grenberg (and Kant),
however, in that I do not think this provides us with an adequate account
of freedom. Here, I push the problem of recognition. I argue that Kant’s
set-up precludes the possibility of knowing that other people are rational
agents, and conclude against transcendental idealism on this score. In its
place, I sketch my own account of the possibility of freedom.
1. Consciousness of activity
Kant sets himself two distinct tasks when it comes to freedom. He wants
to show that (an incompatibilist conception of)5
freedom is possible, and
also that we are entitled to think of ourselves as free. He thinks that
transcendental idealism makes freedom possible, but changes his mind
on what entitles us to think of ourselves as free. In some of his earlier
works, he argues that we are conscious of our agency, and that this
reveals our freedom to us. In this section, I will detail this approach.
In his pre-critical lectures on rational psychology (in the mid-1770s),
Kant offers the following argument for freedom:
I am conscious of determinations and actions, and such a subject that is
conscious of its determinations and actions has absolute freedom. That
the subject has absolute freedom because it is conscious of itself, that
proves it is not a subject being acted upon, but rather [one] acting.
(XXVIII: 268–9)
2. Transcendental idealism and the possibility of freedom
Kant thinks that transcendental idealism disarms this threat. It posits two
orders of things, one governed by natural necessity, and one not. We can
thus accept that the world of sense is governed by natural necessity, but
make room for freedom outside of it.10
Here is Kant himself in the
first Critique:
Do freedom and natural necessity in one and the same action contradict
each other? And this we have answered sufficiently when we showed
that since in freedom a relation is possible to conditions of a kind
entirely different from those in natural necessity, the law of the latter
does not affect the former; hence each is independent of the other, and
can take place without being disturbed by the other. (A 557/B 585)
And he says something similar in Groundwork III:
For that a thing in the appearance (belonging to the world of sense) is
subject to certain laws from which just the same as a thing or a being in
itself is independent, contains not the least contradiction. (IV: 457. 16–
9)
Thus according to Kant, we have the world of sense, which is subject to
natural necessity, and the noumenal, which is independent of such
necessity. In positing these two orders, he opens up a space that makes
freedom and natural necessity com-possible.
Of course, there is the complicated issue of how exactly we are to
understand Kant’s distinction between the world of sense and the
noumenal. I want to circumvent the interpretative debate about how to
best understand transcendental idealism in this paper, as I think that the
problem of recognition affects any account of transcendental idealism.
And I will try to keep my discussion at a general level to reflect this
(although in §4 I will consider a possible response from a ‘two-
standpoint’ view).
Here Kant makes a clear appeal to our consciousness of our agency. He
puts forward a similar claim about self-knowledge in the
first Critique (1781):6
Yet the human being, who is otherwise acquainted with the whole of
nature solely through sense, knows himself also through pure
apperception, and indeed in actions and inner determinations which
cannot be accounted at all among impressions of sense; he obviously is
in one part phenomenon, but in another part, namely in regard to certain
faculties, he is a merely intelligible object, because the actions of this
object cannot at all be ascribed to the receptivity of sensibility. (A 546–
7/B 574–5)
In these two passages, Kant claims that we are conscious of our activity,
which reveals to us that we are free.
This approach receives its last outing in Groundwork III (1785),7
where
(alongside other arguments for freedom),8
Kant claims that:
the legitimate claim even of common human reason to freedom of the
will is founded on the consciousness and the granted presupposition of
the independence of reason from merely subjective determining causes.
(IV: 457. 4–7)
[Freedom …] holds only as a necessary presupposition of reason in a
being that believes itself to be conscious of a will. (IV: 459. 9–14)
Kant’s claim is simple, but effective: we are conscious of our rational
agency. This might appear too quick, but I think it is the right way to go.
Indeed, what better source of evidence could there be for our being
agents, than the robust phenomenology of agency?9
If this appears
unsatisfactory, then there will have to be a reason to doubt this robust
phenomenology. And of course, there is, namely the threat of natural
necessity – if everything is determined by natural necessity, there
appears to be little room for Kant’s conception of agency.
3. The great reversal: consciousness of the moral law
Kant never gave up on the claim that transcendental idealism makes
freedom possible. However, he did abandon the claim that we are
conscious of our activity. In this section, I detail why. I follow Ameriks
in contending that any consciousness of our activity conflicts with the
epistemic limits of transcendental idealism.
In claiming that we are conscious of the causality of our reason, Kant
seems to be assuming that we are somehow acquainted with the other
order of things, that we can (in some sense) experience our activity in
the noumenal. Ameriks (2000, p. 191) argues that Kant became aware of
this after the publication of the Groundwork, and thus:
[I]n the second Critique (1788) Kant had to recast his treatment of
freedom radically so as to be in line with the more severe limits on self-
knowledge that he had come to stress in the second edition revisions of
the first Critique (1787).
I agree with Ameriks that in his earlier works, Kant had not yet seen that
this approach conflicts with transcendental idealism. I also follow
Ameriks in thinking that Kant became clear about this shortly after the
publication of the Groundwork.11
We can see Kant’s change of mind in the second Critique (1788). Here
is the so-called ‘great reversal’:12
I ask instead from what our cognition of the unconditionally
practical starts, whether from freedom or from the practical law. It
cannot start from freedom, for we can neither be immediately conscious
of this, since the first concept of it is negative, nor can we conclude to it
from experience, since experience lets us cognize only the law of
appearances and hence the mechanism of nature, the direct opposite of
freedom. It is therefore the moral law … (V: 29. 28–34)
Ameriks (2000, p. 211) diagnoses Kant’s reversal as follows:
it was only to make a virtue of necessity that (given his deepest beliefs
of longest standing) he felt it was proper to announce that without the
moral law ‘we would never have been justified in assuming anything
like freedom’.
The necessity Ameriks speaks of concerns the epistemic limits of
transcendental idealism. For Kant, we can have no intuition of the
noumenal. Moreover, he conceives the world of sense as entirely
determined by natural necessity, and thus we cannot experience freedom
there either. Kant is clear on both of these points throughout the
second Critique.
That we cannot experience freedom is clear from the following
passages:13
It is […] absolutely impossible to give anywhere in experience an
example of it, since among the causes of things as appearances no
determination of causality that would be absolutely unconditioned can
be found. (V: 48. 23–7)
That this is the true subordination of our concepts and that morality first
discloses to us the concept of freedom, so that it is practical
reason which first poses to speculative reason, with this concept, the
most insoluble problem so as to put it in the greatest perplexity, is clear
from the following: that, since nothing in appearances can be explained
by the concept of freedom and there the mechanism of nature must
instead constitute the only guide. (V: 30. 9–14)
This claim that we cannot experience freedom in nature does not
conflict with the approach of the Groundwork. In the Groundwork, Kant
also claims that we can have no experience of freedom.14
However, as
we have seen, in Groundwork III (as well as his pre-critical lectures on
rational psychology and the A-edition of the first Critique), Kant makes
a crucial appeal to our consciousness of our activity. In the
second Critique, he retreats from this position.
Kant insists that we can have no consciousness of our freedom. We can
see this in the fact of reason passage:
Consciousness of this fundamental law may be called a fact of reason
because one cannot reason it out from antecedent data of reason, for
example, from consciousness of freedom (since this is not antecedently
given to us) and because it instead forces itself upon us of itself as a
synthetic a priori proposition that is not based on any intuition, either
pure or empirical, although it would be analytic if the freedom of the
will were presupposed; but for this, as a positive concept, an intellectual
intuition would be required, which certainly cannot be assumed here.
(V: 31. 24–31)
Here Kant is clear that we have no consciousness of freedom, which he
claims would require an intellectual intuition.15
Elsewhere he claims that
we are not conscious of the freedom of our will independently of our
consciousness of the moral law, and that any such consciousness (of our
own freedom) would require a ‘special intuition of itself [einer
besondern Anschauung seiner selbst]’ (V: 42. 15–6).
This seems right, on Kant’s set-up. The activity (or causality) of reason
is not going to be found in the world of experience. It occurs in the
noumenal realm, and to claim that we are conscious of this activity
would involve some sort of access – ‘a special intuition of itself’ (V: 42.
15–6) – to the noumenal.
This is a crucial development in Kant’s thought. Here is Ameriks (2000,
p. 219) on this, one last time:
[The great reversal] was forced on him once he chose squarely to face
both the full consequences of his theoretical philosophy with respect to
the self and the implications of his deepest beliefs, his principles of
practical philosophy.
I agree with Ameriks that Kant makes this move, and I also think that
this ultimately counts against Kant’s treatment of freedom. I will shortly
make this case, through pushing the problem of recognition. I want to
now set the scene for this by considering Jeanine Grenberg’s recent
work on phenomenology in Kant’s moral philosophy.
Kant’stakeonFreedom
Where Kant was right.
Entirely inspired by Kant’s teachings on freedom, and how to
achieve what he considers true liberation.
 TRADITIONAL FREEDOM
The traditional sense of freedom, is one’s ability to righteously act, speak, and or
think the way they wish. Below is the definition that’ll appear after a quick
google search.
“The power or right to act, speak, or think as one
wants without hindrance or restraint.”
Philosophers all throughout history, argued that this is the state in which
man is most willing to live in. Of course, it is that principle that lead to
the declaration of new nations, through self determination.
The ideals that lead to the birth of democratic governments, where the
people have the opportunity, and obligation, to rule themselves. Above
all else, freedom fuels our desire to actively seek the abolishment of
tyranny, liberating those enslaved under it’s rule.
Although many, if not all of these freedoms are positive, it wasn’t the
case profound philosophers were asserting. This may be surprising to
some, but it’s true. Many free thinkers did indeed advocate for
democracy, self determination, and liberation.
However, on top of that, many of these thinkers went on to separate
freedom into different categories. Some, even opine that the notions of
our traditional freedom are completely backwards!
Kant vs Freedom
The average person, assumes that when presented with alternative
choices, would have the freedom to choose one over the other, on the
basis of individual desire.
This is what Kant called “The Idea of Freedom”. It is also more
commonly known today as libertarian freedom. Kant however, saw
freedom differently, and perhaps in a more sophisticated manner.
Libertarians would state that one is free when they can choose what they
want. Kant in contrast to that, believes that choosing what you want isn’t
freedom. He insisted that acting on the basis of desire is being governed,
not by one’s reason, but by their primitive, animalistic instincts.
Kant’s perception of freedom, is the ability to govern one’s actions on
the basis of reason, and not desire. This can all be reduced to the concept
of Autonomy.
The word Autonomy, derives from Greek, literally translating to self
legislator. So the idea, is not to live by one’s animalistic nature imposed
on them from birth, but rather to live by the laws you impose on
yourself.
So in Kant’s view, libertarian freedom isn’t real, but in reality, is just
enslavement of oneself to their desire.
Kant on Reason
The ideal notion of reason, is to derive conclusions on the basis of
objectives, rather than subjectivity. In other words, using logic backed
with empirical facts and evidence, is considered superior to conclusions
driven from anecdotal experiences.
This is the standard way in which we operate professionally, and
reasonably. Kant agreed that this is positive, however, he saw reason in
another light. Kant describes the reason where one uses their
intelligence, as instrumental reason.
So empiricism is considered instrumental in this case. Differing from
that, he makes the case for what he coined as “Pure Reason”. This
concept simply put, is what one considers “good” and “evil”. With pure
reason, one can decide how to live their lives. With instrumental reason,
one can decide on what they need to do within their life.
Pure Reason in relation to Freedom
The most important aspect of pure reason, is that it’s separate from
libertarian freedom. To further elaborate, libertarian freedom in Kant’s
view is being the slave to your own desires.
So he wouldn’t then describe the concept of one’s notion of “good” and
“evil” as desire.
He set that as a boundary for the classification of individual morals,
where desire can’t be a rational fuel for one’s opinion of what’s moral.
This relates to freedom in a really eye opening way. Through Kant’s
works, we begin to understand that freedom cannot coincide with the
oppression of one’s pure reason, where the oppressor is desire. We must
suspend our desire, to achieve freedom.
When this is done, we can begin to run our lives on the basis of what we
consider moral through the usage of pure reason, rather than succumbing
to our wants.

More Related Content

Recently uploaded

一比一原版(UOL毕业证书)利物浦大学毕业证成绩单原件一模一样
一比一原版(UOL毕业证书)利物浦大学毕业证成绩单原件一模一样一比一原版(UOL毕业证书)利物浦大学毕业证成绩单原件一模一样
一比一原版(UOL毕业证书)利物浦大学毕业证成绩单原件一模一样
mefyqyn
 
一比一原版(TUOS毕业证书)谢菲尔德大学毕业证成绩单原件一模一样
一比一原版(TUOS毕业证书)谢菲尔德大学毕业证成绩单原件一模一样一比一原版(TUOS毕业证书)谢菲尔德大学毕业证成绩单原件一模一样
一比一原版(TUOS毕业证书)谢菲尔德大学毕业证成绩单原件一模一样
mefyqyn
 
FRANK VILCHEZ FARFAN.docxñ`kmip0ujhohjujgu
FRANK VILCHEZ FARFAN.docxñ`kmip0ujhohjujguFRANK VILCHEZ FARFAN.docxñ`kmip0ujhohjujgu
FRANK VILCHEZ FARFAN.docxñ`kmip0ujhohjujgu
EverjhonGonzaloyucra
 
一比一原版美国加州大学戴维斯分校毕业证(ucd毕业证书)学位证书仿制
一比一原版美国加州大学戴维斯分校毕业证(ucd毕业证书)学位证书仿制一比一原版美国加州大学戴维斯分校毕业证(ucd毕业证书)学位证书仿制
一比一原版美国加州大学戴维斯分校毕业证(ucd毕业证书)学位证书仿制
afukemk
 
一比一原版(UBC毕业证书)不列颠哥伦比亚大学毕业证成绩单原件一模一样
一比一原版(UBC毕业证书)不列颠哥伦比亚大学毕业证成绩单原件一模一样一比一原版(UBC毕业证书)不列颠哥伦比亚大学毕业证成绩单原件一模一样
一比一原版(UBC毕业证书)不列颠哥伦比亚大学毕业证成绩单原件一模一样
mefyqyn
 

Recently uploaded (20)

Embed-2-2.pdf[[app[r[prf[-rk;lme;[ed[prp[
Embed-2-2.pdf[[app[r[prf[-rk;lme;[ed[prp[Embed-2-2.pdf[[app[r[prf[-rk;lme;[ed[prp[
Embed-2-2.pdf[[app[r[prf[-rk;lme;[ed[prp[
 
一比一原版(UOL毕业证书)利物浦大学毕业证成绩单原件一模一样
一比一原版(UOL毕业证书)利物浦大学毕业证成绩单原件一模一样一比一原版(UOL毕业证书)利物浦大学毕业证成绩单原件一模一样
一比一原版(UOL毕业证书)利物浦大学毕业证成绩单原件一模一样
 
一比一原版(TUOS毕业证书)谢菲尔德大学毕业证成绩单原件一模一样
一比一原版(TUOS毕业证书)谢菲尔德大学毕业证成绩单原件一模一样一比一原版(TUOS毕业证书)谢菲尔德大学毕业证成绩单原件一模一样
一比一原版(TUOS毕业证书)谢菲尔德大学毕业证成绩单原件一模一样
 
Trending Topics in ITC Litigation with Knobbe Martens
Trending Topics in ITC Litigation with Knobbe MartensTrending Topics in ITC Litigation with Knobbe Martens
Trending Topics in ITC Litigation with Knobbe Martens
 
Petitioner Moot Memorial including Charges and Argument Advanced.docx
Petitioner Moot Memorial including Charges and Argument Advanced.docxPetitioner Moot Memorial including Charges and Argument Advanced.docx
Petitioner Moot Memorial including Charges and Argument Advanced.docx
 
How Can an Attorney Help With My Car Accident Claim?
How Can an Attorney Help With My Car Accident Claim?How Can an Attorney Help With My Car Accident Claim?
How Can an Attorney Help With My Car Accident Claim?
 
Comprehensive Guide on Drafting Directors' Report and its ROC Compliances und...
Comprehensive Guide on Drafting Directors' Report and its ROC Compliances und...Comprehensive Guide on Drafting Directors' Report and its ROC Compliances und...
Comprehensive Guide on Drafting Directors' Report and its ROC Compliances und...
 
Starbucks Corp. v. Sardarbuksh Coffee Co.
Starbucks Corp. v. Sardarbuksh Coffee Co.Starbucks Corp. v. Sardarbuksh Coffee Co.
Starbucks Corp. v. Sardarbuksh Coffee Co.
 
Mergers and Acquisitions in Kenya - An explanation
Mergers and Acquisitions in Kenya - An explanationMergers and Acquisitions in Kenya - An explanation
Mergers and Acquisitions in Kenya - An explanation
 
File Taxes Online Simple Steps for Efficient Filing.pdf
File Taxes Online Simple Steps for Efficient Filing.pdfFile Taxes Online Simple Steps for Efficient Filing.pdf
File Taxes Online Simple Steps for Efficient Filing.pdf
 
From Scratch to Strong: Introduction to Drafting of Criminal Cases and Applic...
From Scratch to Strong: Introduction to Drafting of Criminal Cases and Applic...From Scratch to Strong: Introduction to Drafting of Criminal Cases and Applic...
From Scratch to Strong: Introduction to Drafting of Criminal Cases and Applic...
 
How to Protect Your Children During a Divorce?
How to Protect Your Children During a Divorce?How to Protect Your Children During a Divorce?
How to Protect Your Children During a Divorce?
 
Streamline Legal Operations: A Guide to Paralegal Services
Streamline Legal Operations: A Guide to Paralegal ServicesStreamline Legal Operations: A Guide to Paralegal Services
Streamline Legal Operations: A Guide to Paralegal Services
 
Supreme Court Regulation No. 3 of 2023 on Procedure for Appointment of Arbitr...
Supreme Court Regulation No. 3 of 2023 on Procedure for Appointment of Arbitr...Supreme Court Regulation No. 3 of 2023 on Procedure for Appointment of Arbitr...
Supreme Court Regulation No. 3 of 2023 on Procedure for Appointment of Arbitr...
 
FRANK VILCHEZ FARFAN.docxñ`kmip0ujhohjujgu
FRANK VILCHEZ FARFAN.docxñ`kmip0ujhohjujguFRANK VILCHEZ FARFAN.docxñ`kmip0ujhohjujgu
FRANK VILCHEZ FARFAN.docxñ`kmip0ujhohjujgu
 
一比一原版美国加州大学戴维斯分校毕业证(ucd毕业证书)学位证书仿制
一比一原版美国加州大学戴维斯分校毕业证(ucd毕业证书)学位证书仿制一比一原版美国加州大学戴维斯分校毕业证(ucd毕业证书)学位证书仿制
一比一原版美国加州大学戴维斯分校毕业证(ucd毕业证书)学位证书仿制
 
posts-harmful-to-secular-structure-of-the-country-539103-1.pdf
posts-harmful-to-secular-structure-of-the-country-539103-1.pdfposts-harmful-to-secular-structure-of-the-country-539103-1.pdf
posts-harmful-to-secular-structure-of-the-country-539103-1.pdf
 
Embed-3-2.pdfkp[k[odk[odk[d[ok[d[pkdkdkl
Embed-3-2.pdfkp[k[odk[odk[d[ok[d[pkdkdklEmbed-3-2.pdfkp[k[odk[odk[d[ok[d[pkdkdkl
Embed-3-2.pdfkp[k[odk[odk[d[ok[d[pkdkdkl
 
2024 Managing Labor + Employee Relations Seminar
2024 Managing Labor + Employee Relations Seminar2024 Managing Labor + Employee Relations Seminar
2024 Managing Labor + Employee Relations Seminar
 
一比一原版(UBC毕业证书)不列颠哥伦比亚大学毕业证成绩单原件一模一样
一比一原版(UBC毕业证书)不列颠哥伦比亚大学毕业证成绩单原件一模一样一比一原版(UBC毕业证书)不列颠哥伦比亚大学毕业证成绩单原件一模一样
一比一原版(UBC毕业证书)不列颠哥伦比亚大学毕业证成绩单原件一模一样
 

Featured

How Race, Age and Gender Shape Attitudes Towards Mental Health
How Race, Age and Gender Shape Attitudes Towards Mental HealthHow Race, Age and Gender Shape Attitudes Towards Mental Health
How Race, Age and Gender Shape Attitudes Towards Mental Health
ThinkNow
 
Social Media Marketing Trends 2024 // The Global Indie Insights
Social Media Marketing Trends 2024 // The Global Indie InsightsSocial Media Marketing Trends 2024 // The Global Indie Insights
Social Media Marketing Trends 2024 // The Global Indie Insights
Kurio // The Social Media Age(ncy)
 

Featured (20)

2024 State of Marketing Report – by Hubspot
2024 State of Marketing Report – by Hubspot2024 State of Marketing Report – by Hubspot
2024 State of Marketing Report – by Hubspot
 
Everything You Need To Know About ChatGPT
Everything You Need To Know About ChatGPTEverything You Need To Know About ChatGPT
Everything You Need To Know About ChatGPT
 
Product Design Trends in 2024 | Teenage Engineerings
Product Design Trends in 2024 | Teenage EngineeringsProduct Design Trends in 2024 | Teenage Engineerings
Product Design Trends in 2024 | Teenage Engineerings
 
How Race, Age and Gender Shape Attitudes Towards Mental Health
How Race, Age and Gender Shape Attitudes Towards Mental HealthHow Race, Age and Gender Shape Attitudes Towards Mental Health
How Race, Age and Gender Shape Attitudes Towards Mental Health
 
AI Trends in Creative Operations 2024 by Artwork Flow.pdf
AI Trends in Creative Operations 2024 by Artwork Flow.pdfAI Trends in Creative Operations 2024 by Artwork Flow.pdf
AI Trends in Creative Operations 2024 by Artwork Flow.pdf
 
Skeleton Culture Code
Skeleton Culture CodeSkeleton Culture Code
Skeleton Culture Code
 
PEPSICO Presentation to CAGNY Conference Feb 2024
PEPSICO Presentation to CAGNY Conference Feb 2024PEPSICO Presentation to CAGNY Conference Feb 2024
PEPSICO Presentation to CAGNY Conference Feb 2024
 
Content Methodology: A Best Practices Report (Webinar)
Content Methodology: A Best Practices Report (Webinar)Content Methodology: A Best Practices Report (Webinar)
Content Methodology: A Best Practices Report (Webinar)
 
How to Prepare For a Successful Job Search for 2024
How to Prepare For a Successful Job Search for 2024How to Prepare For a Successful Job Search for 2024
How to Prepare For a Successful Job Search for 2024
 
Social Media Marketing Trends 2024 // The Global Indie Insights
Social Media Marketing Trends 2024 // The Global Indie InsightsSocial Media Marketing Trends 2024 // The Global Indie Insights
Social Media Marketing Trends 2024 // The Global Indie Insights
 
Trends In Paid Search: Navigating The Digital Landscape In 2024
Trends In Paid Search: Navigating The Digital Landscape In 2024Trends In Paid Search: Navigating The Digital Landscape In 2024
Trends In Paid Search: Navigating The Digital Landscape In 2024
 
5 Public speaking tips from TED - Visualized summary
5 Public speaking tips from TED - Visualized summary5 Public speaking tips from TED - Visualized summary
5 Public speaking tips from TED - Visualized summary
 
ChatGPT and the Future of Work - Clark Boyd
ChatGPT and the Future of Work - Clark Boyd ChatGPT and the Future of Work - Clark Boyd
ChatGPT and the Future of Work - Clark Boyd
 
Getting into the tech field. what next
Getting into the tech field. what next Getting into the tech field. what next
Getting into the tech field. what next
 
Google's Just Not That Into You: Understanding Core Updates & Search Intent
Google's Just Not That Into You: Understanding Core Updates & Search IntentGoogle's Just Not That Into You: Understanding Core Updates & Search Intent
Google's Just Not That Into You: Understanding Core Updates & Search Intent
 
How to have difficult conversations
How to have difficult conversations How to have difficult conversations
How to have difficult conversations
 
Introduction to Data Science
Introduction to Data ScienceIntroduction to Data Science
Introduction to Data Science
 
Time Management & Productivity - Best Practices
Time Management & Productivity -  Best PracticesTime Management & Productivity -  Best Practices
Time Management & Productivity - Best Practices
 
The six step guide to practical project management
The six step guide to practical project managementThe six step guide to practical project management
The six step guide to practical project management
 
Beginners Guide to TikTok for Search - Rachel Pearson - We are Tilt __ Bright...
Beginners Guide to TikTok for Search - Rachel Pearson - We are Tilt __ Bright...Beginners Guide to TikTok for Search - Rachel Pearson - We are Tilt __ Bright...
Beginners Guide to TikTok for Search - Rachel Pearson - We are Tilt __ Bright...
 

idea of freedom in the view of kant

  • 1. TOPIC IDEA OF FREEDOM IN KANT PSDA Submitted by: DISHA YADAV ENROLLMENT NO:-364177O3821 SUBJECT:- POLITICAL SCIENCE I SEMESTER:-SECOND SECTION:-2-C Submitted To: DR. GARIMA MAHESHWARI Vivekananda School of Law and Legal Studies VIVEKANANDA INSTITUTE OF PROFESSIONAL STUDIES
  • 2. Pitampura, Delhi-110034 202 IDEA OF FREEDOM IN KANTact ABSTRACT Kant wants to show that freedom is possible in the face of natural necessity. Transcendental idealism is his solution, which locates freedom outside of nature. I accept that this makes freedom possible, but object that it precludes the recognition of other rational agents. In making this case, I trace some of the history of Kant’s thoughts on freedom. In several of his earlier works, he argues that we are aware of our own activity. He later abandons this approach, as he worries that any awareness of our activity involves access to the noumenal, and thereby conflicts with the epistemic limits of transcendental idealism. In its place, from the second Critique onwards, Kant argues that we are conscious of the moral law, which tells me that I ought to do something, thus revealing that I can. This is the only proof of freedom consistent with transcendental idealism, but I argue that such an exclusively first- personal approach precludes the (third-personal) recognition of other rational agents. I conclude that transcendental idealism thus fails to provide an adequate account of freedom. In its place, I sketch an alternative picture of how freedom is possible, one that locates freedom within, rather than outside of nature. Freedom lies at the heart of Kant’s system. He thinks that transcendental idealism makes it possible. There are a variety of well-known objections to this approach, but in this paper I want to draw attention to an overlooked one.1 I accept that transcendental idealism makes freedom possible, but argue that it precludes the recognition of other rational agents. This is not a sceptical worry. I have no problem with accepting that we can – and do – recognise other rational agents, but I think that Kant’s set-up does not allow for this.2 In making this case, I highlight the importance of the third-person for Kant’s moral philosophy. In doing so, I depart from a recent emphasis on the first-personal nature of Kant’s moral philosophy. Without the third-person, Kant’s approach is hopeless, or so I shall argue.
  • 3. I begin with a basic question: how do we know that we are rational agents? For a while, Kant’s answer was that we are conscious of our agency. He then came to worry that this conflicted with the epistemic limits of transcendental idealism, as it involves some sort of awareness of our noumenal self, and so changed his answer. From the second Critique onwards, Kant argues that we are conscious of an unconditional obligation – the moral law – which tells us that we ought to do something, thus revealing that we can.4 Jeanine Grenberg (2013) has recently offered an excellent defence of this later approach, where she insists that the moral phenomenology in question is exclusively first-personal – the experience of the moral law reveals my freedom to me. I agree with Grenberg that this is Kant’s considered position, and also that it is the only proof of freedom consistent with the epistemic limits of transcendental idealism. I depart from Grenberg (and Kant), however, in that I do not think this provides us with an adequate account of freedom. Here, I push the problem of recognition. I argue that Kant’s set-up precludes the possibility of knowing that other people are rational agents, and conclude against transcendental idealism on this score. In its place, I sketch my own account of the possibility of freedom. 1. Consciousness of activity Kant sets himself two distinct tasks when it comes to freedom. He wants to show that (an incompatibilist conception of)5 freedom is possible, and also that we are entitled to think of ourselves as free. He thinks that transcendental idealism makes freedom possible, but changes his mind on what entitles us to think of ourselves as free. In some of his earlier works, he argues that we are conscious of our agency, and that this reveals our freedom to us. In this section, I will detail this approach. In his pre-critical lectures on rational psychology (in the mid-1770s), Kant offers the following argument for freedom: I am conscious of determinations and actions, and such a subject that is conscious of its determinations and actions has absolute freedom. That the subject has absolute freedom because it is conscious of itself, that
  • 4. proves it is not a subject being acted upon, but rather [one] acting. (XXVIII: 268–9) 2. Transcendental idealism and the possibility of freedom Kant thinks that transcendental idealism disarms this threat. It posits two orders of things, one governed by natural necessity, and one not. We can thus accept that the world of sense is governed by natural necessity, but make room for freedom outside of it.10 Here is Kant himself in the first Critique: Do freedom and natural necessity in one and the same action contradict each other? And this we have answered sufficiently when we showed that since in freedom a relation is possible to conditions of a kind entirely different from those in natural necessity, the law of the latter does not affect the former; hence each is independent of the other, and can take place without being disturbed by the other. (A 557/B 585) And he says something similar in Groundwork III: For that a thing in the appearance (belonging to the world of sense) is subject to certain laws from which just the same as a thing or a being in itself is independent, contains not the least contradiction. (IV: 457. 16– 9) Thus according to Kant, we have the world of sense, which is subject to natural necessity, and the noumenal, which is independent of such necessity. In positing these two orders, he opens up a space that makes freedom and natural necessity com-possible. Of course, there is the complicated issue of how exactly we are to understand Kant’s distinction between the world of sense and the noumenal. I want to circumvent the interpretative debate about how to best understand transcendental idealism in this paper, as I think that the problem of recognition affects any account of transcendental idealism. And I will try to keep my discussion at a general level to reflect this (although in §4 I will consider a possible response from a ‘two- standpoint’ view).
  • 5. Here Kant makes a clear appeal to our consciousness of our agency. He puts forward a similar claim about self-knowledge in the first Critique (1781):6 Yet the human being, who is otherwise acquainted with the whole of nature solely through sense, knows himself also through pure apperception, and indeed in actions and inner determinations which cannot be accounted at all among impressions of sense; he obviously is in one part phenomenon, but in another part, namely in regard to certain faculties, he is a merely intelligible object, because the actions of this object cannot at all be ascribed to the receptivity of sensibility. (A 546– 7/B 574–5) In these two passages, Kant claims that we are conscious of our activity, which reveals to us that we are free. This approach receives its last outing in Groundwork III (1785),7 where (alongside other arguments for freedom),8 Kant claims that: the legitimate claim even of common human reason to freedom of the will is founded on the consciousness and the granted presupposition of the independence of reason from merely subjective determining causes. (IV: 457. 4–7) [Freedom …] holds only as a necessary presupposition of reason in a being that believes itself to be conscious of a will. (IV: 459. 9–14) Kant’s claim is simple, but effective: we are conscious of our rational agency. This might appear too quick, but I think it is the right way to go. Indeed, what better source of evidence could there be for our being agents, than the robust phenomenology of agency?9 If this appears unsatisfactory, then there will have to be a reason to doubt this robust phenomenology. And of course, there is, namely the threat of natural necessity – if everything is determined by natural necessity, there appears to be little room for Kant’s conception of agency.
  • 6. 3. The great reversal: consciousness of the moral law Kant never gave up on the claim that transcendental idealism makes freedom possible. However, he did abandon the claim that we are conscious of our activity. In this section, I detail why. I follow Ameriks in contending that any consciousness of our activity conflicts with the epistemic limits of transcendental idealism. In claiming that we are conscious of the causality of our reason, Kant seems to be assuming that we are somehow acquainted with the other order of things, that we can (in some sense) experience our activity in the noumenal. Ameriks (2000, p. 191) argues that Kant became aware of this after the publication of the Groundwork, and thus: [I]n the second Critique (1788) Kant had to recast his treatment of freedom radically so as to be in line with the more severe limits on self- knowledge that he had come to stress in the second edition revisions of the first Critique (1787). I agree with Ameriks that in his earlier works, Kant had not yet seen that this approach conflicts with transcendental idealism. I also follow Ameriks in thinking that Kant became clear about this shortly after the publication of the Groundwork.11 We can see Kant’s change of mind in the second Critique (1788). Here is the so-called ‘great reversal’:12 I ask instead from what our cognition of the unconditionally practical starts, whether from freedom or from the practical law. It cannot start from freedom, for we can neither be immediately conscious of this, since the first concept of it is negative, nor can we conclude to it from experience, since experience lets us cognize only the law of appearances and hence the mechanism of nature, the direct opposite of freedom. It is therefore the moral law … (V: 29. 28–34) Ameriks (2000, p. 211) diagnoses Kant’s reversal as follows:
  • 7. it was only to make a virtue of necessity that (given his deepest beliefs of longest standing) he felt it was proper to announce that without the moral law ‘we would never have been justified in assuming anything like freedom’. The necessity Ameriks speaks of concerns the epistemic limits of transcendental idealism. For Kant, we can have no intuition of the noumenal. Moreover, he conceives the world of sense as entirely determined by natural necessity, and thus we cannot experience freedom there either. Kant is clear on both of these points throughout the second Critique. That we cannot experience freedom is clear from the following passages:13 It is […] absolutely impossible to give anywhere in experience an example of it, since among the causes of things as appearances no determination of causality that would be absolutely unconditioned can be found. (V: 48. 23–7) That this is the true subordination of our concepts and that morality first discloses to us the concept of freedom, so that it is practical reason which first poses to speculative reason, with this concept, the most insoluble problem so as to put it in the greatest perplexity, is clear from the following: that, since nothing in appearances can be explained by the concept of freedom and there the mechanism of nature must instead constitute the only guide. (V: 30. 9–14) This claim that we cannot experience freedom in nature does not conflict with the approach of the Groundwork. In the Groundwork, Kant also claims that we can have no experience of freedom.14 However, as we have seen, in Groundwork III (as well as his pre-critical lectures on rational psychology and the A-edition of the first Critique), Kant makes a crucial appeal to our consciousness of our activity. In the second Critique, he retreats from this position. Kant insists that we can have no consciousness of our freedom. We can see this in the fact of reason passage: Consciousness of this fundamental law may be called a fact of reason because one cannot reason it out from antecedent data of reason, for example, from consciousness of freedom (since this is not antecedently
  • 8. given to us) and because it instead forces itself upon us of itself as a synthetic a priori proposition that is not based on any intuition, either pure or empirical, although it would be analytic if the freedom of the will were presupposed; but for this, as a positive concept, an intellectual intuition would be required, which certainly cannot be assumed here. (V: 31. 24–31) Here Kant is clear that we have no consciousness of freedom, which he claims would require an intellectual intuition.15 Elsewhere he claims that we are not conscious of the freedom of our will independently of our consciousness of the moral law, and that any such consciousness (of our own freedom) would require a ‘special intuition of itself [einer besondern Anschauung seiner selbst]’ (V: 42. 15–6). This seems right, on Kant’s set-up. The activity (or causality) of reason is not going to be found in the world of experience. It occurs in the noumenal realm, and to claim that we are conscious of this activity would involve some sort of access – ‘a special intuition of itself’ (V: 42. 15–6) – to the noumenal. This is a crucial development in Kant’s thought. Here is Ameriks (2000, p. 219) on this, one last time: [The great reversal] was forced on him once he chose squarely to face both the full consequences of his theoretical philosophy with respect to the self and the implications of his deepest beliefs, his principles of practical philosophy. I agree with Ameriks that Kant makes this move, and I also think that this ultimately counts against Kant’s treatment of freedom. I will shortly make this case, through pushing the problem of recognition. I want to now set the scene for this by considering Jeanine Grenberg’s recent work on phenomenology in Kant’s moral philosophy.
  • 9. Kant’stakeonFreedom Where Kant was right. Entirely inspired by Kant’s teachings on freedom, and how to achieve what he considers true liberation.  TRADITIONAL FREEDOM The traditional sense of freedom, is one’s ability to righteously act, speak, and or think the way they wish. Below is the definition that’ll appear after a quick google search. “The power or right to act, speak, or think as one wants without hindrance or restraint.” Philosophers all throughout history, argued that this is the state in which man is most willing to live in. Of course, it is that principle that lead to the declaration of new nations, through self determination.
  • 10. The ideals that lead to the birth of democratic governments, where the people have the opportunity, and obligation, to rule themselves. Above all else, freedom fuels our desire to actively seek the abolishment of tyranny, liberating those enslaved under it’s rule. Although many, if not all of these freedoms are positive, it wasn’t the case profound philosophers were asserting. This may be surprising to some, but it’s true. Many free thinkers did indeed advocate for democracy, self determination, and liberation. However, on top of that, many of these thinkers went on to separate freedom into different categories. Some, even opine that the notions of our traditional freedom are completely backwards! Kant vs Freedom The average person, assumes that when presented with alternative choices, would have the freedom to choose one over the other, on the basis of individual desire. This is what Kant called “The Idea of Freedom”. It is also more commonly known today as libertarian freedom. Kant however, saw freedom differently, and perhaps in a more sophisticated manner. Libertarians would state that one is free when they can choose what they want. Kant in contrast to that, believes that choosing what you want isn’t freedom. He insisted that acting on the basis of desire is being governed, not by one’s reason, but by their primitive, animalistic instincts. Kant’s perception of freedom, is the ability to govern one’s actions on the basis of reason, and not desire. This can all be reduced to the concept of Autonomy.
  • 11. The word Autonomy, derives from Greek, literally translating to self legislator. So the idea, is not to live by one’s animalistic nature imposed on them from birth, but rather to live by the laws you impose on yourself. So in Kant’s view, libertarian freedom isn’t real, but in reality, is just enslavement of oneself to their desire. Kant on Reason The ideal notion of reason, is to derive conclusions on the basis of objectives, rather than subjectivity. In other words, using logic backed with empirical facts and evidence, is considered superior to conclusions driven from anecdotal experiences. This is the standard way in which we operate professionally, and reasonably. Kant agreed that this is positive, however, he saw reason in another light. Kant describes the reason where one uses their intelligence, as instrumental reason. So empiricism is considered instrumental in this case. Differing from that, he makes the case for what he coined as “Pure Reason”. This concept simply put, is what one considers “good” and “evil”. With pure reason, one can decide how to live their lives. With instrumental reason, one can decide on what they need to do within their life. Pure Reason in relation to Freedom
  • 12. The most important aspect of pure reason, is that it’s separate from libertarian freedom. To further elaborate, libertarian freedom in Kant’s view is being the slave to your own desires. So he wouldn’t then describe the concept of one’s notion of “good” and “evil” as desire. He set that as a boundary for the classification of individual morals, where desire can’t be a rational fuel for one’s opinion of what’s moral. This relates to freedom in a really eye opening way. Through Kant’s works, we begin to understand that freedom cannot coincide with the oppression of one’s pure reason, where the oppressor is desire. We must suspend our desire, to achieve freedom. When this is done, we can begin to run our lives on the basis of what we consider moral through the usage of pure reason, rather than succumbing to our wants.