SlideShare a Scribd company logo
1 of 47
Copyright © 1998. All rights reserved.
Copyright © 1998. All rights reserved.
Copyright © 1998. All rights reserved.
Copyright © 1998. All rights reserved.
Copyright © 1998. All rights reserved.
Copyright © 1998. All rights reserved.
Copyright © 1998. All rights reserved.
Copyright © 1998. All rights reserved.
Copyright © 1998. All rights reserved.
Copyright © 1998. All rights reserved.
Copyright © 1998. All rights reserved.
Copyright © 1998. All rights reserved.
Copyright © 1998. All rights reserved.
Copyright © 1998. All rights reserved.
Copyright © 1998. All rights reserved.
Copyright © 1998. All rights reserved.
Copyright © 1998. All rights reserved.
Copyright © 1998. All rights reserved.
Copyright © 1998. All rights reserved.
Copyright © 1998. All rights reserved.
Copyright © 1998. All rights reserved.
Copyright © 1998. All rights reserved.
Copyright © 1998. All rights reserved.
Copyright © 1998. All rights reserved.
Copyright © 1998. All rights reserved.
Introduction from:
Distinction:
A Social Critique of the Judgement of Taste
by Pierre Bourdieu
©1984
Introduction
You said it, my good knight! There ought to be laws to
protect the body of acquired knowledge.
Take one of our good pupils, for example: modest
and diligent, from his earliest grammar classes he’s
kept a little notebook full of phrases.
After hanging on the lips of his teachers for twenty
years, he’s managed to build up an intellectual stock in
trade; doesn’t it belong to him as if it were a house, or
money?
Paul Claudel, Le soulier de satin, Day III, Scene ii
There is an economy of cultural goods, but it has a specific
logic. Sociology
endeavours to establish the conditions in which the consumers
of cultural goods,
and their taste for them, are produced, and at the same time to
describe the
different ways of appropriating such of these objects as are
regarded at a
particular moment as works of art, and the social conditions of
the constitution of
the mode of appropriation that is considered legitimate. But one
cannot fully
understand cultural practices unless ‘culture’, in the restricted,
normative sense of
ordinary usage, is brought back into ‘culture’ in the
anthropological sense, and
the elaborated taste for the most refined objects is reconnected
with the
elementary taste for the flavours of food.
Whereas the ideology of charisma regards taste in legitimate
culture as a gift
of nature, scientific observation shows that cultural needs are
the product of
upbringing and education: surveys establish that all cultural
practices (museum
visits, concert-going, reading etc.), and preferences in
literature, painting or
music, are closely linked to educational level (measured by
qualifications or
length of schooling) and secondarily to social origin.
1
The relative weight of
home background and of formal education (the effectiveness
and duration of
which are closely dependent on social origin) varies according
to the extent to
which the different cultural practices are recognized and taught
by the
educational system, and the influence of social origin is
strongest—other things
being equal—in ‘extra-curricular’ and avant-garde culture. To
the socially
recognized hierarchy of the arts, and within each of them, of
genres, schools or
periods, corresponds a social hierarchy of the consumers. This
predisposes tastes
to function as markers of ‘class’. The manner in which culture
has been acquired
lives on in the manner of using it: the importance attached to
manners can be
1
Bourdieu et al., Un art moyen: essai sur les usages sociaux de
la photographie (Paris,
Ed. de Minuit, 1965); P. Bourdieu and A. Darbel, L’Amour de
l’art: les musées et leur
public (Paris, Ed. de Minuit, 1966).
2
understood once it is seen that it is these imponderables of
practice which
distinguish the different—and ranked—modes of culture
acquisition, early or
late, domestic or scholastic, and the classes of individuals
which they
characterize (such as ‘pedants’ and mondains). Culture also has
its titles of
nobility—awarded by the educational system—and its
pedigrees, measured by
seniority in admission to the nobility.
The definition of cultural nobility is the stake in a struggle
which has gone on
unceasingly, from the seventeenth century to the present day,
between groups
differing in their ideas of culture and of the legitimate relation
to culture and to
works of art, and therefore differing in the conditions of
acquisition of which
these dispositions are the product
2
Even in the classroom, the dominant definition
of the legitimate way of appropriating culture and works of art
favours those who
have had early access to legitimate culture, in a cultured
household, outside of
scholastic disciplines, since even within the educational system
it devalues
scholarly knowledge and interpretation as ‘scholastic’ or even
‘pedantic’ in
favour of direct experience and simple delight.
The logic of what is sometimes called, in typically ‘pedantic’
language, the
‘reading’ of a work of art, offers an objective basis for this
opposition.
Consumption is, in this case, a stage in a process of
communication, that is, an
act of deciphering, decoding, which presupposes practical or
explicit mastery of a
cipher or code. In a sense, one can say that the capacity to see
(voir) is a function
of the knowledge (savoir), or concepts, that is, the words, that
are available to
name visible things, and which are, as it were, programmes for
perception. A
work of art has meaning and interest only for someone who
possesses the cultural
competence, that is, the code, into which it is encoded. The
conscious or
unconscious implementation of explicit or implicit schemes of
perception and
appreciation which constitutes pictorial or musical culture is the
hidden condition
for recognizing the styles characteristic of a period, a school or
an author, and,
more generally, for the familiarity with the internal logic of
works that aesthetic
enjoyment presupposes. A beholder who lacks the specific code
feels lost in a
chaos of sounds and rhythms, colours and lines, without rhyme
or reason. Not
having learnt to adopt the adequate disposition, he stops short at
what Erwin
Panofsky calls the ‘sensible properties’, perceiving a skin as
downy or lace-work
2
The word disposition seems particularly suited to express what
is covered by the
concept of habitus (defined as a system of dispositions)—used
later in this chapter. It
expresses first the result of an organizing action, with a
meaning close to that of words
such as structure; it also designates a way of being, a habitual
state (especially of the
body) and, in particular, a predisposition, tendency, propensity
or inclination. [The
semantic cluster of ‘disposition’ is rather wider in French than
in English, but as this
note—translated literally—shows, the equivalence is adequate.
Translator.] P. Bourdieu,
Outline of a Theory of Practice (Cambridge, Cambridge
UJniversity Press, 1977), p. 214,
n. 1.
3
as delicate, or at the emotional resonances aroused by these
properties, referring
to ‘austere’ colours or a ‘joyful’ melody. He cannot move from
the ‘primary
stratum of the meaning we can grasp on the basis of our
ordinary experience’ to
the ‘stratum of secondary meanings’, i.e., the ‘level of the
meaning of what is
signified’, unless he possesses the concepts which go beyond
the sensible
properties and which identify the specifically stylistic
properties of the work.
3
Thus the encounter with a work of art is not ‘love at first sight’
as is generally
supposed, and the act of empathy, Einfühlung, which is the art-
lover’s pleasure,
presupposes an act of cognition, a decoding operation, which
implies the
implementation of a cognitive acquirement, a cultural code.
4
This typically intellectualist theory of artistic perception
directly contradicts
the experience of the art-lovers closest to the legitimate
definition; acquisition of
legitimate culture by insensible familiarization within the
family circle tends to
favour an enchanted experience of culture which implies
forgetting the
acquisition.
5
The ‘eye’ is a product of history reproduced by education. This
is
true of the mode of artistic perception now accepted as
legitimate, that is, the
aesthetic disposition, the capacity to consider in and for
themselves, as form
rather than function, not only the works designated for such
apprehension, i.e.,
legitimate works of art, but everything in the world, including
cultural objects
which are not yet consecrated—such as, at one time, primitive
arts, or, nowadays,
3
E. Panofsky, ‘Iconography and Iconology: An Introduction to
the Study of Renaissance
Art’, Meaning in the Visual Arts (New York, Doubleday, 1955),
p. 28.
4
It will be seen that this internalized code called culture
functions as cultural capital
owing to the fact that, being unequally distributed, it secures
profits of distinction.
5
The sense of familiarity in no way excludes the ethnocentric
misunderstanding which
results from applying the wrong code. Thus, Michael
Baxandall’s work in historical
ethnology enables us to measure all that separates the
perceptual schemes that now tend
to be applied to Quattrocento paintings and those which their
immediate addressees
applied. The ‘moral and spiritual eye’ of Quattrocento man, that
is, the set of cognitive
and evaluative dispositions which were the basis of his
perception of the world and his
perception of pictorial representation of the world, differs
radically from the ‘pure’ gaze
(purified, first of all, of reference to economic value) with
which the modern cultivated
spectator looks at works of art. As the contracts show, the
clients of Filippo Lippi,
Domenico Ghirlandaio or Piero della Francesca were concerned
to get ‘value for money’.
They approached works of art with the mercantile dispositions
of a businessman who can
calculate quantities and prices at a glance, and they applied
some surprising criteria of
appreciation, such as the expense of the colours, which sets
gold and ultramarine at the
top of the hierarchy. The artists, who shared this world view,
were led to include
arithmetical and geometrical devices in their compositions so as
to flatter this taste for
measurement and calculation; and they tended to exhibit the
technical virtuosity which, in
this context, is the most visible evidence of the quantity and
quality of the labour
provided; M. Baxandall, Painting and Experience in Fifteenth-
Century Italy: A Primer in
the Social History of Pictorial Style (Oxford, Oxford University
Press, 1972).
4
popular photography or kitsch—and natural objects. The ‘pure’
gaze is a
historical invention linked to the emergence of an autonomous
field of artistic
production, that is, a field capable of imposing its own norms
on both the
production and the consumption of its products.
6
An art which, like all Post-
Impressionist painting, is the product of an artistic intention
which asserts the
primacy of the mode of representation over the object of
representation demands
categorically an attention to form which previous art only
demanded
conditionally.
The pure intention of the artist is that of a producer who aims
to be
autonomous, that is, entirely the master of his product, who
tends to reject not
only the ‘programmes’ imposed a priori by scholars and scribes,
but also—
following the old hierarchy of doing and saying—the
interpretations
superimposed a posteriori on his work. The production of an
‘open work’,
intrinsically and deliberately polysemic, can thus be understood
as the final stage
in the conquest of artistic autonomy by poets and, following in
their footsteps, by
painters, who had long been reliant on writers and their work of
‘showing’ and
‘illustrating’. To assert the autonomy of production is to give
primacy to that of
which the artist is master, i.e., form, manner, style, rather than
the ‘subject’, the
external referent, which involves subordination to functions
even if only the most
elementary one, that of representing, signifying, saying
something. It also means
a refusal to recognize any necessity other than that inscribed in
the specific
tradition of the artistic discipline in question: the shift from an
art which imitates
nature to an art which imitates art, deriving from its own history
the exclusive
source of its experiments and even of its breaks with tradition.
An art which ever
increasingly contains reference to its own history demands to be
perceived
historically; it asks to be referred not to an external referent,
the represented or
designated ‘reality’, but to the universe of past and present
works of art. Like
artistic production, in that it is generated in a field, aesthetic
perception is
necessarily historical, inasmuch as it is differential, relational,
attentive to the
deviations (écarts) which make styles. Like the so-called naive
painter who,
operating outside the held and its specific traditions remains
external to the
history of the art, the ‘naive’ spectator cannot attain a specific
grasp of works of
art which only have meaning—or value—in relation to the
specific history of an
artistic tradition. The aesthetic disposition demanded by the
products of a highly
autonomous field of production is inseparable from a specific
cultural
competence. This historical culture functions as a principle of
pertinence which
enables one to identify, among the elements offered to the gaze,
all the distinctive
features and only these, by referring them, consciously or
unconsciously, to the
6
See P. Bourdieu, ‘Le marché des biens symboliques’, L’Anneé
Sociologique, 22 (1973),
49 126; and ‘Outline of a Sociological Theory of Art
Perception’, International Social
Science Journal, 20 (Winter 1968), 589-612.
5
universe of possible alternatives. This mastery is, for the most
part, acquired
simply by contact with works of art—that is, through an implicit
learning
analogous to that which makes it possible to recognize familiar
faces without
explicit rules or criteria—and it generally remains at a practical
level; it is what
makes it possible to identify styles, i.e., modes of expression
characteristic of a
period, a civilization or a school, without having to distinguish
clearly, or state
explicitly, the features which constitute their originality.
Everything seems to
suggest that even among professional valuers, the criteria which
define the
stylistic properties of the ‘typical works’ on which all their
judgements are based
usually remain implicit.
The pure gaze implies a break with the ordinary attitude
towards the world,
which, given the conditions in which it is performed, is also a
social separation.
Orteya y Gasset can be believed when he attributes to modern
art a systematic
refusal of all that is ‘human’, i.e., generic, common—as
opposed to distinctive, or
distinguished—namely, the passions, emotions and feelings
which ‘ordinary’
people invest in their ‘ordinary’ lives. It is as if the ‘popular
aesthetic’ (the
quotation marks are there to indicate that this is an aesthetic ‘in
itself’ not ‘for
itself’) were based on the affirmation of the continuity between
art and life,
which implies the subordination of form to function. This is
seen clearly in the
case of the novel and especially the theatre, where the working-
class audience
refuses any sort of formal experimentation and all the effects
which, by
introducing a distance from the accepted conventions (as
regards scenery, plot
etc.), tend to distance the spectator, preventing him from getting
involved and
fully identifying with the characters (I am thinking of Brechtian
‘alienation’ or
the disruption of plot in the nouveau roman). In contrast to the
detachment and
disinterestedness which aesthetic theory regards as the only way
of recognizing
the work of art for what it is, i.e., autonomous, selbständig, the
‘popular
aesthetic’ ignores or refuses the refusal of ‘facile’ involvement
and ‘vulgar’
enjoyment, a refusal which is the basis of the taste for formal
experiment. And
popular judgements of paintings or photographs spring from an
‘aesthetic’ (in
fact it is an ethos) which is the exact opposite of the Kantian
aesthetic. Whereas,
in order to grasp the specificity of the aesthetic judgement, Kant
strove to
distinguish that which pleases from that which gratifies and,
more generally, to
distinguish disinterestedness, the sole guarantor of the
specifically aesthetic
quality of contemplation, from the interest of reason which
defines the Good,
working-class people expect every image to explicitly perform a
function, if only
that of a sign, and their judgements make reference, often
explicitly, to the norms
of morality or agreeableness. Whether rejecting or praising,
their appreciation
always has an ethical basis.
Popular taste applies the schemes of the ethos, which pertain
in the ordinary
circumstances of life, to legitimate works of art, and so
performs a systematic
reduction of the things of art to the things of life. The very
seriousness (or
6
naivety) which this taste invests in fictions and representations
demonstrates a
contrario that pure taste performs a suspension of ‘naive’
involvement which is
one dimension of a ‘quasi-ludic’ relationship with the
necessities of the world.
Intellectuals could be said to believe in the representation—
literature, theatre,
painting—more than in the things represented, whereas the
people chiefly expect
representations and the conventions which govern them to allow
them to believe
‘naively’ in the things represented. The pure aesthetic is rooted
in an ethic, or
rather, an ethos of elective distance from the necessities of the
natural and social
world, which may take the form of moral agnosticism (visible
when ethical
transgression becomes an artistic parti pris) or of an
aestheticism which presents
the aesthetic disposition as a universally valid principle and
takes the bourgeois
denial of the social world to its limit. The detachment of the
pure gaze cannot be
dissociated from a general disposition towards the world which
is the paradoxical
product of conditioning by negative economic necessities—a
life of ease—that
tends to induce an active distance from necessity.
Although art obviously offers the greatest scope to the
aesthetic disposition,
there is no area of practice in which the aim of purifying,
refining and
sublimating primary needs and impulses cannot assert itself, no
area in which the
stylization of life, that is, the primacy of forms over function,
of manner over
matter, does not produce the same effects. And nothing is more
distinctive, more
distinguished, than the capacity to confer aesthetic status on
objects that are banal
or even ‘common’ (because the ‘common’ people make them
their own,
especially for aesthetic purposes), or the ability to apply the
principles of a ‘pure’
aesthetic to the most everyday choices of everyday life, e.g., in
cooking, clothing
or decoration, completely reversing the popular disposition
which annexes
aesthetics to ethics.
In fact, through the economic and social conditions which they
presuppose,
the different ways of relating to realities and fictions, of
believing in fictions and
the realities they simulate, with more or less distance and
detachment, are very
closely linked to the different possible positions in social space
and,
consequently, bound up with the systems of dispositions
(habitus) characteristic
of the different classes and class fractions. Taste classifies, and
it classifies the
classifier. Social subjects, classified by their classifications,
distinguish
themselves by the distinctions they make, between the beautiful
and the ugly, the
distinguished and the vulgar, in which their position in the
objective
classifications is expressed or betrayed. And statistical analysis
does indeed show
that oppositions similar in structure to those found in cultural
practices also
appear in eating habits. The antithesis between quantity and
quality, substance
and form, corresponds to the opposition—linked to different
distances from
necessity—between the taste of necessity, which favours the
most ‘filling’ and
most economical foods, and the taste of liberty or luxury—
which shifts the
7
emphasis to the manner (of presenting, serving, eating etc.) and
tends to use
stylized forms to deny function.
The science of taste and of cultural consumption begins with a
transgression
that is in no way aesthetic: it has to abolish the sacred frontier
which makes
legitimate culture a separate universe, in order to discover the
intelligible
relations which unite apparently incommensurable ‘choices’,
such as preferences
in music and food, painting and sport, literature and hairstyle.
This barbarous
reintegration of aesthetic consumption into the world of
ordinary consumption
abolishes the opposition, which has been the basis of high
aesthetics since Kant,
between the ‘taste of sense’ and the ‘taste of reflection’, and
between facile
pleasure, pleasure reduced to a pleasure of the senses, and pure
pleasure, pleasure
purified of pleasure, which is predisposed to become a symbol
of moral
excellence and a measure of the capacity for sublimation which
defines the truly
human man. The culture which results from this magical
division is sacred.
Cultural consecration does indeed confer on the objects, persons
and situations it
touches, a sort of ontological promotion akin to a
transubstantiation. Proof
enough of this is found in the two following quotations, which
might almost have
been written for the delight of the sociologist:
‘What struck me most is this: nothing could be obscene on the
stage of our
premier theatre, and the ballerinas of the Opera, even as naked
dancers, sylphs,
sprites or Bacchae, retain an inviolable purity.’
7
‘There are obscene postures: the stimulated intercourse which
offends the
eye. Clearly, it is impossible to approve, although the
interpolation of such
gestures in dance routines does give them a symbolic and
aesthetic quality which
is absent from the intimate scenes the cinema daily flaunts
before its spectators’
eyes . . . As for the nude scene, what can one say, except that it
is brief and
theatrically not very effective? I will not say it is chaste or
innocent, for nothing
commercial can be so described. Let us say it is not shocking,
and that the chief
objection is that it serves as a box-office gimmick. . . . In Hair,
the nakedness
fails to be symbolic.’
8
The denial of lower, coarse, vulgar, venal, servile—in a word,
natural—
enjoyment, which constitutes the sacred sphere of culture,
implies an affirmation
of the superiority of those who can be satisfied with the
sublimated, refined,
disinterested, gratuitous, distinguished pleasures forever closed
to the profane.
That is why art and cultural consumption are predisposed,
consciously and
deliberately or not, to fulfil a social function of legitimating
social differences.
Translated by Richard Nice
7
O. Merlin, ‘Mlle. Thibon dans la vision de Marguerite’, Le
Monde, 9 December 1965.
8
F. Chenique, ‘Hair est-il immoral?’ Le Monde, 28 January
1970.
2. 0 4 THE CONSUMER SOCIETY READER
personally. For this is the basis of award of the instinct of
workmanship,-
and that instinct is the court of final appeal in any question of
economic
truth or adequacy. It is a question as to the award rendered by
passionate common sense. The question is, therefore, not
whether, under
the existing circumstances of individual habit and social
custom, a given
expenditure conduces to the particular consumer's gratification
or peace
of mind; but whether, aside from acquired tastes and from the
canons
of usage and conventional decency, its result is a net gain in
comfort or
in the fulness of life. Customary expenditure must be classed
under the
head of waste in so far as the custom on which it rests is
traceable to
the habit of making an invidious pecuniary comparison-in so far
as it
is conceived that it could not have become customary and
prescriptive
without the backing of this principle of pecuniary reputability
or relative
economic success.
It is obviously not necessary that a given object of expenditure
should
be exclusively wasteful in order to come in under the category
of con-
spicuous waste. An article may be useful and wasteful both, and
its
utility to the consumer may be made up of use and waste in the
most
varying proportions. Consumable goods, and even productive
goods,
generally show the two elements in combination, as constituents
of their
utility; although, in a general way, the element of waste tends to
pre-
dominate in articles of consumption, while the contrary is true
of articles
designed for productive use. Even in articles which appear at
first glance
to serve for pure ostentation only, it is always possible to detect
the
presence of some, at least ostensible, useful purpose; and on the
other
hand, even in special machinery and tools contrived for some
particular
industrial process, as well as in the rudest appliances of human
industry,
the traces of conspicuous waste, or at least of the habit of
ostentation,
usually become evident on a close scrutiny. It would be
hazardous to
assert that a useful purpose is ever absent from the utility of any
article
or of any service, however obviously its prime purpose and
chief element
is conspicuous waste; and it would be only less hazardous to
assert of
any primarily useful product that the element of waste is in no
way
concerned in its value, immediately or remotely.
12
Pierre Bourdieu
"THE AESTHETIC SENSE AS THE
SENSE OF DISTINCTION"
(1979; translation 19 84)
The aesthetic disposition is one dimension of a distant, self-
assured relation to the world and to others which presupposes
objective
assurance and distance. It is one manifestation of the system of
dispo-
sitions produced by the social conditionings associated with a
particular
class of conditions of existence when they take the paradoxical
form of
the greatest freedom conceivable, at a given moment, with
respect to
the constraints of economic necessity. But it is also a distinctive
expres-
sion of a privileged position in social space whose distinctive
value is
objectively established in its relationship to expressions
generated from
different conditions. Like every sort of taste, it unites and
separates.
Being the product of the conditionings associated with a
particular class
of conditions of existence, it unites all those who are the
product of
similar conditions while distinguishing them from all others.
And it dis-
tinguishes in an essential way, since taste is the basis of all that
one
has-people and things-and all that one is for others, whereby
one
classifies oneself and is classified by others.
Tastes (i.e., manifested preferences) are the practical
affirmation of an
inevitable difference. It is no accident that, when they have to
be justi-
fied, they are asserted purely negatively, by the refusal of other
tastes. I
In matters of taste, more than anywhere else, all determination
is ne-
and tastes are perhaps first and foremost distastes, disgust pro-
voked by horror or visceral intolerance ("sick-making") of the
tastes of
others. "De gustibus non est disputandum": not because "taus
les gouts
sont dans la nature," but because each taste feels itself to be
natural-
and so it almost is, being a habitus-which amounts to rejecting
others
as unnatural and therefore vicious. Aesthetic intolerance can be
terribly
violent. Aversion to different life-styles is perhaps one of the
strongest
barriers between the classes; class endogamy is evidence of
this. The
most intolerable thing for those who regard themselves as the
possessors
of legitimate culture is the sacrilegious reuniting of tastes
which taste
"."'.11, tloi dictates shall be separated. This means that the
games of artists and
aesthetes and their struggles for the monopoly of artistic
legitimacy are
-,=
'"'''1'''
-"! .::
loOO THE CONSUMER SOCIETY READER
less innocent than they seem. At stake in every struggle over art
there c
is also the imposition of an art of living, that is, the
transmutation of
an arbitrary way of living into the legitimate way of life which
casts
every other way of living into arbitrariness.; The artist's life-
style. is
always a challenge thrown at the bourgeois life-style, which it
seeks to
condemn as unreal and even absurd, by a sort of practical
demonstra-
tion of the emptiness of the values and powers it pursues. The
neutral-
izing relation to the world which defines dle aesthetic
disposition
potentially implies a subversion of the spirit of seriousness
required by
bourgeois investments. Like the visibly ethical judgments of
those who
lack the means to make art the basis of dleir art of living, to see
the
world and other people through literary reminiscences and
pictorial ref-
erences, the "pure" and purely aesthetic judgments of the artist
and the
aesthete spring from the dispositions of an ethos;4 but because
of 'tp.e _
legitimacy which they command so long as their relationship to
the dis-
positions and interests of a group defined by strong cultural
capital and
weak economic capital remains unrecognized, they provide a
sort:of
absolute reference point in the necessarily endless play of
mutually self':'
relativizing tastes. By a paradoxical reversal, dley thereby help
to
imate the bourgeois claim to "natural distinction" as difference
made
absolute.
Objectively and subjectively aesthetic stances adopted in
matters like
cosmetics, clodling or home decoration are opportunities to
experience
or assert one's position in social space, as a rank to be upheld or
a
distance to be kept. It goes without saying that the social
classes are not
equally inclined and prepared to enter this game of refusal and
coun-
terrefusal; and that the strategies aimed at transforming the
basic dis ...
positions of a life-style into a system of aesthetic principles,
objective
differences into elective distinctions, passive options
(constituted exeer ...
nally by the logic of the distinctive relationships) into
conscious, elective
choices are in fact reserved for members of the dominant class,
indeed
the very top bourgeoisie, and for artists, who as the inventors
and pro"
fessionals of the "stylization of life" are alone able to make
their art of
living one of dIe fine arts. By contrast, the entry of the petite
into the game of distinction is marked, inter alia, by the anxiety
of
exposing ones'elf to classification by offering to the taste of
others such
infallible indices of personal taste as clothes or furniture, even
a simple
pair of armchairs, as in one of Nathalie Sarraute's novels. As for
the
working classes, perhaps their sole function in the system of
aesthetic
positions is to serve as a foil, a negative reference point, in
relation to
which all aesthetics define themselves, by successive negations.
s Ignoring
or ignorant of manner and style, the "aesthetic" (in itself) of the
working
classes and culturally most deprived fractions of the middle
classes
fines as "nice," "pretty," "lovely" (rather than "beautiful")
things that
are already defined as such in the "aesthetic" of calendars and
postcards:
THE AESTHETCC SENSE AS THE SENSE OF
DISTCNCTCON lo07
a sunset, a lirtle girl playing with a cat, a folk dance, an old
master, a
first communion, a children's procession. The striving toward
distinction
comes in with petit-bourgeois aestheticism, which delights in all
the
cheap substitutes for chic objects and practices-driftwood and
painted
pebbles, cane and raffia, "art" handicrafts and art photography.
This aestheticism defines itself against the "aesthetic" of the
working
classes, refusing their favorite subjects, the themes of "views,"
such as
mountain landscapes, sunsets and woods, or souvenir photos,
such as
the first communion, the monument or the old master (see
diagram I).
In photography, this taste prefers objects that are close to those
of the
popular aesthetic but semi-neutralized by more or less explicit
reference
to a pictorial tradition or by a visible stylistic intention
combining the
human picturesque (weaver at his loom, tramps quarreling, folk
dance)
with gratuitous form (pebbles, rope, tree bark).
It is significant dlat this middle-brow art par excellence finds
one of
its preferred subjects in one of the spectacles most
characteristic of
middle-brow culture (along with the circus, light opera and
bull-fights),
the folk dance (which is particularly appreciated by skilled
workers and
foremen, junior executives, clerical and commercial employees)
(C.S.
VII). Like the photographic recording of the social picturesque,
whose
populist objectivism distances dIe lower classes by constituting
them as
an object of contemplation or even commiseration or
indignation, the
spectacle of the "people" making a spectacle of itself, as in folk
dancing,
is an opportunity to experience the relationship of distant
proximity, in
the form of the idealized vision purveyed by aesthetic realism
and po-
pulist nostalgia, which is a basic element in the relationship of
the petite
bourgeoisie to the working or peasant classes and their
traditions. But
this middle-brow aestheticism in turn serves as a foil to the
most alert
members of the new middle-class fractions, who reject its
favored sub-
jects, and to the secondary teachers whose aestheticism (the
aestheticism
of consumers, since they are relatively infrequent practitioners
of pho-
tography and the other arts) purports to be able to treat any
object
aesthetically, with the exception of those so constituted by the
middle-
brow art of the petite bourgeoisie (such as the weaver and the
folk
dance, which are deemed merely "interesting").6 These would-
be aes-
thetes demonstrate by their distinctive refusals that they possess
the
practical mastery of the relationships between objects and
groups which
is the basis of all judgments of the type "<;::a fait" ("It looks
...") ("<;::a
fait petit-bourgeois," "<;::a fait nouveau riche," etc.), without
being able
to go so far as to ascribe beauty to the most marked objects of
the
popular aesthetic (first communion) or the petit-bourgeois
aesthetic
(mother and child, folk dance) which the relations of structural
prox-
imity spontaneously lead them to detest.
Explicit aesthetic choices are in fact often constituted in
opposition
to the choices of the groups closest in social space, with whom
the
. L L _.. &.£2&&&&£ dL
THE AESTHETIC SENSE AS THE SENSE OF DISTINCTION
2.09
competition is most direct and most immediate, and more
precisely, no
doubt, in relation to those choices most clearly marked by the
intention { (perceived as pretension) of marking distinction vis-
a-vis lower groups,
"" such as, for intellectuals, the primary teachers' Brassens,
Jean Ferrat or§] ·1 ::a i ... Ferre. Thus 'the song, as a cultural
property which (like photography)
',1:1 la .s is almost universally accessible and genuinely
common (since hardly 8,g ; a i i -:- i 13 -e 111
anyone is not exposed at one moment or another to the
"successes" of s II iii j '6ll..lS POUlJa tJ1 the day), calls for
particular vigilance from those who intend to mark
their difference. The intellectuals, artists and higher-education
teachers
CIl seem to hesitate between systematic refusal of what can
only be, at best,
a middle-brow art, and a selective acceptance which manifests
the uni- E gI3J e § " ] Ii '§ versality of their culture and their
aesthetic disposition.' For their part, .... 'B
'1:1" ::I 1 J11 8. ... ... tl L11e. the employers and professionals,
who have little interest in the "intel-
i-8 j J " i :s i ! h: j j B 1 lectual" song, indicate their distance
from ordinary songs by rejecting
'" III with disgust the most popular and most "vulgar" singers,
such as Lesiii 'bi. oS .8 1 I § '5 j I j
Compagnons de la Chanson, Mireille Madlieu, Adamo or Sheila,
and
tl s making an exception for the oldest and most consecrated
singers (like
j
.g,. Edith Piaf or Charles Trenet) or those closest to operetta
and bel canto .
;; f.... !i _ But it is the middle classes who find in song (as in
photography) an
opportunity to manifest their artistic pretension by refusing the
favorite Ii /I: IS til8. 'B J 8 il i -:i 1=!.,fA .c singers of the
working classes, such as Mireille Mathieu, Adamo, I:lIl " iE-i'i t
e Charles Aznavour or Tino Rossi, and declaring their
preference for the :!l
Fi a-crgi11! singers who endeavour to dignify this "minor"
genre. That is why the
'0 '" primary teachers distinguish themselves most clearly from
the other frac-
&b tions of the petite bourgeoisie in this area, where, more
easily than in5 f =.8[ rs the domain of legitimate art, they can
invest their academic dispositions IS ,1; • and assert their own
taste in the choice of singers who offer populist 0 e -1!l '§8,05
poetry in the primary-school tradition, such as Jacques Douai or
Bras-1 e• H ,Q £ IS 5 ri ... 13 '0.1. S-rse. ",111.<:1 sens (who
was on the syllabus of the Saint-Cloud entrance examination .£l
ii1>!-6 .<•.I'6 a few years agol. s •.,,)I:,el §l:1i!i oa1'i
,Q5 i IfI j f1 ;e:l 01 Ul_..2 '6ll II: '0 tl ¢l IS til . It may also be
assumed that the affirmation of the omnipotence of
'J:! the aesthetic gaze found among higher-education teachers,
the group ·8
most inclined to say that all the objects mentioned could make a
beau-fi'5
as
{:i$=€ I'B tiful photograph and to profess their recognition of
modern art or of
- .'P. .,.i i f = ! I ,j'j",il ..s .!. the artistic status of the
photograph, stems much more from a self-'B § distinguishing
intention than from a true aesthetic universalism. This . 1:l. .s
,Q e 11 ! "y-- j '.!;i:U fIJ i '" .", 'tI >. '" "'.<:I has not escaped
dIe most knowing avant-garde producers, who carry ... fl 0 '+of
"'111 -:u )J;j'r,.. 13
til /I: S ;:. (J SS:.':lO -:=<U u ii 0 sufficient authority to
challenge, if need be, the very dogma of the om-t:i'!i. ]i :9 OJ
',1:1 a r.1' g = O{,jO,ii(l}.,Q
nipotence of art,9 and are in a position to recognize this faith as
a de-.-.
"'" Ii: fensive maneuver to avoid self-exposure by reckless
refusals: "Who
Ii! ;2··:' would say this: 'When I look at a picture, I'm not
interested in what it
is _ i'l represents'? Nowadays, the sort of people who don't
know much about s,!o! I art. Saying that is typical of someone
who hasn't any idea about art. ::E-5
. (I Twenty years ago, I'm not even sure that twenty years ago
the abstract
'A:f.' r
painters would have said that; I don't think so. It's exactly what
a guy
{4Y:
"
EmmELL 22 i §li§b44J1&iJZYMi.,." 3L 1 ".MUiL .. __
2.IO THE CONSUMER SOCIETY READER
says when he hasn't a clue: 'I'm not one ,of these old fogies, I
know
what counts is whether it's pretty' " (avant-garde painter, age
35). They
alone, at aU events, can afford the audacious imposture of
refusing all
refusals by recuperating, ill parody or sublimation, the very
objects re-
fused by the lower-degree aesdteticism. The "rehabilitation" of
"vulgar"
objects is more risky, but, also more "profitable," the smaller
the dis-
tance in social space or time, and the "horrors" of popular
kitsch are
easier to "recuperate" than those of petit-bourgeois imitation,
just .as
the "abominations" of bourgeois taste can begin to be found
"amusing"
when they are sufficiendy dated to' cease to be "compromising."
The artist agrees with the "bourgeois" in one respect: he prefers
naiv-
ety to: '; The essential merit of the "common people"
is that they have none of the pretensions to art (or power) which
inspire
the ambitions of the ,"petit' bourgeois." Their indifference
tacitly ac-
knowledges the monopoly. That is why, in the mythology of
artists and
intellectuals, whose outflanking and double-negating strategies
times lead them back to "popular" tastes and opinions, the
"people"
so often playa role not unlike that of the peasantry in the
conservative
ideologies of the declining aristocracy.
ENDNOTES
r. Two examples, chosen from among hundreds, bur
paradigmatic, of explicit
use of the scheme "something other than": "La Fiancee du pirate
is one of
those very true French films that are really satirical, really
funny, because it
does not resort to the carefully defused, prudently inoffensive
comedy one
finds in La Grande 'adreuille and Ie Petit Baiglzeur . ... In
short, it IS some-
thing other than the dreary hackwork of boulevard farce" U. L.
Bory, Le
Nouvel Observateur) 8 December 1969: italics mine). "Through
distance, or
at [east, dlcough difterence, to endeavour to present a text on
pictorial mo-
dernity other than the hackneyed banalities of a certain style 07
art criticism.
Between verbose aphasia, the textual transcription of picrures.
endamations
of recognition, and the works of specialized aesthetics, perhal?s
marking some-
of dIe ways in which conceptual, theoretical work gets to gnps
with contem-
porary production" (G. Gassiot-Talabot et al., Figurations 1960-
1973 [Paris, Union generale des editions, 19731. p. 7; italics
mine).
2.. This essential negativity, which is part of the very logic of
the constitution of
taste and its change, explains why, as Gambrich points out, "the
temlinol-
ogy of art history was so larliely built on words dena ring some
principle of
exclusion. Most movements m art erect some new taboo, some
new negative
principle, such as the banishing from painting by the
impressionists of all
'anecdotal' elements. The positive slogans and shibboleths
which we read in
artists' or critics' manifestos past or present are usually much
less well de-
fined" (E. H. Gombrich, News and Form: Studies in the Art of
the Renais-
sance [London, New York, Phaidon Press, I966J, p. 89).
3· This is seen clearly in the case of the theater, which touches
more directly
and more overtly on the implicit or explicit principles of the art
of living.
Especially in the case of comedy, it presul?Poses common
values or interests
or, more precisely, a complicity and connIvance based on
immediate assent
to the same self-evident propositions, dIose of the doxa, dIe
totality of opin-
ions accepted at the level of pre-reflective belief. (This explains
why the insti-
tutions supplying the products, and the products themselves, are
more
sharply differentiated m the theater than in any other art.)
THE AESTHETlC SENSE AS THE SENSE OF DISTINCTlON
2.11
4. For an analysis of "art for art's sake" as the expression of the
artistic life-
style, see P. Bourdieu, "L'invention de la vie d'artiste," Actes,
2. (1975), 67-
93·
5. This is true despite the apparent exception in which some
artists return to
certain popular ,Preferences, which haC! a totally different
meaning in a cul-
tural configuranon dominated by choices which for them would
be quite im-
probable or even impossible. These returns to the "popular"
style, which
often pass for a return to the "people" are detennined not by any
genuine
relationship to tbe working classes, who are generally spumed-
even in ide-
alization, which is a form of refusal-but by the internal relations
of the
field of artistic production or the field of the dominant class.
(This point has
a general validity, and one would need to examine what the
writings of in-
tellectuals on the working classes owe to the specific interests
of intellectuals
in struggles in which what is at stake, if not the people, is the
legitimacy
conferred, in certain conditions, by appearing as dIe spokesman
for popular
interests. )
6. It is in dlese two categories that we encounter the most
marked refusal of
souvenir photos ("Souvenir photos are stupid and banal"; "The
main point
of a photo is to preserve the images of those one loves"), of
realism in paint-
ing (" A beautiful picture should reproduce what is beautiful in
nature'" or
in photography ("For a ehotograph to be good, you just have to
be ab e to
recognize what it shows), and die most resolute assertion of
faith in mod-
em painting (in refusal of the opinion: "Modern painting is just
slapped on
anyhow ..... 1.
7. One of the major limitations imfosed by tbe list of pre.formed
choices is
that it does not bring out these conflicts" and the strategies
aimed at get-
ting around them. A respondent who has, "against the chosen
Geor-
ges Brassens or Jacques Douai might have been able to mdicate
his refusal of
song, while showing his "open-mindedness," by citing (with an
implicit rede-
finition) something by Kurt Weill or an ola Neap,olitan song.
(The France-
Musique radio pro&ram of "personal selections, ' "Le concert
egoiste," is
very revealing in thIS respect.)
8. Saint-Cloud: second to ENS me d'Ulm in the hierarchy of the
Ecoles norma-
les superieures (translator).
9. This dogma is still recognized and professed in less advanced
sectors of the
field of artistic production, as this typical declaration shows:
"However, I
will say that these paintings by Gaston Planet are totally
incomprehensible: I
wiU say that I like tbem to be so. Not enigmatic. But entirely
mute. Without
points of reference. Without distractions" (Paul Rossi, Gaston
Planet cata-
logue).
')',,. - " KSLE£.. n .. ]22_. &2i&£§!...t%·JJ..
•.f..il&Mii&E§1";;;:;;;t!$!£.£&E_ t. i£b..'ii'M4Jib..:.<m¥! w.L
t.liXZ tl&Qk4t .
Soc 210 – Sociology of Culture:
Exam #2 – Short Essay
Short Essay Questions:
1. As Bourdieu tells us cultural capital is not only about the
objects of consumption. What is a potentially even more
important cultural capital resource (think language)? Further,
what does Bourdieu mean when he says: “it is no accident that
when tastes have to be justified they are asserted purely
negatively”? How is this related to symbolic violence? Make
sure you define symbolic violence.
2. Holt describes six dimensions of taste and consumption
practice in American society. Describe three of these
dimensions. Be sure to explain what freedom from necessity
has to do with cultural taste and why cultural capital cannot be
reduced to economic capital according to Holt.
Be sure to answer every part of the question; you should be able
to answer these in around 1 page (double spaced, one inch
margins, 12 point Times New Roman font (points will be taken
off for not following this format)). For full credit, answer the
question fully, use examples, cite sociological and media
articles, refer to the discussion boards when necessary and be
sure to use your own language. That is, do not simply copy my
Power Point notes; doing that does not demonstrate an
understanding of the course material. Once again, attach a file
as well as paste the text directly into the submission text box in
this assignment.

More Related Content

Similar to Copyright © 1998. All rights reserved.Copyright © 1998.docx

Different Culture - Different sign perception
Different Culture - Different sign perceptionDifferent Culture - Different sign perception
Different Culture - Different sign perceptionguest5efb65
 
Week 1 definition and meaning
Week 1 definition and meaningWeek 1 definition and meaning
Week 1 definition and meaningCarlo Caharian
 
LAS-ARTS-CONTEMPORARY-12-Q1-WEEK3-ADONIS.CAPULONG.pdf
LAS-ARTS-CONTEMPORARY-12-Q1-WEEK3-ADONIS.CAPULONG.pdfLAS-ARTS-CONTEMPORARY-12-Q1-WEEK3-ADONIS.CAPULONG.pdf
LAS-ARTS-CONTEMPORARY-12-Q1-WEEK3-ADONIS.CAPULONG.pdfAdonisMCapulong
 
Introduction to Musicology Lecture
Introduction to Musicology LectureIntroduction to Musicology Lecture
Introduction to Musicology LecturePaul Carr
 
Art Appreciation Course
Art Appreciation CourseArt Appreciation Course
Art Appreciation CourseScott Donald
 
Analysis of an object from the beginnings of civilization to.docx
Analysis of an object from the beginnings of civilization to.docxAnalysis of an object from the beginnings of civilization to.docx
Analysis of an object from the beginnings of civilization to.docxwrite22
 
httpwww.jstor.orgMind in Matter An Introduction to Mat.docx
httpwww.jstor.orgMind in Matter An Introduction to Mat.docxhttpwww.jstor.orgMind in Matter An Introduction to Mat.docx
httpwww.jstor.orgMind in Matter An Introduction to Mat.docxsheronlewthwaite
 
ARTS APPRECIATIONssfsdgfsegergwtegwergtergdfghergsger
ARTS APPRECIATIONssfsdgfsegergwtegwergtergdfghergsgerARTS APPRECIATIONssfsdgfsegergwtegwergtergdfghergsger
ARTS APPRECIATIONssfsdgfsegergwtegwergtergdfghergsgerJustinDaveGallardo
 
11 Art and Ethics Peggy Blood and Pamela J. Sachant 11
11 Art and Ethics Peggy Blood and Pamela J. Sachant 1111 Art and Ethics Peggy Blood and Pamela J. Sachant 11
11 Art and Ethics Peggy Blood and Pamela J. Sachant 11SantosConleyha
 
11 Art and Ethics Peggy Blood and Pamela J. Sachant 11
11 Art and Ethics Peggy Blood and Pamela J. Sachant 1111 Art and Ethics Peggy Blood and Pamela J. Sachant 11
11 Art and Ethics Peggy Blood and Pamela J. Sachant 11BenitoSumpter862
 
BASIC CONCEPTS OF LITERATURE
BASIC CONCEPTS OF LITERATUREBASIC CONCEPTS OF LITERATURE
BASIC CONCEPTS OF LITERATUREshahzadebaujiti
 
CATC / PhD Presentation - Brussels June 2015 (G. Tordzro)
CATC / PhD Presentation - Brussels June 2015 (G. Tordzro)CATC / PhD Presentation - Brussels June 2015 (G. Tordzro)
CATC / PhD Presentation - Brussels June 2015 (G. Tordzro)RMBorders
 
LING 305 WCOLFV analysis of the Planned Parenthood Fact SheetR.docx
LING 305 WCOLFV analysis of the Planned Parenthood Fact SheetR.docxLING 305 WCOLFV analysis of the Planned Parenthood Fact SheetR.docx
LING 305 WCOLFV analysis of the Planned Parenthood Fact SheetR.docxSHIVA101531
 
Aesthetics Versus Art History
Aesthetics Versus Art HistoryAesthetics Versus Art History
Aesthetics Versus Art HistoryClaire Webber
 
TOK_SB_IBDIP_CH8(full permission).pdf
TOK_SB_IBDIP_CH8(full permission).pdfTOK_SB_IBDIP_CH8(full permission).pdf
TOK_SB_IBDIP_CH8(full permission).pdfRodneyFrankCUADROSMI
 
13. arts as knowledge
13. arts as knowledge13. arts as knowledge
13. arts as knowledgeJustin Morris
 

Similar to Copyright © 1998. All rights reserved.Copyright © 1998.docx (20)

Different Culture - Different sign perception
Different Culture - Different sign perceptionDifferent Culture - Different sign perception
Different Culture - Different sign perception
 
Week 1 definition and meaning
Week 1 definition and meaningWeek 1 definition and meaning
Week 1 definition and meaning
 
LAS-ARTS-CONTEMPORARY-12-Q1-WEEK3-ADONIS.CAPULONG.pdf
LAS-ARTS-CONTEMPORARY-12-Q1-WEEK3-ADONIS.CAPULONG.pdfLAS-ARTS-CONTEMPORARY-12-Q1-WEEK3-ADONIS.CAPULONG.pdf
LAS-ARTS-CONTEMPORARY-12-Q1-WEEK3-ADONIS.CAPULONG.pdf
 
Fall15Module2.2
Fall15Module2.2Fall15Module2.2
Fall15Module2.2
 
Introduction to Musicology Lecture
Introduction to Musicology LectureIntroduction to Musicology Lecture
Introduction to Musicology Lecture
 
Art Appreciation Course
Art Appreciation CourseArt Appreciation Course
Art Appreciation Course
 
Analysis of an object from the beginnings of civilization to.docx
Analysis of an object from the beginnings of civilization to.docxAnalysis of an object from the beginnings of civilization to.docx
Analysis of an object from the beginnings of civilization to.docx
 
Humanities Essays
Humanities EssaysHumanities Essays
Humanities Essays
 
httpwww.jstor.orgMind in Matter An Introduction to Mat.docx
httpwww.jstor.orgMind in Matter An Introduction to Mat.docxhttpwww.jstor.orgMind in Matter An Introduction to Mat.docx
httpwww.jstor.orgMind in Matter An Introduction to Mat.docx
 
Semiotics Essay
Semiotics EssaySemiotics Essay
Semiotics Essay
 
ARTS APPRECIATIONssfsdgfsegergwtegwergtergdfghergsger
ARTS APPRECIATIONssfsdgfsegergwtegwergtergdfghergsgerARTS APPRECIATIONssfsdgfsegergwtegwergtergdfghergsger
ARTS APPRECIATIONssfsdgfsegergwtegwergtergdfghergsger
 
SUMMER15UVC4
SUMMER15UVC4SUMMER15UVC4
SUMMER15UVC4
 
11 Art and Ethics Peggy Blood and Pamela J. Sachant 11
11 Art and Ethics Peggy Blood and Pamela J. Sachant 1111 Art and Ethics Peggy Blood and Pamela J. Sachant 11
11 Art and Ethics Peggy Blood and Pamela J. Sachant 11
 
11 Art and Ethics Peggy Blood and Pamela J. Sachant 11
11 Art and Ethics Peggy Blood and Pamela J. Sachant 1111 Art and Ethics Peggy Blood and Pamela J. Sachant 11
11 Art and Ethics Peggy Blood and Pamela J. Sachant 11
 
BASIC CONCEPTS OF LITERATURE
BASIC CONCEPTS OF LITERATUREBASIC CONCEPTS OF LITERATURE
BASIC CONCEPTS OF LITERATURE
 
CATC / PhD Presentation - Brussels June 2015 (G. Tordzro)
CATC / PhD Presentation - Brussels June 2015 (G. Tordzro)CATC / PhD Presentation - Brussels June 2015 (G. Tordzro)
CATC / PhD Presentation - Brussels June 2015 (G. Tordzro)
 
LING 305 WCOLFV analysis of the Planned Parenthood Fact SheetR.docx
LING 305 WCOLFV analysis of the Planned Parenthood Fact SheetR.docxLING 305 WCOLFV analysis of the Planned Parenthood Fact SheetR.docx
LING 305 WCOLFV analysis of the Planned Parenthood Fact SheetR.docx
 
Aesthetics Versus Art History
Aesthetics Versus Art HistoryAesthetics Versus Art History
Aesthetics Versus Art History
 
TOK_SB_IBDIP_CH8(full permission).pdf
TOK_SB_IBDIP_CH8(full permission).pdfTOK_SB_IBDIP_CH8(full permission).pdf
TOK_SB_IBDIP_CH8(full permission).pdf
 
13. arts as knowledge
13. arts as knowledge13. arts as knowledge
13. arts as knowledge
 

More from maxinesmith73660

You have been chosen to present in front of your local governing boa.docx
You have been chosen to present in front of your local governing boa.docxYou have been chosen to present in front of your local governing boa.docx
You have been chosen to present in front of your local governing boa.docxmaxinesmith73660
 
You have been charged with overseeing the implementation of cybersec.docx
You have been charged with overseeing the implementation of cybersec.docxYou have been charged with overseeing the implementation of cybersec.docx
You have been charged with overseeing the implementation of cybersec.docxmaxinesmith73660
 
You have been commissioned to create a manual covering the installat.docx
You have been commissioned to create a manual covering the installat.docxYou have been commissioned to create a manual covering the installat.docx
You have been commissioned to create a manual covering the installat.docxmaxinesmith73660
 
You have been challenged by a mentor you respect and admire to demon.docx
You have been challenged by a mentor you respect and admire to demon.docxYou have been challenged by a mentor you respect and admire to demon.docx
You have been challenged by a mentor you respect and admire to demon.docxmaxinesmith73660
 
You have been chosen as the consultant group to assess the organizat.docx
You have been chosen as the consultant group to assess the organizat.docxYou have been chosen as the consultant group to assess the organizat.docx
You have been chosen as the consultant group to assess the organizat.docxmaxinesmith73660
 
You have been assigned a reading by WMF Petrie; Diospolis Parva (.docx
You have been assigned a reading by WMF Petrie; Diospolis Parva (.docxYou have been assigned a reading by WMF Petrie; Diospolis Parva (.docx
You have been assigned a reading by WMF Petrie; Diospolis Parva (.docxmaxinesmith73660
 
You have been asked to speak to city, municipal, and state elected a.docx
You have been asked to speak to city, municipal, and state elected a.docxYou have been asked to speak to city, municipal, and state elected a.docx
You have been asked to speak to city, municipal, and state elected a.docxmaxinesmith73660
 
You have been asked to provide a presentation, covering the history .docx
You have been asked to provide a presentation, covering the history .docxYou have been asked to provide a presentation, covering the history .docx
You have been asked to provide a presentation, covering the history .docxmaxinesmith73660
 
You have been asked to organize a community health fair at a loc.docx
You have been asked to organize a community health fair at a loc.docxYou have been asked to organize a community health fair at a loc.docx
You have been asked to organize a community health fair at a loc.docxmaxinesmith73660
 
You have been asked to explain the differences between certain categ.docx
You have been asked to explain the differences between certain categ.docxYou have been asked to explain the differences between certain categ.docx
You have been asked to explain the differences between certain categ.docxmaxinesmith73660
 
You have been asked to evaluate a 3-year-old child in your clinic.  .docx
You have been asked to evaluate a 3-year-old child in your clinic.  .docxYou have been asked to evaluate a 3-year-old child in your clinic.  .docx
You have been asked to evaluate a 3-year-old child in your clinic.  .docxmaxinesmith73660
 
You have been asked to develop UML diagrams to graphically depict .docx
You have been asked to develop UML diagrams to graphically depict .docxYou have been asked to develop UML diagrams to graphically depict .docx
You have been asked to develop UML diagrams to graphically depict .docxmaxinesmith73660
 
You have been asked to develop UML diagrams to graphically depict an.docx
You have been asked to develop UML diagrams to graphically depict an.docxYou have been asked to develop UML diagrams to graphically depict an.docx
You have been asked to develop UML diagrams to graphically depict an.docxmaxinesmith73660
 
You have been asked to develop a quality improvement (QI) process fo.docx
You have been asked to develop a quality improvement (QI) process fo.docxYou have been asked to develop a quality improvement (QI) process fo.docx
You have been asked to develop a quality improvement (QI) process fo.docxmaxinesmith73660
 
You have been asked to design and deliver a Microsoft PowerPoint pre.docx
You have been asked to design and deliver a Microsoft PowerPoint pre.docxYou have been asked to design and deliver a Microsoft PowerPoint pre.docx
You have been asked to design and deliver a Microsoft PowerPoint pre.docxmaxinesmith73660
 
You have been asked to be the project manager for the development of.docx
You have been asked to be the project manager for the development of.docxYou have been asked to be the project manager for the development of.docx
You have been asked to be the project manager for the development of.docxmaxinesmith73660
 
You have been asked to conduct research on a past forensic case to a.docx
You have been asked to conduct research on a past forensic case to a.docxYou have been asked to conduct research on a past forensic case to a.docx
You have been asked to conduct research on a past forensic case to a.docxmaxinesmith73660
 
You have been asked for the summary to include the following compone.docx
You have been asked for the summary to include the following compone.docxYou have been asked for the summary to include the following compone.docx
You have been asked for the summary to include the following compone.docxmaxinesmith73660
 
You have been asked to be the project manager for the developmen.docx
You have been asked to be the project manager for the developmen.docxYou have been asked to be the project manager for the developmen.docx
You have been asked to be the project manager for the developmen.docxmaxinesmith73660
 
You have been asked by management, as a senior member of your co.docx
You have been asked by management, as a senior member of your co.docxYou have been asked by management, as a senior member of your co.docx
You have been asked by management, as a senior member of your co.docxmaxinesmith73660
 

More from maxinesmith73660 (20)

You have been chosen to present in front of your local governing boa.docx
You have been chosen to present in front of your local governing boa.docxYou have been chosen to present in front of your local governing boa.docx
You have been chosen to present in front of your local governing boa.docx
 
You have been charged with overseeing the implementation of cybersec.docx
You have been charged with overseeing the implementation of cybersec.docxYou have been charged with overseeing the implementation of cybersec.docx
You have been charged with overseeing the implementation of cybersec.docx
 
You have been commissioned to create a manual covering the installat.docx
You have been commissioned to create a manual covering the installat.docxYou have been commissioned to create a manual covering the installat.docx
You have been commissioned to create a manual covering the installat.docx
 
You have been challenged by a mentor you respect and admire to demon.docx
You have been challenged by a mentor you respect and admire to demon.docxYou have been challenged by a mentor you respect and admire to demon.docx
You have been challenged by a mentor you respect and admire to demon.docx
 
You have been chosen as the consultant group to assess the organizat.docx
You have been chosen as the consultant group to assess the organizat.docxYou have been chosen as the consultant group to assess the organizat.docx
You have been chosen as the consultant group to assess the organizat.docx
 
You have been assigned a reading by WMF Petrie; Diospolis Parva (.docx
You have been assigned a reading by WMF Petrie; Diospolis Parva (.docxYou have been assigned a reading by WMF Petrie; Diospolis Parva (.docx
You have been assigned a reading by WMF Petrie; Diospolis Parva (.docx
 
You have been asked to speak to city, municipal, and state elected a.docx
You have been asked to speak to city, municipal, and state elected a.docxYou have been asked to speak to city, municipal, and state elected a.docx
You have been asked to speak to city, municipal, and state elected a.docx
 
You have been asked to provide a presentation, covering the history .docx
You have been asked to provide a presentation, covering the history .docxYou have been asked to provide a presentation, covering the history .docx
You have been asked to provide a presentation, covering the history .docx
 
You have been asked to organize a community health fair at a loc.docx
You have been asked to organize a community health fair at a loc.docxYou have been asked to organize a community health fair at a loc.docx
You have been asked to organize a community health fair at a loc.docx
 
You have been asked to explain the differences between certain categ.docx
You have been asked to explain the differences between certain categ.docxYou have been asked to explain the differences between certain categ.docx
You have been asked to explain the differences between certain categ.docx
 
You have been asked to evaluate a 3-year-old child in your clinic.  .docx
You have been asked to evaluate a 3-year-old child in your clinic.  .docxYou have been asked to evaluate a 3-year-old child in your clinic.  .docx
You have been asked to evaluate a 3-year-old child in your clinic.  .docx
 
You have been asked to develop UML diagrams to graphically depict .docx
You have been asked to develop UML diagrams to graphically depict .docxYou have been asked to develop UML diagrams to graphically depict .docx
You have been asked to develop UML diagrams to graphically depict .docx
 
You have been asked to develop UML diagrams to graphically depict an.docx
You have been asked to develop UML diagrams to graphically depict an.docxYou have been asked to develop UML diagrams to graphically depict an.docx
You have been asked to develop UML diagrams to graphically depict an.docx
 
You have been asked to develop a quality improvement (QI) process fo.docx
You have been asked to develop a quality improvement (QI) process fo.docxYou have been asked to develop a quality improvement (QI) process fo.docx
You have been asked to develop a quality improvement (QI) process fo.docx
 
You have been asked to design and deliver a Microsoft PowerPoint pre.docx
You have been asked to design and deliver a Microsoft PowerPoint pre.docxYou have been asked to design and deliver a Microsoft PowerPoint pre.docx
You have been asked to design and deliver a Microsoft PowerPoint pre.docx
 
You have been asked to be the project manager for the development of.docx
You have been asked to be the project manager for the development of.docxYou have been asked to be the project manager for the development of.docx
You have been asked to be the project manager for the development of.docx
 
You have been asked to conduct research on a past forensic case to a.docx
You have been asked to conduct research on a past forensic case to a.docxYou have been asked to conduct research on a past forensic case to a.docx
You have been asked to conduct research on a past forensic case to a.docx
 
You have been asked for the summary to include the following compone.docx
You have been asked for the summary to include the following compone.docxYou have been asked for the summary to include the following compone.docx
You have been asked for the summary to include the following compone.docx
 
You have been asked to be the project manager for the developmen.docx
You have been asked to be the project manager for the developmen.docxYou have been asked to be the project manager for the developmen.docx
You have been asked to be the project manager for the developmen.docx
 
You have been asked by management, as a senior member of your co.docx
You have been asked by management, as a senior member of your co.docxYou have been asked by management, as a senior member of your co.docx
You have been asked by management, as a senior member of your co.docx
 

Recently uploaded

Painted Grey Ware.pptx, PGW Culture of India
Painted Grey Ware.pptx, PGW Culture of IndiaPainted Grey Ware.pptx, PGW Culture of India
Painted Grey Ware.pptx, PGW Culture of IndiaVirag Sontakke
 
CELL CYCLE Division Science 8 quarter IV.pptx
CELL CYCLE Division Science 8 quarter IV.pptxCELL CYCLE Division Science 8 quarter IV.pptx
CELL CYCLE Division Science 8 quarter IV.pptxJiesonDelaCerna
 
History Class XII Ch. 3 Kinship, Caste and Class (1).pptx
History Class XII Ch. 3 Kinship, Caste and Class (1).pptxHistory Class XII Ch. 3 Kinship, Caste and Class (1).pptx
History Class XII Ch. 3 Kinship, Caste and Class (1).pptxsocialsciencegdgrohi
 
Solving Puzzles Benefits Everyone (English).pptx
Solving Puzzles Benefits Everyone (English).pptxSolving Puzzles Benefits Everyone (English).pptx
Solving Puzzles Benefits Everyone (English).pptxOH TEIK BIN
 
How to Make a Pirate ship Primary Education.pptx
How to Make a Pirate ship Primary Education.pptxHow to Make a Pirate ship Primary Education.pptx
How to Make a Pirate ship Primary Education.pptxmanuelaromero2013
 
EPANDING THE CONTENT OF AN OUTLINE using notes.pptx
EPANDING THE CONTENT OF AN OUTLINE using notes.pptxEPANDING THE CONTENT OF AN OUTLINE using notes.pptx
EPANDING THE CONTENT OF AN OUTLINE using notes.pptxRaymartEstabillo3
 
Biting mechanism of poisonous snakes.pdf
Biting mechanism of poisonous snakes.pdfBiting mechanism of poisonous snakes.pdf
Biting mechanism of poisonous snakes.pdfadityarao40181
 
Capitol Tech U Doctoral Presentation - April 2024.pptx
Capitol Tech U Doctoral Presentation - April 2024.pptxCapitol Tech U Doctoral Presentation - April 2024.pptx
Capitol Tech U Doctoral Presentation - April 2024.pptxCapitolTechU
 
ECONOMIC CONTEXT - PAPER 1 Q3: NEWSPAPERS.pptx
ECONOMIC CONTEXT - PAPER 1 Q3: NEWSPAPERS.pptxECONOMIC CONTEXT - PAPER 1 Q3: NEWSPAPERS.pptx
ECONOMIC CONTEXT - PAPER 1 Q3: NEWSPAPERS.pptxiammrhaywood
 
Software Engineering Methodologies (overview)
Software Engineering Methodologies (overview)Software Engineering Methodologies (overview)
Software Engineering Methodologies (overview)eniolaolutunde
 
Introduction to AI in Higher Education_draft.pptx
Introduction to AI in Higher Education_draft.pptxIntroduction to AI in Higher Education_draft.pptx
Introduction to AI in Higher Education_draft.pptxpboyjonauth
 
Computed Fields and api Depends in the Odoo 17
Computed Fields and api Depends in the Odoo 17Computed Fields and api Depends in the Odoo 17
Computed Fields and api Depends in the Odoo 17Celine George
 
Interactive Powerpoint_How to Master effective communication
Interactive Powerpoint_How to Master effective communicationInteractive Powerpoint_How to Master effective communication
Interactive Powerpoint_How to Master effective communicationnomboosow
 
Proudly South Africa powerpoint Thorisha.pptx
Proudly South Africa powerpoint Thorisha.pptxProudly South Africa powerpoint Thorisha.pptx
Proudly South Africa powerpoint Thorisha.pptxthorishapillay1
 
Types of Journalistic Writing Grade 8.pptx
Types of Journalistic Writing Grade 8.pptxTypes of Journalistic Writing Grade 8.pptx
Types of Journalistic Writing Grade 8.pptxEyham Joco
 
Hierarchy of management that covers different levels of management
Hierarchy of management that covers different levels of managementHierarchy of management that covers different levels of management
Hierarchy of management that covers different levels of managementmkooblal
 
internship ppt on smartinternz platform as salesforce developer
internship ppt on smartinternz platform as salesforce developerinternship ppt on smartinternz platform as salesforce developer
internship ppt on smartinternz platform as salesforce developerunnathinaik
 
How to Configure Email Server in Odoo 17
How to Configure Email Server in Odoo 17How to Configure Email Server in Odoo 17
How to Configure Email Server in Odoo 17Celine George
 

Recently uploaded (20)

Painted Grey Ware.pptx, PGW Culture of India
Painted Grey Ware.pptx, PGW Culture of IndiaPainted Grey Ware.pptx, PGW Culture of India
Painted Grey Ware.pptx, PGW Culture of India
 
ESSENTIAL of (CS/IT/IS) class 06 (database)
ESSENTIAL of (CS/IT/IS) class 06 (database)ESSENTIAL of (CS/IT/IS) class 06 (database)
ESSENTIAL of (CS/IT/IS) class 06 (database)
 
CELL CYCLE Division Science 8 quarter IV.pptx
CELL CYCLE Division Science 8 quarter IV.pptxCELL CYCLE Division Science 8 quarter IV.pptx
CELL CYCLE Division Science 8 quarter IV.pptx
 
History Class XII Ch. 3 Kinship, Caste and Class (1).pptx
History Class XII Ch. 3 Kinship, Caste and Class (1).pptxHistory Class XII Ch. 3 Kinship, Caste and Class (1).pptx
History Class XII Ch. 3 Kinship, Caste and Class (1).pptx
 
Solving Puzzles Benefits Everyone (English).pptx
Solving Puzzles Benefits Everyone (English).pptxSolving Puzzles Benefits Everyone (English).pptx
Solving Puzzles Benefits Everyone (English).pptx
 
How to Make a Pirate ship Primary Education.pptx
How to Make a Pirate ship Primary Education.pptxHow to Make a Pirate ship Primary Education.pptx
How to Make a Pirate ship Primary Education.pptx
 
EPANDING THE CONTENT OF AN OUTLINE using notes.pptx
EPANDING THE CONTENT OF AN OUTLINE using notes.pptxEPANDING THE CONTENT OF AN OUTLINE using notes.pptx
EPANDING THE CONTENT OF AN OUTLINE using notes.pptx
 
Biting mechanism of poisonous snakes.pdf
Biting mechanism of poisonous snakes.pdfBiting mechanism of poisonous snakes.pdf
Biting mechanism of poisonous snakes.pdf
 
Capitol Tech U Doctoral Presentation - April 2024.pptx
Capitol Tech U Doctoral Presentation - April 2024.pptxCapitol Tech U Doctoral Presentation - April 2024.pptx
Capitol Tech U Doctoral Presentation - April 2024.pptx
 
ECONOMIC CONTEXT - PAPER 1 Q3: NEWSPAPERS.pptx
ECONOMIC CONTEXT - PAPER 1 Q3: NEWSPAPERS.pptxECONOMIC CONTEXT - PAPER 1 Q3: NEWSPAPERS.pptx
ECONOMIC CONTEXT - PAPER 1 Q3: NEWSPAPERS.pptx
 
Software Engineering Methodologies (overview)
Software Engineering Methodologies (overview)Software Engineering Methodologies (overview)
Software Engineering Methodologies (overview)
 
Introduction to AI in Higher Education_draft.pptx
Introduction to AI in Higher Education_draft.pptxIntroduction to AI in Higher Education_draft.pptx
Introduction to AI in Higher Education_draft.pptx
 
Computed Fields and api Depends in the Odoo 17
Computed Fields and api Depends in the Odoo 17Computed Fields and api Depends in the Odoo 17
Computed Fields and api Depends in the Odoo 17
 
9953330565 Low Rate Call Girls In Rohini Delhi NCR
9953330565 Low Rate Call Girls In Rohini  Delhi NCR9953330565 Low Rate Call Girls In Rohini  Delhi NCR
9953330565 Low Rate Call Girls In Rohini Delhi NCR
 
Interactive Powerpoint_How to Master effective communication
Interactive Powerpoint_How to Master effective communicationInteractive Powerpoint_How to Master effective communication
Interactive Powerpoint_How to Master effective communication
 
Proudly South Africa powerpoint Thorisha.pptx
Proudly South Africa powerpoint Thorisha.pptxProudly South Africa powerpoint Thorisha.pptx
Proudly South Africa powerpoint Thorisha.pptx
 
Types of Journalistic Writing Grade 8.pptx
Types of Journalistic Writing Grade 8.pptxTypes of Journalistic Writing Grade 8.pptx
Types of Journalistic Writing Grade 8.pptx
 
Hierarchy of management that covers different levels of management
Hierarchy of management that covers different levels of managementHierarchy of management that covers different levels of management
Hierarchy of management that covers different levels of management
 
internship ppt on smartinternz platform as salesforce developer
internship ppt on smartinternz platform as salesforce developerinternship ppt on smartinternz platform as salesforce developer
internship ppt on smartinternz platform as salesforce developer
 
How to Configure Email Server in Odoo 17
How to Configure Email Server in Odoo 17How to Configure Email Server in Odoo 17
How to Configure Email Server in Odoo 17
 

Copyright © 1998. All rights reserved.Copyright © 1998.docx

  • 1. Copyright © 1998. All rights reserved. Copyright © 1998. All rights reserved. Copyright © 1998. All rights reserved. Copyright © 1998. All rights reserved. Copyright © 1998. All rights reserved. Copyright © 1998. All rights reserved. Copyright © 1998. All rights reserved. Copyright © 1998. All rights reserved.
  • 2. Copyright © 1998. All rights reserved. Copyright © 1998. All rights reserved. Copyright © 1998. All rights reserved. Copyright © 1998. All rights reserved. Copyright © 1998. All rights reserved. Copyright © 1998. All rights reserved. Copyright © 1998. All rights reserved. Copyright © 1998. All rights reserved. Copyright © 1998. All rights reserved.
  • 3. Copyright © 1998. All rights reserved. Copyright © 1998. All rights reserved. Copyright © 1998. All rights reserved. Copyright © 1998. All rights reserved. Copyright © 1998. All rights reserved. Copyright © 1998. All rights reserved. Copyright © 1998. All rights reserved. Copyright © 1998. All rights reserved. Introduction from:
  • 4. Distinction: A Social Critique of the Judgement of Taste by Pierre Bourdieu ©1984 Introduction You said it, my good knight! There ought to be laws to protect the body of acquired knowledge. Take one of our good pupils, for example: modest and diligent, from his earliest grammar classes he’s kept a little notebook full of phrases. After hanging on the lips of his teachers for twenty years, he’s managed to build up an intellectual stock in trade; doesn’t it belong to him as if it were a house, or money? Paul Claudel, Le soulier de satin, Day III, Scene ii There is an economy of cultural goods, but it has a specific logic. Sociology
  • 5. endeavours to establish the conditions in which the consumers of cultural goods, and their taste for them, are produced, and at the same time to describe the different ways of appropriating such of these objects as are regarded at a particular moment as works of art, and the social conditions of the constitution of the mode of appropriation that is considered legitimate. But one cannot fully understand cultural practices unless ‘culture’, in the restricted, normative sense of ordinary usage, is brought back into ‘culture’ in the anthropological sense, and the elaborated taste for the most refined objects is reconnected with the elementary taste for the flavours of food. Whereas the ideology of charisma regards taste in legitimate culture as a gift of nature, scientific observation shows that cultural needs are the product of upbringing and education: surveys establish that all cultural practices (museum
  • 6. visits, concert-going, reading etc.), and preferences in literature, painting or music, are closely linked to educational level (measured by qualifications or length of schooling) and secondarily to social origin. 1 The relative weight of home background and of formal education (the effectiveness and duration of which are closely dependent on social origin) varies according to the extent to which the different cultural practices are recognized and taught by the educational system, and the influence of social origin is strongest—other things being equal—in ‘extra-curricular’ and avant-garde culture. To the socially recognized hierarchy of the arts, and within each of them, of genres, schools or periods, corresponds a social hierarchy of the consumers. This predisposes tastes to function as markers of ‘class’. The manner in which culture has been acquired lives on in the manner of using it: the importance attached to manners can be
  • 7. 1 Bourdieu et al., Un art moyen: essai sur les usages sociaux de la photographie (Paris, Ed. de Minuit, 1965); P. Bourdieu and A. Darbel, L’Amour de l’art: les musées et leur public (Paris, Ed. de Minuit, 1966). 2 understood once it is seen that it is these imponderables of practice which distinguish the different—and ranked—modes of culture acquisition, early or late, domestic or scholastic, and the classes of individuals which they characterize (such as ‘pedants’ and mondains). Culture also has its titles of nobility—awarded by the educational system—and its pedigrees, measured by seniority in admission to the nobility. The definition of cultural nobility is the stake in a struggle which has gone on
  • 8. unceasingly, from the seventeenth century to the present day, between groups differing in their ideas of culture and of the legitimate relation to culture and to works of art, and therefore differing in the conditions of acquisition of which these dispositions are the product 2 Even in the classroom, the dominant definition of the legitimate way of appropriating culture and works of art favours those who have had early access to legitimate culture, in a cultured household, outside of scholastic disciplines, since even within the educational system it devalues scholarly knowledge and interpretation as ‘scholastic’ or even ‘pedantic’ in favour of direct experience and simple delight. The logic of what is sometimes called, in typically ‘pedantic’ language, the ‘reading’ of a work of art, offers an objective basis for this opposition. Consumption is, in this case, a stage in a process of communication, that is, an
  • 9. act of deciphering, decoding, which presupposes practical or explicit mastery of a cipher or code. In a sense, one can say that the capacity to see (voir) is a function of the knowledge (savoir), or concepts, that is, the words, that are available to name visible things, and which are, as it were, programmes for perception. A work of art has meaning and interest only for someone who possesses the cultural competence, that is, the code, into which it is encoded. The conscious or unconscious implementation of explicit or implicit schemes of perception and appreciation which constitutes pictorial or musical culture is the hidden condition for recognizing the styles characteristic of a period, a school or an author, and, more generally, for the familiarity with the internal logic of works that aesthetic enjoyment presupposes. A beholder who lacks the specific code feels lost in a chaos of sounds and rhythms, colours and lines, without rhyme or reason. Not
  • 10. having learnt to adopt the adequate disposition, he stops short at what Erwin Panofsky calls the ‘sensible properties’, perceiving a skin as downy or lace-work 2 The word disposition seems particularly suited to express what is covered by the concept of habitus (defined as a system of dispositions)—used later in this chapter. It expresses first the result of an organizing action, with a meaning close to that of words such as structure; it also designates a way of being, a habitual state (especially of the body) and, in particular, a predisposition, tendency, propensity or inclination. [The semantic cluster of ‘disposition’ is rather wider in French than in English, but as this note—translated literally—shows, the equivalence is adequate. Translator.] P. Bourdieu, Outline of a Theory of Practice (Cambridge, Cambridge UJniversity Press, 1977), p. 214, n. 1.
  • 11. 3 as delicate, or at the emotional resonances aroused by these properties, referring to ‘austere’ colours or a ‘joyful’ melody. He cannot move from the ‘primary stratum of the meaning we can grasp on the basis of our ordinary experience’ to the ‘stratum of secondary meanings’, i.e., the ‘level of the meaning of what is signified’, unless he possesses the concepts which go beyond the sensible properties and which identify the specifically stylistic properties of the work. 3 Thus the encounter with a work of art is not ‘love at first sight’ as is generally supposed, and the act of empathy, Einfühlung, which is the art- lover’s pleasure, presupposes an act of cognition, a decoding operation, which implies the implementation of a cognitive acquirement, a cultural code. 4
  • 12. This typically intellectualist theory of artistic perception directly contradicts the experience of the art-lovers closest to the legitimate definition; acquisition of legitimate culture by insensible familiarization within the family circle tends to favour an enchanted experience of culture which implies forgetting the acquisition. 5 The ‘eye’ is a product of history reproduced by education. This is true of the mode of artistic perception now accepted as legitimate, that is, the aesthetic disposition, the capacity to consider in and for themselves, as form rather than function, not only the works designated for such apprehension, i.e., legitimate works of art, but everything in the world, including cultural objects which are not yet consecrated—such as, at one time, primitive arts, or, nowadays, 3 E. Panofsky, ‘Iconography and Iconology: An Introduction to the Study of Renaissance
  • 13. Art’, Meaning in the Visual Arts (New York, Doubleday, 1955), p. 28. 4 It will be seen that this internalized code called culture functions as cultural capital owing to the fact that, being unequally distributed, it secures profits of distinction. 5 The sense of familiarity in no way excludes the ethnocentric misunderstanding which results from applying the wrong code. Thus, Michael Baxandall’s work in historical ethnology enables us to measure all that separates the perceptual schemes that now tend to be applied to Quattrocento paintings and those which their immediate addressees applied. The ‘moral and spiritual eye’ of Quattrocento man, that is, the set of cognitive and evaluative dispositions which were the basis of his perception of the world and his perception of pictorial representation of the world, differs radically from the ‘pure’ gaze (purified, first of all, of reference to economic value) with which the modern cultivated spectator looks at works of art. As the contracts show, the clients of Filippo Lippi,
  • 14. Domenico Ghirlandaio or Piero della Francesca were concerned to get ‘value for money’. They approached works of art with the mercantile dispositions of a businessman who can calculate quantities and prices at a glance, and they applied some surprising criteria of appreciation, such as the expense of the colours, which sets gold and ultramarine at the top of the hierarchy. The artists, who shared this world view, were led to include arithmetical and geometrical devices in their compositions so as to flatter this taste for measurement and calculation; and they tended to exhibit the technical virtuosity which, in this context, is the most visible evidence of the quantity and quality of the labour provided; M. Baxandall, Painting and Experience in Fifteenth- Century Italy: A Primer in the Social History of Pictorial Style (Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1972). 4
  • 15. popular photography or kitsch—and natural objects. The ‘pure’ gaze is a historical invention linked to the emergence of an autonomous field of artistic production, that is, a field capable of imposing its own norms on both the production and the consumption of its products. 6 An art which, like all Post- Impressionist painting, is the product of an artistic intention which asserts the primacy of the mode of representation over the object of representation demands categorically an attention to form which previous art only demanded conditionally. The pure intention of the artist is that of a producer who aims to be autonomous, that is, entirely the master of his product, who tends to reject not only the ‘programmes’ imposed a priori by scholars and scribes, but also— following the old hierarchy of doing and saying—the interpretations
  • 16. superimposed a posteriori on his work. The production of an ‘open work’, intrinsically and deliberately polysemic, can thus be understood as the final stage in the conquest of artistic autonomy by poets and, following in their footsteps, by painters, who had long been reliant on writers and their work of ‘showing’ and ‘illustrating’. To assert the autonomy of production is to give primacy to that of which the artist is master, i.e., form, manner, style, rather than the ‘subject’, the external referent, which involves subordination to functions even if only the most elementary one, that of representing, signifying, saying something. It also means a refusal to recognize any necessity other than that inscribed in the specific tradition of the artistic discipline in question: the shift from an art which imitates nature to an art which imitates art, deriving from its own history the exclusive source of its experiments and even of its breaks with tradition. An art which ever
  • 17. increasingly contains reference to its own history demands to be perceived historically; it asks to be referred not to an external referent, the represented or designated ‘reality’, but to the universe of past and present works of art. Like artistic production, in that it is generated in a field, aesthetic perception is necessarily historical, inasmuch as it is differential, relational, attentive to the deviations (écarts) which make styles. Like the so-called naive painter who, operating outside the held and its specific traditions remains external to the history of the art, the ‘naive’ spectator cannot attain a specific grasp of works of art which only have meaning—or value—in relation to the specific history of an artistic tradition. The aesthetic disposition demanded by the products of a highly autonomous field of production is inseparable from a specific cultural competence. This historical culture functions as a principle of pertinence which
  • 18. enables one to identify, among the elements offered to the gaze, all the distinctive features and only these, by referring them, consciously or unconsciously, to the 6 See P. Bourdieu, ‘Le marché des biens symboliques’, L’Anneé Sociologique, 22 (1973), 49 126; and ‘Outline of a Sociological Theory of Art Perception’, International Social Science Journal, 20 (Winter 1968), 589-612. 5 universe of possible alternatives. This mastery is, for the most part, acquired simply by contact with works of art—that is, through an implicit learning analogous to that which makes it possible to recognize familiar faces without explicit rules or criteria—and it generally remains at a practical level; it is what makes it possible to identify styles, i.e., modes of expression characteristic of a
  • 19. period, a civilization or a school, without having to distinguish clearly, or state explicitly, the features which constitute their originality. Everything seems to suggest that even among professional valuers, the criteria which define the stylistic properties of the ‘typical works’ on which all their judgements are based usually remain implicit. The pure gaze implies a break with the ordinary attitude towards the world, which, given the conditions in which it is performed, is also a social separation. Orteya y Gasset can be believed when he attributes to modern art a systematic refusal of all that is ‘human’, i.e., generic, common—as opposed to distinctive, or distinguished—namely, the passions, emotions and feelings which ‘ordinary’ people invest in their ‘ordinary’ lives. It is as if the ‘popular aesthetic’ (the quotation marks are there to indicate that this is an aesthetic ‘in itself’ not ‘for itself’) were based on the affirmation of the continuity between
  • 20. art and life, which implies the subordination of form to function. This is seen clearly in the case of the novel and especially the theatre, where the working- class audience refuses any sort of formal experimentation and all the effects which, by introducing a distance from the accepted conventions (as regards scenery, plot etc.), tend to distance the spectator, preventing him from getting involved and fully identifying with the characters (I am thinking of Brechtian ‘alienation’ or the disruption of plot in the nouveau roman). In contrast to the detachment and disinterestedness which aesthetic theory regards as the only way of recognizing the work of art for what it is, i.e., autonomous, selbständig, the ‘popular aesthetic’ ignores or refuses the refusal of ‘facile’ involvement and ‘vulgar’ enjoyment, a refusal which is the basis of the taste for formal experiment. And popular judgements of paintings or photographs spring from an
  • 21. ‘aesthetic’ (in fact it is an ethos) which is the exact opposite of the Kantian aesthetic. Whereas, in order to grasp the specificity of the aesthetic judgement, Kant strove to distinguish that which pleases from that which gratifies and, more generally, to distinguish disinterestedness, the sole guarantor of the specifically aesthetic quality of contemplation, from the interest of reason which defines the Good, working-class people expect every image to explicitly perform a function, if only that of a sign, and their judgements make reference, often explicitly, to the norms of morality or agreeableness. Whether rejecting or praising, their appreciation always has an ethical basis. Popular taste applies the schemes of the ethos, which pertain in the ordinary circumstances of life, to legitimate works of art, and so performs a systematic reduction of the things of art to the things of life. The very seriousness (or
  • 22. 6 naivety) which this taste invests in fictions and representations demonstrates a contrario that pure taste performs a suspension of ‘naive’ involvement which is one dimension of a ‘quasi-ludic’ relationship with the necessities of the world. Intellectuals could be said to believe in the representation— literature, theatre, painting—more than in the things represented, whereas the people chiefly expect representations and the conventions which govern them to allow them to believe ‘naively’ in the things represented. The pure aesthetic is rooted in an ethic, or rather, an ethos of elective distance from the necessities of the natural and social world, which may take the form of moral agnosticism (visible when ethical transgression becomes an artistic parti pris) or of an aestheticism which presents
  • 23. the aesthetic disposition as a universally valid principle and takes the bourgeois denial of the social world to its limit. The detachment of the pure gaze cannot be dissociated from a general disposition towards the world which is the paradoxical product of conditioning by negative economic necessities—a life of ease—that tends to induce an active distance from necessity. Although art obviously offers the greatest scope to the aesthetic disposition, there is no area of practice in which the aim of purifying, refining and sublimating primary needs and impulses cannot assert itself, no area in which the stylization of life, that is, the primacy of forms over function, of manner over matter, does not produce the same effects. And nothing is more distinctive, more distinguished, than the capacity to confer aesthetic status on objects that are banal or even ‘common’ (because the ‘common’ people make them their own, especially for aesthetic purposes), or the ability to apply the
  • 24. principles of a ‘pure’ aesthetic to the most everyday choices of everyday life, e.g., in cooking, clothing or decoration, completely reversing the popular disposition which annexes aesthetics to ethics. In fact, through the economic and social conditions which they presuppose, the different ways of relating to realities and fictions, of believing in fictions and the realities they simulate, with more or less distance and detachment, are very closely linked to the different possible positions in social space and, consequently, bound up with the systems of dispositions (habitus) characteristic of the different classes and class fractions. Taste classifies, and it classifies the classifier. Social subjects, classified by their classifications, distinguish themselves by the distinctions they make, between the beautiful and the ugly, the distinguished and the vulgar, in which their position in the objective
  • 25. classifications is expressed or betrayed. And statistical analysis does indeed show that oppositions similar in structure to those found in cultural practices also appear in eating habits. The antithesis between quantity and quality, substance and form, corresponds to the opposition—linked to different distances from necessity—between the taste of necessity, which favours the most ‘filling’ and most economical foods, and the taste of liberty or luxury— which shifts the 7 emphasis to the manner (of presenting, serving, eating etc.) and tends to use stylized forms to deny function. The science of taste and of cultural consumption begins with a transgression that is in no way aesthetic: it has to abolish the sacred frontier which makes legitimate culture a separate universe, in order to discover the
  • 26. intelligible relations which unite apparently incommensurable ‘choices’, such as preferences in music and food, painting and sport, literature and hairstyle. This barbarous reintegration of aesthetic consumption into the world of ordinary consumption abolishes the opposition, which has been the basis of high aesthetics since Kant, between the ‘taste of sense’ and the ‘taste of reflection’, and between facile pleasure, pleasure reduced to a pleasure of the senses, and pure pleasure, pleasure purified of pleasure, which is predisposed to become a symbol of moral excellence and a measure of the capacity for sublimation which defines the truly human man. The culture which results from this magical division is sacred. Cultural consecration does indeed confer on the objects, persons and situations it touches, a sort of ontological promotion akin to a transubstantiation. Proof enough of this is found in the two following quotations, which
  • 27. might almost have been written for the delight of the sociologist: ‘What struck me most is this: nothing could be obscene on the stage of our premier theatre, and the ballerinas of the Opera, even as naked dancers, sylphs, sprites or Bacchae, retain an inviolable purity.’ 7 ‘There are obscene postures: the stimulated intercourse which offends the eye. Clearly, it is impossible to approve, although the interpolation of such gestures in dance routines does give them a symbolic and aesthetic quality which is absent from the intimate scenes the cinema daily flaunts before its spectators’ eyes . . . As for the nude scene, what can one say, except that it is brief and theatrically not very effective? I will not say it is chaste or innocent, for nothing commercial can be so described. Let us say it is not shocking, and that the chief objection is that it serves as a box-office gimmick. . . . In Hair,
  • 28. the nakedness fails to be symbolic.’ 8 The denial of lower, coarse, vulgar, venal, servile—in a word, natural— enjoyment, which constitutes the sacred sphere of culture, implies an affirmation of the superiority of those who can be satisfied with the sublimated, refined, disinterested, gratuitous, distinguished pleasures forever closed to the profane. That is why art and cultural consumption are predisposed, consciously and deliberately or not, to fulfil a social function of legitimating social differences. Translated by Richard Nice 7 O. Merlin, ‘Mlle. Thibon dans la vision de Marguerite’, Le Monde, 9 December 1965. 8 F. Chenique, ‘Hair est-il immoral?’ Le Monde, 28 January 1970.
  • 29. 2. 0 4 THE CONSUMER SOCIETY READER personally. For this is the basis of award of the instinct of workmanship,- and that instinct is the court of final appeal in any question of economic truth or adequacy. It is a question as to the award rendered by passionate common sense. The question is, therefore, not whether, under the existing circumstances of individual habit and social custom, a given expenditure conduces to the particular consumer's gratification or peace of mind; but whether, aside from acquired tastes and from the canons of usage and conventional decency, its result is a net gain in comfort or in the fulness of life. Customary expenditure must be classed under the head of waste in so far as the custom on which it rests is traceable to the habit of making an invidious pecuniary comparison-in so far as it is conceived that it could not have become customary and prescriptive without the backing of this principle of pecuniary reputability or relative economic success. It is obviously not necessary that a given object of expenditure should be exclusively wasteful in order to come in under the category of con-
  • 30. spicuous waste. An article may be useful and wasteful both, and its utility to the consumer may be made up of use and waste in the most varying proportions. Consumable goods, and even productive goods, generally show the two elements in combination, as constituents of their utility; although, in a general way, the element of waste tends to pre- dominate in articles of consumption, while the contrary is true of articles designed for productive use. Even in articles which appear at first glance to serve for pure ostentation only, it is always possible to detect the presence of some, at least ostensible, useful purpose; and on the other hand, even in special machinery and tools contrived for some particular industrial process, as well as in the rudest appliances of human industry, the traces of conspicuous waste, or at least of the habit of ostentation, usually become evident on a close scrutiny. It would be hazardous to assert that a useful purpose is ever absent from the utility of any article or of any service, however obviously its prime purpose and chief element is conspicuous waste; and it would be only less hazardous to assert of any primarily useful product that the element of waste is in no way concerned in its value, immediately or remotely.
  • 31. 12 Pierre Bourdieu "THE AESTHETIC SENSE AS THE SENSE OF DISTINCTION" (1979; translation 19 84) The aesthetic disposition is one dimension of a distant, self- assured relation to the world and to others which presupposes objective assurance and distance. It is one manifestation of the system of dispo- sitions produced by the social conditionings associated with a particular class of conditions of existence when they take the paradoxical form of the greatest freedom conceivable, at a given moment, with respect to the constraints of economic necessity. But it is also a distinctive expres- sion of a privileged position in social space whose distinctive value is objectively established in its relationship to expressions generated from different conditions. Like every sort of taste, it unites and separates. Being the product of the conditionings associated with a particular class of conditions of existence, it unites all those who are the product of similar conditions while distinguishing them from all others. And it dis- tinguishes in an essential way, since taste is the basis of all that one has-people and things-and all that one is for others, whereby one
  • 32. classifies oneself and is classified by others. Tastes (i.e., manifested preferences) are the practical affirmation of an inevitable difference. It is no accident that, when they have to be justi- fied, they are asserted purely negatively, by the refusal of other tastes. I In matters of taste, more than anywhere else, all determination is ne- and tastes are perhaps first and foremost distastes, disgust pro- voked by horror or visceral intolerance ("sick-making") of the tastes of others. "De gustibus non est disputandum": not because "taus les gouts sont dans la nature," but because each taste feels itself to be natural- and so it almost is, being a habitus-which amounts to rejecting others as unnatural and therefore vicious. Aesthetic intolerance can be terribly violent. Aversion to different life-styles is perhaps one of the strongest barriers between the classes; class endogamy is evidence of this. The most intolerable thing for those who regard themselves as the possessors of legitimate culture is the sacrilegious reuniting of tastes which taste "."'.11, tloi dictates shall be separated. This means that the games of artists and aesthetes and their struggles for the monopoly of artistic legitimacy are
  • 33. -,= '"'''1''' -"! .:: loOO THE CONSUMER SOCIETY READER less innocent than they seem. At stake in every struggle over art there c is also the imposition of an art of living, that is, the transmutation of an arbitrary way of living into the legitimate way of life which casts every other way of living into arbitrariness.; The artist's life- style. is always a challenge thrown at the bourgeois life-style, which it seeks to condemn as unreal and even absurd, by a sort of practical demonstra- tion of the emptiness of the values and powers it pursues. The neutral- izing relation to the world which defines dle aesthetic disposition potentially implies a subversion of the spirit of seriousness required by bourgeois investments. Like the visibly ethical judgments of those who lack the means to make art the basis of dleir art of living, to see the world and other people through literary reminiscences and pictorial ref- erences, the "pure" and purely aesthetic judgments of the artist and the aesthete spring from the dispositions of an ethos;4 but because of 'tp.e _
  • 34. legitimacy which they command so long as their relationship to the dis- positions and interests of a group defined by strong cultural capital and weak economic capital remains unrecognized, they provide a sort:of absolute reference point in the necessarily endless play of mutually self':' relativizing tastes. By a paradoxical reversal, dley thereby help to imate the bourgeois claim to "natural distinction" as difference made absolute. Objectively and subjectively aesthetic stances adopted in matters like cosmetics, clodling or home decoration are opportunities to experience or assert one's position in social space, as a rank to be upheld or a distance to be kept. It goes without saying that the social classes are not equally inclined and prepared to enter this game of refusal and coun- terrefusal; and that the strategies aimed at transforming the basic dis ... positions of a life-style into a system of aesthetic principles, objective differences into elective distinctions, passive options (constituted exeer ... nally by the logic of the distinctive relationships) into conscious, elective choices are in fact reserved for members of the dominant class, indeed the very top bourgeoisie, and for artists, who as the inventors and pro"
  • 35. fessionals of the "stylization of life" are alone able to make their art of living one of dIe fine arts. By contrast, the entry of the petite into the game of distinction is marked, inter alia, by the anxiety of exposing ones'elf to classification by offering to the taste of others such infallible indices of personal taste as clothes or furniture, even a simple pair of armchairs, as in one of Nathalie Sarraute's novels. As for the working classes, perhaps their sole function in the system of aesthetic positions is to serve as a foil, a negative reference point, in relation to which all aesthetics define themselves, by successive negations. s Ignoring or ignorant of manner and style, the "aesthetic" (in itself) of the working classes and culturally most deprived fractions of the middle classes fines as "nice," "pretty," "lovely" (rather than "beautiful") things that are already defined as such in the "aesthetic" of calendars and postcards: THE AESTHETCC SENSE AS THE SENSE OF DISTCNCTCON lo07 a sunset, a lirtle girl playing with a cat, a folk dance, an old master, a first communion, a children's procession. The striving toward distinction comes in with petit-bourgeois aestheticism, which delights in all the cheap substitutes for chic objects and practices-driftwood and
  • 36. painted pebbles, cane and raffia, "art" handicrafts and art photography. This aestheticism defines itself against the "aesthetic" of the working classes, refusing their favorite subjects, the themes of "views," such as mountain landscapes, sunsets and woods, or souvenir photos, such as the first communion, the monument or the old master (see diagram I). In photography, this taste prefers objects that are close to those of the popular aesthetic but semi-neutralized by more or less explicit reference to a pictorial tradition or by a visible stylistic intention combining the human picturesque (weaver at his loom, tramps quarreling, folk dance) with gratuitous form (pebbles, rope, tree bark). It is significant dlat this middle-brow art par excellence finds one of its preferred subjects in one of the spectacles most characteristic of middle-brow culture (along with the circus, light opera and bull-fights), the folk dance (which is particularly appreciated by skilled workers and foremen, junior executives, clerical and commercial employees) (C.S. VII). Like the photographic recording of the social picturesque, whose populist objectivism distances dIe lower classes by constituting them as an object of contemplation or even commiseration or
  • 37. indignation, the spectacle of the "people" making a spectacle of itself, as in folk dancing, is an opportunity to experience the relationship of distant proximity, in the form of the idealized vision purveyed by aesthetic realism and po- pulist nostalgia, which is a basic element in the relationship of the petite bourgeoisie to the working or peasant classes and their traditions. But this middle-brow aestheticism in turn serves as a foil to the most alert members of the new middle-class fractions, who reject its favored sub- jects, and to the secondary teachers whose aestheticism (the aestheticism of consumers, since they are relatively infrequent practitioners of pho- tography and the other arts) purports to be able to treat any object aesthetically, with the exception of those so constituted by the middle- brow art of the petite bourgeoisie (such as the weaver and the folk dance, which are deemed merely "interesting").6 These would- be aes- thetes demonstrate by their distinctive refusals that they possess the practical mastery of the relationships between objects and groups which is the basis of all judgments of the type "<;::a fait" ("It looks ...") ("<;::a fait petit-bourgeois," "<;::a fait nouveau riche," etc.), without being able to go so far as to ascribe beauty to the most marked objects of
  • 38. the popular aesthetic (first communion) or the petit-bourgeois aesthetic (mother and child, folk dance) which the relations of structural prox- imity spontaneously lead them to detest. Explicit aesthetic choices are in fact often constituted in opposition to the choices of the groups closest in social space, with whom the . L L _.. &.£2&&&&£ dL THE AESTHETIC SENSE AS THE SENSE OF DISTINCTION 2.09 competition is most direct and most immediate, and more precisely, no doubt, in relation to those choices most clearly marked by the intention { (perceived as pretension) of marking distinction vis- a-vis lower groups, "" such as, for intellectuals, the primary teachers' Brassens, Jean Ferrat or§] ·1 ::a i ... Ferre. Thus 'the song, as a cultural property which (like photography) ',1:1 la .s is almost universally accessible and genuinely common (since hardly 8,g ; a i i -:- i 13 -e 111 anyone is not exposed at one moment or another to the "successes" of s II iii j '6ll..lS POUlJa tJ1 the day), calls for particular vigilance from those who intend to mark their difference. The intellectuals, artists and higher-education teachers
  • 39. CIl seem to hesitate between systematic refusal of what can only be, at best, a middle-brow art, and a selective acceptance which manifests the uni- E gI3J e § " ] Ii '§ versality of their culture and their aesthetic disposition.' For their part, .... 'B '1:1" ::I 1 J11 8. ... ... tl L11e. the employers and professionals, who have little interest in the "intel- i-8 j J " i :s i ! h: j j B 1 lectual" song, indicate their distance from ordinary songs by rejecting '" III with disgust the most popular and most "vulgar" singers, such as Lesiii 'bi. oS .8 1 I § '5 j I j Compagnons de la Chanson, Mireille Madlieu, Adamo or Sheila, and tl s making an exception for the oldest and most consecrated singers (like j .g,. Edith Piaf or Charles Trenet) or those closest to operetta and bel canto . ;; f.... !i _ But it is the middle classes who find in song (as in photography) an opportunity to manifest their artistic pretension by refusing the favorite Ii /I: IS til8. 'B J 8 il i -:i 1=!.,fA .c singers of the working classes, such as Mireille Mathieu, Adamo, I:lIl " iE-i'i t e Charles Aznavour or Tino Rossi, and declaring their preference for the :!l Fi a-crgi11! singers who endeavour to dignify this "minor" genre. That is why the '0 '" primary teachers distinguish themselves most clearly from the other frac- &b tions of the petite bourgeoisie in this area, where, more
  • 40. easily than in5 f =.8[ rs the domain of legitimate art, they can invest their academic dispositions IS ,1; • and assert their own taste in the choice of singers who offer populist 0 e -1!l '§8,05 poetry in the primary-school tradition, such as Jacques Douai or Bras-1 e• H ,Q £ IS 5 ri ... 13 '0.1. S-rse. ",111.<:1 sens (who was on the syllabus of the Saint-Cloud entrance examination .£l ii1>!-6 .<•.I'6 a few years agol. s •.,,)I:,el §l:1i!i oa1'i ,Q5 i IfI j f1 ;e:l 01 Ul_..2 '6ll II: '0 tl ¢l IS til . It may also be assumed that the affirmation of the omnipotence of 'J:! the aesthetic gaze found among higher-education teachers, the group ·8 most inclined to say that all the objects mentioned could make a beau-fi'5 as {:i$=€ I'B tiful photograph and to profess their recognition of modern art or of - .'P. .,.i i f = ! I ,j'j",il ..s .!. the artistic status of the photograph, stems much more from a self-'B § distinguishing intention than from a true aesthetic universalism. This . 1:l. .s ,Q e 11 ! "y-- j '.!;i:U fIJ i '" .", 'tI >. '" "'.<:I has not escaped dIe most knowing avant-garde producers, who carry ... fl 0 '+of "'111 -:u )J;j'r,.. 13 til /I: S ;:. (J SS:.':lO -:=<U u ii 0 sufficient authority to challenge, if need be, the very dogma of the om-t:i'!i. ]i :9 OJ ',1:1 a r.1' g = O{,jO,ii(l}.,Q nipotence of art,9 and are in a position to recognize this faith as a de-.-. "'" Ii: fensive maneuver to avoid self-exposure by reckless refusals: "Who
  • 41. Ii! ;2··:' would say this: 'When I look at a picture, I'm not interested in what it is _ i'l represents'? Nowadays, the sort of people who don't know much about s,!o! I art. Saying that is typical of someone who hasn't any idea about art. ::E-5 . (I Twenty years ago, I'm not even sure that twenty years ago the abstract 'A:f.' r painters would have said that; I don't think so. It's exactly what a guy {4Y: " EmmELL 22 i §li§b44J1&iJZYMi.,." 3L 1 ".MUiL .. __ 2.IO THE CONSUMER SOCIETY READER says when he hasn't a clue: 'I'm not one ,of these old fogies, I know what counts is whether it's pretty' " (avant-garde painter, age 35). They alone, at aU events, can afford the audacious imposture of refusing all refusals by recuperating, ill parody or sublimation, the very objects re- fused by the lower-degree aesdteticism. The "rehabilitation" of "vulgar" objects is more risky, but, also more "profitable," the smaller the dis- tance in social space or time, and the "horrors" of popular kitsch are easier to "recuperate" than those of petit-bourgeois imitation,
  • 42. just .as the "abominations" of bourgeois taste can begin to be found "amusing" when they are sufficiendy dated to' cease to be "compromising." The artist agrees with the "bourgeois" in one respect: he prefers naiv- ety to: '; The essential merit of the "common people" is that they have none of the pretensions to art (or power) which inspire the ambitions of the ,"petit' bourgeois." Their indifference tacitly ac- knowledges the monopoly. That is why, in the mythology of artists and intellectuals, whose outflanking and double-negating strategies times lead them back to "popular" tastes and opinions, the "people" so often playa role not unlike that of the peasantry in the conservative ideologies of the declining aristocracy. ENDNOTES r. Two examples, chosen from among hundreds, bur paradigmatic, of explicit use of the scheme "something other than": "La Fiancee du pirate is one of those very true French films that are really satirical, really funny, because it does not resort to the carefully defused, prudently inoffensive comedy one finds in La Grande 'adreuille and Ie Petit Baiglzeur . ... In short, it IS some- thing other than the dreary hackwork of boulevard farce" U. L. Bory, Le Nouvel Observateur) 8 December 1969: italics mine). "Through
  • 43. distance, or at [east, dlcough difterence, to endeavour to present a text on pictorial mo- dernity other than the hackneyed banalities of a certain style 07 art criticism. Between verbose aphasia, the textual transcription of picrures. endamations of recognition, and the works of specialized aesthetics, perhal?s marking some- of dIe ways in which conceptual, theoretical work gets to gnps with contem- porary production" (G. Gassiot-Talabot et al., Figurations 1960- 1973 [Paris, Union generale des editions, 19731. p. 7; italics mine). 2.. This essential negativity, which is part of the very logic of the constitution of taste and its change, explains why, as Gambrich points out, "the temlinol- ogy of art history was so larliely built on words dena ring some principle of exclusion. Most movements m art erect some new taboo, some new negative principle, such as the banishing from painting by the impressionists of all 'anecdotal' elements. The positive slogans and shibboleths which we read in artists' or critics' manifestos past or present are usually much less well de- fined" (E. H. Gombrich, News and Form: Studies in the Art of the Renais- sance [London, New York, Phaidon Press, I966J, p. 89). 3· This is seen clearly in the case of the theater, which touches more directly and more overtly on the implicit or explicit principles of the art
  • 44. of living. Especially in the case of comedy, it presul?Poses common values or interests or, more precisely, a complicity and connIvance based on immediate assent to the same self-evident propositions, dIose of the doxa, dIe totality of opin- ions accepted at the level of pre-reflective belief. (This explains why the insti- tutions supplying the products, and the products themselves, are more sharply differentiated m the theater than in any other art.) THE AESTHETlC SENSE AS THE SENSE OF DISTINCTlON 2.11 4. For an analysis of "art for art's sake" as the expression of the artistic life- style, see P. Bourdieu, "L'invention de la vie d'artiste," Actes, 2. (1975), 67- 93· 5. This is true despite the apparent exception in which some artists return to certain popular ,Preferences, which haC! a totally different meaning in a cul- tural configuranon dominated by choices which for them would be quite im- probable or even impossible. These returns to the "popular" style, which often pass for a return to the "people" are detennined not by any genuine relationship to tbe working classes, who are generally spumed- even in ide- alization, which is a form of refusal-but by the internal relations of the
  • 45. field of artistic production or the field of the dominant class. (This point has a general validity, and one would need to examine what the writings of in- tellectuals on the working classes owe to the specific interests of intellectuals in struggles in which what is at stake, if not the people, is the legitimacy conferred, in certain conditions, by appearing as dIe spokesman for popular interests. ) 6. It is in dlese two categories that we encounter the most marked refusal of souvenir photos ("Souvenir photos are stupid and banal"; "The main point of a photo is to preserve the images of those one loves"), of realism in paint- ing (" A beautiful picture should reproduce what is beautiful in nature'" or in photography ("For a ehotograph to be good, you just have to be ab e to recognize what it shows), and die most resolute assertion of faith in mod- em painting (in refusal of the opinion: "Modern painting is just slapped on anyhow ..... 1. 7. One of the major limitations imfosed by tbe list of pre.formed choices is that it does not bring out these conflicts" and the strategies aimed at get- ting around them. A respondent who has, "against the chosen Geor- ges Brassens or Jacques Douai might have been able to mdicate his refusal of
  • 46. song, while showing his "open-mindedness," by citing (with an implicit rede- finition) something by Kurt Weill or an ola Neap,olitan song. (The France- Musique radio pro&ram of "personal selections, ' "Le concert egoiste," is very revealing in thIS respect.) 8. Saint-Cloud: second to ENS me d'Ulm in the hierarchy of the Ecoles norma- les superieures (translator). 9. This dogma is still recognized and professed in less advanced sectors of the field of artistic production, as this typical declaration shows: "However, I will say that these paintings by Gaston Planet are totally incomprehensible: I wiU say that I like tbem to be so. Not enigmatic. But entirely mute. Without points of reference. Without distractions" (Paul Rossi, Gaston Planet cata- logue). ')',,. - " KSLE£.. n .. ]22_. &2i&£§!...t%·JJ.. •.f..il&Mii&E§1";;;:;;;t!$!£.£&E_ t. i£b..'ii'M4Jib..:.<m¥! w.L t.liXZ tl&Qk4t . Soc 210 – Sociology of Culture: Exam #2 – Short Essay Short Essay Questions:
  • 47. 1. As Bourdieu tells us cultural capital is not only about the objects of consumption. What is a potentially even more important cultural capital resource (think language)? Further, what does Bourdieu mean when he says: “it is no accident that when tastes have to be justified they are asserted purely negatively”? How is this related to symbolic violence? Make sure you define symbolic violence. 2. Holt describes six dimensions of taste and consumption practice in American society. Describe three of these dimensions. Be sure to explain what freedom from necessity has to do with cultural taste and why cultural capital cannot be reduced to economic capital according to Holt. Be sure to answer every part of the question; you should be able to answer these in around 1 page (double spaced, one inch margins, 12 point Times New Roman font (points will be taken off for not following this format)). For full credit, answer the question fully, use examples, cite sociological and media articles, refer to the discussion boards when necessary and be sure to use your own language. That is, do not simply copy my Power Point notes; doing that does not demonstrate an understanding of the course material. Once again, attach a file as well as paste the text directly into the submission text box in this assignment.