SlideShare a Scribd company logo
1 of 172
293
Peter Singer has written about assisted reproduction, animal
rights, abortion, infanticide, the environment, and famine relief.
Because of his controversial beliefs, Singer’s appointment to
Princeton University in 1999 created a public uproar
reminiscent
of 1940, when the City College of New York appointed
Bertrand
Russell, one of the twentieth century’s greatest philosophers, to
a
one-year professorship. In Russell’s case, the outcry culminated
in a judge’s ruling that canceled the state university’s appoint-
ment. Commenting on the case, Albert Einstein said, “Great
spirits have always found violent opposition from mediocrities.”
Since Princeton is a private university, Singer’s ordeal stayed
out
of the courts.
The treatment of nonhuman animals has traditionally been
regarded as a trivial matter. Until recently, almost every ethicist
who wrote on the subject provided some rationale for excluding
animals from moral concern. Aristotle said that, in the natural
order of things, animals exist to serve human purposes. The
Chris-
tian tradition added that man alone is made in God’s image and
that animals do not have souls. Immanuel Kant said that animals
are not self-conscious, so we can have no duties to them.
Chapter 27
All Animals Are Equal
Peter Singer
Peter Singer, “All Animals Are Equal” in Animal Rights and
Human Obligations, ed. Tom
Regan and Peter Singer (Upper Saddle River, NJ: Pearson
Education, 1989), 215–26. Copy-
right © 1989 Peter Singer. Used with permission of the author.
Rachels & Rachels_9781538127926.indb 293 17-06-2019
19:00:27
The Right Thing to Do : Readings in Moral Philosophy, edited
by James Rachels, and Stuart Rachels, Rowman &
Littlefield Publishers, 2019. ProQuest Ebook Central,
http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/newschoolarch-
ebooks/detail.action?docID=5798603.
Created from newschoolarch-ebooks on 2020-05-14 19:49:07.
C
op
yr
ig
ht
©
2
01
9.
R
ow
m
an
&
L
itt
le
fie
ld
P
ub
lis
he
rs
. A
ll
rig
ht
s
re
se
rv
ed
.
Chapter 27294
The utilitarians took a different view, holding that we should
consider the interests of all beings, human and nonhuman. Peter
Singer (1946–) took up this argument in the mid-1970s.
Today, Professor Singer splits his time between Princeton
University in the United States and Melbourne University in
Australia.
“Animal Liberation” may sound more like a parody of other
liberation
movements than a serious objective. The idea of “The Rights of
Ani-
mals” actually was once used to parody the case for women’s
rights.
When Mary Wollstonecraft, a forerunner of today’s feminists,
pub-
lished her Vindication of the Rights of Woman in 1792, her
views were
widely regarded as absurd, and before long an anonymous
publication
appeared entitled A Vindication of the Rights of Brutes. The
author of
this satirical work (now known to have been Thomas Taylor, a
distin-
guished Cambridge philosopher) tried to refute Mary
Wollstonecraft’s
arguments by showing that they could be carried one stage
further. If
the argument for equality was sound when applied to women,
why
should it not be applied to dogs, cats, and horses? The reasoning
seemed
to hold for these “brutes” too; yet to hold that brutes had rights
was
manifestly absurd. Therefore the reasoning by which this
conclusion
had been reached must be unsound, and if unsound when
applied to
brutes, it must also be unsound when applied to women, since
the very
same arguments had been used in each case.
In order to explain the basis of the case for the equality of
animals, it
will be helpful to start with an examination of the case for the
equality
of women. Let us assume that we wish to defend the case for
women’s
rights against the attack by Thomas Taylor. How should we
reply?
One way in which we might reply is by saying that the case for
equal-
ity between men and women cannot validly be extended to
nonhuman
animals. Women have a right to vote, for instance, because they
are just
as capable of making rational decisions about the future as men
are;
dogs, on the other hand, are incapable of understanding the
significance
of voting, so they cannot have the right to vote. There are many
other
obvious ways in which men and women resemble each other
closely,
while humans and animals differ greatly. So, it might be said,
men and
women are similar beings and should have similar rights, while
humans
and nonhumans are different and should not have equal rights.
Rachels & Rachels_9781538127926.indb 294 17-06-2019
19:00:27
The Right Thing to Do : Readings in Moral Philosophy, edited
by James Rachels, and Stuart Rachels, Rowman &
Littlefield Publishers, 2019. ProQuest Ebook Central,
http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/newschoolarch-
ebooks/detail.action?docID=5798603.
Created from newschoolarch-ebooks on 2020-05-14 19:49:07.
C
op
yr
ig
ht
©
2
01
9.
R
ow
m
an
&
L
itt
le
fie
ld
P
ub
lis
he
rs
. A
ll
rig
ht
s
re
se
rv
ed
.
All Animals Are Equal 295
The reasoning behind this reply to Taylor’s analogy is correct
up to
a point, but it does not go far enough. There are obviously
important
differences between humans and other animals, and these
differences
must give rise to some differences in the rights that each have.
Recog-
nizing this evident fact, however, is no barrier to the case for
extending
the basic principle of equality to nonhuman animals. The
differences
that exist between men and women are equally undeniable, and
the
supporters of Women’s Liberation are aware that these
differences may
give rise to different rights. Many feminists hold that women
have the
right to an abortion on request. It does not follow that since
these same
feminists are campaigning for equality between men and women
they
must support the right of men to have abortions too. Since a
man cannot
have an abortion, it is meaningless to talk of his right to have
one. Since
dogs can’t vote, it is meaningless to talk of their right to vote.
There is
no reason why either Women’s Liberation or Animal Liberation
should
get involved in such nonsense. The extension of the basic
principle of
equality from one group to another does not imply that we must
treat
both groups in exactly the same way, or grant exactly the same
rights
to both groups. Whether we should do so will depend on the
nature of
the members of the two groups. The basic principle of equality
does
not require equal or identical treatment; it requires equal
consideration.
Equal consideration for different beings may lead to different
treatment
and different rights.
So there is a different way of replying to Taylor’s attempt to
parody
the case for women’s rights, a way that does not deny the
obvious dif-
ferences between human beings and nonhumans but goes more
deeply
into the question of equality and concludes by finding nothing
absurd in
the idea that the basic principle of equality applies to so-called
brutes.
At this point such a conclusion may appear odd; but if we
examine
more deeply the basis on which our opposition to discrimination
on
grounds of race or sex ultimately rests, we will see that we
would be
on shaky ground if we were to demand equality for blacks,
women, and
other groups of oppressed humans while denying equal
consideration
to nonhumans. To make this clear we need to see, first, exactly
why
racism and sexism are wrong. When we say that all human
beings,
whatever their race, creed, or sex, are equal, what is it that we
are
asserting? Those who wish to defend hierarchical, inegalitarian
societ-
ies have often pointed out that by whatever test we choose it
simply is
not true that all humans are equal. Like it or not we must face
the fact
Rachels & Rachels_9781538127926.indb 295 17-06-2019
19:00:27
The Right Thing to Do : Readings in Moral Philosophy, edited
by James Rachels, and Stuart Rachels, Rowman &
Littlefield Publishers, 2019. ProQuest Ebook Central,
http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/newschoolarch-
ebooks/detail.action?docID=5798603.
Created from newschoolarch-ebooks on 2020-05-14 19:49:07.
C
op
yr
ig
ht
©
2
01
9.
R
ow
m
an
&
L
itt
le
fie
ld
P
ub
lis
he
rs
. A
ll
rig
ht
s
re
se
rv
ed
.
Chapter 27296
that humans come in different shapes and sizes; they come with
differ-
ent moral capacities, different intellectual abilities, different
amounts of
benevolent feeling and sensitivity to the needs of others,
different abili-
ties to communicate effectively, and different capacities to
experience
pleasure and pain. In short, if the demand for equality were
based on the
actual equality of all human beings, we would have to stop
demanding
equality.
Still, one might cling to the view that the demand for equality
among
human beings is based on the actual equality of the different
races and
sexes. Although, it may be said, humans differ as individuals,
there
are no differences between the races and sexes as such. From
the mere
fact that a person is black or a woman we cannot infer anything
about
that person’s intellectual or moral capacities. This, it may be
said, is
why racism and sexism are wrong. The white racist claims that
whites
are superior to blacks, but this is false; although there are
differences
among individuals, some blacks are superior to some whites in
all of
the capacities and abilities that could conceivably be relevant.
The
opponent of sexism would say the same: a person’s sex is no
guide to
his or her abilities, and this is why it is unjustifiable to
discriminate on
the basis of sex.
The existence of individual variations that cut across the lines
of
race or sex, however, provides us with no defense at all against
a more
sophisticated opponent of equality, one who proposes that, say,
the
interests of all those with IQ scores below 100 be given less
consid-
eration than the interests of those with ratings over 100.
Perhaps those
scoring below the mark would, in this society, be made the
slaves of
those scoring higher. Would a hierarchical society of this sort
really
be so much better than one based on race or sex? I think not.
But if
we tie the moral principle of equality to the factual equality of
the dif-
ferent races or sexes, taken as a whole, our opposition to racism
and
sexism does not provide us with any basis for objecting to this
kind of
inegalitarianism.
There is a second important reason why we ought not to base
our
opposition to racism and sexism on any kind of factual equality,
even
the limited kind that asserts that variations in capacities and
abilities are
spread evenly among the different races and between the sexes:
we can
have no absolute guarantee that these capacities and abilities
really are
distributed evenly, without regard to race or sex, among human
beings.
So far as actual abilities are concerned there do seem to be
certain
Rachels & Rachels_9781538127926.indb 296 17-06-2019
19:00:27
The Right Thing to Do : Readings in Moral Philosophy, edited
by James Rachels, and Stuart Rachels, Rowman &
Littlefield Publishers, 2019. ProQuest Ebook Central,
http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/newschoolarch-
ebooks/detail.action?docID=5798603.
Created from newschoolarch-ebooks on 2020-05-14 19:49:07.
C
op
yr
ig
ht
©
2
01
9.
R
ow
m
an
&
L
itt
le
fie
ld
P
ub
lis
he
rs
. A
ll
rig
ht
s
re
se
rv
ed
.
All Animals Are Equal 297
measurable differences both among races and between sexes.
These
differences do not, of course, appear in every case, but only
when aver-
ages are taken. More important still, we do not yet know how
many of
these differences are really due to the different genetic
endowments of
the different races and sexes, and how many are due to poor
schools,
poor housing, and other factors that are the result of past and
continuing
discrimination. Perhaps all of the important differences will
eventually
prove to be environmental rather than genetic. Anyone opposed
to rac-
ism and sexism will certainly hope that this will be so, for it
will make
the task of ending discrimination a lot easier; nevertheless, it
would be
dangerous to rest the case against racism and sexism on the
belief that
all significant differences are environmental in origin. The
opponent of,
say, racism who takes this line will be unable to avoid
conceding that if
differences in ability did after all prove to have some genetic
connection
with race, racism would in some way be defensible.
Fortunately there is no need to pin the case for equality to one
par-
ticular outcome of a scientific investigation. The appropriate
response
to those who claim to have found evidence of genetically based
differ-
ences in ability among the races or between the sexes is not to
stick
to the belief that the genetic explanation must be wrong,
whatever
evidence to the contrary may turn up; instead we should make it
quite
clear that the claim to equality does not depend on intelligence,
moral
capacity, physical strength, or similar matters of fact. Equality
is a
moral idea, not an assertion of fact. There is no logically
compelling
reason for assuming that a factual difference in ability between
two
people justifies any difference in the amount of consideration
we give to
their needs and interests. The principle of the equality of human
beings
is not a description of an alleged actual equality among humans:
it is a
prescription of how we should treat human beings.
Jeremy Bentham, the founder of the reforming utilitarian school
of
moral philosophy, incorporated the essential basis of moral
equality
into his system of ethics by means of the formula: “Each to
count for
one and none for more than one.” In other words, the interests
of every
being affected by an action are to be taken into account and
given the
same weight as the like interests of any other being. A later
utilitar-
ian, Henry Sidgwick, put the point in this way: “The good of
any one
individual is of no more importance, from the point of view (if I
may
say so) of the Universe, than the good of any other.” More
recently the
leading figures in contemporary moral philosophy have shown a
great
Rachels & Rachels_9781538127926.indb 297 17-06-2019
19:00:27
The Right Thing to Do : Readings in Moral Philosophy, edited
by James Rachels, and Stuart Rachels, Rowman &
Littlefield Publishers, 2019. ProQuest Ebook Central,
http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/newschoolarch-
ebooks/detail.action?docID=5798603.
Created from newschoolarch-ebooks on 2020-05-14 19:49:07.
C
op
yr
ig
ht
©
2
01
9.
R
ow
m
an
&
L
itt
le
fie
ld
P
ub
lis
he
rs
. A
ll
rig
ht
s
re
se
rv
ed
.
Chapter 27298
deal of agreement in specifying as a fundamental presupposition
of their
moral theories some similar requirement that works to give
everyone’s
interests equal consideration—although these writers generally
cannot
agree on how this requirement is best formulated.
It is an implication of this principle of equality that our concern
for
others and our readiness to consider their interests ought not to
depend
on what they are like or on what abilities they may possess.
Precisely
what our concern or consideration requires us to do may vary
according
to the characteristics of those affected by what we do: concern
for the
well-being of children growing up in America would require
that we
teach them to read; concern for the well-being of pigs may
require no
more than that we leave them with other pigs in a place where
there is
adequate food and room to run freely. But the basic element—
the tak-
ing into account of the interests of the being, whatever those
interests
may be—must, according to the principle of equality, be
extended to
all beings, black or white, masculine or feminine, human or
nonhuman.
Thomas Jefferson, who was responsible for writing the principle
of
the equality of men into the American Declaration of
Independence,
saw this point. It led him to oppose slavery even though he was
unable
to free himself fully from his slaveholding background. He
wrote in a
letter to the author of a book that emphasized the notable
intellectual
achievements of Negroes in order to refute the then common
view that
they had limited intellectual capacities:
Be assured that no person living wishes more sincerely than I
do, to see a
complete refutation of the doubts I myself have entertained and
expressed on
the grade of understanding allotted to them by nature, and to
find that they
are on a par with ourselves . . . but whatever be their degree of
talent it is no
measure of their rights. Because Sir Isaac Newton was superior
to others in
understanding, he was not therefore lord of the property or
persons of others.
Similarly, when in the 1850s the call for women’s rights was
raised in
the United States, a remarkable black feminist named Sojourner
Truth
made the same point in more robust terms at a feminist
convention:
They talk about this thing in the head; what do they call it?
[“Intel-
lect,” whispered someone nearby.] That’s it. What’s that got to
do with
women’s rights or Negroes’ rights? If my cup won’t hold but a
pint and
yours holds a quart, wouldn’t you be mean not to let me have
my little
half-measure full?
Rachels & Rachels_9781538127926.indb 298 17-06-2019
19:00:27
The Right Thing to Do : Readings in Moral Philosophy, edited
by James Rachels, and Stuart Rachels, Rowman &
Littlefield Publishers, 2019. ProQuest Ebook Central,
http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/newschoolarch-
ebooks/detail.action?docID=5798603.
Created from newschoolarch-ebooks on 2020-05-14 19:49:07.
C
op
yr
ig
ht
©
2
01
9.
R
ow
m
an
&
L
itt
le
fie
ld
P
ub
lis
he
rs
. A
ll
rig
ht
s
re
se
rv
ed
.
All Animals Are Equal 299
It is on this basis that the case against racism and the case
against sex-
ism must both ultimately rest; and it is in accordance with this
principle
that the attitude that we may call “speciesism,” by analogy with
racism,
must also be condemned. Speciesism—the word is not an
attractive
one, but I can think of no better term—is a prejudice or attitude
of bias
in favor of the interests of members of one’s own species and
against
those of members of other species. It should be obvious that the
fun-
damental objections to racism and sexism made by Thomas
Jefferson
and Sojourner Truth apply equally to speciesism. If possessing a
higher
degree of intelligence does not entitle one human to use another
for his
or her own ends, how can it entitle humans to exploit
nonhumans for
the same purpose?
Many philosophers and other writers have proposed the
principle of
equal consideration of interests, in some form or other, as a
basic moral
principle; but not many of them have recognized that this
principle
applies to members of other species as well as to our own.
Jeremy Ben-
tham was one of the few who did realize this. In a forward-
looking pas-
sage written at a time when black slaves had been freed by the
French
but in the British dominions were still being treated in the way
we now
treat animals, Bentham wrote:
The day may come when the rest of the animal creation may
acquire
those rights which never could have been withholden from them
but by
the hand of tyranny. The French have already discovered that
the black-
ness of the skin is no reason why a human being should be
abandoned
without redress to the caprice of a tormentor. It may one day
come to be
recognized that the number of the legs, the villosity of the skin,
or the
termination of the os sacrum are reasons equally insufficient for
aban-
doning a sensitive being to the same fate. What else is it that
should trace
the insuperable line? Is it the faculty of reason, or perhaps the
faculty of
discourse? But a full-grown horse or dog is beyond comparison
a more
rational, as well as a more conversable animal, than an infant of
a day
or a week or even a month, old. But suppose they were
otherwise, what
would it avail? The question is not, Can they reason? nor Can
they talk?
but, Can they suffer?
In this passage Bentham points to the capacity for suffering as
the
vital characteristic that gives a being the right to equal
consideration.
The capacity for suffering—or more strictly, for suffering
and/or enjoy-
ment or happiness—is not just another characteristic like the
capacity
Rachels & Rachels_9781538127926.indb 299 17-06-2019
19:00:27
The Right Thing to Do : Readings in Moral Philosophy, edited
by James Rachels, and Stuart Rachels, Rowman &
Littlefield Publishers, 2019. ProQuest Ebook Central,
http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/newschoolarch-
ebooks/detail.action?docID=5798603.
Created from newschoolarch-ebooks on 2020-05-14 19:49:07.
C
op
yr
ig
ht
©
2
01
9.
R
ow
m
an
&
L
itt
le
fie
ld
P
ub
lis
he
rs
. A
ll
rig
ht
s
re
se
rv
ed
.
Chapter 27300
for language or higher mathematics. Bentham is not saying that
those
who try to mark “the insuperable line” that determines whether
the
interests of a being should be considered happen to have chosen
the
wrong characteristic. By saying that we must consider the
interests of
all beings with the capacity for suffering or enjoyment Bentham
does
not arbitrarily exclude from consideration any interests at all—
as those
who draw the line with reference to the possession of reason or
lan-
guage do. The capacity for suffering and enjoyment is a
prerequisite
for having interests at all, a condition that must be satisfied
before we
can speak of interests in a meaningful way. It would be
nonsense to say
that it was not in the interests of a stone to be kicked along the
road
by a schoolboy. A stone does not have interests because it
cannot suf-
fer. Nothing that we can do to it could possibly make any
difference to
its welfare. The capacity for suffering and enjoyment is,
however, not
only necessary, but also sufficient for us to say that a being has
inter-
ests—at an absolute minimum, an interest in not suffering. A
mouse,
for example, does have an interest in not being kicked along the
road,
because it will suffer if it is.
Although Bentham speaks of “rights” in the passage I have
quoted,
the argument is really about equality rather than about rights.
Indeed,
in a different passage, Bentham famously described “natural
rights”
as “nonsense” and “natural and imprescriptable rights” as
“nonsense
upon stilts.” He talked of moral rights as a shorthand way of
referring
to protections that people and animals morally ought to have;
but the
real weight of the moral argument does not rest on the assertion
of the
existence of the right, for this in turn has to be justified on the
basis of
the possibilities for suffering and happiness. In this way we can
argue
for equality for animals without getting embroiled in
philosophical con-
troversies about the ultimate nature of rights.
In misguided attempts to refute the arguments of this book,
some
philosophers have gone to much trouble developing arguments
to show
that animals do not have rights. They have claimed that to have
rights
a being must be autonomous, or must be a member of a
community,
or must have the ability to respect the rights of others, or must
possess
a sense of justice. These claims are irrelevant to the case for
Animal
Liberation. The language of rights is a convenient political
shorthand.
It is even more valuable in the era of thirty-second TV news
clips than
it was in Bentham’s day; but in the argument for a radical
change in our
attitude to animals, it is in no way necessary.
Rachels & Rachels_9781538127926.indb 300 17-06-2019
19:00:28
The Right Thing to Do : Readings in Moral Philosophy, edited
by James Rachels, and Stuart Rachels, Rowman &
Littlefield Publishers, 2019. ProQuest Ebook Central,
http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/newschoolarch-
ebooks/detail.action?docID=5798603.
Created from newschoolarch-ebooks on 2020-05-14 19:49:07.
C
op
yr
ig
ht
©
2
01
9.
R
ow
m
an
&
L
itt
le
fie
ld
P
ub
lis
he
rs
. A
ll
rig
ht
s
re
se
rv
ed
.
All Animals Are Equal 301
If a being suffers there can be no moral justification for
refusing to
take that suffering into consideration. No matter what the nature
of the
being, the principle of equality requires that its suffering be
counted
equally with the like suffering—insofar as rough comparisons
can be
made—of any other being. If a being is not capable of suffering,
or of
experiencing enjoyment or happiness, there is nothing to be
taken into
account. So the limit of sentience (using the term as a
convenient if not
strictly accurate shorthand for the capacity to suffer and/or
experience
enjoyment) is the only defensible boundary of concern for the
interests
of others. To mark this boundary by some other characteristic
like intel-
ligence or rationality would be to mark it in an arbitrary
manner. Why
not choose some other characteristic, like skin color?
Racists violate the principle of equality by giving greater
weight to
the interests of members of their own race when there is a clash
between
their interests and the interests of those of another race. Sexists
violate
the principle of equality by favoring the interests of their own
sex. Simi-
larly, speciesists allow the interests of their own species to
override the
greater interests of members of other species. The pattern is
identical
in each case. . . .
Animals can feel pain. As we saw earlier, there can be no moral
jus-
tification for regarding the pain (or pleasure) that animals feel
as less
important than the same amount of pain (or pleasure) felt by
humans.
But what practical consequences follow from this conclusion?
To pre-
vent misunderstanding I shall spell out what I mean a little more
fully.
If I give a horse a hard slap across its rump with my open hand,
the horse may start, but it presumably feels little pain. Its skin
is thick
enough to protect it against a mere slap. If I slap a baby in the
same
way, however, the baby will cry and presumably feel pain, for
its skin
is more sensitive. So it is worse to slap a baby than a horse, if
both
slaps are administered with equal force. But there must be some
kind of
blow—I don’t know exactly what it would be, but perhaps a
blow with
a heavy stick—that would cause the horse as much pain as we
cause a
baby by slapping it with our hand. That is what I mean by “the
same
amount of pain,” and if we consider it wrong to inflict that
much pain
on a baby for no good reason then we must, unless we are
speciesists,
consider it equally wrong to inflict the same amount of pain on
a horse
for no good reason.
Rachels & Rachels_9781538127926.indb 301 17-06-2019
19:00:28
The Right Thing to Do : Readings in Moral Philosophy, edited
by James Rachels, and Stuart Rachels, Rowman &
Littlefield Publishers, 2019. ProQuest Ebook Central,
http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/newschoolarch-
ebooks/detail.action?docID=5798603.
Created from newschoolarch-ebooks on 2020-05-14 19:49:07.
C
op
yr
ig
ht
©
2
01
9.
R
ow
m
an
&
L
itt
le
fie
ld
P
ub
lis
he
rs
. A
ll
rig
ht
s
re
se
rv
ed
.
Chapter 27302
Other differences between humans and animals cause other
com-
plications. Normal adult human beings have mental capacities
that
will, in certain circumstances, lead them to suffer more than
animals
would in the same circumstances. If, for instance, we decided to
per-
form extremely painful or lethal scientific experiments on
normal adult
humans, kidnapped at random from public parks for this
purpose, adults
who enjoy strolling in parks would become fearful that they
would be
kidnapped. The resultant terror would be a form of suffering
additional
to the pain of the experiment. The same experiments performed
on
nonhuman animals would cause less suffering since the animals
would
not have the anticipatory dread of being kidnapped and
experimented
upon. This does not mean, of course, that it would be right to
perform
the experiment on animals, but only that there is a reason,
which is
not speciesist, for preferring to use animals rather than normal
adult
human beings, if the experiment is to be done at all. It should
be noted,
however, that this same argument gives us a reason for
preferring to
use human infants—orphans perhaps—or severely retarded
human
beings for experiments, rather than adults, since infants and
retarded
humans would also have no idea of what was going to happen to
them.
So far as this argument is concerned nonhuman animals and
infants and
retarded humans are in the same category; and if we use this
argument
to justify experiments on nonhuman animals we have to ask
ourselves
whether we are also prepared to allow experiments on human
infants
and retarded adults; and if we make a distinction between
animals and
these humans, on what basis can we do it, other than a bare-
faced—and
morally indefensible—preference for members of our own
species?
There are many matters in which the superior mental powers of
normal adult humans make a difference: anticipation, more
detailed …
305
Farm animals in America once grazed on open fields beside
coun-
try roads. Those days, however, are gone. Today, farm animals
live in smelly, crowded, automated warehouses. Every indepen-
dent study has found these factories to be inhumane. The
cramped
conditions are stressful and unnatural for the animals; cows
pumped full of food often experience internal abscesses;
chickens
and turkeys have their beaks cut off, and pigs and cows have
their
tails severed—all without anesthesia—to avoid the fighting that
occurs precisely because the animals are packed in so tightly.
The number of animals that suffer under these conditions is
staggering—in the billions, year after year. When people in our
culture think of a moral horror, they often think of the Holo-
caust—the campaign of genocide in which Hitler and his Nazi
thugs starved, beat, and ultimately murdered 5.7 million Jews.
They do not think of factory farming. Yet for every human
being
who suffered under Hitler’s tyranny, several thousand animals
have suffered in these farms during the past twenty years. The
Nobel laureate Isaac Bashevis Singer wrote, “In relation to
[animals], all people are Nazis; for the animals it is an eternal
Treblinka.”
Chapter 28
Torturing Puppies and Eating Meat
It’s All in Good Taste
Alastair Norcross
Alastair Norcross, “Torturing Puppies and Eating Meat: It’s All
in Good Taste” in Southwest
Philosophy Review, vol. 20, no. 1 (2004): 117–23. Copyright ©
2004. Used with permission
of the author.
Rachels & Rachels_9781538127926.indb 305 17-06-2019
19:00:28
The Right Thing to Do : Readings in Moral Philosophy, edited
by James Rachels, and Stuart Rachels, Rowman &
Littlefield Publishers, 2019. ProQuest Ebook Central,
http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/newschoolarch-
ebooks/detail.action?docID=5798603.
Created from newschoolarch-ebooks on 2020-05-14 19:50:09.
C
o
p
yr
ig
h
t
©
2
0
1
9
.
R
o
w
m
a
n
&
L
itt
le
fie
ld
P
u
b
lis
h
e
rs
.
A
ll
ri
g
h
ts
r
e
se
rv
e
d
.
Chapter 28306
In this selection, Alastair Norcross asks how we can justify
treating chickens in ways that we would never treat puppies.
Despite the seriousness of the topic, Norcross’s piece contains
humor—some of it directed at my home state of Alabama, and
some directed specifically at the city of Tuscaloosa, where I
live.
We Alabamians can take the ridicule—even when it’s not in
good
taste.
Alastair Norcross is a professor of philosophy at the University
of Colorado at Boulder, where many people play the banjo.
Consider the story of Fred, who receives a visit from the police
one
day. They have been summoned by Fred’s neighbors, who have
been
disturbed by strange sounds emanating from Fred’s basement.
When
they enter the basement they are confronted by the following
scene:
Twenty-six small wire cages, each containing a puppy, some
whin-
ing, some whimpering, some howling. The puppies range in age
from
newborn to about six months. Many of them show signs of
mutilation.
Urine and feces cover the bottoms of the cages and the
basement floor.
Fred explains that he keeps the puppies for twenty-six weeks,
and then
butchers them while holding them upside-down. During their
lives he
performs a series of mutilations on them, such as slicing off
their noses
and their paws with a hot knife, all without any form of
anesthesia.
Except for the mutilations, the puppies are never allowed out of
the
cages, which are barely big enough to hold them at twenty-six
weeks.
The police are horrified, and promptly charge Fred with animal
abuse.
As details of the case are publicized, the public is outraged.
Newspa-
pers are flooded with letters demanding that Fred be severely
punished.
There are calls for more severe penalties for animal abuse. Fred
is
denounced as a vile sadist.
Finally, at his trial, Fred explains his behavior, and argues that
he is
blameless and therefore deserves no punishment. He is, he
explains, a
great lover of chocolate. A couple of years ago, he was involved
in a car
accident, which resulted in some head trauma. Upon his release
from
the hospital, having apparently suffered no lasting ill effects, he
visited
his favorite restaurant and ordered their famous rich dark
chocolate
mousse. Imagine his dismay when he discovered that his
experience
of the mousse was a pale shadow of its former self. The mousse
tasted
bland, slightly pleasant, but with none of the intense chocolaty
flavor
Rachels & Rachels_9781538127926.indb 306 17-06-2019
19:00:28
The Right Thing to Do : Readings in Moral Philosophy, edited
by James Rachels, and Stuart Rachels, Rowman &
Littlefield Publishers, 2019. ProQuest Ebook Central,
http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/newschoolarch-
ebooks/detail.action?docID=5798603.
Created from newschoolarch-ebooks on 2020-05-14 19:50:09.
C
o
p
yr
ig
h
t
©
2
0
1
9
.
R
o
w
m
a
n
&
L
itt
le
fie
ld
P
u
b
lis
h
e
rs
.
A
ll
ri
g
h
ts
r
e
se
rv
e
d
.
Torturing Puppies and Eating Meat 307
he remembered so well. The waiter assured him that the recipe
was
unchanged from the last time he had tasted it, just the day
before his
accident. In some consternation, Fred rushed out to buy a bar of
his
favorite Belgian chocolate. Again, he was dismayed to discover
that
his experience of the chocolate was barely even pleasurable.
Extensive
investigation revealed that his experience of other foods
remained
unaffected, but chocolate, in all its forms, now tasted bland and
insipid.
Desperate for a solution to his problem, Fred visited a renowned
gusta-
tory neurologist, Dr. T. Bud. Extensive tests revealed that the
accident
had irreparably damaged the godiva gland, which secretes
cocoamone,
the hormone responsible for the experience of chocolate. Fred
urgently
requested hormone replacement therapy. Dr. Bud informed him
that,
until recently, there had been no known source of cocoamone,
other
than the human godiva gland, and that it was impossible to
collect
cocoamone from one person to be used by another. However, a
chance
discovery had altered the situation. A forensic veterinary
surgeon, per-
forming an autopsy on a severely abused puppy, had discovered
high
concentrations of cocoamone in the puppy’s brain. It turned out
that
puppies, who don’t normally produce cocoamone, could be
stimulated
to do so by extended periods of severe stress and suffering. The
research
that led to this discovery, while gaining tenure for its authors,
had not
been widely publicized, for fear of antagonizing animal welfare
groups.
Although this research clearly gave Fred the hope of tasting
chocolate
again, there were no commercially available sources of puppy-
derived
cocoamone. Lack of demand, combined with fear of bad
publicity, had
deterred drug companies from getting into the puppy torturing
business.
Fred appeals to the court to imagine his anguish, on discovering
that a
solution to his severe deprivation was possible, but not readily
avail-
able. But he wasn’t inclined to sit around bemoaning his cruel
fate. He
did what any chocolate lover would do. He read the research,
and set
up his own cocoamone collection lab in his basement. Six
months of
intense puppy suffering, followed by a brutal death, produced
enough
cocoamone to last him a week, hence the twenty-six cages. He
isn’t a
sadist or an animal abuser, he explains. If there were a method
of col-
lecting cocoamone without torturing puppies, he would gladly
employ
it. He derives no pleasure from the suffering of the puppies
itself. He
sympathizes with those who are horrified by the pain and misery
of the
animals, but the court must realize that human pleasure is at
stake. The
puppies, while undeniably cute, are mere animals. He admits
that he
Rachels & Rachels_9781538127926.indb 307 17-06-2019
19:00:28
The Right Thing to Do : Readings in Moral Philosophy, edited
by James Rachels, and Stuart Rachels, Rowman &
Littlefield Publishers, 2019. ProQuest Ebook Central,
http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/newschoolarch-
ebooks/detail.action?docID=5798603.
Created from newschoolarch-ebooks on 2020-05-14 19:50:09.
C
o
p
yr
ig
h
t
©
2
0
1
9
.
R
o
w
m
a
n
&
L
itt
le
fie
ld
P
u
b
lis
h
e
rs
.
A
ll
ri
g
h
ts
r
e
se
rv
e
d
.
Chapter 28308
would be just as healthy without chocolate, if not more so. But
this isn’t
a matter of survival or health. His life would be unacceptably
impover-
ished without the experience of chocolate.
End of story. Clearly, we are horrified by Fred’s behavior, and
unconvinced by his attempted justification. It is, of course,
unfortunate
for Fred that he can no longer enjoy the taste of chocolate, but
that in no
way excuses the imposition of severe suffering on the puppies. I
expect
near universal agreement with this claim (the exceptions being
those
who are either inhumanly callous or thinking ahead, and wish to
avoid
the following conclusion, to which such agreement commits
them).
No decent person would even contemplate torturing puppies
merely to
enhance a gustatory experience. However, billions of animals
endure
intense suffering every year for precisely this end. Most of the
chicken,
veal, beef, and pork consumed in the United States comes from
inten-
sive confinement facilities, in which the animals live cramped,
stress-
filled lives and endure un-anaesthetized mutilations. The vast
majority
of people would suffer no ill health from the elimination of
meat from
their diets. Quite the reverse. The supposed benefits from this
system
of factory farming, apart from the profits accruing to
agribusiness, are
increased levels of gustatory pleasure for those who claim that
they
couldn’t enjoy a meat-free diet as much as their current meat-
filled
diets. If we are prepared to condemn Fred for torturing puppies
merely
to enhance his gustatory experiences, shouldn’t we similarly
condemn
the millions who purchase and consume factory-raised meat?
Are there
any morally significant differences between Fred’s behavior and
their
behavior?
The first difference that might seem to be relevant is that Fred
tor-
tures the puppies himself, whereas most Americans consume
meat that
comes from animals that have been tortured by others. But is
this really
relevant? What if Fred had been squeamish and had employed
someone
else to torture the puppies and extract the cocoamone? Would
we have
thought any better of Fred? Of course not.
Another difference between Fred and many consumers of
factory-
raised meat is that many, perhaps most, such consumers are
unaware
of the treatment of the animals, before they appear in neatly
wrapped
packages on supermarket shelves. Perhaps I should moderate my
chal-
lenge, then. If we are prepared to condemn Fred for torturing
puppies
merely to enhance his gustatory experiences, shouldn’t we
similarly
condemn those who purchase and consume factory-raised meat,
in full,
Rachels & Rachels_9781538127926.indb 308 17-06-2019
19:00:29
The Right Thing to Do : Readings in Moral Philosophy, edited
by James Rachels, and Stuart Rachels, Rowman &
Littlefield Publishers, 2019. ProQuest Ebook Central,
http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/newschoolarch-
ebooks/detail.action?docID=5798603.
Created from newschoolarch-ebooks on 2020-05-14 19:50:09.
C
o
p
yr
ig
h
t
©
2
0
1
9
.
R
o
w
m
a
n
&
L
itt
le
fie
ld
P
u
b
lis
h
e
rs
.
A
ll
ri
g
h
ts
r
e
se
rv
e
d
.
Torturing Puppies and Eating Meat 309
or even partial, awareness of the suffering endured by the
animals?
While many consumers are still blissfully ignorant of the
appalling
treatment meted out to meat, that number is rapidly dwindling,
thanks
to vigorous publicity campaigns waged by animal welfare
groups. Fur-
thermore, any meat-eating readers of this article are now
deprived of
the excuse of ignorance.
Perhaps a consumer of factory-raised animals could argue as
follows:
While I agree that Fred’s behavior is abominable, mine is
crucially dif-
ferent. If Fred did not consume his chocolate, he would not
raise and
torture puppies (or pay someone else to do so). Therefore Fred
could
prevent the suffering of the puppies. However, if I did not buy
and
consume factory-raised meat, no animals would be spared lives
of mis-
ery. Agribusiness is much too large to respond to the behavior
of one
consumer. Therefore I cannot prevent the suffering of any
animals. I
may well regret the suffering inflicted on animals for the sake
of human
enjoyment. I may even agree that the human enjoyment doesn’t
justify
the suffering. However, since the animals will suffer no matter
what I
do, I may as well enjoy the taste of their flesh.
There are at least two lines of response to this attempted
defense.
First, consider an analogous case. You visit a friend in an exotic
location, say Alabama. Your friend takes you out to eat at the
finest
restaurant in Tuscaloosa. For dessert you select the house
specialty,
“Chocolate Mousse à la Bama,” served with a small cup of
coffee,
which you are instructed to drink before eating the mousse. The
mousse
is quite simply the most delicious dessert you have ever tasted.
Never
before has chocolate tasted so rich and satisfying. Tempted to
order a
second, you ask your friend what makes this mousse so
delicious. He
informs you that the mousse itself is ordinary, but the coffee
contains
a concentrated dose of cocoamone, the newly discovered
chocolate-
enhancing hormone. Researchers at Auburn University have
perfected
a technique for extracting cocoamone from the brains of freshly
slaugh-
tered puppies, who have been subjected to lives of pain and
frustration.
Each puppy’s brain yields four doses, each of which is effective
for
about fifteen minutes, just long enough to enjoy one serving of
mousse.
You are, naturally, horrified and disgusted. You will certainly
not order
another serving, you tell your friend. In fact, you are shocked
that your
friend, who had always seemed to be a morally decent person,
could
have both recommended the dessert to you and eaten one
himself, in
full awareness of the loathsome process necessary for the
experience.
Rachels & Rachels_9781538127926.indb 309 17-06-2019
19:00:29
The Right Thing to Do : Readings in Moral Philosophy, edited
by James Rachels, and Stuart Rachels, Rowman &
Littlefield Publishers, 2019. ProQuest Ebook Central,
http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/newschoolarch-
ebooks/detail.action?docID=5798603.
Created from newschoolarch-ebooks on 2020-05-14 19:50:09.
C
o
p
yr
ig
h
t
©
2
0
1
9
.
R
o
w
m
a
n
&
L
itt
le
fie
ld
P
u
b
lis
h
e
rs
.
A
ll
ri
g
h
ts
r
e
se
rv
e
d
.
Chapter 28310
He agrees that the suffering of the puppies is outrageous, and
that the
gain in human pleasure in no way justifies the appalling
treatment they
have to endure. However, neither he nor you can save any
puppies
by refraining from consuming cocoamone. Cocoamone
production is
now Alabama’s leading industry, surpassing even banjo-making
and
inbreeding.1 The industry is much too large to respond to the
behavior
of one or two consumers. Since the puppies will suffer no
matter what
either of you does, you may as well enjoy the mousse.
If it is as obvious as it seems that a morally decent person, who
is
aware of the details of cocoamone production, couldn’t order
Chocolate
Mousse à la Bama, it should be equally obvious that a morally
decent
person, who is aware of the details of factory farming, can’t
purchase
and consume factory-raised meat. If the attempted excuse of
causal
impotence is compelling in the latter case, it should be
compelling in
the former case. But it isn’t.
The second response to the claim of causal impotence is to deny
it.
Consider the case of chickens, the most cruelly treated of all
animals
raised for human consumption, with the possible exception of
veal
calves. In 1998, almost 8 billion chickens were slaughtered in
the
United States,2 almost all of them raised on factory farms.
Suppose that
there are 250 million chicken eaters in the United States, and
that each
one consumes, on average, 25 chickens per year (this leaves a
fair num-
ber of chickens slaughtered for nonhuman consumption, or for
export).
Clearly, if only one of those chicken eaters gave up eating
chicken, the
industry would not respond. Equally clearly, if they all gave up
eat-
ing chicken, billions of chickens (approximately 6.25 billion per
year)
would not be bred, tortured, and killed. But there must also be
some
number of consumers, far short of 250 million, whose
renunciation of
chicken would cause the industry to reduce the number of
chickens
bred in factory farms. The industry may not be able to respond
to each
individual’s behavior, but it must respond to the behavior of
fairly
large numbers. Suppose that the industry is sensitive to a
reduction in
demand for chicken equivalent to 10,000 people becoming
vegetarians.
(This seems like a reasonable guess, but I have no idea what the
actual
numbers are, nor is it important.) For each group of 10,000 who
give
up chicken, a quarter of a million fewer chickens are bred per
year. It
appears, then, that if you give up eating chicken, you have only
a one in
ten thousand chance of making any difference to the lives of
chickens,
unless it is certain that fewer than 10,000 people will ever give
up eating
Rachels & Rachels_9781538127926.indb 310 17-06-2019
19:00:29
The Right Thing to Do : Readings in Moral Philosophy, edited
by James Rachels, and Stuart Rachels, Rowman &
Littlefield Publishers, 2019. ProQuest Ebook Central,
http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/newschoolarch-
ebooks/detail.action?docID=5798603.
Created from newschoolarch-ebooks on 2020-05-14 19:50:09.
C
o
p
yr
ig
h
t
©
2
0
1
9
.
R
o
w
m
a
n
&
L
itt
le
fie
ld
P
u
b
lis
h
e
rs
.
A
ll
ri
g
h
ts
r
e
se
rv
e
d
.
Torturing Puppies and Eating Meat 311
chicken, in which case you have no chance. Isn’t a one in ten
thousand
chance small enough to render your continued consumption of
chicken
blameless? Not at all. While the chance that your behavior is
harmful
may be small, the harm that is risked is enormous. The larger
the num-
bers needed to make a difference to chicken production, the
larger the
difference such numbers would make. A one in ten thousand
chance
of saving 250,000 chickens per year from excruciating lives is
morally
and mathematically equivalent to the certainty of saving 25
chickens
per year. We commonly accept that even small risks of great
harms are
unacceptable. That is why we disapprove of parents who fail to
secure
their children in car seats or with seat belts, who leave their
small chil-
dren unattended at home, or who drink or smoke heavily during
preg-
nancy. Or consider commercial aircraft safety measures. The
chances
that the oxygen masks, the lifejackets, or the emergency exits
on any
given plane will be called on to save any lives in a given week,
are far
smaller than one in ten thousand. And yet we would be outraged
to
discover that an airline had knowingly allowed a plane to fly for
a week
with non-functioning emergency exits, oxygen masks, and
lifejackets.
So, even if it is true that your giving up factory raised chicken
has only
a tiny chance of preventing suffering, given that the amount of
suffer-
ing that would be prevented is in inverse proportion to your
chance of
preventing it, your continued consumption is not thereby
excused.
But perhaps it is not even true that your giving up chicken has
only
a tiny chance of making any difference. Suppose again that the
poultry
industry only reduces production when a threshold of 10,000
fresh veg-
etarians is reached. Suppose also, as is almost certainly true,
that veg-
etarianism is growing in popularity in the United States (and
elsewhere).
Then, even if you are not the one, newly converted vegetarian,
to reach the
next threshold of 10,000, your conversion will reduce the time
required
before the next threshold is reached. The sooner the threshold is
reached,
the sooner production, and therefore animal suffering, is
reduced. Your
behavior, therefore, does make a difference. Furthermore, many
people
who become vegetarians influence others to become vegetarian,
who in
turn influence others, and so on. It appears, then, that the claim
of causal
impotence is mere wishful thinking, on the part of those meat
lovers who
are morally sensitive enough to realize that human gustatory
pleasure
does not justify inflicting extreme suffering on animals. . . .
I have been unable to discover any morally relevant differences
between the behavior of Fred, the puppy torturer, and the
behavior of
Rachels & Rachels_9781538127926.indb 311 17-06-2019
19:00:29
The Right Thing to Do : Readings in Moral Philosophy, edited
by James Rachels, and Stuart Rachels, Rowman &
Littlefield Publishers, 2019. ProQuest Ebook Central,
http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/newschoolarch-
ebooks/detail.action?docID=5798603.
Created from newschoolarch-ebooks on 2020-05-14 19:50:09.
C
o
p
yr
ig
h
t
©
2
0
1
9
.
R
o
w
m
a
n
&
L
itt
le
fie
ld
P
u
b
lis
h
e
rs
.
A
ll
ri
g
h
ts
r
e
se
rv
e
d
.
Chapter 28312
the millions of people who purchase and consume factory-raised
meat,
at least those who do so in the knowledge that the animals live
lives
of suffering and deprivation. Just as morality demands that we
not tor-
ture puppies merely to enhance our own eating pleasure,
morality also
demands that we not support factory farming by purchasing
factory-
raised meat.
NOTES
1. I realize that I am playing on stereotypes for comic effect.
Banjo-making,
of course, has never really been one of Alabama’s leading
industries.
2. Livestock Slaughter 1998 Summary, NASS, USDA
(Washington, DC:
March 1999), 2; and Poultry Slaughter, NASS, USDA
(Washington, DC: Feb-
ruary 2, 1999), 1f.
Rachels & Rachels_9781538127926.indb 312 17-06-2019
19:00:29
The Right Thing to Do : Readings in Moral Philosophy, edited
by James Rachels, and Stuart Rachels, Rowman &
Littlefield Publishers, 2019. ProQuest Ebook Central,
http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/newschoolarch-
ebooks/detail.action?docID=5798603.
Created from newschoolarch-ebooks on 2020-05-14 19:50:09.
C
o
p
yr
ig
h
t
©
2
0
1
9
.
R
o
w
m
a
n
&
L
itt
le
fie
ld
P
u
b
lis
h
e
rs
.
A
ll
ri
g
h
ts
r
e
se
rv
e
d
.
375
In this selection, J. Gay-Williams offers several standard objec-
tions to euthanasia: that it goes against our natural instincts;
that
it violates human dignity; that it forecloses the possibility of
miraculous cures; that the critically ill, and their caretakers,
might
give up too easily if euthanasia were an option; and, finally,
that
the legalization of euthanasia might lead to horrific abuses.
“J. Gay-Williams” is a pseudonym. We are not told the author’s
real name.
My impression is that euthanasia—the idea, if not the practice—
is
slowly gaining acceptance within our society. Cynics might
attribute
this to an increasing tendency to devalue human life, but I do
not believe
this is the major factor. The acceptance is much more likely to
be the
result of unthinking sympathy and benevolence. Well-
publicized, tragic
stories like that of Karen Quinlan elicit from us deep feelings of
com-
passion. We think to ourselves, “She and her family would be
better off
if she were dead.” It is an easy step from this very human
response to
the view that if someone (and others) would be better off dead,
then it
might be all right to kill that person. Although I respect the
compas-
sion that leads to this conclusion, I believe the conclusion is
wrong.
Chapter 34
The Wrongfulness of Euthanasia
J. Gay-Williams
J. Gay-Williams, “The Wrongfulness of Euthanasia” in
Intervention and Reflection, ed. Ron-
ald Munson (Belmont, CA: Cengage Learning, 2017). Copyright
© 2008, 2012, 2017 Ronald
Munson. Used with permission.
Rachels & Rachels_9781538127926.indb 375 17-06-2019
19:00:37
The Right Thing to Do : Readings in Moral Philosophy, edited
by James Rachels, and Stuart Rachels, Rowman &
Littlefield Publishers, 2019. ProQuest Ebook Central,
http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/newschoolarch-
ebooks/detail.action?docID=5798603.
Created from newschoolarch-ebooks on 2020-05-14 19:25:22.
C
o
p
yr
ig
h
t
©
2
0
1
9
.
R
o
w
m
a
n
&
L
itt
le
fie
ld
P
u
b
lis
h
e
rs
.
A
ll
ri
g
h
ts
r
e
se
rv
e
d
.
Chapter 34376
I want to show that euthanasia is wrong. It is inherently wrong,
but it is
also wrong judged from the standpoints of self-interest and of
practical
effects.
Before presenting my arguments to support this claim, it would
be
well to define “euthanasia.” An essential aspect of euthanasia is
that it
involves taking a human life, either one’s own or that of
another. Also,
the person whose life is taken must be someone who is believed
to
be suffering from some disease or injury from which recovery
cannot
reasonably be expected. Finally, the action must be deliberate
and inten-
tional. Thus, euthanasia is intentionally taking the life of a
presumably
hopeless person. Whether the life is one’s own or that of
another, the
taking of it is still euthanasia.
It is important to be clear about the deliberate and intentional
aspect
of the killing. If a hopeless person is given an injection of the
wrong
drug by mistake and this causes his death, this is wrongful
killing but
not euthanasia. The killing cannot be the result of accident.
Further-
more, if the person is given an injection of a drug that is
believed to
be necessary to treat his disease or better his condition and the
person
dies as a result, then this is neither wrongful killing nor
euthanasia. The
intention was to make the patient well, not kill him. Similarly,
when
a patient’s condition is such that it is not reasonable to hope
that any
medical procedures or treatments will save his life, a failure to
imple-
ment the procedures or treatments is not euthanasia. If the
person dies,
this will be as a result of his injuries or disease and not because
of his
failure to receive treatment.
The failure to continue treatment after it has been realized that
the
patient has little chance of benefiting from it has been
characterized by
some as “passive euthanasia.” This phrase is misleading and
mistaken.
In such cases, the person involved is not killed (the first
essential aspect
of euthanasia), nor is the death of the person intended by the
withhold-
ing of additional treatment (the third essential aspect of
euthanasia).
The aim may be to spare the person additional and unjustifiable
pain, to
save him from the indignities of hopeless manipulations, and to
avoid
increasing the financial and emotional burden on his family.
When I
buy a pencil it is so that I can use it to write, not to contribute
to an
increase in the gross national product (GNP). This may be the
unin-
tended consequence of my action, but it is not the aim of my
action. So
it is with failing to continue the treatment of a dying person. I
intend
Rachels & Rachels_9781538127926.indb 376 17-06-2019
19:00:37
The Right Thing to Do : Readings in Moral Philosophy, edited
by James Rachels, and Stuart Rachels, Rowman &
Littlefield Publishers, 2019. ProQuest Ebook Central,
http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/newschoolarch-
ebooks/detail.action?docID=5798603.
Created from newschoolarch-ebooks on 2020-05-14 19:25:22.
C
o
p
yr
ig
h
t
©
2
0
1
9
.
R
o
w
m
a
n
&
L
itt
le
fie
ld
P
u
b
lis
h
e
rs
.
A
ll
ri
g
h
ts
r
e
se
rv
e
d
.
The Wrongfulness of Euthanasia 377
his death no more than I intend to reduce the GNP by not using
medical
supplies. His is an unintended dying, and so-called “passive
euthanasia”
is not euthanasia at all.
1. THE ARGUMENT FROM NATURE
Every human being has a natural inclination to continue living.
Our
reflexes and responses fit us to fight attackers, flee wild
animals, and
dodge out of the way of trucks. In our daily lives we exercise
the cau-
tion and care necessary to protect ourselves. Our bodies are
similarly
structured for survival right down to the molecular level. When
we are
cut, our capillaries seal shut, our blood clots, and fibrinogen is
produced
to start the process of healing the wound. When we are invaded
by
bacteria, antibodies are produced to fight against the alien
organisms,
and their remains are swept out of the body by special cells
designed
for clean-up work.
Euthanasia does violence to this natural goal of survival. It is
literally
acting against nature because all the processes of nature are
bent towards
the end of bodily survival. Euthanasia defeats these subtle
mechanisms
in a way that, in a particular case, disease and injury might not.
It is possible, but not necessary, to make an appeal to revealed
reli-
gion in this connection. Man as trustee of his body acts against
God,
its rightful possessor, when he takes his own life. He also
violates the
commandment to hold life sacred and never to take it without
just and
compelling cause. But since this appeal will persuade only those
who
are prepared to accept that religion has access to revealed
truths, I shall
not employ this line of argument.
It is enough, I believe, to recognize that the organization of the
human body and our patterns of behavioral responses make the
continu-
ation of life a natural goal. By reason alone, then, we can
recognize that
euthanasia sets us against our own nature. Furthermore, in doing
so,
euthanasia does violence to our dignity. Our dignity comes from
seek-
ing our ends. When one of our goals is survival, and actions are
taken
that eliminate that goal, then our natural dignity suffers. Unlike
animals,
we are conscious through reason of our nature and our ends.
Euthanasia
involves acting as if this dual nature—inclination towards
survival and
awareness of this as an end—did not exist. Thus, euthanasia
denies our
Rachels & Rachels_9781538127926.indb 377 17-06-2019
19:00:38
The Right Thing to Do : Readings in Moral Philosophy, edited
by James Rachels, and Stuart Rachels, Rowman &
Littlefield Publishers, 2019. ProQuest Ebook Central,
http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/newschoolarch-
ebooks/detail.action?docID=5798603.
Created from newschoolarch-ebooks on 2020-05-14 19:25:22.
C
o
p
yr
ig
h
t
©
2
0
1
9
.
R
o
w
m
a
n
&
L
itt
le
fie
ld
P
u
b
lis
h
e
rs
.
A
ll
ri
g
h
ts
r
e
se
rv
e
d
.
Chapter 34378
basic human character and requires that we regard ourselves or
others
as something less than fully human.
2. THE ARGUMENT FROM SELF-INTEREST
The above arguments are, I believe, sufficient to show that
euthanasia
is inherently wrong. But there are reasons for considering it
wrong
when judged by standards other than reason. Because death is
final
and irreversible, euthanasia contains within it the possibility
that we
will work against our own interest if we practice it or allow it to
be
practiced on us.
Contemporary medicine has high standards of excellence and a
proven record of accomplishment, but it does not possess
perfect and
complete knowledge. A mistaken diagnosis is possible, and so is
a
mistaken prognosis. Consequently, we may believe that we are
dying
of a disease when, as a matter of fact, we may not be. We may
think
that we have no hope of recovery when, as a matter of fact, our
chances
are quite good. In such circumstances, if euthanasia were
permitted, we
would die needlessly. Death is final and the chance of error too
great to
approve the practice of euthanasia.
Also, there is always the possibility that an experimental
procedure
or a hitherto untried technique will pull us through. We should
at least
keep this option open, but euthanasia closes it off. Furthermore,
spon-
taneous remission does occur in many cases. For no apparent
reason,
a patient simply recovers when those all around him, including
his
physicians, expected him to die. Euthanasia would just
guarantee their
expectations and leave no room for the “miraculous” recoveries
that
frequently occur.
Finally, knowing that we can take our life at any time (or ask
another to take it) might well incline us to give up too easily.
The
will to live is strong in all of us, but it can be weakened by pain
and
suffering and feelings of hopelessness. If during a bad time we
allow
ourselves to be killed, we never have a chance to reconsider.
Recovery
from a serious illness requires that we fight for it, and anything
that
weakens our determination by suggesting that there is an easy
way
out is ultimately against our own interest. Also, we may be
inclined
towards euthanasia because of our concern for others. If we see
our
Rachels & Rachels_9781538127926.indb 378 17-06-2019
19:00:38
The Right Thing to Do : Readings in Moral Philosophy, edited
by James Rachels, and Stuart Rachels, Rowman &
Littlefield Publishers, 2019. ProQuest Ebook Central,
http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/newschoolarch-
ebooks/detail.action?docID=5798603.
Created from newschoolarch-ebooks on 2020-05-14 19:25:22.
C
o
p
yr
ig
h
t
©
2
0
1
9
.
R
o
w
m
a
n
&
L
itt
le
fie
ld
P
u
b
lis
h
e
rs
.
A
ll
ri
g
h
ts
r
e
se
rv
e
d
.
The Wrongfulness of Euthanasia 379
sickness and suffering as an emotional and financial burden on
our
family, we may feel that to leave our life is to make their lives
easier.
The very presence of the possibility of euthanasia may keep us
from
surviving when we might.
3. THE ARGUMENT FROM PRACTICAL EFFECTS
Doctors and nurses are, for the most part, totally committed to
sav-
ing lives. A life lost is, for them, almost a personal failure, an
insult
to their skills and knowledge. Euthanasia as a practice might
well
alter this. It could have a corrupting influence so that in any
case that
is severe, doctors and nurses might not try hard enough to save
the
patient. They might decide that the patient would simply be
“bet-
ter off dead” and take the steps necessary to make that come
about.
This attitude could then carry over to their dealings with
patients less
seriously ill. The result would be an overall decline in the
quality of
medical care.
Finally, euthanasia as a policy is a slippery slope. A person
appar-
ently hopelessly ill may be allowed to take his own life. Then
he may be
permitted to deputize others to do it for him should he no longer
be able
to act. The judgment of others then becomes the ruling factor.
Already
at this point euthanasia is not personal and voluntary, for others
are
acting “on behalf of” the patient as they see fit. This may well
incline
them to act on behalf of other patients who have not authorized
them
to exercise their judgment. It is only a short step, then, from
voluntary
euthanasia (self-inflicted or authorized) to directed euthanasia
adminis-
tered to a patient who has given no authorization, to involuntary
eutha-
nasia conducted as part of a social policy. Recently many
psychiatrists
and sociologists have argued that we define as “mental illness”
those
forms of behavior that we disapprove of. This gives us license
then to
lock up those who display the behavior. The category of the
“hopelessly
ill” provides the possibility of even worse abuse. Embedded in a
social
policy, it would give society or its representatives the authority
to elimi-
nate all those who might be considered too “ill” to function
normally
any longer. The dangers of euthanasia are too great to all to run
the risk
of approving it in any form. The first slippery step may well
lead to a
serious and harmful fall.
Rachels & Rachels_9781538127926.indb 379 17-06-2019
19:00:38
The Right Thing to Do : Readings in Moral Philosophy, edited
by James Rachels, and Stuart Rachels, Rowman &
Littlefield Publishers, 2019. ProQuest Ebook Central,
http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/newschoolarch-
ebooks/detail.action?docID=5798603.
Created from newschoolarch-ebooks on 2020-05-14 19:25:22.
C
o
p
yr
ig
h
t
©
2
0
1
9
.
R
o
w
m
a
n
&
L
itt
le
fie
ld
P
u
b
lis
h
e
rs
.
A
ll
ri
g
h
ts
r
e
se
rv
e
d
.
Chapter 34380
I hope that I have succeeded in showing why the benevolence
that
inclines us to give approval of euthanasia is misplaced.
Euthanasia is
inherently wrong because it violates the nature and dignity of
human
beings. But even those who are not convinced by this must be
persuaded
that the potential personal and social dangers inherent in
euthanasia are
sufficient to forbid our approving it either as a personal practice
or as
a public policy.
Suffering is surely a terrible thing, and we have a clear duty to
com-
fort those in need and to ease their suffering when we can. But
suffering
is also a natural part of life with values for the individual and
for oth-
ers that we should not overlook. We may legitimately seek for
others
and for ourselves an easeful death, as Arthur Dyck has pointed
out.
Euthanasia, however, is not just an easeful death. It is a
wrongful death.
Euthanasia is not just dying. It is killing.
Rachels & Rachels_9781538127926.indb 380 17-06-2019
19:00:38
The Right Thing to Do : Readings in Moral Philosophy, edited
by James Rachels, and Stuart Rachels, Rowman &
Littlefield Publishers, 2019. ProQuest Ebook Central,
http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/newschoolarch-
ebooks/detail.action?docID=5798603.
Created from newschoolarch-ebooks on 2020-05-14 19:25:22.
C
o
p
yr
ig
h
t
©
2
0
1
9
.
R
o
w
m
a
n
&
L
itt
le
fie
ld
P
u
b
lis
h
e
rs
.
A
ll
ri
g
h
ts
r
e
se
rv
e
d
.
197
The Australian philosopher Peter Singer (1946–) is the most
widely read author in the field of ethics. In this essay, he
consid-
ers whether it is morally defensible for well-off people to spend
money on luxuries while other people starve.
As I write this, in November 1971, people are dying in East
Bengal
from lack of food, shelter, and medical care. The suffering and
death
that are occurring there now are not inevitable, not unavoidable
in any
fatalistic sense of the term. Constant poverty, a cyclone, and a
civil
war have turned at least nine million people into destitute
refugees;
nevertheless, it is not beyond the capacity of the richer nations
to give
enough assistance to reduce any further suffering to very small
propor-
tions. The decisions and actions of human beings can prevent
this kind
of suffering. Unfortunately, human beings have not made the
necessary
decisions. At the individual level, people have, with very few
excep-
tions, not responded to the situation in any significant way.
Generally
speaking, people have not given large sums to relief funds; they
have
not written to their parliamentary representatives demanding
increased
government assistance; they have not demonstrated in the
streets, held
symbolic fasts, or done anything else directed toward providing
the
Chapter 19
Famine, Affluence, and Morality
Peter Singer
Peter Singer, “Famine, Affluence, and Morality” in Philosophy
and Public Affairs, vol. 1,
no. 1 (spring 1972): 229–43. Copyright © 1972 Peter Singer.
Used with permission of the
author.
Rachels & Rachels_9781538127926.indb 197 17-06-2019
19:00:12
The Right Thing to Do : Readings in Moral Philosophy, edited
by James Rachels, and Stuart Rachels, Rowman &
Littlefield Publishers, 2019. ProQuest Ebook Central,
http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/newschoolarch-
ebooks/detail.action?docID=5798603.
Created from newschoolarch-ebooks on 2020-05-14 19:30:46.
C
op
yr
ig
ht
©
2
01
9.
R
ow
m
an
&
L
itt
le
fie
ld
P
ub
lis
he
rs
. A
ll
rig
ht
s
re
se
rv
ed
.
Chapter 19198
refugees with the means to satisfy their essential needs. At the
govern-
ment level, no government has given the sort of massive aid that
would
enable the refugees to survive for more than a few days. Britain,
for
instance, has given rather more than most countries. It has, to
date,
given £14,750,000. For comparative purposes, Britain’s share of
the
non-recoverable development costs of the Anglo-French
Concorde
project is already in excess of £275,000,000, and on present
estimates
will reach £440,000,000. The implication is that the British
government
values a supersonic transport more than thirty times as highly as
it val-
ues the lives of the nine million refugees. Australia is another
country
which, on a per capita basis, is well up in the “aid to Bengal”
table.
Australia’s aid, however, amounts to less than one-twelfth of
the cost
of Sydney’s new opera house. . . .
These are the essential facts about the present situation in
Bengal. So
far as it concerns us here, there is nothing unique about this
situation
except its magnitude. The Bengal emergency is just the latest
and most
acute of a series of major emergencies in various parts of the
world,
arising both from natural and from manmade causes. There are
also
many parts of the world in which people die from malnutrition
and lack
of food independent of any special emergency. I take Bengal as
my
example only because it is the present concern, and because the
size
of the problem has ensured that it has been given adequate
publicity.
Neither individuals nor governments can claim to be unaware of
what
is happening there.
What are the moral implications of a situation like this? In what
fol-
lows, I shall argue that the way people in relatively affluent
countries
react to a situation like that in Bengal cannot be justified;
indeed, the
whole way we look at moral issues—our moral conceptual
scheme—
needs to be altered, and with it, the way of life that has come to
be taken
for granted in our society. . . .
I begin with the assumption that suffering and death from lack
of
food, shelter, and medical care are bad. I think most people will
agree
about this, although one may reach the same view by different
routes. I
shall not argue for this view. People can hold all sorts of
eccentric posi-
tions, and perhaps from some of them it would not follow that
death by
starvation is in itself bad. It is difficult, perhaps impossible, to
refute
such positions, and so for brevity I will henceforth take this
assumption
as accepted. Those who disagree need read no further.
Rachels & Rachels_9781538127926.indb 198 17-06-2019
19:00:12
The Right Thing to Do : Readings in Moral Philosophy, edited
by James Rachels, and Stuart Rachels, Rowman &
Littlefield Publishers, 2019. ProQuest Ebook Central,
http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/newschoolarch-
ebooks/detail.action?docID=5798603.
Created from newschoolarch-ebooks on 2020-05-14 19:30:46.
C
op
yr
ig
ht
©
2
01
9.
R
ow
m
an
&
L
itt
le
fie
ld
P
ub
lis
he
rs
. A
ll
rig
ht
s
re
se
rv
ed
.
Famine, Affluence, and Morality 199
My next point is this: if it is in our power to prevent something
bad
from happening, without thereby sacrificing anything of
comparable
moral importance, we ought, morally, to do it. By “without
sacrificing
anything of comparable moral importance” I mean without
causing
anything else comparably bad to happen, or doing something
that is
wrong in itself, or failing to promote some moral good,
comparable in
significance to the bad thing that we can prevent. This principle
seems
almost as uncontroversial as the last one. It requires us only to
prevent
what is bad, and to promote what is good, and it requires this of
us only
when we can do it without sacrificing anything that is, from the
moral
point of view, comparably important. I could even, as far as the
appli-
cation of my argument to the Bengal emergency is concerned,
qualify
the point so as to make it: if it is in our power to prevent
something
very bad from happening, without thereby sacrificing anything
morally
significant, we ought, morally, to do it. An application of this
principle
would be as follows: if I am walking past a shallow pond and
see a child
drowning in it, I ought to wade in and pull the child out. This
will mean
getting my clothes muddy, but this is insignificant, while the
death of
the child would presumably be a very bad thing.
The uncontroversial appearance of the principle just stated is
decep-
tive. If it were acted upon, even in its qualified form, our lives,
our soci-
ety, and our world would be fundamentally changed. For the
principle
takes, firstly, no account of proximity or distance. It makes no
moral
difference whether the person I can help is a neighbor’s child
ten yards
from me or a Bengali whose name I shall never know, ten
thousand
miles away. Secondly, the principle makes no distinction
between cases
in which I am the only person who could possibly do anything
and cases
in which I am just one among millions in the same position.
I do not think I need to say much in defense of the refusal to
take
proximity and distance into account. The fact that a person is
physi-
cally near to us, so that we have personal contact with him, may
make
it more likely that we shall assist him, but this does not show
that we
ought to help him rather than another who happens to be further
away.
If we accept any principle of impartiality, universalizability,
equality, or
whatever, we cannot discriminate against someone merely
because he is
far away from us (or we are far away from him). Admittedly, it
is pos-
sible that we are in a better position to judge what needs to be
done to
help a person near to us than one far away, and perhaps also to
provide
Rachels & Rachels_9781538127926.indb 199 17-06-2019
19:00:13
The Right Thing to Do : Readings in Moral Philosophy, edited
by James Rachels, and Stuart Rachels, Rowman &
Littlefield Publishers, 2019. ProQuest Ebook Central,
http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/newschoolarch-
ebooks/detail.action?docID=5798603.
Created from newschoolarch-ebooks on 2020-05-14 19:30:46.
C
op
yr
ig
ht
©
2
01
9.
R
ow
m
an
&
L
itt
le
fie
ld
P
ub
lis
he
rs
. A
ll
rig
ht
s
re
se
rv
ed
.
Chapter 19200
the assistance we judge to be necessary. If this were the case, it
would
be a reason for helping those near to us first. This may once
have been
a justification for being more concerned with the poor in one’s
town
than with famine victims in India. Unfortunately for those who
like to
keep their moral responsibilities limited, instant communication
and
swift transportation have changed the situation. From the moral
point of
view, the development of the world into a “global village” has
made an
important, though still unrecognized, difference to our moral
situation.
Expert observers and supervisors, sent out by famine relief
organiza-
tions or permanently stationed in famine-prone areas, can direct
our aid
to a refugee in Bengal almost as effectively as we could get it to
some-
one in our own block. There would seem, therefore, to be no
possible
justification for discriminating on geographical grounds.
There may be a greater need to defend the second implication of
my principle—that the fact that there are millions of other
people in
the same position, in respect to the Bengali refugees, as I am,
does not
make the situation significantly different from a situation in
which I
am the only person who can prevent something very bad from
occur-
ring. Again, of course, I admit that there is a psychological
difference
between the cases; one feels less guilty about doing nothing if
one can
point to others, similarly placed, who have also done nothing.
Yet this
can make no real difference to our moral obligations. Should I
consider
that I am less obliged to pull the drowning child out of the pond
if on
looking around I see other people, no further away than I am,
who have
also noticed the child but are doing nothing? One has only to
ask this
question to see the absurdity of the view that numbers lessen
obligation.
It is a view that is an ideal excuse for inactivity; unfortunately
most of
the major evils—poverty, overpopulation, pollution—are
problems in
which everyone is almost equally involved.
The view that numbers do make a difference can be made
plausible
if stated in this way: if everyone in circumstances like mine
gave £5 to
the Bengal Relief Fund, there would be enough to provide food,
shelter,
and medical care for the refugees; there is no reason why I
should give
more than anyone else in the same circumstances as I am;
therefore I
have no obligation to give more than £5. Each premise in this
argument
is true, and the argument looks sound. It may convince us,
unless we
notice that it is based on a hypothetical premise, although the
conclu-
sion is not stated hypothetically. The argument would be sound
if the
Rachels & Rachels_9781538127926.indb 200 17-06-2019
19:00:13
The Right Thing to Do : Readings in Moral Philosophy, edited
by James Rachels, and Stuart Rachels, Rowman &
Littlefield Publishers, 2019. ProQuest Ebook Central,
http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/newschoolarch-
ebooks/detail.action?docID=5798603.
Created from newschoolarch-ebooks on 2020-05-14 19:30:46.
C
op
yr
ig
ht
©
2
01
9.
R
ow
m
an
&
L
itt
le
fie
ld
P
ub
lis
he
rs
. A
ll
rig
ht
s
re
se
rv
ed
.
Famine, Affluence, and Morality 201
conclusion were: if everyone in circumstances like mine were to
give
£5, I would have no obligation to give more than £5. If the
conclusion
were so stated, however, it would be obvious that the argument
has no
bearing on a situation in which it is not the case that everyone
else gives
£5. This, of course, is the actual situation. It is more or less
certain that
not everyone in circumstances like mine will give £5. So there
will not
be enough to provide the needed food, shelter, and medical care.
There-
fore by giving more than £5 I will prevent more suffering than I
would
if I gave just £5. . . .
If my argument so far has been sound, neither our distance from
a preventable evil nor the number of other people who, in
respect to
that evil, are in the same situation as we are, lessens our
obligation to
mitigate or prevent that evil. I shall therefore take as
established the
principle I asserted earlier. As I have already said, I need to
assert it
only in its qualified form: if it is in our power to prevent
something very
bad from happening, without thereby sacrificing anything else
morally
significant, we ought, morally, to do it.
The outcome of this argument is that our traditional moral
categories
are upset. The traditional distinction between duty and charity
cannot
be drawn, or at least, not in the place we normally draw it.
Giving
money to the Bengal Relief Fund is regarded as an act of charity
in
our society. The bodies which collect money are known as
“charities.”
These organizations see themselves in this way—if you send
them
a check, you will be thanked for your “generosity.” Because
giving
money is regarded as an act of charity, it is not thought that
there is
anything wrong with not giving. The charitable man may be
praised,
but the man who is not charitable is not condemned. People do
not feel
in any way ashamed or guilty about spending money on new
clothes or
a new car instead of giving it to famine relief. (Indeed, the
alternative
does not occur to them.) This way of looking at the matter
cannot be
justified. When we buy new clothes not to keep ourselves warm
but to
look “well-dressed” we are not providing for any important
need. We
would not be sacrificing anything significant if we were to
continue to
wear our old clothes, and give the money to famine relief. By
doing so,
we would be preventing another person from starving. It follows
from
what I have said earlier that we ought to give money away,
rather than
spend it on clothes which we do not need to keep us warm. To
do so is
not charitable, or generous. Nor is it the kind of act which
philosophers
Rachels & Rachels_9781538127926.indb 201 17-06-2019
19:00:13
The Right Thing to Do : Readings in Moral Philosophy, edited
by James Rachels, and Stuart Rachels, Rowman &
Littlefield Publishers, 2019. ProQuest Ebook Central,
http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/newschoolarch-
ebooks/detail.action?docID=5798603.
Created from newschoolarch-ebooks on 2020-05-14 19:30:46.
C
op
yr
ig
ht
©
2
01
9.
R
ow
m
an
&
L
itt
le
fie
ld
P
ub
lis
he
rs
. A
ll
rig
ht
s
re
se
rv
ed
.
Chapter 19202
and theologians have called “supererogatory”—an act which it
would
be good to do, but not wrong not to do. On the contrary, we
ought to
give the money away, and it is wrong not to do so. . . .
One objection to the position I have taken might be simply that
it
is too drastic a revision of our moral scheme. People do not
ordinarily
judge in the way I have suggested they should. Most people
reserve
their moral condemnation for those who violate some moral
norm,
such as the norm against taking another person’s property. They
do not
condemn those who indulge in luxury instead of giving to
famine relief.
But given that I did not set out to present a morally neutral
description
of the way people make moral judgments, the way people do in
fact
judge has nothing to do with the validity of my conclusion. My
conclu-
sion follows from the principle which I advanced earlier, and
unless that
principle is rejected, or the arguments are shown to be unsound,
I think
the conclusion must stand, however strange it appears. . . .
It has been argued by some writers, among them Sidgwick and
Urm-
son, that we need to have a basic moral code which is not too
far beyond
the capacities of the ordinary man, for otherwise there will be a
general
breakdown of compliance with the moral code. Crudely stated,
this
argument suggests that if we tell people that they ought to
refrain from
murder and give everything they do not really need to famine
relief,
they will do neither, whereas if we tell them that they ought to
refrain
from murder and that it is good to give to famine relief but not
wrong
not to do so, they will at least refrain from murder. The issue
here is:
Where should we draw the line between conduct that is required
and
conduct that is good although not required, so as to get the best
possible
result? This would seem to be an empirical question, although a
very
difficult one. One objection to the Sidgwick-Urmson line of
argument
is that it takes insufficient account of the effect that moral
standards can
have on the decisions we make. Given a society in which a
wealthy man
who gives 5 percent of his income to famine relief is regarded
as most
generous, it is not surprising that a proposal that we all ought to
give
away half our incomes will be thought to be absurdly
unrealistic. In a
society which held that no man should have more than enough
while
others have less than they need, such a proposal might seem
narrow-
minded. What it is possible for a man to do and what he is
likely to do
are both, I think, very greatly influenced by what people around
him
are doing and expecting him to do. In any case, the possibility
that by
spreading the idea that we ought to be doing very much more
than we
Rachels & Rachels_9781538127926.indb 202 17-06-2019
19:00:13
The Right Thing to Do : Readings in Moral Philosophy, edited
by James Rachels, and Stuart Rachels, Rowman &
Littlefield Publishers, 2019. ProQuest Ebook Central,
http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/newschoolarch-
ebooks/detail.action?docID=5798603.
Created from newschoolarch-ebooks on 2020-05-14 19:30:46.
C
op
yr
ig
ht
©
2
01
9.
R
ow
m
an
&
L
itt
le
fie
ld
P
ub
lis
he
rs
. A
ll
rig
ht
s
re
se
rv
ed
.
Famine, Affluence, and Morality 203
are to relieve famine we shall bring about a general breakdown
of moral
behavior seems remote. If the stakes are an end to widespread
starva-
tion, it is worth the risk. Finally, it should be emphasized that
these
considerations are relevant only to the issue of what we should
require
from others, and not to what we ourselves ought to do.
The second objection to my attack on the present distinction
between
duty and charity is one which has from time to time been made
against
utilitarianism. It follows from some forms of utilitarian theory
that we
all ought, morally, to be working full time to increase the
balance of
happiness over misery. The position I have taken here would not
lead
to this conclusion in all circumstances, for if there were no bad
occur-
rences that we could prevent without sacrificing something of
com-
parable moral importance, my argument would have no
application.
Given the present conditions in many parts of the world,
however, it
does follow from my argument that we ought, morally, to be
working
full time to relieve great suffering of the sort that occurs as a
result of
famine or other disasters. Of course, mitigating circumstances
can be
adduced—for instance, that if we wear ourselves out through
over-
work, we shall be less effective than we would otherwise have
been.
Nevertheless, when all considerations of this sort have been
taken into
account, the conclusion remains: we ought to be preventing as
much
suffering as we can without sacrificing something else of
comparable
moral importance. This conclusion is one which we may be
reluctant
to face. I cannot see, though, why it should be regarded as a
criticism
of the position for which I have argued, rather than a criticism
of our
ordinary standards of behavior. Since most people are self-
interested to
some degree, very few of us are likely to do everything that we
ought
to do. It would, however, hardly be honest to take this as
evidence that
it is not the case that we ought to do it.
It may still be thought that my conclusions are so wildly out of
line
with what everyone else thinks and has always thought that
there must
be something wrong with the argument somewhere. In order to
show
that my conclusions, while certainly contrary to contemporary
Western
moral standards, would not have seemed so extraordinary at
other times
and in other places, I would like to quote a passage from a
writer not
normally thought of as a way-out radical, Thomas Aquinas.
Now, according to the natural order instituted by divine
providence, mate-
rial goods are provided for the satisfaction of human needs.
Therefore
Rachels & Rachels_9781538127926.indb 203 17-06-2019
19:00:13
The Right Thing to Do : Readings in Moral Philosophy, edited
by James Rachels, and Stuart Rachels, Rowman &
Littlefield Publishers, 2019. ProQuest Ebook Central,
http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/newschoolarch-
ebooks/detail.action?docID=5798603.
Created from newschoolarch-ebooks on 2020-05-14 19:30:46.
C
op
yr
ig
ht
©
2
01
9.
R
ow
m
an
&
L
itt
le
fie
ld
P
ub
lis
he
rs
. A
ll
rig
ht
s
re
se
rv
ed
.
Chapter 19204
the division and appropriation of property, which proceeds from
human
law, must not hinder the satisfaction of man’s necessity from
such goods.
Equally, whatever a man has in superabundance is owed, of
natural right,
to the poor for their sustenance. So Ambrosius says, and it is
also to be
found in the Decretum Gratiani: “The bread which you withhold
belongs
to the hungry; the clothing you shut away, to the naked; and the
money
you bury in the earth is the redemption and freedom of the
penniless.”1
I now want to consider a number of points, more practical than
philo-
sophical, which are relevant to the application of the moral
conclusion
we have reached. These points challenge not the idea that we
ought to
be doing all we can to prevent starvation, but the idea that
giving away
a great deal of money is the best means to this end. . . .
Another, more serious reason for not giving to famine relief
funds is
that until there is effective population control, relieving famine
merely
postpones starvation. If we save the Bengal refugees now,
others, per-
haps the children of these refugees, will face starvation in a few
years’
time. In support of this, one may cite the now well-known facts
about
the population explosion and the relatively limited scope for
expanded
production.
. . . I accept that the earth cannot support indefinitely a
population
rising at the present rate. This certainly poses a problem for
anyone
who thinks it important to prevent famine. Again, however, one
could
accept the argument without drawing the conclusion that it
absolves one
from any obligation to do anything to prevent famine. The
conclusion
that should be drawn is that the best means of preventing
famine, in the
long run, is population control. It would then follow from the
position
reached earlier that one ought to be doing all one can to
promote popu-
lation control (unless one held that all forms of population
control were
wrong in themselves, or would have significantly bad
consequences).
Since there are organizations working specifically for
population con-
trol, one would then support them rather than more orthodox
methods
of preventing famine.
A third point raised by the conclusion reached earlier relates to
the
question of just how much we all ought to be giving away. One
pos-
sibility . . . is that we ought to give until we reach the level of
marginal
utility—that is, the level at which, by giving more, I would
cause as
much suffering to myself or my dependents as I would relieve
by my
gift. This would mean, of course, that one would reduce oneself
to very
Rachels & Rachels_9781538127926.indb 204 17-06-2019
19:00:13
The Right Thing to Do : Readings in Moral Philosophy, edited
by James Rachels, and Stuart Rachels, Rowman &
Littlefield Publishers, 2019. ProQuest Ebook Central,
http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/newschoolarch-
ebooks/detail.action?docID=5798603.
Created from newschoolarch-ebooks on 2020-05-14 19:30:46.
C
op
yr
ig
ht
©
2
01
9.
R
ow
m
an
&
L
itt
le
fie
ld
P
ub
lis
he
rs
. A
ll
rig
ht
s
re
se
rv
ed
.
Famine, Affluence, and Morality 205
near the material circumstances of a Bengali refugee. It will be
recalled
that earlier I put forward both a strong and a moderate version
of the
principle of preventing bad occurrences. The strong version,
which
required us to prevent bad things from happening unless in
doing so
we would be sacrificing something of comparable moral
significance,
does seem to require reducing ourselves to the level of marginal
utility.
I should also say that the strong version seems to me to be the
correct
one. I proposed the more moderate version—that we should
prevent
bad occurrences unless, to do so, we had to sacrifice something
morally
significant—only in order to show that, even on this surely
undeniable
principle, a great change in our way of life is required. On the
more
moderate principle, it may not follow that we ought to reduce
ourselves
to the level of marginal utility, for one might hold that to
reduce oneself
and one’s family to this level is to cause something
significantly bad to
happen. Whether this is so I shall not discuss, since, as I have
said, I
can see no good reason for holding the moderate version of the
principle
rather than the strong version. Even if we accepted the principle
only
in its moderate form, however, it should be clear that we would
have to
give away enough to ensure that the consumer society,
dependent as it is
on people spending on trivia rather than giving to famine relief,
would
slow down and perhaps disappear entirely. There are several
reasons
why this would be desirable in itself. The value and necessity of
eco-
nomic growth are now being questioned not only by
conservationists,
but by economists as well. There is no doubt, too, that the
consumer
society has had a distorting effect on the goals and purposes of
its mem-
bers. Yet looking at the matter purely from the point of view of
overseas
aid, there must be a limit to the extent to which we should
deliberately
slow down our economy; for it might be the case that if we gave
away,
say, 40 percent of our Gross National Product (GNP), we would
slow
down the economy so much that in absolute terms we would be
giving
less than if we gave 25 percent of the much larger GNP that we
would
have if we limited our contribution to this smaller percentage.
I mention this only as an indication of the sort of factor that one
would have to take into account in working out an ideal. Since
Western
societies generally consider 1 percent of the GNP an acceptable
level
for overseas aid, the matter is entirely academic. Nor does it
affect the
question of how much an individual should give in a society in
which
very few are giving substantial amounts.
Rachels & Rachels_9781538127926.indb 205 17-06-2019
19:00:14
The Right Thing to Do : Readings in Moral Philosophy, edited
by James Rachels, and Stuart Rachels, Rowman &
Littlefield Publishers, 2019. ProQuest Ebook Central,
http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/newschoolarch-
ebooks/detail.action?docID=5798603.
Created from newschoolarch-ebooks on 2020-05-14 19:30:46.
C
op
yr
ig
ht
©
2
01
9.
R
ow
m
an
&
L
itt
le
fie
ld
P
ub
lis
he
rs
. A
ll
rig
ht
s
re
se
rv
ed
.
Chapter 19206
. . . The issue is one which faces everyone who has more money
than he
needs to support himself and his dependents, or who is in a
position to
take some sort of political action. These categories must include
practi-
cally every teacher and student of philosophy in the universities
of the
Western world. If philosophy is to deal with matters that are
relevant
to both teachers and students, this is an issue that philosophers
should
discuss.
Discussion, though, is not enough. What is the point of relating
phi-
losophy to public (and personal) affairs if we do not take our
conclu-
sions seriously? In this instance, taking our conclusion
seriously means
acting upon it. The philosopher will not find it any easier than
anyone
else to alter his attitudes and way of life to the extent that, if I
am right,
is involved in doing everything that we ought to be doing. At
the very
least, though, one can make a start. The philosopher who does
so will
have to sacrifice some of the benefits of the consumer society,
but he
can find compensation in the satisfaction of a way of life in
which
theory and practice, if not yet in harmony, are at least coming
together.
NOTE
1. Summa Theologica, II-II, Question 66, Article 7, in Aquinas,
Selected
Political Writings, ed. A. P. d’Entrèves, trans. J. G. Dawson
(Oxford: Basil
Blackwell, 1948), p. 171.
Rachels & Rachels_9781538127926.indb 206 17-06-2019
19:00:14
The Right Thing to Do : Readings in Moral Philosophy, edited
by James Rachels, and Stuart Rachels, Rowman &
Littlefield Publishers, 2019. ProQuest Ebook Central,
http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/newschoolarch-
ebooks/detail.action?docID=5798603.
Created from newschoolarch-ebooks on 2020-05-14 19:30:46.
C
op
yr
ig
ht
©
2
01
9.
R
ow
m
369
James Rachels wrote The End of Life: Euthanasia and Morality
(1986). Here he defends the “argument from mercy.”
Euthanasia,
he thinks, is justified when death is the only way to escape
awful
pain. In Rachels’ main example, the pain is suffered by someone
dying from cancer.
Rachels himself died of cancer in 2003. At the end of his life,
nothing persuaded him to change his view of euthanasia. But he
did wonder whether the argument from mercy would require less
intentional killing than he had thought. Often a humane death
occurs via “permanent sedation.” This is when a dying patient is
given more and more pain medication for pain relief, which
causes
the patient to lose consciousness (or “go to sleep”) before
dying.
Under such circumstances, the intention to kill is unnecessary.
The single most powerful argument in support of euthanasia is
the
argument from mercy. It is also an exceptionally simple
argument, at
least in its main idea, which makes one uncomplicated point.
Termi-
nally ill patients sometimes suffer pain so horrible that it is
beyond the
comprehension of those who have not actually experienced it.
Their
suffering can be so terrible that we do not even like to read
about it or
Chapter 33
The Morality of Euthanasia
James Rachels
James Rachels, “The Morality of Euthanasia” in Philosophy and
Public Affairs, vol. 1, no. 1
(autumn 1971): 47–66. Used with permission.
Rachels & Rachels_9781538127926.indb 369 17-06-2019
19:00:37
The Right Thing to Do : Readings in Moral Philosophy, edited
by James Rachels, and Stuart Rachels, Rowman &
Littlefield Publishers, 2019. ProQuest Ebook Central,
http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/newschoolarch-
ebooks/detail.action?docID=5798603.
Created from newschoolarch-ebooks on 2020-05-14 19:24:15.
C
op
yr
ig
ht
©
2
01
9.
R
ow
m
an
&
L
itt
le
fie
ld
P
ub
lis
he
rs
. A
ll
rig
ht
s
re
se
rv
ed
.
Chapter 33370
think about it; we recoil even from the description of such
agony. The
argument from mercy says euthanasia is justified because it
provides
an end to that.
The great Irish satirist Jonathan Swift took eight years to die,
while,
in the words of Joseph Fletcher, “His mind crumbled to pieces.”
At
times the pain in his blinded eyes was so intense he had to be
restrained
from tearing them out with his own hands. Knives and other
potential
instruments of suicide had to be kept from him. For the last
three years
of his life, he could do nothing but sit and drool; and when he
finally
293Peter Singer has written about assisted reproduction, a.docx
293Peter Singer has written about assisted reproduction, a.docx
293Peter Singer has written about assisted reproduction, a.docx
293Peter Singer has written about assisted reproduction, a.docx
293Peter Singer has written about assisted reproduction, a.docx
293Peter Singer has written about assisted reproduction, a.docx
293Peter Singer has written about assisted reproduction, a.docx
293Peter Singer has written about assisted reproduction, a.docx
293Peter Singer has written about assisted reproduction, a.docx
293Peter Singer has written about assisted reproduction, a.docx
293Peter Singer has written about assisted reproduction, a.docx
293Peter Singer has written about assisted reproduction, a.docx
293Peter Singer has written about assisted reproduction, a.docx
293Peter Singer has written about assisted reproduction, a.docx
293Peter Singer has written about assisted reproduction, a.docx
293Peter Singer has written about assisted reproduction, a.docx
293Peter Singer has written about assisted reproduction, a.docx
293Peter Singer has written about assisted reproduction, a.docx
293Peter Singer has written about assisted reproduction, a.docx
293Peter Singer has written about assisted reproduction, a.docx
293Peter Singer has written about assisted reproduction, a.docx
293Peter Singer has written about assisted reproduction, a.docx
293Peter Singer has written about assisted reproduction, a.docx
293Peter Singer has written about assisted reproduction, a.docx
293Peter Singer has written about assisted reproduction, a.docx
293Peter Singer has written about assisted reproduction, a.docx
293Peter Singer has written about assisted reproduction, a.docx
293Peter Singer has written about assisted reproduction, a.docx
293Peter Singer has written about assisted reproduction, a.docx
293Peter Singer has written about assisted reproduction, a.docx
293Peter Singer has written about assisted reproduction, a.docx
293Peter Singer has written about assisted reproduction, a.docx
293Peter Singer has written about assisted reproduction, a.docx
293Peter Singer has written about assisted reproduction, a.docx
293Peter Singer has written about assisted reproduction, a.docx
293Peter Singer has written about assisted reproduction, a.docx
293Peter Singer has written about assisted reproduction, a.docx
293Peter Singer has written about assisted reproduction, a.docx
293Peter Singer has written about assisted reproduction, a.docx
293Peter Singer has written about assisted reproduction, a.docx
293Peter Singer has written about assisted reproduction, a.docx
293Peter Singer has written about assisted reproduction, a.docx

More Related Content

More from BHANU281672

6 pagesThe following sections are in the final consulting .docx
6 pagesThe following sections are in the final consulting .docx6 pagesThe following sections are in the final consulting .docx
6 pagesThe following sections are in the final consulting .docxBHANU281672
 
600 words needed1. What do we mean by the New Public Administr.docx
600 words needed1. What do we mean by the New Public Administr.docx600 words needed1. What do we mean by the New Public Administr.docx
600 words needed1. What do we mean by the New Public Administr.docxBHANU281672
 
6 peer responses due in 24 hours Each set of 2 responses wil.docx
6 peer responses due in 24 hours Each set of 2 responses wil.docx6 peer responses due in 24 hours Each set of 2 responses wil.docx
6 peer responses due in 24 hours Each set of 2 responses wil.docxBHANU281672
 
6 page paper onWhat is second language acquisition and why is .docx
6 page paper onWhat is second language acquisition and why is .docx6 page paper onWhat is second language acquisition and why is .docx
6 page paper onWhat is second language acquisition and why is .docxBHANU281672
 
600 Words1) Specify some of the ways in which human resource m.docx
600 Words1) Specify some of the ways in which human resource m.docx600 Words1) Specify some of the ways in which human resource m.docx
600 Words1) Specify some of the ways in which human resource m.docxBHANU281672
 
612020 Originality Reporthttpsucumberlands.blackboard.docx
612020 Originality Reporthttpsucumberlands.blackboard.docx612020 Originality Reporthttpsucumberlands.blackboard.docx
612020 Originality Reporthttpsucumberlands.blackboard.docxBHANU281672
 
61520, 256 PMGlobal Innovation and Intellectual Property.docx
61520, 256 PMGlobal Innovation and Intellectual Property.docx61520, 256 PMGlobal Innovation and Intellectual Property.docx
61520, 256 PMGlobal Innovation and Intellectual Property.docxBHANU281672
 
6 Developing Strategic and Operational PlansIngram Publish.docx
6 Developing Strategic and Operational PlansIngram Publish.docx6 Developing Strategic and Operational PlansIngram Publish.docx
6 Developing Strategic and Operational PlansIngram Publish.docxBHANU281672
 
6212020 Originality Reporthttpsucumberlands.blackboar.docx
6212020 Originality Reporthttpsucumberlands.blackboar.docx6212020 Originality Reporthttpsucumberlands.blackboar.docx
6212020 Originality Reporthttpsucumberlands.blackboar.docxBHANU281672
 
617httpsdrive.google.comdriveu0mobilefolders1e8xYisfDL.docx
617httpsdrive.google.comdriveu0mobilefolders1e8xYisfDL.docx617httpsdrive.google.comdriveu0mobilefolders1e8xYisfDL.docx
617httpsdrive.google.comdriveu0mobilefolders1e8xYisfDL.docxBHANU281672
 
6.2 What protocols comprise TLS6.3 What is the difference.docx
6.2 What protocols comprise TLS6.3 What is the difference.docx6.2 What protocols comprise TLS6.3 What is the difference.docx
6.2 What protocols comprise TLS6.3 What is the difference.docxBHANU281672
 
6.2 What protocols comprise TLS6.3 What is the difference bet.docx
6.2 What protocols comprise TLS6.3 What is the difference bet.docx6.2 What protocols comprise TLS6.3 What is the difference bet.docx
6.2 What protocols comprise TLS6.3 What is the difference bet.docxBHANU281672
 
6-3 Discussion Making DecisionsDiscussion Topic Starts Jun 5, 2.docx
6-3 Discussion Making DecisionsDiscussion Topic Starts Jun 5, 2.docx6-3 Discussion Making DecisionsDiscussion Topic Starts Jun 5, 2.docx
6-3 Discussion Making DecisionsDiscussion Topic Starts Jun 5, 2.docxBHANU281672
 
5An American in IndiaWhat is my inheritance To what am .docx
5An American in IndiaWhat is my inheritance To what am .docx5An American in IndiaWhat is my inheritance To what am .docx
5An American in IndiaWhat is my inheritance To what am .docxBHANU281672
 
6 PEER RESPONSES DUE IN 24 HOURS.. EACH SET OF 2 HAS ITS OWN INSTRUC.docx
6 PEER RESPONSES DUE IN 24 HOURS.. EACH SET OF 2 HAS ITS OWN INSTRUC.docx6 PEER RESPONSES DUE IN 24 HOURS.. EACH SET OF 2 HAS ITS OWN INSTRUC.docx
6 PEER RESPONSES DUE IN 24 HOURS.. EACH SET OF 2 HAS ITS OWN INSTRUC.docxBHANU281672
 
6 peer responses due in 18 hours Each set of 2 responses will ha.docx
6 peer responses due in 18 hours Each set of 2 responses will ha.docx6 peer responses due in 18 hours Each set of 2 responses will ha.docx
6 peer responses due in 18 hours Each set of 2 responses will ha.docxBHANU281672
 
5I.Observer Effects and Examiner BiasChisum and Turvey.docx
5I.Observer Effects and Examiner BiasChisum and Turvey.docx5I.Observer Effects and Examiner BiasChisum and Turvey.docx
5I.Observer Effects and Examiner BiasChisum and Turvey.docxBHANU281672
 
6 Change Management StagesA Management Checklist to Guide Your E.docx
6 Change Management StagesA Management Checklist to Guide Your E.docx6 Change Management StagesA Management Checklist to Guide Your E.docx
6 Change Management StagesA Management Checklist to Guide Your E.docxBHANU281672
 
5How to prevent falls in nursing home patients.docx
5How to prevent falls in nursing home patients.docx5How to prevent falls in nursing home patients.docx
5How to prevent falls in nursing home patients.docxBHANU281672
 
5Needs Statement and Management PlanNeeds Statement and .docx
5Needs Statement and Management PlanNeeds Statement and .docx5Needs Statement and Management PlanNeeds Statement and .docx
5Needs Statement and Management PlanNeeds Statement and .docxBHANU281672
 

More from BHANU281672 (20)

6 pagesThe following sections are in the final consulting .docx
6 pagesThe following sections are in the final consulting .docx6 pagesThe following sections are in the final consulting .docx
6 pagesThe following sections are in the final consulting .docx
 
600 words needed1. What do we mean by the New Public Administr.docx
600 words needed1. What do we mean by the New Public Administr.docx600 words needed1. What do we mean by the New Public Administr.docx
600 words needed1. What do we mean by the New Public Administr.docx
 
6 peer responses due in 24 hours Each set of 2 responses wil.docx
6 peer responses due in 24 hours Each set of 2 responses wil.docx6 peer responses due in 24 hours Each set of 2 responses wil.docx
6 peer responses due in 24 hours Each set of 2 responses wil.docx
 
6 page paper onWhat is second language acquisition and why is .docx
6 page paper onWhat is second language acquisition and why is .docx6 page paper onWhat is second language acquisition and why is .docx
6 page paper onWhat is second language acquisition and why is .docx
 
600 Words1) Specify some of the ways in which human resource m.docx
600 Words1) Specify some of the ways in which human resource m.docx600 Words1) Specify some of the ways in which human resource m.docx
600 Words1) Specify some of the ways in which human resource m.docx
 
612020 Originality Reporthttpsucumberlands.blackboard.docx
612020 Originality Reporthttpsucumberlands.blackboard.docx612020 Originality Reporthttpsucumberlands.blackboard.docx
612020 Originality Reporthttpsucumberlands.blackboard.docx
 
61520, 256 PMGlobal Innovation and Intellectual Property.docx
61520, 256 PMGlobal Innovation and Intellectual Property.docx61520, 256 PMGlobal Innovation and Intellectual Property.docx
61520, 256 PMGlobal Innovation and Intellectual Property.docx
 
6 Developing Strategic and Operational PlansIngram Publish.docx
6 Developing Strategic and Operational PlansIngram Publish.docx6 Developing Strategic and Operational PlansIngram Publish.docx
6 Developing Strategic and Operational PlansIngram Publish.docx
 
6212020 Originality Reporthttpsucumberlands.blackboar.docx
6212020 Originality Reporthttpsucumberlands.blackboar.docx6212020 Originality Reporthttpsucumberlands.blackboar.docx
6212020 Originality Reporthttpsucumberlands.blackboar.docx
 
617httpsdrive.google.comdriveu0mobilefolders1e8xYisfDL.docx
617httpsdrive.google.comdriveu0mobilefolders1e8xYisfDL.docx617httpsdrive.google.comdriveu0mobilefolders1e8xYisfDL.docx
617httpsdrive.google.comdriveu0mobilefolders1e8xYisfDL.docx
 
6.2 What protocols comprise TLS6.3 What is the difference.docx
6.2 What protocols comprise TLS6.3 What is the difference.docx6.2 What protocols comprise TLS6.3 What is the difference.docx
6.2 What protocols comprise TLS6.3 What is the difference.docx
 
6.2 What protocols comprise TLS6.3 What is the difference bet.docx
6.2 What protocols comprise TLS6.3 What is the difference bet.docx6.2 What protocols comprise TLS6.3 What is the difference bet.docx
6.2 What protocols comprise TLS6.3 What is the difference bet.docx
 
6-3 Discussion Making DecisionsDiscussion Topic Starts Jun 5, 2.docx
6-3 Discussion Making DecisionsDiscussion Topic Starts Jun 5, 2.docx6-3 Discussion Making DecisionsDiscussion Topic Starts Jun 5, 2.docx
6-3 Discussion Making DecisionsDiscussion Topic Starts Jun 5, 2.docx
 
5An American in IndiaWhat is my inheritance To what am .docx
5An American in IndiaWhat is my inheritance To what am .docx5An American in IndiaWhat is my inheritance To what am .docx
5An American in IndiaWhat is my inheritance To what am .docx
 
6 PEER RESPONSES DUE IN 24 HOURS.. EACH SET OF 2 HAS ITS OWN INSTRUC.docx
6 PEER RESPONSES DUE IN 24 HOURS.. EACH SET OF 2 HAS ITS OWN INSTRUC.docx6 PEER RESPONSES DUE IN 24 HOURS.. EACH SET OF 2 HAS ITS OWN INSTRUC.docx
6 PEER RESPONSES DUE IN 24 HOURS.. EACH SET OF 2 HAS ITS OWN INSTRUC.docx
 
6 peer responses due in 18 hours Each set of 2 responses will ha.docx
6 peer responses due in 18 hours Each set of 2 responses will ha.docx6 peer responses due in 18 hours Each set of 2 responses will ha.docx
6 peer responses due in 18 hours Each set of 2 responses will ha.docx
 
5I.Observer Effects and Examiner BiasChisum and Turvey.docx
5I.Observer Effects and Examiner BiasChisum and Turvey.docx5I.Observer Effects and Examiner BiasChisum and Turvey.docx
5I.Observer Effects and Examiner BiasChisum and Turvey.docx
 
6 Change Management StagesA Management Checklist to Guide Your E.docx
6 Change Management StagesA Management Checklist to Guide Your E.docx6 Change Management StagesA Management Checklist to Guide Your E.docx
6 Change Management StagesA Management Checklist to Guide Your E.docx
 
5How to prevent falls in nursing home patients.docx
5How to prevent falls in nursing home patients.docx5How to prevent falls in nursing home patients.docx
5How to prevent falls in nursing home patients.docx
 
5Needs Statement and Management PlanNeeds Statement and .docx
5Needs Statement and Management PlanNeeds Statement and .docx5Needs Statement and Management PlanNeeds Statement and .docx
5Needs Statement and Management PlanNeeds Statement and .docx
 

Recently uploaded

Q4-W6-Restating Informational Text Grade 3
Q4-W6-Restating Informational Text Grade 3Q4-W6-Restating Informational Text Grade 3
Q4-W6-Restating Informational Text Grade 3JemimahLaneBuaron
 
Introduction to AI in Higher Education_draft.pptx
Introduction to AI in Higher Education_draft.pptxIntroduction to AI in Higher Education_draft.pptx
Introduction to AI in Higher Education_draft.pptxpboyjonauth
 
CARE OF CHILD IN INCUBATOR..........pptx
CARE OF CHILD IN INCUBATOR..........pptxCARE OF CHILD IN INCUBATOR..........pptx
CARE OF CHILD IN INCUBATOR..........pptxGaneshChakor2
 
Mastering the Unannounced Regulatory Inspection
Mastering the Unannounced Regulatory InspectionMastering the Unannounced Regulatory Inspection
Mastering the Unannounced Regulatory InspectionSafetyChain Software
 
Sanyam Choudhary Chemistry practical.pdf
Sanyam Choudhary Chemistry practical.pdfSanyam Choudhary Chemistry practical.pdf
Sanyam Choudhary Chemistry practical.pdfsanyamsingh5019
 
Crayon Activity Handout For the Crayon A
Crayon Activity Handout For the Crayon ACrayon Activity Handout For the Crayon A
Crayon Activity Handout For the Crayon AUnboundStockton
 
URLs and Routing in the Odoo 17 Website App
URLs and Routing in the Odoo 17 Website AppURLs and Routing in the Odoo 17 Website App
URLs and Routing in the Odoo 17 Website AppCeline George
 
Paris 2024 Olympic Geographies - an activity
Paris 2024 Olympic Geographies - an activityParis 2024 Olympic Geographies - an activity
Paris 2024 Olympic Geographies - an activityGeoBlogs
 
Presiding Officer Training module 2024 lok sabha elections
Presiding Officer Training module 2024 lok sabha electionsPresiding Officer Training module 2024 lok sabha elections
Presiding Officer Training module 2024 lok sabha electionsanshu789521
 
POINT- BIOCHEMISTRY SEM 2 ENZYMES UNIT 5.pptx
POINT- BIOCHEMISTRY SEM 2 ENZYMES UNIT 5.pptxPOINT- BIOCHEMISTRY SEM 2 ENZYMES UNIT 5.pptx
POINT- BIOCHEMISTRY SEM 2 ENZYMES UNIT 5.pptxSayali Powar
 
“Oh GOSH! Reflecting on Hackteria's Collaborative Practices in a Global Do-It...
“Oh GOSH! Reflecting on Hackteria's Collaborative Practices in a Global Do-It...“Oh GOSH! Reflecting on Hackteria's Collaborative Practices in a Global Do-It...
“Oh GOSH! Reflecting on Hackteria's Collaborative Practices in a Global Do-It...Marc Dusseiller Dusjagr
 
The basics of sentences session 2pptx copy.pptx
The basics of sentences session 2pptx copy.pptxThe basics of sentences session 2pptx copy.pptx
The basics of sentences session 2pptx copy.pptxheathfieldcps1
 
Software Engineering Methodologies (overview)
Software Engineering Methodologies (overview)Software Engineering Methodologies (overview)
Software Engineering Methodologies (overview)eniolaolutunde
 
PSYCHIATRIC History collection FORMAT.pptx
PSYCHIATRIC   History collection FORMAT.pptxPSYCHIATRIC   History collection FORMAT.pptx
PSYCHIATRIC History collection FORMAT.pptxPoojaSen20
 
18-04-UA_REPORT_MEDIALITERAСY_INDEX-DM_23-1-final-eng.pdf
18-04-UA_REPORT_MEDIALITERAСY_INDEX-DM_23-1-final-eng.pdf18-04-UA_REPORT_MEDIALITERAСY_INDEX-DM_23-1-final-eng.pdf
18-04-UA_REPORT_MEDIALITERAСY_INDEX-DM_23-1-final-eng.pdfssuser54595a
 
A Critique of the Proposed National Education Policy Reform
A Critique of the Proposed National Education Policy ReformA Critique of the Proposed National Education Policy Reform
A Critique of the Proposed National Education Policy ReformChameera Dedduwage
 
Introduction to ArtificiaI Intelligence in Higher Education
Introduction to ArtificiaI Intelligence in Higher EducationIntroduction to ArtificiaI Intelligence in Higher Education
Introduction to ArtificiaI Intelligence in Higher Educationpboyjonauth
 
Science 7 - LAND and SEA BREEZE and its Characteristics
Science 7 - LAND and SEA BREEZE and its CharacteristicsScience 7 - LAND and SEA BREEZE and its Characteristics
Science 7 - LAND and SEA BREEZE and its CharacteristicsKarinaGenton
 

Recently uploaded (20)

Model Call Girl in Bikash Puri Delhi reach out to us at 🔝9953056974🔝
Model Call Girl in Bikash Puri  Delhi reach out to us at 🔝9953056974🔝Model Call Girl in Bikash Puri  Delhi reach out to us at 🔝9953056974🔝
Model Call Girl in Bikash Puri Delhi reach out to us at 🔝9953056974🔝
 
Q4-W6-Restating Informational Text Grade 3
Q4-W6-Restating Informational Text Grade 3Q4-W6-Restating Informational Text Grade 3
Q4-W6-Restating Informational Text Grade 3
 
Introduction to AI in Higher Education_draft.pptx
Introduction to AI in Higher Education_draft.pptxIntroduction to AI in Higher Education_draft.pptx
Introduction to AI in Higher Education_draft.pptx
 
CARE OF CHILD IN INCUBATOR..........pptx
CARE OF CHILD IN INCUBATOR..........pptxCARE OF CHILD IN INCUBATOR..........pptx
CARE OF CHILD IN INCUBATOR..........pptx
 
Mastering the Unannounced Regulatory Inspection
Mastering the Unannounced Regulatory InspectionMastering the Unannounced Regulatory Inspection
Mastering the Unannounced Regulatory Inspection
 
Staff of Color (SOC) Retention Efforts DDSD
Staff of Color (SOC) Retention Efforts DDSDStaff of Color (SOC) Retention Efforts DDSD
Staff of Color (SOC) Retention Efforts DDSD
 
Sanyam Choudhary Chemistry practical.pdf
Sanyam Choudhary Chemistry practical.pdfSanyam Choudhary Chemistry practical.pdf
Sanyam Choudhary Chemistry practical.pdf
 
Crayon Activity Handout For the Crayon A
Crayon Activity Handout For the Crayon ACrayon Activity Handout For the Crayon A
Crayon Activity Handout For the Crayon A
 
URLs and Routing in the Odoo 17 Website App
URLs and Routing in the Odoo 17 Website AppURLs and Routing in the Odoo 17 Website App
URLs and Routing in the Odoo 17 Website App
 
Paris 2024 Olympic Geographies - an activity
Paris 2024 Olympic Geographies - an activityParis 2024 Olympic Geographies - an activity
Paris 2024 Olympic Geographies - an activity
 
Presiding Officer Training module 2024 lok sabha elections
Presiding Officer Training module 2024 lok sabha electionsPresiding Officer Training module 2024 lok sabha elections
Presiding Officer Training module 2024 lok sabha elections
 
POINT- BIOCHEMISTRY SEM 2 ENZYMES UNIT 5.pptx
POINT- BIOCHEMISTRY SEM 2 ENZYMES UNIT 5.pptxPOINT- BIOCHEMISTRY SEM 2 ENZYMES UNIT 5.pptx
POINT- BIOCHEMISTRY SEM 2 ENZYMES UNIT 5.pptx
 
“Oh GOSH! Reflecting on Hackteria's Collaborative Practices in a Global Do-It...
“Oh GOSH! Reflecting on Hackteria's Collaborative Practices in a Global Do-It...“Oh GOSH! Reflecting on Hackteria's Collaborative Practices in a Global Do-It...
“Oh GOSH! Reflecting on Hackteria's Collaborative Practices in a Global Do-It...
 
The basics of sentences session 2pptx copy.pptx
The basics of sentences session 2pptx copy.pptxThe basics of sentences session 2pptx copy.pptx
The basics of sentences session 2pptx copy.pptx
 
Software Engineering Methodologies (overview)
Software Engineering Methodologies (overview)Software Engineering Methodologies (overview)
Software Engineering Methodologies (overview)
 
PSYCHIATRIC History collection FORMAT.pptx
PSYCHIATRIC   History collection FORMAT.pptxPSYCHIATRIC   History collection FORMAT.pptx
PSYCHIATRIC History collection FORMAT.pptx
 
18-04-UA_REPORT_MEDIALITERAСY_INDEX-DM_23-1-final-eng.pdf
18-04-UA_REPORT_MEDIALITERAСY_INDEX-DM_23-1-final-eng.pdf18-04-UA_REPORT_MEDIALITERAСY_INDEX-DM_23-1-final-eng.pdf
18-04-UA_REPORT_MEDIALITERAСY_INDEX-DM_23-1-final-eng.pdf
 
A Critique of the Proposed National Education Policy Reform
A Critique of the Proposed National Education Policy ReformA Critique of the Proposed National Education Policy Reform
A Critique of the Proposed National Education Policy Reform
 
Introduction to ArtificiaI Intelligence in Higher Education
Introduction to ArtificiaI Intelligence in Higher EducationIntroduction to ArtificiaI Intelligence in Higher Education
Introduction to ArtificiaI Intelligence in Higher Education
 
Science 7 - LAND and SEA BREEZE and its Characteristics
Science 7 - LAND and SEA BREEZE and its CharacteristicsScience 7 - LAND and SEA BREEZE and its Characteristics
Science 7 - LAND and SEA BREEZE and its Characteristics
 

293Peter Singer has written about assisted reproduction, a.docx

  • 1. 293 Peter Singer has written about assisted reproduction, animal rights, abortion, infanticide, the environment, and famine relief. Because of his controversial beliefs, Singer’s appointment to Princeton University in 1999 created a public uproar reminiscent of 1940, when the City College of New York appointed Bertrand Russell, one of the twentieth century’s greatest philosophers, to a one-year professorship. In Russell’s case, the outcry culminated in a judge’s ruling that canceled the state university’s appoint- ment. Commenting on the case, Albert Einstein said, “Great spirits have always found violent opposition from mediocrities.” Since Princeton is a private university, Singer’s ordeal stayed out of the courts. The treatment of nonhuman animals has traditionally been regarded as a trivial matter. Until recently, almost every ethicist who wrote on the subject provided some rationale for excluding animals from moral concern. Aristotle said that, in the natural order of things, animals exist to serve human purposes. The Chris- tian tradition added that man alone is made in God’s image and that animals do not have souls. Immanuel Kant said that animals are not self-conscious, so we can have no duties to them. Chapter 27 All Animals Are Equal
  • 2. Peter Singer Peter Singer, “All Animals Are Equal” in Animal Rights and Human Obligations, ed. Tom Regan and Peter Singer (Upper Saddle River, NJ: Pearson Education, 1989), 215–26. Copy- right © 1989 Peter Singer. Used with permission of the author. Rachels & Rachels_9781538127926.indb 293 17-06-2019 19:00:27 The Right Thing to Do : Readings in Moral Philosophy, edited by James Rachels, and Stuart Rachels, Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, 2019. ProQuest Ebook Central, http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/newschoolarch- ebooks/detail.action?docID=5798603. Created from newschoolarch-ebooks on 2020-05-14 19:49:07. C op yr ig ht © 2 01 9. R ow m
  • 4. The utilitarians took a different view, holding that we should consider the interests of all beings, human and nonhuman. Peter Singer (1946–) took up this argument in the mid-1970s. Today, Professor Singer splits his time between Princeton University in the United States and Melbourne University in Australia. “Animal Liberation” may sound more like a parody of other liberation movements than a serious objective. The idea of “The Rights of Ani- mals” actually was once used to parody the case for women’s rights. When Mary Wollstonecraft, a forerunner of today’s feminists, pub- lished her Vindication of the Rights of Woman in 1792, her views were widely regarded as absurd, and before long an anonymous publication appeared entitled A Vindication of the Rights of Brutes. The author of this satirical work (now known to have been Thomas Taylor, a distin- guished Cambridge philosopher) tried to refute Mary Wollstonecraft’s arguments by showing that they could be carried one stage further. If the argument for equality was sound when applied to women, why should it not be applied to dogs, cats, and horses? The reasoning seemed to hold for these “brutes” too; yet to hold that brutes had rights was manifestly absurd. Therefore the reasoning by which this
  • 5. conclusion had been reached must be unsound, and if unsound when applied to brutes, it must also be unsound when applied to women, since the very same arguments had been used in each case. In order to explain the basis of the case for the equality of animals, it will be helpful to start with an examination of the case for the equality of women. Let us assume that we wish to defend the case for women’s rights against the attack by Thomas Taylor. How should we reply? One way in which we might reply is by saying that the case for equal- ity between men and women cannot validly be extended to nonhuman animals. Women have a right to vote, for instance, because they are just as capable of making rational decisions about the future as men are; dogs, on the other hand, are incapable of understanding the significance of voting, so they cannot have the right to vote. There are many other obvious ways in which men and women resemble each other closely, while humans and animals differ greatly. So, it might be said, men and women are similar beings and should have similar rights, while humans and nonhumans are different and should not have equal rights.
  • 6. Rachels & Rachels_9781538127926.indb 294 17-06-2019 19:00:27 The Right Thing to Do : Readings in Moral Philosophy, edited by James Rachels, and Stuart Rachels, Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, 2019. ProQuest Ebook Central, http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/newschoolarch- ebooks/detail.action?docID=5798603. Created from newschoolarch-ebooks on 2020-05-14 19:49:07. C op yr ig ht © 2 01 9. R ow m an & L itt le fie
  • 7. ld P ub lis he rs . A ll rig ht s re se rv ed . All Animals Are Equal 295 The reasoning behind this reply to Taylor’s analogy is correct up to a point, but it does not go far enough. There are obviously important differences between humans and other animals, and these differences must give rise to some differences in the rights that each have.
  • 8. Recog- nizing this evident fact, however, is no barrier to the case for extending the basic principle of equality to nonhuman animals. The differences that exist between men and women are equally undeniable, and the supporters of Women’s Liberation are aware that these differences may give rise to different rights. Many feminists hold that women have the right to an abortion on request. It does not follow that since these same feminists are campaigning for equality between men and women they must support the right of men to have abortions too. Since a man cannot have an abortion, it is meaningless to talk of his right to have one. Since dogs can’t vote, it is meaningless to talk of their right to vote. There is no reason why either Women’s Liberation or Animal Liberation should get involved in such nonsense. The extension of the basic principle of equality from one group to another does not imply that we must treat both groups in exactly the same way, or grant exactly the same rights to both groups. Whether we should do so will depend on the nature of the members of the two groups. The basic principle of equality does not require equal or identical treatment; it requires equal consideration. Equal consideration for different beings may lead to different
  • 9. treatment and different rights. So there is a different way of replying to Taylor’s attempt to parody the case for women’s rights, a way that does not deny the obvious dif- ferences between human beings and nonhumans but goes more deeply into the question of equality and concludes by finding nothing absurd in the idea that the basic principle of equality applies to so-called brutes. At this point such a conclusion may appear odd; but if we examine more deeply the basis on which our opposition to discrimination on grounds of race or sex ultimately rests, we will see that we would be on shaky ground if we were to demand equality for blacks, women, and other groups of oppressed humans while denying equal consideration to nonhumans. To make this clear we need to see, first, exactly why racism and sexism are wrong. When we say that all human beings, whatever their race, creed, or sex, are equal, what is it that we are asserting? Those who wish to defend hierarchical, inegalitarian societ- ies have often pointed out that by whatever test we choose it simply is not true that all humans are equal. Like it or not we must face the fact
  • 10. Rachels & Rachels_9781538127926.indb 295 17-06-2019 19:00:27 The Right Thing to Do : Readings in Moral Philosophy, edited by James Rachels, and Stuart Rachels, Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, 2019. ProQuest Ebook Central, http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/newschoolarch- ebooks/detail.action?docID=5798603. Created from newschoolarch-ebooks on 2020-05-14 19:49:07. C op yr ig ht © 2 01 9. R ow m an & L itt le fie
  • 11. ld P ub lis he rs . A ll rig ht s re se rv ed . Chapter 27296 that humans come in different shapes and sizes; they come with differ- ent moral capacities, different intellectual abilities, different amounts of benevolent feeling and sensitivity to the needs of others, different abili- ties to communicate effectively, and different capacities to
  • 12. experience pleasure and pain. In short, if the demand for equality were based on the actual equality of all human beings, we would have to stop demanding equality. Still, one might cling to the view that the demand for equality among human beings is based on the actual equality of the different races and sexes. Although, it may be said, humans differ as individuals, there are no differences between the races and sexes as such. From the mere fact that a person is black or a woman we cannot infer anything about that person’s intellectual or moral capacities. This, it may be said, is why racism and sexism are wrong. The white racist claims that whites are superior to blacks, but this is false; although there are differences among individuals, some blacks are superior to some whites in all of the capacities and abilities that could conceivably be relevant. The opponent of sexism would say the same: a person’s sex is no guide to his or her abilities, and this is why it is unjustifiable to discriminate on the basis of sex. The existence of individual variations that cut across the lines of race or sex, however, provides us with no defense at all against
  • 13. a more sophisticated opponent of equality, one who proposes that, say, the interests of all those with IQ scores below 100 be given less consid- eration than the interests of those with ratings over 100. Perhaps those scoring below the mark would, in this society, be made the slaves of those scoring higher. Would a hierarchical society of this sort really be so much better than one based on race or sex? I think not. But if we tie the moral principle of equality to the factual equality of the dif- ferent races or sexes, taken as a whole, our opposition to racism and sexism does not provide us with any basis for objecting to this kind of inegalitarianism. There is a second important reason why we ought not to base our opposition to racism and sexism on any kind of factual equality, even the limited kind that asserts that variations in capacities and abilities are spread evenly among the different races and between the sexes: we can have no absolute guarantee that these capacities and abilities really are distributed evenly, without regard to race or sex, among human beings. So far as actual abilities are concerned there do seem to be certain
  • 14. Rachels & Rachels_9781538127926.indb 296 17-06-2019 19:00:27 The Right Thing to Do : Readings in Moral Philosophy, edited by James Rachels, and Stuart Rachels, Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, 2019. ProQuest Ebook Central, http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/newschoolarch- ebooks/detail.action?docID=5798603. Created from newschoolarch-ebooks on 2020-05-14 19:49:07. C op yr ig ht © 2 01 9. R ow m an & L itt le fie
  • 15. ld P ub lis he rs . A ll rig ht s re se rv ed . All Animals Are Equal 297 measurable differences both among races and between sexes. These differences do not, of course, appear in every case, but only when aver- ages are taken. More important still, we do not yet know how many of these differences are really due to the different genetic
  • 16. endowments of the different races and sexes, and how many are due to poor schools, poor housing, and other factors that are the result of past and continuing discrimination. Perhaps all of the important differences will eventually prove to be environmental rather than genetic. Anyone opposed to rac- ism and sexism will certainly hope that this will be so, for it will make the task of ending discrimination a lot easier; nevertheless, it would be dangerous to rest the case against racism and sexism on the belief that all significant differences are environmental in origin. The opponent of, say, racism who takes this line will be unable to avoid conceding that if differences in ability did after all prove to have some genetic connection with race, racism would in some way be defensible. Fortunately there is no need to pin the case for equality to one par- ticular outcome of a scientific investigation. The appropriate response to those who claim to have found evidence of genetically based differ- ences in ability among the races or between the sexes is not to stick to the belief that the genetic explanation must be wrong, whatever evidence to the contrary may turn up; instead we should make it quite clear that the claim to equality does not depend on intelligence,
  • 17. moral capacity, physical strength, or similar matters of fact. Equality is a moral idea, not an assertion of fact. There is no logically compelling reason for assuming that a factual difference in ability between two people justifies any difference in the amount of consideration we give to their needs and interests. The principle of the equality of human beings is not a description of an alleged actual equality among humans: it is a prescription of how we should treat human beings. Jeremy Bentham, the founder of the reforming utilitarian school of moral philosophy, incorporated the essential basis of moral equality into his system of ethics by means of the formula: “Each to count for one and none for more than one.” In other words, the interests of every being affected by an action are to be taken into account and given the same weight as the like interests of any other being. A later utilitar- ian, Henry Sidgwick, put the point in this way: “The good of any one individual is of no more importance, from the point of view (if I may say so) of the Universe, than the good of any other.” More recently the leading figures in contemporary moral philosophy have shown a great
  • 18. Rachels & Rachels_9781538127926.indb 297 17-06-2019 19:00:27 The Right Thing to Do : Readings in Moral Philosophy, edited by James Rachels, and Stuart Rachels, Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, 2019. ProQuest Ebook Central, http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/newschoolarch- ebooks/detail.action?docID=5798603. Created from newschoolarch-ebooks on 2020-05-14 19:49:07. C op yr ig ht © 2 01 9. R ow m an & L itt le fie
  • 19. ld P ub lis he rs . A ll rig ht s re se rv ed . Chapter 27298 deal of agreement in specifying as a fundamental presupposition of their moral theories some similar requirement that works to give everyone’s interests equal consideration—although these writers generally cannot agree on how this requirement is best formulated.
  • 20. It is an implication of this principle of equality that our concern for others and our readiness to consider their interests ought not to depend on what they are like or on what abilities they may possess. Precisely what our concern or consideration requires us to do may vary according to the characteristics of those affected by what we do: concern for the well-being of children growing up in America would require that we teach them to read; concern for the well-being of pigs may require no more than that we leave them with other pigs in a place where there is adequate food and room to run freely. But the basic element— the tak- ing into account of the interests of the being, whatever those interests may be—must, according to the principle of equality, be extended to all beings, black or white, masculine or feminine, human or nonhuman. Thomas Jefferson, who was responsible for writing the principle of the equality of men into the American Declaration of Independence, saw this point. It led him to oppose slavery even though he was unable to free himself fully from his slaveholding background. He wrote in a letter to the author of a book that emphasized the notable intellectual
  • 21. achievements of Negroes in order to refute the then common view that they had limited intellectual capacities: Be assured that no person living wishes more sincerely than I do, to see a complete refutation of the doubts I myself have entertained and expressed on the grade of understanding allotted to them by nature, and to find that they are on a par with ourselves . . . but whatever be their degree of talent it is no measure of their rights. Because Sir Isaac Newton was superior to others in understanding, he was not therefore lord of the property or persons of others. Similarly, when in the 1850s the call for women’s rights was raised in the United States, a remarkable black feminist named Sojourner Truth made the same point in more robust terms at a feminist convention: They talk about this thing in the head; what do they call it? [“Intel- lect,” whispered someone nearby.] That’s it. What’s that got to do with women’s rights or Negroes’ rights? If my cup won’t hold but a pint and yours holds a quart, wouldn’t you be mean not to let me have my little half-measure full? Rachels & Rachels_9781538127926.indb 298 17-06-2019 19:00:27
  • 22. The Right Thing to Do : Readings in Moral Philosophy, edited by James Rachels, and Stuart Rachels, Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, 2019. ProQuest Ebook Central, http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/newschoolarch- ebooks/detail.action?docID=5798603. Created from newschoolarch-ebooks on 2020-05-14 19:49:07. C op yr ig ht © 2 01 9. R ow m an & L itt le fie ld
  • 23. P ub lis he rs . A ll rig ht s re se rv ed . All Animals Are Equal 299 It is on this basis that the case against racism and the case against sex- ism must both ultimately rest; and it is in accordance with this principle that the attitude that we may call “speciesism,” by analogy with racism, must also be condemned. Speciesism—the word is not an attractive one, but I can think of no better term—is a prejudice or attitude
  • 24. of bias in favor of the interests of members of one’s own species and against those of members of other species. It should be obvious that the fun- damental objections to racism and sexism made by Thomas Jefferson and Sojourner Truth apply equally to speciesism. If possessing a higher degree of intelligence does not entitle one human to use another for his or her own ends, how can it entitle humans to exploit nonhumans for the same purpose? Many philosophers and other writers have proposed the principle of equal consideration of interests, in some form or other, as a basic moral principle; but not many of them have recognized that this principle applies to members of other species as well as to our own. Jeremy Ben- tham was one of the few who did realize this. In a forward- looking pas- sage written at a time when black slaves had been freed by the French but in the British dominions were still being treated in the way we now treat animals, Bentham wrote: The day may come when the rest of the animal creation may acquire those rights which never could have been withholden from them but by the hand of tyranny. The French have already discovered that
  • 25. the black- ness of the skin is no reason why a human being should be abandoned without redress to the caprice of a tormentor. It may one day come to be recognized that the number of the legs, the villosity of the skin, or the termination of the os sacrum are reasons equally insufficient for aban- doning a sensitive being to the same fate. What else is it that should trace the insuperable line? Is it the faculty of reason, or perhaps the faculty of discourse? But a full-grown horse or dog is beyond comparison a more rational, as well as a more conversable animal, than an infant of a day or a week or even a month, old. But suppose they were otherwise, what would it avail? The question is not, Can they reason? nor Can they talk? but, Can they suffer? In this passage Bentham points to the capacity for suffering as the vital characteristic that gives a being the right to equal consideration. The capacity for suffering—or more strictly, for suffering and/or enjoy- ment or happiness—is not just another characteristic like the capacity Rachels & Rachels_9781538127926.indb 299 17-06-2019 19:00:27 The Right Thing to Do : Readings in Moral Philosophy, edited
  • 26. by James Rachels, and Stuart Rachels, Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, 2019. ProQuest Ebook Central, http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/newschoolarch- ebooks/detail.action?docID=5798603. Created from newschoolarch-ebooks on 2020-05-14 19:49:07. C op yr ig ht © 2 01 9. R ow m an & L itt le fie ld P
  • 27. ub lis he rs . A ll rig ht s re se rv ed . Chapter 27300 for language or higher mathematics. Bentham is not saying that those who try to mark “the insuperable line” that determines whether the interests of a being should be considered happen to have chosen the wrong characteristic. By saying that we must consider the interests of all beings with the capacity for suffering or enjoyment Bentham does not arbitrarily exclude from consideration any interests at all—
  • 28. as those who draw the line with reference to the possession of reason or lan- guage do. The capacity for suffering and enjoyment is a prerequisite for having interests at all, a condition that must be satisfied before we can speak of interests in a meaningful way. It would be nonsense to say that it was not in the interests of a stone to be kicked along the road by a schoolboy. A stone does not have interests because it cannot suf- fer. Nothing that we can do to it could possibly make any difference to its welfare. The capacity for suffering and enjoyment is, however, not only necessary, but also sufficient for us to say that a being has inter- ests—at an absolute minimum, an interest in not suffering. A mouse, for example, does have an interest in not being kicked along the road, because it will suffer if it is. Although Bentham speaks of “rights” in the passage I have quoted, the argument is really about equality rather than about rights. Indeed, in a different passage, Bentham famously described “natural rights” as “nonsense” and “natural and imprescriptable rights” as “nonsense upon stilts.” He talked of moral rights as a shorthand way of referring to protections that people and animals morally ought to have;
  • 29. but the real weight of the moral argument does not rest on the assertion of the existence of the right, for this in turn has to be justified on the basis of the possibilities for suffering and happiness. In this way we can argue for equality for animals without getting embroiled in philosophical con- troversies about the ultimate nature of rights. In misguided attempts to refute the arguments of this book, some philosophers have gone to much trouble developing arguments to show that animals do not have rights. They have claimed that to have rights a being must be autonomous, or must be a member of a community, or must have the ability to respect the rights of others, or must possess a sense of justice. These claims are irrelevant to the case for Animal Liberation. The language of rights is a convenient political shorthand. It is even more valuable in the era of thirty-second TV news clips than it was in Bentham’s day; but in the argument for a radical change in our attitude to animals, it is in no way necessary. Rachels & Rachels_9781538127926.indb 300 17-06-2019 19:00:28 The Right Thing to Do : Readings in Moral Philosophy, edited by James Rachels, and Stuart Rachels, Rowman &
  • 30. Littlefield Publishers, 2019. ProQuest Ebook Central, http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/newschoolarch- ebooks/detail.action?docID=5798603. Created from newschoolarch-ebooks on 2020-05-14 19:49:07. C op yr ig ht © 2 01 9. R ow m an & L itt le fie ld P ub
  • 31. lis he rs . A ll rig ht s re se rv ed . All Animals Are Equal 301 If a being suffers there can be no moral justification for refusing to take that suffering into consideration. No matter what the nature of the being, the principle of equality requires that its suffering be counted equally with the like suffering—insofar as rough comparisons can be made—of any other being. If a being is not capable of suffering, or of experiencing enjoyment or happiness, there is nothing to be taken into
  • 32. account. So the limit of sentience (using the term as a convenient if not strictly accurate shorthand for the capacity to suffer and/or experience enjoyment) is the only defensible boundary of concern for the interests of others. To mark this boundary by some other characteristic like intel- ligence or rationality would be to mark it in an arbitrary manner. Why not choose some other characteristic, like skin color? Racists violate the principle of equality by giving greater weight to the interests of members of their own race when there is a clash between their interests and the interests of those of another race. Sexists violate the principle of equality by favoring the interests of their own sex. Simi- larly, speciesists allow the interests of their own species to override the greater interests of members of other species. The pattern is identical in each case. . . . Animals can feel pain. As we saw earlier, there can be no moral jus- tification for regarding the pain (or pleasure) that animals feel as less important than the same amount of pain (or pleasure) felt by humans. But what practical consequences follow from this conclusion? To pre- vent misunderstanding I shall spell out what I mean a little more fully.
  • 33. If I give a horse a hard slap across its rump with my open hand, the horse may start, but it presumably feels little pain. Its skin is thick enough to protect it against a mere slap. If I slap a baby in the same way, however, the baby will cry and presumably feel pain, for its skin is more sensitive. So it is worse to slap a baby than a horse, if both slaps are administered with equal force. But there must be some kind of blow—I don’t know exactly what it would be, but perhaps a blow with a heavy stick—that would cause the horse as much pain as we cause a baby by slapping it with our hand. That is what I mean by “the same amount of pain,” and if we consider it wrong to inflict that much pain on a baby for no good reason then we must, unless we are speciesists, consider it equally wrong to inflict the same amount of pain on a horse for no good reason. Rachels & Rachels_9781538127926.indb 301 17-06-2019 19:00:28 The Right Thing to Do : Readings in Moral Philosophy, edited by James Rachels, and Stuart Rachels, Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, 2019. ProQuest Ebook Central, http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/newschoolarch- ebooks/detail.action?docID=5798603. Created from newschoolarch-ebooks on 2020-05-14 19:49:07.
  • 35. . A ll rig ht s re se rv ed . Chapter 27302 Other differences between humans and animals cause other com- plications. Normal adult human beings have mental capacities that will, in certain circumstances, lead them to suffer more than animals would in the same circumstances. If, for instance, we decided to per- form extremely painful or lethal scientific experiments on normal adult humans, kidnapped at random from public parks for this purpose, adults who enjoy strolling in parks would become fearful that they would be kidnapped. The resultant terror would be a form of suffering additional to the pain of the experiment. The same experiments performed
  • 36. on nonhuman animals would cause less suffering since the animals would not have the anticipatory dread of being kidnapped and experimented upon. This does not mean, of course, that it would be right to perform the experiment on animals, but only that there is a reason, which is not speciesist, for preferring to use animals rather than normal adult human beings, if the experiment is to be done at all. It should be noted, however, that this same argument gives us a reason for preferring to use human infants—orphans perhaps—or severely retarded human beings for experiments, rather than adults, since infants and retarded humans would also have no idea of what was going to happen to them. So far as this argument is concerned nonhuman animals and infants and retarded humans are in the same category; and if we use this argument to justify experiments on nonhuman animals we have to ask ourselves whether we are also prepared to allow experiments on human infants and retarded adults; and if we make a distinction between animals and these humans, on what basis can we do it, other than a bare- faced—and morally indefensible—preference for members of our own species?
  • 37. There are many matters in which the superior mental powers of normal adult humans make a difference: anticipation, more detailed … 305 Farm animals in America once grazed on open fields beside coun- try roads. Those days, however, are gone. Today, farm animals live in smelly, crowded, automated warehouses. Every indepen- dent study has found these factories to be inhumane. The cramped conditions are stressful and unnatural for the animals; cows pumped full of food often experience internal abscesses; chickens and turkeys have their beaks cut off, and pigs and cows have their tails severed—all without anesthesia—to avoid the fighting that occurs precisely because the animals are packed in so tightly. The number of animals that suffer under these conditions is staggering—in the billions, year after year. When people in our culture think of a moral horror, they often think of the Holo- caust—the campaign of genocide in which Hitler and his Nazi thugs starved, beat, and ultimately murdered 5.7 million Jews. They do not think of factory farming. Yet for every human being who suffered under Hitler’s tyranny, several thousand animals have suffered in these farms during the past twenty years. The Nobel laureate Isaac Bashevis Singer wrote, “In relation to [animals], all people are Nazis; for the animals it is an eternal Treblinka.” Chapter 28
  • 38. Torturing Puppies and Eating Meat It’s All in Good Taste Alastair Norcross Alastair Norcross, “Torturing Puppies and Eating Meat: It’s All in Good Taste” in Southwest Philosophy Review, vol. 20, no. 1 (2004): 117–23. Copyright © 2004. Used with permission of the author. Rachels & Rachels_9781538127926.indb 305 17-06-2019 19:00:28 The Right Thing to Do : Readings in Moral Philosophy, edited by James Rachels, and Stuart Rachels, Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, 2019. ProQuest Ebook Central, http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/newschoolarch- ebooks/detail.action?docID=5798603. Created from newschoolarch-ebooks on 2020-05-14 19:50:09. C o p yr ig h t © 2 0 1
  • 40. ts r e se rv e d . Chapter 28306 In this selection, Alastair Norcross asks how we can justify treating chickens in ways that we would never treat puppies. Despite the seriousness of the topic, Norcross’s piece contains humor—some of it directed at my home state of Alabama, and some directed specifically at the city of Tuscaloosa, where I live. We Alabamians can take the ridicule—even when it’s not in good taste. Alastair Norcross is a professor of philosophy at the University of Colorado at Boulder, where many people play the banjo. Consider the story of Fred, who receives a visit from the police one day. They have been summoned by Fred’s neighbors, who have been disturbed by strange sounds emanating from Fred’s basement. When they enter the basement they are confronted by the following scene:
  • 41. Twenty-six small wire cages, each containing a puppy, some whin- ing, some whimpering, some howling. The puppies range in age from newborn to about six months. Many of them show signs of mutilation. Urine and feces cover the bottoms of the cages and the basement floor. Fred explains that he keeps the puppies for twenty-six weeks, and then butchers them while holding them upside-down. During their lives he performs a series of mutilations on them, such as slicing off their noses and their paws with a hot knife, all without any form of anesthesia. Except for the mutilations, the puppies are never allowed out of the cages, which are barely big enough to hold them at twenty-six weeks. The police are horrified, and promptly charge Fred with animal abuse. As details of the case are publicized, the public is outraged. Newspa- pers are flooded with letters demanding that Fred be severely punished. There are calls for more severe penalties for animal abuse. Fred is denounced as a vile sadist. Finally, at his trial, Fred explains his behavior, and argues that he is blameless and therefore deserves no punishment. He is, he explains, a great lover of chocolate. A couple of years ago, he was involved in a car
  • 42. accident, which resulted in some head trauma. Upon his release from the hospital, having apparently suffered no lasting ill effects, he visited his favorite restaurant and ordered their famous rich dark chocolate mousse. Imagine his dismay when he discovered that his experience of the mousse was a pale shadow of its former self. The mousse tasted bland, slightly pleasant, but with none of the intense chocolaty flavor Rachels & Rachels_9781538127926.indb 306 17-06-2019 19:00:28 The Right Thing to Do : Readings in Moral Philosophy, edited by James Rachels, and Stuart Rachels, Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, 2019. ProQuest Ebook Central, http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/newschoolarch- ebooks/detail.action?docID=5798603. Created from newschoolarch-ebooks on 2020-05-14 19:50:09. C o p yr ig h t © 2 0 1
  • 44. ts r e se rv e d . Torturing Puppies and Eating Meat 307 he remembered so well. The waiter assured him that the recipe was unchanged from the last time he had tasted it, just the day before his accident. In some consternation, Fred rushed out to buy a bar of his favorite Belgian chocolate. Again, he was dismayed to discover that his experience of the chocolate was barely even pleasurable. Extensive investigation revealed that his experience of other foods remained unaffected, but chocolate, in all its forms, now tasted bland and insipid. Desperate for a solution to his problem, Fred visited a renowned gusta- tory neurologist, Dr. T. Bud. Extensive tests revealed that the accident had irreparably damaged the godiva gland, which secretes cocoamone, the hormone responsible for the experience of chocolate. Fred
  • 45. urgently requested hormone replacement therapy. Dr. Bud informed him that, until recently, there had been no known source of cocoamone, other than the human godiva gland, and that it was impossible to collect cocoamone from one person to be used by another. However, a chance discovery had altered the situation. A forensic veterinary surgeon, per- forming an autopsy on a severely abused puppy, had discovered high concentrations of cocoamone in the puppy’s brain. It turned out that puppies, who don’t normally produce cocoamone, could be stimulated to do so by extended periods of severe stress and suffering. The research that led to this discovery, while gaining tenure for its authors, had not been widely publicized, for fear of antagonizing animal welfare groups. Although this research clearly gave Fred the hope of tasting chocolate again, there were no commercially available sources of puppy- derived cocoamone. Lack of demand, combined with fear of bad publicity, had deterred drug companies from getting into the puppy torturing business. Fred appeals to the court to imagine his anguish, on discovering that a solution to his severe deprivation was possible, but not readily avail- able. But he wasn’t inclined to sit around bemoaning his cruel
  • 46. fate. He did what any chocolate lover would do. He read the research, and set up his own cocoamone collection lab in his basement. Six months of intense puppy suffering, followed by a brutal death, produced enough cocoamone to last him a week, hence the twenty-six cages. He isn’t a sadist or an animal abuser, he explains. If there were a method of col- lecting cocoamone without torturing puppies, he would gladly employ it. He derives no pleasure from the suffering of the puppies itself. He sympathizes with those who are horrified by the pain and misery of the animals, but the court must realize that human pleasure is at stake. The puppies, while undeniably cute, are mere animals. He admits that he Rachels & Rachels_9781538127926.indb 307 17-06-2019 19:00:28 The Right Thing to Do : Readings in Moral Philosophy, edited by James Rachels, and Stuart Rachels, Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, 2019. ProQuest Ebook Central, http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/newschoolarch- ebooks/detail.action?docID=5798603. Created from newschoolarch-ebooks on 2020-05-14 19:50:09. C o p yr
  • 48. rs . A ll ri g h ts r e se rv e d . Chapter 28308 would be just as healthy without chocolate, if not more so. But this isn’t a matter of survival or health. His life would be unacceptably impover- ished without the experience of chocolate. End of story. Clearly, we are horrified by Fred’s behavior, and unconvinced by his attempted justification. It is, of course, unfortunate for Fred that he can no longer enjoy the taste of chocolate, but that in no way excuses the imposition of severe suffering on the puppies. I
  • 49. expect near universal agreement with this claim (the exceptions being those who are either inhumanly callous or thinking ahead, and wish to avoid the following conclusion, to which such agreement commits them). No decent person would even contemplate torturing puppies merely to enhance a gustatory experience. However, billions of animals endure intense suffering every year for precisely this end. Most of the chicken, veal, beef, and pork consumed in the United States comes from inten- sive confinement facilities, in which the animals live cramped, stress- filled lives and endure un-anaesthetized mutilations. The vast majority of people would suffer no ill health from the elimination of meat from their diets. Quite the reverse. The supposed benefits from this system of factory farming, apart from the profits accruing to agribusiness, are increased levels of gustatory pleasure for those who claim that they couldn’t enjoy a meat-free diet as much as their current meat- filled diets. If we are prepared to condemn Fred for torturing puppies merely to enhance his gustatory experiences, shouldn’t we similarly condemn the millions who purchase and consume factory-raised meat? Are there any morally significant differences between Fred’s behavior and
  • 50. their behavior? The first difference that might seem to be relevant is that Fred tor- tures the puppies himself, whereas most Americans consume meat that comes from animals that have been tortured by others. But is this really relevant? What if Fred had been squeamish and had employed someone else to torture the puppies and extract the cocoamone? Would we have thought any better of Fred? Of course not. Another difference between Fred and many consumers of factory- raised meat is that many, perhaps most, such consumers are unaware of the treatment of the animals, before they appear in neatly wrapped packages on supermarket shelves. Perhaps I should moderate my chal- lenge, then. If we are prepared to condemn Fred for torturing puppies merely to enhance his gustatory experiences, shouldn’t we similarly condemn those who purchase and consume factory-raised meat, in full, Rachels & Rachels_9781538127926.indb 308 17-06-2019 19:00:29 The Right Thing to Do : Readings in Moral Philosophy, edited by James Rachels, and Stuart Rachels, Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, 2019. ProQuest Ebook Central,
  • 51. http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/newschoolarch- ebooks/detail.action?docID=5798603. Created from newschoolarch-ebooks on 2020-05-14 19:50:09. C o p yr ig h t © 2 0 1 9 . R o w m a n & L itt le fie ld
  • 52. P u b lis h e rs . A ll ri g h ts r e se rv e d . Torturing Puppies and Eating Meat 309 or even partial, awareness of the suffering endured by the animals? While many consumers are still blissfully ignorant of the appalling
  • 53. treatment meted out to meat, that number is rapidly dwindling, thanks to vigorous publicity campaigns waged by animal welfare groups. Fur- thermore, any meat-eating readers of this article are now deprived of the excuse of ignorance. Perhaps a consumer of factory-raised animals could argue as follows: While I agree that Fred’s behavior is abominable, mine is crucially dif- ferent. If Fred did not consume his chocolate, he would not raise and torture puppies (or pay someone else to do so). Therefore Fred could prevent the suffering of the puppies. However, if I did not buy and consume factory-raised meat, no animals would be spared lives of mis- ery. Agribusiness is much too large to respond to the behavior of one consumer. Therefore I cannot prevent the suffering of any animals. I may well regret the suffering inflicted on animals for the sake of human enjoyment. I may even agree that the human enjoyment doesn’t justify the suffering. However, since the animals will suffer no matter what I do, I may as well enjoy the taste of their flesh. There are at least two lines of response to this attempted defense. First, consider an analogous case. You visit a friend in an exotic location, say Alabama. Your friend takes you out to eat at the
  • 54. finest restaurant in Tuscaloosa. For dessert you select the house specialty, “Chocolate Mousse à la Bama,” served with a small cup of coffee, which you are instructed to drink before eating the mousse. The mousse is quite simply the most delicious dessert you have ever tasted. Never before has chocolate tasted so rich and satisfying. Tempted to order a second, you ask your friend what makes this mousse so delicious. He informs you that the mousse itself is ordinary, but the coffee contains a concentrated dose of cocoamone, the newly discovered chocolate- enhancing hormone. Researchers at Auburn University have perfected a technique for extracting cocoamone from the brains of freshly slaugh- tered puppies, who have been subjected to lives of pain and frustration. Each puppy’s brain yields four doses, each of which is effective for about fifteen minutes, just long enough to enjoy one serving of mousse. You are, naturally, horrified and disgusted. You will certainly not order another serving, you tell your friend. In fact, you are shocked that your friend, who had always seemed to be a morally decent person, could have both recommended the dessert to you and eaten one himself, in full awareness of the loathsome process necessary for the
  • 55. experience. Rachels & Rachels_9781538127926.indb 309 17-06-2019 19:00:29 The Right Thing to Do : Readings in Moral Philosophy, edited by James Rachels, and Stuart Rachels, Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, 2019. ProQuest Ebook Central, http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/newschoolarch- ebooks/detail.action?docID=5798603. Created from newschoolarch-ebooks on 2020-05-14 19:50:09. C o p yr ig h t © 2 0 1 9 . R o w m a n &
  • 57. Chapter 28310 He agrees that the suffering of the puppies is outrageous, and that the gain in human pleasure in no way justifies the appalling treatment they have to endure. However, neither he nor you can save any puppies by refraining from consuming cocoamone. Cocoamone production is now Alabama’s leading industry, surpassing even banjo-making and inbreeding.1 The industry is much too large to respond to the behavior of one or two consumers. Since the puppies will suffer no matter what either of you does, you may as well enjoy the mousse. If it is as obvious as it seems that a morally decent person, who is aware of the details of cocoamone production, couldn’t order Chocolate Mousse à la Bama, it should be equally obvious that a morally decent person, who is aware of the details of factory farming, can’t purchase and consume factory-raised meat. If the attempted excuse of causal impotence is compelling in the latter case, it should be compelling in the former case. But it isn’t. The second response to the claim of causal impotence is to deny it.
  • 58. Consider the case of chickens, the most cruelly treated of all animals raised for human consumption, with the possible exception of veal calves. In 1998, almost 8 billion chickens were slaughtered in the United States,2 almost all of them raised on factory farms. Suppose that there are 250 million chicken eaters in the United States, and that each one consumes, on average, 25 chickens per year (this leaves a fair num- ber of chickens slaughtered for nonhuman consumption, or for export). Clearly, if only one of those chicken eaters gave up eating chicken, the industry would not respond. Equally clearly, if they all gave up eat- ing chicken, billions of chickens (approximately 6.25 billion per year) would not be bred, tortured, and killed. But there must also be some number of consumers, far short of 250 million, whose renunciation of chicken would cause the industry to reduce the number of chickens bred in factory farms. The industry may not be able to respond to each individual’s behavior, but it must respond to the behavior of fairly large numbers. Suppose that the industry is sensitive to a reduction in demand for chicken equivalent to 10,000 people becoming vegetarians. (This seems like a reasonable guess, but I have no idea what the actual
  • 59. numbers are, nor is it important.) For each group of 10,000 who give up chicken, a quarter of a million fewer chickens are bred per year. It appears, then, that if you give up eating chicken, you have only a one in ten thousand chance of making any difference to the lives of chickens, unless it is certain that fewer than 10,000 people will ever give up eating Rachels & Rachels_9781538127926.indb 310 17-06-2019 19:00:29 The Right Thing to Do : Readings in Moral Philosophy, edited by James Rachels, and Stuart Rachels, Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, 2019. ProQuest Ebook Central, http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/newschoolarch- ebooks/detail.action?docID=5798603. Created from newschoolarch-ebooks on 2020-05-14 19:50:09. C o p yr ig h t © 2 0 1 9 .
  • 61. r e se rv e d . Torturing Puppies and Eating Meat 311 chicken, in which case you have no chance. Isn’t a one in ten thousand chance small enough to render your continued consumption of chicken blameless? Not at all. While the chance that your behavior is harmful may be small, the harm that is risked is enormous. The larger the num- bers needed to make a difference to chicken production, the larger the difference such numbers would make. A one in ten thousand chance of saving 250,000 chickens per year from excruciating lives is morally and mathematically equivalent to the certainty of saving 25 chickens per year. We commonly accept that even small risks of great harms are unacceptable. That is why we disapprove of parents who fail to secure their children in car seats or with seat belts, who leave their small chil- dren unattended at home, or who drink or smoke heavily during
  • 62. preg- nancy. Or consider commercial aircraft safety measures. The chances that the oxygen masks, the lifejackets, or the emergency exits on any given plane will be called on to save any lives in a given week, are far smaller than one in ten thousand. And yet we would be outraged to discover that an airline had knowingly allowed a plane to fly for a week with non-functioning emergency exits, oxygen masks, and lifejackets. So, even if it is true that your giving up factory raised chicken has only a tiny chance of preventing suffering, given that the amount of suffer- ing that would be prevented is in inverse proportion to your chance of preventing it, your continued consumption is not thereby excused. But perhaps it is not even true that your giving up chicken has only a tiny chance of making any difference. Suppose again that the poultry industry only reduces production when a threshold of 10,000 fresh veg- etarians is reached. Suppose also, as is almost certainly true, that veg- etarianism is growing in popularity in the United States (and elsewhere). Then, even if you are not the one, newly converted vegetarian, to reach the next threshold of 10,000, your conversion will reduce the time required
  • 63. before the next threshold is reached. The sooner the threshold is reached, the sooner production, and therefore animal suffering, is reduced. Your behavior, therefore, does make a difference. Furthermore, many people who become vegetarians influence others to become vegetarian, who in turn influence others, and so on. It appears, then, that the claim of causal impotence is mere wishful thinking, on the part of those meat lovers who are morally sensitive enough to realize that human gustatory pleasure does not justify inflicting extreme suffering on animals. . . . I have been unable to discover any morally relevant differences between the behavior of Fred, the puppy torturer, and the behavior of Rachels & Rachels_9781538127926.indb 311 17-06-2019 19:00:29 The Right Thing to Do : Readings in Moral Philosophy, edited by James Rachels, and Stuart Rachels, Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, 2019. ProQuest Ebook Central, http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/newschoolarch- ebooks/detail.action?docID=5798603. Created from newschoolarch-ebooks on 2020-05-14 19:50:09. C o p yr ig
  • 65. . A ll ri g h ts r e se rv e d . Chapter 28312 the millions of people who purchase and consume factory-raised meat, at least those who do so in the knowledge that the animals live lives of suffering and deprivation. Just as morality demands that we not tor- ture puppies merely to enhance our own eating pleasure, morality also demands that we not support factory farming by purchasing factory- raised meat. NOTES
  • 66. 1. I realize that I am playing on stereotypes for comic effect. Banjo-making, of course, has never really been one of Alabama’s leading industries. 2. Livestock Slaughter 1998 Summary, NASS, USDA (Washington, DC: March 1999), 2; and Poultry Slaughter, NASS, USDA (Washington, DC: Feb- ruary 2, 1999), 1f. Rachels & Rachels_9781538127926.indb 312 17-06-2019 19:00:29 The Right Thing to Do : Readings in Moral Philosophy, edited by James Rachels, and Stuart Rachels, Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, 2019. ProQuest Ebook Central, http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/newschoolarch- ebooks/detail.action?docID=5798603. Created from newschoolarch-ebooks on 2020-05-14 19:50:09. C o p yr ig h t © 2 0 1 9 .
  • 68. r e se rv e d . 375 In this selection, J. Gay-Williams offers several standard objec- tions to euthanasia: that it goes against our natural instincts; that it violates human dignity; that it forecloses the possibility of miraculous cures; that the critically ill, and their caretakers, might give up too easily if euthanasia were an option; and, finally, that the legalization of euthanasia might lead to horrific abuses. “J. Gay-Williams” is a pseudonym. We are not told the author’s real name. My impression is that euthanasia—the idea, if not the practice— is slowly gaining acceptance within our society. Cynics might attribute this to an increasing tendency to devalue human life, but I do not believe this is the major factor. The acceptance is much more likely to be the result of unthinking sympathy and benevolence. Well-
  • 69. publicized, tragic stories like that of Karen Quinlan elicit from us deep feelings of com- passion. We think to ourselves, “She and her family would be better off if she were dead.” It is an easy step from this very human response to the view that if someone (and others) would be better off dead, then it might be all right to kill that person. Although I respect the compas- sion that leads to this conclusion, I believe the conclusion is wrong. Chapter 34 The Wrongfulness of Euthanasia J. Gay-Williams J. Gay-Williams, “The Wrongfulness of Euthanasia” in Intervention and Reflection, ed. Ron- ald Munson (Belmont, CA: Cengage Learning, 2017). Copyright © 2008, 2012, 2017 Ronald Munson. Used with permission. Rachels & Rachels_9781538127926.indb 375 17-06-2019 19:00:37 The Right Thing to Do : Readings in Moral Philosophy, edited by James Rachels, and Stuart Rachels, Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, 2019. ProQuest Ebook Central, http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/newschoolarch- ebooks/detail.action?docID=5798603. Created from newschoolarch-ebooks on 2020-05-14 19:25:22. C
  • 71. h e rs . A ll ri g h ts r e se rv e d . Chapter 34376 I want to show that euthanasia is wrong. It is inherently wrong, but it is also wrong judged from the standpoints of self-interest and of practical effects. Before presenting my arguments to support this claim, it would be well to define “euthanasia.” An essential aspect of euthanasia is
  • 72. that it involves taking a human life, either one’s own or that of another. Also, the person whose life is taken must be someone who is believed to be suffering from some disease or injury from which recovery cannot reasonably be expected. Finally, the action must be deliberate and inten- tional. Thus, euthanasia is intentionally taking the life of a presumably hopeless person. Whether the life is one’s own or that of another, the taking of it is still euthanasia. It is important to be clear about the deliberate and intentional aspect of the killing. If a hopeless person is given an injection of the wrong drug by mistake and this causes his death, this is wrongful killing but not euthanasia. The killing cannot be the result of accident. Further- more, if the person is given an injection of a drug that is believed to be necessary to treat his disease or better his condition and the person dies as a result, then this is neither wrongful killing nor euthanasia. The intention was to make the patient well, not kill him. Similarly, when a patient’s condition is such that it is not reasonable to hope that any medical procedures or treatments will save his life, a failure to imple- ment the procedures or treatments is not euthanasia. If the
  • 73. person dies, this will be as a result of his injuries or disease and not because of his failure to receive treatment. The failure to continue treatment after it has been realized that the patient has little chance of benefiting from it has been characterized by some as “passive euthanasia.” This phrase is misleading and mistaken. In such cases, the person involved is not killed (the first essential aspect of euthanasia), nor is the death of the person intended by the withhold- ing of additional treatment (the third essential aspect of euthanasia). The aim may be to spare the person additional and unjustifiable pain, to save him from the indignities of hopeless manipulations, and to avoid increasing the financial and emotional burden on his family. When I buy a pencil it is so that I can use it to write, not to contribute to an increase in the gross national product (GNP). This may be the unin- tended consequence of my action, but it is not the aim of my action. So it is with failing to continue the treatment of a dying person. I intend Rachels & Rachels_9781538127926.indb 376 17-06-2019 19:00:37 The Right Thing to Do : Readings in Moral Philosophy, edited
  • 74. by James Rachels, and Stuart Rachels, Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, 2019. ProQuest Ebook Central, http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/newschoolarch- ebooks/detail.action?docID=5798603. Created from newschoolarch-ebooks on 2020-05-14 19:25:22. C o p yr ig h t © 2 0 1 9 . R o w m a n & L itt le fie
  • 75. ld P u b lis h e rs . A ll ri g h ts r e se rv e d . The Wrongfulness of Euthanasia 377 his death no more than I intend to reduce the GNP by not using medical
  • 76. supplies. His is an unintended dying, and so-called “passive euthanasia” is not euthanasia at all. 1. THE ARGUMENT FROM NATURE Every human being has a natural inclination to continue living. Our reflexes and responses fit us to fight attackers, flee wild animals, and dodge out of the way of trucks. In our daily lives we exercise the cau- tion and care necessary to protect ourselves. Our bodies are similarly structured for survival right down to the molecular level. When we are cut, our capillaries seal shut, our blood clots, and fibrinogen is produced to start the process of healing the wound. When we are invaded by bacteria, antibodies are produced to fight against the alien organisms, and their remains are swept out of the body by special cells designed for clean-up work. Euthanasia does violence to this natural goal of survival. It is literally acting against nature because all the processes of nature are bent towards the end of bodily survival. Euthanasia defeats these subtle mechanisms in a way that, in a particular case, disease and injury might not. It is possible, but not necessary, to make an appeal to revealed reli-
  • 77. gion in this connection. Man as trustee of his body acts against God, its rightful possessor, when he takes his own life. He also violates the commandment to hold life sacred and never to take it without just and compelling cause. But since this appeal will persuade only those who are prepared to accept that religion has access to revealed truths, I shall not employ this line of argument. It is enough, I believe, to recognize that the organization of the human body and our patterns of behavioral responses make the continu- ation of life a natural goal. By reason alone, then, we can recognize that euthanasia sets us against our own nature. Furthermore, in doing so, euthanasia does violence to our dignity. Our dignity comes from seek- ing our ends. When one of our goals is survival, and actions are taken that eliminate that goal, then our natural dignity suffers. Unlike animals, we are conscious through reason of our nature and our ends. Euthanasia involves acting as if this dual nature—inclination towards survival and awareness of this as an end—did not exist. Thus, euthanasia denies our Rachels & Rachels_9781538127926.indb 377 17-06-2019 19:00:38 The Right Thing to Do : Readings in Moral Philosophy, edited
  • 78. by James Rachels, and Stuart Rachels, Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, 2019. ProQuest Ebook Central, http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/newschoolarch- ebooks/detail.action?docID=5798603. Created from newschoolarch-ebooks on 2020-05-14 19:25:22. C o p yr ig h t © 2 0 1 9 . R o w m a n & L itt le fie
  • 79. ld P u b lis h e rs . A ll ri g h ts r e se rv e d . Chapter 34378 basic human character and requires that we regard ourselves or others
  • 80. as something less than fully human. 2. THE ARGUMENT FROM SELF-INTEREST The above arguments are, I believe, sufficient to show that euthanasia is inherently wrong. But there are reasons for considering it wrong when judged by standards other than reason. Because death is final and irreversible, euthanasia contains within it the possibility that we will work against our own interest if we practice it or allow it to be practiced on us. Contemporary medicine has high standards of excellence and a proven record of accomplishment, but it does not possess perfect and complete knowledge. A mistaken diagnosis is possible, and so is a mistaken prognosis. Consequently, we may believe that we are dying of a disease when, as a matter of fact, we may not be. We may think that we have no hope of recovery when, as a matter of fact, our chances are quite good. In such circumstances, if euthanasia were permitted, we would die needlessly. Death is final and the chance of error too great to approve the practice of euthanasia. Also, there is always the possibility that an experimental procedure or a hitherto untried technique will pull us through. We should
  • 81. at least keep this option open, but euthanasia closes it off. Furthermore, spon- taneous remission does occur in many cases. For no apparent reason, a patient simply recovers when those all around him, including his physicians, expected him to die. Euthanasia would just guarantee their expectations and leave no room for the “miraculous” recoveries that frequently occur. Finally, knowing that we can take our life at any time (or ask another to take it) might well incline us to give up too easily. The will to live is strong in all of us, but it can be weakened by pain and suffering and feelings of hopelessness. If during a bad time we allow ourselves to be killed, we never have a chance to reconsider. Recovery from a serious illness requires that we fight for it, and anything that weakens our determination by suggesting that there is an easy way out is ultimately against our own interest. Also, we may be inclined towards euthanasia because of our concern for others. If we see our Rachels & Rachels_9781538127926.indb 378 17-06-2019 19:00:38 The Right Thing to Do : Readings in Moral Philosophy, edited by James Rachels, and Stuart Rachels, Rowman &
  • 82. Littlefield Publishers, 2019. ProQuest Ebook Central, http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/newschoolarch- ebooks/detail.action?docID=5798603. Created from newschoolarch-ebooks on 2020-05-14 19:25:22. C o p yr ig h t © 2 0 1 9 . R o w m a n & L itt le fie
  • 83. ld P u b lis h e rs . A ll ri g h ts r e se rv e d . The Wrongfulness of Euthanasia 379 sickness and suffering as an emotional and financial burden on our family, we may feel that to leave our life is to make their lives
  • 84. easier. The very presence of the possibility of euthanasia may keep us from surviving when we might. 3. THE ARGUMENT FROM PRACTICAL EFFECTS Doctors and nurses are, for the most part, totally committed to sav- ing lives. A life lost is, for them, almost a personal failure, an insult to their skills and knowledge. Euthanasia as a practice might well alter this. It could have a corrupting influence so that in any case that is severe, doctors and nurses might not try hard enough to save the patient. They might decide that the patient would simply be “bet- ter off dead” and take the steps necessary to make that come about. This attitude could then carry over to their dealings with patients less seriously ill. The result would be an overall decline in the quality of medical care. Finally, euthanasia as a policy is a slippery slope. A person appar- ently hopelessly ill may be allowed to take his own life. Then he may be permitted to deputize others to do it for him should he no longer be able to act. The judgment of others then becomes the ruling factor. Already at this point euthanasia is not personal and voluntary, for others
  • 85. are acting “on behalf of” the patient as they see fit. This may well incline them to act on behalf of other patients who have not authorized them to exercise their judgment. It is only a short step, then, from voluntary euthanasia (self-inflicted or authorized) to directed euthanasia adminis- tered to a patient who has given no authorization, to involuntary eutha- nasia conducted as part of a social policy. Recently many psychiatrists and sociologists have argued that we define as “mental illness” those forms of behavior that we disapprove of. This gives us license then to lock up those who display the behavior. The category of the “hopelessly ill” provides the possibility of even worse abuse. Embedded in a social policy, it would give society or its representatives the authority to elimi- nate all those who might be considered too “ill” to function normally any longer. The dangers of euthanasia are too great to all to run the risk of approving it in any form. The first slippery step may well lead to a serious and harmful fall. Rachels & Rachels_9781538127926.indb 379 17-06-2019 19:00:38 The Right Thing to Do : Readings in Moral Philosophy, edited by James Rachels, and Stuart Rachels, Rowman &
  • 86. Littlefield Publishers, 2019. ProQuest Ebook Central, http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/newschoolarch- ebooks/detail.action?docID=5798603. Created from newschoolarch-ebooks on 2020-05-14 19:25:22. C o p yr ig h t © 2 0 1 9 . R o w m a n & L itt le fie
  • 87. ld P u b lis h e rs . A ll ri g h ts r e se rv e d . Chapter 34380 I hope that I have succeeded in showing why the benevolence that inclines us to give approval of euthanasia is misplaced.
  • 88. Euthanasia is inherently wrong because it violates the nature and dignity of human beings. But even those who are not convinced by this must be persuaded that the potential personal and social dangers inherent in euthanasia are sufficient to forbid our approving it either as a personal practice or as a public policy. Suffering is surely a terrible thing, and we have a clear duty to com- fort those in need and to ease their suffering when we can. But suffering is also a natural part of life with values for the individual and for oth- ers that we should not overlook. We may legitimately seek for others and for ourselves an easeful death, as Arthur Dyck has pointed out. Euthanasia, however, is not just an easeful death. It is a wrongful death. Euthanasia is not just dying. It is killing. Rachels & Rachels_9781538127926.indb 380 17-06-2019 19:00:38 The Right Thing to Do : Readings in Moral Philosophy, edited by James Rachels, and Stuart Rachels, Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, 2019. ProQuest Ebook Central, http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/newschoolarch- ebooks/detail.action?docID=5798603. Created from newschoolarch-ebooks on 2020-05-14 19:25:22. C
  • 90. h e rs . A ll ri g h ts r e se rv e d . 197 The Australian philosopher Peter Singer (1946–) is the most widely read author in the field of ethics. In this essay, he consid- ers whether it is morally defensible for well-off people to spend money on luxuries while other people starve. As I write this, in November 1971, people are dying in East Bengal
  • 91. from lack of food, shelter, and medical care. The suffering and death that are occurring there now are not inevitable, not unavoidable in any fatalistic sense of the term. Constant poverty, a cyclone, and a civil war have turned at least nine million people into destitute refugees; nevertheless, it is not beyond the capacity of the richer nations to give enough assistance to reduce any further suffering to very small propor- tions. The decisions and actions of human beings can prevent this kind of suffering. Unfortunately, human beings have not made the necessary decisions. At the individual level, people have, with very few excep- tions, not responded to the situation in any significant way. Generally speaking, people have not given large sums to relief funds; they have not written to their parliamentary representatives demanding increased government assistance; they have not demonstrated in the streets, held symbolic fasts, or done anything else directed toward providing the Chapter 19 Famine, Affluence, and Morality Peter Singer Peter Singer, “Famine, Affluence, and Morality” in Philosophy and Public Affairs, vol. 1,
  • 92. no. 1 (spring 1972): 229–43. Copyright © 1972 Peter Singer. Used with permission of the author. Rachels & Rachels_9781538127926.indb 197 17-06-2019 19:00:12 The Right Thing to Do : Readings in Moral Philosophy, edited by James Rachels, and Stuart Rachels, Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, 2019. ProQuest Ebook Central, http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/newschoolarch- ebooks/detail.action?docID=5798603. Created from newschoolarch-ebooks on 2020-05-14 19:30:46. C op yr ig ht © 2 01 9. R ow m an & L
  • 93. itt le fie ld P ub lis he rs . A ll rig ht s re se rv ed . Chapter 19198 refugees with the means to satisfy their essential needs. At the govern- ment level, no government has given the sort of massive aid that
  • 94. would enable the refugees to survive for more than a few days. Britain, for instance, has given rather more than most countries. It has, to date, given £14,750,000. For comparative purposes, Britain’s share of the non-recoverable development costs of the Anglo-French Concorde project is already in excess of £275,000,000, and on present estimates will reach £440,000,000. The implication is that the British government values a supersonic transport more than thirty times as highly as it val- ues the lives of the nine million refugees. Australia is another country which, on a per capita basis, is well up in the “aid to Bengal” table. Australia’s aid, however, amounts to less than one-twelfth of the cost of Sydney’s new opera house. . . . These are the essential facts about the present situation in Bengal. So far as it concerns us here, there is nothing unique about this situation except its magnitude. The Bengal emergency is just the latest and most acute of a series of major emergencies in various parts of the world, arising both from natural and from manmade causes. There are also many parts of the world in which people die from malnutrition and lack of food independent of any special emergency. I take Bengal as
  • 95. my example only because it is the present concern, and because the size of the problem has ensured that it has been given adequate publicity. Neither individuals nor governments can claim to be unaware of what is happening there. What are the moral implications of a situation like this? In what fol- lows, I shall argue that the way people in relatively affluent countries react to a situation like that in Bengal cannot be justified; indeed, the whole way we look at moral issues—our moral conceptual scheme— needs to be altered, and with it, the way of life that has come to be taken for granted in our society. . . . I begin with the assumption that suffering and death from lack of food, shelter, and medical care are bad. I think most people will agree about this, although one may reach the same view by different routes. I shall not argue for this view. People can hold all sorts of eccentric posi- tions, and perhaps from some of them it would not follow that death by starvation is in itself bad. It is difficult, perhaps impossible, to refute such positions, and so for brevity I will henceforth take this assumption as accepted. Those who disagree need read no further.
  • 96. Rachels & Rachels_9781538127926.indb 198 17-06-2019 19:00:12 The Right Thing to Do : Readings in Moral Philosophy, edited by James Rachels, and Stuart Rachels, Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, 2019. ProQuest Ebook Central, http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/newschoolarch- ebooks/detail.action?docID=5798603. Created from newschoolarch-ebooks on 2020-05-14 19:30:46. C op yr ig ht © 2 01 9. R ow m an & L itt le
  • 97. fie ld P ub lis he rs . A ll rig ht s re se rv ed . Famine, Affluence, and Morality 199 My next point is this: if it is in our power to prevent something bad from happening, without thereby sacrificing anything of comparable moral importance, we ought, morally, to do it. By “without sacrificing
  • 98. anything of comparable moral importance” I mean without causing anything else comparably bad to happen, or doing something that is wrong in itself, or failing to promote some moral good, comparable in significance to the bad thing that we can prevent. This principle seems almost as uncontroversial as the last one. It requires us only to prevent what is bad, and to promote what is good, and it requires this of us only when we can do it without sacrificing anything that is, from the moral point of view, comparably important. I could even, as far as the appli- cation of my argument to the Bengal emergency is concerned, qualify the point so as to make it: if it is in our power to prevent something very bad from happening, without thereby sacrificing anything morally significant, we ought, morally, to do it. An application of this principle would be as follows: if I am walking past a shallow pond and see a child drowning in it, I ought to wade in and pull the child out. This will mean getting my clothes muddy, but this is insignificant, while the death of the child would presumably be a very bad thing. The uncontroversial appearance of the principle just stated is decep- tive. If it were acted upon, even in its qualified form, our lives, our soci-
  • 99. ety, and our world would be fundamentally changed. For the principle takes, firstly, no account of proximity or distance. It makes no moral difference whether the person I can help is a neighbor’s child ten yards from me or a Bengali whose name I shall never know, ten thousand miles away. Secondly, the principle makes no distinction between cases in which I am the only person who could possibly do anything and cases in which I am just one among millions in the same position. I do not think I need to say much in defense of the refusal to take proximity and distance into account. The fact that a person is physi- cally near to us, so that we have personal contact with him, may make it more likely that we shall assist him, but this does not show that we ought to help him rather than another who happens to be further away. If we accept any principle of impartiality, universalizability, equality, or whatever, we cannot discriminate against someone merely because he is far away from us (or we are far away from him). Admittedly, it is pos- sible that we are in a better position to judge what needs to be done to help a person near to us than one far away, and perhaps also to provide Rachels & Rachels_9781538127926.indb 199 17-06-2019
  • 100. 19:00:13 The Right Thing to Do : Readings in Moral Philosophy, edited by James Rachels, and Stuart Rachels, Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, 2019. ProQuest Ebook Central, http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/newschoolarch- ebooks/detail.action?docID=5798603. Created from newschoolarch-ebooks on 2020-05-14 19:30:46. C op yr ig ht © 2 01 9. R ow m an & L itt le fie
  • 101. ld P ub lis he rs . A ll rig ht s re se rv ed . Chapter 19200 the assistance we judge to be necessary. If this were the case, it would be a reason for helping those near to us first. This may once have been a justification for being more concerned with the poor in one’s town than with famine victims in India. Unfortunately for those who like to
  • 102. keep their moral responsibilities limited, instant communication and swift transportation have changed the situation. From the moral point of view, the development of the world into a “global village” has made an important, though still unrecognized, difference to our moral situation. Expert observers and supervisors, sent out by famine relief organiza- tions or permanently stationed in famine-prone areas, can direct our aid to a refugee in Bengal almost as effectively as we could get it to some- one in our own block. There would seem, therefore, to be no possible justification for discriminating on geographical grounds. There may be a greater need to defend the second implication of my principle—that the fact that there are millions of other people in the same position, in respect to the Bengali refugees, as I am, does not make the situation significantly different from a situation in which I am the only person who can prevent something very bad from occur- ring. Again, of course, I admit that there is a psychological difference between the cases; one feels less guilty about doing nothing if one can point to others, similarly placed, who have also done nothing. Yet this can make no real difference to our moral obligations. Should I consider that I am less obliged to pull the drowning child out of the pond
  • 103. if on looking around I see other people, no further away than I am, who have also noticed the child but are doing nothing? One has only to ask this question to see the absurdity of the view that numbers lessen obligation. It is a view that is an ideal excuse for inactivity; unfortunately most of the major evils—poverty, overpopulation, pollution—are problems in which everyone is almost equally involved. The view that numbers do make a difference can be made plausible if stated in this way: if everyone in circumstances like mine gave £5 to the Bengal Relief Fund, there would be enough to provide food, shelter, and medical care for the refugees; there is no reason why I should give more than anyone else in the same circumstances as I am; therefore I have no obligation to give more than £5. Each premise in this argument is true, and the argument looks sound. It may convince us, unless we notice that it is based on a hypothetical premise, although the conclu- sion is not stated hypothetically. The argument would be sound if the Rachels & Rachels_9781538127926.indb 200 17-06-2019 19:00:13 The Right Thing to Do : Readings in Moral Philosophy, edited
  • 104. by James Rachels, and Stuart Rachels, Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, 2019. ProQuest Ebook Central, http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/newschoolarch- ebooks/detail.action?docID=5798603. Created from newschoolarch-ebooks on 2020-05-14 19:30:46. C op yr ig ht © 2 01 9. R ow m an & L itt le fie ld P
  • 105. ub lis he rs . A ll rig ht s re se rv ed . Famine, Affluence, and Morality 201 conclusion were: if everyone in circumstances like mine were to give £5, I would have no obligation to give more than £5. If the conclusion were so stated, however, it would be obvious that the argument has no bearing on a situation in which it is not the case that everyone else gives £5. This, of course, is the actual situation. It is more or less certain that not everyone in circumstances like mine will give £5. So there
  • 106. will not be enough to provide the needed food, shelter, and medical care. There- fore by giving more than £5 I will prevent more suffering than I would if I gave just £5. . . . If my argument so far has been sound, neither our distance from a preventable evil nor the number of other people who, in respect to that evil, are in the same situation as we are, lessens our obligation to mitigate or prevent that evil. I shall therefore take as established the principle I asserted earlier. As I have already said, I need to assert it only in its qualified form: if it is in our power to prevent something very bad from happening, without thereby sacrificing anything else morally significant, we ought, morally, to do it. The outcome of this argument is that our traditional moral categories are upset. The traditional distinction between duty and charity cannot be drawn, or at least, not in the place we normally draw it. Giving money to the Bengal Relief Fund is regarded as an act of charity in our society. The bodies which collect money are known as “charities.” These organizations see themselves in this way—if you send them a check, you will be thanked for your “generosity.” Because giving
  • 107. money is regarded as an act of charity, it is not thought that there is anything wrong with not giving. The charitable man may be praised, but the man who is not charitable is not condemned. People do not feel in any way ashamed or guilty about spending money on new clothes or a new car instead of giving it to famine relief. (Indeed, the alternative does not occur to them.) This way of looking at the matter cannot be justified. When we buy new clothes not to keep ourselves warm but to look “well-dressed” we are not providing for any important need. We would not be sacrificing anything significant if we were to continue to wear our old clothes, and give the money to famine relief. By doing so, we would be preventing another person from starving. It follows from what I have said earlier that we ought to give money away, rather than spend it on clothes which we do not need to keep us warm. To do so is not charitable, or generous. Nor is it the kind of act which philosophers Rachels & Rachels_9781538127926.indb 201 17-06-2019 19:00:13 The Right Thing to Do : Readings in Moral Philosophy, edited by James Rachels, and Stuart Rachels, Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, 2019. ProQuest Ebook Central, http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/newschoolarch-
  • 108. ebooks/detail.action?docID=5798603. Created from newschoolarch-ebooks on 2020-05-14 19:30:46. C op yr ig ht © 2 01 9. R ow m an & L itt le fie ld P ub lis
  • 109. he rs . A ll rig ht s re se rv ed . Chapter 19202 and theologians have called “supererogatory”—an act which it would be good to do, but not wrong not to do. On the contrary, we ought to give the money away, and it is wrong not to do so. . . . One objection to the position I have taken might be simply that it is too drastic a revision of our moral scheme. People do not ordinarily judge in the way I have suggested they should. Most people reserve their moral condemnation for those who violate some moral norm,
  • 110. such as the norm against taking another person’s property. They do not condemn those who indulge in luxury instead of giving to famine relief. But given that I did not set out to present a morally neutral description of the way people make moral judgments, the way people do in fact judge has nothing to do with the validity of my conclusion. My conclu- sion follows from the principle which I advanced earlier, and unless that principle is rejected, or the arguments are shown to be unsound, I think the conclusion must stand, however strange it appears. . . . It has been argued by some writers, among them Sidgwick and Urm- son, that we need to have a basic moral code which is not too far beyond the capacities of the ordinary man, for otherwise there will be a general breakdown of compliance with the moral code. Crudely stated, this argument suggests that if we tell people that they ought to refrain from murder and give everything they do not really need to famine relief, they will do neither, whereas if we tell them that they ought to refrain from murder and that it is good to give to famine relief but not wrong not to do so, they will at least refrain from murder. The issue here is: Where should we draw the line between conduct that is required and
  • 111. conduct that is good although not required, so as to get the best possible result? This would seem to be an empirical question, although a very difficult one. One objection to the Sidgwick-Urmson line of argument is that it takes insufficient account of the effect that moral standards can have on the decisions we make. Given a society in which a wealthy man who gives 5 percent of his income to famine relief is regarded as most generous, it is not surprising that a proposal that we all ought to give away half our incomes will be thought to be absurdly unrealistic. In a society which held that no man should have more than enough while others have less than they need, such a proposal might seem narrow- minded. What it is possible for a man to do and what he is likely to do are both, I think, very greatly influenced by what people around him are doing and expecting him to do. In any case, the possibility that by spreading the idea that we ought to be doing very much more than we Rachels & Rachels_9781538127926.indb 202 17-06-2019 19:00:13 The Right Thing to Do : Readings in Moral Philosophy, edited by James Rachels, and Stuart Rachels, Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, 2019. ProQuest Ebook Central, http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/newschoolarch-
  • 112. ebooks/detail.action?docID=5798603. Created from newschoolarch-ebooks on 2020-05-14 19:30:46. C op yr ig ht © 2 01 9. R ow m an & L itt le fie ld P ub lis
  • 113. he rs . A ll rig ht s re se rv ed . Famine, Affluence, and Morality 203 are to relieve famine we shall bring about a general breakdown of moral behavior seems remote. If the stakes are an end to widespread starva- tion, it is worth the risk. Finally, it should be emphasized that these considerations are relevant only to the issue of what we should require from others, and not to what we ourselves ought to do. The second objection to my attack on the present distinction between duty and charity is one which has from time to time been made against
  • 114. utilitarianism. It follows from some forms of utilitarian theory that we all ought, morally, to be working full time to increase the balance of happiness over misery. The position I have taken here would not lead to this conclusion in all circumstances, for if there were no bad occur- rences that we could prevent without sacrificing something of com- parable moral importance, my argument would have no application. Given the present conditions in many parts of the world, however, it does follow from my argument that we ought, morally, to be working full time to relieve great suffering of the sort that occurs as a result of famine or other disasters. Of course, mitigating circumstances can be adduced—for instance, that if we wear ourselves out through over- work, we shall be less effective than we would otherwise have been. Nevertheless, when all considerations of this sort have been taken into account, the conclusion remains: we ought to be preventing as much suffering as we can without sacrificing something else of comparable moral importance. This conclusion is one which we may be reluctant to face. I cannot see, though, why it should be regarded as a criticism of the position for which I have argued, rather than a criticism of our
  • 115. ordinary standards of behavior. Since most people are self- interested to some degree, very few of us are likely to do everything that we ought to do. It would, however, hardly be honest to take this as evidence that it is not the case that we ought to do it. It may still be thought that my conclusions are so wildly out of line with what everyone else thinks and has always thought that there must be something wrong with the argument somewhere. In order to show that my conclusions, while certainly contrary to contemporary Western moral standards, would not have seemed so extraordinary at other times and in other places, I would like to quote a passage from a writer not normally thought of as a way-out radical, Thomas Aquinas. Now, according to the natural order instituted by divine providence, mate- rial goods are provided for the satisfaction of human needs. Therefore Rachels & Rachels_9781538127926.indb 203 17-06-2019 19:00:13 The Right Thing to Do : Readings in Moral Philosophy, edited by James Rachels, and Stuart Rachels, Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, 2019. ProQuest Ebook Central, http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/newschoolarch- ebooks/detail.action?docID=5798603. Created from newschoolarch-ebooks on 2020-05-14 19:30:46.
  • 117. . A ll rig ht s re se rv ed . Chapter 19204 the division and appropriation of property, which proceeds from human law, must not hinder the satisfaction of man’s necessity from such goods. Equally, whatever a man has in superabundance is owed, of natural right, to the poor for their sustenance. So Ambrosius says, and it is also to be found in the Decretum Gratiani: “The bread which you withhold belongs to the hungry; the clothing you shut away, to the naked; and the money you bury in the earth is the redemption and freedom of the penniless.”1 I now want to consider a number of points, more practical than
  • 118. philo- sophical, which are relevant to the application of the moral conclusion we have reached. These points challenge not the idea that we ought to be doing all we can to prevent starvation, but the idea that giving away a great deal of money is the best means to this end. . . . Another, more serious reason for not giving to famine relief funds is that until there is effective population control, relieving famine merely postpones starvation. If we save the Bengal refugees now, others, per- haps the children of these refugees, will face starvation in a few years’ time. In support of this, one may cite the now well-known facts about the population explosion and the relatively limited scope for expanded production. . . . I accept that the earth cannot support indefinitely a population rising at the present rate. This certainly poses a problem for anyone who thinks it important to prevent famine. Again, however, one could accept the argument without drawing the conclusion that it absolves one from any obligation to do anything to prevent famine. The conclusion that should be drawn is that the best means of preventing famine, in the long run, is population control. It would then follow from the
  • 119. position reached earlier that one ought to be doing all one can to promote popu- lation control (unless one held that all forms of population control were wrong in themselves, or would have significantly bad consequences). Since there are organizations working specifically for population con- trol, one would then support them rather than more orthodox methods of preventing famine. A third point raised by the conclusion reached earlier relates to the question of just how much we all ought to be giving away. One pos- sibility . . . is that we ought to give until we reach the level of marginal utility—that is, the level at which, by giving more, I would cause as much suffering to myself or my dependents as I would relieve by my gift. This would mean, of course, that one would reduce oneself to very Rachels & Rachels_9781538127926.indb 204 17-06-2019 19:00:13 The Right Thing to Do : Readings in Moral Philosophy, edited by James Rachels, and Stuart Rachels, Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, 2019. ProQuest Ebook Central, http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/newschoolarch- ebooks/detail.action?docID=5798603. Created from newschoolarch-ebooks on 2020-05-14 19:30:46.
  • 121. . A ll rig ht s re se rv ed . Famine, Affluence, and Morality 205 near the material circumstances of a Bengali refugee. It will be recalled that earlier I put forward both a strong and a moderate version of the principle of preventing bad occurrences. The strong version, which required us to prevent bad things from happening unless in doing so we would be sacrificing something of comparable moral significance, does seem to require reducing ourselves to the level of marginal utility. I should also say that the strong version seems to me to be the correct one. I proposed the more moderate version—that we should prevent bad occurrences unless, to do so, we had to sacrifice something
  • 122. morally significant—only in order to show that, even on this surely undeniable principle, a great change in our way of life is required. On the more moderate principle, it may not follow that we ought to reduce ourselves to the level of marginal utility, for one might hold that to reduce oneself and one’s family to this level is to cause something significantly bad to happen. Whether this is so I shall not discuss, since, as I have said, I can see no good reason for holding the moderate version of the principle rather than the strong version. Even if we accepted the principle only in its moderate form, however, it should be clear that we would have to give away enough to ensure that the consumer society, dependent as it is on people spending on trivia rather than giving to famine relief, would slow down and perhaps disappear entirely. There are several reasons why this would be desirable in itself. The value and necessity of eco- nomic growth are now being questioned not only by conservationists, but by economists as well. There is no doubt, too, that the consumer society has had a distorting effect on the goals and purposes of its mem- bers. Yet looking at the matter purely from the point of view of overseas aid, there must be a limit to the extent to which we should
  • 123. deliberately slow down our economy; for it might be the case that if we gave away, say, 40 percent of our Gross National Product (GNP), we would slow down the economy so much that in absolute terms we would be giving less than if we gave 25 percent of the much larger GNP that we would have if we limited our contribution to this smaller percentage. I mention this only as an indication of the sort of factor that one would have to take into account in working out an ideal. Since Western societies generally consider 1 percent of the GNP an acceptable level for overseas aid, the matter is entirely academic. Nor does it affect the question of how much an individual should give in a society in which very few are giving substantial amounts. Rachels & Rachels_9781538127926.indb 205 17-06-2019 19:00:14 The Right Thing to Do : Readings in Moral Philosophy, edited by James Rachels, and Stuart Rachels, Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, 2019. ProQuest Ebook Central, http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/newschoolarch- ebooks/detail.action?docID=5798603. Created from newschoolarch-ebooks on 2020-05-14 19:30:46. C op
  • 125. rig ht s re se rv ed . Chapter 19206 . . . The issue is one which faces everyone who has more money than he needs to support himself and his dependents, or who is in a position to take some sort of political action. These categories must include practi- cally every teacher and student of philosophy in the universities of the Western world. If philosophy is to deal with matters that are relevant to both teachers and students, this is an issue that philosophers should discuss. Discussion, though, is not enough. What is the point of relating phi- losophy to public (and personal) affairs if we do not take our conclu- sions seriously? In this instance, taking our conclusion seriously means
  • 126. acting upon it. The philosopher will not find it any easier than anyone else to alter his attitudes and way of life to the extent that, if I am right, is involved in doing everything that we ought to be doing. At the very least, though, one can make a start. The philosopher who does so will have to sacrifice some of the benefits of the consumer society, but he can find compensation in the satisfaction of a way of life in which theory and practice, if not yet in harmony, are at least coming together. NOTE 1. Summa Theologica, II-II, Question 66, Article 7, in Aquinas, Selected Political Writings, ed. A. P. d’Entrèves, trans. J. G. Dawson (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1948), p. 171. Rachels & Rachels_9781538127926.indb 206 17-06-2019 19:00:14 The Right Thing to Do : Readings in Moral Philosophy, edited by James Rachels, and Stuart Rachels, Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, 2019. ProQuest Ebook Central, http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/newschoolarch- ebooks/detail.action?docID=5798603. Created from newschoolarch-ebooks on 2020-05-14 19:30:46. C op
  • 127. yr ig ht © 2 01 9. R ow m 369 James Rachels wrote The End of Life: Euthanasia and Morality (1986). Here he defends the “argument from mercy.” Euthanasia, he thinks, is justified when death is the only way to escape awful pain. In Rachels’ main example, the pain is suffered by someone dying from cancer. Rachels himself died of cancer in 2003. At the end of his life, nothing persuaded him to change his view of euthanasia. But he did wonder whether the argument from mercy would require less intentional killing than he had thought. Often a humane death occurs via “permanent sedation.” This is when a dying patient is given more and more pain medication for pain relief, which causes the patient to lose consciousness (or “go to sleep”) before
  • 128. dying. Under such circumstances, the intention to kill is unnecessary. The single most powerful argument in support of euthanasia is the argument from mercy. It is also an exceptionally simple argument, at least in its main idea, which makes one uncomplicated point. Termi- nally ill patients sometimes suffer pain so horrible that it is beyond the comprehension of those who have not actually experienced it. Their suffering can be so terrible that we do not even like to read about it or Chapter 33 The Morality of Euthanasia James Rachels James Rachels, “The Morality of Euthanasia” in Philosophy and Public Affairs, vol. 1, no. 1 (autumn 1971): 47–66. Used with permission. Rachels & Rachels_9781538127926.indb 369 17-06-2019 19:00:37 The Right Thing to Do : Readings in Moral Philosophy, edited by James Rachels, and Stuart Rachels, Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, 2019. ProQuest Ebook Central, http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/newschoolarch- ebooks/detail.action?docID=5798603. Created from newschoolarch-ebooks on 2020-05-14 19:24:15. C
  • 130. ll rig ht s re se rv ed . Chapter 33370 think about it; we recoil even from the description of such agony. The argument from mercy says euthanasia is justified because it provides an end to that. The great Irish satirist Jonathan Swift took eight years to die, while, in the words of Joseph Fletcher, “His mind crumbled to pieces.” At times the pain in his blinded eyes was so intense he had to be restrained from tearing them out with his own hands. Knives and other potential instruments of suicide had to be kept from him. For the last three years of his life, he could do nothing but sit and drool; and when he finally