SlideShare a Scribd company logo
1 of 24
Download to read offline
Cambridge Journal of Economics 2011, 35, 705–728 
doi:10.1093/cje/beq049 
Advance Access publication 5 January 2011 
Behavioural and experimental economics: 
are they really transforming economics? 
Ana C. Santos* 
Behavioural and experimental economics are part of an increasingly pluralistic 
mainstream economics, sharing with other recently established research pro-grammes 
the revision of fundamental assumptions of the previously dominant 
neoclassical economics research programme. The recent proliferation and consol-idation 
of these new approaches creates the possibility for the emergence of a new 
orthodoxy of economics, i.e. a new general research programme capable of replacing 
neoclassicism. The goal of this paper is to investigate the potential contribution of 
behavioural and experimental economics to help build a general research pro-gramme 
capable of supplanting neoclassical economics and thereby transforming 
economics. To this end, it focuses on two influential applied fields of behavioural and 
experimental economics—choice architecture and design economics. 
Key words: Anomalies, Choice architecture, Design economics, Market design, 
Recent economics 
JEL classifications: A12, B52, C90 
1. Introduction 
Behavioural and experimental economics are part of recent mainstream economics, 
sharing with other emergent research programmes the rejection of fundamental assump-tions 
and commitments of the previously dominant neoclassical economics research 
programme. The recent proliferation and consolidation of the new approaches, with 
overlapping areas of research and concerns, is now raising the possibility for the emergence 
of a new orthodoxy of economics, i.e. a new general research programme capable of 
replacing neoclassicism (Davis, 2006, 2008). The goal of this paper is to investigate the 
potential contribution of behavioural and experimental economics to transform econom-ics. 
I focus, in particular, on their capacity to carry out two major transformations that are 
deemed as characterising the ongoing process of change in the discipline: (i) the revision of 
the neoclassical economics model of human action, homo economicus; and (ii) the new 
economic approach to market building. In order to do this, I look at two recent applications 
Manuscript received 11 October 2009; final version received 17 November 2010. 
Address for correspondence: CES, Center for Social Studies, University of Coimbra, Cole´gio de S. Jero´nimo, 
Apartado 3087, 3001-401 Coimbra, Portugal; email: anacsantos@ces.uc.pt 
* University of Coimbra, Portugal. I acknowledge financial support from Fundacxa˜o Calouste Gulbenkian 
(n 21-107001-S). I would also like to thank the comments of Joa˜o Rodrigues and Jose´ Castro Caldas and 
those of three anonymous referees. Usual disclaimers naturally apply. 
 The Author 2011. Published by Oxford University Press on behalf of the Cambridge Political Economy Society. 
All rights reserved. 
Downloaded from cje.oxfordjournals.org by Robert Looney on July 2, 2011
706 A. C. Santos 
of these research programmes—choice architecture and design economics—which, as we 
shall see, focus on each one of these features in turn. 
The new research programmes, also comprising, among others, game theory, evolu-tionary 
economics and neuroeconomics, have a common denominator. They all are 
relatively recent developments whose emergence relied on conceptual contents imported 
from other disciplines, such as psychology, biology and neuroscience (Davis, 2006, 2008). 
Their trajectories thus stand in stark contrast to that of neoclassical economics, which is 
consolidated around a fairly well-delimited analytical toolkit that has been widely applied 
to other fields of research. The model of human action, homo economicus, and the model of 
the competitive market have been particularly instrumental to the expansion of the 
neoclassical approach outside the conventional realm of economics. They have been 
pivotal in the so-called ‘economics imperialism’ movement, contributing to universalising 
and naturalising a particular version of the market and the egotistic and rational attributes 
of human beings (Carvalho and Rodrigues, 2008). 
That the new fields of research have relied on content imported from disciplines with 
radically different principles, presuppositions and conceptual frameworks, making up 
a rather heterogeneous and pluralistic mainstream economics, naturally fuels the 
expectation of change in economics. John Davis (2008), for example, considers that the 
recent approaches carry a great transformative potential, superior to that of the traditional 
heterodox approaches. Notwithstanding the fact that both recent and traditional heterodox 
approaches depart from key assumptions of neoclassical economics and have close ties with 
sciences outside economics, only the new research programmes are moving inwards 
toward the core of economics in a deliberate attempt to redirect it. This is taken to be the 
case of current behavioural economics. Having its origins in psychology and its primary 
focus on the critique of homo economicus, behavioural economics is now attempting to 
incorporate new behavioural assumptions into new models of human action (cf. Camerer 
and Loewenstein, 2004). Traditional heterodox approaches, in contrast, remain oriented 
toward the periphery of economics, rejecting core neoclassical principles rather than 
attempting to reform them, and insisting on an alternative foundation for economics, one 
more based on closer ties to other social sciences. The greater transformative potential of 
the new approaches is further supported by the higher professional status that the 
practitioners of the new approaches seem to be enjoying, as testified by the award, in 2002, 
of the Bank of Sweden Prize in Economic Sciences in Memory of Alfred Nobel to Daniel 
Kahneman, ‘for having integrated insights from psychological research into economic 
science, especially concerning human judgment and decision-making under uncertainty’ 
and to Vernon Smith ‘for having established laboratory experiments as a tool in empirical 
economic analysis, especially in the study of alternative market mechanisms’.1 
Choice architecture and design economics are policy applications that provide 
a privileged vantage point from which to assess the potential of the new approaches to 
transform economics. This is so because, as we shall see, policy proposals render 
particularly salient economists’ conceptions of economics and of the social world. 
Choice architecture and design economics unequivocally depart from the research 
strategies of neoclassical economics. Rather than assuming at the outset that human beings 
are homo economicus, i.e. that they are always capable of maximising their individual utility, 
choice architecture takes as a starting point how people actually deal with particular forms 
of decision-problems. The purpose of choice architecture is to prepare contexts of choice 
1 http://nobelprize.org/nobel_prizes/economics/laureates/2002/ 
Downloaded from cje.oxfordjournals.org by Robert Looney on July 2, 2011
Behavioural and experimental economics 707 
to help individuals make better choices, as judged by individuals themselves, or by society 
as a whole (Thaler and Sunstein, 2003, 2008). Design economics is in turn devoted to the 
conception of specific allocation mechanisms that aim at coordinating individual actions 
for the accomplishment of the goals set by the designer (Roth, 2002). Rather than 
assuming that markets emerge spontaneously and automatically generate efficient 
allocations of resources, design economics puts at the forefront the complex social 
engineering processes involved in the building of markets and market-like allocation 
mechanisms that determine individual outcomes and the aggregate results that are 
obtained by having people interacting under those mechanisms. 
Yet it is not clear that the reform of the core principles of economics is under way. Both 
choice architecture and design economics seem to retain two fundamental principles of 
neoclassical economics—rationality and efficiency. Having observed that economic agents 
are not always rational and that their actions in market and non-market contexts do not 
always produce desirable outcomes, economists seem now to be dedicated to the 
fabrication of the conditions of rationality and efficiency. And there is a clear division of 
labour. While architect-economists are devoted to the creation of contexts of choice that 
make rational choices viable, designer-economists are devoted to the construction of 
market mechanisms that ensure socially efficient outcomes. Thus, while importing new 
models of individual decision-making and new experimental technologies, choice 
architecture and design economics still seem to retain the neoclassical view of rational 
choice, defined in terms of the choice that confers the individual the highest net benefit 
given constraints, and of the market understood as a mere allocation mechanism. This 
might in fact explain the success of choice architects and design economists as policy 
advisors. Notwithstanding the ongoing process of change in economics, economic 
discourse and general perceptions about economics may lag far behind. Policy proposals 
that appeal to the standard normative notions of rationality and efficiency might thus still 
be well-received by policy-makers and the general public. However that may be, the fact of 
the matter is that Richard Thaler, Cass Sunstein and Alvin Roth are all accomplished and 
much sought after scholars to give advice and help reconfigure a variety of socioeconomic 
institutions.2 
If on the one hand, the rejection of key assumptions of neoclassical economics may entail 
a transformative potential, the preservation of the neoclassical criteria of rationality and 
efficiency, on the other hand, may suggest that neoclassical economics principles are still 
very much present in the new approaches. The goal of this paper is to investigate this 
tension so as to evaluate the prospects of change in economics and the emergence of a new 
general research programme capable of replacing neoclassicism. Section 2 starts off by 
briefly reviewing the recent transformations taking place in economics. Section 3 presents 
and analyses choice architecture while Section 4 is given over to the presentation and 
examination of design economics. Section 5 then discusses the tensions that arise from the 
revision of the key assumptions of the neoclassical research programme that preserves its 
normative criteria of rationality and efficiency. Based on the analysis of choice architecture 
2 Thaler and Sunstein are from Chicago University and were famously advertised as campaign advisors to 
the then Presidential candidate, Barack Obama. Sunstein is the current Administrator of the White House 
Office of Information and Regulatory Affairs. Thaler was advisor to the leader of the British Conservative 
party, David Cameron, and continues to advise the institutional investment firm Fuller  Thaler Asset 
Management, Inc., which he founded (see Chakrabortty, 2008; Lewis, 2008; Wilby, 2008). Roth is from 
Harvard University and he too has been a consultant for various American public entities, such as The 
National Resident Matching Program and The New York City Department of Education. 
Downloaded from cje.oxfordjournals.org by Robert Looney on July 2, 2011
708 A. C. Santos 
and design economics, Section 6 draws the main conclusions of the paper regarding the 
potential of behavioural and experimental economics to transform economics. 
2. Neoclassical dominance and the new mainstream pluralism 
This paper appraises the departures of choice architecture and design economics from 
neoclassical economics so as to assess the potential of behavioural and experimental 
economics to transform economics. At this juncture, two caveats are in order. First, 
controversy abounds regarding the implications of behavioural and experimental econom-ics, 
within and between the practitioners of the two research programmes. The 
experimental economist Vernon Smith (2008, pp. 155–6), for instance, seems to consider 
behavioural economics to be outside the scope of economics, dealing with ‘the 
performance consistency (choice rationality) of individual decision making’, which ‘is 
not where the action is in understanding economic performance and human achievement’. 
Economics is instead about how ‘wealth is created by task specialization across individuals, 
groups, populations, regions and climates’, where ‘specialization is determined by the 
depth and breadth of the market’. Smith thus seems to exclude from experimental 
economics individual decision-making experiments. Experimental economics concerns 
instead ‘market performance (market rationality), incentives in public good provision and 
small group interactions, and other environments with dispersed individual valuations’. 
Camerer and Lowenstein (2004, p. 3) consider instead that experimental economics is 
defined by the laboratory method, as applied to both individual choice and market 
behaviour. Behavioural economics is particularly devoted to improving ‘the realism of the 
psychological underpinnings of economic analysis’, which is deemed to advance the field of 
economics by ‘generating theoretical insights, making better predictions of field phenom-ena, 
and suggesting better policy’. For the purpose of the analysis to be carried out, I will 
focus on behavioural economics’ revisions to homo economicus, and on the contribution of 
experimental market economics to the reconsideration of the neoclassical conception of 
the market. Examination of the transformative potential of behavioural economics will be 
based on the analysis of choice architecture and that of experimental market economics on 
the analysis of design economics. This means, and this is the second caveat, that the 
analysis to be carried out will be necessarily partial. Nonetheless, choice architecture and 
design economics are taken to be particularly informative of the ongoing process of change 
in the discipline, namely concerning: (i) the revision of the neoclassical economics model 
of human action, homo economicus (e.g. Frey and Benz, 2004); and (ii) the recent economic 
approach to market building (e.g. Mirowski, 2007). 
Homo economicus is the neoclassical economics model of human action. Homo economicus 
is rational and typically selfish. He chooses so as to maximise his utility and succeeds in 
doing so. No cognitive limitation of any kind gets in his way when calculating the costs and 
benefits of the alternatives at hand. Nor does he have self-control problems that impede the 
selection and the pursuit of the alternative that benefits him the most. Because he is 
generally guided by his narrow self-interest, choice depends on his individual subjective 
preferences and the constraints he faces, in particular his income and the relative prices 
(explicit or implicit) of the different choice alternatives. The natural habitat of homo 
economicus is the market. The market, through its price mechanism, is deemed to provide 
the relevant information and the required incentives for multiplying the range of choice 
and thereby for maximising individual utility and social welfare, which is no more than the 
sum of individual utilities. 
Downloaded from cje.oxfordjournals.org by Robert Looney on July 2, 2011
Behavioural and experimental economics 709 
According to the neoclassical approach, governments should abstain from ‘intervening’ 
in the market; otherwise they will distort prices and thereby undermine rational decision-making 
and social well-being. Government action should be restricted to so-called market 
failures, for in these cases prices no longer reflect the costs and benefits of alternative 
options. But even in these cases governments should avoid as much as possible restricting 
individual choice through laws and regulation. They should instead try to mould individual 
behaviour via the use of pecuniary incentives, attempting to align individual and group 
interests by changing the costs and benefits of the various courses of actions. Pecuniary 
incentives are deemed to be effective in a rational world where individuals react to changes 
in their possibility space in a systematic and predictable way, refraining from pursuing 
costly and undesirable actions, which do not need to be outlawed, and engaging in more 
beneficial activities. 
Even though the ‘market’ is the central institution of neoclassical economics, it has not 
been constituted as an object of study on its own right. There has been little interest in 
studying how specific markets operate and how prices are actually obtained. Instead, it has 
been taken as a relatively homogenous and undifferentiated entity, to which are associated 
vague notions of supply and demand that jointly determine the equilibrium price of 
commodities (Hodgson, 2008). 
The abstract model of human action and the vague conception of the market are two key 
elements in economics imperialism, which has consisted of the extension of the economic 
approach to a variety of non-economic fields of research in politics, law, history, the arts 
and the family (Frey and Benz, 2004).3 This process has also been extended to public 
discourse and to the conducting of public policy, resulting in an increased commodifica-tion 
of social life. Neoclassical economics has in this way been part of a process of 
universalisation of market-based social relations (Carvalho and Rodrigues, 2008). 
Recent research challenges the homo economicus model and places a greater emphasis on 
the role of institutions, specifically of market institutions, in guiding and shaping human 
behaviour, as well as in determining aggregate outcomes. As Philip Mirowski (2007, 
p. 211) summarises, we are moving ‘from a period when ‘‘the market’’ has been left implicit 
and undefined to an era in which markets are becoming the center of attention’. Economics 
has hence ‘become less fixated upon agency and more concerned to theorize the meaning 
and significance of a diversity of (small-m) markets’. Recent change in economics has thus 
consisted of the inversion of interest in the status and nature of agents in favour of the 
specifications of markets. 
These transformations are by and large the result of both behavioural and experimental 
economics. The gradual establishment of these fields of research, most notably since the 
1990s, has contributed to draw the profession’s attention to the study of the behavioural 
deviations from the predictions of the rational model of human action, and to the role of 
socioeconomic institutions in determining individual behaviour and aggregate outcomes. 
Choice architecture and design economics derive the policy implications of the recently 
acquired understanding of human behaviour and of the role of the overall institutional 
setting. They rely on distinct resources, however. Choice architecture builds upon the 
‘behavioural’ experiments of economics, as well as from evidence obtained from other 
methods and from other disciplines (especially from cognitive psychology), which have 
produced knowledge of individuals’ attributes (e.g. preferences, attitudes toward risk, and 
so on) and of the processes by which people select and apply heuristics or abide by social 
3 See Ma¨ki (2009) for a discussion on the notion of economics imperialism. 
Downloaded from cje.oxfordjournals.org by Robert Looney on July 2, 2011
710 A. C. Santos 
norms when facing particular individual and collective decision-making problems. Design 
economics builds instead upon the ‘technological’ experiments of economics that are 
particularly tailored to study market institutions, namely their incentive compatibility 
attributes, i.e. their capacity to induce self-interested individuals to take the actions that 
achieve desirable results at the aggregate level (cf. Santos 2007; 2010, cap. 10). 
Behavioural experiments have produced a substantial amount of evidence that shows 
that human beings are prone to systematic error even in areas of economic relevance where 
stakes are high (e.g. Thaler, 1992; Camerer, 1995). Rather than grounding individual 
choice on the calculus of the costs and benefits of alternative options so as to choose the 
alternative that provides the highest net benefit, individuals have recourse to a variety of 
decisional rules and are influenced by various contextual factors that jeopardise the pursuit 
of individuals’ best interests. The increased understanding of how people actually select 
and apply rules for dealing with particular forms of decision problems and of the influence 
of contexts on individual choices is the starting point of choice architecture devoted to the 
study of choice setups that can curb human idiosyncrasies to good result, as judged by 
individuals themselves, or by society as a whole (Thaler and Sunstein, 2003, 2008). 
Technological experiments have produced a substantial amount of evidence of the 
relative performance of various market mechanisms (e.g. Kagel, 1995). More recently, 
they have been used as engineering tools for building new markets from scratch. That is, 
they have been used for building ‘economic machines’, which ‘are supposed to work for 
several years, in different contexts and without constant supervision of their manufacturer’ 
(Guala, 2001, p. 464) or as ‘testbeds’ of ‘a working prototype of a process that is going to be 
employed in a complex environment’ (Plott, 1997, p. 605). These experiments have forced 
economists to explicitly recognise that markets are the outcome of complex social 
engineering processes that determine the rules under which individuals are to act and 
the aggregate results that obtain by having economic agents interacting under these rules 
(Roth, 2002). In the next two sections, I look in more detail into the policy proposals of 
choice architecture and design economics so as to investigate the extent to which they 
depart from neoclassical economics and thereby assess the potential of the recent 
approaches to transforming economics. 
3. The assumptions of neoclassical economic theory, behavioural anomalies 
and choice architecture 
The neoclassical economics model of human action, homo economicus, relies on two basic 
assumptions—unbounded rationality and self-interest— which underlie the utility max-imising 
analysis of human behaviour. Experimental work first carried out by cognitive 
psychologists, and subsequently by economists, identified so-called ‘anomalies’, 
i.e. patterns of judgment and choice that are inconsistent with utility maximisation, 
challenging both assumptions.4 Behavioural economists have, then, attempted to replace 
the standard assumptions of economics with more realistic descriptions of human 
behaviour that could account for people’s bounded rationality and other-regarding 
considerations. However, the revised conception of human action was not accompanied 
by an equivalent change in economic theorising. While accommodating ‘anomalous’ 
4 Richard Thaler had an important role in introducing these results to economists in the column 
‘anomalies’ of the prestigious Journal of Economic Perspectives, between 1987 and 1990. His The Winner’s 
Curse: Paradoxes and Anomalies of Economic Life, published in 1992, brings together some of these 
experimental results. See also Camerer (1995). 
Downloaded from cje.oxfordjournals.org by Robert Looney on July 2, 2011
behaviours, an important part of theoretical work has maintained formal rigour and kept 
the traditional fields of application and the disciplinary boundaries intact (cf. Camerer and 
Lowenstein, 2004). This strategy allowed economists to retain the utility maximising 
principle, considering, for example, that individuals simply have a richer set of preferences 
than was traditionally considered, such as the so-called social preferences (cf. Camerer and 
Fehr, 2004).5 
But empirical research unequivocally challenges the standard rationality assumption. 
People do make systematic mistakes, failing to choose what is best for them. Rather than 
basing their decisions on the calculus of the net benefits of various choice alternatives, people 
have recourse to simple rules of thumb, or heuristics, which help them cope with various 
problems in a quick and satisfactory way, thus allowing saving precious time with time-consuming 
deliberation (Tversky and Kahneman, 1974). However, sometimes these 
heuristics lead to inferior choices, i.e. choices that would be corrected if people had 
complete information, unlimited cognitive abilities and unbreakable willpower, and took 
time to make their calculations. This body of evidence leads Thaler and Sunstein (2008, pp. 
6–7) to conclude that rather than homo economicus, people are homo sapiens, that is, humans. 
The psychologists Amos Tversky and Daniel Kahneman (1974) long ago identified three 
pervasive heuristics—anchoring and adjustment, availability and representativeness—and 
the biases they generate. The ‘anchoring and adjustment’ heuristic, to give one example, 
leads to excessive influence of a particular feature of the problem (which works as an 
‘anchor’) because individuals often fail adequately to take into account other relevant 
elements of the decision problem. The psychologists have also noted that the framing of the 
decision-problem, i.e. the way the problem is described and presented, has a strong impact 
on the choices individuals make (Tversky and Kahneman, 1981; Kahneman and Tversky, 
2000). This goes against the assumption that individual preferences and the inherent costs 
and benefits of the alternatives at hand are the sole determinants of human behaviour. Not 
only do people ignore features that economic theory takes as relevant, they are also 
influenced by factors that economists do not consider. 
The status quo bias is a particularly frequent behavioural pattern (Samuelson and 
Zeckhauser, 1988) and of particular interest to choice architecture, as we shall see below. It 
consists of the tendency to stick to one’s current situation, even when the risk of altering the 
situation is low compared to maintaining the situation. This behaviour may be explained 
by people’s aversion to losses, i.e. the tendency to place a greater negative value on losses 
(e.g. letting go of the present situation) than on gains (e.g. the benefits of change). Status 
quo bias may also be caused by what is known as the ‘omission/commission bias’—people’s 
tendency to care more about errors of their own actions (commission) than about errors 
that occur as a result of their inaction (omission) (Ritov and Baron, 1992). Another 
possible cause of the status quo bias is procrastination, i.e. the tendency to delay beneficial 
actions that involve immediate costs, such as dieting (O’Donoghue and Rabin, 1999). 
Individuals’ excessive optimism and overconfidence in their own abilities may further 
exacerbate this tendency. 
The opposite behavioural pattern is also frequent and important. People are as well 
prone to hasty decisions due to self-control problems, which may lead them to fall into 
temptation, doing things that they later regret. This often occurs when the benefits of the 
goods or actions are immediate and costs are delayed. This effect is even stronger if 
5 See also Starmer (2000) for a review of theoretical developments prompted by experimental research on 
individual decision-making under risk. 
Behavioural and experimental economics 711 
Downloaded from cje.oxfordjournals.org by Robert Looney on July 2, 2011
712 A. C. Santos 
individuals are in emotionally or biologically ‘hot’ states, which may provoke an 
overestimation of the short-term benefits of falling prey to the temptation (Loewenstein 
et al., 2003). 
Notwithstanding the accumulated evidence, many (non-behavioural) economists re-main 
sceptical. They argue that people do a better job of choosing in the ‘real world’, 
especially in markets where they face problems that really matter to them and the stakes are 
high (e.g. Binmore, 1999). But the anomalous phenomena have been replicated with 
higher stakes, both in the lab (Camerer and Hogarth, 1999) and in the ‘real’ world, as in 
financial markets (Shiller, 2000). 
The consideration that individuals are boundedly rational and weakly willpowered is 
now inspiring various versions of so-called ‘soft paternalistic’ approaches to individual 
decision-making—asymmetric paternalism, cautious paternalism, libertarian paternalism 
(cf. Camerer et al., 2003)—devoted to helping people make choices more in line with 
maximising behaviour, while avoiding as much as possible placing limits on individual 
choice and thus causing harm to those who behave rationally. Choice architecture, 
proposed by Richard Thaler and Cass Sunstein, is a case in point.6 
The starting point of choice architecture is the human propensity to err. Choice 
architecture departs from the assumption that ‘almost all people, almost all of the time, 
make choices that are in their best interest or at the very least are better than the choices 
that would be made by someone else’ (Thaler and Sunstein, 2008, p. 9). As the empirical 
studies mentioned above show, not so infrequently people make choices they would not 
have made if they had relevant information, unlimited cognitive abilities to process it and 
complete self-control. They are particularly vulnerable when they face complex and 
infrequent decisions that offer poor feedback. Not only will they have difficulty in 
translating aspects of the situation into terms they can easily understand, but they may also 
be exploited by those who can profit from their vulnerability to make predictable mistakes. 
Based on an informed view of actual human behaviour, the choice architect has, then, 
‘the responsibility for organizing the context in which people make decisions’ (Thaler and 
Sunstein, 2008, p. 3). The goal is ‘to steer people’s choices in directions that will improve 
their lives’, that is, ‘‘that will make choosers better off, as judged by themselves’ (p. 5) A 
critical aspect of choice architecture is that it emphatically avoids constraining the options 
of the individual. Its aim is instead to alter ‘people’s behaviour in a predictable way without 
forbidding any options or significantly changing their economic incentives’ (p. 6).7 As 
Thaler and Sunstein put it, ‘[f]reedom to choose is the best safeguard against bad choice 
architecture’ (p. 11). 
Choice architecture is devoted to the design of what the authors call ‘nudges’ that 
attempt to induce the choices that best serve individual (or collective) interests by taking 
into account how people make decisions in particular contexts. Two key instruments of 
choice architecture are default options and disclosure devices. Default options deal with 
individuals’ status quo biases by carefully designing a solution that is automatically selected 
if the individual fails to choose for him/herself. Thaler and Sunstein point out that default 
options should only be proposed if it is unambiguous that they serve individuals’ best 
interests. Automatic enrolment in the American 401(k) employee saving plans, to give an 
example, is thought to benefit employees, since the costs of saving too little for retirement 
are admittedly much greater and severe than the costs of saving too much. In any case, 
6 Except when stated otherwise, this section refers to Thaler and Sunstein (2008). 
7 The authors are here referring to pecuniary incentives. 
Downloaded from cje.oxfordjournals.org by Robert Looney on July 2, 2011
Behavioural and experimental economics 713 
those who do not wish to be part of the plan may always opt out. The authors consider that 
the low rates of opt outs observed in the past suggest that most employees do benefit from 
this measure, enrolling earlier than they would otherwise do, if they did so at all. These 
measures would not be necessary in a fully rational world in which individuals always 
choose the best option regardless of the default. But individuals’ inertia and tendency to 
procrastinate more likely lead to no action. Default options have been shown to be 
particularly effective, especially so if they also entail an explicit endorsement from the 
default setter that it is the recommended course of action (Thaler and Sunstein, 2008, 
p. 83). 
The choice architect may also select the relevant information for decision-making and 
design information disseminating devices that facilitate comparison of the alternative 
options. This solution is proposed for decisions involving complex pricing schemes, such as 
mortgages, cell phone calling plans and insurance policies. According to Thaler and 
Sunstein, in these cases the government should regulate disclosure practices, requiring that 
customers be informed of fees, in a legible format, and be given regular reports of the fees 
that have been charged. These reports would provide consumers with feedback so that they 
could shift their demand to the services that most adequately fit their consumption 
patterns. Besides the design of defaults or information disclosure devices, choice architects 
may have recourse to other tools to attenuate people’s propensity to err, say the framing of 
the context of choice, which may be tamed to better capture the analytical structure of the 
decision-problem; moreover, they may take advantage of people’s attributes, for instance, 
people’s susceptibility to social influence, by making salient the prudent and beneficial 
actions of others. 
Consumption, saving and investment decisions constitute obvious areas for the 
application of choice architecture. The high rates of household indebtedness in developed 
economies (but not only) are to some extent explained by individuals’ failure to make wise 
consumption/investment decisions, due to non-transparent and difficult-to-process in-formation 
and to self-control problems, given that the temptation of immediate 
gratification is too salient as compared with the costs of hasty/risky decisions that are 
only suffered at a later time. 
Matters are at present even more complicated by the highly sophisticated and complex 
financial markets that have rendered credit and investment decisions increasingly more 
difficult. Less educated individuals are in a particularly disadvantaged position because 
they are more vulnerable to aggressive campaigns and marketing strategies deployed by 
those who profit from consumers’ hasty decisions. This is explicitly recognised by Thaler 
and Sunstein, when referring to mortgage markets: 
When markets get more complicated, unsophisticated and uneducated shoppers will be 
especially disadvantaged by the complexity. The unsophisticated shoppers are also more likely 
to be given bad or self-interested advice by people serving in roles that appear to be helpful and 
purely advisory. In this market, mortgage brokers who cater to rich clients probably have 
a greater incentive to establish a reputation for fair dealing. By contrast, mortgage brokers who 
cater to the poor are often more interested in making a quick buck. (Thaler and Sunstein, 2008, 
p. 134) 
In this particular situation, Thaler and Sunstein’s proposal is to demand that mortgage 
lenders provide the relevant information in a readable format so that all the fees and interest 
rate provisions can be more easily compared. They argue that this will not only make it easier 
to shop, but it will also allow independent third parties to offer much better advice, thus 
making the mortgage market more competitive (Thaler and Sunstein, 2008, p. 138). 
Downloaded from cje.oxfordjournals.org by Robert Looney on July 2, 2011
714 A. C. Santos 
Choice architecture thus mobilises the recently acquired understanding of how 
individuals process information and make decisions, to design contexts of choice that 
help people make better choices. The choice architect may focus on the design of default 
options that protect individuals from inertia or conceive information devices to help 
improve people’s ability to select options that make them better off. At the same time the 
designer should avoid, as much as possible, changing the incentive structure of the 
problem-situation. The authors stress ‘[t]he central goal would be to inform costumers of 
fees rather than set prices’ (Thaler and Sunstein, 2008, p. 83). 
It is by now clear that the neoclassical models of rational choice and of the competitive 
market loom in the background of choice architecture. The problem, as Thaler and Sunstein 
see it, is that individuals fail to conform to the rational choice model due to incomplete 
information, cognitive limitations and weak willpower. Prevalent incentives in opaquemarkets 
may even exacerbate this problem because it can be highly profitable to exploit people’s 
bounded rationality. The choice architect should then help people with decision-making so 
that they more closely align their demand with the actual benefits derived from consumption. 
In this way, choice architecture also contributes to bettering the functioning of competitive 
markets by reducing the detrimental effects of asymmetric information between buyers and 
sellers. The more consumersmake the right choices, the more markets become competitive. 
Thaler and Sunstein thus work within the larger framework of the neoclassical research 
programme trying to deal with the problems of asymmetric information and decision-makers’ 
bounded rationality. Even though they acknowledge that in many circumstances 
choice architectures are unavoidably designed by someone else for others to make their 
choices, they do not address this key issue to choice architecture. They merely identify 
complex and difficult decision-making as obvious areas for the intervention of the 
benevolent choice architect. Thus, they do not consider the possibility that some of 
people’s ‘errors’ might in fact be the result, intended or unintended, of current choice 
architectures. This means that choice architecture only addresses those problems caused 
by incomplete information, bounded rationality and weak willpower, leaving out those that 
stem from faulty choice architectures. This is patent when Thaler and Sunstein discuss 
mortgage markets, disregarding the participation of the wider financial system in growing 
household rates of overindebtedness, limiting their focus on the complexity of these kinds 
of decision, the main problem to be fixed by choice architecture. 
The work of Robert J. Shiller (2000, 2008) on financial markets illustrates the interplay 
between choice architectures and human behaviour showing that understanding individual 
decision-making requires understanding the institutional structure inside of which people 
act. Shiller interprets the so-called subprime crisis not so much in terms of the complexity 
of the decision-making process, but instead in terms of an ‘epidemic of irrational 
enthusiasm for housing investments’ caused by the perverse incentives of the financial 
sector. On Shiller’s view, the unsustainable levels of mortgage borrowing in the USA were 
ultimately caused by dramatic institutional changes in financial markets over the last three 
decades, through deregulation and, more recently, financial innovation, culminating in 
what is known as the New Financial Architecture. The new institutional setting, together 
with rising housing prices and low interest rates, rendered mortgage lending a highly 
lucrative investment fed by a new securitisation industry.8 When house prices collapsed 
8 The feedback mechanisms are well-known: mortgage brokers sold loans, investment bankers packaged 
the loans into securities, banks and specialist institutions serviced the securities, rating agencies gave their seal 
of approval, and insurance companies protected holders of such securities against loss through the use of 
credit default swaps. 
Downloaded from cje.oxfordjournals.org by Robert Looney on July 2, 2011
Behavioural and experimental economics 715 
and interest rates rose, and borrowers started to default on their payments, the mortgage 
market collapsed, impacting on other parts of the globe, since mortgage-based financial 
products had been dispersed around the world. The end result was the greatest financial 
crisis since 1929. According to Shiller, the ‘subprime solution’ must result in a profound 
restructuring of the housing and financial economy of the magnitude of the New Deal. 
This therefore suggests, at least as regards individual decision-making in financial markets, 
that a more significant amount of institutional engineering than solving people’s status quo 
biases or hasty decision making is required. Otherwise, governments will have to be called 
upon to rescue financial actors with ever more massive bailouts to guarantee the sector’s 
sustainability (Crotty, 2009). 
The minimalist solutions of choice architecture contain an implicit acceptance of the 
prevalent institutional arrangements. This is clear in Thaler and Sunstein’s rhetoric, where 
choice architecture is to be subjected to the preservation of ‘freedom of choice’ and of the 
free functioning of the market, which is deemed as characterising the present situation. 
The solutions proposed, however mild, may nonetheless have effects on the status quo ante. 
If the new choice architecture is to be effective, in the sense that it succeeds in steering 
individual behaviour in desirable directions, it necessarily interferes with the interests in 
place, reallocating economic opportunities among differently situated individuals. Those 
most adversely affected by the new institutional setup will probably resist, depicting the 
new policy as an unnatural ‘intervention’ into some natural state. 
However, policy is not some alien ‘intervention’ into a naturally evolved reality. The 
status quo ante is itself the result of past political processes—a point that has been made by 
various generations of institutional economists, especially in the tradition of John 
Commons (1931). It is only our ‘institutionalised mind’ that sees current practices, 
choices and actions as normal, right and correct, and changes to that situation as artificial 
‘interventions’ (Bromley, 2006). And people, as behavioural economists would now add, 
have a tendency to resist change. To conclude with the wording of Warren J. Samuels 
(1989, p. 432) ‘[w]hat is normally considered ‘‘intervention’’ is not the intrusion of 
government in an area in which government hitherto has been absent but the change of the 
interests to which government gives its support or which government is used to support’. 
The objection that institutional change is coercive and inhibitive of individual ‘freedom’ is 
therefore incoherent, as is the complaint that public policy creates ‘distortions’ in an 
otherwise frictionless economy (Bromley, 2006). What institutional change does is alter 
the previous allocation of economic opportunities among differently situated individuals, 
advancing the economic and social agendas of some and impeding those of others. From this 
it follows that the concept of efficiency cannot refer to some natural state of world. Efficiency 
is always measured by reference to some institutional setup that indicates which instances of 
costs and benefits are to be considered and recorded (Samuels, 1992). If the context 
changes, what will count as rational and efficient will change too. This is illustrated in the 
next section, where institutional change is more explicitly addressed in design economics. 
4. Design economics and the expansion of markets 
Design economics affords the economist a more active role in the (re)design of contexts of 
choice. Design economics is in fact presented as the engineering field of economics. In 
Roth’s (2002, p. 1341) account, it is ‘the part of economics intended to further the design 
and maintenance of markets and other economic institutions’. And like any other 
engineering field, design economics is taken to deal with the ‘natural’ complications that 
Downloaded from cje.oxfordjournals.org by Robert Looney on July 2, 2011
716 A. C. Santos 
arise when applying theory to practicalmatters, for which end it mobilises the resources from 
three emergent research programmes of economics: game theory, computational and 
experimental economics. Game theory provides the general framework for addressing 
design, in particular, for the definition of the ‘rules of the game’. The tools of computational 
and experimental economics are instead used to ‘bridge the gap’ between theory and the 
institutional details of particular markets. Computational methods, in particular, ‘will help us 
analyze games that may be too complex to solve analytically’, while laboratory experiments 
‘will help inform us about how people will behave when confronted with these environments, 
both when they are inexperienced and as they gain experience’ (Roth, 2002, pp. 1373–4). 
Design economics emerged in the 1990s when game theorists began to be hired as 
consultants for the design of various allocation mechanisms that were soon to be 
implemented in real world environments. The design and implementation of these new 
mechanisms raised technical complications for which no theory or past experience could 
suggest any solution, and new devices had to be designed from scratch. Two famous 
exemplars of these allocations mechanisms are the design of labour clearinghouses for the 
US National Resident Matching Program (NRMP) that would assign hospital positions to 
young doctors, and the design of an auction mechanism for the US Federal Communi-cations 
Commission (FCC) that would allocate licenses to use the electromagnetic 
spectrum for various telecommunications services. 
The NRMP clearinghouse called for the design of a matching algorithm that would 
allocate applicants to residence programs based on preferences lists of both doctors and 
hospitals, avoiding favouring one side of the market over the other, while producing 
a stable matching (i.e. a matching on which both parties could agree). To this end, the 
performances of alternative algorithms were assessed and compared in terms of the impact 
on each side of the market, speed, stability and so forth. The FCC auction was intended to 
allocate airwave spectrum rights in a transparent and efficient way. But while economists 
were hired to design new allocation mechanisms the responsibility for selecting or deciding 
whether to adopt the proposed design was retained by the public authority that hired them, 
in consultation with its various constituencies. 
The FCC auction provides a very useful illustration of design economics, which is worth 
looking at more closely.9 The FCC auctions have been greeted as the biggest engineering 
success of economics. In 1994, the FCC implemented what was to be known as the 
simultaneous–multiple-round–independent auction, which would soon be praised as ‘the 
greatest auction in history’ (McAfee and McMillan, 1996, p. 159). This auction launched 
a market for thousands of spectrum licenses, and its success in raising billions of dollars for 
the public treasury has been taken as evidence of the successful accomplishment of the 
goals set by the regulator. 
According to the official version, as recounted by the game theorists involved in their 
design, the auctions aimed at creating a transparent and efficient market that would 
allocate the airwave spectrum rights to highest value users—those who most valued and 
made best use of them.10 Until 1982, spectrum licenses were assigned by an administrative 
9 See Guala (2001) for a more detailed account of the engineering work involved in the construction of the 
FCC auctions. 
10 This account is based on game theorists’ reports of events, after efficiency had been set as the main goal 
of the auction to the detriment of welfare goals defined by Congress, such as the expansion of public access to 
new technologies, products and services, and the decentralisation of the licenses awarded to include small 
businesses, rural telephone companies and minority groups. For a more complete account of the political 
process involving the FCC auctions see Nik-Khah (2008). 
Downloaded from cje.oxfordjournals.org by Robert Looney on July 2, 2011
Behavioural and experimental economics 717 
hearing process (recognisably slow and non-transparent), which allocated licenses for free. 
After 1982, licenses were sold and allocated via a lottery system, which significantly 
improved the speed and transparency of the allocation mechanism, but it did not prevent 
opportunistic behaviour. Licenses could be bought and resold by individuals who did not 
want to use them and thus undeservedly appropriated revenue raised by the commercial 
use of the public spectrum. 
The auction mechanism seemed to offer a tremendous advantage over the alternatives. It 
offered the possibility of identifying the firms with the highest use-values for the spectrum, 
which would be in a position to pay the highest prices for using it and, as a result, maximise 
the FCC’s revenue. This in turn required the design of an auction mechanism that 
encouraged bidders to reveal their true valuations, while preventing opportunistic 
behaviour on their part. 
The building of the FCC auctions was a complex endeavor, best depicted as a patchwork 
of various and partial solutions to the particular issues that arise when building new 
markets. Auction design resembled ‘a kind of engineering activity’ that had recourse to all 
sorts of resources ranging from ‘practical judgments, guided by theory and all available 
evidence’ to ‘ad hoc methods to resolve issues about which theory is silent’ (Milgrom, 2000, 
p. 271). Game theory merely assisted in ‘developing intuition’, in particular in ‘show[ing] 
how people behave in various circumstances and [. . .] identify[ing] the tradeoffs involved in 
altering those circumstances’ (McAfee and McMillan, 1996, p. 171). 
The auction had to tackle three major technical issues. First, to ensure that the highest-value 
users bought and paid for the licenses at their value; second, to allow the composition 
of favoured combinations of licenses, which had to take into account licenses’ comple-mentarities 
and substitutability; and, third, to prevent opportunistic behaviour on the part 
of bidders, which would jeopardise the competitive gains obtained from instituting the 
market. Theory would help look at the strategic structure of the decision-making problem 
and anticipate ‘how bidders choose their bids, not knowing the value of the item for sale 
and not knowing what their rivals know; and what the seller can do to stimulate the bidding 
competition, not knowing how much any of the bidders is willing to pay’ (McMillan, 1994, 
p. 146). 
Based on advice from the game theorists, the FCC opted for the simultaneous–multiple-round– 
independent auction, which gave bidders the possibility of operating in several 
markets at the same time and thus of composing desirable aggregations of items or 
adjusting their aggregation to a last-resort composition if their first-choice aggregations 
became unattainable. The licenses would then be allocated to the highest bidder that paid 
his/her bid price. Many detailed rules were then defined to organise the running of the 
auction, namely how bidders were to engage in the transactions while attempting to 
prevent the opportunistic exploiting of any gap.11 
The next step consisted of gluing together these partial solutions and evaluating whether 
they could be implemented in an operational environment. Laboratory experiments were 
crucial in order to put the various pieces together into a workable mechanism and solve the 
11 For example, an activity rule required the payment of deposits on the total number of desired licenses at 
the beginning of the auction to ensure that market participants had actually intended to own and use the 
licenses. Given the high stakes at play, the government was also concerned with simplifying procedures in 
order to reduce the incidence of mistakes. To avoid the ‘winner’s curse’, i.e. selling of licenses to traders who 
overestimated their value, or to avoid the extra-cautionary behaviour of risk-averse bidders, the bids were 
announced at every round so that traders could make better estimates of the licenses’ values. The incidence of 
unpredictable mistakes was further taken into account by allowing bid withdrawal, though with a penalty. 
The auction rules in the end amounted to a 130 page document. 
Downloaded from cje.oxfordjournals.org by Robert Looney on July 2, 2011
718 A. C. Santos 
complications that emerged while trying to do so (Guala, 2001; Nik-Khah, 2008). The 
building of the FCC auctions thus followed a division of labour in which game theorists 
proposed the auction form and the rules that would organise the functioning of the market; 
and experimental economists implemented these rules in an electronic market. After 
stabilising the auction rules, the experimenters subsequently tested the auction under 
conditions that closely resembled the market to be implemented and thereby assessed the 
combined effect of the auction’s rules, which could not possibly be predicted by non-experimental 
means. 
Even though the accounts of the game theorists make us believe otherwise, the success 
story of the FCC auctions is not uncontroversial. In an evaluation of the results, Peter 
Cramton (1998, p. 735), a successful design economist, states that ‘any auction would look 
good relative to the FCC’s past experience with comparative hearings and lotteries’. At the 
same time, he concedes that ‘[s]ince I do not observe the bidders’ actual valuations, it is 
impossible to say exactly how efficient the auctions were’ and retreats to the more vague 
claim that the auctions were successful for the government, as judged by the revenues 
raised, and for bidders, as judged by the stability of license compositions (pp. 728–9). 
Edward Nik-Khah, based on the archives of the FCC, tells a different story, concluding: 
‘[o]verall, the allocation of licenses produced by the auctions proved to be unstable, as the 
industry has gone through a spate of mergers, acquisitions, and bankruptcies, ultimately 
leading to a high degree of license concentration’ (Nik-Khah, 2008, p. 90). Based on the 
analysis of 10 years of FCC auctions, comprising the data of 58 auctions, Gregory F. Rose 
and Mark Lloyd (2006) conclude that the auctions failed to maximise receipts and 
promote efficiency in the sector because bidders managed to carry out manipulative 
strategies (e.g. tacit collusion and pre-emptive bidding), which resulted in the auctioning of 
licenses at significantly lower prices. 
Yet game theorists were eager to wrap their contribution in the allure of science, 
emphasising that ‘the auction design process was driven not by politics, but by economics’ 
(McMillan, 1994, p. 147). But the process of building the auction was marked by the 
interests of the constituencies in place, namely those of the large telecommunications 
corporations. Large corporations hired game theorists to help them to position themselves 
in the policy-making process, first by lobbying for the most favourable architectures for the 
auctions and then by assisting in defining their clients’ bidding strategies (Nik-Khah, 
2008).12 As Charles Plott (1997, p. 606), one prominent consultant, candidly acknowl-edged: 
‘Business understood that the rules and form of the auction could influence who 
acquired what and how much was paid’. Thus, the building of the FCC auction was not 
a mere engineering exercise. It was a complex political process, where big companies 
actively exercised their influence before and during its operation. Because the FCC failed 
to prevent collusion and other anti-trust strategies, taking place both inside and outside the 
market, the market became more concentrated in the hands of a few large corporations. 
The FCC auctions thus make it plain that markets, and non-market allocation 
mechanisms for that matter, are complex institutional arrangements that require the 
engineering efforts of various social scientists and social actors, and that market outcomes 
depend on the particular configurations of these arrangements. Rather than assuming at 
the outset that markets ensure efficiency, via the symbiotic conjunction of agents’ 
12 To give just a few prominent names, Paul Milgrom, Robert Wilson and Charles Plott were hired by 
Pacific Bell, Preston McAfee by Airtouch Communications, Peter Cramton by CI, John Ledyard and David 
Porter by the National Telecommunications and Information Administration and, finally, JohnMcMillan by 
the FCC. 
Downloaded from cje.oxfordjournals.org by Robert Looney on July 2, 2011
Behavioural and experimental economics 719 
rationality and the information disseminated through prices, design economists are 
devoted to the study of ‘the rules of the game’. In Roth’s wording: 
The largest lesson in all this is that design is important because markets don’t always grow like 
weeds—some of them are hothouse orchids. Time and place have to be established, related goods 
need to be assembled, or related markets linked so that complementarities can be handled, 
incentive problems have to be overcome, etc. (Roth, 2002, pp. 1373–4) 
It is also clear that design economics is to be devoted to the ‘technical issues’ that arise in 
market building. That allocation mechanisms are the outcome of difficult and complex 
political processes is not adequately taken into account, especially the impact of these processes 
on the ‘technical’ goals set beforehand. Design economists, qua specialised technicians, deal 
with the technical complications that arise in social engineering, specifically with those that 
stem from the strategic environment and the opportunistic behaviour of economic agents, 
who will try to outwit the regulator, and from the cognitive limitations of real economic 
agents that may compromise the goals set by the regulator. This means that design 
economists also take into account the actual characteristics of economic agents. The 
effectiveness of market mechanisms requires that the design setter be able to predict how 
economic agents will behave under the new institutional setup. But in contrast to choice 
architecture, design economists focus on the structure of incentives. The new arrange-ments 
must be incentive compatible devices. They should align individual and collective 
interests in such a way that individuals’ incentives correspond to what is needed to achieve 
group optima, while making sure that economic agents understand the incentive structure 
so that they behave predictably, like homo economicus. In the FCC auctions this meant that 
the auction mechanism had to succeed in eliciting the subjective values of spectrum 
licenses to ensure telecom companies acquired the desired licenses, while contributing to 
an efficient allocation of the licenses, thus defined, and the maximisation of FCC revenue. 
In sum, design economics is devoted to the (re)design of complex markets and other 
economic institutions to be implemented in context-specific environments, to which end the 
opportunistic behaviour of economic agents and their propensity to err must be taken into 
account. The ultimate goal is to conceive a structure of incentives such that individual actions 
can generate desirable social states. Insofar as it overlooks the political process involved in the 
(re)building of new economic institutions, design economics risks failing on their own terms, 
that is, it fails to pursue its narrowly defined goals of efficiency. The higher the stakes, the 
more the (re)creation of a new market gives rise to an intense struggle for influence over the 
collective definition of ‘the new rules of the game’. The outcome will contain a high degree of 
uncertainty and it will depend on the correlation of power of those involved and their 
capability to bring forward their favoured solutions. This means that market building frames 
and shapes the interactions of individuals for the attainment of rather elusive goals, say the 
allocation of resources in an operational way, while attempting to curb opportunistic 
behaviour on their part. To put it in another way, the efficacy of design economics ultimately 
hinges on determining the extent to which economists are able to implement their models in 
the real world and make reality conform to their theoretical constructs, that is, on 
determining the performativity of economics (to be further discussed in Section 5).13 
13 This view is also shared by Vernon Smith (2008, ch. 6). While generally favourable to market design, he 
thinks that the ‘ecological fitness’ of ‘rational constructivist designs’ is only achieved, if at all, after a long 
process of trial-and-error that corrects behavioural incentives and strategic problems not considered in 
design. Smith clearly does not think that the FCC auctions have already stabilised and achieved their 
ecological fitness. 
Downloaded from cje.oxfordjournals.org by Robert Looney on July 2, 2011
720 A. C. Santos 
This exclusive concentration on ‘technical’ issues is even more salient when design 
economists propose the extension of market relations to non-market domains of social life. 
The introduction of market-like arrangements that set up contractual forms of exchange 
involving the transfer of money and property rights has encountered severe resistance, 
since this new form of exchange becomes ‘repugnant’, as Roth puts it, when money is 
added to the transaction. This ‘distaste for certain kinds of transactions can be a real 
constraint on markets and how they are designed, every bit as real as the constraints 
imposed by technology or by the requirements of incentives and efficiency’ (Roth, 2007, p. 
38). The challenge, from the point of view of the design economist, is to learn how to deal 
with these constraints, which are perceived as part of a technical problem that needs to be 
tackled. Roth then urges economists to understand better and engage more with the 
phenomena of repugnant transactions. This is so because ‘attitudes about the repugnance 
(or other kinds of inappropriateness) of transactions shape whole markets, and therefore 
shape what choices people face’ (Roth, 2007, p. 38). When referring to the debate over the 
creation of a market for the sale of kidneys, Roth (2007, pp. 53–4) makes this clearer by 
contrasting the irrational reactions of its opponents to the frustration of economists ‘at the 
failure to adopt what they see as a feasible solution that could be implemented quickly’. In 
Roth’s view, design economists, qua rational technicians, should take on ‘the important 
educational role of pointing to inefficiencies and tradeoffs, and costs and benefits’ (Roth, 
2007, p. 53). They should nonetheless be aware that the sources of repugnance (such as 
other-regarding motivations) mayaffect the efficacy of incentive schemes due to the crowding 
out of altruistic motivations (cf. Frey, 1997; Frey and Jegen, 2001).14 In order to be effective, 
new markets have to deal with all sorts of complications that arise in market building. 
To sum up, design economics is devoted to the (re)design of complex market institutions 
that deal with varied technical complications in context-specific environments. The 
ultimate goal is to (re)align the structure of incentives so that individual actions can bring 
about desirable social states. Design economics is not circumscribed to the market domain. 
The expansion of markets or market-like forms of exchange to other domains of social life, 
however, requires that the economist qua social engineer take on the pedagogic role of 
pointing to inefficiencies and tradeoffs, as well as costs and benefits, in discussions 
informed by taboo or visceral reactions.15 This brings into the analysis the impact of other-regarding 
considerations on the efficacy of public policy. The underlying political processes 
of market design and the struggle for political influence are left out, however. 
5. Choice architectures and market designs are political constructs 
Choice architecture and design economics convey two major transformations deemed as 
characterising the ongoing process of change in the discipline: (i) the revision of the 
neoclassical model of human action, homo economicus; and (ii) the recent economics 
approach to market building. But while fully acknowledging that individuals are not always 
rational and that markets are complex socially engineered institutions, these recent 
developments retain the view of economics as the science of choice, which ought to 
conform to the rational choice model, and select the market as the most adequate 
institution to coordinate individual actions in various realms of social life. With minor or 
14 To be further explained below. 
15 Roth’s account provides an unflattering caricature of critical reactions to the expansion of market forms 
of social interaction. See the Journal of Economic Perspectives, vol. 21, no. 3, for the debate around the creation 
of a market for the sale of human kidneys, where both positions are more reasonably presented and discussed. 
Downloaded from cje.oxfordjournals.org by Robert Looney on July 2, 2011
Behavioural and experimental economics 721 
major tinkering with the institutional setup, economists are committed to helping people 
make rational choices and to coordinate their actions efficiently for the attainment of 
socially desirable ends. Institutional change targets incentive structures, information 
disclosure devices and other calculation tools to assist individuals when determining the 
costs and benefits of alternative options. They will then make choices more aligned with 
the maximisation of individual utility and with what is required to achieve socially desirable 
outcomes. 
Not only do these proposals retain the fundamental principles of neoclassical 
economics—rationality and efficiency—they also continue to promote their expansion to 
various domains of social life. Through the architecture of contexts of choice and the 
design of market mechanisms, economists are putting their expertise at the service of 
individual rationality and economic efficiency, within and beyond the traditional domain of 
economics. 
Choice architecture and design economics promote a particular version of economics 
imperialism that goes beyond the mere export of its concepts to territories traditionally 
occupied by disciplines other than economics. They actually aim at inculcating economic 
calculus in human deliberation and introducing market-like forms of social interaction 
where they have been absent. In other words, what is at stake here is the deliberate attempt 
to make society more like its description in neoclassical economic theories, i.e. the 
performativity of economics (Mackenzie, 2006; Callon, 2007; Mackenzie et al., 2007). 
Whether or not they have succeeded in this endeavour is an empirical question that cannot 
be addressed here.16 For now, it is suffice to note that while taking into account predictable 
behavioural irrationalities and the opportunistic behaviour of economic agents in their 
policy proposals, both choice architecture and design economics retain and promote the 
expansion of the neoclassical concepts of rationality and efficiency in their market-based 
solutions. This is problematic, however. 
The recognition that context influences the choices people make and that the particular 
institutional configurations determine individual and aggregate outcomes jeopardises the 
ideal of freedom of choice, deemed as characterising the status quo, and the neoclassical 
goals of rationality and efficiency. The acknowledgment that the contexts of choice and 
social interaction require institutional change, moreover, opens the political Pandora’s box 
that neoclassical economics kept closed. Institutional change is fundamentally political. It 
requires the action of public authorities to carry it out and it impacts on the balance of 
economic and political power among different social groups. As Daniel Bromley (2008, 
p. 220) puts it, ‘public policy has but one purpose—to bring about changes in individual 
behaviour’ and it does so ‘by altering the institutional arrangements that define the choice 
sets—the fields of action—for individuals seeking their best advantage from inside of 
a specific institutional structure’. 
The dichotomy between the market, the locus of freedom of choice, and non-market 
domains is now harder to sustain. Choice architecture and design economics make it plain 
that both individual choices and their aggregate outcomes depend on extant institutional 
arrangements, stemming from prior political processes that defined the range of admissible 
action for different groups of people. As institutional economists have reminded us, it is 
only our familiarity with extant institutions that creates the illusion that current 
institutional set-ups are natural and fixed, and whence the perception that their change 
is the outcome of an artificial ‘intervention’. This is the more so, the more institutional 
16 This issue has, however, been addressed in (Santos and Rodrigues, 2009). 
Downloaded from cje.oxfordjournals.org by Robert Looney on July 2, 2011
722 A. C. Santos 
change alters the distribution of resources, power and opportunities. Those most affected 
by the new institutional setup tend to depict the new policy as an unnatural ‘intervention’ 
and will struggle hard to prevent it. But, as the FCC auctions illustrate, markets are the 
outcome of complex political processes requiring the involvement of an organised power 
capable of imposing a new set of rules defining who can participate and how. As Ha-Joon 
Chang put it: 
Emphasizing the institutional nature of the market [. . .] requires that we have to bring politics 
explicitly into the analysis of the market (and not just into the analysis of the state) and stop 
pretending that markets need to be, and can be, ‘de-politicised’. Markets are in the end political 
constructs in the sense that they are defined by a range of formal and informal institutions that 
embody certain rights and obligations, whose legitimacy (and therefore whose contestability) is 
ultimately determined in the realm of politics (Chang, 2002, p. 553) 
It is now clearer that choice architecture and design economics are not mere technical 
solutions. Their proposals may affect the distribution of economic and political power and, 
insofar as they do, they may see their legitimacy questioned on grounds that they violate 
freedom of choice or introduce distortions in the market. That is, they may be faced with 
the liberal rejection that they are unwarranted ‘interventions’ to solve problems that are 
best corrected by the ‘free’ functioning of the market.17 
The expectation of this kind of reaction may indeed explain the overly defensive tone of 
Thaler and Sunstein and their insistence on the principle of ‘freedom of choice’, defined 
negatively as the protection from interference by others. As we have seen, they have 
repeatedly stressed that choice architectures are to leave the menu of choices unaltered and 
grant individuals the exclusive power to use and dispose of things and services as they wish. 
They thereby accept the status quo ante as legitimate and avoid, as much as possible, 
altering it. By so doing they focus on people’s choices, leaving the analysis of the context 
and the circumstances of the individual in the background, as is typical of neoclassical 
economic theory (cf. Peter, 2004). This means that choice architecture is circumscribed to 
problems of choice that stem from people’s bounded rationality. It cannot deal with those 
problems that stem from the wider institutional setup where individuals act and interact. 
Design economics, in contrast, proposes major institutional change, which may 
substantially alter the relative position of different social groups. The proposal of the 
expansion of markets to new spheres of social life has, moreover, forced design economists 
to acknowledge that market relations can be coercive. The discussion around the creation 
of a market for the sale of kidneys made the coercive power of pecuniary incentives more 
salient for economists, acknowledging that the introduction of a monetary payment may 
force the most deprived groups of the population to engage in unwanted transactions due 
to extreme economic necessity (Roth, 2007). Design economists have therefore, if only 
implicitly, recognised that the government does not have the prerogative of the use of 
power to control people’s behaviour. Power can be exerted by various means and by 
various actors.18 Nonetheless, design economists still advocate market-based solutions to 
various kinds of social problem. Even when the legitimacy of these solutions is questioned, 
bringing about ‘reactions of repugnance’, Roth, as we have seen, pushes economists not to 
give up their traditional role of pointing to trade-offs and the costs and benefits of the 
alternatives at hand, proposing that the coercive power of pecuniary incentives be tackled 
17 See Sugden (2008) for a critique of choice architecture along these lines. 
18 See Grant (2006) for a comparative exercise on the various forms of power, including coercion, 
bargaining and persuasion. 
Downloaded from cje.oxfordjournals.org by Robert Looney on July 2, 2011
Behavioural and experimental economics 723 
by tuning in to their optimum level and by replacing part of monetary compensations with 
in-kind rewards (Roth, 2007, p. 50). 
An ample literature, however, exists in the area of political philosophy, which discusses 
the need to block the expansion of markets so as to prevent so-called desperate transactions 
(Walzer, 1983, 1984; Anderson, 1990, 1993). In this view, and unlike neoclassical 
economics, restricting market expansion may, in fact, enhance individual freedom. 
Keeping the various spheres of social life separated may be the most effective way to 
ensure a range of options large enough actually to allow people to act in conformity with 
their preferences and values. For, as Elizabeth Anderson (1990, p. 201) puts it, ‘the 
realization of some values demands that certain goods be produced, exchanged, and 
enjoyed outside market relations, in accordance with nonmarket norms’.19 
On this view, not only may the introduction of market relations in realms of social life 
traditionally protected from monetised exchanges create an unacceptable strain on 
individuals and impede the realisation and expression of values important to human life, 
but it may also have a detrimental impact on the values fostered. This is so because 
preferences are endogenous (Bowles, 1998). They are affected by the institutional 
arrangements that delineate the patterns of social interaction amongst the people who 
make up society. The social norms and relations of the market, by conveying particular 
ideals and nurturing specific values, may crowd out other fundamental values (Frey, 1997; 
Frey and Jegen, 2001). Anderson’s (1993), for example, depicts market social relations as 
impersonal and selfish, where individuals perceive their relations with others as a means to 
satisfy their own ends, feeling free to pursue their personal advantage without consider-ation 
for that of others. 
In markets people are less compelled to follow non-market norms and values. By 
aligning self-interest with the interests of others, market mechanisms moreover obviates 
the need for ethical reasoning; as a result, individuals no longer have the opportunity, as 
Steve Turnbull puts it, to ‘flex their ethical muscles’ (Frohlich and Oppenheimer, 2003, 
p. 290). Individuals’ ability to behave in accordance with non-market norms and values, 
then, will be seriously compromised. On the contrary, living with the tension between the 
best strategy from a rational, self-interested point of view and the ethically best strategy 
keeps the ethic imperative active.20 
From this it follows that choice architecture and design economics are to be subjected to 
ethical evaluation. Insofar as choice architecture and design economics alter the balance of 
economic opportunities among people in order to control or influence their actions toward 
the goals set by choice architects, by economic designers or by those who hire them, the 
legitimacy of their proposals must be subject to ethical evaluation, like any other political 
instrument or proposal. The market rhetoric of freedom of choice and economic efficiency 
does not obviate the need for such ethical assessment. Indeed, if one takes Ruth Grant’s 
(2006) criteria—legitimacy of purpose, voluntary response and the effect on the character 
of the parties involved—one clearly comprehends that expanding the range of choice does 
not ensure that the available options are equally legitimate, that individuals are capable of 
pursuing their most preferred actions, or that the outcomes of individual actions are 
19 See Rodrigues (2008) for a review on this literature. 
20 Frohlich and Oppenheimer (2003) describe a prisoner’s dilemma experiment where there is a conflict 
between the best individual strategy and the best social strategy. The removal of this conflict through the 
introduction of an incentive compatible device is effective in promoting the desirable behaviour. But when the 
device is removed, the level of cooperative behaviour reaches its minimum level, lower than the level observed 
in groups accustomed to the moral dilemma. 
Downloaded from cje.oxfordjournals.org by Robert Looney on July 2, 2011
724 A. C. Santos 
morally innocuous to the parties in the transaction. This ethical assessment gains particular 
relevance when considering, as the studies of behavioural economics have shown, that 
people are not always aware of the role of the context and of the institutional arrangements 
in determining their perceptions of it, and thus of their actions. This relevance is further 
magnified by the scientistic discourse that often accompanies the proposal of economists’ 
solutions, which are purged of political content so as to appear innocuous to the parties 
involved. As Grant (2006, p. 30) argues, in these instances it seems that ‘there is no need to 
convince people that collective goals are good or to motivate them to pursue those goals by 
appeals to rational argument, personal conviction or intrinsic motivations’. As a result, 
‘[e]xperts and powerful elites [may] direct institutions and shape people’s choices without 
the sort of public discussion and consent that characterizes democratic processes in 
general’. But the ethical superiority of market and market-like solutions cannot be taken for 
granted. It must be assessed and compared with other instruments of public policy. 
To conclude, as long as choice architecture and design economics aim at altering 
economic institutions and thereby the balance of power between individuals, they must be 
part of a wider process of public discussion and consent; otherwise they risk being 
instruments of manipulation. For they may deceive people into believing that they are 
acting autonomously when they are actually being used for somebody else’s purposes. The 
slogans ‘freedom to choose’ and ‘market efficiency’ are not substitutes of public discussion. 
The economic and ethical benefits of public policies must be demonstrated rather than 
assumed with the creation of new markets and market-like institutional arrangements. 
6. Concluding remarks 
Behavioural and experimental economics are part of the new mainstream of economics. 
This is testified by the publication of behavioural and experimental research in top 
economics journals and by the professional status their practitioners have acquired, inside 
and outside academia. Policy makers are asking choice architects and design economists 
for advice in the construction of various institutional setups that aim at steering human 
behaviour in the directions set by policy-makers. 
Both choice architecture and design economics depart from the neoclassical model of 
human action, the homo economicus. The effectiveness of their policy proposals depend on 
an accurate depiction of human beings, namely on their ability correctly to predict how 
people will behave in the proposed institutional settings. And they both recognise the 
relevance of the wider social and institutional context in people’s behaviour. This is in fact 
their starting point. Choice architecture and design economics aim to improve the 
institutional setting so as to help people make better choices for themselves and be more 
aligned with what is required for the attainment of desirable socio-economic goals. These 
proposals rely specifically on providing individuals with the required information and on 
suggesting various devices that can help them to make the right calculations, thereby 
preventing the detrimental effects of the bounded rationality of homo sapiens. 
There is a crucial distinction between the two proposals, however. Whereas choice 
architecture explicitly seeks to preserve the status quo ante, leaving the range of individual 
choices and the structure of economic incentives intact, design economics may be 
mobilised to produce major institutional change, altering the allocation of the set of 
economic and political opportunities among differently situated groups of individuals. But 
they are equally political constructs. They either protect or alter the balance of economic 
and political power between different groups of people. 
Downloaded from cje.oxfordjournals.org by Robert Looney on July 2, 2011
Yet both proposals are presented as technical solutions to various kinds of socioeco-nomic 
problems. While choice architecture deals with individual cognitive biases, helping 
people the better to satisfy their wants, design economics deals with incentive problems, 
trade-offs and other technical problems, to ensure the efficient allocation of goods, e.g. the 
distribution of goods to those who value and are willing and able to pay the most for them. 
They do not consider, much less address, how the new institutional arrangements will 
impact on the distribution of economic and political opportunities and how interested 
parties will react in turn. This omission may jeopardise the efficacy of proposed solutions 
on their own terms. Institutional change may bring about an intense struggle for influence 
over the collective definition of the new ‘rules of the game’ or may instill strong resistance 
due to its impact on important values unprotected by the narrow neoclassical normative 
principles of rationality and efficiency. Insofar as they have these impacts, the proposals of 
choice architecture and design economics ought to be subjected to public discussion. 
The implication of the foregoing analysis for the direction of economics is not 
unambiguous. On the one hand, it may seem that the new research programmes are 
adopting a rather conservative strategy, one that does not substantially change the nature of 
economics. Economics is still largely about rational choice in efficient markets, where 
human behaviour is still analysed in terms of the selection of the best alternative under 
given constraints and goods are allocated to those who subjectively value, and are willing 
and able to pay the most for them. On the other hand, the policy proposals make clear the 
relevance of the institutional setup to individual and collective wellbeing, which cannot be 
adequately dealt with within the neoclassical economics framework. Paraphrasing Chang 
(2002), by emphasising the institutional dimension of human action, choice architecture 
and design economics bring politics explicitly into economic analysis. And this may just be 
the contribution of the recent research programmes to the building of a new orthodoxy 
capable of replacing the old neoclassicism. 
The analysis carried out thus suggests that the potential of the behavioural and 
experimental approaches to transform economics lies in the consideration of the political 
dimension of institutional change, a lacuna in the neoclassical economics approach. This 
requires the explicit recognition that policy-making is not a mere technical exercise. The 
economic and moral desirability of alternative socioeconomic institutions has to be 
discussed and argued for. It also suggests that this research agenda can benefit from 
collaborative work with heterodox economists, namely the tradition of old institutionalism, 
who have addressed institutional change as part of a larger political process, and with 
political philosophers who have studied the morality of markets, which must be subjected 
to ethical scrutiny and democratic validation. Such a research programme would place the 
analysis of institutions in a wider framework, one that explicitly recognises institutional 
change as a political process, one that alters the distribution of economic and political 
opportunities among individuals and that impacts on the motivations and values nurtured 
in political communities. The possibility of reconciling these approaches would require of 
traditional heterodox economists a greater interest in core topics, and of behavioural and 
experimental economists a more receptive attitude toward the ethical appraisal of 
alternative socioeconomic institutions. 
Bibliography 
Anderson, E. 1990. The ethical limitations of the market, Economics and Philosophy, vol. 6, 
179–205 
Behavioural and experimental economics 725 
Downloaded from cje.oxfordjournals.org by Robert Looney on July 2, 2011
726 A. C. Santos 
Anderson, E. 1993. Value in Ethics and Economics, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press 
Binmore, K. 1999. Why experiment in economics? The Economic Journal, vol. 109, F16–24 
Bromley, D. 2006. Sufficient Reason: Volitional Pragmatism and the Meaning of Economic 
Institutions, Princeton, NJ, Princeton University Press 
Bromley, D. 2008. Beyond market failure: volitional pragmatism as a new theory of public policy, 
Economia Polı´tica, vol. 25, no. 2, 219–41 
Bowles, S. 1998. Endogenous preferences: the cultural consequences of markets and other 
economic institutions, Journal of Economic Literature, vol. 36, no. 2, 75–111 
Callon, M. 2007. What does it mean to say that economics is performative? pp. 311–57 in 
MacKenzie, D., Muniesa, F., and Siu, L. (eds), Do Economists Make Markets? On the 
Performativity of Economics, Princeton, NJ, Princeton University Press 
Camerer, C. F. 1995. Individual decision making, pp. 587–703 in Kagel, J. H. and Roth, A. E. 
(eds), The Handbook of Experimental Economics, Princeton, NJ, Princeton University Press 
Camerer, C. F. and Fehr, E. 2004. Measuring social norms and preferences using 
experimental games: a guide for social scientists, pp. 55–95 in Henrich, J., Boyd, R., 
Bowles, S., Camerer, C., Fehr, E., and Gintis, H. (eds), Foundations of Human Sociality: 
Economic Experiments and Ethnographic Evidence from Fifteen Small-Scale Societies, Oxford, 
Oxford University Press 
Camerer, C. F. and Hogarth, R. M. 1999. The effects of financial incentives in experiments: 
a review and capital–labor–production framework, Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, vol. 19, 7–42 
Camerer, C. F. and Loewenstein, G. 2004. Behavioral economics: past, present, future, pp. 3–51 
in Camerer, C. F., Loewenstein, G., and Rabin, M. (eds), Advances in Behavioral Economics, 
Princeton, NJ, Princeton University Press 
Camerer, C. F., Issacharof, S., Loewenstein, G., O’Donoghue, T. and Rabin, M. 2003. 
Regulation for conservatives: behavioral economics and the case for asymmetric paternalism, 
University of Pennsylvania Law Review, vol. 151, 1211–54 
Carvalho, L. F. and Rodrigues, J. 2008. Are markets everywhere? Understanding contemporary 
processes of commodification, pp. 267–86 in Davis, J. B. and Dolfsma, W. (eds), The Elgar 
Companion to Social Economics, Massachusetts, USA, Edward Elgar 
Chakrabortty, A. 2008. From Obama to Cameron, why do so many politicians want a piece of 
Richard Thaler? The Guardian, July 12, available at: http://www.guardian.co.uk/politics/2008/ 
jul/12/economy.conservatives [date last accessed June 20, 2011] 
Chang, H.-J. 2002. Breaking the mould: as institutionalist political economy alternative to 
the neo-liberal theory of the market and the state, Cambridge Journal of Economics, vol. 26, 
539–59 
Commons, J. R. 1931. Institutional economics, American Economic Review, vol. 21, 648–57 
Cramton, P. 1998. The efficiency of the FCC spectrum auctions, Journal of Law and Economics, 
vol. 41, 727–36 
Crotty, J. 2009. Structural causes of the global financial crisis: a critical assessment of the ‘New 
Financial Architecture’, Cambridge Journal of Economics, vol. 33, 563–80 
Davis, J. 2006. The turn in economics: neoclassical dominance to mainstream pluralism? Journal 
of Institutional Economics, vol. 2, no. 1, 1–20 
Davis, J. 2008. The turn in recent economics and return of orthodoxy, Cambridge Journal of 
Economics, vol. 32, 349–66 
Frey, B. S. 1997. Not Just For The Money – An Economic Theory of Personal Motivation, 
Cheltenham, UK and Lyme, USA, Edward Elgar 
Frey, B. S. and Benz, M. 2004. From imperialism to inspiration: a survey of economics and 
psychology, pp. 61–83 in Davis, J., Marciano, A., and Runde, J. (eds), The Elgar Companion to 
Economics and Philosophy, Aldershot, UK, Edward Elgar 
Frey, B. S. and Jegen, R. 2001. Motivation Crowding Theory: a survey of the empirical evidence, 
Journal of Economic Surveys, vol. 15, 589–611 
Frohlich, N. and Oppenheimer, J. 2003. Optimal policies and socially oriented behaviour: some 
problematic effects of an incentive compatible device, Public Choice, vol. 117, 273–93 
Grant, R. 2006. Ethics and incentives: a political approach, American Political Science Review, 
vol. 100, no. 1, 29–39 
Guala, F. 2001. Building economic machines: the FCC auctions, Studies in History and Philosophy 
of Science, vol. 32, 453–77 
Downloaded from cje.oxfordjournals.org by Robert Looney on July 2, 2011
Hodgson, G. M. 2008. Markets, pp. 251–66 in Davis, J. B. and Dolfsma, W. (eds), The Elgar 
Companion to Social Economics, Massachusetts, USA, Edward Elgar 
Kahneman, D. and Tversky, A. (eds) 2000. Choices, Values, and Frames, Cambridge, UK, 
Cambridge University Press 
Kagel, J. H. 1995. Auctions: a survey of experimental research, pp. 501–85 in Kagel, J. H. and 
Roth, A. E. (eds), The Handbook of Experimental Economics, Princeton, NJ, Princeton 
University Press 
Lewis, C. 2008. Why Barack Obama and David Cameron are keen to ‘nudge’ you, Times Online, 
July 14 [date last accessed June 2, 2010] 
Loewenstein, G., O’Donoghue, T. and Rabin, M. 2003. Projection bias in predicting future 
utility, The Quarterly Journal of Economics, vol. 118, no. 4, 1209–48 
Ma¨ki, U. 2009. Economics imperialism: concepts and constraints, Philosophy of the Social 
Sciences, vol. 39, no. 3, 351–80 
MacKenzie, D. 2006. Is economics performative? Option theory and the construction of 
derivative markets, Journal of the History of Economic Thought, vol. 28, no. 1, 29–55 
MacKenzie, D., Muniesa, F. and Siu, L. (eds) 2007. Do Economists Make Markets? On The 
Performativity of Economics, Princeton, NJ, Princeton University Press 
McAfee, R. P. and McMillan, J. 1996. Analysing the airwaves auction, Journal of Economic 
Perspectives, vol. 10, 159–75 
McMillan, J. 1994. Selling spectrum rights, Journal of Economic Perspectives, vol. 8, no. 3, 
145–62 
Milgrom, P. 2000. Putting auction theory to work: the simultaneous ascending auction, Journal 
of Political Economy, vol. 108, no. 2, 245–72 
Mirowski, P. 2007. Markets come to bits: Markomata and the future of computational 
evolutionary economics, Journal of Economic Behaviour and Organization, vol. 63, 209–42 
Nik-Khah, E. 2008. A tale of two auctions, Journal of Institutional Economics, vol. 4, no. 1, 73–97 
O’Donoghue, T. and Rabin, M. 1999. Doing It Now or Later, The American Economic Review, 
vol. 103, 118–20 
Peter, F. 2004. Choice, consent, and the legitimacy of market transactions, Economics and 
Philosophy, vol. 20, 1–18 
Plott, C. 1997. Laboratory experimental testbeds: application to the PCS auction, Journal of 
Economics and Management Strategy, vol. 6, 605–38 
Ritov, I. and Baron, J. 1992. Status-quo and omission bias, Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, vol. 5, 
49–61 
Rodrigues, J. 2008. Boundaries, values and the contested nature of market expansion, New 
Political Economy, vol. 13, 315–33 
Rose, G. F. and Lloyd, M. 2006. The Failure of FCC Spectrum Auctions,Washington, DC, Center 
for American Progress. http://www.americanprogress.org/kf/spectrum_auctions_may06.pdf 
Roth, A. E. 2002. The economist as engineer: game theory, experimentation, and computation 
as tools for design economics, Econometrica, vol. 70, 1341–78 
Roth, A. E. 2007. Repugnance as a constraint on markets, Journal of Economic Perspectives, 
vol. 21, no. 3, 37–58 
Samuels, W. J. 1989. Some fundamentals on the economic role of the government, Journal of 
Economic Issues, vol. 23, no. 2, 427–33 
Samuels,W. J. 1992.Welfare economics, power and property, pp. 56–138 in Samuels,W. J. (ed.), 
Essays on the Economic Role of the Government, Vol. I, New York, New York University Press 
Samuelson, W. and Zeckhauser, R. J. 1998. Status quo bias in decision making, Journal of Risk 
and Uncertainty, vol. 1, no. 1, 7–59 
Santos, A. C. 2007. The ‘Materials’ of Experimental Economics: technological versus behavioral 
experiments, Journal of Economic Methodology, 14, 311–337 
Santos, A. C. 2010. The Social Epistemology of Experimental Economics, London, Routldege 
Santos, A. C. and Rodrigues, J. 2009. Economics as Social Engineering? Questioning the 
Performativity Thesis, Cambridge Journal of Economics, 33, 985–1000 
Shiller, R. J. 2000. Irrational Exuberance, Princeton, NJ, Princeton University Press 
Shiller, R. J. 2008. The Subprime Solution, Princeton, NJ, Princeton University Press 
Smith, V. L. 2008. Rationality in Economics: Constructivist and Ecological Forms, Cambridge, 
Cambridge University Press 
Behavioural and experimental economics 727 
Downloaded from cje.oxfordjournals.org by Robert Looney on July 2, 2011
728 A. C. Santos 
Starmer, C. 2000. Developments in Non-Expected Utility Theory: The Hunt for a Descriptive 
Theory of Choice under Risk, Journal of Economic Literature, 38, 332–82 
Sugden, R. 2008. Why incoherent preferences do not justify paternalism, Constitutional Political 
Economy, 19, 226–248 
Thaler, R. 1992. The Winner’s Curse: Paradoxes and Anomalies of Economic Life, Princeton, NJ, 
Princeton University Press 
Thaler, R. H. and Sunstein, C. 2003. Libertarian paternalism, The American Economics Review, 
vol. 93, no. 2, 175–9 
Thaler, R. H. and Sunstein, C. R. 2008. Nudge: Improving Decisions About Health, Wealth, and 
Happiness, New Haven, CTand London, UK, Yale University Press 
Tversky, A. and Kahneman, D. 1974. Judgement and uncertainty: heuristics and biases, Science, 
vol. 185, 1124–31 
Tversky, A. and Kahneman, D. 1981. The framing of decision and the psychology of choice, 
Science, vol. 211, 453–8 
Walzer, M. 1983. Spheres of Justice, New York, NY, Basic Books 
Walzer, M. 1984. Liberalism and the art of separation, Political Theory, vol. 12, 315–30 
Wilby, P. 2008. Cameron’s free-market guru, New Statesman, July 24. http:// 
www.newstatesman.com/society/2008/07/thaler-friedman-cameron-social [date last accessed 
June 20, 2011] 
Downloaded from cje.oxfordjournals.org by Robert Looney on July 2, 2011

More Related Content

What's hot

Conceptualizing the Innovation Process Towards the ‘Active Innovation Paradig...
Conceptualizing the Innovation Process Towards the ‘Active Innovation Paradig...Conceptualizing the Innovation Process Towards the ‘Active Innovation Paradig...
Conceptualizing the Innovation Process Towards the ‘Active Innovation Paradig...
Maxim Kotsemir
 
Economics & The Complexity Vision
Economics & The Complexity VisionEconomics & The Complexity Vision
Economics & The Complexity Vision
Greg Pratt
 
The Scope And Method Of Economics
The Scope And Method Of EconomicsThe Scope And Method Of Economics
The Scope And Method Of Economics
s.coffey
 
Economics & The Complexity Vision 2
Economics & The Complexity Vision 2Economics & The Complexity Vision 2
Economics & The Complexity Vision 2
Greg Pratt
 

What's hot (14)

1 b module hmts
1 b module hmts1 b module hmts
1 b module hmts
 
Innovation system 101-lecture-2
Innovation system 101-lecture-2Innovation system 101-lecture-2
Innovation system 101-lecture-2
 
Developments in measuring the “creative” workforce
Developments in measuring the “creative” workforceDevelopments in measuring the “creative” workforce
Developments in measuring the “creative” workforce
 
Lecture 6 (Part-1) Innovation Systems 101
Lecture 6 (Part-1) Innovation Systems 101Lecture 6 (Part-1) Innovation Systems 101
Lecture 6 (Part-1) Innovation Systems 101
 
Conceptualizing the Innovation Process Towards the ‘Active Innovation Paradig...
Conceptualizing the Innovation Process Towards the ‘Active Innovation Paradig...Conceptualizing the Innovation Process Towards the ‘Active Innovation Paradig...
Conceptualizing the Innovation Process Towards the ‘Active Innovation Paradig...
 
Bounded rationality in organisation
Bounded rationality in organisationBounded rationality in organisation
Bounded rationality in organisation
 
Economics & The Complexity Vision
Economics & The Complexity VisionEconomics & The Complexity Vision
Economics & The Complexity Vision
 
99083
9908399083
99083
 
CASE Network Studies and Analyses 456 - The Impact of Socio-Ecological Transi...
CASE Network Studies and Analyses 456 - The Impact of Socio-Ecological Transi...CASE Network Studies and Analyses 456 - The Impact of Socio-Ecological Transi...
CASE Network Studies and Analyses 456 - The Impact of Socio-Ecological Transi...
 
Sociological institutionalism for a (mostly) economist audience
Sociological institutionalism for a (mostly) economist  audienceSociological institutionalism for a (mostly) economist  audience
Sociological institutionalism for a (mostly) economist audience
 
Principles of Neo-schumpeterian Economics
Principles of Neo-schumpeterian EconomicsPrinciples of Neo-schumpeterian Economics
Principles of Neo-schumpeterian Economics
 
Local exchanges for_sm_es
Local exchanges for_sm_esLocal exchanges for_sm_es
Local exchanges for_sm_es
 
The Scope And Method Of Economics
The Scope And Method Of EconomicsThe Scope And Method Of Economics
The Scope And Method Of Economics
 
Economics & The Complexity Vision 2
Economics & The Complexity Vision 2Economics & The Complexity Vision 2
Economics & The Complexity Vision 2
 

Viewers also liked

A Career In Communication Disorders
A Career In Communication DisordersA Career In Communication Disorders
A Career In Communication Disorders
215138
 
Computers in the Classroom
Computers in the ClassroomComputers in the Classroom
Computers in the Classroom
gueste29e7f7
 
Les règles d'or pour réussir sur Twitter - Erwan le Nagard
Les règles d'or pour réussir sur Twitter  - Erwan le NagardLes règles d'or pour réussir sur Twitter  - Erwan le Nagard
Les règles d'or pour réussir sur Twitter - Erwan le Nagard
LACT
 

Viewers also liked (20)

Cptl Wem Presentation 2009 Final V2
Cptl   Wem Presentation   2009   Final V2Cptl   Wem Presentation   2009   Final V2
Cptl Wem Presentation 2009 Final V2
 
A Career In Communication Disorders
A Career In Communication DisordersA Career In Communication Disorders
A Career In Communication Disorders
 
2004 cópia
2004   cópia2004   cópia
2004 cópia
 
Mark Edgar Thomas Robinson
Mark Edgar Thomas RobinsonMark Edgar Thomas Robinson
Mark Edgar Thomas Robinson
 
Week11
Week11Week11
Week11
 
Week7
Week7Week7
Week7
 
Liz\'s Print Portfoliio
Liz\'s Print PortfoliioLiz\'s Print Portfoliio
Liz\'s Print Portfoliio
 
Week11
Week11Week11
Week11
 
Better managing your loyalty program - Improving your member experience: the ...
Better managing your loyalty program - Improving your member experience: the ...Better managing your loyalty program - Improving your member experience: the ...
Better managing your loyalty program - Improving your member experience: the ...
 
Computers in the Classroom
Computers in the ClassroomComputers in the Classroom
Computers in the Classroom
 
Toronto Real Estate Market Watch Nov 09
Toronto Real Estate Market Watch Nov 09Toronto Real Estate Market Watch Nov 09
Toronto Real Estate Market Watch Nov 09
 
101002 computers
101002 computers101002 computers
101002 computers
 
Past 2015 x
Past 2015 xPast 2015 x
Past 2015 x
 
AllstateDCXUS16
AllstateDCXUS16AllstateDCXUS16
AllstateDCXUS16
 
Sde3
Sde3Sde3
Sde3
 
Big Data for Airlines: A Digital Journey from Social Media to your Bottom Line
Big Data for Airlines: A Digital Journey from Social Media to your Bottom LineBig Data for Airlines: A Digital Journey from Social Media to your Bottom Line
Big Data for Airlines: A Digital Journey from Social Media to your Bottom Line
 
Sde4
Sde4Sde4
Sde4
 
Conférence Availpro - Nouvelles tendances de distribution hôtelière
Conférence Availpro - Nouvelles tendances de distribution hôtelièreConférence Availpro - Nouvelles tendances de distribution hôtelière
Conférence Availpro - Nouvelles tendances de distribution hôtelière
 
FICJ e.magazine Décembre 2013
FICJ e.magazine Décembre 2013FICJ e.magazine Décembre 2013
FICJ e.magazine Décembre 2013
 
Les règles d'or pour réussir sur Twitter - Erwan le Nagard
Les règles d'or pour réussir sur Twitter  - Erwan le NagardLes règles d'or pour réussir sur Twitter  - Erwan le Nagard
Les règles d'or pour réussir sur Twitter - Erwan le Nagard
 

Similar to Economia del comportamiento transformando a la economía

How the Culture of Economics Stops Economists from Studying Group Behavior an...
How the Culture of Economics Stops Economists from Studying Group Behavior an...How the Culture of Economics Stops Economists from Studying Group Behavior an...
How the Culture of Economics Stops Economists from Studying Group Behavior an...
berat celik
 
The role of positive and normative economics in scholarly research
The  role  of positive  and  normative  economics  in scholarly  researchThe  role  of positive  and  normative  economics  in scholarly  research
The role of positive and normative economics in scholarly research
Dr. Vignes Gopal
 
Introduction Symposium on Robust Political Economy
Introduction Symposium on Robust Political EconomyIntroduction Symposium on Robust Political Economy
Introduction Symposium on Robust Political Economy
Nick Cowen
 
ARTICLE IN PRESS0890-8389$ - sedoi10.1016j.baC.docx
ARTICLE IN PRESS0890-8389$ - sedoi10.1016j.baC.docxARTICLE IN PRESS0890-8389$ - sedoi10.1016j.baC.docx
ARTICLE IN PRESS0890-8389$ - sedoi10.1016j.baC.docx
fredharris32
 
Designing from Place - A Regenerative Framework and Methodology - BR7463 v6
Designing from Place - A Regenerative Framework and Methodology - BR7463 v6Designing from Place - A Regenerative Framework and Methodology - BR7463 v6
Designing from Place - A Regenerative Framework and Methodology - BR7463 v6
Bill Reed
 

Similar to Economia del comportamiento transformando a la economía (20)

An Empirical And Theoretical Literature Review On Endogenous Growth In Latin ...
An Empirical And Theoretical Literature Review On Endogenous Growth In Latin ...An Empirical And Theoretical Literature Review On Endogenous Growth In Latin ...
An Empirical And Theoretical Literature Review On Endogenous Growth In Latin ...
 
Islamic finance - faith and charity
Islamic finance - faith and charityIslamic finance - faith and charity
Islamic finance - faith and charity
 
welfare economics.pdf
welfare economics.pdfwelfare economics.pdf
welfare economics.pdf
 
How the Culture of Economics Stops Economists from Studying Group Behavior an...
How the Culture of Economics Stops Economists from Studying Group Behavior an...How the Culture of Economics Stops Economists from Studying Group Behavior an...
How the Culture of Economics Stops Economists from Studying Group Behavior an...
 
Definition Nature Scope and Significance of Economics, Business Economics - D...
Definition Nature Scope and Significance of Economics, Business Economics - D...Definition Nature Scope and Significance of Economics, Business Economics - D...
Definition Nature Scope and Significance of Economics, Business Economics - D...
 
How the Culture of Economics Stops Economists from Studying Group Behavior an...
How the Culture of Economics Stops Economists from Studying Group Behavior an...How the Culture of Economics Stops Economists from Studying Group Behavior an...
How the Culture of Economics Stops Economists from Studying Group Behavior an...
 
A Guide For Harvard S Sophomore Economics Concentrators
A Guide For Harvard S Sophomore Economics ConcentratorsA Guide For Harvard S Sophomore Economics Concentrators
A Guide For Harvard S Sophomore Economics Concentrators
 
Articulo microeconomic
Articulo microeconomicArticulo microeconomic
Articulo microeconomic
 
The eco leader
 The eco leader The eco leader
The eco leader
 
Economics needs a scientific revolution Nature Oct 2008
Economics needs a scientific revolution   Nature Oct 2008Economics needs a scientific revolution   Nature Oct 2008
Economics needs a scientific revolution Nature Oct 2008
 
The role of positive and normative economics in scholarly research
The  role  of positive  and  normative  economics  in scholarly  researchThe  role  of positive  and  normative  economics  in scholarly  research
The role of positive and normative economics in scholarly research
 
Why Does Converge Need Systems Thinking And Critical
Why Does Converge Need Systems Thinking And CriticalWhy Does Converge Need Systems Thinking And Critical
Why Does Converge Need Systems Thinking And Critical
 
1 практика 21 год (1).pptx
1 практика 21 год   (1).pptx1 практика 21 год   (1).pptx
1 практика 21 год (1).pptx
 
Introduction Symposium on Robust Political Economy
Introduction Symposium on Robust Political EconomyIntroduction Symposium on Robust Political Economy
Introduction Symposium on Robust Political Economy
 
All That Glitters Is Not Gold. The Political Economy Of Randomized Evaluation...
All That Glitters Is Not Gold. The Political Economy Of Randomized Evaluation...All That Glitters Is Not Gold. The Political Economy Of Randomized Evaluation...
All That Glitters Is Not Gold. The Political Economy Of Randomized Evaluation...
 
ARTICLE IN PRESS0890-8389$ - sedoi10.1016j.baC.docx
ARTICLE IN PRESS0890-8389$ - sedoi10.1016j.baC.docxARTICLE IN PRESS0890-8389$ - sedoi10.1016j.baC.docx
ARTICLE IN PRESS0890-8389$ - sedoi10.1016j.baC.docx
 
Introduction to Institutional Economics.pptx
Introduction to Institutional  Economics.pptxIntroduction to Institutional  Economics.pptx
Introduction to Institutional Economics.pptx
 
02. predicting financial distress logit mode jones
02. predicting financial distress logit mode jones02. predicting financial distress logit mode jones
02. predicting financial distress logit mode jones
 
Development of ecological economics (constanza, 1997)
Development of ecological economics (constanza, 1997)Development of ecological economics (constanza, 1997)
Development of ecological economics (constanza, 1997)
 
Designing from Place - A Regenerative Framework and Methodology - BR7463 v6
Designing from Place - A Regenerative Framework and Methodology - BR7463 v6Designing from Place - A Regenerative Framework and Methodology - BR7463 v6
Designing from Place - A Regenerative Framework and Methodology - BR7463 v6
 

Recently uploaded

[[Nerul]] MNavi Mumbai Honoreble Call Girls Number-9833754194-Panvel Best Es...
[[Nerul]] MNavi Mumbai Honoreble  Call Girls Number-9833754194-Panvel Best Es...[[Nerul]] MNavi Mumbai Honoreble  Call Girls Number-9833754194-Panvel Best Es...
[[Nerul]] MNavi Mumbai Honoreble Call Girls Number-9833754194-Panvel Best Es...
priyasharma62062
 
Garia ^ (Call Girls) in Kolkata - Book 8005736733 Call Girls Available 24 Hou...
Garia ^ (Call Girls) in Kolkata - Book 8005736733 Call Girls Available 24 Hou...Garia ^ (Call Girls) in Kolkata - Book 8005736733 Call Girls Available 24 Hou...
Garia ^ (Call Girls) in Kolkata - Book 8005736733 Call Girls Available 24 Hou...
HyderabadDolls
 

Recently uploaded (20)

Call Girls In Kolkata-📞7033799463-Independent Escorts Services In Dam Dam Air...
Call Girls In Kolkata-📞7033799463-Independent Escorts Services In Dam Dam Air...Call Girls In Kolkata-📞7033799463-Independent Escorts Services In Dam Dam Air...
Call Girls In Kolkata-📞7033799463-Independent Escorts Services In Dam Dam Air...
 
Collecting banker, Capacity of collecting Banker, conditions under section 13...
Collecting banker, Capacity of collecting Banker, conditions under section 13...Collecting banker, Capacity of collecting Banker, conditions under section 13...
Collecting banker, Capacity of collecting Banker, conditions under section 13...
 
W.D. Gann Theory Complete Information.pdf
W.D. Gann Theory Complete Information.pdfW.D. Gann Theory Complete Information.pdf
W.D. Gann Theory Complete Information.pdf
 
[[Nerul]] MNavi Mumbai Honoreble Call Girls Number-9833754194-Panvel Best Es...
[[Nerul]] MNavi Mumbai Honoreble  Call Girls Number-9833754194-Panvel Best Es...[[Nerul]] MNavi Mumbai Honoreble  Call Girls Number-9833754194-Panvel Best Es...
[[Nerul]] MNavi Mumbai Honoreble Call Girls Number-9833754194-Panvel Best Es...
 
Garia ^ (Call Girls) in Kolkata - Book 8005736733 Call Girls Available 24 Hou...
Garia ^ (Call Girls) in Kolkata - Book 8005736733 Call Girls Available 24 Hou...Garia ^ (Call Girls) in Kolkata - Book 8005736733 Call Girls Available 24 Hou...
Garia ^ (Call Girls) in Kolkata - Book 8005736733 Call Girls Available 24 Hou...
 
Indore City REd Light Area Call Girls-✔✔9155612368 Escorts In Indore Female E...
Indore City REd Light Area Call Girls-✔✔9155612368 Escorts In Indore Female E...Indore City REd Light Area Call Girls-✔✔9155612368 Escorts In Indore Female E...
Indore City REd Light Area Call Girls-✔✔9155612368 Escorts In Indore Female E...
 
Dubai Call Girls Deira O525547819 Dubai Call Girls Bur Dubai Multiple
Dubai Call Girls Deira O525547819 Dubai Call Girls Bur Dubai MultipleDubai Call Girls Deira O525547819 Dubai Call Girls Bur Dubai Multiple
Dubai Call Girls Deira O525547819 Dubai Call Girls Bur Dubai Multiple
 
20240419-SMC-submission-Annual-Superannuation-Performance-Test-–-design-optio...
20240419-SMC-submission-Annual-Superannuation-Performance-Test-–-design-optio...20240419-SMC-submission-Annual-Superannuation-Performance-Test-–-design-optio...
20240419-SMC-submission-Annual-Superannuation-Performance-Test-–-design-optio...
 
✂️ 👅 Independent Bhubaneswar Escorts Odisha Call Girls With Room Bhubaneswar ...
✂️ 👅 Independent Bhubaneswar Escorts Odisha Call Girls With Room Bhubaneswar ...✂️ 👅 Independent Bhubaneswar Escorts Odisha Call Girls With Room Bhubaneswar ...
✂️ 👅 Independent Bhubaneswar Escorts Odisha Call Girls With Room Bhubaneswar ...
 
Strategic Resources May 2024 Corporate Presentation
Strategic Resources May 2024 Corporate PresentationStrategic Resources May 2024 Corporate Presentation
Strategic Resources May 2024 Corporate Presentation
 
cost-volume-profit analysis.ppt(managerial accounting).pptx
cost-volume-profit analysis.ppt(managerial accounting).pptxcost-volume-profit analysis.ppt(managerial accounting).pptx
cost-volume-profit analysis.ppt(managerial accounting).pptx
 
✂️ 👅 Independent Bhubaneswar Escorts Odisha Call Girls With Room Bhubaneswar ...
✂️ 👅 Independent Bhubaneswar Escorts Odisha Call Girls With Room Bhubaneswar ...✂️ 👅 Independent Bhubaneswar Escorts Odisha Call Girls With Room Bhubaneswar ...
✂️ 👅 Independent Bhubaneswar Escorts Odisha Call Girls With Room Bhubaneswar ...
 
Escorts Indore Call Girls-9155612368-Vijay Nagar Decent Fantastic Call Girls ...
Escorts Indore Call Girls-9155612368-Vijay Nagar Decent Fantastic Call Girls ...Escorts Indore Call Girls-9155612368-Vijay Nagar Decent Fantastic Call Girls ...
Escorts Indore Call Girls-9155612368-Vijay Nagar Decent Fantastic Call Girls ...
 
Famous No1 Amil Baba Love marriage Astrologer Specialist Expert In Pakistan a...
Famous No1 Amil Baba Love marriage Astrologer Specialist Expert In Pakistan a...Famous No1 Amil Baba Love marriage Astrologer Specialist Expert In Pakistan a...
Famous No1 Amil Baba Love marriage Astrologer Specialist Expert In Pakistan a...
 
Russian Call Girls New Bhubaneswar Whatsapp Numbers 9777949614 Russian Escor...
Russian Call Girls New Bhubaneswar Whatsapp Numbers 9777949614  Russian Escor...Russian Call Girls New Bhubaneswar Whatsapp Numbers 9777949614  Russian Escor...
Russian Call Girls New Bhubaneswar Whatsapp Numbers 9777949614 Russian Escor...
 
Effortless Income Tax Filing Online Your Path to Financial Ease..pdf
Effortless Income Tax Filing Online Your Path to Financial Ease..pdfEffortless Income Tax Filing Online Your Path to Financial Ease..pdf
Effortless Income Tax Filing Online Your Path to Financial Ease..pdf
 
Female Russian Escorts Mumbai Call Girls-((ANdheri))9833754194-Jogeshawri Fre...
Female Russian Escorts Mumbai Call Girls-((ANdheri))9833754194-Jogeshawri Fre...Female Russian Escorts Mumbai Call Girls-((ANdheri))9833754194-Jogeshawri Fre...
Female Russian Escorts Mumbai Call Girls-((ANdheri))9833754194-Jogeshawri Fre...
 
Turbhe Fantastic Escorts📞📞9833754194 Kopar Khairane Marathi Call Girls-Kopar ...
Turbhe Fantastic Escorts📞📞9833754194 Kopar Khairane Marathi Call Girls-Kopar ...Turbhe Fantastic Escorts📞📞9833754194 Kopar Khairane Marathi Call Girls-Kopar ...
Turbhe Fantastic Escorts📞📞9833754194 Kopar Khairane Marathi Call Girls-Kopar ...
 
Bhubaneswar🌹Ravi Tailkes ❤CALL GIRLS 9777949614 💟 CALL GIRLS IN bhubaneswar ...
Bhubaneswar🌹Ravi Tailkes  ❤CALL GIRLS 9777949614 💟 CALL GIRLS IN bhubaneswar ...Bhubaneswar🌹Ravi Tailkes  ❤CALL GIRLS 9777949614 💟 CALL GIRLS IN bhubaneswar ...
Bhubaneswar🌹Ravi Tailkes ❤CALL GIRLS 9777949614 💟 CALL GIRLS IN bhubaneswar ...
 
Webinar on E-Invoicing for Fintech Belgium
Webinar on E-Invoicing for Fintech BelgiumWebinar on E-Invoicing for Fintech Belgium
Webinar on E-Invoicing for Fintech Belgium
 

Economia del comportamiento transformando a la economía

  • 1. Cambridge Journal of Economics 2011, 35, 705–728 doi:10.1093/cje/beq049 Advance Access publication 5 January 2011 Behavioural and experimental economics: are they really transforming economics? Ana C. Santos* Behavioural and experimental economics are part of an increasingly pluralistic mainstream economics, sharing with other recently established research pro-grammes the revision of fundamental assumptions of the previously dominant neoclassical economics research programme. The recent proliferation and consol-idation of these new approaches creates the possibility for the emergence of a new orthodoxy of economics, i.e. a new general research programme capable of replacing neoclassicism. The goal of this paper is to investigate the potential contribution of behavioural and experimental economics to help build a general research pro-gramme capable of supplanting neoclassical economics and thereby transforming economics. To this end, it focuses on two influential applied fields of behavioural and experimental economics—choice architecture and design economics. Key words: Anomalies, Choice architecture, Design economics, Market design, Recent economics JEL classifications: A12, B52, C90 1. Introduction Behavioural and experimental economics are part of recent mainstream economics, sharing with other emergent research programmes the rejection of fundamental assump-tions and commitments of the previously dominant neoclassical economics research programme. The recent proliferation and consolidation of the new approaches, with overlapping areas of research and concerns, is now raising the possibility for the emergence of a new orthodoxy of economics, i.e. a new general research programme capable of replacing neoclassicism (Davis, 2006, 2008). The goal of this paper is to investigate the potential contribution of behavioural and experimental economics to transform econom-ics. I focus, in particular, on their capacity to carry out two major transformations that are deemed as characterising the ongoing process of change in the discipline: (i) the revision of the neoclassical economics model of human action, homo economicus; and (ii) the new economic approach to market building. In order to do this, I look at two recent applications Manuscript received 11 October 2009; final version received 17 November 2010. Address for correspondence: CES, Center for Social Studies, University of Coimbra, Cole´gio de S. Jero´nimo, Apartado 3087, 3001-401 Coimbra, Portugal; email: anacsantos@ces.uc.pt * University of Coimbra, Portugal. I acknowledge financial support from Fundacxa˜o Calouste Gulbenkian (n 21-107001-S). I would also like to thank the comments of Joa˜o Rodrigues and Jose´ Castro Caldas and those of three anonymous referees. Usual disclaimers naturally apply. The Author 2011. Published by Oxford University Press on behalf of the Cambridge Political Economy Society. All rights reserved. Downloaded from cje.oxfordjournals.org by Robert Looney on July 2, 2011
  • 2. 706 A. C. Santos of these research programmes—choice architecture and design economics—which, as we shall see, focus on each one of these features in turn. The new research programmes, also comprising, among others, game theory, evolu-tionary economics and neuroeconomics, have a common denominator. They all are relatively recent developments whose emergence relied on conceptual contents imported from other disciplines, such as psychology, biology and neuroscience (Davis, 2006, 2008). Their trajectories thus stand in stark contrast to that of neoclassical economics, which is consolidated around a fairly well-delimited analytical toolkit that has been widely applied to other fields of research. The model of human action, homo economicus, and the model of the competitive market have been particularly instrumental to the expansion of the neoclassical approach outside the conventional realm of economics. They have been pivotal in the so-called ‘economics imperialism’ movement, contributing to universalising and naturalising a particular version of the market and the egotistic and rational attributes of human beings (Carvalho and Rodrigues, 2008). That the new fields of research have relied on content imported from disciplines with radically different principles, presuppositions and conceptual frameworks, making up a rather heterogeneous and pluralistic mainstream economics, naturally fuels the expectation of change in economics. John Davis (2008), for example, considers that the recent approaches carry a great transformative potential, superior to that of the traditional heterodox approaches. Notwithstanding the fact that both recent and traditional heterodox approaches depart from key assumptions of neoclassical economics and have close ties with sciences outside economics, only the new research programmes are moving inwards toward the core of economics in a deliberate attempt to redirect it. This is taken to be the case of current behavioural economics. Having its origins in psychology and its primary focus on the critique of homo economicus, behavioural economics is now attempting to incorporate new behavioural assumptions into new models of human action (cf. Camerer and Loewenstein, 2004). Traditional heterodox approaches, in contrast, remain oriented toward the periphery of economics, rejecting core neoclassical principles rather than attempting to reform them, and insisting on an alternative foundation for economics, one more based on closer ties to other social sciences. The greater transformative potential of the new approaches is further supported by the higher professional status that the practitioners of the new approaches seem to be enjoying, as testified by the award, in 2002, of the Bank of Sweden Prize in Economic Sciences in Memory of Alfred Nobel to Daniel Kahneman, ‘for having integrated insights from psychological research into economic science, especially concerning human judgment and decision-making under uncertainty’ and to Vernon Smith ‘for having established laboratory experiments as a tool in empirical economic analysis, especially in the study of alternative market mechanisms’.1 Choice architecture and design economics are policy applications that provide a privileged vantage point from which to assess the potential of the new approaches to transform economics. This is so because, as we shall see, policy proposals render particularly salient economists’ conceptions of economics and of the social world. Choice architecture and design economics unequivocally depart from the research strategies of neoclassical economics. Rather than assuming at the outset that human beings are homo economicus, i.e. that they are always capable of maximising their individual utility, choice architecture takes as a starting point how people actually deal with particular forms of decision-problems. The purpose of choice architecture is to prepare contexts of choice 1 http://nobelprize.org/nobel_prizes/economics/laureates/2002/ Downloaded from cje.oxfordjournals.org by Robert Looney on July 2, 2011
  • 3. Behavioural and experimental economics 707 to help individuals make better choices, as judged by individuals themselves, or by society as a whole (Thaler and Sunstein, 2003, 2008). Design economics is in turn devoted to the conception of specific allocation mechanisms that aim at coordinating individual actions for the accomplishment of the goals set by the designer (Roth, 2002). Rather than assuming that markets emerge spontaneously and automatically generate efficient allocations of resources, design economics puts at the forefront the complex social engineering processes involved in the building of markets and market-like allocation mechanisms that determine individual outcomes and the aggregate results that are obtained by having people interacting under those mechanisms. Yet it is not clear that the reform of the core principles of economics is under way. Both choice architecture and design economics seem to retain two fundamental principles of neoclassical economics—rationality and efficiency. Having observed that economic agents are not always rational and that their actions in market and non-market contexts do not always produce desirable outcomes, economists seem now to be dedicated to the fabrication of the conditions of rationality and efficiency. And there is a clear division of labour. While architect-economists are devoted to the creation of contexts of choice that make rational choices viable, designer-economists are devoted to the construction of market mechanisms that ensure socially efficient outcomes. Thus, while importing new models of individual decision-making and new experimental technologies, choice architecture and design economics still seem to retain the neoclassical view of rational choice, defined in terms of the choice that confers the individual the highest net benefit given constraints, and of the market understood as a mere allocation mechanism. This might in fact explain the success of choice architects and design economists as policy advisors. Notwithstanding the ongoing process of change in economics, economic discourse and general perceptions about economics may lag far behind. Policy proposals that appeal to the standard normative notions of rationality and efficiency might thus still be well-received by policy-makers and the general public. However that may be, the fact of the matter is that Richard Thaler, Cass Sunstein and Alvin Roth are all accomplished and much sought after scholars to give advice and help reconfigure a variety of socioeconomic institutions.2 If on the one hand, the rejection of key assumptions of neoclassical economics may entail a transformative potential, the preservation of the neoclassical criteria of rationality and efficiency, on the other hand, may suggest that neoclassical economics principles are still very much present in the new approaches. The goal of this paper is to investigate this tension so as to evaluate the prospects of change in economics and the emergence of a new general research programme capable of replacing neoclassicism. Section 2 starts off by briefly reviewing the recent transformations taking place in economics. Section 3 presents and analyses choice architecture while Section 4 is given over to the presentation and examination of design economics. Section 5 then discusses the tensions that arise from the revision of the key assumptions of the neoclassical research programme that preserves its normative criteria of rationality and efficiency. Based on the analysis of choice architecture 2 Thaler and Sunstein are from Chicago University and were famously advertised as campaign advisors to the then Presidential candidate, Barack Obama. Sunstein is the current Administrator of the White House Office of Information and Regulatory Affairs. Thaler was advisor to the leader of the British Conservative party, David Cameron, and continues to advise the institutional investment firm Fuller Thaler Asset Management, Inc., which he founded (see Chakrabortty, 2008; Lewis, 2008; Wilby, 2008). Roth is from Harvard University and he too has been a consultant for various American public entities, such as The National Resident Matching Program and The New York City Department of Education. Downloaded from cje.oxfordjournals.org by Robert Looney on July 2, 2011
  • 4. 708 A. C. Santos and design economics, Section 6 draws the main conclusions of the paper regarding the potential of behavioural and experimental economics to transform economics. 2. Neoclassical dominance and the new mainstream pluralism This paper appraises the departures of choice architecture and design economics from neoclassical economics so as to assess the potential of behavioural and experimental economics to transform economics. At this juncture, two caveats are in order. First, controversy abounds regarding the implications of behavioural and experimental econom-ics, within and between the practitioners of the two research programmes. The experimental economist Vernon Smith (2008, pp. 155–6), for instance, seems to consider behavioural economics to be outside the scope of economics, dealing with ‘the performance consistency (choice rationality) of individual decision making’, which ‘is not where the action is in understanding economic performance and human achievement’. Economics is instead about how ‘wealth is created by task specialization across individuals, groups, populations, regions and climates’, where ‘specialization is determined by the depth and breadth of the market’. Smith thus seems to exclude from experimental economics individual decision-making experiments. Experimental economics concerns instead ‘market performance (market rationality), incentives in public good provision and small group interactions, and other environments with dispersed individual valuations’. Camerer and Lowenstein (2004, p. 3) consider instead that experimental economics is defined by the laboratory method, as applied to both individual choice and market behaviour. Behavioural economics is particularly devoted to improving ‘the realism of the psychological underpinnings of economic analysis’, which is deemed to advance the field of economics by ‘generating theoretical insights, making better predictions of field phenom-ena, and suggesting better policy’. For the purpose of the analysis to be carried out, I will focus on behavioural economics’ revisions to homo economicus, and on the contribution of experimental market economics to the reconsideration of the neoclassical conception of the market. Examination of the transformative potential of behavioural economics will be based on the analysis of choice architecture and that of experimental market economics on the analysis of design economics. This means, and this is the second caveat, that the analysis to be carried out will be necessarily partial. Nonetheless, choice architecture and design economics are taken to be particularly informative of the ongoing process of change in the discipline, namely concerning: (i) the revision of the neoclassical economics model of human action, homo economicus (e.g. Frey and Benz, 2004); and (ii) the recent economic approach to market building (e.g. Mirowski, 2007). Homo economicus is the neoclassical economics model of human action. Homo economicus is rational and typically selfish. He chooses so as to maximise his utility and succeeds in doing so. No cognitive limitation of any kind gets in his way when calculating the costs and benefits of the alternatives at hand. Nor does he have self-control problems that impede the selection and the pursuit of the alternative that benefits him the most. Because he is generally guided by his narrow self-interest, choice depends on his individual subjective preferences and the constraints he faces, in particular his income and the relative prices (explicit or implicit) of the different choice alternatives. The natural habitat of homo economicus is the market. The market, through its price mechanism, is deemed to provide the relevant information and the required incentives for multiplying the range of choice and thereby for maximising individual utility and social welfare, which is no more than the sum of individual utilities. Downloaded from cje.oxfordjournals.org by Robert Looney on July 2, 2011
  • 5. Behavioural and experimental economics 709 According to the neoclassical approach, governments should abstain from ‘intervening’ in the market; otherwise they will distort prices and thereby undermine rational decision-making and social well-being. Government action should be restricted to so-called market failures, for in these cases prices no longer reflect the costs and benefits of alternative options. But even in these cases governments should avoid as much as possible restricting individual choice through laws and regulation. They should instead try to mould individual behaviour via the use of pecuniary incentives, attempting to align individual and group interests by changing the costs and benefits of the various courses of actions. Pecuniary incentives are deemed to be effective in a rational world where individuals react to changes in their possibility space in a systematic and predictable way, refraining from pursuing costly and undesirable actions, which do not need to be outlawed, and engaging in more beneficial activities. Even though the ‘market’ is the central institution of neoclassical economics, it has not been constituted as an object of study on its own right. There has been little interest in studying how specific markets operate and how prices are actually obtained. Instead, it has been taken as a relatively homogenous and undifferentiated entity, to which are associated vague notions of supply and demand that jointly determine the equilibrium price of commodities (Hodgson, 2008). The abstract model of human action and the vague conception of the market are two key elements in economics imperialism, which has consisted of the extension of the economic approach to a variety of non-economic fields of research in politics, law, history, the arts and the family (Frey and Benz, 2004).3 This process has also been extended to public discourse and to the conducting of public policy, resulting in an increased commodifica-tion of social life. Neoclassical economics has in this way been part of a process of universalisation of market-based social relations (Carvalho and Rodrigues, 2008). Recent research challenges the homo economicus model and places a greater emphasis on the role of institutions, specifically of market institutions, in guiding and shaping human behaviour, as well as in determining aggregate outcomes. As Philip Mirowski (2007, p. 211) summarises, we are moving ‘from a period when ‘‘the market’’ has been left implicit and undefined to an era in which markets are becoming the center of attention’. Economics has hence ‘become less fixated upon agency and more concerned to theorize the meaning and significance of a diversity of (small-m) markets’. Recent change in economics has thus consisted of the inversion of interest in the status and nature of agents in favour of the specifications of markets. These transformations are by and large the result of both behavioural and experimental economics. The gradual establishment of these fields of research, most notably since the 1990s, has contributed to draw the profession’s attention to the study of the behavioural deviations from the predictions of the rational model of human action, and to the role of socioeconomic institutions in determining individual behaviour and aggregate outcomes. Choice architecture and design economics derive the policy implications of the recently acquired understanding of human behaviour and of the role of the overall institutional setting. They rely on distinct resources, however. Choice architecture builds upon the ‘behavioural’ experiments of economics, as well as from evidence obtained from other methods and from other disciplines (especially from cognitive psychology), which have produced knowledge of individuals’ attributes (e.g. preferences, attitudes toward risk, and so on) and of the processes by which people select and apply heuristics or abide by social 3 See Ma¨ki (2009) for a discussion on the notion of economics imperialism. Downloaded from cje.oxfordjournals.org by Robert Looney on July 2, 2011
  • 6. 710 A. C. Santos norms when facing particular individual and collective decision-making problems. Design economics builds instead upon the ‘technological’ experiments of economics that are particularly tailored to study market institutions, namely their incentive compatibility attributes, i.e. their capacity to induce self-interested individuals to take the actions that achieve desirable results at the aggregate level (cf. Santos 2007; 2010, cap. 10). Behavioural experiments have produced a substantial amount of evidence that shows that human beings are prone to systematic error even in areas of economic relevance where stakes are high (e.g. Thaler, 1992; Camerer, 1995). Rather than grounding individual choice on the calculus of the costs and benefits of alternative options so as to choose the alternative that provides the highest net benefit, individuals have recourse to a variety of decisional rules and are influenced by various contextual factors that jeopardise the pursuit of individuals’ best interests. The increased understanding of how people actually select and apply rules for dealing with particular forms of decision problems and of the influence of contexts on individual choices is the starting point of choice architecture devoted to the study of choice setups that can curb human idiosyncrasies to good result, as judged by individuals themselves, or by society as a whole (Thaler and Sunstein, 2003, 2008). Technological experiments have produced a substantial amount of evidence of the relative performance of various market mechanisms (e.g. Kagel, 1995). More recently, they have been used as engineering tools for building new markets from scratch. That is, they have been used for building ‘economic machines’, which ‘are supposed to work for several years, in different contexts and without constant supervision of their manufacturer’ (Guala, 2001, p. 464) or as ‘testbeds’ of ‘a working prototype of a process that is going to be employed in a complex environment’ (Plott, 1997, p. 605). These experiments have forced economists to explicitly recognise that markets are the outcome of complex social engineering processes that determine the rules under which individuals are to act and the aggregate results that obtain by having economic agents interacting under these rules (Roth, 2002). In the next two sections, I look in more detail into the policy proposals of choice architecture and design economics so as to investigate the extent to which they depart from neoclassical economics and thereby assess the potential of the recent approaches to transforming economics. 3. The assumptions of neoclassical economic theory, behavioural anomalies and choice architecture The neoclassical economics model of human action, homo economicus, relies on two basic assumptions—unbounded rationality and self-interest— which underlie the utility max-imising analysis of human behaviour. Experimental work first carried out by cognitive psychologists, and subsequently by economists, identified so-called ‘anomalies’, i.e. patterns of judgment and choice that are inconsistent with utility maximisation, challenging both assumptions.4 Behavioural economists have, then, attempted to replace the standard assumptions of economics with more realistic descriptions of human behaviour that could account for people’s bounded rationality and other-regarding considerations. However, the revised conception of human action was not accompanied by an equivalent change in economic theorising. While accommodating ‘anomalous’ 4 Richard Thaler had an important role in introducing these results to economists in the column ‘anomalies’ of the prestigious Journal of Economic Perspectives, between 1987 and 1990. His The Winner’s Curse: Paradoxes and Anomalies of Economic Life, published in 1992, brings together some of these experimental results. See also Camerer (1995). Downloaded from cje.oxfordjournals.org by Robert Looney on July 2, 2011
  • 7. behaviours, an important part of theoretical work has maintained formal rigour and kept the traditional fields of application and the disciplinary boundaries intact (cf. Camerer and Lowenstein, 2004). This strategy allowed economists to retain the utility maximising principle, considering, for example, that individuals simply have a richer set of preferences than was traditionally considered, such as the so-called social preferences (cf. Camerer and Fehr, 2004).5 But empirical research unequivocally challenges the standard rationality assumption. People do make systematic mistakes, failing to choose what is best for them. Rather than basing their decisions on the calculus of the net benefits of various choice alternatives, people have recourse to simple rules of thumb, or heuristics, which help them cope with various problems in a quick and satisfactory way, thus allowing saving precious time with time-consuming deliberation (Tversky and Kahneman, 1974). However, sometimes these heuristics lead to inferior choices, i.e. choices that would be corrected if people had complete information, unlimited cognitive abilities and unbreakable willpower, and took time to make their calculations. This body of evidence leads Thaler and Sunstein (2008, pp. 6–7) to conclude that rather than homo economicus, people are homo sapiens, that is, humans. The psychologists Amos Tversky and Daniel Kahneman (1974) long ago identified three pervasive heuristics—anchoring and adjustment, availability and representativeness—and the biases they generate. The ‘anchoring and adjustment’ heuristic, to give one example, leads to excessive influence of a particular feature of the problem (which works as an ‘anchor’) because individuals often fail adequately to take into account other relevant elements of the decision problem. The psychologists have also noted that the framing of the decision-problem, i.e. the way the problem is described and presented, has a strong impact on the choices individuals make (Tversky and Kahneman, 1981; Kahneman and Tversky, 2000). This goes against the assumption that individual preferences and the inherent costs and benefits of the alternatives at hand are the sole determinants of human behaviour. Not only do people ignore features that economic theory takes as relevant, they are also influenced by factors that economists do not consider. The status quo bias is a particularly frequent behavioural pattern (Samuelson and Zeckhauser, 1988) and of particular interest to choice architecture, as we shall see below. It consists of the tendency to stick to one’s current situation, even when the risk of altering the situation is low compared to maintaining the situation. This behaviour may be explained by people’s aversion to losses, i.e. the tendency to place a greater negative value on losses (e.g. letting go of the present situation) than on gains (e.g. the benefits of change). Status quo bias may also be caused by what is known as the ‘omission/commission bias’—people’s tendency to care more about errors of their own actions (commission) than about errors that occur as a result of their inaction (omission) (Ritov and Baron, 1992). Another possible cause of the status quo bias is procrastination, i.e. the tendency to delay beneficial actions that involve immediate costs, such as dieting (O’Donoghue and Rabin, 1999). Individuals’ excessive optimism and overconfidence in their own abilities may further exacerbate this tendency. The opposite behavioural pattern is also frequent and important. People are as well prone to hasty decisions due to self-control problems, which may lead them to fall into temptation, doing things that they later regret. This often occurs when the benefits of the goods or actions are immediate and costs are delayed. This effect is even stronger if 5 See also Starmer (2000) for a review of theoretical developments prompted by experimental research on individual decision-making under risk. Behavioural and experimental economics 711 Downloaded from cje.oxfordjournals.org by Robert Looney on July 2, 2011
  • 8. 712 A. C. Santos individuals are in emotionally or biologically ‘hot’ states, which may provoke an overestimation of the short-term benefits of falling prey to the temptation (Loewenstein et al., 2003). Notwithstanding the accumulated evidence, many (non-behavioural) economists re-main sceptical. They argue that people do a better job of choosing in the ‘real world’, especially in markets where they face problems that really matter to them and the stakes are high (e.g. Binmore, 1999). But the anomalous phenomena have been replicated with higher stakes, both in the lab (Camerer and Hogarth, 1999) and in the ‘real’ world, as in financial markets (Shiller, 2000). The consideration that individuals are boundedly rational and weakly willpowered is now inspiring various versions of so-called ‘soft paternalistic’ approaches to individual decision-making—asymmetric paternalism, cautious paternalism, libertarian paternalism (cf. Camerer et al., 2003)—devoted to helping people make choices more in line with maximising behaviour, while avoiding as much as possible placing limits on individual choice and thus causing harm to those who behave rationally. Choice architecture, proposed by Richard Thaler and Cass Sunstein, is a case in point.6 The starting point of choice architecture is the human propensity to err. Choice architecture departs from the assumption that ‘almost all people, almost all of the time, make choices that are in their best interest or at the very least are better than the choices that would be made by someone else’ (Thaler and Sunstein, 2008, p. 9). As the empirical studies mentioned above show, not so infrequently people make choices they would not have made if they had relevant information, unlimited cognitive abilities to process it and complete self-control. They are particularly vulnerable when they face complex and infrequent decisions that offer poor feedback. Not only will they have difficulty in translating aspects of the situation into terms they can easily understand, but they may also be exploited by those who can profit from their vulnerability to make predictable mistakes. Based on an informed view of actual human behaviour, the choice architect has, then, ‘the responsibility for organizing the context in which people make decisions’ (Thaler and Sunstein, 2008, p. 3). The goal is ‘to steer people’s choices in directions that will improve their lives’, that is, ‘‘that will make choosers better off, as judged by themselves’ (p. 5) A critical aspect of choice architecture is that it emphatically avoids constraining the options of the individual. Its aim is instead to alter ‘people’s behaviour in a predictable way without forbidding any options or significantly changing their economic incentives’ (p. 6).7 As Thaler and Sunstein put it, ‘[f]reedom to choose is the best safeguard against bad choice architecture’ (p. 11). Choice architecture is devoted to the design of what the authors call ‘nudges’ that attempt to induce the choices that best serve individual (or collective) interests by taking into account how people make decisions in particular contexts. Two key instruments of choice architecture are default options and disclosure devices. Default options deal with individuals’ status quo biases by carefully designing a solution that is automatically selected if the individual fails to choose for him/herself. Thaler and Sunstein point out that default options should only be proposed if it is unambiguous that they serve individuals’ best interests. Automatic enrolment in the American 401(k) employee saving plans, to give an example, is thought to benefit employees, since the costs of saving too little for retirement are admittedly much greater and severe than the costs of saving too much. In any case, 6 Except when stated otherwise, this section refers to Thaler and Sunstein (2008). 7 The authors are here referring to pecuniary incentives. Downloaded from cje.oxfordjournals.org by Robert Looney on July 2, 2011
  • 9. Behavioural and experimental economics 713 those who do not wish to be part of the plan may always opt out. The authors consider that the low rates of opt outs observed in the past suggest that most employees do benefit from this measure, enrolling earlier than they would otherwise do, if they did so at all. These measures would not be necessary in a fully rational world in which individuals always choose the best option regardless of the default. But individuals’ inertia and tendency to procrastinate more likely lead to no action. Default options have been shown to be particularly effective, especially so if they also entail an explicit endorsement from the default setter that it is the recommended course of action (Thaler and Sunstein, 2008, p. 83). The choice architect may also select the relevant information for decision-making and design information disseminating devices that facilitate comparison of the alternative options. This solution is proposed for decisions involving complex pricing schemes, such as mortgages, cell phone calling plans and insurance policies. According to Thaler and Sunstein, in these cases the government should regulate disclosure practices, requiring that customers be informed of fees, in a legible format, and be given regular reports of the fees that have been charged. These reports would provide consumers with feedback so that they could shift their demand to the services that most adequately fit their consumption patterns. Besides the design of defaults or information disclosure devices, choice architects may have recourse to other tools to attenuate people’s propensity to err, say the framing of the context of choice, which may be tamed to better capture the analytical structure of the decision-problem; moreover, they may take advantage of people’s attributes, for instance, people’s susceptibility to social influence, by making salient the prudent and beneficial actions of others. Consumption, saving and investment decisions constitute obvious areas for the application of choice architecture. The high rates of household indebtedness in developed economies (but not only) are to some extent explained by individuals’ failure to make wise consumption/investment decisions, due to non-transparent and difficult-to-process in-formation and to self-control problems, given that the temptation of immediate gratification is too salient as compared with the costs of hasty/risky decisions that are only suffered at a later time. Matters are at present even more complicated by the highly sophisticated and complex financial markets that have rendered credit and investment decisions increasingly more difficult. Less educated individuals are in a particularly disadvantaged position because they are more vulnerable to aggressive campaigns and marketing strategies deployed by those who profit from consumers’ hasty decisions. This is explicitly recognised by Thaler and Sunstein, when referring to mortgage markets: When markets get more complicated, unsophisticated and uneducated shoppers will be especially disadvantaged by the complexity. The unsophisticated shoppers are also more likely to be given bad or self-interested advice by people serving in roles that appear to be helpful and purely advisory. In this market, mortgage brokers who cater to rich clients probably have a greater incentive to establish a reputation for fair dealing. By contrast, mortgage brokers who cater to the poor are often more interested in making a quick buck. (Thaler and Sunstein, 2008, p. 134) In this particular situation, Thaler and Sunstein’s proposal is to demand that mortgage lenders provide the relevant information in a readable format so that all the fees and interest rate provisions can be more easily compared. They argue that this will not only make it easier to shop, but it will also allow independent third parties to offer much better advice, thus making the mortgage market more competitive (Thaler and Sunstein, 2008, p. 138). Downloaded from cje.oxfordjournals.org by Robert Looney on July 2, 2011
  • 10. 714 A. C. Santos Choice architecture thus mobilises the recently acquired understanding of how individuals process information and make decisions, to design contexts of choice that help people make better choices. The choice architect may focus on the design of default options that protect individuals from inertia or conceive information devices to help improve people’s ability to select options that make them better off. At the same time the designer should avoid, as much as possible, changing the incentive structure of the problem-situation. The authors stress ‘[t]he central goal would be to inform costumers of fees rather than set prices’ (Thaler and Sunstein, 2008, p. 83). It is by now clear that the neoclassical models of rational choice and of the competitive market loom in the background of choice architecture. The problem, as Thaler and Sunstein see it, is that individuals fail to conform to the rational choice model due to incomplete information, cognitive limitations and weak willpower. Prevalent incentives in opaquemarkets may even exacerbate this problem because it can be highly profitable to exploit people’s bounded rationality. The choice architect should then help people with decision-making so that they more closely align their demand with the actual benefits derived from consumption. In this way, choice architecture also contributes to bettering the functioning of competitive markets by reducing the detrimental effects of asymmetric information between buyers and sellers. The more consumersmake the right choices, the more markets become competitive. Thaler and Sunstein thus work within the larger framework of the neoclassical research programme trying to deal with the problems of asymmetric information and decision-makers’ bounded rationality. Even though they acknowledge that in many circumstances choice architectures are unavoidably designed by someone else for others to make their choices, they do not address this key issue to choice architecture. They merely identify complex and difficult decision-making as obvious areas for the intervention of the benevolent choice architect. Thus, they do not consider the possibility that some of people’s ‘errors’ might in fact be the result, intended or unintended, of current choice architectures. This means that choice architecture only addresses those problems caused by incomplete information, bounded rationality and weak willpower, leaving out those that stem from faulty choice architectures. This is patent when Thaler and Sunstein discuss mortgage markets, disregarding the participation of the wider financial system in growing household rates of overindebtedness, limiting their focus on the complexity of these kinds of decision, the main problem to be fixed by choice architecture. The work of Robert J. Shiller (2000, 2008) on financial markets illustrates the interplay between choice architectures and human behaviour showing that understanding individual decision-making requires understanding the institutional structure inside of which people act. Shiller interprets the so-called subprime crisis not so much in terms of the complexity of the decision-making process, but instead in terms of an ‘epidemic of irrational enthusiasm for housing investments’ caused by the perverse incentives of the financial sector. On Shiller’s view, the unsustainable levels of mortgage borrowing in the USA were ultimately caused by dramatic institutional changes in financial markets over the last three decades, through deregulation and, more recently, financial innovation, culminating in what is known as the New Financial Architecture. The new institutional setting, together with rising housing prices and low interest rates, rendered mortgage lending a highly lucrative investment fed by a new securitisation industry.8 When house prices collapsed 8 The feedback mechanisms are well-known: mortgage brokers sold loans, investment bankers packaged the loans into securities, banks and specialist institutions serviced the securities, rating agencies gave their seal of approval, and insurance companies protected holders of such securities against loss through the use of credit default swaps. Downloaded from cje.oxfordjournals.org by Robert Looney on July 2, 2011
  • 11. Behavioural and experimental economics 715 and interest rates rose, and borrowers started to default on their payments, the mortgage market collapsed, impacting on other parts of the globe, since mortgage-based financial products had been dispersed around the world. The end result was the greatest financial crisis since 1929. According to Shiller, the ‘subprime solution’ must result in a profound restructuring of the housing and financial economy of the magnitude of the New Deal. This therefore suggests, at least as regards individual decision-making in financial markets, that a more significant amount of institutional engineering than solving people’s status quo biases or hasty decision making is required. Otherwise, governments will have to be called upon to rescue financial actors with ever more massive bailouts to guarantee the sector’s sustainability (Crotty, 2009). The minimalist solutions of choice architecture contain an implicit acceptance of the prevalent institutional arrangements. This is clear in Thaler and Sunstein’s rhetoric, where choice architecture is to be subjected to the preservation of ‘freedom of choice’ and of the free functioning of the market, which is deemed as characterising the present situation. The solutions proposed, however mild, may nonetheless have effects on the status quo ante. If the new choice architecture is to be effective, in the sense that it succeeds in steering individual behaviour in desirable directions, it necessarily interferes with the interests in place, reallocating economic opportunities among differently situated individuals. Those most adversely affected by the new institutional setup will probably resist, depicting the new policy as an unnatural ‘intervention’ into some natural state. However, policy is not some alien ‘intervention’ into a naturally evolved reality. The status quo ante is itself the result of past political processes—a point that has been made by various generations of institutional economists, especially in the tradition of John Commons (1931). It is only our ‘institutionalised mind’ that sees current practices, choices and actions as normal, right and correct, and changes to that situation as artificial ‘interventions’ (Bromley, 2006). And people, as behavioural economists would now add, have a tendency to resist change. To conclude with the wording of Warren J. Samuels (1989, p. 432) ‘[w]hat is normally considered ‘‘intervention’’ is not the intrusion of government in an area in which government hitherto has been absent but the change of the interests to which government gives its support or which government is used to support’. The objection that institutional change is coercive and inhibitive of individual ‘freedom’ is therefore incoherent, as is the complaint that public policy creates ‘distortions’ in an otherwise frictionless economy (Bromley, 2006). What institutional change does is alter the previous allocation of economic opportunities among differently situated individuals, advancing the economic and social agendas of some and impeding those of others. From this it follows that the concept of efficiency cannot refer to some natural state of world. Efficiency is always measured by reference to some institutional setup that indicates which instances of costs and benefits are to be considered and recorded (Samuels, 1992). If the context changes, what will count as rational and efficient will change too. This is illustrated in the next section, where institutional change is more explicitly addressed in design economics. 4. Design economics and the expansion of markets Design economics affords the economist a more active role in the (re)design of contexts of choice. Design economics is in fact presented as the engineering field of economics. In Roth’s (2002, p. 1341) account, it is ‘the part of economics intended to further the design and maintenance of markets and other economic institutions’. And like any other engineering field, design economics is taken to deal with the ‘natural’ complications that Downloaded from cje.oxfordjournals.org by Robert Looney on July 2, 2011
  • 12. 716 A. C. Santos arise when applying theory to practicalmatters, for which end it mobilises the resources from three emergent research programmes of economics: game theory, computational and experimental economics. Game theory provides the general framework for addressing design, in particular, for the definition of the ‘rules of the game’. The tools of computational and experimental economics are instead used to ‘bridge the gap’ between theory and the institutional details of particular markets. Computational methods, in particular, ‘will help us analyze games that may be too complex to solve analytically’, while laboratory experiments ‘will help inform us about how people will behave when confronted with these environments, both when they are inexperienced and as they gain experience’ (Roth, 2002, pp. 1373–4). Design economics emerged in the 1990s when game theorists began to be hired as consultants for the design of various allocation mechanisms that were soon to be implemented in real world environments. The design and implementation of these new mechanisms raised technical complications for which no theory or past experience could suggest any solution, and new devices had to be designed from scratch. Two famous exemplars of these allocations mechanisms are the design of labour clearinghouses for the US National Resident Matching Program (NRMP) that would assign hospital positions to young doctors, and the design of an auction mechanism for the US Federal Communi-cations Commission (FCC) that would allocate licenses to use the electromagnetic spectrum for various telecommunications services. The NRMP clearinghouse called for the design of a matching algorithm that would allocate applicants to residence programs based on preferences lists of both doctors and hospitals, avoiding favouring one side of the market over the other, while producing a stable matching (i.e. a matching on which both parties could agree). To this end, the performances of alternative algorithms were assessed and compared in terms of the impact on each side of the market, speed, stability and so forth. The FCC auction was intended to allocate airwave spectrum rights in a transparent and efficient way. But while economists were hired to design new allocation mechanisms the responsibility for selecting or deciding whether to adopt the proposed design was retained by the public authority that hired them, in consultation with its various constituencies. The FCC auction provides a very useful illustration of design economics, which is worth looking at more closely.9 The FCC auctions have been greeted as the biggest engineering success of economics. In 1994, the FCC implemented what was to be known as the simultaneous–multiple-round–independent auction, which would soon be praised as ‘the greatest auction in history’ (McAfee and McMillan, 1996, p. 159). This auction launched a market for thousands of spectrum licenses, and its success in raising billions of dollars for the public treasury has been taken as evidence of the successful accomplishment of the goals set by the regulator. According to the official version, as recounted by the game theorists involved in their design, the auctions aimed at creating a transparent and efficient market that would allocate the airwave spectrum rights to highest value users—those who most valued and made best use of them.10 Until 1982, spectrum licenses were assigned by an administrative 9 See Guala (2001) for a more detailed account of the engineering work involved in the construction of the FCC auctions. 10 This account is based on game theorists’ reports of events, after efficiency had been set as the main goal of the auction to the detriment of welfare goals defined by Congress, such as the expansion of public access to new technologies, products and services, and the decentralisation of the licenses awarded to include small businesses, rural telephone companies and minority groups. For a more complete account of the political process involving the FCC auctions see Nik-Khah (2008). Downloaded from cje.oxfordjournals.org by Robert Looney on July 2, 2011
  • 13. Behavioural and experimental economics 717 hearing process (recognisably slow and non-transparent), which allocated licenses for free. After 1982, licenses were sold and allocated via a lottery system, which significantly improved the speed and transparency of the allocation mechanism, but it did not prevent opportunistic behaviour. Licenses could be bought and resold by individuals who did not want to use them and thus undeservedly appropriated revenue raised by the commercial use of the public spectrum. The auction mechanism seemed to offer a tremendous advantage over the alternatives. It offered the possibility of identifying the firms with the highest use-values for the spectrum, which would be in a position to pay the highest prices for using it and, as a result, maximise the FCC’s revenue. This in turn required the design of an auction mechanism that encouraged bidders to reveal their true valuations, while preventing opportunistic behaviour on their part. The building of the FCC auctions was a complex endeavor, best depicted as a patchwork of various and partial solutions to the particular issues that arise when building new markets. Auction design resembled ‘a kind of engineering activity’ that had recourse to all sorts of resources ranging from ‘practical judgments, guided by theory and all available evidence’ to ‘ad hoc methods to resolve issues about which theory is silent’ (Milgrom, 2000, p. 271). Game theory merely assisted in ‘developing intuition’, in particular in ‘show[ing] how people behave in various circumstances and [. . .] identify[ing] the tradeoffs involved in altering those circumstances’ (McAfee and McMillan, 1996, p. 171). The auction had to tackle three major technical issues. First, to ensure that the highest-value users bought and paid for the licenses at their value; second, to allow the composition of favoured combinations of licenses, which had to take into account licenses’ comple-mentarities and substitutability; and, third, to prevent opportunistic behaviour on the part of bidders, which would jeopardise the competitive gains obtained from instituting the market. Theory would help look at the strategic structure of the decision-making problem and anticipate ‘how bidders choose their bids, not knowing the value of the item for sale and not knowing what their rivals know; and what the seller can do to stimulate the bidding competition, not knowing how much any of the bidders is willing to pay’ (McMillan, 1994, p. 146). Based on advice from the game theorists, the FCC opted for the simultaneous–multiple-round– independent auction, which gave bidders the possibility of operating in several markets at the same time and thus of composing desirable aggregations of items or adjusting their aggregation to a last-resort composition if their first-choice aggregations became unattainable. The licenses would then be allocated to the highest bidder that paid his/her bid price. Many detailed rules were then defined to organise the running of the auction, namely how bidders were to engage in the transactions while attempting to prevent the opportunistic exploiting of any gap.11 The next step consisted of gluing together these partial solutions and evaluating whether they could be implemented in an operational environment. Laboratory experiments were crucial in order to put the various pieces together into a workable mechanism and solve the 11 For example, an activity rule required the payment of deposits on the total number of desired licenses at the beginning of the auction to ensure that market participants had actually intended to own and use the licenses. Given the high stakes at play, the government was also concerned with simplifying procedures in order to reduce the incidence of mistakes. To avoid the ‘winner’s curse’, i.e. selling of licenses to traders who overestimated their value, or to avoid the extra-cautionary behaviour of risk-averse bidders, the bids were announced at every round so that traders could make better estimates of the licenses’ values. The incidence of unpredictable mistakes was further taken into account by allowing bid withdrawal, though with a penalty. The auction rules in the end amounted to a 130 page document. Downloaded from cje.oxfordjournals.org by Robert Looney on July 2, 2011
  • 14. 718 A. C. Santos complications that emerged while trying to do so (Guala, 2001; Nik-Khah, 2008). The building of the FCC auctions thus followed a division of labour in which game theorists proposed the auction form and the rules that would organise the functioning of the market; and experimental economists implemented these rules in an electronic market. After stabilising the auction rules, the experimenters subsequently tested the auction under conditions that closely resembled the market to be implemented and thereby assessed the combined effect of the auction’s rules, which could not possibly be predicted by non-experimental means. Even though the accounts of the game theorists make us believe otherwise, the success story of the FCC auctions is not uncontroversial. In an evaluation of the results, Peter Cramton (1998, p. 735), a successful design economist, states that ‘any auction would look good relative to the FCC’s past experience with comparative hearings and lotteries’. At the same time, he concedes that ‘[s]ince I do not observe the bidders’ actual valuations, it is impossible to say exactly how efficient the auctions were’ and retreats to the more vague claim that the auctions were successful for the government, as judged by the revenues raised, and for bidders, as judged by the stability of license compositions (pp. 728–9). Edward Nik-Khah, based on the archives of the FCC, tells a different story, concluding: ‘[o]verall, the allocation of licenses produced by the auctions proved to be unstable, as the industry has gone through a spate of mergers, acquisitions, and bankruptcies, ultimately leading to a high degree of license concentration’ (Nik-Khah, 2008, p. 90). Based on the analysis of 10 years of FCC auctions, comprising the data of 58 auctions, Gregory F. Rose and Mark Lloyd (2006) conclude that the auctions failed to maximise receipts and promote efficiency in the sector because bidders managed to carry out manipulative strategies (e.g. tacit collusion and pre-emptive bidding), which resulted in the auctioning of licenses at significantly lower prices. Yet game theorists were eager to wrap their contribution in the allure of science, emphasising that ‘the auction design process was driven not by politics, but by economics’ (McMillan, 1994, p. 147). But the process of building the auction was marked by the interests of the constituencies in place, namely those of the large telecommunications corporations. Large corporations hired game theorists to help them to position themselves in the policy-making process, first by lobbying for the most favourable architectures for the auctions and then by assisting in defining their clients’ bidding strategies (Nik-Khah, 2008).12 As Charles Plott (1997, p. 606), one prominent consultant, candidly acknowl-edged: ‘Business understood that the rules and form of the auction could influence who acquired what and how much was paid’. Thus, the building of the FCC auction was not a mere engineering exercise. It was a complex political process, where big companies actively exercised their influence before and during its operation. Because the FCC failed to prevent collusion and other anti-trust strategies, taking place both inside and outside the market, the market became more concentrated in the hands of a few large corporations. The FCC auctions thus make it plain that markets, and non-market allocation mechanisms for that matter, are complex institutional arrangements that require the engineering efforts of various social scientists and social actors, and that market outcomes depend on the particular configurations of these arrangements. Rather than assuming at the outset that markets ensure efficiency, via the symbiotic conjunction of agents’ 12 To give just a few prominent names, Paul Milgrom, Robert Wilson and Charles Plott were hired by Pacific Bell, Preston McAfee by Airtouch Communications, Peter Cramton by CI, John Ledyard and David Porter by the National Telecommunications and Information Administration and, finally, JohnMcMillan by the FCC. Downloaded from cje.oxfordjournals.org by Robert Looney on July 2, 2011
  • 15. Behavioural and experimental economics 719 rationality and the information disseminated through prices, design economists are devoted to the study of ‘the rules of the game’. In Roth’s wording: The largest lesson in all this is that design is important because markets don’t always grow like weeds—some of them are hothouse orchids. Time and place have to be established, related goods need to be assembled, or related markets linked so that complementarities can be handled, incentive problems have to be overcome, etc. (Roth, 2002, pp. 1373–4) It is also clear that design economics is to be devoted to the ‘technical issues’ that arise in market building. That allocation mechanisms are the outcome of difficult and complex political processes is not adequately taken into account, especially the impact of these processes on the ‘technical’ goals set beforehand. Design economists, qua specialised technicians, deal with the technical complications that arise in social engineering, specifically with those that stem from the strategic environment and the opportunistic behaviour of economic agents, who will try to outwit the regulator, and from the cognitive limitations of real economic agents that may compromise the goals set by the regulator. This means that design economists also take into account the actual characteristics of economic agents. The effectiveness of market mechanisms requires that the design setter be able to predict how economic agents will behave under the new institutional setup. But in contrast to choice architecture, design economists focus on the structure of incentives. The new arrange-ments must be incentive compatible devices. They should align individual and collective interests in such a way that individuals’ incentives correspond to what is needed to achieve group optima, while making sure that economic agents understand the incentive structure so that they behave predictably, like homo economicus. In the FCC auctions this meant that the auction mechanism had to succeed in eliciting the subjective values of spectrum licenses to ensure telecom companies acquired the desired licenses, while contributing to an efficient allocation of the licenses, thus defined, and the maximisation of FCC revenue. In sum, design economics is devoted to the (re)design of complex markets and other economic institutions to be implemented in context-specific environments, to which end the opportunistic behaviour of economic agents and their propensity to err must be taken into account. The ultimate goal is to conceive a structure of incentives such that individual actions can generate desirable social states. Insofar as it overlooks the political process involved in the (re)building of new economic institutions, design economics risks failing on their own terms, that is, it fails to pursue its narrowly defined goals of efficiency. The higher the stakes, the more the (re)creation of a new market gives rise to an intense struggle for influence over the collective definition of ‘the new rules of the game’. The outcome will contain a high degree of uncertainty and it will depend on the correlation of power of those involved and their capability to bring forward their favoured solutions. This means that market building frames and shapes the interactions of individuals for the attainment of rather elusive goals, say the allocation of resources in an operational way, while attempting to curb opportunistic behaviour on their part. To put it in another way, the efficacy of design economics ultimately hinges on determining the extent to which economists are able to implement their models in the real world and make reality conform to their theoretical constructs, that is, on determining the performativity of economics (to be further discussed in Section 5).13 13 This view is also shared by Vernon Smith (2008, ch. 6). While generally favourable to market design, he thinks that the ‘ecological fitness’ of ‘rational constructivist designs’ is only achieved, if at all, after a long process of trial-and-error that corrects behavioural incentives and strategic problems not considered in design. Smith clearly does not think that the FCC auctions have already stabilised and achieved their ecological fitness. Downloaded from cje.oxfordjournals.org by Robert Looney on July 2, 2011
  • 16. 720 A. C. Santos This exclusive concentration on ‘technical’ issues is even more salient when design economists propose the extension of market relations to non-market domains of social life. The introduction of market-like arrangements that set up contractual forms of exchange involving the transfer of money and property rights has encountered severe resistance, since this new form of exchange becomes ‘repugnant’, as Roth puts it, when money is added to the transaction. This ‘distaste for certain kinds of transactions can be a real constraint on markets and how they are designed, every bit as real as the constraints imposed by technology or by the requirements of incentives and efficiency’ (Roth, 2007, p. 38). The challenge, from the point of view of the design economist, is to learn how to deal with these constraints, which are perceived as part of a technical problem that needs to be tackled. Roth then urges economists to understand better and engage more with the phenomena of repugnant transactions. This is so because ‘attitudes about the repugnance (or other kinds of inappropriateness) of transactions shape whole markets, and therefore shape what choices people face’ (Roth, 2007, p. 38). When referring to the debate over the creation of a market for the sale of kidneys, Roth (2007, pp. 53–4) makes this clearer by contrasting the irrational reactions of its opponents to the frustration of economists ‘at the failure to adopt what they see as a feasible solution that could be implemented quickly’. In Roth’s view, design economists, qua rational technicians, should take on ‘the important educational role of pointing to inefficiencies and tradeoffs, and costs and benefits’ (Roth, 2007, p. 53). They should nonetheless be aware that the sources of repugnance (such as other-regarding motivations) mayaffect the efficacy of incentive schemes due to the crowding out of altruistic motivations (cf. Frey, 1997; Frey and Jegen, 2001).14 In order to be effective, new markets have to deal with all sorts of complications that arise in market building. To sum up, design economics is devoted to the (re)design of complex market institutions that deal with varied technical complications in context-specific environments. The ultimate goal is to (re)align the structure of incentives so that individual actions can bring about desirable social states. Design economics is not circumscribed to the market domain. The expansion of markets or market-like forms of exchange to other domains of social life, however, requires that the economist qua social engineer take on the pedagogic role of pointing to inefficiencies and tradeoffs, as well as costs and benefits, in discussions informed by taboo or visceral reactions.15 This brings into the analysis the impact of other-regarding considerations on the efficacy of public policy. The underlying political processes of market design and the struggle for political influence are left out, however. 5. Choice architectures and market designs are political constructs Choice architecture and design economics convey two major transformations deemed as characterising the ongoing process of change in the discipline: (i) the revision of the neoclassical model of human action, homo economicus; and (ii) the recent economics approach to market building. But while fully acknowledging that individuals are not always rational and that markets are complex socially engineered institutions, these recent developments retain the view of economics as the science of choice, which ought to conform to the rational choice model, and select the market as the most adequate institution to coordinate individual actions in various realms of social life. With minor or 14 To be further explained below. 15 Roth’s account provides an unflattering caricature of critical reactions to the expansion of market forms of social interaction. See the Journal of Economic Perspectives, vol. 21, no. 3, for the debate around the creation of a market for the sale of human kidneys, where both positions are more reasonably presented and discussed. Downloaded from cje.oxfordjournals.org by Robert Looney on July 2, 2011
  • 17. Behavioural and experimental economics 721 major tinkering with the institutional setup, economists are committed to helping people make rational choices and to coordinate their actions efficiently for the attainment of socially desirable ends. Institutional change targets incentive structures, information disclosure devices and other calculation tools to assist individuals when determining the costs and benefits of alternative options. They will then make choices more aligned with the maximisation of individual utility and with what is required to achieve socially desirable outcomes. Not only do these proposals retain the fundamental principles of neoclassical economics—rationality and efficiency—they also continue to promote their expansion to various domains of social life. Through the architecture of contexts of choice and the design of market mechanisms, economists are putting their expertise at the service of individual rationality and economic efficiency, within and beyond the traditional domain of economics. Choice architecture and design economics promote a particular version of economics imperialism that goes beyond the mere export of its concepts to territories traditionally occupied by disciplines other than economics. They actually aim at inculcating economic calculus in human deliberation and introducing market-like forms of social interaction where they have been absent. In other words, what is at stake here is the deliberate attempt to make society more like its description in neoclassical economic theories, i.e. the performativity of economics (Mackenzie, 2006; Callon, 2007; Mackenzie et al., 2007). Whether or not they have succeeded in this endeavour is an empirical question that cannot be addressed here.16 For now, it is suffice to note that while taking into account predictable behavioural irrationalities and the opportunistic behaviour of economic agents in their policy proposals, both choice architecture and design economics retain and promote the expansion of the neoclassical concepts of rationality and efficiency in their market-based solutions. This is problematic, however. The recognition that context influences the choices people make and that the particular institutional configurations determine individual and aggregate outcomes jeopardises the ideal of freedom of choice, deemed as characterising the status quo, and the neoclassical goals of rationality and efficiency. The acknowledgment that the contexts of choice and social interaction require institutional change, moreover, opens the political Pandora’s box that neoclassical economics kept closed. Institutional change is fundamentally political. It requires the action of public authorities to carry it out and it impacts on the balance of economic and political power among different social groups. As Daniel Bromley (2008, p. 220) puts it, ‘public policy has but one purpose—to bring about changes in individual behaviour’ and it does so ‘by altering the institutional arrangements that define the choice sets—the fields of action—for individuals seeking their best advantage from inside of a specific institutional structure’. The dichotomy between the market, the locus of freedom of choice, and non-market domains is now harder to sustain. Choice architecture and design economics make it plain that both individual choices and their aggregate outcomes depend on extant institutional arrangements, stemming from prior political processes that defined the range of admissible action for different groups of people. As institutional economists have reminded us, it is only our familiarity with extant institutions that creates the illusion that current institutional set-ups are natural and fixed, and whence the perception that their change is the outcome of an artificial ‘intervention’. This is the more so, the more institutional 16 This issue has, however, been addressed in (Santos and Rodrigues, 2009). Downloaded from cje.oxfordjournals.org by Robert Looney on July 2, 2011
  • 18. 722 A. C. Santos change alters the distribution of resources, power and opportunities. Those most affected by the new institutional setup tend to depict the new policy as an unnatural ‘intervention’ and will struggle hard to prevent it. But, as the FCC auctions illustrate, markets are the outcome of complex political processes requiring the involvement of an organised power capable of imposing a new set of rules defining who can participate and how. As Ha-Joon Chang put it: Emphasizing the institutional nature of the market [. . .] requires that we have to bring politics explicitly into the analysis of the market (and not just into the analysis of the state) and stop pretending that markets need to be, and can be, ‘de-politicised’. Markets are in the end political constructs in the sense that they are defined by a range of formal and informal institutions that embody certain rights and obligations, whose legitimacy (and therefore whose contestability) is ultimately determined in the realm of politics (Chang, 2002, p. 553) It is now clearer that choice architecture and design economics are not mere technical solutions. Their proposals may affect the distribution of economic and political power and, insofar as they do, they may see their legitimacy questioned on grounds that they violate freedom of choice or introduce distortions in the market. That is, they may be faced with the liberal rejection that they are unwarranted ‘interventions’ to solve problems that are best corrected by the ‘free’ functioning of the market.17 The expectation of this kind of reaction may indeed explain the overly defensive tone of Thaler and Sunstein and their insistence on the principle of ‘freedom of choice’, defined negatively as the protection from interference by others. As we have seen, they have repeatedly stressed that choice architectures are to leave the menu of choices unaltered and grant individuals the exclusive power to use and dispose of things and services as they wish. They thereby accept the status quo ante as legitimate and avoid, as much as possible, altering it. By so doing they focus on people’s choices, leaving the analysis of the context and the circumstances of the individual in the background, as is typical of neoclassical economic theory (cf. Peter, 2004). This means that choice architecture is circumscribed to problems of choice that stem from people’s bounded rationality. It cannot deal with those problems that stem from the wider institutional setup where individuals act and interact. Design economics, in contrast, proposes major institutional change, which may substantially alter the relative position of different social groups. The proposal of the expansion of markets to new spheres of social life has, moreover, forced design economists to acknowledge that market relations can be coercive. The discussion around the creation of a market for the sale of kidneys made the coercive power of pecuniary incentives more salient for economists, acknowledging that the introduction of a monetary payment may force the most deprived groups of the population to engage in unwanted transactions due to extreme economic necessity (Roth, 2007). Design economists have therefore, if only implicitly, recognised that the government does not have the prerogative of the use of power to control people’s behaviour. Power can be exerted by various means and by various actors.18 Nonetheless, design economists still advocate market-based solutions to various kinds of social problem. Even when the legitimacy of these solutions is questioned, bringing about ‘reactions of repugnance’, Roth, as we have seen, pushes economists not to give up their traditional role of pointing to trade-offs and the costs and benefits of the alternatives at hand, proposing that the coercive power of pecuniary incentives be tackled 17 See Sugden (2008) for a critique of choice architecture along these lines. 18 See Grant (2006) for a comparative exercise on the various forms of power, including coercion, bargaining and persuasion. Downloaded from cje.oxfordjournals.org by Robert Looney on July 2, 2011
  • 19. Behavioural and experimental economics 723 by tuning in to their optimum level and by replacing part of monetary compensations with in-kind rewards (Roth, 2007, p. 50). An ample literature, however, exists in the area of political philosophy, which discusses the need to block the expansion of markets so as to prevent so-called desperate transactions (Walzer, 1983, 1984; Anderson, 1990, 1993). In this view, and unlike neoclassical economics, restricting market expansion may, in fact, enhance individual freedom. Keeping the various spheres of social life separated may be the most effective way to ensure a range of options large enough actually to allow people to act in conformity with their preferences and values. For, as Elizabeth Anderson (1990, p. 201) puts it, ‘the realization of some values demands that certain goods be produced, exchanged, and enjoyed outside market relations, in accordance with nonmarket norms’.19 On this view, not only may the introduction of market relations in realms of social life traditionally protected from monetised exchanges create an unacceptable strain on individuals and impede the realisation and expression of values important to human life, but it may also have a detrimental impact on the values fostered. This is so because preferences are endogenous (Bowles, 1998). They are affected by the institutional arrangements that delineate the patterns of social interaction amongst the people who make up society. The social norms and relations of the market, by conveying particular ideals and nurturing specific values, may crowd out other fundamental values (Frey, 1997; Frey and Jegen, 2001). Anderson’s (1993), for example, depicts market social relations as impersonal and selfish, where individuals perceive their relations with others as a means to satisfy their own ends, feeling free to pursue their personal advantage without consider-ation for that of others. In markets people are less compelled to follow non-market norms and values. By aligning self-interest with the interests of others, market mechanisms moreover obviates the need for ethical reasoning; as a result, individuals no longer have the opportunity, as Steve Turnbull puts it, to ‘flex their ethical muscles’ (Frohlich and Oppenheimer, 2003, p. 290). Individuals’ ability to behave in accordance with non-market norms and values, then, will be seriously compromised. On the contrary, living with the tension between the best strategy from a rational, self-interested point of view and the ethically best strategy keeps the ethic imperative active.20 From this it follows that choice architecture and design economics are to be subjected to ethical evaluation. Insofar as choice architecture and design economics alter the balance of economic opportunities among people in order to control or influence their actions toward the goals set by choice architects, by economic designers or by those who hire them, the legitimacy of their proposals must be subject to ethical evaluation, like any other political instrument or proposal. The market rhetoric of freedom of choice and economic efficiency does not obviate the need for such ethical assessment. Indeed, if one takes Ruth Grant’s (2006) criteria—legitimacy of purpose, voluntary response and the effect on the character of the parties involved—one clearly comprehends that expanding the range of choice does not ensure that the available options are equally legitimate, that individuals are capable of pursuing their most preferred actions, or that the outcomes of individual actions are 19 See Rodrigues (2008) for a review on this literature. 20 Frohlich and Oppenheimer (2003) describe a prisoner’s dilemma experiment where there is a conflict between the best individual strategy and the best social strategy. The removal of this conflict through the introduction of an incentive compatible device is effective in promoting the desirable behaviour. But when the device is removed, the level of cooperative behaviour reaches its minimum level, lower than the level observed in groups accustomed to the moral dilemma. Downloaded from cje.oxfordjournals.org by Robert Looney on July 2, 2011
  • 20. 724 A. C. Santos morally innocuous to the parties in the transaction. This ethical assessment gains particular relevance when considering, as the studies of behavioural economics have shown, that people are not always aware of the role of the context and of the institutional arrangements in determining their perceptions of it, and thus of their actions. This relevance is further magnified by the scientistic discourse that often accompanies the proposal of economists’ solutions, which are purged of political content so as to appear innocuous to the parties involved. As Grant (2006, p. 30) argues, in these instances it seems that ‘there is no need to convince people that collective goals are good or to motivate them to pursue those goals by appeals to rational argument, personal conviction or intrinsic motivations’. As a result, ‘[e]xperts and powerful elites [may] direct institutions and shape people’s choices without the sort of public discussion and consent that characterizes democratic processes in general’. But the ethical superiority of market and market-like solutions cannot be taken for granted. It must be assessed and compared with other instruments of public policy. To conclude, as long as choice architecture and design economics aim at altering economic institutions and thereby the balance of power between individuals, they must be part of a wider process of public discussion and consent; otherwise they risk being instruments of manipulation. For they may deceive people into believing that they are acting autonomously when they are actually being used for somebody else’s purposes. The slogans ‘freedom to choose’ and ‘market efficiency’ are not substitutes of public discussion. The economic and ethical benefits of public policies must be demonstrated rather than assumed with the creation of new markets and market-like institutional arrangements. 6. Concluding remarks Behavioural and experimental economics are part of the new mainstream of economics. This is testified by the publication of behavioural and experimental research in top economics journals and by the professional status their practitioners have acquired, inside and outside academia. Policy makers are asking choice architects and design economists for advice in the construction of various institutional setups that aim at steering human behaviour in the directions set by policy-makers. Both choice architecture and design economics depart from the neoclassical model of human action, the homo economicus. The effectiveness of their policy proposals depend on an accurate depiction of human beings, namely on their ability correctly to predict how people will behave in the proposed institutional settings. And they both recognise the relevance of the wider social and institutional context in people’s behaviour. This is in fact their starting point. Choice architecture and design economics aim to improve the institutional setting so as to help people make better choices for themselves and be more aligned with what is required for the attainment of desirable socio-economic goals. These proposals rely specifically on providing individuals with the required information and on suggesting various devices that can help them to make the right calculations, thereby preventing the detrimental effects of the bounded rationality of homo sapiens. There is a crucial distinction between the two proposals, however. Whereas choice architecture explicitly seeks to preserve the status quo ante, leaving the range of individual choices and the structure of economic incentives intact, design economics may be mobilised to produce major institutional change, altering the allocation of the set of economic and political opportunities among differently situated groups of individuals. But they are equally political constructs. They either protect or alter the balance of economic and political power between different groups of people. Downloaded from cje.oxfordjournals.org by Robert Looney on July 2, 2011
  • 21. Yet both proposals are presented as technical solutions to various kinds of socioeco-nomic problems. While choice architecture deals with individual cognitive biases, helping people the better to satisfy their wants, design economics deals with incentive problems, trade-offs and other technical problems, to ensure the efficient allocation of goods, e.g. the distribution of goods to those who value and are willing and able to pay the most for them. They do not consider, much less address, how the new institutional arrangements will impact on the distribution of economic and political opportunities and how interested parties will react in turn. This omission may jeopardise the efficacy of proposed solutions on their own terms. Institutional change may bring about an intense struggle for influence over the collective definition of the new ‘rules of the game’ or may instill strong resistance due to its impact on important values unprotected by the narrow neoclassical normative principles of rationality and efficiency. Insofar as they have these impacts, the proposals of choice architecture and design economics ought to be subjected to public discussion. The implication of the foregoing analysis for the direction of economics is not unambiguous. On the one hand, it may seem that the new research programmes are adopting a rather conservative strategy, one that does not substantially change the nature of economics. Economics is still largely about rational choice in efficient markets, where human behaviour is still analysed in terms of the selection of the best alternative under given constraints and goods are allocated to those who subjectively value, and are willing and able to pay the most for them. On the other hand, the policy proposals make clear the relevance of the institutional setup to individual and collective wellbeing, which cannot be adequately dealt with within the neoclassical economics framework. Paraphrasing Chang (2002), by emphasising the institutional dimension of human action, choice architecture and design economics bring politics explicitly into economic analysis. And this may just be the contribution of the recent research programmes to the building of a new orthodoxy capable of replacing the old neoclassicism. The analysis carried out thus suggests that the potential of the behavioural and experimental approaches to transform economics lies in the consideration of the political dimension of institutional change, a lacuna in the neoclassical economics approach. This requires the explicit recognition that policy-making is not a mere technical exercise. The economic and moral desirability of alternative socioeconomic institutions has to be discussed and argued for. It also suggests that this research agenda can benefit from collaborative work with heterodox economists, namely the tradition of old institutionalism, who have addressed institutional change as part of a larger political process, and with political philosophers who have studied the morality of markets, which must be subjected to ethical scrutiny and democratic validation. Such a research programme would place the analysis of institutions in a wider framework, one that explicitly recognises institutional change as a political process, one that alters the distribution of economic and political opportunities among individuals and that impacts on the motivations and values nurtured in political communities. The possibility of reconciling these approaches would require of traditional heterodox economists a greater interest in core topics, and of behavioural and experimental economists a more receptive attitude toward the ethical appraisal of alternative socioeconomic institutions. Bibliography Anderson, E. 1990. The ethical limitations of the market, Economics and Philosophy, vol. 6, 179–205 Behavioural and experimental economics 725 Downloaded from cje.oxfordjournals.org by Robert Looney on July 2, 2011
  • 22. 726 A. C. Santos Anderson, E. 1993. Value in Ethics and Economics, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press Binmore, K. 1999. Why experiment in economics? The Economic Journal, vol. 109, F16–24 Bromley, D. 2006. Sufficient Reason: Volitional Pragmatism and the Meaning of Economic Institutions, Princeton, NJ, Princeton University Press Bromley, D. 2008. Beyond market failure: volitional pragmatism as a new theory of public policy, Economia Polı´tica, vol. 25, no. 2, 219–41 Bowles, S. 1998. Endogenous preferences: the cultural consequences of markets and other economic institutions, Journal of Economic Literature, vol. 36, no. 2, 75–111 Callon, M. 2007. What does it mean to say that economics is performative? pp. 311–57 in MacKenzie, D., Muniesa, F., and Siu, L. (eds), Do Economists Make Markets? On the Performativity of Economics, Princeton, NJ, Princeton University Press Camerer, C. F. 1995. Individual decision making, pp. 587–703 in Kagel, J. H. and Roth, A. E. (eds), The Handbook of Experimental Economics, Princeton, NJ, Princeton University Press Camerer, C. F. and Fehr, E. 2004. Measuring social norms and preferences using experimental games: a guide for social scientists, pp. 55–95 in Henrich, J., Boyd, R., Bowles, S., Camerer, C., Fehr, E., and Gintis, H. (eds), Foundations of Human Sociality: Economic Experiments and Ethnographic Evidence from Fifteen Small-Scale Societies, Oxford, Oxford University Press Camerer, C. F. and Hogarth, R. M. 1999. The effects of financial incentives in experiments: a review and capital–labor–production framework, Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, vol. 19, 7–42 Camerer, C. F. and Loewenstein, G. 2004. Behavioral economics: past, present, future, pp. 3–51 in Camerer, C. F., Loewenstein, G., and Rabin, M. (eds), Advances in Behavioral Economics, Princeton, NJ, Princeton University Press Camerer, C. F., Issacharof, S., Loewenstein, G., O’Donoghue, T. and Rabin, M. 2003. Regulation for conservatives: behavioral economics and the case for asymmetric paternalism, University of Pennsylvania Law Review, vol. 151, 1211–54 Carvalho, L. F. and Rodrigues, J. 2008. Are markets everywhere? Understanding contemporary processes of commodification, pp. 267–86 in Davis, J. B. and Dolfsma, W. (eds), The Elgar Companion to Social Economics, Massachusetts, USA, Edward Elgar Chakrabortty, A. 2008. From Obama to Cameron, why do so many politicians want a piece of Richard Thaler? The Guardian, July 12, available at: http://www.guardian.co.uk/politics/2008/ jul/12/economy.conservatives [date last accessed June 20, 2011] Chang, H.-J. 2002. Breaking the mould: as institutionalist political economy alternative to the neo-liberal theory of the market and the state, Cambridge Journal of Economics, vol. 26, 539–59 Commons, J. R. 1931. Institutional economics, American Economic Review, vol. 21, 648–57 Cramton, P. 1998. The efficiency of the FCC spectrum auctions, Journal of Law and Economics, vol. 41, 727–36 Crotty, J. 2009. Structural causes of the global financial crisis: a critical assessment of the ‘New Financial Architecture’, Cambridge Journal of Economics, vol. 33, 563–80 Davis, J. 2006. The turn in economics: neoclassical dominance to mainstream pluralism? Journal of Institutional Economics, vol. 2, no. 1, 1–20 Davis, J. 2008. The turn in recent economics and return of orthodoxy, Cambridge Journal of Economics, vol. 32, 349–66 Frey, B. S. 1997. Not Just For The Money – An Economic Theory of Personal Motivation, Cheltenham, UK and Lyme, USA, Edward Elgar Frey, B. S. and Benz, M. 2004. From imperialism to inspiration: a survey of economics and psychology, pp. 61–83 in Davis, J., Marciano, A., and Runde, J. (eds), The Elgar Companion to Economics and Philosophy, Aldershot, UK, Edward Elgar Frey, B. S. and Jegen, R. 2001. Motivation Crowding Theory: a survey of the empirical evidence, Journal of Economic Surveys, vol. 15, 589–611 Frohlich, N. and Oppenheimer, J. 2003. Optimal policies and socially oriented behaviour: some problematic effects of an incentive compatible device, Public Choice, vol. 117, 273–93 Grant, R. 2006. Ethics and incentives: a political approach, American Political Science Review, vol. 100, no. 1, 29–39 Guala, F. 2001. Building economic machines: the FCC auctions, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, vol. 32, 453–77 Downloaded from cje.oxfordjournals.org by Robert Looney on July 2, 2011
  • 23. Hodgson, G. M. 2008. Markets, pp. 251–66 in Davis, J. B. and Dolfsma, W. (eds), The Elgar Companion to Social Economics, Massachusetts, USA, Edward Elgar Kahneman, D. and Tversky, A. (eds) 2000. Choices, Values, and Frames, Cambridge, UK, Cambridge University Press Kagel, J. H. 1995. Auctions: a survey of experimental research, pp. 501–85 in Kagel, J. H. and Roth, A. E. (eds), The Handbook of Experimental Economics, Princeton, NJ, Princeton University Press Lewis, C. 2008. Why Barack Obama and David Cameron are keen to ‘nudge’ you, Times Online, July 14 [date last accessed June 2, 2010] Loewenstein, G., O’Donoghue, T. and Rabin, M. 2003. Projection bias in predicting future utility, The Quarterly Journal of Economics, vol. 118, no. 4, 1209–48 Ma¨ki, U. 2009. Economics imperialism: concepts and constraints, Philosophy of the Social Sciences, vol. 39, no. 3, 351–80 MacKenzie, D. 2006. Is economics performative? Option theory and the construction of derivative markets, Journal of the History of Economic Thought, vol. 28, no. 1, 29–55 MacKenzie, D., Muniesa, F. and Siu, L. (eds) 2007. Do Economists Make Markets? On The Performativity of Economics, Princeton, NJ, Princeton University Press McAfee, R. P. and McMillan, J. 1996. Analysing the airwaves auction, Journal of Economic Perspectives, vol. 10, 159–75 McMillan, J. 1994. Selling spectrum rights, Journal of Economic Perspectives, vol. 8, no. 3, 145–62 Milgrom, P. 2000. Putting auction theory to work: the simultaneous ascending auction, Journal of Political Economy, vol. 108, no. 2, 245–72 Mirowski, P. 2007. Markets come to bits: Markomata and the future of computational evolutionary economics, Journal of Economic Behaviour and Organization, vol. 63, 209–42 Nik-Khah, E. 2008. A tale of two auctions, Journal of Institutional Economics, vol. 4, no. 1, 73–97 O’Donoghue, T. and Rabin, M. 1999. Doing It Now or Later, The American Economic Review, vol. 103, 118–20 Peter, F. 2004. Choice, consent, and the legitimacy of market transactions, Economics and Philosophy, vol. 20, 1–18 Plott, C. 1997. Laboratory experimental testbeds: application to the PCS auction, Journal of Economics and Management Strategy, vol. 6, 605–38 Ritov, I. and Baron, J. 1992. Status-quo and omission bias, Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, vol. 5, 49–61 Rodrigues, J. 2008. Boundaries, values and the contested nature of market expansion, New Political Economy, vol. 13, 315–33 Rose, G. F. and Lloyd, M. 2006. The Failure of FCC Spectrum Auctions,Washington, DC, Center for American Progress. http://www.americanprogress.org/kf/spectrum_auctions_may06.pdf Roth, A. E. 2002. The economist as engineer: game theory, experimentation, and computation as tools for design economics, Econometrica, vol. 70, 1341–78 Roth, A. E. 2007. Repugnance as a constraint on markets, Journal of Economic Perspectives, vol. 21, no. 3, 37–58 Samuels, W. J. 1989. Some fundamentals on the economic role of the government, Journal of Economic Issues, vol. 23, no. 2, 427–33 Samuels,W. J. 1992.Welfare economics, power and property, pp. 56–138 in Samuels,W. J. (ed.), Essays on the Economic Role of the Government, Vol. I, New York, New York University Press Samuelson, W. and Zeckhauser, R. J. 1998. Status quo bias in decision making, Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, vol. 1, no. 1, 7–59 Santos, A. C. 2007. The ‘Materials’ of Experimental Economics: technological versus behavioral experiments, Journal of Economic Methodology, 14, 311–337 Santos, A. C. 2010. The Social Epistemology of Experimental Economics, London, Routldege Santos, A. C. and Rodrigues, J. 2009. Economics as Social Engineering? Questioning the Performativity Thesis, Cambridge Journal of Economics, 33, 985–1000 Shiller, R. J. 2000. Irrational Exuberance, Princeton, NJ, Princeton University Press Shiller, R. J. 2008. The Subprime Solution, Princeton, NJ, Princeton University Press Smith, V. L. 2008. Rationality in Economics: Constructivist and Ecological Forms, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press Behavioural and experimental economics 727 Downloaded from cje.oxfordjournals.org by Robert Looney on July 2, 2011
  • 24. 728 A. C. Santos Starmer, C. 2000. Developments in Non-Expected Utility Theory: The Hunt for a Descriptive Theory of Choice under Risk, Journal of Economic Literature, 38, 332–82 Sugden, R. 2008. Why incoherent preferences do not justify paternalism, Constitutional Political Economy, 19, 226–248 Thaler, R. 1992. The Winner’s Curse: Paradoxes and Anomalies of Economic Life, Princeton, NJ, Princeton University Press Thaler, R. H. and Sunstein, C. 2003. Libertarian paternalism, The American Economics Review, vol. 93, no. 2, 175–9 Thaler, R. H. and Sunstein, C. R. 2008. Nudge: Improving Decisions About Health, Wealth, and Happiness, New Haven, CTand London, UK, Yale University Press Tversky, A. and Kahneman, D. 1974. Judgement and uncertainty: heuristics and biases, Science, vol. 185, 1124–31 Tversky, A. and Kahneman, D. 1981. The framing of decision and the psychology of choice, Science, vol. 211, 453–8 Walzer, M. 1983. Spheres of Justice, New York, NY, Basic Books Walzer, M. 1984. Liberalism and the art of separation, Political Theory, vol. 12, 315–30 Wilby, P. 2008. Cameron’s free-market guru, New Statesman, July 24. http:// www.newstatesman.com/society/2008/07/thaler-friedman-cameron-social [date last accessed June 20, 2011] Downloaded from cje.oxfordjournals.org by Robert Looney on July 2, 2011