SlideShare a Scribd company logo
Dharmakirti​ ​and​ ​Thomas​ ​Nagel
on​ ​the​ ​Origin​ ​of​ ​Mental​ ​Activity
Submitted​ ​by:​ ​Timo​ ​Pieters​ ​(Vrije​ ​Universiteit)
Submitted​ ​to:​ ​Victor​ ​van​ ​Bijlert​ ​(Vrije​ ​Universiteit)
and​ ​Henk​ ​Blezer​ ​(Leiden​ ​University)
Date​ ​of​ ​submission:​ ​4th​ ​of​ ​August,​ ​2017
BA:​ ​Religiewetenschappen,​ ​traject​ ​Boeddhisme
Word​ ​count:​ ​13.483
Final​ ​Thesis​ ​submitted​ ​in​ ​partial​ ​fulfilment​ ​of​ ​the​ ​requirements
for​ ​the​ ​degree​ ​of​ ​Bachelor​ ​of​ ​Arts
1
Verklaring​ ​van​ ​originaliteit
Hierbij​ ​verklaar​ ​ik​ ​dat​ ​deze​ ​scriptie​ ​een​ ​origineel​ ​werk​ ​is.​ ​De​ ​scriptie​ ​is​ ​het​ ​resultaat​ ​van​ ​mijn
eigen​ ​onderzoek​ ​en​ ​is​ ​alleen​ ​door​ ​mijzelf​ ​geschreven,​ ​tenzij​ ​anders​ ​aangegeven.​ ​Als​ ​informatie
en​ ​ideeën​ ​uit​ ​andere​ ​bronnen​ ​zijn​ ​overgenomen,​ ​wordt​ ​dat​ ​expliciet​ ​en​ ​volledig​ ​vermeld​ ​in​ ​de
tekst​ ​of​ ​in​ ​de​ ​noten.​ ​Een​ ​bibliografie​ ​is​ ​bijgevoegd.
Plaats​ ​en​ ​datum: Handtekening:
Arnhem,​ ​Nederland​ ​(08-08-2017)
Verklaring​ ​van​ ​goedkeuring
Hierbij​ ​stem​ ​ik​ ​ermee​ ​in​ ​dat​ ​mijn​ ​scriptie​ ​na​ ​goedkeuring​ ​beschikbaar​ ​wordt​ ​gesteld​ ​voor
vermenigvuldiging​ ​en​ ​interbibliothecair​ ​leenverkeer,​ ​en​ ​dat​ ​de​ ​titel​ ​en​ ​samenvatting
beschikbaar​ ​worden​ ​gesteld​ ​voor​ ​externe​ ​organisaties​ ​en​ ​door​ ​de​ ​Vrije​ ​Universiteit​ ​mogen
worden​ ​gepubliceerd.
Plaats​ ​en​ ​datum: ​ ​​ ​​ ​​ ​​ ​​ ​​ ​​ ​​ ​Handtekening:
Arnhem,​ ​Nederland​ ​(08-08-2017)
Introduction
It​ ​is​ ​assumed​ ​by​ ​many​ ​that​ ​the​ ​nature​ ​and​ ​origin​ ​of​ ​the​ ​mind​ ​are​ ​fully​ ​understood​ ​in​ ​our​ ​current
age.​ ​Our​ ​ancestors​ ​might​ ​have​ ​been​ ​rather​ ​preoccupied​ ​with​ ​where​ ​it​ ​came​ ​from,​ ​what​ ​it​ ​is,​ ​and
where​ ​it​ ​might​ ​go​ ​(either​ ​dogmatically​ ​or​ ​philosophically),​ ​but​ ​today​ ​we​ ​are​ ​no​ ​longer​ ​“in​ ​the
dark”.​ ​Ever​ ​since​ ​the​ ​Enlightenment​ ​eurocentric​ ​civilization​ ​has​ ​been​ ​shedding​ ​it’s​ ​brilliant,
rational​ ​light​ ​on​ ​all​ ​phenomena​ ​shrouded​ ​in​ ​the​ ​darkness​ ​of​ ​dogmatic​ ​and​ ​mythological
antiquity,​ ​and​ ​has​ ​separated​ ​the​ ​wheat​ ​from​ ​the​ ​chaff.​ ​By​ ​the​ ​sheer​ ​passage​ ​of​ ​time​ ​we​ ​have
drifted​ ​closer​ ​and​ ​closer​ ​to​ ​a​ ​truly​ ​objective​ ​appreciation​ ​of​ ​reality​ ​as​ ​it​ ​is.​ ​We​ ​now​ ​know​ ​reality
to​ ​be​ ​mere​ ​matter,​ ​which​ ​means​ ​that​ ​objective​ ​reality​ ​is​ ​largely​ ​devoid​ ​of​ ​“what​ ​matters”:​ ​value,
meaning,​ ​purpose,​ ​and​ ​the​ ​mind​ ​that​ ​perceives​ ​“what​ ​matters”.​ ​These​ ​things​ ​in​ ​fact​ ​only​ ​exist
within​ ​the​ ​confines​ ​of​ ​human​ ​skulls,​ ​encapsulated​ ​in​ ​the​ ​intricately​ ​complex​ ​configurations​ ​of
nerve​ ​cells​ ​that​ ​constitute​ ​the​ ​very​ ​locus​ ​of​ ​our​ ​being:​ ​the​ ​brain.​ ​Our​ ​subjective​ ​experience​ ​of​ ​life
is​ ​for​ ​all​ ​intents​ ​and​ ​purposes​ ​a​ ​virtual​ ​reality​ ​simulation,​ ​running​ ​on​ ​the​ ​electrochemical
hardware​ ​of​ ​our​ ​neural​ ​circuits.​ ​The​ ​objective​ ​in​ ​this​ ​simulation​ ​is​ ​to​ ​ensure​ ​the​ ​survival​ ​of​ ​the
organism​ ​long​ ​enough​ ​so​ ​that​ ​it​ ​can​ ​pass​ ​on​ ​its​ ​genetic​ ​material,​ ​safeguarding​ ​its​ ​continuity
2
above​ ​all​ ​else.​ ​Aside​ ​from​ ​the​ ​obvious​ ​sarcasm​ ​with​ ​which​ ​I​ ​have​ ​just​ ​narrated​ ​this​ ​story,​ ​it
actually​ ​represents​ ​an​ ​accurate​ ​portrayal​ ​of​ ​the​ ​narrative​ ​that​ ​I​ ​was​ ​taught​ ​throughout​ ​my
primary​ ​and​ ​secondary​ ​schooling,​ ​not​ ​just​ ​about​ ​the​ ​history​ ​of​ ​human​ ​knowledge,​ ​but​ ​more
importantly​ ​about​ ​the​ ​nature​ ​of​ ​objective​ ​and​ ​subjective​ ​reality​ ​(mind).​ ​The​ ​most​ ​pernicious
thing​ ​I​ ​learned​ ​was​ ​that​ ​“we”​ ​had​ ​already​ ​figured​ ​it​ ​out.​ ​There​ ​is​ ​nothing​ ​more​ ​to​ ​learn​ ​about
the​ ​mind;​ ​it​ ​is​ ​basically​ ​caused​ ​by​ ​(or​ ​identical​ ​with)​ ​brain​ ​activity,​ ​so​ ​when​ ​you​ ​die​ ​it​ ​is​ ​simply
“lights​ ​out”.​ ​Your​ ​consciousness​ ​ceases​ ​to​ ​exist.​ ​After​ ​considerable​ ​research​ ​it​ ​dawned​ ​on​ ​me​ ​that
this​ ​might​ ​in​ ​fact​ ​be​ ​an​ ​unproven​ ​assumption​ ​that​ ​nevertheless​ ​had​ ​far-reaching​ ​consequences
when​ ​held.​ ​That​ ​is​ ​not​ ​to​ ​say​ ​that​ ​there​ ​is​ ​no​ ​reason​ ​to​ ​think​ ​this​ ​assumption​ ​might​ ​be​ ​true,​ ​but
just​ ​that​ ​the​ ​assumption​ ​has​ ​never​ ​actually​ ​been​ ​proven​ ​correct​ ​scientifically.​ ​During​ ​my
freshman​ ​year​ ​in​ ​university​ ​it​ ​dawned​ ​on​ ​me​ ​that​ ​the​ ​way​ ​one​ ​views​ ​the​ ​origin​ ​of​ ​the​ ​mind
determines​ ​one’s​ ​entire​ ​orientation​ ​towards​ ​life;​ ​it​ ​is​ ​not​ ​just​ ​an​ ​isolated​ ​fact-bit​ ​sitting​ ​in​ ​the
background.​ ​If​ ​one​ ​truly​ ​thinks​ ​that​ ​one’s​ ​mind​ ​equals​ ​electrical​ ​activity​ ​in​ ​the​ ​brain​ ​then
indeed​ ​the​ ​way​ ​of​ ​life​ ​that​ ​follows​ ​from​ ​this​ ​worldview​ ​could​ ​easily​ ​be​ ​hedonistic,​ ​that​ ​is​ ​to​ ​say;
exclusively​ ​maximizing​ ​sensory​ ​pleasure,​ ​survival,​ ​and​ ​procreation.​ ​This​ ​is​ ​not​ ​to​ ​say​ ​that​ ​one
will​ ​live​ ​an​ ​unethical​ ​or​ ​meaningless​ ​life,​ ​but​ ​that​ ​such​ ​a​ ​worldview​ ​does​ ​not​ ​warrant​ ​those
dimensions​ ​of​ ​life​ ​necessarily.​ ​I​ ​will​ ​define​ ​“mind”​ ​throughout​ ​this​ ​thesis​ ​as​ ​the​ ​individual,
mental​ ​activity​ ​of​ ​subjective​ ​experiencing,​ ​or​ ​“mental​ ​activity”​ ​for​ ​short.​ ​Given​ ​the
aforementioned​ ​relevance​ ​of​ ​the​ ​question​ ​where​ ​mental​ ​activity​ ​comes​ ​from,​ ​and​ ​the​ ​likelihood
that​ ​we​ ​do​ ​not​ ​fully​ ​understand​ ​the​ ​answer​ ​to​ ​this​ ​question​ ​yet,​ ​I​ ​will​ ​explore​ ​two​ ​main​ ​thinkers
that​ ​have​ ​seriously​ ​considered​ ​it.​ ​The​ ​first​ ​will​ ​be​ ​Dharmakirti,​ ​a​ ​Buddhist​ ​logician​ ​from​ ​the
6th-7th​ ​century​ ​in​ ​India.​ ​The​ ​second​ ​is​ ​Thomas​ ​Nagel,​ ​who​ ​became​ ​renowned​ ​for​ ​his​ ​paper
“What​ ​Is​ ​it​ ​Like​ ​to​ ​Be​ ​a​ ​Bat?”​ ​in​ ​which​ ​he​ ​explored​ ​the​ ​phenomenological​ ​character​ ​of
consciousness. ​ ​Both​ ​of​ ​these​ ​thinkers​ ​present​ ​a​ ​remarkably​ ​convincing​ ​critique​ ​of​ ​a​ ​range​ ​of
1
theories​ ​that​ ​can​ ​be​ ​characterized​ ​as​ ​“psychophysical​ ​reductionism”,​ ​or​ ​the​ ​idea​ ​that​ ​subjective
states​ ​of​ ​consciousness​ ​are​ ​caused​ ​by​ ​or​ ​identical​ ​with​ ​physical​ ​phenomena​ ​(in​ ​the​ ​body).​ ​In
spite​ ​of​ ​the​ ​more​ ​than​ ​1400​ ​years​ ​between​ ​them​ ​they​ ​also​ ​seem​ ​to​ ​use​ ​strikingly​ ​similar
arguments.​ ​The​ ​main​ ​question​ ​for​ ​this​ ​thesis​ ​therefore​ ​is:​ ​“What​ ​are​ ​the​ ​relevant​ ​implications​ ​of
Dharmakirti’s​ ​arguments​ ​(found​ ​in​ ​his​ ​​Pramanavarttika​)​ ​concerning​ ​the​ ​origin​ ​of​ ​mental​ ​activity
for​ ​the​ ​contemporary​ ​philosophical​ ​discussion​ ​(as​ ​articulated​ ​by​ ​Thomas​ ​Nagel​ ​in​ ​his​ ​​Mind​ ​and
Cosmos​)​ ​about​ ​the​ ​origin​ ​of​ ​mental​ ​activity?”​ ​The​ ​structure​ ​of​ ​the​ ​thesis​ ​will​ ​be​ ​subdivided​ ​into
the​ ​following​ ​questions:
1.1:​ ​What​ ​are​ ​the​ ​fundamental​ ​philosophical​ ​premises​ ​of​ ​Dharmakirti’s​ ​opponent?
1.2:​ ​What​ ​is​ ​the​ ​epistemological​ ​context​ ​for​ ​Dharmakirti’s​ ​philosophy​ ​of​ ​mind?
1.3:​ ​What​ ​are​ ​Dharmakirti’s​ ​arguments​ ​against​ ​his​ ​opponent’s​ ​physicalist​ ​philosophy​ ​of​ ​mind?
1.4:​ ​What​ ​are​ ​the​ ​cosmological​ ​implications​ ​of​ ​Dharmakirti’s​ ​philosophy​ ​of​ ​mind?
2.1:​ ​What​ ​are​ ​the​ ​fundamental​ ​premises​ ​of​ ​psychophysical​ ​reductionism?
2.2:​ ​What​ ​is​ ​the​ ​epistemological​ ​context​ ​for​ ​Thomas​ ​Nagel’s​ ​philosophy​ ​of​ ​mind?
2.3:​ ​What​ ​are​ ​Thomas​ ​Nagel’s​ ​arguments​ ​against​ ​psychophysical​ ​reductionism?
2.4:​ ​What​ ​are​ ​the​ ​cosmological​ ​implications​ ​of​ ​Thomas​ ​Nagel’s​ ​anti-reductionist​ ​philosophy​ ​of​ ​mind?
1
​ ​​Thomas​ ​Nagel,​ ​"What​ ​Is​ ​It​ ​Like​ ​to​ ​Be​ ​a​ ​Bat?"​ ​​The​ ​Philosophical​ ​Review​​ ​83,​ ​no.​ ​4​ ​(1974):​ ​435-50.
3
1.1:​ ​What​ ​are​ ​the​ ​fundamental​ ​philosophical​ ​premises​ ​of​ ​Dharmakirti’s​ ​opponent?
The​ ​school​ ​or​ ​philosophical​ ​position​ ​that​ ​Dharmakirti​ ​(supposedly)​ ​argued​ ​against​ ​was​ ​that​ ​of
the​ ​​Charvakas​​ ​(“the​ ​materialists”).​ ​It​ ​is​ ​as​ ​of​ ​yet​ ​unclear​ ​whether​ ​Dharmakirti​ ​argued​ ​against​ ​a
real​ ​philosophical​ ​opponent,​ ​or​ ​that​ ​he​ ​merely​ ​constructed​ ​straw-man​ ​arguments​ ​to​ ​contrast​ ​his
own.​ ​Eli​ ​Franco​ ​mentions​ ​in​ ​his​ ​study​ ​of​ ​Dharmakirti’s​ ​​Pramanavarttika​ ​​that​ ​his​ ​opponent​ ​could
have​ ​been​ ​the​ ​philosopher​ ​Kambalasvatara,​ ​but​ ​he​ ​likewise​ ​keeps​ ​the​ ​issue​ ​ambiguous.2
Regardless,​ ​this​ ​is​ ​not​ ​of​ ​ultimate​ ​concern​ ​to​ ​the​ ​topic​ ​at​ ​hand​ ​in​ ​this​ ​thesis,​ ​which​ ​is​ ​mostly
concerned​ ​with​ ​the​ ​arguments​ ​themselves,​ ​and​ ​not​ ​necessarily​ ​with​ ​who​ ​used​ ​them.​ ​The
Charvaka​ ​school​ ​was​ ​a​ ​likely​ ​candidate​ ​because,​ ​based​ ​on​ ​the​ ​minimal​ ​sources​ ​we​ ​have​ ​about
them,​ ​their​ ​hallmark​ ​was​ ​the​ ​criticism​ ​of​ ​rebirth​ ​and​ ​the​ ​mechanics​ ​of​ ​behavioral​ ​causality​ ​(Skt:
karma​). ​ ​The​ ​problem​ ​remains​ ​that​ ​almost​ ​all​ ​texts​ ​about​ ​the​ ​Charvakas​ ​are​ ​now​ ​lost,​ ​so​ ​it’s
3
virtually​ ​impossible​ ​for​ ​us​ ​to​ ​get​ ​a​ ​fully​ ​reliable​ ​account​ ​of​ ​their​ ​ideas​ ​and​ ​practices.​ ​Despite
that,​ ​their​ ​philosophical​ ​school​ ​seems​ ​to​ ​have​ ​been​ ​in​ ​existence​ ​up​ ​until​ ​the​ ​second​ ​half​ ​of​ ​the
first​ ​millennium. ​ ​Virtually​ ​all​ ​that​ ​survives​ ​about​ ​them​ ​is​ ​in​ ​the​ ​form​ ​of​ ​references​ ​to​ ​them​ ​by
4
opponent​ ​schools,​ ​which​ ​could​ ​obviously​ ​just​ ​consist​ ​of​ ​straw-man​ ​characterizations​ ​of​ ​their
ideas.​ ​They​ ​most​ ​clearly​ ​rejected​ ​rebirth​ ​and​ ​​karma​ ​​by​ ​rejecting​ ​the​ ​notion​ ​of​ ​“another​ ​world”
(Skt:​ ​​paraloka​)​ ​that​ ​one​ ​might​ ​go​ ​to​ ​after​ ​death,​ ​such​ ​as​ ​a​ ​heaven​ ​or​ ​a​ ​next​ ​life.​ ​They​ ​argued​ ​this
on​ ​the​ ​basis​ ​of​ ​their​ ​assertion​ ​that​ ​only​ ​the​ ​(four)​ ​material​ ​elements​ ​are​ ​truly​ ​real,​ ​and​ ​that​ ​the
mental​ ​was​ ​a​ ​kind​ ​of​ ​epiphenomenon​ ​that​ ​could​ ​either​ ​be​ ​reduced​ ​to,​ ​or​ ​eliminated​ ​in​ ​favour​ ​of,
the​ ​material,​ ​just​ ​as​ ​the​ ​intoxicating​ ​properties​ ​of​ ​beer​ ​can​ ​be​ ​fully​ ​explained​ ​by​ ​its​ ​material
constituents. ​ ​They​ ​insisted​ ​that​ ​there​ ​was​ ​no​ ​intangible​ ​aspect​ ​of​ ​the​ ​human​ ​being​ ​aside​ ​from
5
the​ ​material​ ​elements​ ​that​ ​it​ ​is​ ​composed​ ​of​ ​that​ ​could​ ​leave​ ​the​ ​body​ ​and​ ​experience​ ​things
elsewhere.​ ​Interestingly​ ​enough,​ ​their​ ​rejection​ ​of​ ​the​ ​“other​ ​world”​ ​was​ ​based​ ​on​ ​a​ ​rejection​ ​of
an​ ​abiding​ ​self/soul,​ ​which​ ​Buddhists​ ​generally​ ​also​ ​reject.​ ​This​ ​idea​ ​again​ ​was​ ​based​ ​on​ ​the
notion​ ​that​ ​the​ ​supposed​ ​constituents​ ​of​ ​the​ ​self,​ ​including​ ​consciousness​ ​and​ ​perception,​ ​arise
directly​ ​from​ ​the​ ​material​ ​elements​ ​of​ ​the​ ​body.​ ​This​ ​means​ ​that​ ​there​ ​is​ ​no​ ​place​ ​for​ ​a​ ​self​ ​that
holds​ ​these​ ​constituents​ ​together,​ ​that​ ​would​ ​remain​ ​intact​ ​after​ ​death.​ ​Buddhists​ ​likewise​ ​reject
this​ ​notion​ ​of​ ​an​ ​abiding​ ​self​ ​that​ ​exists​ ​independently​ ​and​ ​unchanged,​ ​and​ ​that​ ​would​ ​provide
a​ ​static,​ ​unaffected​ ​continuity​ ​for​ ​our​ ​experiences. ​ ​They​ ​do​ ​not​ ​however​ ​reject​ ​the​ ​continuity​ ​of
6
consciousness,​ ​which​ ​they​ ​generally​ ​define​ ​as​ ​a​ ​thoroughly​ ​impermanent​ ​continuum,​ ​consisting
of​ ​causally​ ​interrelated​ ​mental​ ​events​ ​that​ ​have​ ​no​ ​independent​ ​status.​ ​Dharmakirti’s​ ​critique​ ​of
materialistic​ ​reductionism​ ​was​ ​therefore​ ​not​ ​based​ ​on​ ​the​ ​Charvaka​ ​rejection​ ​of​ ​the​ ​self,​ ​but​ ​on
their​ ​rejection​ ​of​ ​the​ ​existence​ ​of​ ​past​ ​and​ ​future​ ​lives.
2
​ ​Eli​ ​Franco,​ ​​Dharmakirti​ ​on​ ​Compassion​ ​and​ ​Rebirth,​ ​​(Wien:​ ​Arbeitskreis​ ​für​ ​Tibetische​ ​und​ ​Buddhistische​ ​Studien
Universität​ ​Wien,​ ​1997),​ ​5.
3
​ ​Johannes​ ​Bronkhorst,​ ​“Greater​ ​Magadha:​ ​Studies​ ​in​ ​the​ ​Culture​ ​of​ ​Early​ ​India,”​ ​in​ ​​Handbook​ ​of​ ​Oriental​ ​Studies,
Section​ ​two,​ ​India;​ ​v.​ ​19,​ ​​ed.​ ​Johannes​ ​Bronkhorst​ ​et​ ​al.​ ​(Leiden:​ ​Brill,​ ​1946),​ ​150.
4
​ ​Ibid,​ ​158.
5
​ ​Tom​ ​J.F.​ ​Tillemans,​ ​“On​ ​Minds,​ ​Dharmakirti,​ ​and​ ​Madhyamaka.”​ ​2.​ ​The​ ​present​ ​paper,​ ​in​ ​different​ ​forms,​ ​was
presented​ ​at​ ​the​ ​Center​ ​for​ ​Buddhist​ ​Studies​ ​of​ ​the​ ​University​ ​of​ ​Kathmandu​ ​and​ ​the​ ​Dept.​ ​of​ ​Philosophy​ ​of​ ​the
University​ ​of​ ​Kyoto.​ ​It​ ​was​ ​subsequently​ ​the​ ​keynote​ ​address​ ​of​ ​the​ ​XVIth​ ​Congress​ ​of​ ​the​ ​International
Association​ ​of​ ​Buddhist​ ​Studies,​ ​Taiwan,​ ​2011.​ ​This​ ​free​ ​version​ ​was​ ​obtained​ ​from​ ​Tillemans’​ ​academia.edu​ ​site.
6
​ ​Except​ ​for​ ​the​ ​interesting​ ​anomaly​ ​of​ ​the​ ​​Pudgalavadin​​ ​school,​ ​that​ ​did​ ​maintain​ ​the​ ​notion​ ​of​ ​a​ ​self-sufficient
personality.
4
1.2:​ ​What​ ​is​ ​the​ ​epistemological​ ​context​ ​for​ ​Dharmakirti’s​ ​philosophy​ ​of​ ​mind?
In​ ​the​ ​period​ ​when​ ​Dharmakirti​ ​was​ ​active​ ​(the​ ​6th-7th​ ​century​ ​CE)​ ​the​ ​vast​ ​monastic
universities​ ​of​ ​India​ ​were​ ​strongholds​ ​of​ ​Buddhist​ ​learning​ ​and​ ​practice.​ ​Dharmakirti​ ​held​ ​his
teaching​ ​position​ ​at​ ​the​ ​most​ ​impressive​ ​Buddhist​ ​monastic​ ​university​ ​that​ ​was​ ​probably​ ​ever
built:​ ​Nalanda.​ ​The​ ​university​ ​was​ ​founded​ ​in​ ​the​ ​early​ ​sixth​ ​century​ ​by​ ​the​ ​king​ ​Sakraditya​ ​and
his​ ​son​ ​Budhagupta. ​ ​Interestingly,​ ​it​ ​held​ ​a​ ​prominent​ ​role​ ​in​ ​the​ ​teaching​ ​life​ ​of​ ​the​ ​Buddha
7
himself​ ​when​ ​it​ ​was​ ​still​ ​a​ ​village​ ​and​ ​communal​ ​retreat​ ​place,​ ​as​ ​it​ ​figures​ ​in​ ​no​ ​less​ ​than​ ​nine
Pali​ ​scriptures. ​ ​Unfortunately​ ​from​ ​986​ ​CE​ ​onwards​ ​the​ ​Muslim​ ​Turks​ ​started​ ​raiding
8
North-West​ ​India​ ​from​ ​Afghanistan​ ​all​ ​the​ ​way​ ​to​ ​the​ ​plundering​ ​of​ ​West-India​ ​in​ ​the​ ​11th
century.​ ​These​ ​Muslims​ ​forcibly​ ​converted​ ​people​ ​and​ ​destroyed​ ​Buddhist​ ​art​ ​treasures​ ​out​ ​of
their​ ​distaste​ ​for​ ​idolatry,​ ​so​ ​much​ ​so​ ​in​ ​fact​ ​that​ ​in​ ​India​ ​the​ ​Islamic​ ​term​ ​for​ ​an​ ​“idol”​ ​became
“​budd​”. ​ ​This​ ​all​ ​culminated​ ​in​ ​the​ ​complete​ ​destruction​ ​of​ ​Nalanda​ ​university​ ​in​ ​1198​ ​CE​ ​by​ ​the
9
Muslim​ ​armies​ ​of​ ​the​ ​Mamluk​ ​dynasty.​ ​According​ ​to​ ​the​ ​Tibetan​ ​historian​ ​gSum-pa​ ​mKhan-po
Ye-shes​ ​dPal,​ ​Nalanda’s​ ​campus​ ​housed​ ​three​ ​separate​ ​libraries,​ ​each​ ​with​ ​its​ ​own​ ​name
(Ratnasagara,​ ​Ratnodadhi​ ​and​ ​Ratnaranjaka),​ ​containing​ ​hundreds​ ​of​ ​thousands​ ​of​ ​volumes​ ​on
many​ ​disciplines.​ ​The​ ​largest​ ​of​ ​these​ ​was​ ​nine​ ​stories​ ​high. ​ ​According​ ​to​ ​oral​ ​tradition​ ​these
10
libraries​ ​burned​ ​for​ ​up​ ​to​ ​three​ ​months​ ​after​ ​the​ ​invaders​ ​set​ ​it​ ​ablaze.​ ​The​ ​curriculum​ ​that​ ​was
studied​ ​encompassed​ ​the​ ​Indian​ ​“five​ ​sciences”​ ​(Skt:​ ​​Pancavidya​)​ ​of​ ​(1)​ ​linguistics,​ ​(2)​ ​logic​ ​and
reasoning,​ ​(3)​ ​medicine​ ​(​ayurveda​),​ ​(4)​ ​fine​ ​arts​ ​and​ ​crafts​ ​(from​ ​mathematics​ ​to​ ​painting),​ ​and
finally​ ​(5)​ ​the​ ​“inner​ ​science”​ ​of​ ​spirituality​ ​(​adhyatma​ ​vidya​). ​ ​This​ ​last​ ​branch​ ​was​ ​the​ ​one​ ​that
11
differed​ ​for​ ​each​ ​respective​ ​Indian​ ​tradition.​ ​For​ ​the​ ​Brahmins​ ​this​ ​last​ ​science​ ​meant​ ​the​ ​study
of​ ​the​ ​four​ ​Veda’s.​ ​In​ ​the​ ​case​ ​of​ ​Nalanda​ ​it​ ​meant​ ​the​ ​study​ ​of​ ​the​ ​three​ ​categories​ ​of​ ​Buddhist
scriptures​ ​on​ ​(1)​ ​monastic​ ​discipline​ ​(​Vinaya​),​ ​(2)​ ​discourses​ ​(​Sutra’s)​,​ ​and​ ​(3)
metapsychology/phenomenology​ ​(​Abhidharma​).​ ​These​ ​three​ ​collections​ ​of​ ​scriptures​ ​describe​ ​in
many​ ​different​ ​ways​ ​the​ ​path​ ​to​ ​liberation​ ​(​moksha​)​ ​and​ ​full​ ​enlightenment​ ​(​samyaksambodhi​).
The​ ​way​ ​Dharmakirti​ ​fits​ ​into​ ​this​ ​system​ ​is​ ​through​ ​his​ ​contributions​ ​to​ ​the​ ​science​ ​of​ ​logic
and​ ​reasoning,​ ​and​ ​the​ ​way​ ​those​ ​(epistemological)​ ​principles​ ​tie​ ​into​ ​the​ ​inner​ ​science​ ​of​ ​mind.
Dharmakirti​ ​built​ ​his​ ​philosophy​ ​on​ ​the​ ​innovations​ ​of​ ​his​ ​predecessor,​ ​Dignaga​ ​(480​ ​-​ ​540​ ​CE),
who​ ​was​ ​the​ ​first​ ​teacher​ ​to​ ​systematically​ ​formulate​ ​a​ ​Buddhist​ ​system​ ​of​ ​logic​ ​and
epistemology.​ ​Dignaga​ ​based​ ​his​ ​innovations​ ​on​ ​the​ ​work​ ​of​ ​earlier​ ​Buddhist​ ​philosophers,​ ​most
notably​ ​Vasubandhu​ ​(4th-5th​ ​century​ ​CE).​ ​Vasubandhu​ ​was​ ​most​ ​probably​ ​the​ ​first​ ​Buddhist
thinker​ ​to​ ​suggest​ ​that​ ​the​ ​only​ ​two​ ​valid​ ​means​ ​of​ ​ascertaining​ ​reality​ ​are​ ​perception
(​pratyaksa​)​ ​and​ ​inference​ ​(​anumana​). ​ ​The​ ​knowledge​ ​gained​ ​is​ ​then​ ​communicated​ ​by​ ​means​ ​of
12
7
​ ​Hartmut​ ​​Scharfe,​ ​​Education​ ​in​ ​Ancient​ ​India​.​ ​Handbook​ ​of​ ​Oriental​ ​Studies.​ ​Section​ ​Two,​ ​India​ ​=​ ​Handbuch​ ​Der
Orientalistik.​ ​Indien,​ ​V.​ ​16.​ ​(Leiden:​ ​Brill​ ​2002),​ ​149.
8
​ ​H.​ ​N.​ ​Shastri,​ ​Nalanda​ ​and​ ​its​ ​Epigraphic​ ​Material​ ​(Delhi:​ ​Sri​ ​Satguru,​ ​1942);​ ​in​ ​Stewart,​ ​op.​ ​cit.,​ ​67-
68.
9
​ ​Peter​ ​Harvey,​ ​​An​ ​Introduction​ ​to​ ​Buddhism:​ ​Teachings,​ ​History​ ​and​ ​Practices,​ ​​(New​ ​York:​ ​Cambridge​ ​University​ ​Press,
2013),​ ​149.
10
​ ​Joseph​ ​Loizzo,​​ ​“Sri-Nalanda-Mahavihara:​ ​“Ivory​ ​Tower”​ ​of​ ​India’s​ ​Golden​ ​Age,”​ ​​in​ ​​“CANDRAKIRTI​ ​AND​ ​THE
MOONFLOWER​ ​OF​ ​NALANDA”​ ​(PhD​ ​diss.,​ ​Columbia​ ​University,​ ​2001).​ ​​13.
11
​ ​Jonathan​ ​C.​ ​Gold,​ ​​The​ ​Dharma's​ ​Gatekeepers:​ ​Sakya​ ​Pandita​ ​on​ ​Buddhist​ ​scholarship​ ​in​ ​Tibet.​ ​​(SUNY​ ​Press,​ ​2008),​ ​15.
12
​ ​Vittorio​ ​A.​ ​van​ ​Bijlert,​ ​​Epistemology​ ​and​ ​Authority.​ ​​(Wien:​ ​Arbeitskreis​ ​für​ ​Tibetische​ ​und​ ​Buddhistische​ ​Studien
Universität​ ​Wien,​ ​1989),​ ​45.
5
logical​ ​proof​ ​(​sadhana​)​ ​consisting​ ​of​ ​syllogisms.​ ​He​ ​defined​ ​perception​ ​as​ ​a​ ​form​ ​of​ ​cognition
that​ ​is​ ​not​ ​necessarily​ ​constituted​ ​by​ ​language.​ ​Only​ ​after​ ​raw​ ​(sensory)​ ​perception​ ​has​ ​occurred
can​ ​objects​ ​be​ ​attributed​ ​names​ ​and​ ​concepts.​ ​Perception​ ​is​ ​therefore​ ​knowledge​ ​that​ ​is​ ​solely
caused​ ​by​ ​the​ ​object​ ​in​ ​question.​ ​Conventional​ ​(conceptual)​ ​knowledge,​ ​being​ ​projected​ ​onto
conglomerates​ ​of​ ​fluctuating​ ​processes,​ ​is​ ​hereby​ ​rejected​ ​as​ ​a​ ​valid​ ​form​ ​of​ ​knowledge.
Interestingly,​ ​Vasubandhu​ ​does​ ​include​ ​both​ ​sensory​ ​and​ ​mental​ ​perception​ ​(meaning​ ​internal
objects​ ​such​ ​as​ ​emotions)​ ​in​ ​his​ ​definition.​ ​This​ ​fits​ ​the​ ​general​ ​Buddhist​ ​heuristic​ ​model​ ​of​ ​the
mind​ ​as​ ​the​ ​sixth​ ​sense,​ ​which​ ​perceives​ ​“internal”​ ​objects.​ ​Perception​ ​therefore​ ​has​ ​to​ ​be​ ​(1)
non-erroneous,​ ​(2)​ ​free​ ​from​ ​conceptualizations,​ ​and​ ​(3)​ ​not​ ​a​ ​product​ ​of​ ​inference​ ​in​ ​order​ ​to
count​ ​as​ ​a​ ​valid​ ​source​ ​of​ ​knowledge.​ ​Inference​ ​is​ ​then​ ​based​ ​on​ ​the​ ​direct​ ​perception​ ​of​ ​certain
things​ ​always​ ​being​ ​connected​ ​(invariably​ ​concomitant​ ​-​ ​​nantariyaka​),​ ​which​ ​allows​ ​one​ ​to
validly​ ​infer​ ​the​ ​presence​ ​of​ ​objects​ ​that​ ​are​ ​not​ ​directly​ ​perceived,​ ​the​ ​most​ ​common​ ​example
being​ ​fire​ ​and​ ​smoke. ​ ​The​ ​syllogism​ ​then​ ​represents​ ​the​ ​form​ ​of​ ​deductive​ ​reasoning
13
(inference)​ ​that​ ​can​ ​actually​ ​convey​ ​a​ ​fact​ ​to​ ​another​ ​person.​ ​Dignaga​ ​(480-540​ ​AD)​ ​then
expanded​ ​on​ ​Vasubandhu’s​ ​framework​ ​to​ ​make​ ​the​ ​most​ ​significant​ ​contributions​ ​to​ ​Buddhist
logic​ ​and​ ​epistemology​ ​before​ ​Dharmakirti.​ ​His​ ​main​ ​work​ ​on​ ​epistemology​ ​was​ ​titled
Pramanasamuccaya​ ​​(“Comprehensive​ ​Account​ ​of​ ​the​ ​Means​ ​of​ ​Valid​ ​Cognition”).​ ​Dignaga’s​ ​first
innovation​ ​was​ ​to​ ​connect​ ​the​ ​two​ ​means​ ​of​ ​valid​ ​cognition​ ​(perception​ ​and​ ​inference)​ ​to​ ​the
two​ ​aspects​ ​of​ ​perceived​ ​objects,​ ​namely​ ​their​ ​uniqueness​ ​(the​ ​particular),​ ​and​ ​conceptualized
generality​ ​(the​ ​universal)​ ​respectively. ​ ​The​ ​characteristics​ ​that​ ​all​ ​phenomena​ ​equally​ ​possess
14
are​ ​their​ ​(1)​ ​impermanence,​ ​(2)​ ​unsatisfactoriness​ ​(Skt:​ ​​duhkha​),​ ​(3)​ ​openness​ ​(Skt:​ ​​sunyata​),​ ​and
(4)​ ​insubstantiality.​ ​The​ ​clear​ ​conceptual​ ​(and​ ​therefore​ ​inferential)​ ​discernment​ ​of​ ​these​ ​four
universal​ ​characteristics,​ ​which​ ​is​ ​seen​ ​as​ ​a​ ​necessary​ ​condition​ ​for​ ​the​ ​attainment​ ​of​ ​liberation
from​ ​suffering,​ ​is​ ​interestingly​ ​predicated​ ​on​ ​the​ ​momentary​ ​uniqueness​ ​that​ ​objects​ ​clearly
possess​ ​when​ ​directly​ ​perceived. ​ ​Perception​ ​is​ ​therefore​ ​defined​ ​as​ ​being​ ​free​ ​from
15
conceptualization​ ​(name-giving),​ ​just​ ​like​ ​in​ ​Vasubandhu’s​ ​definition.​ ​Dignaga​ ​then
distinguishes​ ​five​ ​kinds​ ​of​ ​conceptualization​ ​(name-giving):​ ​names​ ​(1)​ ​denoting​ ​only​ ​one​ ​object,
(2)​ ​denoting​ ​a​ ​class​ ​(genus),​ ​(3)​ ​denoting​ ​a​ ​quality,​ ​(4)​ ​action​ ​noun​ ​or​ ​verb,​ ​(5)​ ​denoting​ ​a
substance.​ ​The​ ​four​ ​kinds​ ​of​ ​perception​ ​he​ ​distinguished​ ​were​ ​of​ ​(1)​ ​sensory​ ​impressions,​ ​(2)
mental​ ​awareness​ ​of​ ​them,​ ​(3)​ ​mental​ ​awareness​ ​of​ ​emotions,​ ​and​ ​(4)​ ​higher​ ​(yogic)​ ​perception.
Cognition​ ​also​ ​always​ ​(reflexively)​ ​cognizes​ ​itself,​ ​which​ ​means​ ​it​ ​does​ ​not​ ​need​ ​an​ ​internal
witness​ ​to​ ​become​ ​aware​ ​of​ ​the​ ​knowledge​ ​gained. ​ ​Dharmakirti​ ​then​ ​easily​ ​became​ ​the​ ​most
16
influential​ ​figure​ ​in​ ​Buddhist​ ​epistemology,​ ​and​ ​elucidated​ ​his​ ​own​ ​innovations​ ​in​ ​his
commentary​ ​on​ ​Dignaga’s​ ​work,​ ​titled​ ​​Pramanavarttika​ ​​(“Commentary​ ​on​ ​Valid​ ​Cognition”).
One​ ​of​ ​the​ ​primary​ ​epistemological​ ​innovations​ ​that​ ​Dharmakirti​ ​made​ ​was​ ​to​ ​clearly​ ​specify
what​ ​constitutes​ ​a​ ​valid​ ​inference,​ ​which​ ​concerns​ ​both​ ​“internal”​ ​inference​ ​(logical​ ​thought)
and​ ​“explicit”​ ​inference​ ​(stated​ ​syllogism).​ ​His​ ​main​ ​concern​ ​in​ ​this​ ​was​ ​that​ ​inference,​ ​once​ ​it​ ​is
a​ ​valid​ ​source​ ​of​ ​knowledge​ ​about​ ​reality,​ ​enables​ ​one​ ​to​ ​discern​ ​between​ ​what​ ​is​ ​useful​ ​and
13
​ ​Ibid,​ ​49.
14
​ ​van​ ​Bijlert,​ ​​Epistemology​ ​and​ ​Authority​,​ ​56.
15
​ ​Ibid,​ ​57.
16
​ ​Ibid,​ ​58.
6
what​ ​is​ ​not. ​ ​This​ ​has​ ​the​ ​profound​ ​implication​ ​that​ ​what​ ​it​ ​means​ ​for​ ​knowledge​ ​to​ ​be​ ​correct
17
is​ ​that​ ​it​ ​is​ ​(causally)​ ​efficacious.​ ​In​ ​other​ ​words,​ ​valid​ ​cognition​ ​of​ ​reality​ ​by​ ​definition​ ​enables
one​ ​to​ ​attain​ ​one’s​ ​goals.​ ​As​ ​Dharmakirti​ ​says​ ​in​ ​the​ ​opening​ ​line​ ​of​ ​his​ ​​Nyayabindu​ ​​(“Drop​ ​of
Reasoning”):​ ​“​The​ ​accomplishment​ ​of​ ​all​ ​human​ ​aims​ ​is​ ​preceded​ ​by​ ​right​ ​[valid]​ ​knowledge,​ ​therefore,
the​ ​latter​ ​is​ ​here​ ​explained.” ​ ​Dharmakirti’s​ ​goal​ ​then,​ ​like​ ​Dignaga’s,​ ​was​ ​therefore​ ​ultimately​ ​a
18
“pragmatic”​ ​one,​ ​namely​ ​to​ ​attain​ ​the​ ​ultimate​ ​human​ ​aim​ ​of​ ​liberation​ ​from​ ​suffering​ ​and​ ​to
attain​ ​the​ ​capacities​ ​that​ ​enable​ ​one​ ​to​ ​help​ ​all​ ​other​ ​beings​ ​do​ ​the​ ​same​ ​(full​ ​enlightenment).
Their​ ​epistemological​ ​project,​ ​which​ ​was​ ​to​ ​establish​ ​the​ ​validity​ ​of​ ​Buddha’s​ ​accounts​ ​about
reality​ ​based​ ​on​ ​logic,​ ​was​ ​merely​ ​an​ ​instrument​ ​for​ ​this​ ​ultimate​ ​goal.​ ​The​ ​logical​ ​structure​ ​that
Dignaga​ ​used​ ​for​ ​this​ ​can​ ​be​ ​accurately​ ​summarized​ ​by​ ​the​ ​following​ ​diagram​ ​taken​ ​from​ ​Eli
Franco’s​ ​work​ ​on​ ​Dharmakirti’s​ ​​Pramanavarttika​,​ ​annotated​ ​with​ ​his​ ​English​ ​translations​ ​of​ ​the
Sanskrit​ ​terms.​ ​The​ ​goal​ ​here​ ​is​ ​first​ ​of​ ​all​ ​to​ ​establish​ ​how​ ​the​ ​Buddha​ ​could​ ​have​ ​become​ ​a
“protector”​ ​of​ ​beings​ ​(​tayitva​),​ ​that​ ​is;​ ​truly​ ​protecting​ ​them​ ​from​ ​suffering​ ​as​ ​such​ ​by​ ​teaching
them​ ​the​ ​path​ ​to​ ​liberation​ ​(​nirvana​)​ ​from​ ​all​ ​suffering​ ​and​ ​its​ ​causes.​ ​The​ ​Buddha​ ​needs​ ​to​ ​have
been​ ​a​ ​true​ ​“protector”​ ​in​ ​this​ ​sense​ ​in​ ​order​ ​to​ ​be​ ​a​ ​valid​ ​“means​ ​of​ ​knowledge”
(​pramanabhutatva​).
In​ ​order​ ​for​ ​him​ ​to​ ​become​ ​a​ ​protector​ ​he​ ​needs​ ​to​ ​have​ ​had​ ​infinite​ ​compassion​ ​for​ ​all
lifeforms​ ​equally,​ ​i.e.​ ​“seeking​ ​the​ ​benefit​ ​of​ ​all​ ​beings”​ ​(​jagaddhitaisita​).​ ​The​ ​development​ ​of​ ​such
compassion​ ​would​ ​only​ ​be​ ​realistic​ ​if​ ​the​ ​following​ ​two​ ​preconditions​ ​were​ ​present;​ ​(1)​ ​the
existence​ ​of​ ​an​ ​infinite​ ​number​ ​of​ ​past​ ​lives,​ ​and​ ​(2)​ ​the​ ​capacity​ ​of​ ​mind​ ​to​ ​infinitely​ ​develop
mental​ ​capacities​ ​and​ ​qualities​ ​like​ ​compassion. ​ ​It​ ​is​ ​within​ ​this​ ​context​ ​that​ ​Dharmakirti​ ​sets
19
out​ ​to​ ​establish​ ​the​ ​existence​ ​of​ ​beginningless​ ​past​ ​lives​ ​through​ ​logic.​ ​Dharmakirti​ ​slightly
changed​ ​Dignaga’s​ ​logical​ ​and​ ​causal​ ​structure​ ​to​ ​more​ ​clearly​ ​elucidate​ ​why​ ​this​ ​capacity​ ​for
17
​ ​Bijlert,​ ​94.
18
​ ​Christian​ ​Coseru,​ ​​Perceiving​ ​Reality:​ ​Consciousness,​ ​Intentionality,​ ​and​ ​Cognition​ ​in​ ​Buddhist​ ​Philosophy,​ ​​New​ ​York:
Oxford​ ​University​ ​Press,​ ​2012.​ ​128​ ​(note​ ​11).
19
​ ​The​ ​fully​ ​developed​ ​compassion​ ​of​ ​the​ ​Buddha​ ​encompasses​ ​“perfection​ ​in​ ​intention”​ ​(​asayasampat​)​ ​in​ ​this
diagram.
7
infinite​ ​compassion​ ​is​ ​so​ ​crucial​ ​for​ ​the​ ​possibility​ ​of​ ​becoming​ ​a​ ​“protector”​ ​of​ ​beings,​ ​and
therefore​ ​the​ ​possibility​ ​of​ ​being​ ​a​ ​valid​ ​source​ ​of​ ​knowledge​ ​(about​ ​liberation​ ​and
enlightenment).20
Since​ ​Dharmakirti’s​ ​​Pramanasiddhi​ ​​chapter​ ​(in​ ​his​ ​“Commentary​ ​on​ ​Valid​ ​Cognition”),​ ​which​ ​is
about​ ​the​ ​nature​ ​and​ ​origin​ ​of​ ​mental​ ​activity​ ​(subjective​ ​experiencing),​ ​is​ ​written​ ​in​ ​the​ ​form
of​ ​a​ ​debate​ ​we​ ​will​ ​examine​ ​the​ ​claims​ ​and​ ​arguments​ ​from​ ​both​ ​sides​ ​in​ ​debate​ ​form.​ ​The​ ​lively
form​ ​of​ ​debate​ ​that​ ​was​ ​practiced​ ​at​ ​Nalanda​ ​still​ ​survives​ ​in​ ​the​ ​Tibetan​ ​monastic​ ​universities,
so​ ​for​ ​the​ ​sake​ ​of​ ​imagination​ ​I​ ​invite​ ​the​ ​reader​ ​to​ ​this​ ​small​ ​video​ ​fragment​ ​of​ ​monks​ ​debating
in​ ​this​ ​way,​ ​so​ ​we​ ​might​ ​get​ ​a​ ​taste​ ​for​ ​what​ ​such​ ​debates​ ​must​ ​have​ ​been​ ​like​ ​to​ ​witness.21
1.3:​ ​What​ ​are​ ​Dharmakirti’s​ ​arguments​ ​against​ ​his​ ​opponent’s​ ​physicalist​ ​philosophy​ ​of​ ​mind?
As​ ​I​ ​have​ ​remarked​ ​before,​ ​it​ ​is​ ​impossible​ ​for​ ​us​ ​to​ ​determine​ ​whether​ ​the​ ​debate​ ​between
Dharmakirti​ ​and​ ​the​ ​Charvakas​ ​as​ ​it​ ​ensues​ ​in​ ​the​ ​​Pramanasiddhi​ ​​chapter​ ​is​ ​representative​ ​of​ ​a
debate​ ​that​ ​took​ ​place​ ​between​ ​actual​ ​opponents.​ ​That​ ​is​ ​not​ ​relevant​ ​for​ ​the​ ​discussion​ ​in​ ​this
thesis​ ​however,​ ​since​ ​it​ ​merely​ ​judges​ ​the​ ​relevance​ ​of​ ​the​ ​arguments​ ​themselves.​ ​I​ ​will​ ​now​ ​go
through​ ​Dharmakirti’s​ ​central​ ​arguments​ ​against​ ​his​ ​opponents’​ ​physicalism​ ​in​ ​an​ ​enumerated
fashion​ ​to​ ​maintain​ ​some​ ​conceptual​ ​clarity​ ​along​ ​the​ ​way.​ ​I​ ​have​ ​chosen​ ​to​ ​paraphrase​ ​the
arguments​ ​based​ ​on​ ​Dharmakirti’s​ ​original​ ​text​ ​as​ ​well​ ​as​ ​Franco’s​ ​elucidation​ ​of​ ​each​ ​argument
in​ ​his​ ​book.​ ​Claims​ ​and​ ​arguments​ ​by​ ​Dharmakirti​ ​are​ ​abbreviated​ ​as​ ​​Dk.C​​ ​and​ ​​Dk.A
respectively.​ ​Claims​ ​and​ ​arguments​ ​by​ ​his​ ​(actual​ ​or​ ​constructed)​ ​opponent​ ​are​ ​abbreviated​ ​as
Cv.C​​ ​and​ ​​Cv.A​​ ​respectively.​ ​The​ ​enumeration​ ​couples​ ​each​ ​claim​ ​to​ ​its​ ​corresponding
argument.​ ​Its​ ​order​ ​is​ ​based​ ​on​ ​Franco’s​ ​elucidation​ ​rather​ ​than​ ​on​ ​Dharmakirti’s​ ​original​ ​text.​ ​I
will​ ​go​ ​through​ ​all​ ​the​ ​arguments​ ​to​ ​avoid​ ​a​ ​biased​ ​selection,​ ​but​ ​will​ ​emphasize​ ​the​ ​relevant
arguments​ ​for​ ​the​ ​overall​ ​discussion,​ ​which​ ​will​ ​be​ ​indicated​ ​with​ ​an​ ​​underline​,​ ​in​ ​the
conclusion​ ​and​ ​discussion.​ ​Before​ ​we​ ​get​ ​into​ ​the​ ​actual​ ​debate​ ​we​ ​must​ ​clarify​ ​certain​ ​terms.
The​ ​word​ ​“mind”​ ​in​ ​this​ ​debate​ ​refers​ ​to​ ​“mental​ ​activity”,​ ​defined​ ​by​ ​Dharmakirti​ ​as​ ​a​ ​stream
of​ ​successive​ ​mental​ ​(cognitive)​ ​events,​ ​rather​ ​than​ ​a​ ​monolithic​ ​entity​ ​of​ ​“mind”.​ ​The​ ​term
“support”​ ​(​asraya​)​ ​within​ ​the​ ​context​ ​of​ ​this​ ​debate​ ​refers​ ​to​ ​an​ ​“obtaining​ ​cause”​ ​(Skt:
upadanahetu​)​ ​within​ ​a​ ​causal​ ​sequence​ ​(continuum),​ ​which​ ​in​ ​Abhidharma​ ​is​ ​defined​ ​as​ ​the
cause​ ​from​ ​which​ ​the​ ​result​ ​is​ ​obtained​ ​and​ ​which​ ​transforms​ ​into​ ​the​ ​result​ ​(and​ ​thereby​ ​ceases
20
​ ​Franco,​ ​​Dharmakirti​ ​on​ ​Compassion​ ​and​ ​Rebirth​,​ ​95.
21
​ ​​https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=V6daHMqrMUY
8
to​ ​exist). ​ ​The​ ​translation​ ​as​ ​“obtaining​ ​cause”​ ​is​ ​because​ ​it​ ​is​ ​that​ ​from​ ​which​ ​the​ ​result​ ​is
22
“obtained”.​ ​I​ ​consciously​ ​choose​ ​to​ ​avoid​ ​the​ ​common​ ​translations​ ​of​ ​“substantial​ ​substratum”​ ​or
“material​ ​cause”​ ​since​ ​they​ ​could​ ​be​ ​misunderstood​ ​in​ ​this​ ​context​ ​as​ ​referring​ ​to​ ​the​ ​physical
elements​ ​that​ ​make​ ​up​ ​something.​ ​Obtaining​ ​causes​ ​stand​ ​in​ ​contrast​ ​to​ ​“simultaneously​ ​acting
conditions”​ ​(Skt:​ ​​sahakaripratyaya​)​,​ ​​which​ ​are​ ​assisting​ ​factors​ ​​that​ ​must​ ​exist​ ​prior​ ​to​ ​the​ ​arising
of​ ​something​ ​and​ ​which​ ​assist​ ​in​ ​making​ ​the​ ​arising​ ​occur,​ ​but​ ​do​ ​not​ ​transform​ ​into​ ​what
arises. ​ ​The​ ​classical​ ​example​ ​is​ ​that​ ​of​ ​a​ ​seed​ ​turning​ ​into​ ​a​ ​sprout.​ ​The​ ​seed​ ​here​ ​is​ ​the
23
obtaining​ ​cause,​ ​and​ ​therefore​ ​transforms​ ​into​ ​the​ ​sprout.​ ​Water,​ ​sunlight,​ ​and​ ​soil​ ​are​ ​merely
simultaneously​ ​acting​ ​conditions​ ​for​ ​this​ ​to​ ​occur.​ ​The​ ​six​ ​“senses”​ ​(Skt:​ ​​indriya​)​ ​in​ ​this​ ​debate
are​ ​more​ ​usefully​ ​translated​ ​as​ ​six​ ​types​ ​of​ ​“cognitive​ ​sensors”,​ ​or​ ​sensors​ ​for​ ​short,​ ​since​ ​in
modern​ ​classifications​ ​they​ ​would​ ​include​ ​their​ ​respective​ ​nervous​ ​systems,​ ​including​ ​the​ ​brain
areas​ ​necessary​ ​for​ ​processing,​ ​and​ ​not​ ​just​ ​the​ ​visible​ ​sense​ ​organs.​ ​The​ ​only​ ​exception​ ​is​ ​the
sixth​ ​non-physical​ ​type;​ ​the​ ​mind​ ​sensors,​ ​which​ ​are​ ​the​ ​six​ ​“primary​ ​consciousnesses”​ ​used​ ​in
Abhidharma​ ​models​ ​of​ ​the​ ​mind.​ ​It​ ​will​ ​suffice​ ​to​ ​say​ ​that​ ​these​ ​six​ ​types​ ​of​ ​consciousness
merely​ ​cognize​ ​the​ ​essential​ ​nature​ ​of​ ​the​ ​object,​ ​which​ ​is​ ​the​ ​category​ ​to​ ​which​ ​it​ ​belongs
(sight/sound/etc).​ ​Hence​ ​these​ ​six​ ​consciousnesses​ ​each​ ​correspond​ ​to​ ​a​ ​sensory​ ​or​ ​mental​ ​field.
Dk.C​ ​1:​​ ​The​ ​sensors​ ​are​ ​not​ ​the​ ​support​ ​of​ ​the​ ​mental​ ​cognition​ ​(Skt:​ ​manomati),​ ​but​ ​the​ ​mental​ ​cognition
is​ ​the​ ​support​ ​of​ ​the​ ​sensors​ ​(verse​ ​39).
Dk.A​ ​1:​​ ​​Destroying​ ​or​ ​damaging​ ​the​ ​sensors​ ​does​ ​not​ ​destroy​ ​or​ ​damage​ ​the​ ​mental​ ​cognition,​ ​but​ ​when
the​ ​mental​ ​cognition​ ​is​ ​destroyed​ ​the​ ​sensors​ ​are​ ​likewise​ ​destroyed.​ ​Therefore​ ​the​ ​sensors​ ​arise​ ​from
cognition.24
Dharmakirti​ ​argues​ ​against​ ​a​ ​major​ ​premise​ ​of​ ​his​ ​opponents’​ ​philosophy,​ ​which​ ​is​ ​that​ ​mental
cognition​ ​arises​ ​from​ ​(i.e.​ ​is​ ​caused​ ​by)​ ​the​ ​five​ ​types​ ​of​ ​physical​ ​sensors​ ​(the​ ​sensory​ ​systems​ ​of
the​ ​body).​ ​Unfortunately​ ​Dharmakirti​ ​does​ ​not​ ​specify​ ​what​ ​he​ ​means​ ​by​ ​“mental​ ​cognition”
(​manomati​).​ ​There​ ​seem​ ​to​ ​be​ ​three​ ​possible​ ​interpretations.​ ​The​ ​first​ ​is​ ​that​ ​mental​ ​cognition
refers​ ​to​ ​mental​ ​activity​ ​as​ ​the​ ​subjective​ ​experiencing​ ​of​ ​cognitive​ ​appearances,​ ​stimulated​ ​by
the​ ​six​ ​types​ ​of​ ​sensors.​ ​The​ ​second​ ​is​ ​the​ ​Buddhist​ ​Idealist​ ​(​Chittamatra​)​ ​interpretation​ ​where
mental​ ​cognition​ ​refers​ ​to​ ​the​ ​“foundation​ ​consciousness”​ ​(​alayavijnana​)​ ​that​ ​underlies​ ​all
cognition,​ ​and​ ​that​ ​stores​ ​(karmic)​ ​imprints​ ​and​ ​tendencies.​ ​In​ ​this​ ​view,​ ​one​ ​cannot​ ​be​ ​sure​ ​of
the​ ​existence​ ​of​ ​an​ ​objective​ ​body​ ​as​ ​such,​ ​but​ ​only​ ​of​ ​the​ ​cognitive​ ​appearances​ ​of​ ​a​ ​body​ ​that
appear​ ​to​ ​the​ ​mind.​ ​In​ ​this​ ​view​ ​the​ ​body​ ​is​ ​therefore​ ​an​ ​“image”​ ​in​ ​this​ ​foundation
consciousness. ​ ​The​ ​third​ ​interpretation​ ​would​ ​be​ ​the​ ​Buddhist​ ​Realist​ ​(​Sautrantika​)​ ​view​ ​that
25
Dharmakirti​ ​elucidates​ ​in​ ​verse​ ​42:​ ​​Even​ ​if​ ​there​ ​is​ ​no​ ​cognition​ ​without​ ​sensors,​ ​there​ ​are​ ​no​ ​sensors
without​ ​cognition​ ​either;​ ​therefore,​ ​sensors​ ​and​ ​cognition​ ​are​ ​(at​ ​least)​ ​mutual​ ​causes​ ​and​ ​have​ ​mutual
causes. ​ ​​In​ ​this​ ​interpretation​ ​sensors​ ​and​ ​cognition​ ​are​ ​interdependent,​ ​and​ ​therefore​ ​cannot
26
exist​ ​separately.​ ​The​ ​truly​ ​relevant​ ​interpretation​ ​for​ ​this​ ​thesis​ ​is​ ​the​ ​first,​ ​which​ ​was
articulated​ ​by​ ​Dan​ ​Arnold.​ ​Here,​ ​Dharmakirti​ ​argues​ ​that​ ​it​ ​is​ ​possible​ ​for​ ​there​ ​to​ ​be​ ​mental
22
​ ​I​ ​use​ ​the​ ​translations​ ​from​ ​Dr.​ ​Alexander​ ​Berzin’s​ ​glossary​ ​(​https://glossary.studybuddhism.com/​)​ ​throughout​ ​this
thesis,​ ​unless​ ​otherwise​ ​specified.​ ​Search:​ ​“obtaining​ ​cause”.
23
​ ​Tillemans,​ ​“On​ ​Minds,​ ​Dharmakirti,​ ​and​ ​Madhyamaka.”​ ​3.
24
​ ​Franco,​ ​​Dharmakirti​ ​on​ ​Compassion​ ​and​ ​Rebirth,​ ​​74.
25
​ ​The​ ​​Chittamatra​ ​​philosophy​ ​is​ ​quite​ ​complex,​ ​partly​ ​due​ ​to​ ​its​ ​heterogeneity.​ ​I​ ​will​ ​not​ ​attempt​ ​a​ ​survey​ ​here.
26
​ ​Franco,​ ​​Dharmakirti​ ​on​ ​Compassion​ ​and​ ​Rebirth,​ ​75.
9
activity​ ​(subjective​ ​appearances)​ ​without​ ​sensory​ ​input,​ ​while​ ​in​ ​contrast,​ ​sensory​ ​input​ ​in​ ​and
of​ ​itself​ ​does​ ​not​ ​constitute​ ​mental​ ​activity.​ ​The​ ​mental​ ​is​ ​therefore​ ​conceptually​ ​basic​ ​here. ​ ​If
27
sensory​ ​input​ ​were​ ​the​ ​obtaining​ ​cause​ ​for​ ​mental​ ​activity,​ ​then​ ​it​ ​follows​ ​that​ ​restricting​ ​this
input,​ ​as​ ​in​ ​the​ ​case​ ​of​ ​sensory​ ​deprivation,​ ​should​ ​proportionally​ ​diminish​ ​mental​ ​activity
(cognition)​ ​as​ ​well.​ ​If​ ​one​ ​were​ ​to​ ​enter​ ​an​ ​ideal​ ​sensory​ ​deprivation​ ​tank​ ​for​ ​instance,​ ​one
would​ ​experience​ ​a​ ​complete​ ​cessation​ ​of​ ​mental​ ​activity,​ ​and​ ​go​ ​unconscious. ​ ​Having​ ​spent​ ​an
28
hour​ ​in​ ​such​ ​a​ ​tank​ ​myself,​ ​I​ ​can​ ​attest​ ​to​ ​the​ ​fact​ ​that​ ​the​ ​opposite​ ​occurs.​ ​The​ ​mind​ ​actually
becomes​ ​more​ ​cognitively​ ​active.​ ​One​ ​generally​ ​experiences​ ​enhanced​ ​imagination​ ​(including
visions/hallucination),​ ​crystal​ ​clear​ ​thinking,​ ​and​ ​even​ ​mystical​ ​experiences.​ ​Now,​ ​one​ ​could
argue​ ​that​ ​these​ ​are​ ​never​ ​ideal​ ​circumstances,​ ​and​ ​that​ ​one​ ​always​ ​has​ ​some​ ​sensory​ ​input.​ ​Still,
significant​ ​reduction​ ​ought​ ​to​ ​diminish​ ​mental​ ​activity​ ​proportionally,​ ​which​ ​does​ ​not​ ​seem​ ​to
occur.​ ​If​ ​one​ ​were​ ​to​ ​claim​ ​that​ ​the​ ​five​ ​sensory​ ​systems​ ​are​ ​instead​ ​the​ ​obtaining​ ​cause​ ​for
mental​ ​activity,​ ​then​ ​it​ ​follows​ ​that​ ​destroying​ ​one​ ​of​ ​these​ ​sensory​ ​systems​ ​should​ ​immediately
impair​ ​the​ ​mind​ ​and​ ​its​ ​cognitive​ ​capacities.​ ​There​ ​are​ ​numerous​ ​cases​ ​however​ ​of​ ​people​ ​that
miss​ ​multiple​ ​sensory​ ​systems,​ ​but​ ​regardless​ ​of​ ​that​ ​have​ ​no​ ​significant​ ​reduction​ ​in​ ​mental
functionality,​ ​such​ ​as​ ​the​ ​famous​ ​case​ ​of​ ​Helen​ ​Keller.​ ​She​ ​became​ ​deaf​ ​and​ ​blind​ ​as​ ​an​ ​infant,
yet​ ​she​ ​obtained​ ​a​ ​bachelor​ ​of​ ​arts​ ​degree,​ ​and​ ​published​ ​twelve​ ​books​ ​on​ ​multiple​ ​fields​ ​of
study.​ ​Her​ ​mental​ ​(cognitive)​ ​capacities​ ​therefore​ ​greatly​ ​exceeded​ ​those​ ​of​ ​“normal”​ ​people​ ​that
have​ ​all​ ​their​ ​sensory​ ​systems​ ​intact.​ ​Dharmakirti’s​ ​criticism​ ​of​ ​the​ ​sensory​ ​(nervous)​ ​systems​ ​or
their​ ​input​ ​being​ ​the​ ​obtaining​ ​cause​ ​of​ ​mind​ ​is​ ​therefore​ ​a​ ​strong​ ​argument.​ ​This​ ​argument​ ​will
be​ ​reviewed​ ​in​ ​the​ ​conclusion​ ​and​ ​discussion.
Dk.C​ ​2:​​ ​Mind​ ​(mental​ ​activity)​ ​is​ ​completely​ ​autonomous.
Dk.A​ ​2:​​ ​​The​ ​body​ ​cannot​ ​be​ ​the​ ​obtaining​ ​cause​ ​for​ ​the​ ​mind,​ ​and​ ​may​ ​influence​ ​the​ ​mind​ ​only​ ​in​ ​a
circumstantial​ ​way,​ ​just​ ​as​ ​fire​ ​may​ ​produce​ ​liquidity​ ​in​ ​copper​ ​as​ ​long​ ​as​ ​they​ ​occur​ ​together,​ ​but​ ​copper
is​ ​neither​ ​produced​ ​by​ ​fire​ ​nor​ ​ceases​ ​to​ ​exist​ ​when​ ​the​ ​fire​ ​is​ ​extinguished.29
Dharmakirti​ ​articulates​ ​the​ ​difference​ ​that​ ​the​ ​body​ ​(the​ ​five​ ​sensors)​ ​is​ ​merely​ ​a​ ​simultaneously
acting​ ​condition​ ​for​ ​the​ ​mind​ ​to​ ​function,​ ​and​ ​not​ ​its​ ​obtaining​ ​cause.​ ​Again,​ ​this​ ​is​ ​relevant
because​ ​if​ ​mental​ ​activity​ ​ends​ ​with​ ​the​ ​body​ ​it​ ​cannot​ ​be​ ​said​ ​to​ ​infinitely​ ​expand​ ​its​ ​capacities
and​ ​qualities,​ ​as​ ​would​ ​be​ ​required​ ​for​ ​the​ ​existence​ ​of​ ​a​ ​Buddha.
Cv.C​ ​1:​​ ​Repeated​ ​practice​ ​for​ ​more​ ​than​ ​one​ ​life​ ​is​ ​impossible.
Cv.A​ ​1:​ ​​The​ ​body​ ​is​ ​the​ ​obtaining​ ​cause​ ​of​ ​cognition​ ​and​ ​therefore​ ​destroying​ ​the​ ​body​ ​destroys​ ​cognition
as​ ​well.
Franco​ ​characterizes​ ​the​ ​opponent​ ​view​ ​in​ ​this​ ​case​ ​to​ ​be​ ​one​ ​of​ ​epiphenomenalism,​ ​meaning
that​ ​the​ ​mind​ ​is​ ​an​ ​effect​ ​or​ ​emergent​ ​property​ ​of​ ​the​ ​body,​ ​but​ ​never​ ​its​ ​cause. ​ ​This​ ​also
30
implies​ ​the​ ​mind​ ​does​ ​not​ ​have​ ​causal​ ​efficacy​ ​in​ ​this​ ​view,​ ​and​ ​therefore​ ​corresponds​ ​quite
neatly​ ​to​ ​the​ ​modern​ ​version​ ​of​ ​epiphenomenalism​ ​(mind​ ​as​ ​an​ ​emergent​ ​property).
27
​ ​Dan​ ​Arnold,​ ​“Dharmakirti’s​ ​Dualism:​ ​Critical​ ​Reflections​ ​on​ ​a​ ​Buddhist​ ​Proof​ ​of​ ​Rebirth,”​ ​​Philosophy​ ​Compass​ ​v3
n5​ ​(September​ ​2008):​ ​​1079-1096.​ ​1085.
28
​ ​These​ ​lightless,​ ​soundproof​ ​tanks​ ​(almost)​ ​remove​ ​all​ ​sensory​ ​input,​ ​including​ ​tactile,​ ​since​ ​one​ ​floats​ ​in​ ​highly
saline​ ​water​ ​that​ ​is​ ​heated​ ​to​ ​skin​ ​temperature.
29
​ ​Franco,​ ​​Dharmakirti​ ​on​ ​Compassion​ ​and​ ​Rebirth​,​ ​93.
30
​ ​Ibid,​ ​99.
10
Dk.C​ ​3:​ ​​The​ ​relationship​ ​between​ ​the​ ​obtaining​ ​cause​ ​(the​ ​body)​ ​and​ ​its​ ​effect​ ​(mental​ ​cognition)​ ​does​ ​not
function​ ​as​ ​proposed​ ​(by​ ​the​ ​opponent).
Dk.A​ ​3:​​ ​​Exhalation,​ ​inhalation,​ ​sensors​ ​and​ ​cognition​ ​(i.e.​ ​“sentience”)​ ​do​ ​not​ ​arise​ ​from​ ​the​ ​body​ ​alone,
independently​ ​of​ ​causes​ ​of​ ​their​ ​own​ ​kind.31
Dharmakirti​ ​rejects​ ​the​ ​opponent’s​ ​claim​ ​because​ ​it​ ​is​ ​absurd​ ​to​ ​assume​ ​that​ ​at​ ​the​ ​time​ ​of​ ​birth,
breathing,​ ​sensors,​ ​and​ ​cognition,​ ​can​ ​arise​ ​from​ ​the​ ​body​ ​alone,​ ​independent​ ​of​ ​causes​ ​that​ ​are
similar​ ​in​ ​nature.​ ​This​ ​implies​ ​that​ ​“sentient”​ ​phenomena​ ​have​ ​to​ ​arise​ ​dependent​ ​upon​ ​causes
of​ ​the​ ​same​ ​ontological​ ​kind​ ​or​ ​category​ ​of​ ​phenomena,​ ​i.e.,​ ​possess​ ​the​ ​same​ ​characteristic
properties.​ ​This,​ ​in​ ​essence,​ ​is​ ​Dharmakirti’s​ ​main​ ​argument:​ ​sentient​ ​phenomena​ ​(breaths,
sensors,​ ​and​ ​cognition)​ ​must​ ​have​ ​among​ ​their​ ​causes​ ​events​ ​that​ ​are​ ​themselves​ ​sentient
(possess​ ​the​ ​same​ ​properties​ ​of​ ​“sentience”),​ ​because​ ​phenomena​ ​must​ ​have​ ​ontologically
homogeneous​ ​causes. ​ ​Even​ ​the​ ​modern​ ​physicalist​ ​model​ ​endorses​ ​this​ ​axiomatic​ ​principle;​ ​it​ ​is
32
impossible​ ​for​ ​physical​ ​phenomena​ ​(matter/energy)​ ​to​ ​give​ ​rise​ ​to​ ​phenomena​ ​that​ ​have​ ​no
physical​ ​properties.​ ​As​ ​we​ ​will​ ​see,​ ​this​ ​presented​ ​a​ ​virtually​ ​insurmountable​ ​challenge​ ​for
modern​ ​thinkers​ ​to​ ​somehow​ ​give​ ​mental​ ​(subjective)​ ​phenomena​ ​a​ ​place​ ​in​ ​the​ ​causal​ ​world,
regardless​ ​of​ ​their​ ​non-physical,​ ​phenomenological​ ​characteristics.​ ​We​ ​will​ ​return​ ​to​ ​the
relevant​ ​implications​ ​of​ ​this​ ​in​ ​the​ ​conclusion​ ​and​ ​discussion.
Cv.C​ ​2:​​ ​​Consciousness​ ​(sentience)​ ​arises​ ​from​ ​the​ ​material​ ​elements​ ​(of​ ​the​ ​body),​ ​and​ ​not​ ​from​ ​causes​ ​of
the​ ​same​ ​kind.​ ​Only​ ​a​ ​special​ ​transformation​ ​of​ ​the​ ​elements​ ​into​ ​the​ ​form​ ​of​ ​a​ ​body​ ​produces​ ​life
(sentience).
Cv.A​ ​2:​​ ​Therefore​ ​only​ ​certain​ ​parts​ ​of​ ​the​ ​elements​ ​cause​ ​sentience,​ ​just​ ​like​ ​certain​ ​stones​ ​contain​ ​gold,
while​ ​others​ ​do​ ​not.
Dk.C​ ​4:​​ ​The​ ​diversity​ ​of​ ​life,​ ​and​ ​the​ ​regularity​ ​within​ ​its​ ​diversity,​ ​would​ ​be​ ​unexplainable​ ​if​ ​life​ ​arose
from​ ​the​ ​material​ ​elements​ ​alone.33
The​ ​material​ ​elements​ ​referred​ ​to​ ​here​ ​are​ ​those​ ​found​ ​in​ ​Abhidharma;​ ​earth​ ​(solidity),​ ​water
(cohesion),​ ​fire​ ​(heat/energy),​ ​and​ ​wind​ ​(motion).​ ​These​ ​“elements”​ ​are​ ​quite​ ​unlike​ ​the​ ​elements
of​ ​the​ ​periodic​ ​table,​ ​because​ ​they​ ​are​ ​more​ ​like​ ​principles​ ​or​ ​forces.​ ​All​ ​four​ ​are​ ​said​ ​to​ ​occur​ ​in
all​ ​material​ ​phenomena,​ ​but​ ​in​ ​varying​ ​proportions,​ ​which​ ​gives​ ​each​ ​phenomenon​ ​its​ ​distinct
characteristics.​ ​Dharmakirti’s​ ​point​ ​is​ ​that​ ​since​ ​these​ ​elemental​ ​forces​ ​are​ ​omnipresent,​ ​it​ ​is
impossible​ ​to​ ​account​ ​for​ ​the​ ​diversities​ ​and​ ​regularities​ ​of​ ​life​ ​that​ ​supposedly​ ​arise​ ​from​ ​them.
A​ ​modern​ ​parallel​ ​of​ ​the​ ​four​ ​elements​ ​would​ ​perhaps​ ​be​ ​the​ ​“four​ ​fundamental​ ​forces”​ ​used​ ​in
physics,​ ​that​ ​are​ ​also​ ​not​ ​reducible​ ​to​ ​more​ ​basic​ ​forces:​ ​(1)​ ​the​ ​gravitational​ ​force​ ​(attributed​ ​to
the​ ​curvature​ ​of​ ​spacetime),​ ​(2)​ ​the​ ​electromagnetic​ ​force​ ​(manifests​ ​itself​ ​through​ ​the​ ​forces
between​ ​electric​ ​charges​ ​and​ ​magnetic​ ​fields,​ ​involving​ ​the​ ​exchange​ ​of​ ​photons),​ ​(3)​ ​the​ ​weak
nuclear​ ​force​ ​(mediates​ ​radioactive​ ​decay),​ ​and​ ​(4)​ ​the​ ​strong​ ​nuclear​ ​force​ ​(holds​ ​the​ ​atomic
nucleus​ ​together). ​ ​All​ ​of​ ​these​ ​are​ ​mathematically​ ​described​ ​as​ ​fields.​ ​The​ ​modern​ ​account​ ​of
34
the​ ​origin​ ​of​ ​life​ ​(“sentience”)​ ​is​ ​fundamentally​ ​a​ ​reductive​ ​one,​ ​namely​ ​that​ ​all​ ​of​ ​(conscious)
life​ ​spontaneously​ ​emerged​ ​from​ ​the​ ​most​ ​fundamental​ ​physical​ ​forces​ ​of​ ​nature.​ ​Dharmakirti’s
31
​ ​Ibid,​ ​102.
32
​ ​Dan​ ​Arnold,​ ​“Dharmakirti’s​ ​Dualism:​ ​Critical​ ​Reflections​ ​on​ ​a​ ​Buddhist​ ​Proof​ ​of​ ​Rebirth,”​ ​1083.
33
​ ​Franco,​ ​​Dharmakirti​ ​on​ ​Compassion​ ​and​ ​Rebirth​,​ ​108.
34
​ ​​http://hyperphysics.phy-astr.gsu.edu/hbase/Forces/funfor.html
11
argument​ ​is​ ​therefore​ ​also​ ​an​ ​argument​ ​against​ ​modern​ ​reductive​ ​accounts​ ​of​ ​the​ ​origin​ ​of​ ​life,
such​ ​as​ ​the​ ​Oparin-Haldane​ ​hypothesis. ​ ​Dharmakirti’s​ ​point​ ​is​ ​solid,​ ​since​ ​the​ ​fact​ ​that​ ​the
35
reductionist​ ​model​ ​still​ ​remains​ ​unproven​ ​today​ ​suggests​ ​that​ ​it​ ​is​ ​almost​ ​impossible​ ​to​ ​explain
the​ ​diversity​ ​and​ ​the​ ​regularity​ ​within​ ​the​ ​diversity​ ​of​ ​life,​ ​based​ ​on​ ​analysing​ ​its​ ​elementary
physical​ ​components​ ​alone.
Dk.A​ ​4:​ ​​If​ ​sentient​ ​phenomena​ ​(sensors,​ ​cognitions)​ ​were​ ​produced​ ​purely​ ​by​ ​the​ ​material​ ​elements​ ​alone,
without​ ​causes​ ​of​ ​their​ ​own​ ​kind,​ ​then​ ​just​ ​as​ ​the​ ​elements​ ​are​ ​transformed​ ​into​ ​the​ ​cause​ ​of​ ​life
somewhere​ ​(where​ ​they​ ​take​ ​the​ ​form​ ​of​ ​a​ ​body),​ ​the​ ​same​ ​would​ ​happen​ ​everywhere​ ​because​ ​the​ ​cause​ ​of
the​ ​transformation​ ​is​ ​the​ ​same​.36
The​ ​absurd​ ​consequence​ ​of​ ​the​ ​material​ ​elements​ ​causing​ ​life​ ​(sentience)​ ​is​ ​that​ ​life​ ​would
spring​ ​forth​ ​continuously​ ​wherever​ ​these​ ​material​ ​elements​ ​(physical​ ​forces)​ ​exist,​ ​which​ ​would
happen​ ​everywhere,​ ​all​ ​the​ ​time,​ ​since​ ​the​ ​elements​ ​are​ ​present​ ​everywhere.​ ​Clearly​ ​this​ ​is​ ​not
happening.​ ​The​ ​material​ ​elements​ ​alone​ ​therefore​ ​cannot​ ​account​ ​for​ ​the​ ​existence​ ​and​ ​diversity
of​ ​life,​ ​and​ ​sentient​ ​phenomena​ ​can​ ​likewise​ ​not​ ​arise​ ​from​ ​the​ ​body​ ​alone​ ​independently​ ​of
causes​ ​of​ ​their​ ​own​ ​kind.
Cv.C​ ​3:​ ​​Every​ ​cognition​ ​at​ ​death​ ​(the​ ​final​ ​cognition​ ​in​ ​life)​ ​does​ ​not​ ​link​ ​to​ ​another​ ​cognition​ ​(in​ ​the​ ​next
life).
Cv.A​ ​3:​​ ​Because​ ​it​ ​is​ ​a​ ​cognition​ ​at​ ​death,​ ​just​ ​like​ ​the​ ​last​ ​cognition​ ​of​ ​the​ ​Arhat​ ​(liberated​ ​being). ​ ​Thus,
37
everyone​ ​is​ ​liberated​ ​after​ ​death,​ ​just​ ​like​ ​the​ ​Arhat.
An​ ​Arhat​ ​is​ ​defined​ ​as​ ​a​ ​being​ ​who​ ​has​ ​totally​ ​uprooted​ ​suffering​ ​and​ ​its​ ​causes​ ​(disturbing
emotions,​ ​karma),​ ​and​ ​therefore​ ​has​ ​no​ ​impetus​ ​to​ ​compulsively​ ​take​ ​on​ ​a​ ​new​ ​body​ ​on​ ​the​ ​basis
of​ ​craving​ ​(disturbing​ ​emotions)​ ​after​ ​death.​ ​Some​ ​believe​ ​that​ ​an​ ​Arhat​ ​therefore​ ​actually
ceases​ ​to​ ​exist​ ​at​ ​death,​ ​since​ ​there​ ​is​ ​no​ ​impetus​ ​for​ ​further​ ​cognitions.
Dk.C​ ​5:​ ​​There​ ​is​ ​no​ ​contradiction​ ​whatsoever​ ​between​ ​the​ ​cognition​ ​at​ ​death​ ​of​ ​an​ ​Arhat​ ​and​ ​the
production​ ​of​ ​a​ ​further​ ​cognition.
Dk.A​ ​5:​ ​​It​ ​is​ ​the​ ​disconnection​ ​from​ ​the​ ​defilements​ ​(disturbing​ ​emotions)​ ​which​ ​prevents​ ​rebirth.
Dharmakirti​ ​therefore​ ​disproves​ ​this​ ​notion​ ​of​ ​death​ ​being​ ​equal​ ​to​ ​liberation,​ ​and​ ​that​ ​Arhats
cease​ ​to​ ​exist​ ​when​ ​they​ ​become​ ​liberated.
Dk.C​ ​6:​​ ​The​ ​body​ ​as​ ​the​ ​cause​ ​of​ ​cognition​ ​is​ ​likewise​ ​not​ ​established.
Dk.A​ ​6:​ ​​Because​ ​that​ ​which​ ​is​ ​claimed​ ​to​ ​be​ ​a​ ​cause​ ​is​ ​not​ ​a​ ​cause​ ​at​ ​all,​ ​it’s​ ​absence​ ​cannot​ ​be​ ​adduced​ ​as
reason.​ ​​If​ ​the​ ​mental​ ​cognition​ ​were​ ​to​ ​arise​ ​from​ ​the​ ​body​ ​with​ ​sensors​ ​it​ ​would​ ​be​ ​like​ ​(have​ ​the​ ​nature
of)​ ​a​ ​sense​ ​cognition,​ ​which​ ​means​ ​it​ ​would​ ​be​ ​limited​ ​to​ ​certain​ ​kinds​ ​of​ ​objects.​ ​Nor​ ​does​ ​it​ ​arise​ ​from
the​ ​body​ ​with​ ​all​ ​the​ ​sensors​ ​together,​ ​because​ ​the​ ​sensors​ ​do​ ​not​ ​cooperate​ ​(blend​ ​together).​ ​Nor​ ​does​ ​it
arise​ ​from​ ​the​ ​body​ ​without​ ​the​ ​sensors,​ ​because​ ​the​ ​body​ ​(alone)​ ​is​ ​devoid​ ​of​ ​consciousness.38
If​ ​the​ ​mental​ ​cognition​ ​were​ ​caused​ ​by​ ​the​ ​body​ ​there​ ​would​ ​be​ ​three​ ​possibilities.​ ​Either​ ​it​ ​is
caused​ ​by​ ​(1)​ ​one​ ​sensory​ ​system​ ​of​ ​the​ ​body,​ ​(2)​ ​by​ ​the​ ​body​ ​with​ ​all​ ​sensory​ ​systems​ ​together,
or​ ​(3)​ ​the​ ​body​ ​independently​ ​of​ ​its​ ​sensory​ ​systems.​ ​If​ ​the​ ​first​ ​were​ ​true​ ​then​ ​mental​ ​cognition
35
​ ​This​ ​hypothesis​ ​claims​ ​that​ ​biological​ ​life​ ​spontaneously​ ​emerged​ ​from​ ​the​ ​interactions​ ​of​ ​elementary
compounds.
36
​ ​Ibid,​ ​113.​ ​The​ ​physicalist​ ​opponent​ ​does​ ​not​ ​admit​ ​to​ ​any​ ​existents​ ​over​ ​and​ ​above​ ​the​ ​material​ ​elements,​ ​so​ ​the
(obtaining)​ ​cause​ ​is​ ​omnipresent.
37
​ ​Arhats​ ​are​ ​beings​ ​who​ ​have​ ​attained​ ​​nirvana​ ​​(liberation​ ​from​ ​suffering),​ ​but​ ​are​ ​not​ ​enlightened​ ​(a​ ​Buddha).
38
​ ​Ibid,​ ​119.
12
would​ ​have​ ​the​ ​nature​ ​of​ ​that​ ​sensory​ ​system,​ ​and​ ​could​ ​therefore​ ​only​ ​cognize​ ​a​ ​certain​ ​range
of​ ​objects.​ ​If​ ​the​ ​second​ ​were​ ​true,​ ​then​ ​Dharmakirti’s​ ​first​ ​argument​ ​applies​ ​that​ ​destroying​ ​one
sensory​ ​system​ ​would​ ​terminate​ ​mental​ ​activity,​ ​since​ ​its​ ​obtaining​ ​cause​ ​is​ ​no​ ​longer​ ​complete.
If​ ​the​ ​third​ ​were​ ​true​ ​then​ ​a​ ​dead​ ​body​ ​would​ ​have​ ​consciousness​ ​as​ ​well,​ ​which​ ​is​ ​an​ ​absurd
consequence.
Cv.A​ ​4:​ ​​Why,​ ​if​ ​the​ ​body​ ​is​ ​not​ ​the​ ​cause​ ​of​ ​the​ ​mental​ ​cognition,​ ​do​ ​they​ ​always​ ​exist​ ​together?
Dk.C​ ​7:​ ​​They​ ​have​ ​the​ ​same​ ​cause,
Dk.A​ ​7:​ ​​just​ ​as​ ​sight​ ​and​ ​hearing​ ​of​ ​the​ ​same​ ​person​ ​or​ ​color​ ​and​ ​flavour​ ​of​ ​the​ ​same​ ​object​ ​always​ ​exist
together​ ​without​ ​being​ ​each​ ​other’s​ ​cause.
Cv.C​ ​5:​ ​​It​ ​cannot​ ​be​ ​explained​ ​why​ ​the​ ​mental​ ​cognition​ ​is​ ​transformed​ ​by​ ​the​ ​body​ ​if​ ​the​ ​body​ ​is​ ​not​ ​its
cause.
Cv.A​ ​5:​ ​​For​ ​instance,​ ​the​ ​transformation​ ​of​ ​the​ ​body​ ​by​ ​poison​ ​causes​ ​a​ ​mental​ ​transformation​ ​as​ ​pain.39
Dk.C​ ​8:​ ​​The​ ​transformation​ ​occurs,​ ​but​ ​the​ ​body​ ​is​ ​not​ ​the​ ​obtaining​ ​cause.
Dk.A​ ​8:​ ​​The​ ​transformation​ ​is​ ​caused​ ​by​ ​the​ ​apprehension​ ​(cognition)​ ​of​ ​the​ ​body​ ​(the​ ​body​ ​as​ ​object,​ ​not
as​ ​cause).​ ​The​ ​body​ ​may​ ​be​ ​said​ ​to​ ​be​ ​an​ ​assisting​ ​factor​ ​in​ ​the​ ​production​ ​of​ ​cognition,​ ​but​ ​not​ ​its​ ​cause.
Dk.C​ ​9:​ ​​The​ ​fact​ ​that​ ​the​ ​body​ ​is​ ​sometimes​ ​the​ ​assisting​ ​factor​ ​for​ ​the​ ​sequence​ ​of​ ​cognitions​ ​(mental
activity)​ ​does​ ​not​ ​mean​ ​that​ ​the​ ​sequence​ ​ceases​ ​to​ ​exist​ ​when​ ​the​ ​body​ ​ceases​ ​to​ ​exist.
Dk.A​ ​9.1:​ ​​Just​ ​as​ ​fire​ ​may​ ​change​ ​the​ ​color​ ​of​ ​a​ ​pot,​ ​but​ ​the​ ​pot​ ​does​ ​not​ ​cease​ ​to​ ​exist​ ​when​ ​the​ ​fire​ ​stops.
Dk.A​ ​9.2:​ ​​If​ ​the​ ​body​ ​were​ ​the​ ​obtaining​ ​cause​ ​of​ ​cognition,​ ​there​ ​would​ ​follow​ ​an​ ​absurd​ ​consequence,
namely​ ​that​ ​the​ ​cognition​ ​would​ ​last​ ​as​ ​long​ ​as​ ​the​ ​body,​ ​in​ ​which​ ​case​ ​a​ ​dead​ ​body​ ​too​ ​would​ ​have​ ​to
have​ ​cognition.40
Tom​ ​Tillemans​ ​argues​ ​that​ ​this​ ​line​ ​of​ ​reasoning​ ​is​ ​based​ ​on​ ​scientific​ ​ignorance​ ​on​ ​the​ ​part​ ​of
Dharmakirti,​ ​since​ ​modern​ ​research​ ​has​ ​shown​ ​that​ ​an​ ​alive​ ​body​ ​is​ ​not​ ​physically​ ​identical​ ​to​ ​a
dead​ ​body,​ ​and​ ​therefore​ ​the​ ​two​ ​cannot​ ​be​ ​equated​ ​in​ ​this​ ​context. ​ ​I​ ​would​ ​argue​ ​that,​ ​even​ ​if
41
one​ ​factors​ ​in​ ​the​ ​appropriate​ ​differences,​ ​the​ ​argument​ ​still​ ​discredits​ ​the​ ​possibility​ ​of​ ​most
tissues​ ​of​ ​the​ ​body​ ​acting​ ​as​ ​the​ ​obtaining​ ​cause​ ​for​ ​mental​ ​activity.​ ​Most​ ​tissues​ ​of​ ​the​ ​body
remain​ ​physically​ ​identical​ ​immediately​ ​after​ ​the​ ​onset​ ​of​ ​clinical​ ​death,​ ​yet​ ​mental​ ​activity
ceases.​ ​What​ ​the​ ​argument​ ​fails​ ​to​ ​prove​ ​however,​ ​is​ ​that​ ​brain​ ​activity​ ​could​ ​be​ ​the​ ​obtaining
cause​ ​for​ ​mental​ ​activity,​ ​since​ ​this​ ​obviously​ ​ceases​ ​upon​ ​death.​ ​Therefore​ ​I​ ​will​ ​further​ ​explore
this​ ​version​ ​of​ ​the​ ​argument​ ​in​ ​the​ ​conclusion​ ​and​ ​discussion.
Cv.C​ ​6:​ ​​Cognition​ ​is​ ​absent​ ​in​ ​a​ ​dead​ ​body,
Cv.A​ ​6:​ ​​because​ ​breath​ ​is​ ​also​ ​a​ ​cause​ ​of​ ​cognition,​ ​and​ ​there​ ​is​ ​no​ ​breath​ ​in​ ​a​ ​dead​ ​body.42
This​ ​is​ ​quite​ ​possibly​ ​a​ ​reference​ ​to​ ​vitalism,​ ​the​ ​idea​ ​that​ ​there​ ​is​ ​a​ ​subtle​ ​animating​ ​principle
associated​ ​with​ ​the​ ​physical​ ​breath​ ​that​ ​animates​ ​the​ ​body,​ ​and​ ​that​ ​is​ ​closely​ ​associated​ ​with
consciousness.​ ​One​ ​need​ ​only​ ​refer​ ​to​ ​physical​ ​breath​ ​however​ ​to​ ​follow​ ​the​ ​discussion​ ​further.
Here​ ​Dharmakirti​ ​begins​ ​a​ ​lengthy​ ​discussion​ ​of​ ​why​ ​cognition​ ​is​ ​independent​ ​of​ ​the​ ​breaths.
This​ ​is​ ​not​ ​truly​ ​relevant​ ​in​ ​relation​ ​to​ ​modern​ ​discussion,​ ​and​ ​therefore​ ​to​ ​this​ ​thesis,​ ​but​ ​I
have​ ​included​ ​it​ ​for​ ​the​ ​sake​ ​of​ ​comprehensiveness​ ​and​ ​context.
39
​ ​Ibid,​ ​119.
40
​ ​Ibid,​ ​121.
41
​ ​Tillemans,​ ​“On​ ​Minds,​ ​Dharmakirti,​ ​and​ ​Madhyamaka.”​ ​3.
42
​ ​Franco,​ ​​Dharmakirti​ ​on​ ​Compassion​ ​and​ ​Rebirth,​ ​​234.
13
Dk.C​ ​10:​ ​​Cognition​ ​is​ ​the​ ​cause​ ​of​ ​the​ ​breath,​ ​not​ ​the​ ​other​ ​way​ ​around.43
Dk.A​ ​10.1:​ ​​It​ ​can​ ​be​ ​observed​ ​that​ ​breath​ ​is​ ​controlled​ ​by​ ​cognition,​ ​not​ ​the​ ​other​ ​way​ ​around.
Dk.A​ ​10.2:​ ​​Breath​ ​is​ ​impossible​ ​without​ ​consciousness,​ ​since​ ​drawing​ ​in​ ​and​ ​pushing​ ​out​ ​air​ ​can​ ​not
happen​ ​without​ ​an​ ​effort,​ ​and​ ​effort​ ​implies​ ​consciousness.
Dk.A​ ​10.3:​ ​​If​ ​cognition​ ​were​ ​the​ ​resultant​ ​effect​ ​of​ ​exhalation​ ​and​ ​inhalation​ ​it​ ​would​ ​increase​ ​and
decrease​ ​according​ ​to​ ​the​ ​increase​ ​and​ ​decrease​ ​in​ ​breathing.
Dk.A​ ​10.4:​ ​​If​ ​breath​ ​in​ ​fact​ ​were​ ​the​ ​cause​ ​of​ ​cognition,​ ​then​ ​the​ ​cognition​ ​would​ ​be​ ​present​ ​as​ ​long​ ​as
exhalation​ ​and​ ​inhalation​ ​are​ ​present,​ ​and​ ​they,​ ​being​ ​caused​ ​by​ ​the​ ​body,​ ​would​ ​be​ ​present​ ​as​ ​long​ ​as​ ​the
body​ ​is​ ​present.​ ​Consequently​ ​there​ ​would​ ​be​ ​no​ ​dead​ ​body,​ ​which​ ​is​ ​an​ ​inadmissible​ ​consequence.
Dk.C​ ​11:​ ​​There​ ​is​ ​no​ ​inadmissible​ ​consequence​ ​if​ ​one​ ​assumes​ ​that​ ​cognition​ ​is​ ​the​ ​cause​ ​of​ ​cognition,
Dk.A​ ​11:​ ​​because​ ​there​ ​is​ ​a​ ​further​ ​cause​ ​for​ ​the​ ​continuity​ ​of​ ​a​ ​sequence​ ​of​ ​cognitions​ ​in​ ​a​ ​certain​ ​body.
Here​ ​Dharmakirti​ ​reveals​ ​his​ ​own​ ​position,​ ​which​ ​is​ ​that​ ​mental​ ​activity​ ​is​ ​a​ ​causal​ ​stream​ ​of
mental​ ​moments​ ​that​ ​have​ ​no​ ​beginning​ ​or​ ​end.
Cv.C​ ​7:​ ​​The​ ​body​ ​inhabited​ ​or​ ​governed​ ​by​ ​exhalation,​ ​inhalation,​ ​etc.,​ ​produces​ ​the​ ​cognition.
Dharmakirti​ ​then​ ​goes​ ​into​ ​a​ ​discussion​ ​of​ ​what​ ​are​ ​the​ ​restricting​ ​factors​ ​that​ ​prevent​ ​the
arising​ ​of​ ​more​ ​than​ ​one​ ​cognition​ ​at​ ​a​ ​time​ ​per​ ​body.​ ​He​ ​seems​ ​to​ ​apply​ ​a​ ​Middle​ ​Way
(​Madhyamaka​)​ ​analysis​ ​of​ ​paradoxical​ ​consequences.
Dk.C​ ​12:​ ​​Given​ ​the​ ​assumption​ ​that​ ​the​ ​body​ ​is​ ​composed​ ​of​ ​atoms​ ​(particles/parts),​ ​these​ ​parts​ ​either
produce​ ​the​ ​cognition​ ​collectively,​ ​as​ ​an​ ​aggregate,​ ​or​ ​individually,​ ​each​ ​by​ ​itself.
His​ ​way​ ​of​ ​framing​ ​exhausts​ ​all​ ​logical​ ​possibilities​ ​of​ ​how​ ​the​ ​parts​ ​could​ ​produce​ ​cognition.
Dk.A​ ​12.1:​ ​​If​ ​the​ ​parts​ ​were​ ​to​ ​produce​ ​cognition​ ​collectively​ ​then​ ​cognition​ ​would​ ​not​ ​arise​ ​when​ ​a​ ​single
part​ ​of​ ​the​ ​body​ ​is​ ​missing.
This​ ​is​ ​an​ ​absurd​ ​consequence,​ ​since​ ​it​ ​clearly​ ​does​ ​not​ ​occur.​ ​The​ ​parts​ ​could​ ​be​ ​interpreted​ ​as
atoms,​ ​bodyparts,​ ​or​ ​sensory​ ​systems,​ ​but​ ​in​ ​all​ ​instances​ ​the​ ​argument​ ​works.
Dk.A​ ​12.2:​ ​​If​ ​each​ ​individual​ ​part​ ​of​ ​the​ ​body​ ​were​ ​capable​ ​of​ ​producing​ ​cognition​ ​by​ ​itself,​ ​there​ ​would
arise​ ​as​ ​many​ ​cognitions​ ​as​ ​there​ ​are​ ​parts​ ​(or​ ​atoms)​ ​of​ ​the​ ​body.44
If​ ​each​ ​individual​ ​part​ ​could​ ​give​ ​rise​ ​to​ ​(act​ ​as​ ​the​ ​obtaining​ ​cause​ ​of)​ ​cognition​ ​they​ ​would
give​ ​rise​ ​to​ ​as​ ​many​ ​“minds”​ ​as​ ​there​ ​are​ ​parts​ ​of​ ​the​ ​body.​ ​This​ ​also​ ​an​ ​absurd​ ​consequence.​ ​We
will​ ​return​ ​to​ ​this​ ​argument​ ​in​ ​the​ ​conclusion​ ​and​ ​discussion.
Cv.C​ ​8:​ ​​The​ ​breaths​ ​are​ ​the​ ​main​ ​cause​ ​of​ ​cognition,​ ​and​ ​not​ ​every​ ​part​ ​of​ ​the​ ​body​ ​is​ ​capable​ ​of
producing​ ​a​ ​cognition.
Dk.C​ ​13:​ ​​This​ ​will​ ​not​ ​solve​ ​the​ ​problem,
Dk.A​ ​13.1:​ ​​because​ ​the​ ​fact​ ​that​ ​there​ ​are​ ​multiple​ ​breaths​ ​implies​ ​there​ ​would​ ​still​ ​be​ ​several​ ​cognitions​ ​at
the​ ​same​ ​time.
Dk.A​ ​13.2:​ ​​Even​ ​if​ ​one​ ​assumes​ ​that​ ​there​ ​is​ ​only​ ​one​ ​breath,​ ​this​ ​could​ ​not​ ​account​ ​for​ ​the​ ​gradual​ ​arising
of​ ​many​ ​cognitions​ ​during​ ​one’s​ ​lifetime,
Dharmakirti​ ​here​ ​uses​ ​a​ ​variant​ ​of​ ​the​ ​"neither​ ​one​ ​nor​ ​many"​ ​argument.
Dk.C​ ​14:​ ​​Breath​ ​cannot​ ​be​ ​restricting​ ​factor​ ​of​ ​cognition,
Dk.A​ ​14:​​ ​because​ ​many​ ​cognitions​ ​can​ ​arise​ ​during​ ​one​ ​long​ ​breath​ ​(such​ ​as​ ​looking​ ​around​ ​in​ ​a​ ​circle
while​ ​taking​ ​a​ ​deep​ ​breath).
43
​ ​Franco,​ ​​Dharmakirti​ ​on​ ​Compassion​ ​and​ ​Rebirth,​ ​​121.
44
​ ​Ibid,​ ​123.
14
Cv.A​ ​9:​ ​​If​ ​one​ ​conceives​ ​of​ ​breath​ ​as​ ​momentary​ ​one​ ​may​ ​assume​ ​that​ ​many​ ​momentary​ ​breaths​ ​are​ ​the
cause​ ​of​ ​many​ ​momentary​ ​cognitions.
Dk.C​ ​15:​ ​​This​ ​merely​ ​shifts​ ​the​ ​same​ ​problem​ ​to​ ​the​ ​breaths.
Dk.A​ ​15.1:​​ ​If​ ​the​ ​manifold​ ​cognitions​ ​arise​ ​from​ ​many​ ​gradual​ ​breaths​ ​then​ ​the​ ​breaths​ ​can​ ​only​ ​arise​ ​from
gradual​ ​causes.​ ​The​ ​body​ ​is​ ​not​ ​gradual​ ​however,​ ​and​ ​therefore​ ​cannot​ ​produce​ ​gradual​ ​breaths.
Dk.A​ ​15.2:​ ​​Nor​ ​could​ ​the​ ​previous​ ​breath​ ​cause​ ​the​ ​next​ ​one,​ ​because​ ​there​ ​is​ ​no​ ​previous​ ​breath​ ​for​ ​the
first​ ​breath​ ​in​ ​this​ ​life​ ​according​ ​to​ ​the​ ​Charvaka.
Dk.A​ ​15.3:​​ ​One​ ​cannot​ ​assume​ ​that​ ​breath​ ​is​ ​one​ ​(unitary)​ ​because​ ​it​ ​is​ ​connected​ ​with​ ​different​ ​places.
Cv.C​ ​10:​ ​​The​ ​breaths​ ​are​ ​many​ ​and​ ​they​ ​produce​ ​cognition​ ​together.
Dk.A​ ​16:​ ​​If​ ​one​ ​were​ ​to​ ​stop​ ​breathing​ ​for​ ​a​ ​moment​ ​the​ ​cognition​ ​could​ ​not​ ​arise,​ ​which​ ​clearly​ ​does​ ​not
occur.
Dk.A​ ​16.2:​ ​​One​ ​cannot​ ​say​ ​that​ ​in​ ​different​ ​situations​ ​different​ ​breaths​ ​produce​ ​cognition,​ ​because
cognition​ ​would​ ​vary​ ​according​ ​to​ ​whether​ ​it​ ​is​ ​produced​ ​by​ ​one​ ​breath​ ​or​ ​the​ ​other.45
The​ ​debate​ ​still​ ​continues,​ ​but​ ​now​ ​Dharmakirti​ ​arrives​ ​at​ ​his​ ​own​ ​philosophy​ ​of​ ​mind.​ ​He​ ​first
has​ ​to​ ​show​ ​how​ ​he​ ​avoids​ ​the​ ​inadmissible​ ​consequence​ ​that​ ​all​ ​momentary​ ​cognitions​ ​would
arise​ ​at​ ​the​ ​same​ ​time.
Dk.C​ ​17:​ ​​One​ ​cognition​ ​produces​ ​only​ ​one​ ​cognition​,
Dk.A​ ​17.1:​ ​​because​ ​its​ ​capacity​ ​is​ ​limited​.46
Dk.A​ ​17.2:​ ​​As​ ​long​ ​as​ ​one​ ​keeps​ ​looking​ ​at​ ​one​ ​object,​ ​one​ ​cannot​ ​see​ ​another​ ​object.​ ​The​ ​fact​ ​that​ ​a
cognition​ ​which​ ​could​ ​have​ ​arisen,​ ​at​ ​least​ ​in​ ​principle,​ ​does​ ​not​ ​arise,​ ​points​ ​at​ ​this​ ​restriction​.47
Dharmakirti​ ​here​ ​argues​ ​for​ ​the​ ​momentariness​ ​of​ ​mental​ ​events.​ ​His​ ​argument​ ​rests​ ​on​ ​the
limited​ ​capacity​ ​of​ ​the​ ​mind​ ​to​ ​only​ ​cognize​ ​one​ ​phenomenon​ ​at​ ​a​ ​time.​ ​The​ ​fact​ ​that​ ​several
cognitions​ ​at​ ​a​ ​time​ ​could​ ​in​ ​principle​ ​arise,​ ​but​ ​in​ ​fact​ ​do​ ​not​ ​arise,​ ​indicates​ ​an​ ​intrinsic
restriction​ ​on​ ​the​ ​cognitive​ ​capacity​ ​of​ ​the​ ​mind.​ ​Cognitive​ ​psychological​ ​research​ ​interestingly
indicates​ ​the​ ​same​ ​thing;​ ​the​ ​attentional​ ​system​ ​is​ ​only​ ​capable​ ​of​ ​attending​ ​to​ ​one​ ​thing​ ​at​ ​a
time.​ ​Multitasking​ ​turns​ ​out​ ​to​ ​be​ ​merely​ ​the​ ​rapid​ ​switching​ ​of​ ​attentional​ ​objects,​ ​which
occurs​ ​quickly​ ​enough​ ​to​ ​give​ ​the​ ​illusion​ ​of​ ​simultaneous​ ​processing.48
Cv.C​ ​11:​ ​​Although​ ​the​ ​body​ ​is​ ​capable​ ​of​ ​producing​ ​many​ ​cognitions,​ ​the​ ​cognition​ ​that​ ​arises​ ​first​ ​from
the​ ​body​ ​limits​ ​the​ ​capacity​ ​of​ ​the​ ​body​ ​to​ ​produce​ ​any​ ​further​ ​cognitions.
The​ ​opponent​ ​tries​ ​to​ ​accommodate​ ​the​ ​principle​ ​that​ ​one​ ​cognition​ ​produces​ ​only​ ​one
cognition.​ ​Franco​ ​estimates​ ​this​ ​to​ ​be​ ​a​ ​straw-man​ ​argument​ ​based​ ​on​ ​context.
Dk.C​ ​(commentator) ​ ​18:​ ​​This​ ​suggestion​ ​is​ ​unfounded.
49
Dk.A​ ​(commentator)​ ​18.1:​ ​​It​ ​would​ ​be​ ​like​ ​saying​ ​that​ ​the​ ​first​ ​moment​ ​of​ ​smoke​ ​arises​ ​from​ ​fire​ ​and​ ​then
limits​ ​the​ ​capacity​ ​of​ ​fire​ ​to​ ​produce​ ​more​ ​smoke.
Again​ ​we​ ​see​ ​a​ ​typical​ ​implementation​ ​of​ ​inferential​ ​logic​ ​on​ ​the​ ​basis​ ​of​ ​examples.
Dk.A​ ​(commentator)​ ​18.2:​ ​​Likewise​ ​the​ ​causes​ ​of​ ​the​ ​first​ ​cognition​ ​are​ ​not​ ​somehow​ ​“aware”​ ​of​ ​the​ ​fact
that​ ​cognition​ ​has​ ​been​ ​produced,​ ​and​ ​that​ ​therefore​ ​they​ ​need​ ​not​ ​keep​ ​producing​ ​it.
45
​ ​Ibid,​ ​124.
46
​ ​Skt:​ ​​Saktiniyama.
47
​ ​Ibid,​ ​125.
48
​ ​A.M.​ ​Treisman,​ ​&​ ​G.​ ​Gelade,​ ​“A​ ​feature-integration​ ​theory​ ​of​ ​attention,”​ ​​Cognitive​ ​Psychology​ ​​12(1)​ ​(1980):​ ​97-136.
49
​ ​This​ ​point​ ​was​ ​made​ ​by​ ​one​ ​of​ ​the​ ​commentators​ ​on​ ​the​ ​​Pramanavarttika;​ ​Prajnakaragupta.
15
Dharmakirti’s​ ​theory​ ​then​ ​contains​ ​several​ ​problems.​ ​One​ ​is​ ​that​ ​it​ ​cannot​ ​explain​ ​why​ ​a
cognition​ ​should​ ​be​ ​related​ ​to​ ​the​ ​body.​ ​Cognition​ ​should​ ​in​ ​principle​ ​be​ ​able​ ​to​ ​exist​ ​on​ ​its
own.​ ​Dharmakirti​ ​accepts​ ​this,​ ​and​ ​likewise​ ​most​ ​Buddhists​ ​throughout​ ​history​ ​have​ ​integrated
this​ ​aspect​ ​into​ ​their​ ​cosmology​ ​in​ ​the​ ​form​ ​of​ ​a​ ​formless​ ​realm/sphere​ ​(Skt:​ ​​Arupadhatu​)​ ​where
beings​ ​exist​ ​with​ ​exclusively​ ​mental​ ​faculties.​ ​These​ ​various​ ​spheres​ ​are​ ​also​ ​the​ ​cosmological
manifestations​ ​of​ ​phenomenological​ ​states​ ​of​ ​meditative​ ​absorption​ ​that​ ​a​ ​practitioner​ ​may
familiarize​ ​him​ ​or​ ​herself​ ​with​ ​during​ ​embodied​ ​lifetimes,​ ​which​ ​then​ ​results​ ​in​ ​such​ ​a​ ​rebirth
state.​ ​Under​ ​normal​ ​circumstances​ ​however​ ​the​ ​cognition​ ​of​ ​a​ ​being​ ​would​ ​assist​ ​the​ ​obtaining
cause​ ​of​ ​the​ ​body,​ ​and​ ​then​ ​they​ ​occur​ ​together.
Dk.C​ ​19:​ ​​The​ ​cause​ ​of​ ​the​ ​body​ ​in​ ​the​ ​next​ ​life​ ​are​ ​the​ ​five​ ​bases​ ​(five​ ​sensors).
Dharmakirti​ ​then​ ​echoes​ ​the​ ​Buddhist​ ​view​ ​that​ ​even​ ​a​ ​disembodied​ ​being​ ​in​ ​the​ ​intermediate
state​ ​(​antarabhava​)​ ​after​ ​death​ ​possesses​ ​five​ ​sensors,​ ​albeit​ ​in​ ​a​ ​very​ ​subtle​ ​form​ ​that​ ​is
produced​ ​by​ ​the​ ​mind,​ ​quite​ ​like​ ​the​ ​sensors​ ​one​ ​possesses​ ​in​ ​dreams.50
Cv.C​ ​12:​ ​​Neither​ ​the​ ​formless​ ​spheres​ ​nor​ ​the​ ​five​ ​senses​ ​(in​ ​the​ ​intermediate​ ​state)​ ​are​ ​observed​ ​by
anyone,​ ​nor​ ​are​ ​the​ ​five​ ​senses​ ​seen​ ​to​ ​produce​ ​a​ ​new​ ​body​ ​after​ ​death.
Cv.A​ ​12:​ ​​Therefore​ ​there​ ​is​ ​no​ ​causal​ ​relation​ ​between​ ​them.
Dk.A​ ​20:​ ​​Non-observation​ ​does​ ​not​ ​imply​ ​non-existence.
Dharmakirti​ ​makes​ ​the​ ​epistemological​ ​point​ ​that​ ​mere​ ​non-observation​ ​of​ ​something​ ​does​ ​not
establish​ ​its​ ​non-existence​ ​or​ ​non-occurrence,​ ​and​ ​therefore​ ​is​ ​not​ ​a​ ​valid​ ​inference.​ ​There​ ​are
obviously​ ​innumerable​ ​subtle​ ​features​ ​of​ ​the​ ​world​ ​that​ ​are​ ​not​ ​accessible​ ​to​ ​superficial
perception.​ ​Dignaga​ ​therefore​ ​included​ ​yogic​ ​(extrasensory)​ ​perception,​ ​acquired​ ​through
decades​ ​of​ ​rigorous​ ​meditative​ ​training,​ ​as​ ​a​ ​valid​ ​means​ ​of​ ​knowing​ ​such​ ​subtle​ ​features,​ ​yet
this​ ​can​ ​hardly​ ​function​ ​as​ ​a​ ​means​ ​of​ ​knowledge​ ​in​ ​this​ ​context.​ ​In​ ​recent​ ​decades​ ​however,
multidisciplinary​ ​research​ ​has​ ​delivered​ ​empirical​ ​data​ ​of​ ​causally​ ​effective​ ​and​ ​functionally
independent​ ​mental​ ​phenomena,​ ​including​ ​disembodied​ ​sensory​ ​perception. ​ ​Especially​ ​the
51
“near​ ​death​ ​experience”​ ​(NDE)​ ​research​ ​of​ ​Pim​ ​van​ ​Lommel​ ​(and​ ​Bruce​ ​Greyson)​ ​has​ ​presented
convincing​ ​empirical​ ​data​ ​of​ ​mental​ ​activity,​ ​including​ ​corroborated​ ​sensory​ ​perception,
functioning​ ​independently​ ​of​ ​brain​ ​activity.​ ​In​ ​Pim​ ​van​ ​Lommel’s​ ​long-term​ ​study​ ​the
explanations​ ​of​ ​said​ ​phenomena​ ​that​ ​had​ ​previously​ ​been​ ​put​ ​forward​ ​by​ ​sceptics,​ ​such​ ​as
oxygen-deprivation​ ​(​anoxia​),​ ​narcotics,​ ​and​ ​psychological​ ​disposition,​ ​could​ ​be​ ​positively​ ​ruled
out​ ​as​ ​relevant​ ​factors. ​ ​No​ ​one​ ​has​ ​so​ ​far​ ​been​ ​able​ ​to​ ​conclusively​ ​disprove​ ​these​ ​findings,
52
which​ ​suggests​ ​that​ ​Dharmakirti’s​ ​claim​ ​of​ ​disembodied​ ​sense​ ​perception​ ​actually​ ​has​ ​an
empirical​ ​basis​ ​in​ ​reality.
Cv.C​ ​13:​ ​​The​ ​senses​ ​do​ ​not​ ​link​ ​to​ ​another​ ​life,
Cv.A​ ​13:​ ​​because​ ​they​ ​are​ ​senses,​ ​just​ ​as​ ​the​ ​senses​ ​of​ ​one​ ​person​ ​do​ ​not​ ​link​ ​to​ ​the​ ​senses​ ​of​ ​another.
Dk.C​ ​21:​ ​​The​ ​reason​ ​is​ ​not​ ​conclusive​ ​(Skt:​ ​sesavat).
50
​ ​Robert​ ​Thurman,​ ​​The​ ​Tibetan​ ​Book​ ​of​ ​the​ ​Dead:​ ​Liberation​ ​through​ ​Understanding​ ​in​ ​the​ ​Between,​ ​​Random​ ​House
Publishing​ ​Group,​ ​2011.​ ​255.
51
​ ​Probably​ ​the​ ​most​ ​significant​ ​compendium​ ​of​ ​empirical​ ​research​ ​indicating​ ​the​ ​irreducibility,​ ​functional
independence,​ ​and​ ​causal​ ​efficacy​ ​of​ ​mental​ ​phenomena,​ ​see:​ ​Edward​ ​F.​ ​Kelly​ ​et​ ​al.,​ ​​Irreducible​ ​Mind:​ ​Toward​ ​a
Psychology​ ​for​ ​the​ ​21st​ ​Century,​​ ​Rowman​ ​and​ ​Littlefield​ ​Publishers,​ ​2009.
52
​ ​Pim​ ​van​ ​Lommel,​ ​​Eindeloos​ ​Bewustzijn:​ ​Een​ ​Wetenschappelijke​ ​Visie​ ​op​ ​de​ ​Bijna-Dood​ ​Ervaring.​ ​​Utrecht:​ ​Uitgeverij​ ​Ten
Have,​ ​2012.​ ​H6​ ​(144-146),​ ​H7​ ​(169-171),​ ​H8​ ​(189-191).
16
Dharmakirti_and_Thomas_Nagel_on_the_Orig.pdf
Dharmakirti_and_Thomas_Nagel_on_the_Orig.pdf
Dharmakirti_and_Thomas_Nagel_on_the_Orig.pdf
Dharmakirti_and_Thomas_Nagel_on_the_Orig.pdf
Dharmakirti_and_Thomas_Nagel_on_the_Orig.pdf
Dharmakirti_and_Thomas_Nagel_on_the_Orig.pdf
Dharmakirti_and_Thomas_Nagel_on_the_Orig.pdf
Dharmakirti_and_Thomas_Nagel_on_the_Orig.pdf
Dharmakirti_and_Thomas_Nagel_on_the_Orig.pdf
Dharmakirti_and_Thomas_Nagel_on_the_Orig.pdf
Dharmakirti_and_Thomas_Nagel_on_the_Orig.pdf
Dharmakirti_and_Thomas_Nagel_on_the_Orig.pdf
Dharmakirti_and_Thomas_Nagel_on_the_Orig.pdf
Dharmakirti_and_Thomas_Nagel_on_the_Orig.pdf
Dharmakirti_and_Thomas_Nagel_on_the_Orig.pdf

More Related Content

Recently uploaded

The Enchantment and Shadows_ Unveiling the Mysteries of Magic and Black Magic...
The Enchantment and Shadows_ Unveiling the Mysteries of Magic and Black Magic...The Enchantment and Shadows_ Unveiling the Mysteries of Magic and Black Magic...
The Enchantment and Shadows_ Unveiling the Mysteries of Magic and Black Magic...
Phoenix O
 
The Hope of Salvation - Jude 1:24-25 - Message
The Hope of Salvation - Jude 1:24-25 - MessageThe Hope of Salvation - Jude 1:24-25 - Message
The Hope of Salvation - Jude 1:24-25 - Message
Cole Hartman
 
How to Stop a Divorce and Save Your Marriage: Divorce Spells That Really Work...
How to Stop a Divorce and Save Your Marriage: Divorce Spells That Really Work...How to Stop a Divorce and Save Your Marriage: Divorce Spells That Really Work...
How to Stop a Divorce and Save Your Marriage: Divorce Spells That Really Work...
Traditional Healer, Love Spells Caster and Money Spells That Work Fast
 
The_Chronological_Life_of_Christ_Part_104_Repentance_and_Restoration
The_Chronological_Life_of_Christ_Part_104_Repentance_and_RestorationThe_Chronological_Life_of_Christ_Part_104_Repentance_and_Restoration
The_Chronological_Life_of_Christ_Part_104_Repentance_and_Restoration
Network Bible Fellowship
 
A Free eBook ~ Valuable LIFE Lessons to Learn ( 5 Sets of Presentations)...
A Free eBook ~ Valuable LIFE Lessons    to Learn   ( 5 Sets of Presentations)...A Free eBook ~ Valuable LIFE Lessons    to Learn   ( 5 Sets of Presentations)...
A Free eBook ~ Valuable LIFE Lessons to Learn ( 5 Sets of Presentations)...
OH TEIK BIN
 
Kala jadu (black magic) expert,Black magic specialist in Dubai vashikaran spe...
Kala jadu (black magic) expert,Black magic specialist in Dubai vashikaran spe...Kala jadu (black magic) expert,Black magic specialist in Dubai vashikaran spe...
Kala jadu (black magic) expert,Black magic specialist in Dubai vashikaran spe...
makhmalhalaaay
 
Important places of Vrindavan-Braj Mandal Parikrama .pptx
Important places of Vrindavan-Braj Mandal Parikrama .pptxImportant places of Vrindavan-Braj Mandal Parikrama .pptx
Important places of Vrindavan-Braj Mandal Parikrama .pptx
ShyamSundar991228
 
A375 Example Taste the taste of the Lord, the taste of the Lord The taste of...
A375 Example Taste the taste of the Lord,  the taste of the Lord The taste of...A375 Example Taste the taste of the Lord,  the taste of the Lord The taste of...
A375 Example Taste the taste of the Lord, the taste of the Lord The taste of...
franktsao4
 
312 A Wise Woman of Abel Beth Maakah Saves The Town
312 A Wise Woman of Abel Beth Maakah Saves The Town312 A Wise Woman of Abel Beth Maakah Saves The Town
312 A Wise Woman of Abel Beth Maakah Saves The Town
Rick Peterson
 
Deerfoot Church of Christ Bulletin 6 16 24
Deerfoot Church of Christ Bulletin 6 16 24Deerfoot Church of Christ Bulletin 6 16 24
Deerfoot Church of Christ Bulletin 6 16 24
deerfootcoc
 
English - The Book of Ruth - King James Bible.pdf
English - The Book of Ruth - King James Bible.pdfEnglish - The Book of Ruth - King James Bible.pdf
English - The Book of Ruth - King James Bible.pdf
Filipino Tracts and Literature Society Inc.
 
快速办理(PU毕业证书)普渡大学毕业证文凭证书一模一样
快速办理(PU毕业证书)普渡大学毕业证文凭证书一模一样快速办理(PU毕业证书)普渡大学毕业证文凭证书一模一样
快速办理(PU毕业证书)普渡大学毕业证文凭证书一模一样
cfk7atz3
 
Sanatan Vastu | Experience Great Living | Vastu Expert
Sanatan Vastu | Experience Great Living | Vastu ExpertSanatan Vastu | Experience Great Living | Vastu Expert
Sanatan Vastu | Experience Great Living | Vastu Expert
Sanatan Vastu
 

Recently uploaded (13)

The Enchantment and Shadows_ Unveiling the Mysteries of Magic and Black Magic...
The Enchantment and Shadows_ Unveiling the Mysteries of Magic and Black Magic...The Enchantment and Shadows_ Unveiling the Mysteries of Magic and Black Magic...
The Enchantment and Shadows_ Unveiling the Mysteries of Magic and Black Magic...
 
The Hope of Salvation - Jude 1:24-25 - Message
The Hope of Salvation - Jude 1:24-25 - MessageThe Hope of Salvation - Jude 1:24-25 - Message
The Hope of Salvation - Jude 1:24-25 - Message
 
How to Stop a Divorce and Save Your Marriage: Divorce Spells That Really Work...
How to Stop a Divorce and Save Your Marriage: Divorce Spells That Really Work...How to Stop a Divorce and Save Your Marriage: Divorce Spells That Really Work...
How to Stop a Divorce and Save Your Marriage: Divorce Spells That Really Work...
 
The_Chronological_Life_of_Christ_Part_104_Repentance_and_Restoration
The_Chronological_Life_of_Christ_Part_104_Repentance_and_RestorationThe_Chronological_Life_of_Christ_Part_104_Repentance_and_Restoration
The_Chronological_Life_of_Christ_Part_104_Repentance_and_Restoration
 
A Free eBook ~ Valuable LIFE Lessons to Learn ( 5 Sets of Presentations)...
A Free eBook ~ Valuable LIFE Lessons    to Learn   ( 5 Sets of Presentations)...A Free eBook ~ Valuable LIFE Lessons    to Learn   ( 5 Sets of Presentations)...
A Free eBook ~ Valuable LIFE Lessons to Learn ( 5 Sets of Presentations)...
 
Kala jadu (black magic) expert,Black magic specialist in Dubai vashikaran spe...
Kala jadu (black magic) expert,Black magic specialist in Dubai vashikaran spe...Kala jadu (black magic) expert,Black magic specialist in Dubai vashikaran spe...
Kala jadu (black magic) expert,Black magic specialist in Dubai vashikaran spe...
 
Important places of Vrindavan-Braj Mandal Parikrama .pptx
Important places of Vrindavan-Braj Mandal Parikrama .pptxImportant places of Vrindavan-Braj Mandal Parikrama .pptx
Important places of Vrindavan-Braj Mandal Parikrama .pptx
 
A375 Example Taste the taste of the Lord, the taste of the Lord The taste of...
A375 Example Taste the taste of the Lord,  the taste of the Lord The taste of...A375 Example Taste the taste of the Lord,  the taste of the Lord The taste of...
A375 Example Taste the taste of the Lord, the taste of the Lord The taste of...
 
312 A Wise Woman of Abel Beth Maakah Saves The Town
312 A Wise Woman of Abel Beth Maakah Saves The Town312 A Wise Woman of Abel Beth Maakah Saves The Town
312 A Wise Woman of Abel Beth Maakah Saves The Town
 
Deerfoot Church of Christ Bulletin 6 16 24
Deerfoot Church of Christ Bulletin 6 16 24Deerfoot Church of Christ Bulletin 6 16 24
Deerfoot Church of Christ Bulletin 6 16 24
 
English - The Book of Ruth - King James Bible.pdf
English - The Book of Ruth - King James Bible.pdfEnglish - The Book of Ruth - King James Bible.pdf
English - The Book of Ruth - King James Bible.pdf
 
快速办理(PU毕业证书)普渡大学毕业证文凭证书一模一样
快速办理(PU毕业证书)普渡大学毕业证文凭证书一模一样快速办理(PU毕业证书)普渡大学毕业证文凭证书一模一样
快速办理(PU毕业证书)普渡大学毕业证文凭证书一模一样
 
Sanatan Vastu | Experience Great Living | Vastu Expert
Sanatan Vastu | Experience Great Living | Vastu ExpertSanatan Vastu | Experience Great Living | Vastu Expert
Sanatan Vastu | Experience Great Living | Vastu Expert
 

Featured

2024 State of Marketing Report – by Hubspot
2024 State of Marketing Report – by Hubspot2024 State of Marketing Report – by Hubspot
2024 State of Marketing Report – by Hubspot
Marius Sescu
 
Everything You Need To Know About ChatGPT
Everything You Need To Know About ChatGPTEverything You Need To Know About ChatGPT
Everything You Need To Know About ChatGPT
Expeed Software
 
Product Design Trends in 2024 | Teenage Engineerings
Product Design Trends in 2024 | Teenage EngineeringsProduct Design Trends in 2024 | Teenage Engineerings
Product Design Trends in 2024 | Teenage Engineerings
Pixeldarts
 
How Race, Age and Gender Shape Attitudes Towards Mental Health
How Race, Age and Gender Shape Attitudes Towards Mental HealthHow Race, Age and Gender Shape Attitudes Towards Mental Health
How Race, Age and Gender Shape Attitudes Towards Mental Health
ThinkNow
 
AI Trends in Creative Operations 2024 by Artwork Flow.pdf
AI Trends in Creative Operations 2024 by Artwork Flow.pdfAI Trends in Creative Operations 2024 by Artwork Flow.pdf
AI Trends in Creative Operations 2024 by Artwork Flow.pdf
marketingartwork
 
Skeleton Culture Code
Skeleton Culture CodeSkeleton Culture Code
Skeleton Culture Code
Skeleton Technologies
 
PEPSICO Presentation to CAGNY Conference Feb 2024
PEPSICO Presentation to CAGNY Conference Feb 2024PEPSICO Presentation to CAGNY Conference Feb 2024
PEPSICO Presentation to CAGNY Conference Feb 2024
Neil Kimberley
 
Content Methodology: A Best Practices Report (Webinar)
Content Methodology: A Best Practices Report (Webinar)Content Methodology: A Best Practices Report (Webinar)
Content Methodology: A Best Practices Report (Webinar)
contently
 
How to Prepare For a Successful Job Search for 2024
How to Prepare For a Successful Job Search for 2024How to Prepare For a Successful Job Search for 2024
How to Prepare For a Successful Job Search for 2024
Albert Qian
 
Social Media Marketing Trends 2024 // The Global Indie Insights
Social Media Marketing Trends 2024 // The Global Indie InsightsSocial Media Marketing Trends 2024 // The Global Indie Insights
Social Media Marketing Trends 2024 // The Global Indie Insights
Kurio // The Social Media Age(ncy)
 
Trends In Paid Search: Navigating The Digital Landscape In 2024
Trends In Paid Search: Navigating The Digital Landscape In 2024Trends In Paid Search: Navigating The Digital Landscape In 2024
Trends In Paid Search: Navigating The Digital Landscape In 2024
Search Engine Journal
 
5 Public speaking tips from TED - Visualized summary
5 Public speaking tips from TED - Visualized summary5 Public speaking tips from TED - Visualized summary
5 Public speaking tips from TED - Visualized summary
SpeakerHub
 
ChatGPT and the Future of Work - Clark Boyd
ChatGPT and the Future of Work - Clark Boyd ChatGPT and the Future of Work - Clark Boyd
ChatGPT and the Future of Work - Clark Boyd
Clark Boyd
 
Getting into the tech field. what next
Getting into the tech field. what next Getting into the tech field. what next
Getting into the tech field. what next
Tessa Mero
 
Google's Just Not That Into You: Understanding Core Updates & Search Intent
Google's Just Not That Into You: Understanding Core Updates & Search IntentGoogle's Just Not That Into You: Understanding Core Updates & Search Intent
Google's Just Not That Into You: Understanding Core Updates & Search Intent
Lily Ray
 
How to have difficult conversations
How to have difficult conversations How to have difficult conversations
How to have difficult conversations
Rajiv Jayarajah, MAppComm, ACC
 
Introduction to Data Science
Introduction to Data ScienceIntroduction to Data Science
Introduction to Data Science
Christy Abraham Joy
 
Time Management & Productivity - Best Practices
Time Management & Productivity -  Best PracticesTime Management & Productivity -  Best Practices
Time Management & Productivity - Best Practices
Vit Horky
 
The six step guide to practical project management
The six step guide to practical project managementThe six step guide to practical project management
The six step guide to practical project management
MindGenius
 
Beginners Guide to TikTok for Search - Rachel Pearson - We are Tilt __ Bright...
Beginners Guide to TikTok for Search - Rachel Pearson - We are Tilt __ Bright...Beginners Guide to TikTok for Search - Rachel Pearson - We are Tilt __ Bright...
Beginners Guide to TikTok for Search - Rachel Pearson - We are Tilt __ Bright...
RachelPearson36
 

Featured (20)

2024 State of Marketing Report – by Hubspot
2024 State of Marketing Report – by Hubspot2024 State of Marketing Report – by Hubspot
2024 State of Marketing Report – by Hubspot
 
Everything You Need To Know About ChatGPT
Everything You Need To Know About ChatGPTEverything You Need To Know About ChatGPT
Everything You Need To Know About ChatGPT
 
Product Design Trends in 2024 | Teenage Engineerings
Product Design Trends in 2024 | Teenage EngineeringsProduct Design Trends in 2024 | Teenage Engineerings
Product Design Trends in 2024 | Teenage Engineerings
 
How Race, Age and Gender Shape Attitudes Towards Mental Health
How Race, Age and Gender Shape Attitudes Towards Mental HealthHow Race, Age and Gender Shape Attitudes Towards Mental Health
How Race, Age and Gender Shape Attitudes Towards Mental Health
 
AI Trends in Creative Operations 2024 by Artwork Flow.pdf
AI Trends in Creative Operations 2024 by Artwork Flow.pdfAI Trends in Creative Operations 2024 by Artwork Flow.pdf
AI Trends in Creative Operations 2024 by Artwork Flow.pdf
 
Skeleton Culture Code
Skeleton Culture CodeSkeleton Culture Code
Skeleton Culture Code
 
PEPSICO Presentation to CAGNY Conference Feb 2024
PEPSICO Presentation to CAGNY Conference Feb 2024PEPSICO Presentation to CAGNY Conference Feb 2024
PEPSICO Presentation to CAGNY Conference Feb 2024
 
Content Methodology: A Best Practices Report (Webinar)
Content Methodology: A Best Practices Report (Webinar)Content Methodology: A Best Practices Report (Webinar)
Content Methodology: A Best Practices Report (Webinar)
 
How to Prepare For a Successful Job Search for 2024
How to Prepare For a Successful Job Search for 2024How to Prepare For a Successful Job Search for 2024
How to Prepare For a Successful Job Search for 2024
 
Social Media Marketing Trends 2024 // The Global Indie Insights
Social Media Marketing Trends 2024 // The Global Indie InsightsSocial Media Marketing Trends 2024 // The Global Indie Insights
Social Media Marketing Trends 2024 // The Global Indie Insights
 
Trends In Paid Search: Navigating The Digital Landscape In 2024
Trends In Paid Search: Navigating The Digital Landscape In 2024Trends In Paid Search: Navigating The Digital Landscape In 2024
Trends In Paid Search: Navigating The Digital Landscape In 2024
 
5 Public speaking tips from TED - Visualized summary
5 Public speaking tips from TED - Visualized summary5 Public speaking tips from TED - Visualized summary
5 Public speaking tips from TED - Visualized summary
 
ChatGPT and the Future of Work - Clark Boyd
ChatGPT and the Future of Work - Clark Boyd ChatGPT and the Future of Work - Clark Boyd
ChatGPT and the Future of Work - Clark Boyd
 
Getting into the tech field. what next
Getting into the tech field. what next Getting into the tech field. what next
Getting into the tech field. what next
 
Google's Just Not That Into You: Understanding Core Updates & Search Intent
Google's Just Not That Into You: Understanding Core Updates & Search IntentGoogle's Just Not That Into You: Understanding Core Updates & Search Intent
Google's Just Not That Into You: Understanding Core Updates & Search Intent
 
How to have difficult conversations
How to have difficult conversations How to have difficult conversations
How to have difficult conversations
 
Introduction to Data Science
Introduction to Data ScienceIntroduction to Data Science
Introduction to Data Science
 
Time Management & Productivity - Best Practices
Time Management & Productivity -  Best PracticesTime Management & Productivity -  Best Practices
Time Management & Productivity - Best Practices
 
The six step guide to practical project management
The six step guide to practical project managementThe six step guide to practical project management
The six step guide to practical project management
 
Beginners Guide to TikTok for Search - Rachel Pearson - We are Tilt __ Bright...
Beginners Guide to TikTok for Search - Rachel Pearson - We are Tilt __ Bright...Beginners Guide to TikTok for Search - Rachel Pearson - We are Tilt __ Bright...
Beginners Guide to TikTok for Search - Rachel Pearson - We are Tilt __ Bright...
 

Dharmakirti_and_Thomas_Nagel_on_the_Orig.pdf

  • 1. Dharmakirti​ ​and​ ​Thomas​ ​Nagel on​ ​the​ ​Origin​ ​of​ ​Mental​ ​Activity Submitted​ ​by:​ ​Timo​ ​Pieters​ ​(Vrije​ ​Universiteit) Submitted​ ​to:​ ​Victor​ ​van​ ​Bijlert​ ​(Vrije​ ​Universiteit) and​ ​Henk​ ​Blezer​ ​(Leiden​ ​University) Date​ ​of​ ​submission:​ ​4th​ ​of​ ​August,​ ​2017 BA:​ ​Religiewetenschappen,​ ​traject​ ​Boeddhisme Word​ ​count:​ ​13.483 Final​ ​Thesis​ ​submitted​ ​in​ ​partial​ ​fulfilment​ ​of​ ​the​ ​requirements for​ ​the​ ​degree​ ​of​ ​Bachelor​ ​of​ ​Arts 1
  • 2. Verklaring​ ​van​ ​originaliteit Hierbij​ ​verklaar​ ​ik​ ​dat​ ​deze​ ​scriptie​ ​een​ ​origineel​ ​werk​ ​is.​ ​De​ ​scriptie​ ​is​ ​het​ ​resultaat​ ​van​ ​mijn eigen​ ​onderzoek​ ​en​ ​is​ ​alleen​ ​door​ ​mijzelf​ ​geschreven,​ ​tenzij​ ​anders​ ​aangegeven.​ ​Als​ ​informatie en​ ​ideeën​ ​uit​ ​andere​ ​bronnen​ ​zijn​ ​overgenomen,​ ​wordt​ ​dat​ ​expliciet​ ​en​ ​volledig​ ​vermeld​ ​in​ ​de tekst​ ​of​ ​in​ ​de​ ​noten.​ ​Een​ ​bibliografie​ ​is​ ​bijgevoegd. Plaats​ ​en​ ​datum: Handtekening: Arnhem,​ ​Nederland​ ​(08-08-2017) Verklaring​ ​van​ ​goedkeuring Hierbij​ ​stem​ ​ik​ ​ermee​ ​in​ ​dat​ ​mijn​ ​scriptie​ ​na​ ​goedkeuring​ ​beschikbaar​ ​wordt​ ​gesteld​ ​voor vermenigvuldiging​ ​en​ ​interbibliothecair​ ​leenverkeer,​ ​en​ ​dat​ ​de​ ​titel​ ​en​ ​samenvatting beschikbaar​ ​worden​ ​gesteld​ ​voor​ ​externe​ ​organisaties​ ​en​ ​door​ ​de​ ​Vrije​ ​Universiteit​ ​mogen worden​ ​gepubliceerd. Plaats​ ​en​ ​datum: ​ ​​ ​​ ​​ ​​ ​​ ​​ ​​ ​​ ​Handtekening: Arnhem,​ ​Nederland​ ​(08-08-2017) Introduction It​ ​is​ ​assumed​ ​by​ ​many​ ​that​ ​the​ ​nature​ ​and​ ​origin​ ​of​ ​the​ ​mind​ ​are​ ​fully​ ​understood​ ​in​ ​our​ ​current age.​ ​Our​ ​ancestors​ ​might​ ​have​ ​been​ ​rather​ ​preoccupied​ ​with​ ​where​ ​it​ ​came​ ​from,​ ​what​ ​it​ ​is,​ ​and where​ ​it​ ​might​ ​go​ ​(either​ ​dogmatically​ ​or​ ​philosophically),​ ​but​ ​today​ ​we​ ​are​ ​no​ ​longer​ ​“in​ ​the dark”.​ ​Ever​ ​since​ ​the​ ​Enlightenment​ ​eurocentric​ ​civilization​ ​has​ ​been​ ​shedding​ ​it’s​ ​brilliant, rational​ ​light​ ​on​ ​all​ ​phenomena​ ​shrouded​ ​in​ ​the​ ​darkness​ ​of​ ​dogmatic​ ​and​ ​mythological antiquity,​ ​and​ ​has​ ​separated​ ​the​ ​wheat​ ​from​ ​the​ ​chaff.​ ​By​ ​the​ ​sheer​ ​passage​ ​of​ ​time​ ​we​ ​have drifted​ ​closer​ ​and​ ​closer​ ​to​ ​a​ ​truly​ ​objective​ ​appreciation​ ​of​ ​reality​ ​as​ ​it​ ​is.​ ​We​ ​now​ ​know​ ​reality to​ ​be​ ​mere​ ​matter,​ ​which​ ​means​ ​that​ ​objective​ ​reality​ ​is​ ​largely​ ​devoid​ ​of​ ​“what​ ​matters”:​ ​value, meaning,​ ​purpose,​ ​and​ ​the​ ​mind​ ​that​ ​perceives​ ​“what​ ​matters”.​ ​These​ ​things​ ​in​ ​fact​ ​only​ ​exist within​ ​the​ ​confines​ ​of​ ​human​ ​skulls,​ ​encapsulated​ ​in​ ​the​ ​intricately​ ​complex​ ​configurations​ ​of nerve​ ​cells​ ​that​ ​constitute​ ​the​ ​very​ ​locus​ ​of​ ​our​ ​being:​ ​the​ ​brain.​ ​Our​ ​subjective​ ​experience​ ​of​ ​life is​ ​for​ ​all​ ​intents​ ​and​ ​purposes​ ​a​ ​virtual​ ​reality​ ​simulation,​ ​running​ ​on​ ​the​ ​electrochemical hardware​ ​of​ ​our​ ​neural​ ​circuits.​ ​The​ ​objective​ ​in​ ​this​ ​simulation​ ​is​ ​to​ ​ensure​ ​the​ ​survival​ ​of​ ​the organism​ ​long​ ​enough​ ​so​ ​that​ ​it​ ​can​ ​pass​ ​on​ ​its​ ​genetic​ ​material,​ ​safeguarding​ ​its​ ​continuity 2
  • 3. above​ ​all​ ​else.​ ​Aside​ ​from​ ​the​ ​obvious​ ​sarcasm​ ​with​ ​which​ ​I​ ​have​ ​just​ ​narrated​ ​this​ ​story,​ ​it actually​ ​represents​ ​an​ ​accurate​ ​portrayal​ ​of​ ​the​ ​narrative​ ​that​ ​I​ ​was​ ​taught​ ​throughout​ ​my primary​ ​and​ ​secondary​ ​schooling,​ ​not​ ​just​ ​about​ ​the​ ​history​ ​of​ ​human​ ​knowledge,​ ​but​ ​more importantly​ ​about​ ​the​ ​nature​ ​of​ ​objective​ ​and​ ​subjective​ ​reality​ ​(mind).​ ​The​ ​most​ ​pernicious thing​ ​I​ ​learned​ ​was​ ​that​ ​“we”​ ​had​ ​already​ ​figured​ ​it​ ​out.​ ​There​ ​is​ ​nothing​ ​more​ ​to​ ​learn​ ​about the​ ​mind;​ ​it​ ​is​ ​basically​ ​caused​ ​by​ ​(or​ ​identical​ ​with)​ ​brain​ ​activity,​ ​so​ ​when​ ​you​ ​die​ ​it​ ​is​ ​simply “lights​ ​out”.​ ​Your​ ​consciousness​ ​ceases​ ​to​ ​exist.​ ​After​ ​considerable​ ​research​ ​it​ ​dawned​ ​on​ ​me​ ​that this​ ​might​ ​in​ ​fact​ ​be​ ​an​ ​unproven​ ​assumption​ ​that​ ​nevertheless​ ​had​ ​far-reaching​ ​consequences when​ ​held.​ ​That​ ​is​ ​not​ ​to​ ​say​ ​that​ ​there​ ​is​ ​no​ ​reason​ ​to​ ​think​ ​this​ ​assumption​ ​might​ ​be​ ​true,​ ​but just​ ​that​ ​the​ ​assumption​ ​has​ ​never​ ​actually​ ​been​ ​proven​ ​correct​ ​scientifically.​ ​During​ ​my freshman​ ​year​ ​in​ ​university​ ​it​ ​dawned​ ​on​ ​me​ ​that​ ​the​ ​way​ ​one​ ​views​ ​the​ ​origin​ ​of​ ​the​ ​mind determines​ ​one’s​ ​entire​ ​orientation​ ​towards​ ​life;​ ​it​ ​is​ ​not​ ​just​ ​an​ ​isolated​ ​fact-bit​ ​sitting​ ​in​ ​the background.​ ​If​ ​one​ ​truly​ ​thinks​ ​that​ ​one’s​ ​mind​ ​equals​ ​electrical​ ​activity​ ​in​ ​the​ ​brain​ ​then indeed​ ​the​ ​way​ ​of​ ​life​ ​that​ ​follows​ ​from​ ​this​ ​worldview​ ​could​ ​easily​ ​be​ ​hedonistic,​ ​that​ ​is​ ​to​ ​say; exclusively​ ​maximizing​ ​sensory​ ​pleasure,​ ​survival,​ ​and​ ​procreation.​ ​This​ ​is​ ​not​ ​to​ ​say​ ​that​ ​one will​ ​live​ ​an​ ​unethical​ ​or​ ​meaningless​ ​life,​ ​but​ ​that​ ​such​ ​a​ ​worldview​ ​does​ ​not​ ​warrant​ ​those dimensions​ ​of​ ​life​ ​necessarily.​ ​I​ ​will​ ​define​ ​“mind”​ ​throughout​ ​this​ ​thesis​ ​as​ ​the​ ​individual, mental​ ​activity​ ​of​ ​subjective​ ​experiencing,​ ​or​ ​“mental​ ​activity”​ ​for​ ​short.​ ​Given​ ​the aforementioned​ ​relevance​ ​of​ ​the​ ​question​ ​where​ ​mental​ ​activity​ ​comes​ ​from,​ ​and​ ​the​ ​likelihood that​ ​we​ ​do​ ​not​ ​fully​ ​understand​ ​the​ ​answer​ ​to​ ​this​ ​question​ ​yet,​ ​I​ ​will​ ​explore​ ​two​ ​main​ ​thinkers that​ ​have​ ​seriously​ ​considered​ ​it.​ ​The​ ​first​ ​will​ ​be​ ​Dharmakirti,​ ​a​ ​Buddhist​ ​logician​ ​from​ ​the 6th-7th​ ​century​ ​in​ ​India.​ ​The​ ​second​ ​is​ ​Thomas​ ​Nagel,​ ​who​ ​became​ ​renowned​ ​for​ ​his​ ​paper “What​ ​Is​ ​it​ ​Like​ ​to​ ​Be​ ​a​ ​Bat?”​ ​in​ ​which​ ​he​ ​explored​ ​the​ ​phenomenological​ ​character​ ​of consciousness. ​ ​Both​ ​of​ ​these​ ​thinkers​ ​present​ ​a​ ​remarkably​ ​convincing​ ​critique​ ​of​ ​a​ ​range​ ​of 1 theories​ ​that​ ​can​ ​be​ ​characterized​ ​as​ ​“psychophysical​ ​reductionism”,​ ​or​ ​the​ ​idea​ ​that​ ​subjective states​ ​of​ ​consciousness​ ​are​ ​caused​ ​by​ ​or​ ​identical​ ​with​ ​physical​ ​phenomena​ ​(in​ ​the​ ​body).​ ​In spite​ ​of​ ​the​ ​more​ ​than​ ​1400​ ​years​ ​between​ ​them​ ​they​ ​also​ ​seem​ ​to​ ​use​ ​strikingly​ ​similar arguments.​ ​The​ ​main​ ​question​ ​for​ ​this​ ​thesis​ ​therefore​ ​is:​ ​“What​ ​are​ ​the​ ​relevant​ ​implications​ ​of Dharmakirti’s​ ​arguments​ ​(found​ ​in​ ​his​ ​​Pramanavarttika​)​ ​concerning​ ​the​ ​origin​ ​of​ ​mental​ ​activity for​ ​the​ ​contemporary​ ​philosophical​ ​discussion​ ​(as​ ​articulated​ ​by​ ​Thomas​ ​Nagel​ ​in​ ​his​ ​​Mind​ ​and Cosmos​)​ ​about​ ​the​ ​origin​ ​of​ ​mental​ ​activity?”​ ​The​ ​structure​ ​of​ ​the​ ​thesis​ ​will​ ​be​ ​subdivided​ ​into the​ ​following​ ​questions: 1.1:​ ​What​ ​are​ ​the​ ​fundamental​ ​philosophical​ ​premises​ ​of​ ​Dharmakirti’s​ ​opponent? 1.2:​ ​What​ ​is​ ​the​ ​epistemological​ ​context​ ​for​ ​Dharmakirti’s​ ​philosophy​ ​of​ ​mind? 1.3:​ ​What​ ​are​ ​Dharmakirti’s​ ​arguments​ ​against​ ​his​ ​opponent’s​ ​physicalist​ ​philosophy​ ​of​ ​mind? 1.4:​ ​What​ ​are​ ​the​ ​cosmological​ ​implications​ ​of​ ​Dharmakirti’s​ ​philosophy​ ​of​ ​mind? 2.1:​ ​What​ ​are​ ​the​ ​fundamental​ ​premises​ ​of​ ​psychophysical​ ​reductionism? 2.2:​ ​What​ ​is​ ​the​ ​epistemological​ ​context​ ​for​ ​Thomas​ ​Nagel’s​ ​philosophy​ ​of​ ​mind? 2.3:​ ​What​ ​are​ ​Thomas​ ​Nagel’s​ ​arguments​ ​against​ ​psychophysical​ ​reductionism? 2.4:​ ​What​ ​are​ ​the​ ​cosmological​ ​implications​ ​of​ ​Thomas​ ​Nagel’s​ ​anti-reductionist​ ​philosophy​ ​of​ ​mind? 1 ​ ​​Thomas​ ​Nagel,​ ​"What​ ​Is​ ​It​ ​Like​ ​to​ ​Be​ ​a​ ​Bat?"​ ​​The​ ​Philosophical​ ​Review​​ ​83,​ ​no.​ ​4​ ​(1974):​ ​435-50. 3
  • 4. 1.1:​ ​What​ ​are​ ​the​ ​fundamental​ ​philosophical​ ​premises​ ​of​ ​Dharmakirti’s​ ​opponent? The​ ​school​ ​or​ ​philosophical​ ​position​ ​that​ ​Dharmakirti​ ​(supposedly)​ ​argued​ ​against​ ​was​ ​that​ ​of the​ ​​Charvakas​​ ​(“the​ ​materialists”).​ ​It​ ​is​ ​as​ ​of​ ​yet​ ​unclear​ ​whether​ ​Dharmakirti​ ​argued​ ​against​ ​a real​ ​philosophical​ ​opponent,​ ​or​ ​that​ ​he​ ​merely​ ​constructed​ ​straw-man​ ​arguments​ ​to​ ​contrast​ ​his own.​ ​Eli​ ​Franco​ ​mentions​ ​in​ ​his​ ​study​ ​of​ ​Dharmakirti’s​ ​​Pramanavarttika​ ​​that​ ​his​ ​opponent​ ​could have​ ​been​ ​the​ ​philosopher​ ​Kambalasvatara,​ ​but​ ​he​ ​likewise​ ​keeps​ ​the​ ​issue​ ​ambiguous.2 Regardless,​ ​this​ ​is​ ​not​ ​of​ ​ultimate​ ​concern​ ​to​ ​the​ ​topic​ ​at​ ​hand​ ​in​ ​this​ ​thesis,​ ​which​ ​is​ ​mostly concerned​ ​with​ ​the​ ​arguments​ ​themselves,​ ​and​ ​not​ ​necessarily​ ​with​ ​who​ ​used​ ​them.​ ​The Charvaka​ ​school​ ​was​ ​a​ ​likely​ ​candidate​ ​because,​ ​based​ ​on​ ​the​ ​minimal​ ​sources​ ​we​ ​have​ ​about them,​ ​their​ ​hallmark​ ​was​ ​the​ ​criticism​ ​of​ ​rebirth​ ​and​ ​the​ ​mechanics​ ​of​ ​behavioral​ ​causality​ ​(Skt: karma​). ​ ​The​ ​problem​ ​remains​ ​that​ ​almost​ ​all​ ​texts​ ​about​ ​the​ ​Charvakas​ ​are​ ​now​ ​lost,​ ​so​ ​it’s 3 virtually​ ​impossible​ ​for​ ​us​ ​to​ ​get​ ​a​ ​fully​ ​reliable​ ​account​ ​of​ ​their​ ​ideas​ ​and​ ​practices.​ ​Despite that,​ ​their​ ​philosophical​ ​school​ ​seems​ ​to​ ​have​ ​been​ ​in​ ​existence​ ​up​ ​until​ ​the​ ​second​ ​half​ ​of​ ​the first​ ​millennium. ​ ​Virtually​ ​all​ ​that​ ​survives​ ​about​ ​them​ ​is​ ​in​ ​the​ ​form​ ​of​ ​references​ ​to​ ​them​ ​by 4 opponent​ ​schools,​ ​which​ ​could​ ​obviously​ ​just​ ​consist​ ​of​ ​straw-man​ ​characterizations​ ​of​ ​their ideas.​ ​They​ ​most​ ​clearly​ ​rejected​ ​rebirth​ ​and​ ​​karma​ ​​by​ ​rejecting​ ​the​ ​notion​ ​of​ ​“another​ ​world” (Skt:​ ​​paraloka​)​ ​that​ ​one​ ​might​ ​go​ ​to​ ​after​ ​death,​ ​such​ ​as​ ​a​ ​heaven​ ​or​ ​a​ ​next​ ​life.​ ​They​ ​argued​ ​this on​ ​the​ ​basis​ ​of​ ​their​ ​assertion​ ​that​ ​only​ ​the​ ​(four)​ ​material​ ​elements​ ​are​ ​truly​ ​real,​ ​and​ ​that​ ​the mental​ ​was​ ​a​ ​kind​ ​of​ ​epiphenomenon​ ​that​ ​could​ ​either​ ​be​ ​reduced​ ​to,​ ​or​ ​eliminated​ ​in​ ​favour​ ​of, the​ ​material,​ ​just​ ​as​ ​the​ ​intoxicating​ ​properties​ ​of​ ​beer​ ​can​ ​be​ ​fully​ ​explained​ ​by​ ​its​ ​material constituents. ​ ​They​ ​insisted​ ​that​ ​there​ ​was​ ​no​ ​intangible​ ​aspect​ ​of​ ​the​ ​human​ ​being​ ​aside​ ​from 5 the​ ​material​ ​elements​ ​that​ ​it​ ​is​ ​composed​ ​of​ ​that​ ​could​ ​leave​ ​the​ ​body​ ​and​ ​experience​ ​things elsewhere.​ ​Interestingly​ ​enough,​ ​their​ ​rejection​ ​of​ ​the​ ​“other​ ​world”​ ​was​ ​based​ ​on​ ​a​ ​rejection​ ​of an​ ​abiding​ ​self/soul,​ ​which​ ​Buddhists​ ​generally​ ​also​ ​reject.​ ​This​ ​idea​ ​again​ ​was​ ​based​ ​on​ ​the notion​ ​that​ ​the​ ​supposed​ ​constituents​ ​of​ ​the​ ​self,​ ​including​ ​consciousness​ ​and​ ​perception,​ ​arise directly​ ​from​ ​the​ ​material​ ​elements​ ​of​ ​the​ ​body.​ ​This​ ​means​ ​that​ ​there​ ​is​ ​no​ ​place​ ​for​ ​a​ ​self​ ​that holds​ ​these​ ​constituents​ ​together,​ ​that​ ​would​ ​remain​ ​intact​ ​after​ ​death.​ ​Buddhists​ ​likewise​ ​reject this​ ​notion​ ​of​ ​an​ ​abiding​ ​self​ ​that​ ​exists​ ​independently​ ​and​ ​unchanged,​ ​and​ ​that​ ​would​ ​provide a​ ​static,​ ​unaffected​ ​continuity​ ​for​ ​our​ ​experiences. ​ ​They​ ​do​ ​not​ ​however​ ​reject​ ​the​ ​continuity​ ​of 6 consciousness,​ ​which​ ​they​ ​generally​ ​define​ ​as​ ​a​ ​thoroughly​ ​impermanent​ ​continuum,​ ​consisting of​ ​causally​ ​interrelated​ ​mental​ ​events​ ​that​ ​have​ ​no​ ​independent​ ​status.​ ​Dharmakirti’s​ ​critique​ ​of materialistic​ ​reductionism​ ​was​ ​therefore​ ​not​ ​based​ ​on​ ​the​ ​Charvaka​ ​rejection​ ​of​ ​the​ ​self,​ ​but​ ​on their​ ​rejection​ ​of​ ​the​ ​existence​ ​of​ ​past​ ​and​ ​future​ ​lives. 2 ​ ​Eli​ ​Franco,​ ​​Dharmakirti​ ​on​ ​Compassion​ ​and​ ​Rebirth,​ ​​(Wien:​ ​Arbeitskreis​ ​für​ ​Tibetische​ ​und​ ​Buddhistische​ ​Studien Universität​ ​Wien,​ ​1997),​ ​5. 3 ​ ​Johannes​ ​Bronkhorst,​ ​“Greater​ ​Magadha:​ ​Studies​ ​in​ ​the​ ​Culture​ ​of​ ​Early​ ​India,”​ ​in​ ​​Handbook​ ​of​ ​Oriental​ ​Studies, Section​ ​two,​ ​India;​ ​v.​ ​19,​ ​​ed.​ ​Johannes​ ​Bronkhorst​ ​et​ ​al.​ ​(Leiden:​ ​Brill,​ ​1946),​ ​150. 4 ​ ​Ibid,​ ​158. 5 ​ ​Tom​ ​J.F.​ ​Tillemans,​ ​“On​ ​Minds,​ ​Dharmakirti,​ ​and​ ​Madhyamaka.”​ ​2.​ ​The​ ​present​ ​paper,​ ​in​ ​different​ ​forms,​ ​was presented​ ​at​ ​the​ ​Center​ ​for​ ​Buddhist​ ​Studies​ ​of​ ​the​ ​University​ ​of​ ​Kathmandu​ ​and​ ​the​ ​Dept.​ ​of​ ​Philosophy​ ​of​ ​the University​ ​of​ ​Kyoto.​ ​It​ ​was​ ​subsequently​ ​the​ ​keynote​ ​address​ ​of​ ​the​ ​XVIth​ ​Congress​ ​of​ ​the​ ​International Association​ ​of​ ​Buddhist​ ​Studies,​ ​Taiwan,​ ​2011.​ ​This​ ​free​ ​version​ ​was​ ​obtained​ ​from​ ​Tillemans’​ ​academia.edu​ ​site. 6 ​ ​Except​ ​for​ ​the​ ​interesting​ ​anomaly​ ​of​ ​the​ ​​Pudgalavadin​​ ​school,​ ​that​ ​did​ ​maintain​ ​the​ ​notion​ ​of​ ​a​ ​self-sufficient personality. 4
  • 5. 1.2:​ ​What​ ​is​ ​the​ ​epistemological​ ​context​ ​for​ ​Dharmakirti’s​ ​philosophy​ ​of​ ​mind? In​ ​the​ ​period​ ​when​ ​Dharmakirti​ ​was​ ​active​ ​(the​ ​6th-7th​ ​century​ ​CE)​ ​the​ ​vast​ ​monastic universities​ ​of​ ​India​ ​were​ ​strongholds​ ​of​ ​Buddhist​ ​learning​ ​and​ ​practice.​ ​Dharmakirti​ ​held​ ​his teaching​ ​position​ ​at​ ​the​ ​most​ ​impressive​ ​Buddhist​ ​monastic​ ​university​ ​that​ ​was​ ​probably​ ​ever built:​ ​Nalanda.​ ​The​ ​university​ ​was​ ​founded​ ​in​ ​the​ ​early​ ​sixth​ ​century​ ​by​ ​the​ ​king​ ​Sakraditya​ ​and his​ ​son​ ​Budhagupta. ​ ​Interestingly,​ ​it​ ​held​ ​a​ ​prominent​ ​role​ ​in​ ​the​ ​teaching​ ​life​ ​of​ ​the​ ​Buddha 7 himself​ ​when​ ​it​ ​was​ ​still​ ​a​ ​village​ ​and​ ​communal​ ​retreat​ ​place,​ ​as​ ​it​ ​figures​ ​in​ ​no​ ​less​ ​than​ ​nine Pali​ ​scriptures. ​ ​Unfortunately​ ​from​ ​986​ ​CE​ ​onwards​ ​the​ ​Muslim​ ​Turks​ ​started​ ​raiding 8 North-West​ ​India​ ​from​ ​Afghanistan​ ​all​ ​the​ ​way​ ​to​ ​the​ ​plundering​ ​of​ ​West-India​ ​in​ ​the​ ​11th century.​ ​These​ ​Muslims​ ​forcibly​ ​converted​ ​people​ ​and​ ​destroyed​ ​Buddhist​ ​art​ ​treasures​ ​out​ ​of their​ ​distaste​ ​for​ ​idolatry,​ ​so​ ​much​ ​so​ ​in​ ​fact​ ​that​ ​in​ ​India​ ​the​ ​Islamic​ ​term​ ​for​ ​an​ ​“idol”​ ​became “​budd​”. ​ ​This​ ​all​ ​culminated​ ​in​ ​the​ ​complete​ ​destruction​ ​of​ ​Nalanda​ ​university​ ​in​ ​1198​ ​CE​ ​by​ ​the 9 Muslim​ ​armies​ ​of​ ​the​ ​Mamluk​ ​dynasty.​ ​According​ ​to​ ​the​ ​Tibetan​ ​historian​ ​gSum-pa​ ​mKhan-po Ye-shes​ ​dPal,​ ​Nalanda’s​ ​campus​ ​housed​ ​three​ ​separate​ ​libraries,​ ​each​ ​with​ ​its​ ​own​ ​name (Ratnasagara,​ ​Ratnodadhi​ ​and​ ​Ratnaranjaka),​ ​containing​ ​hundreds​ ​of​ ​thousands​ ​of​ ​volumes​ ​on many​ ​disciplines.​ ​The​ ​largest​ ​of​ ​these​ ​was​ ​nine​ ​stories​ ​high. ​ ​According​ ​to​ ​oral​ ​tradition​ ​these 10 libraries​ ​burned​ ​for​ ​up​ ​to​ ​three​ ​months​ ​after​ ​the​ ​invaders​ ​set​ ​it​ ​ablaze.​ ​The​ ​curriculum​ ​that​ ​was studied​ ​encompassed​ ​the​ ​Indian​ ​“five​ ​sciences”​ ​(Skt:​ ​​Pancavidya​)​ ​of​ ​(1)​ ​linguistics,​ ​(2)​ ​logic​ ​and reasoning,​ ​(3)​ ​medicine​ ​(​ayurveda​),​ ​(4)​ ​fine​ ​arts​ ​and​ ​crafts​ ​(from​ ​mathematics​ ​to​ ​painting),​ ​and finally​ ​(5)​ ​the​ ​“inner​ ​science”​ ​of​ ​spirituality​ ​(​adhyatma​ ​vidya​). ​ ​This​ ​last​ ​branch​ ​was​ ​the​ ​one​ ​that 11 differed​ ​for​ ​each​ ​respective​ ​Indian​ ​tradition.​ ​For​ ​the​ ​Brahmins​ ​this​ ​last​ ​science​ ​meant​ ​the​ ​study of​ ​the​ ​four​ ​Veda’s.​ ​In​ ​the​ ​case​ ​of​ ​Nalanda​ ​it​ ​meant​ ​the​ ​study​ ​of​ ​the​ ​three​ ​categories​ ​of​ ​Buddhist scriptures​ ​on​ ​(1)​ ​monastic​ ​discipline​ ​(​Vinaya​),​ ​(2)​ ​discourses​ ​(​Sutra’s)​,​ ​and​ ​(3) metapsychology/phenomenology​ ​(​Abhidharma​).​ ​These​ ​three​ ​collections​ ​of​ ​scriptures​ ​describe​ ​in many​ ​different​ ​ways​ ​the​ ​path​ ​to​ ​liberation​ ​(​moksha​)​ ​and​ ​full​ ​enlightenment​ ​(​samyaksambodhi​). The​ ​way​ ​Dharmakirti​ ​fits​ ​into​ ​this​ ​system​ ​is​ ​through​ ​his​ ​contributions​ ​to​ ​the​ ​science​ ​of​ ​logic and​ ​reasoning,​ ​and​ ​the​ ​way​ ​those​ ​(epistemological)​ ​principles​ ​tie​ ​into​ ​the​ ​inner​ ​science​ ​of​ ​mind. Dharmakirti​ ​built​ ​his​ ​philosophy​ ​on​ ​the​ ​innovations​ ​of​ ​his​ ​predecessor,​ ​Dignaga​ ​(480​ ​-​ ​540​ ​CE), who​ ​was​ ​the​ ​first​ ​teacher​ ​to​ ​systematically​ ​formulate​ ​a​ ​Buddhist​ ​system​ ​of​ ​logic​ ​and epistemology.​ ​Dignaga​ ​based​ ​his​ ​innovations​ ​on​ ​the​ ​work​ ​of​ ​earlier​ ​Buddhist​ ​philosophers,​ ​most notably​ ​Vasubandhu​ ​(4th-5th​ ​century​ ​CE).​ ​Vasubandhu​ ​was​ ​most​ ​probably​ ​the​ ​first​ ​Buddhist thinker​ ​to​ ​suggest​ ​that​ ​the​ ​only​ ​two​ ​valid​ ​means​ ​of​ ​ascertaining​ ​reality​ ​are​ ​perception (​pratyaksa​)​ ​and​ ​inference​ ​(​anumana​). ​ ​The​ ​knowledge​ ​gained​ ​is​ ​then​ ​communicated​ ​by​ ​means​ ​of 12 7 ​ ​Hartmut​ ​​Scharfe,​ ​​Education​ ​in​ ​Ancient​ ​India​.​ ​Handbook​ ​of​ ​Oriental​ ​Studies.​ ​Section​ ​Two,​ ​India​ ​=​ ​Handbuch​ ​Der Orientalistik.​ ​Indien,​ ​V.​ ​16.​ ​(Leiden:​ ​Brill​ ​2002),​ ​149. 8 ​ ​H.​ ​N.​ ​Shastri,​ ​Nalanda​ ​and​ ​its​ ​Epigraphic​ ​Material​ ​(Delhi:​ ​Sri​ ​Satguru,​ ​1942);​ ​in​ ​Stewart,​ ​op.​ ​cit.,​ ​67- 68. 9 ​ ​Peter​ ​Harvey,​ ​​An​ ​Introduction​ ​to​ ​Buddhism:​ ​Teachings,​ ​History​ ​and​ ​Practices,​ ​​(New​ ​York:​ ​Cambridge​ ​University​ ​Press, 2013),​ ​149. 10 ​ ​Joseph​ ​Loizzo,​​ ​“Sri-Nalanda-Mahavihara:​ ​“Ivory​ ​Tower”​ ​of​ ​India’s​ ​Golden​ ​Age,”​ ​​in​ ​​“CANDRAKIRTI​ ​AND​ ​THE MOONFLOWER​ ​OF​ ​NALANDA”​ ​(PhD​ ​diss.,​ ​Columbia​ ​University,​ ​2001).​ ​​13. 11 ​ ​Jonathan​ ​C.​ ​Gold,​ ​​The​ ​Dharma's​ ​Gatekeepers:​ ​Sakya​ ​Pandita​ ​on​ ​Buddhist​ ​scholarship​ ​in​ ​Tibet.​ ​​(SUNY​ ​Press,​ ​2008),​ ​15. 12 ​ ​Vittorio​ ​A.​ ​van​ ​Bijlert,​ ​​Epistemology​ ​and​ ​Authority.​ ​​(Wien:​ ​Arbeitskreis​ ​für​ ​Tibetische​ ​und​ ​Buddhistische​ ​Studien Universität​ ​Wien,​ ​1989),​ ​45. 5
  • 6. logical​ ​proof​ ​(​sadhana​)​ ​consisting​ ​of​ ​syllogisms.​ ​He​ ​defined​ ​perception​ ​as​ ​a​ ​form​ ​of​ ​cognition that​ ​is​ ​not​ ​necessarily​ ​constituted​ ​by​ ​language.​ ​Only​ ​after​ ​raw​ ​(sensory)​ ​perception​ ​has​ ​occurred can​ ​objects​ ​be​ ​attributed​ ​names​ ​and​ ​concepts.​ ​Perception​ ​is​ ​therefore​ ​knowledge​ ​that​ ​is​ ​solely caused​ ​by​ ​the​ ​object​ ​in​ ​question.​ ​Conventional​ ​(conceptual)​ ​knowledge,​ ​being​ ​projected​ ​onto conglomerates​ ​of​ ​fluctuating​ ​processes,​ ​is​ ​hereby​ ​rejected​ ​as​ ​a​ ​valid​ ​form​ ​of​ ​knowledge. Interestingly,​ ​Vasubandhu​ ​does​ ​include​ ​both​ ​sensory​ ​and​ ​mental​ ​perception​ ​(meaning​ ​internal objects​ ​such​ ​as​ ​emotions)​ ​in​ ​his​ ​definition.​ ​This​ ​fits​ ​the​ ​general​ ​Buddhist​ ​heuristic​ ​model​ ​of​ ​the mind​ ​as​ ​the​ ​sixth​ ​sense,​ ​which​ ​perceives​ ​“internal”​ ​objects.​ ​Perception​ ​therefore​ ​has​ ​to​ ​be​ ​(1) non-erroneous,​ ​(2)​ ​free​ ​from​ ​conceptualizations,​ ​and​ ​(3)​ ​not​ ​a​ ​product​ ​of​ ​inference​ ​in​ ​order​ ​to count​ ​as​ ​a​ ​valid​ ​source​ ​of​ ​knowledge.​ ​Inference​ ​is​ ​then​ ​based​ ​on​ ​the​ ​direct​ ​perception​ ​of​ ​certain things​ ​always​ ​being​ ​connected​ ​(invariably​ ​concomitant​ ​-​ ​​nantariyaka​),​ ​which​ ​allows​ ​one​ ​to validly​ ​infer​ ​the​ ​presence​ ​of​ ​objects​ ​that​ ​are​ ​not​ ​directly​ ​perceived,​ ​the​ ​most​ ​common​ ​example being​ ​fire​ ​and​ ​smoke. ​ ​The​ ​syllogism​ ​then​ ​represents​ ​the​ ​form​ ​of​ ​deductive​ ​reasoning 13 (inference)​ ​that​ ​can​ ​actually​ ​convey​ ​a​ ​fact​ ​to​ ​another​ ​person.​ ​Dignaga​ ​(480-540​ ​AD)​ ​then expanded​ ​on​ ​Vasubandhu’s​ ​framework​ ​to​ ​make​ ​the​ ​most​ ​significant​ ​contributions​ ​to​ ​Buddhist logic​ ​and​ ​epistemology​ ​before​ ​Dharmakirti.​ ​His​ ​main​ ​work​ ​on​ ​epistemology​ ​was​ ​titled Pramanasamuccaya​ ​​(“Comprehensive​ ​Account​ ​of​ ​the​ ​Means​ ​of​ ​Valid​ ​Cognition”).​ ​Dignaga’s​ ​first innovation​ ​was​ ​to​ ​connect​ ​the​ ​two​ ​means​ ​of​ ​valid​ ​cognition​ ​(perception​ ​and​ ​inference)​ ​to​ ​the two​ ​aspects​ ​of​ ​perceived​ ​objects,​ ​namely​ ​their​ ​uniqueness​ ​(the​ ​particular),​ ​and​ ​conceptualized generality​ ​(the​ ​universal)​ ​respectively. ​ ​The​ ​characteristics​ ​that​ ​all​ ​phenomena​ ​equally​ ​possess 14 are​ ​their​ ​(1)​ ​impermanence,​ ​(2)​ ​unsatisfactoriness​ ​(Skt:​ ​​duhkha​),​ ​(3)​ ​openness​ ​(Skt:​ ​​sunyata​),​ ​and (4)​ ​insubstantiality.​ ​The​ ​clear​ ​conceptual​ ​(and​ ​therefore​ ​inferential)​ ​discernment​ ​of​ ​these​ ​four universal​ ​characteristics,​ ​which​ ​is​ ​seen​ ​as​ ​a​ ​necessary​ ​condition​ ​for​ ​the​ ​attainment​ ​of​ ​liberation from​ ​suffering,​ ​is​ ​interestingly​ ​predicated​ ​on​ ​the​ ​momentary​ ​uniqueness​ ​that​ ​objects​ ​clearly possess​ ​when​ ​directly​ ​perceived. ​ ​Perception​ ​is​ ​therefore​ ​defined​ ​as​ ​being​ ​free​ ​from 15 conceptualization​ ​(name-giving),​ ​just​ ​like​ ​in​ ​Vasubandhu’s​ ​definition.​ ​Dignaga​ ​then distinguishes​ ​five​ ​kinds​ ​of​ ​conceptualization​ ​(name-giving):​ ​names​ ​(1)​ ​denoting​ ​only​ ​one​ ​object, (2)​ ​denoting​ ​a​ ​class​ ​(genus),​ ​(3)​ ​denoting​ ​a​ ​quality,​ ​(4)​ ​action​ ​noun​ ​or​ ​verb,​ ​(5)​ ​denoting​ ​a substance.​ ​The​ ​four​ ​kinds​ ​of​ ​perception​ ​he​ ​distinguished​ ​were​ ​of​ ​(1)​ ​sensory​ ​impressions,​ ​(2) mental​ ​awareness​ ​of​ ​them,​ ​(3)​ ​mental​ ​awareness​ ​of​ ​emotions,​ ​and​ ​(4)​ ​higher​ ​(yogic)​ ​perception. Cognition​ ​also​ ​always​ ​(reflexively)​ ​cognizes​ ​itself,​ ​which​ ​means​ ​it​ ​does​ ​not​ ​need​ ​an​ ​internal witness​ ​to​ ​become​ ​aware​ ​of​ ​the​ ​knowledge​ ​gained. ​ ​Dharmakirti​ ​then​ ​easily​ ​became​ ​the​ ​most 16 influential​ ​figure​ ​in​ ​Buddhist​ ​epistemology,​ ​and​ ​elucidated​ ​his​ ​own​ ​innovations​ ​in​ ​his commentary​ ​on​ ​Dignaga’s​ ​work,​ ​titled​ ​​Pramanavarttika​ ​​(“Commentary​ ​on​ ​Valid​ ​Cognition”). One​ ​of​ ​the​ ​primary​ ​epistemological​ ​innovations​ ​that​ ​Dharmakirti​ ​made​ ​was​ ​to​ ​clearly​ ​specify what​ ​constitutes​ ​a​ ​valid​ ​inference,​ ​which​ ​concerns​ ​both​ ​“internal”​ ​inference​ ​(logical​ ​thought) and​ ​“explicit”​ ​inference​ ​(stated​ ​syllogism).​ ​His​ ​main​ ​concern​ ​in​ ​this​ ​was​ ​that​ ​inference,​ ​once​ ​it​ ​is a​ ​valid​ ​source​ ​of​ ​knowledge​ ​about​ ​reality,​ ​enables​ ​one​ ​to​ ​discern​ ​between​ ​what​ ​is​ ​useful​ ​and 13 ​ ​Ibid,​ ​49. 14 ​ ​van​ ​Bijlert,​ ​​Epistemology​ ​and​ ​Authority​,​ ​56. 15 ​ ​Ibid,​ ​57. 16 ​ ​Ibid,​ ​58. 6
  • 7. what​ ​is​ ​not. ​ ​This​ ​has​ ​the​ ​profound​ ​implication​ ​that​ ​what​ ​it​ ​means​ ​for​ ​knowledge​ ​to​ ​be​ ​correct 17 is​ ​that​ ​it​ ​is​ ​(causally)​ ​efficacious.​ ​In​ ​other​ ​words,​ ​valid​ ​cognition​ ​of​ ​reality​ ​by​ ​definition​ ​enables one​ ​to​ ​attain​ ​one’s​ ​goals.​ ​As​ ​Dharmakirti​ ​says​ ​in​ ​the​ ​opening​ ​line​ ​of​ ​his​ ​​Nyayabindu​ ​​(“Drop​ ​of Reasoning”):​ ​“​The​ ​accomplishment​ ​of​ ​all​ ​human​ ​aims​ ​is​ ​preceded​ ​by​ ​right​ ​[valid]​ ​knowledge,​ ​therefore, the​ ​latter​ ​is​ ​here​ ​explained.” ​ ​Dharmakirti’s​ ​goal​ ​then,​ ​like​ ​Dignaga’s,​ ​was​ ​therefore​ ​ultimately​ ​a 18 “pragmatic”​ ​one,​ ​namely​ ​to​ ​attain​ ​the​ ​ultimate​ ​human​ ​aim​ ​of​ ​liberation​ ​from​ ​suffering​ ​and​ ​to attain​ ​the​ ​capacities​ ​that​ ​enable​ ​one​ ​to​ ​help​ ​all​ ​other​ ​beings​ ​do​ ​the​ ​same​ ​(full​ ​enlightenment). Their​ ​epistemological​ ​project,​ ​which​ ​was​ ​to​ ​establish​ ​the​ ​validity​ ​of​ ​Buddha’s​ ​accounts​ ​about reality​ ​based​ ​on​ ​logic,​ ​was​ ​merely​ ​an​ ​instrument​ ​for​ ​this​ ​ultimate​ ​goal.​ ​The​ ​logical​ ​structure​ ​that Dignaga​ ​used​ ​for​ ​this​ ​can​ ​be​ ​accurately​ ​summarized​ ​by​ ​the​ ​following​ ​diagram​ ​taken​ ​from​ ​Eli Franco’s​ ​work​ ​on​ ​Dharmakirti’s​ ​​Pramanavarttika​,​ ​annotated​ ​with​ ​his​ ​English​ ​translations​ ​of​ ​the Sanskrit​ ​terms.​ ​The​ ​goal​ ​here​ ​is​ ​first​ ​of​ ​all​ ​to​ ​establish​ ​how​ ​the​ ​Buddha​ ​could​ ​have​ ​become​ ​a “protector”​ ​of​ ​beings​ ​(​tayitva​),​ ​that​ ​is;​ ​truly​ ​protecting​ ​them​ ​from​ ​suffering​ ​as​ ​such​ ​by​ ​teaching them​ ​the​ ​path​ ​to​ ​liberation​ ​(​nirvana​)​ ​from​ ​all​ ​suffering​ ​and​ ​its​ ​causes.​ ​The​ ​Buddha​ ​needs​ ​to​ ​have been​ ​a​ ​true​ ​“protector”​ ​in​ ​this​ ​sense​ ​in​ ​order​ ​to​ ​be​ ​a​ ​valid​ ​“means​ ​of​ ​knowledge” (​pramanabhutatva​). In​ ​order​ ​for​ ​him​ ​to​ ​become​ ​a​ ​protector​ ​he​ ​needs​ ​to​ ​have​ ​had​ ​infinite​ ​compassion​ ​for​ ​all lifeforms​ ​equally,​ ​i.e.​ ​“seeking​ ​the​ ​benefit​ ​of​ ​all​ ​beings”​ ​(​jagaddhitaisita​).​ ​The​ ​development​ ​of​ ​such compassion​ ​would​ ​only​ ​be​ ​realistic​ ​if​ ​the​ ​following​ ​two​ ​preconditions​ ​were​ ​present;​ ​(1)​ ​the existence​ ​of​ ​an​ ​infinite​ ​number​ ​of​ ​past​ ​lives,​ ​and​ ​(2)​ ​the​ ​capacity​ ​of​ ​mind​ ​to​ ​infinitely​ ​develop mental​ ​capacities​ ​and​ ​qualities​ ​like​ ​compassion. ​ ​It​ ​is​ ​within​ ​this​ ​context​ ​that​ ​Dharmakirti​ ​sets 19 out​ ​to​ ​establish​ ​the​ ​existence​ ​of​ ​beginningless​ ​past​ ​lives​ ​through​ ​logic.​ ​Dharmakirti​ ​slightly changed​ ​Dignaga’s​ ​logical​ ​and​ ​causal​ ​structure​ ​to​ ​more​ ​clearly​ ​elucidate​ ​why​ ​this​ ​capacity​ ​for 17 ​ ​Bijlert,​ ​94. 18 ​ ​Christian​ ​Coseru,​ ​​Perceiving​ ​Reality:​ ​Consciousness,​ ​Intentionality,​ ​and​ ​Cognition​ ​in​ ​Buddhist​ ​Philosophy,​ ​​New​ ​York: Oxford​ ​University​ ​Press,​ ​2012.​ ​128​ ​(note​ ​11). 19 ​ ​The​ ​fully​ ​developed​ ​compassion​ ​of​ ​the​ ​Buddha​ ​encompasses​ ​“perfection​ ​in​ ​intention”​ ​(​asayasampat​)​ ​in​ ​this diagram. 7
  • 8. infinite​ ​compassion​ ​is​ ​so​ ​crucial​ ​for​ ​the​ ​possibility​ ​of​ ​becoming​ ​a​ ​“protector”​ ​of​ ​beings,​ ​and therefore​ ​the​ ​possibility​ ​of​ ​being​ ​a​ ​valid​ ​source​ ​of​ ​knowledge​ ​(about​ ​liberation​ ​and enlightenment).20 Since​ ​Dharmakirti’s​ ​​Pramanasiddhi​ ​​chapter​ ​(in​ ​his​ ​“Commentary​ ​on​ ​Valid​ ​Cognition”),​ ​which​ ​is about​ ​the​ ​nature​ ​and​ ​origin​ ​of​ ​mental​ ​activity​ ​(subjective​ ​experiencing),​ ​is​ ​written​ ​in​ ​the​ ​form of​ ​a​ ​debate​ ​we​ ​will​ ​examine​ ​the​ ​claims​ ​and​ ​arguments​ ​from​ ​both​ ​sides​ ​in​ ​debate​ ​form.​ ​The​ ​lively form​ ​of​ ​debate​ ​that​ ​was​ ​practiced​ ​at​ ​Nalanda​ ​still​ ​survives​ ​in​ ​the​ ​Tibetan​ ​monastic​ ​universities, so​ ​for​ ​the​ ​sake​ ​of​ ​imagination​ ​I​ ​invite​ ​the​ ​reader​ ​to​ ​this​ ​small​ ​video​ ​fragment​ ​of​ ​monks​ ​debating in​ ​this​ ​way,​ ​so​ ​we​ ​might​ ​get​ ​a​ ​taste​ ​for​ ​what​ ​such​ ​debates​ ​must​ ​have​ ​been​ ​like​ ​to​ ​witness.21 1.3:​ ​What​ ​are​ ​Dharmakirti’s​ ​arguments​ ​against​ ​his​ ​opponent’s​ ​physicalist​ ​philosophy​ ​of​ ​mind? As​ ​I​ ​have​ ​remarked​ ​before,​ ​it​ ​is​ ​impossible​ ​for​ ​us​ ​to​ ​determine​ ​whether​ ​the​ ​debate​ ​between Dharmakirti​ ​and​ ​the​ ​Charvakas​ ​as​ ​it​ ​ensues​ ​in​ ​the​ ​​Pramanasiddhi​ ​​chapter​ ​is​ ​representative​ ​of​ ​a debate​ ​that​ ​took​ ​place​ ​between​ ​actual​ ​opponents.​ ​That​ ​is​ ​not​ ​relevant​ ​for​ ​the​ ​discussion​ ​in​ ​this thesis​ ​however,​ ​since​ ​it​ ​merely​ ​judges​ ​the​ ​relevance​ ​of​ ​the​ ​arguments​ ​themselves.​ ​I​ ​will​ ​now​ ​go through​ ​Dharmakirti’s​ ​central​ ​arguments​ ​against​ ​his​ ​opponents’​ ​physicalism​ ​in​ ​an​ ​enumerated fashion​ ​to​ ​maintain​ ​some​ ​conceptual​ ​clarity​ ​along​ ​the​ ​way.​ ​I​ ​have​ ​chosen​ ​to​ ​paraphrase​ ​the arguments​ ​based​ ​on​ ​Dharmakirti’s​ ​original​ ​text​ ​as​ ​well​ ​as​ ​Franco’s​ ​elucidation​ ​of​ ​each​ ​argument in​ ​his​ ​book.​ ​Claims​ ​and​ ​arguments​ ​by​ ​Dharmakirti​ ​are​ ​abbreviated​ ​as​ ​​Dk.C​​ ​and​ ​​Dk.A respectively.​ ​Claims​ ​and​ ​arguments​ ​by​ ​his​ ​(actual​ ​or​ ​constructed)​ ​opponent​ ​are​ ​abbreviated​ ​as Cv.C​​ ​and​ ​​Cv.A​​ ​respectively.​ ​The​ ​enumeration​ ​couples​ ​each​ ​claim​ ​to​ ​its​ ​corresponding argument.​ ​Its​ ​order​ ​is​ ​based​ ​on​ ​Franco’s​ ​elucidation​ ​rather​ ​than​ ​on​ ​Dharmakirti’s​ ​original​ ​text.​ ​I will​ ​go​ ​through​ ​all​ ​the​ ​arguments​ ​to​ ​avoid​ ​a​ ​biased​ ​selection,​ ​but​ ​will​ ​emphasize​ ​the​ ​relevant arguments​ ​for​ ​the​ ​overall​ ​discussion,​ ​which​ ​will​ ​be​ ​indicated​ ​with​ ​an​ ​​underline​,​ ​in​ ​the conclusion​ ​and​ ​discussion.​ ​Before​ ​we​ ​get​ ​into​ ​the​ ​actual​ ​debate​ ​we​ ​must​ ​clarify​ ​certain​ ​terms. The​ ​word​ ​“mind”​ ​in​ ​this​ ​debate​ ​refers​ ​to​ ​“mental​ ​activity”,​ ​defined​ ​by​ ​Dharmakirti​ ​as​ ​a​ ​stream of​ ​successive​ ​mental​ ​(cognitive)​ ​events,​ ​rather​ ​than​ ​a​ ​monolithic​ ​entity​ ​of​ ​“mind”.​ ​The​ ​term “support”​ ​(​asraya​)​ ​within​ ​the​ ​context​ ​of​ ​this​ ​debate​ ​refers​ ​to​ ​an​ ​“obtaining​ ​cause”​ ​(Skt: upadanahetu​)​ ​within​ ​a​ ​causal​ ​sequence​ ​(continuum),​ ​which​ ​in​ ​Abhidharma​ ​is​ ​defined​ ​as​ ​the cause​ ​from​ ​which​ ​the​ ​result​ ​is​ ​obtained​ ​and​ ​which​ ​transforms​ ​into​ ​the​ ​result​ ​(and​ ​thereby​ ​ceases 20 ​ ​Franco,​ ​​Dharmakirti​ ​on​ ​Compassion​ ​and​ ​Rebirth​,​ ​95. 21 ​ ​​https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=V6daHMqrMUY 8
  • 9. to​ ​exist). ​ ​The​ ​translation​ ​as​ ​“obtaining​ ​cause”​ ​is​ ​because​ ​it​ ​is​ ​that​ ​from​ ​which​ ​the​ ​result​ ​is 22 “obtained”.​ ​I​ ​consciously​ ​choose​ ​to​ ​avoid​ ​the​ ​common​ ​translations​ ​of​ ​“substantial​ ​substratum”​ ​or “material​ ​cause”​ ​since​ ​they​ ​could​ ​be​ ​misunderstood​ ​in​ ​this​ ​context​ ​as​ ​referring​ ​to​ ​the​ ​physical elements​ ​that​ ​make​ ​up​ ​something.​ ​Obtaining​ ​causes​ ​stand​ ​in​ ​contrast​ ​to​ ​“simultaneously​ ​acting conditions”​ ​(Skt:​ ​​sahakaripratyaya​)​,​ ​​which​ ​are​ ​assisting​ ​factors​ ​​that​ ​must​ ​exist​ ​prior​ ​to​ ​the​ ​arising of​ ​something​ ​and​ ​which​ ​assist​ ​in​ ​making​ ​the​ ​arising​ ​occur,​ ​but​ ​do​ ​not​ ​transform​ ​into​ ​what arises. ​ ​The​ ​classical​ ​example​ ​is​ ​that​ ​of​ ​a​ ​seed​ ​turning​ ​into​ ​a​ ​sprout.​ ​The​ ​seed​ ​here​ ​is​ ​the 23 obtaining​ ​cause,​ ​and​ ​therefore​ ​transforms​ ​into​ ​the​ ​sprout.​ ​Water,​ ​sunlight,​ ​and​ ​soil​ ​are​ ​merely simultaneously​ ​acting​ ​conditions​ ​for​ ​this​ ​to​ ​occur.​ ​The​ ​six​ ​“senses”​ ​(Skt:​ ​​indriya​)​ ​in​ ​this​ ​debate are​ ​more​ ​usefully​ ​translated​ ​as​ ​six​ ​types​ ​of​ ​“cognitive​ ​sensors”,​ ​or​ ​sensors​ ​for​ ​short,​ ​since​ ​in modern​ ​classifications​ ​they​ ​would​ ​include​ ​their​ ​respective​ ​nervous​ ​systems,​ ​including​ ​the​ ​brain areas​ ​necessary​ ​for​ ​processing,​ ​and​ ​not​ ​just​ ​the​ ​visible​ ​sense​ ​organs.​ ​The​ ​only​ ​exception​ ​is​ ​the sixth​ ​non-physical​ ​type;​ ​the​ ​mind​ ​sensors,​ ​which​ ​are​ ​the​ ​six​ ​“primary​ ​consciousnesses”​ ​used​ ​in Abhidharma​ ​models​ ​of​ ​the​ ​mind.​ ​It​ ​will​ ​suffice​ ​to​ ​say​ ​that​ ​these​ ​six​ ​types​ ​of​ ​consciousness merely​ ​cognize​ ​the​ ​essential​ ​nature​ ​of​ ​the​ ​object,​ ​which​ ​is​ ​the​ ​category​ ​to​ ​which​ ​it​ ​belongs (sight/sound/etc).​ ​Hence​ ​these​ ​six​ ​consciousnesses​ ​each​ ​correspond​ ​to​ ​a​ ​sensory​ ​or​ ​mental​ ​field. Dk.C​ ​1:​​ ​The​ ​sensors​ ​are​ ​not​ ​the​ ​support​ ​of​ ​the​ ​mental​ ​cognition​ ​(Skt:​ ​manomati),​ ​but​ ​the​ ​mental​ ​cognition is​ ​the​ ​support​ ​of​ ​the​ ​sensors​ ​(verse​ ​39). Dk.A​ ​1:​​ ​​Destroying​ ​or​ ​damaging​ ​the​ ​sensors​ ​does​ ​not​ ​destroy​ ​or​ ​damage​ ​the​ ​mental​ ​cognition,​ ​but​ ​when the​ ​mental​ ​cognition​ ​is​ ​destroyed​ ​the​ ​sensors​ ​are​ ​likewise​ ​destroyed.​ ​Therefore​ ​the​ ​sensors​ ​arise​ ​from cognition.24 Dharmakirti​ ​argues​ ​against​ ​a​ ​major​ ​premise​ ​of​ ​his​ ​opponents’​ ​philosophy,​ ​which​ ​is​ ​that​ ​mental cognition​ ​arises​ ​from​ ​(i.e.​ ​is​ ​caused​ ​by)​ ​the​ ​five​ ​types​ ​of​ ​physical​ ​sensors​ ​(the​ ​sensory​ ​systems​ ​of the​ ​body).​ ​Unfortunately​ ​Dharmakirti​ ​does​ ​not​ ​specify​ ​what​ ​he​ ​means​ ​by​ ​“mental​ ​cognition” (​manomati​).​ ​There​ ​seem​ ​to​ ​be​ ​three​ ​possible​ ​interpretations.​ ​The​ ​first​ ​is​ ​that​ ​mental​ ​cognition refers​ ​to​ ​mental​ ​activity​ ​as​ ​the​ ​subjective​ ​experiencing​ ​of​ ​cognitive​ ​appearances,​ ​stimulated​ ​by the​ ​six​ ​types​ ​of​ ​sensors.​ ​The​ ​second​ ​is​ ​the​ ​Buddhist​ ​Idealist​ ​(​Chittamatra​)​ ​interpretation​ ​where mental​ ​cognition​ ​refers​ ​to​ ​the​ ​“foundation​ ​consciousness”​ ​(​alayavijnana​)​ ​that​ ​underlies​ ​all cognition,​ ​and​ ​that​ ​stores​ ​(karmic)​ ​imprints​ ​and​ ​tendencies.​ ​In​ ​this​ ​view,​ ​one​ ​cannot​ ​be​ ​sure​ ​of the​ ​existence​ ​of​ ​an​ ​objective​ ​body​ ​as​ ​such,​ ​but​ ​only​ ​of​ ​the​ ​cognitive​ ​appearances​ ​of​ ​a​ ​body​ ​that appear​ ​to​ ​the​ ​mind.​ ​In​ ​this​ ​view​ ​the​ ​body​ ​is​ ​therefore​ ​an​ ​“image”​ ​in​ ​this​ ​foundation consciousness. ​ ​The​ ​third​ ​interpretation​ ​would​ ​be​ ​the​ ​Buddhist​ ​Realist​ ​(​Sautrantika​)​ ​view​ ​that 25 Dharmakirti​ ​elucidates​ ​in​ ​verse​ ​42:​ ​​Even​ ​if​ ​there​ ​is​ ​no​ ​cognition​ ​without​ ​sensors,​ ​there​ ​are​ ​no​ ​sensors without​ ​cognition​ ​either;​ ​therefore,​ ​sensors​ ​and​ ​cognition​ ​are​ ​(at​ ​least)​ ​mutual​ ​causes​ ​and​ ​have​ ​mutual causes. ​ ​​In​ ​this​ ​interpretation​ ​sensors​ ​and​ ​cognition​ ​are​ ​interdependent,​ ​and​ ​therefore​ ​cannot 26 exist​ ​separately.​ ​The​ ​truly​ ​relevant​ ​interpretation​ ​for​ ​this​ ​thesis​ ​is​ ​the​ ​first,​ ​which​ ​was articulated​ ​by​ ​Dan​ ​Arnold.​ ​Here,​ ​Dharmakirti​ ​argues​ ​that​ ​it​ ​is​ ​possible​ ​for​ ​there​ ​to​ ​be​ ​mental 22 ​ ​I​ ​use​ ​the​ ​translations​ ​from​ ​Dr.​ ​Alexander​ ​Berzin’s​ ​glossary​ ​(​https://glossary.studybuddhism.com/​)​ ​throughout​ ​this thesis,​ ​unless​ ​otherwise​ ​specified.​ ​Search:​ ​“obtaining​ ​cause”. 23 ​ ​Tillemans,​ ​“On​ ​Minds,​ ​Dharmakirti,​ ​and​ ​Madhyamaka.”​ ​3. 24 ​ ​Franco,​ ​​Dharmakirti​ ​on​ ​Compassion​ ​and​ ​Rebirth,​ ​​74. 25 ​ ​The​ ​​Chittamatra​ ​​philosophy​ ​is​ ​quite​ ​complex,​ ​partly​ ​due​ ​to​ ​its​ ​heterogeneity.​ ​I​ ​will​ ​not​ ​attempt​ ​a​ ​survey​ ​here. 26 ​ ​Franco,​ ​​Dharmakirti​ ​on​ ​Compassion​ ​and​ ​Rebirth,​ ​75. 9
  • 10. activity​ ​(subjective​ ​appearances)​ ​without​ ​sensory​ ​input,​ ​while​ ​in​ ​contrast,​ ​sensory​ ​input​ ​in​ ​and of​ ​itself​ ​does​ ​not​ ​constitute​ ​mental​ ​activity.​ ​The​ ​mental​ ​is​ ​therefore​ ​conceptually​ ​basic​ ​here. ​ ​If 27 sensory​ ​input​ ​were​ ​the​ ​obtaining​ ​cause​ ​for​ ​mental​ ​activity,​ ​then​ ​it​ ​follows​ ​that​ ​restricting​ ​this input,​ ​as​ ​in​ ​the​ ​case​ ​of​ ​sensory​ ​deprivation,​ ​should​ ​proportionally​ ​diminish​ ​mental​ ​activity (cognition)​ ​as​ ​well.​ ​If​ ​one​ ​were​ ​to​ ​enter​ ​an​ ​ideal​ ​sensory​ ​deprivation​ ​tank​ ​for​ ​instance,​ ​one would​ ​experience​ ​a​ ​complete​ ​cessation​ ​of​ ​mental​ ​activity,​ ​and​ ​go​ ​unconscious. ​ ​Having​ ​spent​ ​an 28 hour​ ​in​ ​such​ ​a​ ​tank​ ​myself,​ ​I​ ​can​ ​attest​ ​to​ ​the​ ​fact​ ​that​ ​the​ ​opposite​ ​occurs.​ ​The​ ​mind​ ​actually becomes​ ​more​ ​cognitively​ ​active.​ ​One​ ​generally​ ​experiences​ ​enhanced​ ​imagination​ ​(including visions/hallucination),​ ​crystal​ ​clear​ ​thinking,​ ​and​ ​even​ ​mystical​ ​experiences.​ ​Now,​ ​one​ ​could argue​ ​that​ ​these​ ​are​ ​never​ ​ideal​ ​circumstances,​ ​and​ ​that​ ​one​ ​always​ ​has​ ​some​ ​sensory​ ​input.​ ​Still, significant​ ​reduction​ ​ought​ ​to​ ​diminish​ ​mental​ ​activity​ ​proportionally,​ ​which​ ​does​ ​not​ ​seem​ ​to occur.​ ​If​ ​one​ ​were​ ​to​ ​claim​ ​that​ ​the​ ​five​ ​sensory​ ​systems​ ​are​ ​instead​ ​the​ ​obtaining​ ​cause​ ​for mental​ ​activity,​ ​then​ ​it​ ​follows​ ​that​ ​destroying​ ​one​ ​of​ ​these​ ​sensory​ ​systems​ ​should​ ​immediately impair​ ​the​ ​mind​ ​and​ ​its​ ​cognitive​ ​capacities.​ ​There​ ​are​ ​numerous​ ​cases​ ​however​ ​of​ ​people​ ​that miss​ ​multiple​ ​sensory​ ​systems,​ ​but​ ​regardless​ ​of​ ​that​ ​have​ ​no​ ​significant​ ​reduction​ ​in​ ​mental functionality,​ ​such​ ​as​ ​the​ ​famous​ ​case​ ​of​ ​Helen​ ​Keller.​ ​She​ ​became​ ​deaf​ ​and​ ​blind​ ​as​ ​an​ ​infant, yet​ ​she​ ​obtained​ ​a​ ​bachelor​ ​of​ ​arts​ ​degree,​ ​and​ ​published​ ​twelve​ ​books​ ​on​ ​multiple​ ​fields​ ​of study.​ ​Her​ ​mental​ ​(cognitive)​ ​capacities​ ​therefore​ ​greatly​ ​exceeded​ ​those​ ​of​ ​“normal”​ ​people​ ​that have​ ​all​ ​their​ ​sensory​ ​systems​ ​intact.​ ​Dharmakirti’s​ ​criticism​ ​of​ ​the​ ​sensory​ ​(nervous)​ ​systems​ ​or their​ ​input​ ​being​ ​the​ ​obtaining​ ​cause​ ​of​ ​mind​ ​is​ ​therefore​ ​a​ ​strong​ ​argument.​ ​This​ ​argument​ ​will be​ ​reviewed​ ​in​ ​the​ ​conclusion​ ​and​ ​discussion. Dk.C​ ​2:​​ ​Mind​ ​(mental​ ​activity)​ ​is​ ​completely​ ​autonomous. Dk.A​ ​2:​​ ​​The​ ​body​ ​cannot​ ​be​ ​the​ ​obtaining​ ​cause​ ​for​ ​the​ ​mind,​ ​and​ ​may​ ​influence​ ​the​ ​mind​ ​only​ ​in​ ​a circumstantial​ ​way,​ ​just​ ​as​ ​fire​ ​may​ ​produce​ ​liquidity​ ​in​ ​copper​ ​as​ ​long​ ​as​ ​they​ ​occur​ ​together,​ ​but​ ​copper is​ ​neither​ ​produced​ ​by​ ​fire​ ​nor​ ​ceases​ ​to​ ​exist​ ​when​ ​the​ ​fire​ ​is​ ​extinguished.29 Dharmakirti​ ​articulates​ ​the​ ​difference​ ​that​ ​the​ ​body​ ​(the​ ​five​ ​sensors)​ ​is​ ​merely​ ​a​ ​simultaneously acting​ ​condition​ ​for​ ​the​ ​mind​ ​to​ ​function,​ ​and​ ​not​ ​its​ ​obtaining​ ​cause.​ ​Again,​ ​this​ ​is​ ​relevant because​ ​if​ ​mental​ ​activity​ ​ends​ ​with​ ​the​ ​body​ ​it​ ​cannot​ ​be​ ​said​ ​to​ ​infinitely​ ​expand​ ​its​ ​capacities and​ ​qualities,​ ​as​ ​would​ ​be​ ​required​ ​for​ ​the​ ​existence​ ​of​ ​a​ ​Buddha. Cv.C​ ​1:​​ ​Repeated​ ​practice​ ​for​ ​more​ ​than​ ​one​ ​life​ ​is​ ​impossible. Cv.A​ ​1:​ ​​The​ ​body​ ​is​ ​the​ ​obtaining​ ​cause​ ​of​ ​cognition​ ​and​ ​therefore​ ​destroying​ ​the​ ​body​ ​destroys​ ​cognition as​ ​well. Franco​ ​characterizes​ ​the​ ​opponent​ ​view​ ​in​ ​this​ ​case​ ​to​ ​be​ ​one​ ​of​ ​epiphenomenalism,​ ​meaning that​ ​the​ ​mind​ ​is​ ​an​ ​effect​ ​or​ ​emergent​ ​property​ ​of​ ​the​ ​body,​ ​but​ ​never​ ​its​ ​cause. ​ ​This​ ​also 30 implies​ ​the​ ​mind​ ​does​ ​not​ ​have​ ​causal​ ​efficacy​ ​in​ ​this​ ​view,​ ​and​ ​therefore​ ​corresponds​ ​quite neatly​ ​to​ ​the​ ​modern​ ​version​ ​of​ ​epiphenomenalism​ ​(mind​ ​as​ ​an​ ​emergent​ ​property). 27 ​ ​Dan​ ​Arnold,​ ​“Dharmakirti’s​ ​Dualism:​ ​Critical​ ​Reflections​ ​on​ ​a​ ​Buddhist​ ​Proof​ ​of​ ​Rebirth,”​ ​​Philosophy​ ​Compass​ ​v3 n5​ ​(September​ ​2008):​ ​​1079-1096.​ ​1085. 28 ​ ​These​ ​lightless,​ ​soundproof​ ​tanks​ ​(almost)​ ​remove​ ​all​ ​sensory​ ​input,​ ​including​ ​tactile,​ ​since​ ​one​ ​floats​ ​in​ ​highly saline​ ​water​ ​that​ ​is​ ​heated​ ​to​ ​skin​ ​temperature. 29 ​ ​Franco,​ ​​Dharmakirti​ ​on​ ​Compassion​ ​and​ ​Rebirth​,​ ​93. 30 ​ ​Ibid,​ ​99. 10
  • 11. Dk.C​ ​3:​ ​​The​ ​relationship​ ​between​ ​the​ ​obtaining​ ​cause​ ​(the​ ​body)​ ​and​ ​its​ ​effect​ ​(mental​ ​cognition)​ ​does​ ​not function​ ​as​ ​proposed​ ​(by​ ​the​ ​opponent). Dk.A​ ​3:​​ ​​Exhalation,​ ​inhalation,​ ​sensors​ ​and​ ​cognition​ ​(i.e.​ ​“sentience”)​ ​do​ ​not​ ​arise​ ​from​ ​the​ ​body​ ​alone, independently​ ​of​ ​causes​ ​of​ ​their​ ​own​ ​kind.31 Dharmakirti​ ​rejects​ ​the​ ​opponent’s​ ​claim​ ​because​ ​it​ ​is​ ​absurd​ ​to​ ​assume​ ​that​ ​at​ ​the​ ​time​ ​of​ ​birth, breathing,​ ​sensors,​ ​and​ ​cognition,​ ​can​ ​arise​ ​from​ ​the​ ​body​ ​alone,​ ​independent​ ​of​ ​causes​ ​that​ ​are similar​ ​in​ ​nature.​ ​This​ ​implies​ ​that​ ​“sentient”​ ​phenomena​ ​have​ ​to​ ​arise​ ​dependent​ ​upon​ ​causes of​ ​the​ ​same​ ​ontological​ ​kind​ ​or​ ​category​ ​of​ ​phenomena,​ ​i.e.,​ ​possess​ ​the​ ​same​ ​characteristic properties.​ ​This,​ ​in​ ​essence,​ ​is​ ​Dharmakirti’s​ ​main​ ​argument:​ ​sentient​ ​phenomena​ ​(breaths, sensors,​ ​and​ ​cognition)​ ​must​ ​have​ ​among​ ​their​ ​causes​ ​events​ ​that​ ​are​ ​themselves​ ​sentient (possess​ ​the​ ​same​ ​properties​ ​of​ ​“sentience”),​ ​because​ ​phenomena​ ​must​ ​have​ ​ontologically homogeneous​ ​causes. ​ ​Even​ ​the​ ​modern​ ​physicalist​ ​model​ ​endorses​ ​this​ ​axiomatic​ ​principle;​ ​it​ ​is 32 impossible​ ​for​ ​physical​ ​phenomena​ ​(matter/energy)​ ​to​ ​give​ ​rise​ ​to​ ​phenomena​ ​that​ ​have​ ​no physical​ ​properties.​ ​As​ ​we​ ​will​ ​see,​ ​this​ ​presented​ ​a​ ​virtually​ ​insurmountable​ ​challenge​ ​for modern​ ​thinkers​ ​to​ ​somehow​ ​give​ ​mental​ ​(subjective)​ ​phenomena​ ​a​ ​place​ ​in​ ​the​ ​causal​ ​world, regardless​ ​of​ ​their​ ​non-physical,​ ​phenomenological​ ​characteristics.​ ​We​ ​will​ ​return​ ​to​ ​the relevant​ ​implications​ ​of​ ​this​ ​in​ ​the​ ​conclusion​ ​and​ ​discussion. Cv.C​ ​2:​​ ​​Consciousness​ ​(sentience)​ ​arises​ ​from​ ​the​ ​material​ ​elements​ ​(of​ ​the​ ​body),​ ​and​ ​not​ ​from​ ​causes​ ​of the​ ​same​ ​kind.​ ​Only​ ​a​ ​special​ ​transformation​ ​of​ ​the​ ​elements​ ​into​ ​the​ ​form​ ​of​ ​a​ ​body​ ​produces​ ​life (sentience). Cv.A​ ​2:​​ ​Therefore​ ​only​ ​certain​ ​parts​ ​of​ ​the​ ​elements​ ​cause​ ​sentience,​ ​just​ ​like​ ​certain​ ​stones​ ​contain​ ​gold, while​ ​others​ ​do​ ​not. Dk.C​ ​4:​​ ​The​ ​diversity​ ​of​ ​life,​ ​and​ ​the​ ​regularity​ ​within​ ​its​ ​diversity,​ ​would​ ​be​ ​unexplainable​ ​if​ ​life​ ​arose from​ ​the​ ​material​ ​elements​ ​alone.33 The​ ​material​ ​elements​ ​referred​ ​to​ ​here​ ​are​ ​those​ ​found​ ​in​ ​Abhidharma;​ ​earth​ ​(solidity),​ ​water (cohesion),​ ​fire​ ​(heat/energy),​ ​and​ ​wind​ ​(motion).​ ​These​ ​“elements”​ ​are​ ​quite​ ​unlike​ ​the​ ​elements of​ ​the​ ​periodic​ ​table,​ ​because​ ​they​ ​are​ ​more​ ​like​ ​principles​ ​or​ ​forces.​ ​All​ ​four​ ​are​ ​said​ ​to​ ​occur​ ​in all​ ​material​ ​phenomena,​ ​but​ ​in​ ​varying​ ​proportions,​ ​which​ ​gives​ ​each​ ​phenomenon​ ​its​ ​distinct characteristics.​ ​Dharmakirti’s​ ​point​ ​is​ ​that​ ​since​ ​these​ ​elemental​ ​forces​ ​are​ ​omnipresent,​ ​it​ ​is impossible​ ​to​ ​account​ ​for​ ​the​ ​diversities​ ​and​ ​regularities​ ​of​ ​life​ ​that​ ​supposedly​ ​arise​ ​from​ ​them. A​ ​modern​ ​parallel​ ​of​ ​the​ ​four​ ​elements​ ​would​ ​perhaps​ ​be​ ​the​ ​“four​ ​fundamental​ ​forces”​ ​used​ ​in physics,​ ​that​ ​are​ ​also​ ​not​ ​reducible​ ​to​ ​more​ ​basic​ ​forces:​ ​(1)​ ​the​ ​gravitational​ ​force​ ​(attributed​ ​to the​ ​curvature​ ​of​ ​spacetime),​ ​(2)​ ​the​ ​electromagnetic​ ​force​ ​(manifests​ ​itself​ ​through​ ​the​ ​forces between​ ​electric​ ​charges​ ​and​ ​magnetic​ ​fields,​ ​involving​ ​the​ ​exchange​ ​of​ ​photons),​ ​(3)​ ​the​ ​weak nuclear​ ​force​ ​(mediates​ ​radioactive​ ​decay),​ ​and​ ​(4)​ ​the​ ​strong​ ​nuclear​ ​force​ ​(holds​ ​the​ ​atomic nucleus​ ​together). ​ ​All​ ​of​ ​these​ ​are​ ​mathematically​ ​described​ ​as​ ​fields.​ ​The​ ​modern​ ​account​ ​of 34 the​ ​origin​ ​of​ ​life​ ​(“sentience”)​ ​is​ ​fundamentally​ ​a​ ​reductive​ ​one,​ ​namely​ ​that​ ​all​ ​of​ ​(conscious) life​ ​spontaneously​ ​emerged​ ​from​ ​the​ ​most​ ​fundamental​ ​physical​ ​forces​ ​of​ ​nature.​ ​Dharmakirti’s 31 ​ ​Ibid,​ ​102. 32 ​ ​Dan​ ​Arnold,​ ​“Dharmakirti’s​ ​Dualism:​ ​Critical​ ​Reflections​ ​on​ ​a​ ​Buddhist​ ​Proof​ ​of​ ​Rebirth,”​ ​1083. 33 ​ ​Franco,​ ​​Dharmakirti​ ​on​ ​Compassion​ ​and​ ​Rebirth​,​ ​108. 34 ​ ​​http://hyperphysics.phy-astr.gsu.edu/hbase/Forces/funfor.html 11
  • 12. argument​ ​is​ ​therefore​ ​also​ ​an​ ​argument​ ​against​ ​modern​ ​reductive​ ​accounts​ ​of​ ​the​ ​origin​ ​of​ ​life, such​ ​as​ ​the​ ​Oparin-Haldane​ ​hypothesis. ​ ​Dharmakirti’s​ ​point​ ​is​ ​solid,​ ​since​ ​the​ ​fact​ ​that​ ​the 35 reductionist​ ​model​ ​still​ ​remains​ ​unproven​ ​today​ ​suggests​ ​that​ ​it​ ​is​ ​almost​ ​impossible​ ​to​ ​explain the​ ​diversity​ ​and​ ​the​ ​regularity​ ​within​ ​the​ ​diversity​ ​of​ ​life,​ ​based​ ​on​ ​analysing​ ​its​ ​elementary physical​ ​components​ ​alone. Dk.A​ ​4:​ ​​If​ ​sentient​ ​phenomena​ ​(sensors,​ ​cognitions)​ ​were​ ​produced​ ​purely​ ​by​ ​the​ ​material​ ​elements​ ​alone, without​ ​causes​ ​of​ ​their​ ​own​ ​kind,​ ​then​ ​just​ ​as​ ​the​ ​elements​ ​are​ ​transformed​ ​into​ ​the​ ​cause​ ​of​ ​life somewhere​ ​(where​ ​they​ ​take​ ​the​ ​form​ ​of​ ​a​ ​body),​ ​the​ ​same​ ​would​ ​happen​ ​everywhere​ ​because​ ​the​ ​cause​ ​of the​ ​transformation​ ​is​ ​the​ ​same​.36 The​ ​absurd​ ​consequence​ ​of​ ​the​ ​material​ ​elements​ ​causing​ ​life​ ​(sentience)​ ​is​ ​that​ ​life​ ​would spring​ ​forth​ ​continuously​ ​wherever​ ​these​ ​material​ ​elements​ ​(physical​ ​forces)​ ​exist,​ ​which​ ​would happen​ ​everywhere,​ ​all​ ​the​ ​time,​ ​since​ ​the​ ​elements​ ​are​ ​present​ ​everywhere.​ ​Clearly​ ​this​ ​is​ ​not happening.​ ​The​ ​material​ ​elements​ ​alone​ ​therefore​ ​cannot​ ​account​ ​for​ ​the​ ​existence​ ​and​ ​diversity of​ ​life,​ ​and​ ​sentient​ ​phenomena​ ​can​ ​likewise​ ​not​ ​arise​ ​from​ ​the​ ​body​ ​alone​ ​independently​ ​of causes​ ​of​ ​their​ ​own​ ​kind. Cv.C​ ​3:​ ​​Every​ ​cognition​ ​at​ ​death​ ​(the​ ​final​ ​cognition​ ​in​ ​life)​ ​does​ ​not​ ​link​ ​to​ ​another​ ​cognition​ ​(in​ ​the​ ​next life). Cv.A​ ​3:​​ ​Because​ ​it​ ​is​ ​a​ ​cognition​ ​at​ ​death,​ ​just​ ​like​ ​the​ ​last​ ​cognition​ ​of​ ​the​ ​Arhat​ ​(liberated​ ​being). ​ ​Thus, 37 everyone​ ​is​ ​liberated​ ​after​ ​death,​ ​just​ ​like​ ​the​ ​Arhat. An​ ​Arhat​ ​is​ ​defined​ ​as​ ​a​ ​being​ ​who​ ​has​ ​totally​ ​uprooted​ ​suffering​ ​and​ ​its​ ​causes​ ​(disturbing emotions,​ ​karma),​ ​and​ ​therefore​ ​has​ ​no​ ​impetus​ ​to​ ​compulsively​ ​take​ ​on​ ​a​ ​new​ ​body​ ​on​ ​the​ ​basis of​ ​craving​ ​(disturbing​ ​emotions)​ ​after​ ​death.​ ​Some​ ​believe​ ​that​ ​an​ ​Arhat​ ​therefore​ ​actually ceases​ ​to​ ​exist​ ​at​ ​death,​ ​since​ ​there​ ​is​ ​no​ ​impetus​ ​for​ ​further​ ​cognitions. Dk.C​ ​5:​ ​​There​ ​is​ ​no​ ​contradiction​ ​whatsoever​ ​between​ ​the​ ​cognition​ ​at​ ​death​ ​of​ ​an​ ​Arhat​ ​and​ ​the production​ ​of​ ​a​ ​further​ ​cognition. Dk.A​ ​5:​ ​​It​ ​is​ ​the​ ​disconnection​ ​from​ ​the​ ​defilements​ ​(disturbing​ ​emotions)​ ​which​ ​prevents​ ​rebirth. Dharmakirti​ ​therefore​ ​disproves​ ​this​ ​notion​ ​of​ ​death​ ​being​ ​equal​ ​to​ ​liberation,​ ​and​ ​that​ ​Arhats cease​ ​to​ ​exist​ ​when​ ​they​ ​become​ ​liberated. Dk.C​ ​6:​​ ​The​ ​body​ ​as​ ​the​ ​cause​ ​of​ ​cognition​ ​is​ ​likewise​ ​not​ ​established. Dk.A​ ​6:​ ​​Because​ ​that​ ​which​ ​is​ ​claimed​ ​to​ ​be​ ​a​ ​cause​ ​is​ ​not​ ​a​ ​cause​ ​at​ ​all,​ ​it’s​ ​absence​ ​cannot​ ​be​ ​adduced​ ​as reason.​ ​​If​ ​the​ ​mental​ ​cognition​ ​were​ ​to​ ​arise​ ​from​ ​the​ ​body​ ​with​ ​sensors​ ​it​ ​would​ ​be​ ​like​ ​(have​ ​the​ ​nature of)​ ​a​ ​sense​ ​cognition,​ ​which​ ​means​ ​it​ ​would​ ​be​ ​limited​ ​to​ ​certain​ ​kinds​ ​of​ ​objects.​ ​Nor​ ​does​ ​it​ ​arise​ ​from the​ ​body​ ​with​ ​all​ ​the​ ​sensors​ ​together,​ ​because​ ​the​ ​sensors​ ​do​ ​not​ ​cooperate​ ​(blend​ ​together).​ ​Nor​ ​does​ ​it arise​ ​from​ ​the​ ​body​ ​without​ ​the​ ​sensors,​ ​because​ ​the​ ​body​ ​(alone)​ ​is​ ​devoid​ ​of​ ​consciousness.38 If​ ​the​ ​mental​ ​cognition​ ​were​ ​caused​ ​by​ ​the​ ​body​ ​there​ ​would​ ​be​ ​three​ ​possibilities.​ ​Either​ ​it​ ​is caused​ ​by​ ​(1)​ ​one​ ​sensory​ ​system​ ​of​ ​the​ ​body,​ ​(2)​ ​by​ ​the​ ​body​ ​with​ ​all​ ​sensory​ ​systems​ ​together, or​ ​(3)​ ​the​ ​body​ ​independently​ ​of​ ​its​ ​sensory​ ​systems.​ ​If​ ​the​ ​first​ ​were​ ​true​ ​then​ ​mental​ ​cognition 35 ​ ​This​ ​hypothesis​ ​claims​ ​that​ ​biological​ ​life​ ​spontaneously​ ​emerged​ ​from​ ​the​ ​interactions​ ​of​ ​elementary compounds. 36 ​ ​Ibid,​ ​113.​ ​The​ ​physicalist​ ​opponent​ ​does​ ​not​ ​admit​ ​to​ ​any​ ​existents​ ​over​ ​and​ ​above​ ​the​ ​material​ ​elements,​ ​so​ ​the (obtaining)​ ​cause​ ​is​ ​omnipresent. 37 ​ ​Arhats​ ​are​ ​beings​ ​who​ ​have​ ​attained​ ​​nirvana​ ​​(liberation​ ​from​ ​suffering),​ ​but​ ​are​ ​not​ ​enlightened​ ​(a​ ​Buddha). 38 ​ ​Ibid,​ ​119. 12
  • 13. would​ ​have​ ​the​ ​nature​ ​of​ ​that​ ​sensory​ ​system,​ ​and​ ​could​ ​therefore​ ​only​ ​cognize​ ​a​ ​certain​ ​range of​ ​objects.​ ​If​ ​the​ ​second​ ​were​ ​true,​ ​then​ ​Dharmakirti’s​ ​first​ ​argument​ ​applies​ ​that​ ​destroying​ ​one sensory​ ​system​ ​would​ ​terminate​ ​mental​ ​activity,​ ​since​ ​its​ ​obtaining​ ​cause​ ​is​ ​no​ ​longer​ ​complete. If​ ​the​ ​third​ ​were​ ​true​ ​then​ ​a​ ​dead​ ​body​ ​would​ ​have​ ​consciousness​ ​as​ ​well,​ ​which​ ​is​ ​an​ ​absurd consequence. Cv.A​ ​4:​ ​​Why,​ ​if​ ​the​ ​body​ ​is​ ​not​ ​the​ ​cause​ ​of​ ​the​ ​mental​ ​cognition,​ ​do​ ​they​ ​always​ ​exist​ ​together? Dk.C​ ​7:​ ​​They​ ​have​ ​the​ ​same​ ​cause, Dk.A​ ​7:​ ​​just​ ​as​ ​sight​ ​and​ ​hearing​ ​of​ ​the​ ​same​ ​person​ ​or​ ​color​ ​and​ ​flavour​ ​of​ ​the​ ​same​ ​object​ ​always​ ​exist together​ ​without​ ​being​ ​each​ ​other’s​ ​cause. Cv.C​ ​5:​ ​​It​ ​cannot​ ​be​ ​explained​ ​why​ ​the​ ​mental​ ​cognition​ ​is​ ​transformed​ ​by​ ​the​ ​body​ ​if​ ​the​ ​body​ ​is​ ​not​ ​its cause. Cv.A​ ​5:​ ​​For​ ​instance,​ ​the​ ​transformation​ ​of​ ​the​ ​body​ ​by​ ​poison​ ​causes​ ​a​ ​mental​ ​transformation​ ​as​ ​pain.39 Dk.C​ ​8:​ ​​The​ ​transformation​ ​occurs,​ ​but​ ​the​ ​body​ ​is​ ​not​ ​the​ ​obtaining​ ​cause. Dk.A​ ​8:​ ​​The​ ​transformation​ ​is​ ​caused​ ​by​ ​the​ ​apprehension​ ​(cognition)​ ​of​ ​the​ ​body​ ​(the​ ​body​ ​as​ ​object,​ ​not as​ ​cause).​ ​The​ ​body​ ​may​ ​be​ ​said​ ​to​ ​be​ ​an​ ​assisting​ ​factor​ ​in​ ​the​ ​production​ ​of​ ​cognition,​ ​but​ ​not​ ​its​ ​cause. Dk.C​ ​9:​ ​​The​ ​fact​ ​that​ ​the​ ​body​ ​is​ ​sometimes​ ​the​ ​assisting​ ​factor​ ​for​ ​the​ ​sequence​ ​of​ ​cognitions​ ​(mental activity)​ ​does​ ​not​ ​mean​ ​that​ ​the​ ​sequence​ ​ceases​ ​to​ ​exist​ ​when​ ​the​ ​body​ ​ceases​ ​to​ ​exist. Dk.A​ ​9.1:​ ​​Just​ ​as​ ​fire​ ​may​ ​change​ ​the​ ​color​ ​of​ ​a​ ​pot,​ ​but​ ​the​ ​pot​ ​does​ ​not​ ​cease​ ​to​ ​exist​ ​when​ ​the​ ​fire​ ​stops. Dk.A​ ​9.2:​ ​​If​ ​the​ ​body​ ​were​ ​the​ ​obtaining​ ​cause​ ​of​ ​cognition,​ ​there​ ​would​ ​follow​ ​an​ ​absurd​ ​consequence, namely​ ​that​ ​the​ ​cognition​ ​would​ ​last​ ​as​ ​long​ ​as​ ​the​ ​body,​ ​in​ ​which​ ​case​ ​a​ ​dead​ ​body​ ​too​ ​would​ ​have​ ​to have​ ​cognition.40 Tom​ ​Tillemans​ ​argues​ ​that​ ​this​ ​line​ ​of​ ​reasoning​ ​is​ ​based​ ​on​ ​scientific​ ​ignorance​ ​on​ ​the​ ​part​ ​of Dharmakirti,​ ​since​ ​modern​ ​research​ ​has​ ​shown​ ​that​ ​an​ ​alive​ ​body​ ​is​ ​not​ ​physically​ ​identical​ ​to​ ​a dead​ ​body,​ ​and​ ​therefore​ ​the​ ​two​ ​cannot​ ​be​ ​equated​ ​in​ ​this​ ​context. ​ ​I​ ​would​ ​argue​ ​that,​ ​even​ ​if 41 one​ ​factors​ ​in​ ​the​ ​appropriate​ ​differences,​ ​the​ ​argument​ ​still​ ​discredits​ ​the​ ​possibility​ ​of​ ​most tissues​ ​of​ ​the​ ​body​ ​acting​ ​as​ ​the​ ​obtaining​ ​cause​ ​for​ ​mental​ ​activity.​ ​Most​ ​tissues​ ​of​ ​the​ ​body remain​ ​physically​ ​identical​ ​immediately​ ​after​ ​the​ ​onset​ ​of​ ​clinical​ ​death,​ ​yet​ ​mental​ ​activity ceases.​ ​What​ ​the​ ​argument​ ​fails​ ​to​ ​prove​ ​however,​ ​is​ ​that​ ​brain​ ​activity​ ​could​ ​be​ ​the​ ​obtaining cause​ ​for​ ​mental​ ​activity,​ ​since​ ​this​ ​obviously​ ​ceases​ ​upon​ ​death.​ ​Therefore​ ​I​ ​will​ ​further​ ​explore this​ ​version​ ​of​ ​the​ ​argument​ ​in​ ​the​ ​conclusion​ ​and​ ​discussion. Cv.C​ ​6:​ ​​Cognition​ ​is​ ​absent​ ​in​ ​a​ ​dead​ ​body, Cv.A​ ​6:​ ​​because​ ​breath​ ​is​ ​also​ ​a​ ​cause​ ​of​ ​cognition,​ ​and​ ​there​ ​is​ ​no​ ​breath​ ​in​ ​a​ ​dead​ ​body.42 This​ ​is​ ​quite​ ​possibly​ ​a​ ​reference​ ​to​ ​vitalism,​ ​the​ ​idea​ ​that​ ​there​ ​is​ ​a​ ​subtle​ ​animating​ ​principle associated​ ​with​ ​the​ ​physical​ ​breath​ ​that​ ​animates​ ​the​ ​body,​ ​and​ ​that​ ​is​ ​closely​ ​associated​ ​with consciousness.​ ​One​ ​need​ ​only​ ​refer​ ​to​ ​physical​ ​breath​ ​however​ ​to​ ​follow​ ​the​ ​discussion​ ​further. Here​ ​Dharmakirti​ ​begins​ ​a​ ​lengthy​ ​discussion​ ​of​ ​why​ ​cognition​ ​is​ ​independent​ ​of​ ​the​ ​breaths. This​ ​is​ ​not​ ​truly​ ​relevant​ ​in​ ​relation​ ​to​ ​modern​ ​discussion,​ ​and​ ​therefore​ ​to​ ​this​ ​thesis,​ ​but​ ​I have​ ​included​ ​it​ ​for​ ​the​ ​sake​ ​of​ ​comprehensiveness​ ​and​ ​context. 39 ​ ​Ibid,​ ​119. 40 ​ ​Ibid,​ ​121. 41 ​ ​Tillemans,​ ​“On​ ​Minds,​ ​Dharmakirti,​ ​and​ ​Madhyamaka.”​ ​3. 42 ​ ​Franco,​ ​​Dharmakirti​ ​on​ ​Compassion​ ​and​ ​Rebirth,​ ​​234. 13
  • 14. Dk.C​ ​10:​ ​​Cognition​ ​is​ ​the​ ​cause​ ​of​ ​the​ ​breath,​ ​not​ ​the​ ​other​ ​way​ ​around.43 Dk.A​ ​10.1:​ ​​It​ ​can​ ​be​ ​observed​ ​that​ ​breath​ ​is​ ​controlled​ ​by​ ​cognition,​ ​not​ ​the​ ​other​ ​way​ ​around. Dk.A​ ​10.2:​ ​​Breath​ ​is​ ​impossible​ ​without​ ​consciousness,​ ​since​ ​drawing​ ​in​ ​and​ ​pushing​ ​out​ ​air​ ​can​ ​not happen​ ​without​ ​an​ ​effort,​ ​and​ ​effort​ ​implies​ ​consciousness. Dk.A​ ​10.3:​ ​​If​ ​cognition​ ​were​ ​the​ ​resultant​ ​effect​ ​of​ ​exhalation​ ​and​ ​inhalation​ ​it​ ​would​ ​increase​ ​and decrease​ ​according​ ​to​ ​the​ ​increase​ ​and​ ​decrease​ ​in​ ​breathing. Dk.A​ ​10.4:​ ​​If​ ​breath​ ​in​ ​fact​ ​were​ ​the​ ​cause​ ​of​ ​cognition,​ ​then​ ​the​ ​cognition​ ​would​ ​be​ ​present​ ​as​ ​long​ ​as exhalation​ ​and​ ​inhalation​ ​are​ ​present,​ ​and​ ​they,​ ​being​ ​caused​ ​by​ ​the​ ​body,​ ​would​ ​be​ ​present​ ​as​ ​long​ ​as​ ​the body​ ​is​ ​present.​ ​Consequently​ ​there​ ​would​ ​be​ ​no​ ​dead​ ​body,​ ​which​ ​is​ ​an​ ​inadmissible​ ​consequence. Dk.C​ ​11:​ ​​There​ ​is​ ​no​ ​inadmissible​ ​consequence​ ​if​ ​one​ ​assumes​ ​that​ ​cognition​ ​is​ ​the​ ​cause​ ​of​ ​cognition, Dk.A​ ​11:​ ​​because​ ​there​ ​is​ ​a​ ​further​ ​cause​ ​for​ ​the​ ​continuity​ ​of​ ​a​ ​sequence​ ​of​ ​cognitions​ ​in​ ​a​ ​certain​ ​body. Here​ ​Dharmakirti​ ​reveals​ ​his​ ​own​ ​position,​ ​which​ ​is​ ​that​ ​mental​ ​activity​ ​is​ ​a​ ​causal​ ​stream​ ​of mental​ ​moments​ ​that​ ​have​ ​no​ ​beginning​ ​or​ ​end. Cv.C​ ​7:​ ​​The​ ​body​ ​inhabited​ ​or​ ​governed​ ​by​ ​exhalation,​ ​inhalation,​ ​etc.,​ ​produces​ ​the​ ​cognition. Dharmakirti​ ​then​ ​goes​ ​into​ ​a​ ​discussion​ ​of​ ​what​ ​are​ ​the​ ​restricting​ ​factors​ ​that​ ​prevent​ ​the arising​ ​of​ ​more​ ​than​ ​one​ ​cognition​ ​at​ ​a​ ​time​ ​per​ ​body.​ ​He​ ​seems​ ​to​ ​apply​ ​a​ ​Middle​ ​Way (​Madhyamaka​)​ ​analysis​ ​of​ ​paradoxical​ ​consequences. Dk.C​ ​12:​ ​​Given​ ​the​ ​assumption​ ​that​ ​the​ ​body​ ​is​ ​composed​ ​of​ ​atoms​ ​(particles/parts),​ ​these​ ​parts​ ​either produce​ ​the​ ​cognition​ ​collectively,​ ​as​ ​an​ ​aggregate,​ ​or​ ​individually,​ ​each​ ​by​ ​itself. His​ ​way​ ​of​ ​framing​ ​exhausts​ ​all​ ​logical​ ​possibilities​ ​of​ ​how​ ​the​ ​parts​ ​could​ ​produce​ ​cognition. Dk.A​ ​12.1:​ ​​If​ ​the​ ​parts​ ​were​ ​to​ ​produce​ ​cognition​ ​collectively​ ​then​ ​cognition​ ​would​ ​not​ ​arise​ ​when​ ​a​ ​single part​ ​of​ ​the​ ​body​ ​is​ ​missing. This​ ​is​ ​an​ ​absurd​ ​consequence,​ ​since​ ​it​ ​clearly​ ​does​ ​not​ ​occur.​ ​The​ ​parts​ ​could​ ​be​ ​interpreted​ ​as atoms,​ ​bodyparts,​ ​or​ ​sensory​ ​systems,​ ​but​ ​in​ ​all​ ​instances​ ​the​ ​argument​ ​works. Dk.A​ ​12.2:​ ​​If​ ​each​ ​individual​ ​part​ ​of​ ​the​ ​body​ ​were​ ​capable​ ​of​ ​producing​ ​cognition​ ​by​ ​itself,​ ​there​ ​would arise​ ​as​ ​many​ ​cognitions​ ​as​ ​there​ ​are​ ​parts​ ​(or​ ​atoms)​ ​of​ ​the​ ​body.44 If​ ​each​ ​individual​ ​part​ ​could​ ​give​ ​rise​ ​to​ ​(act​ ​as​ ​the​ ​obtaining​ ​cause​ ​of)​ ​cognition​ ​they​ ​would give​ ​rise​ ​to​ ​as​ ​many​ ​“minds”​ ​as​ ​there​ ​are​ ​parts​ ​of​ ​the​ ​body.​ ​This​ ​also​ ​an​ ​absurd​ ​consequence.​ ​We will​ ​return​ ​to​ ​this​ ​argument​ ​in​ ​the​ ​conclusion​ ​and​ ​discussion. Cv.C​ ​8:​ ​​The​ ​breaths​ ​are​ ​the​ ​main​ ​cause​ ​of​ ​cognition,​ ​and​ ​not​ ​every​ ​part​ ​of​ ​the​ ​body​ ​is​ ​capable​ ​of producing​ ​a​ ​cognition. Dk.C​ ​13:​ ​​This​ ​will​ ​not​ ​solve​ ​the​ ​problem, Dk.A​ ​13.1:​ ​​because​ ​the​ ​fact​ ​that​ ​there​ ​are​ ​multiple​ ​breaths​ ​implies​ ​there​ ​would​ ​still​ ​be​ ​several​ ​cognitions​ ​at the​ ​same​ ​time. Dk.A​ ​13.2:​ ​​Even​ ​if​ ​one​ ​assumes​ ​that​ ​there​ ​is​ ​only​ ​one​ ​breath,​ ​this​ ​could​ ​not​ ​account​ ​for​ ​the​ ​gradual​ ​arising of​ ​many​ ​cognitions​ ​during​ ​one’s​ ​lifetime, Dharmakirti​ ​here​ ​uses​ ​a​ ​variant​ ​of​ ​the​ ​"neither​ ​one​ ​nor​ ​many"​ ​argument. Dk.C​ ​14:​ ​​Breath​ ​cannot​ ​be​ ​restricting​ ​factor​ ​of​ ​cognition, Dk.A​ ​14:​​ ​because​ ​many​ ​cognitions​ ​can​ ​arise​ ​during​ ​one​ ​long​ ​breath​ ​(such​ ​as​ ​looking​ ​around​ ​in​ ​a​ ​circle while​ ​taking​ ​a​ ​deep​ ​breath). 43 ​ ​Franco,​ ​​Dharmakirti​ ​on​ ​Compassion​ ​and​ ​Rebirth,​ ​​121. 44 ​ ​Ibid,​ ​123. 14
  • 15. Cv.A​ ​9:​ ​​If​ ​one​ ​conceives​ ​of​ ​breath​ ​as​ ​momentary​ ​one​ ​may​ ​assume​ ​that​ ​many​ ​momentary​ ​breaths​ ​are​ ​the cause​ ​of​ ​many​ ​momentary​ ​cognitions. Dk.C​ ​15:​ ​​This​ ​merely​ ​shifts​ ​the​ ​same​ ​problem​ ​to​ ​the​ ​breaths. Dk.A​ ​15.1:​​ ​If​ ​the​ ​manifold​ ​cognitions​ ​arise​ ​from​ ​many​ ​gradual​ ​breaths​ ​then​ ​the​ ​breaths​ ​can​ ​only​ ​arise​ ​from gradual​ ​causes.​ ​The​ ​body​ ​is​ ​not​ ​gradual​ ​however,​ ​and​ ​therefore​ ​cannot​ ​produce​ ​gradual​ ​breaths. Dk.A​ ​15.2:​ ​​Nor​ ​could​ ​the​ ​previous​ ​breath​ ​cause​ ​the​ ​next​ ​one,​ ​because​ ​there​ ​is​ ​no​ ​previous​ ​breath​ ​for​ ​the first​ ​breath​ ​in​ ​this​ ​life​ ​according​ ​to​ ​the​ ​Charvaka. Dk.A​ ​15.3:​​ ​One​ ​cannot​ ​assume​ ​that​ ​breath​ ​is​ ​one​ ​(unitary)​ ​because​ ​it​ ​is​ ​connected​ ​with​ ​different​ ​places. Cv.C​ ​10:​ ​​The​ ​breaths​ ​are​ ​many​ ​and​ ​they​ ​produce​ ​cognition​ ​together. Dk.A​ ​16:​ ​​If​ ​one​ ​were​ ​to​ ​stop​ ​breathing​ ​for​ ​a​ ​moment​ ​the​ ​cognition​ ​could​ ​not​ ​arise,​ ​which​ ​clearly​ ​does​ ​not occur. Dk.A​ ​16.2:​ ​​One​ ​cannot​ ​say​ ​that​ ​in​ ​different​ ​situations​ ​different​ ​breaths​ ​produce​ ​cognition,​ ​because cognition​ ​would​ ​vary​ ​according​ ​to​ ​whether​ ​it​ ​is​ ​produced​ ​by​ ​one​ ​breath​ ​or​ ​the​ ​other.45 The​ ​debate​ ​still​ ​continues,​ ​but​ ​now​ ​Dharmakirti​ ​arrives​ ​at​ ​his​ ​own​ ​philosophy​ ​of​ ​mind.​ ​He​ ​first has​ ​to​ ​show​ ​how​ ​he​ ​avoids​ ​the​ ​inadmissible​ ​consequence​ ​that​ ​all​ ​momentary​ ​cognitions​ ​would arise​ ​at​ ​the​ ​same​ ​time. Dk.C​ ​17:​ ​​One​ ​cognition​ ​produces​ ​only​ ​one​ ​cognition​, Dk.A​ ​17.1:​ ​​because​ ​its​ ​capacity​ ​is​ ​limited​.46 Dk.A​ ​17.2:​ ​​As​ ​long​ ​as​ ​one​ ​keeps​ ​looking​ ​at​ ​one​ ​object,​ ​one​ ​cannot​ ​see​ ​another​ ​object.​ ​The​ ​fact​ ​that​ ​a cognition​ ​which​ ​could​ ​have​ ​arisen,​ ​at​ ​least​ ​in​ ​principle,​ ​does​ ​not​ ​arise,​ ​points​ ​at​ ​this​ ​restriction​.47 Dharmakirti​ ​here​ ​argues​ ​for​ ​the​ ​momentariness​ ​of​ ​mental​ ​events.​ ​His​ ​argument​ ​rests​ ​on​ ​the limited​ ​capacity​ ​of​ ​the​ ​mind​ ​to​ ​only​ ​cognize​ ​one​ ​phenomenon​ ​at​ ​a​ ​time.​ ​The​ ​fact​ ​that​ ​several cognitions​ ​at​ ​a​ ​time​ ​could​ ​in​ ​principle​ ​arise,​ ​but​ ​in​ ​fact​ ​do​ ​not​ ​arise,​ ​indicates​ ​an​ ​intrinsic restriction​ ​on​ ​the​ ​cognitive​ ​capacity​ ​of​ ​the​ ​mind.​ ​Cognitive​ ​psychological​ ​research​ ​interestingly indicates​ ​the​ ​same​ ​thing;​ ​the​ ​attentional​ ​system​ ​is​ ​only​ ​capable​ ​of​ ​attending​ ​to​ ​one​ ​thing​ ​at​ ​a time.​ ​Multitasking​ ​turns​ ​out​ ​to​ ​be​ ​merely​ ​the​ ​rapid​ ​switching​ ​of​ ​attentional​ ​objects,​ ​which occurs​ ​quickly​ ​enough​ ​to​ ​give​ ​the​ ​illusion​ ​of​ ​simultaneous​ ​processing.48 Cv.C​ ​11:​ ​​Although​ ​the​ ​body​ ​is​ ​capable​ ​of​ ​producing​ ​many​ ​cognitions,​ ​the​ ​cognition​ ​that​ ​arises​ ​first​ ​from the​ ​body​ ​limits​ ​the​ ​capacity​ ​of​ ​the​ ​body​ ​to​ ​produce​ ​any​ ​further​ ​cognitions. The​ ​opponent​ ​tries​ ​to​ ​accommodate​ ​the​ ​principle​ ​that​ ​one​ ​cognition​ ​produces​ ​only​ ​one cognition.​ ​Franco​ ​estimates​ ​this​ ​to​ ​be​ ​a​ ​straw-man​ ​argument​ ​based​ ​on​ ​context. Dk.C​ ​(commentator) ​ ​18:​ ​​This​ ​suggestion​ ​is​ ​unfounded. 49 Dk.A​ ​(commentator)​ ​18.1:​ ​​It​ ​would​ ​be​ ​like​ ​saying​ ​that​ ​the​ ​first​ ​moment​ ​of​ ​smoke​ ​arises​ ​from​ ​fire​ ​and​ ​then limits​ ​the​ ​capacity​ ​of​ ​fire​ ​to​ ​produce​ ​more​ ​smoke. Again​ ​we​ ​see​ ​a​ ​typical​ ​implementation​ ​of​ ​inferential​ ​logic​ ​on​ ​the​ ​basis​ ​of​ ​examples. Dk.A​ ​(commentator)​ ​18.2:​ ​​Likewise​ ​the​ ​causes​ ​of​ ​the​ ​first​ ​cognition​ ​are​ ​not​ ​somehow​ ​“aware”​ ​of​ ​the​ ​fact that​ ​cognition​ ​has​ ​been​ ​produced,​ ​and​ ​that​ ​therefore​ ​they​ ​need​ ​not​ ​keep​ ​producing​ ​it. 45 ​ ​Ibid,​ ​124. 46 ​ ​Skt:​ ​​Saktiniyama. 47 ​ ​Ibid,​ ​125. 48 ​ ​A.M.​ ​Treisman,​ ​&​ ​G.​ ​Gelade,​ ​“A​ ​feature-integration​ ​theory​ ​of​ ​attention,”​ ​​Cognitive​ ​Psychology​ ​​12(1)​ ​(1980):​ ​97-136. 49 ​ ​This​ ​point​ ​was​ ​made​ ​by​ ​one​ ​of​ ​the​ ​commentators​ ​on​ ​the​ ​​Pramanavarttika;​ ​Prajnakaragupta. 15
  • 16. Dharmakirti’s​ ​theory​ ​then​ ​contains​ ​several​ ​problems.​ ​One​ ​is​ ​that​ ​it​ ​cannot​ ​explain​ ​why​ ​a cognition​ ​should​ ​be​ ​related​ ​to​ ​the​ ​body.​ ​Cognition​ ​should​ ​in​ ​principle​ ​be​ ​able​ ​to​ ​exist​ ​on​ ​its own.​ ​Dharmakirti​ ​accepts​ ​this,​ ​and​ ​likewise​ ​most​ ​Buddhists​ ​throughout​ ​history​ ​have​ ​integrated this​ ​aspect​ ​into​ ​their​ ​cosmology​ ​in​ ​the​ ​form​ ​of​ ​a​ ​formless​ ​realm/sphere​ ​(Skt:​ ​​Arupadhatu​)​ ​where beings​ ​exist​ ​with​ ​exclusively​ ​mental​ ​faculties.​ ​These​ ​various​ ​spheres​ ​are​ ​also​ ​the​ ​cosmological manifestations​ ​of​ ​phenomenological​ ​states​ ​of​ ​meditative​ ​absorption​ ​that​ ​a​ ​practitioner​ ​may familiarize​ ​him​ ​or​ ​herself​ ​with​ ​during​ ​embodied​ ​lifetimes,​ ​which​ ​then​ ​results​ ​in​ ​such​ ​a​ ​rebirth state.​ ​Under​ ​normal​ ​circumstances​ ​however​ ​the​ ​cognition​ ​of​ ​a​ ​being​ ​would​ ​assist​ ​the​ ​obtaining cause​ ​of​ ​the​ ​body,​ ​and​ ​then​ ​they​ ​occur​ ​together. Dk.C​ ​19:​ ​​The​ ​cause​ ​of​ ​the​ ​body​ ​in​ ​the​ ​next​ ​life​ ​are​ ​the​ ​five​ ​bases​ ​(five​ ​sensors). Dharmakirti​ ​then​ ​echoes​ ​the​ ​Buddhist​ ​view​ ​that​ ​even​ ​a​ ​disembodied​ ​being​ ​in​ ​the​ ​intermediate state​ ​(​antarabhava​)​ ​after​ ​death​ ​possesses​ ​five​ ​sensors,​ ​albeit​ ​in​ ​a​ ​very​ ​subtle​ ​form​ ​that​ ​is produced​ ​by​ ​the​ ​mind,​ ​quite​ ​like​ ​the​ ​sensors​ ​one​ ​possesses​ ​in​ ​dreams.50 Cv.C​ ​12:​ ​​Neither​ ​the​ ​formless​ ​spheres​ ​nor​ ​the​ ​five​ ​senses​ ​(in​ ​the​ ​intermediate​ ​state)​ ​are​ ​observed​ ​by anyone,​ ​nor​ ​are​ ​the​ ​five​ ​senses​ ​seen​ ​to​ ​produce​ ​a​ ​new​ ​body​ ​after​ ​death. Cv.A​ ​12:​ ​​Therefore​ ​there​ ​is​ ​no​ ​causal​ ​relation​ ​between​ ​them. Dk.A​ ​20:​ ​​Non-observation​ ​does​ ​not​ ​imply​ ​non-existence. Dharmakirti​ ​makes​ ​the​ ​epistemological​ ​point​ ​that​ ​mere​ ​non-observation​ ​of​ ​something​ ​does​ ​not establish​ ​its​ ​non-existence​ ​or​ ​non-occurrence,​ ​and​ ​therefore​ ​is​ ​not​ ​a​ ​valid​ ​inference.​ ​There​ ​are obviously​ ​innumerable​ ​subtle​ ​features​ ​of​ ​the​ ​world​ ​that​ ​are​ ​not​ ​accessible​ ​to​ ​superficial perception.​ ​Dignaga​ ​therefore​ ​included​ ​yogic​ ​(extrasensory)​ ​perception,​ ​acquired​ ​through decades​ ​of​ ​rigorous​ ​meditative​ ​training,​ ​as​ ​a​ ​valid​ ​means​ ​of​ ​knowing​ ​such​ ​subtle​ ​features,​ ​yet this​ ​can​ ​hardly​ ​function​ ​as​ ​a​ ​means​ ​of​ ​knowledge​ ​in​ ​this​ ​context.​ ​In​ ​recent​ ​decades​ ​however, multidisciplinary​ ​research​ ​has​ ​delivered​ ​empirical​ ​data​ ​of​ ​causally​ ​effective​ ​and​ ​functionally independent​ ​mental​ ​phenomena,​ ​including​ ​disembodied​ ​sensory​ ​perception. ​ ​Especially​ ​the 51 “near​ ​death​ ​experience”​ ​(NDE)​ ​research​ ​of​ ​Pim​ ​van​ ​Lommel​ ​(and​ ​Bruce​ ​Greyson)​ ​has​ ​presented convincing​ ​empirical​ ​data​ ​of​ ​mental​ ​activity,​ ​including​ ​corroborated​ ​sensory​ ​perception, functioning​ ​independently​ ​of​ ​brain​ ​activity.​ ​In​ ​Pim​ ​van​ ​Lommel’s​ ​long-term​ ​study​ ​the explanations​ ​of​ ​said​ ​phenomena​ ​that​ ​had​ ​previously​ ​been​ ​put​ ​forward​ ​by​ ​sceptics,​ ​such​ ​as oxygen-deprivation​ ​(​anoxia​),​ ​narcotics,​ ​and​ ​psychological​ ​disposition,​ ​could​ ​be​ ​positively​ ​ruled out​ ​as​ ​relevant​ ​factors. ​ ​No​ ​one​ ​has​ ​so​ ​far​ ​been​ ​able​ ​to​ ​conclusively​ ​disprove​ ​these​ ​findings, 52 which​ ​suggests​ ​that​ ​Dharmakirti’s​ ​claim​ ​of​ ​disembodied​ ​sense​ ​perception​ ​actually​ ​has​ ​an empirical​ ​basis​ ​in​ ​reality. Cv.C​ ​13:​ ​​The​ ​senses​ ​do​ ​not​ ​link​ ​to​ ​another​ ​life, Cv.A​ ​13:​ ​​because​ ​they​ ​are​ ​senses,​ ​just​ ​as​ ​the​ ​senses​ ​of​ ​one​ ​person​ ​do​ ​not​ ​link​ ​to​ ​the​ ​senses​ ​of​ ​another. Dk.C​ ​21:​ ​​The​ ​reason​ ​is​ ​not​ ​conclusive​ ​(Skt:​ ​sesavat). 50 ​ ​Robert​ ​Thurman,​ ​​The​ ​Tibetan​ ​Book​ ​of​ ​the​ ​Dead:​ ​Liberation​ ​through​ ​Understanding​ ​in​ ​the​ ​Between,​ ​​Random​ ​House Publishing​ ​Group,​ ​2011.​ ​255. 51 ​ ​Probably​ ​the​ ​most​ ​significant​ ​compendium​ ​of​ ​empirical​ ​research​ ​indicating​ ​the​ ​irreducibility,​ ​functional independence,​ ​and​ ​causal​ ​efficacy​ ​of​ ​mental​ ​phenomena,​ ​see:​ ​Edward​ ​F.​ ​Kelly​ ​et​ ​al.,​ ​​Irreducible​ ​Mind:​ ​Toward​ ​a Psychology​ ​for​ ​the​ ​21st​ ​Century,​​ ​Rowman​ ​and​ ​Littlefield​ ​Publishers,​ ​2009. 52 ​ ​Pim​ ​van​ ​Lommel,​ ​​Eindeloos​ ​Bewustzijn:​ ​Een​ ​Wetenschappelijke​ ​Visie​ ​op​ ​de​ ​Bijna-Dood​ ​Ervaring.​ ​​Utrecht:​ ​Uitgeverij​ ​Ten Have,​ ​2012.​ ​H6​ ​(144-146),​ ​H7​ ​(169-171),​ ​H8​ ​(189-191). 16