SlideShare a Scribd company logo
1 of 20
Download to read offline
Judicial Legitimacy
	 Creating a constitution is an imposing task. There are many components to consider, and even
then, a constitution cannot fully account for the stability of a nation. The constitution can only set the
fundamental groundwork. That is why in some countries, like the US, components may exist completely
outside the mainstream understanding of what works today. Nonetheless, it is worth attempting to
improve these elements as they are fundamental to the existence of the state. The US judicial branch is
one of these components. As Jacobs indicates, ā€œmany students remain unaware that the American legal
system is an exception to what prevails in most of the rest of the worldā€ (vii). Although the US
constitution has stood the test of time, its ideals with regards to the judiciary are in no way a model for the
modern world. This paper will comparatively analyze the US judicial system with various nations such as
Russia, Germany, and South Africa to create a normative design of the American judicial branch. This
normative model will address the inherit ļ¬‚aws that exist within the American judicial branch, which make
a constitutional nation less sustainable. In order to address these issues, one must ļ¬rst understand why the
judicial branch exists; then how it can best fulļ¬ll these ends; and lastly what cultural, structural, and
appointment mechanisms in a normative US model would look like.
A Brief Introduction to the US Model
Th4e American Paradox
	 The American model is paradoxical in many ways; although its conception made it seem as
though it was the weakest of the three branches, time has proven it to be a major part of the American
polity. The constitution itself, the establishment of judicial review, and the Federalist Papers led to this
initial perception of weakness. In the US constitution, articles I, II, and III outline the three branches.
The legislative and executive branch are the topic of the ļ¬rst two articles; both have more sections, clearly
enumerated powers/responsibilities, and speciļ¬c outlines of who can occupy the position(s). The judiciary
!1
on the other hand is the last of the three articles, has the least sections, is written vaguely, and does not
even outline who is able to be a justice. It seems that the judicial was simply thrown on as an afterthought.
Even the concept of judicial review, an underpinning of how we understand courts today, was established
by the court itself (not the constitution). This further highlights the vagueness and weakness of the judicial
branch as written in the constitution. Moreover, in the famous Federalist 78 , Hamilton outlined that the
court is the weakest of the three branches, because it does not have the power of ā€œthe sword or the
purseā€ (ā€œFederalist no. 78ā€). How then does this courtā€™s decision have ā€œpowerā€ in the checks and balances
system? Through legitimacy. Legitimacy will be deļ¬ned more extensively later in the paper ā€” however, it
is achieved both from the branchā€™s conception and its behavior as an actor in the constitutional system.
Common Law Conundrum
	 As one looks to the US model, it is hard to avoid the elephant in the room: the comparatively rare
common law system. Although an entirely different paper could be written on the various merits of the
common law and Kelsenian system in structuring of the courts, both methods are sustainable. Regardless
of these disputes, even if the US changed to a civil law system, the institutional and structural costs would
outweigh the net beneļ¬ts from the new system. Therefore, this paper will assume efļ¬cacy of the common
law system. Furthermore, another detail to consider is the simple principle that constitutional courts,
judges, and decisions occupy a ā€˜constitutional spaceā€™ that is neither ā€˜judicialā€™ nor ā€˜politicalā€™ (Sweet,
ā€œConstitutional Courts and Parliamentary Democracyā€ 80; ā€œConstitutional Courtsā€ 818). This framing of
a somewhat ambiguous nature of a judicial branch will be an important theme to note throughout this
paper and will be, in part, justiļ¬cation for use of the common law system. For these reasons, this paper
will aim to solve the problems of the judicial branch in the lens of US common law system. If these issues
are going to be addressed, let us start by simply understanding why courts exist.
!2
Why Do Courts Exist?
	 At their very core, courts exist to interpret the law and issue judgements. Since WWII, in judicial
models around the world, courts interpret the law by checking it against the constitution ā€” the document
which underpins all legal texts. It is through this interpretation of the law that they can then check the
powers of the other two branches. This is because of the way balance of powers is conceptualized with
the constitution. Because the polity ā€œagreedā€ on the constitution, they created two agents: the executive
and legislative, both with positive lawmaking capabilities of whom ā€œthe peopleā€ are the principals. The
courts in a way keep those agents honest to the principles of their creation enumerated in the constitution
ā€” behaving as a trustee. Their nature as overseers of the system leads to a simultaneous responsibility for
protecting citizenā€™s rights. There are two ļ¬‚awed assumptions to note with this traditional model. First,
because the courts adjudicate based off the constitution, their decisions are assumed to be bound by the
breadth of the constitution. Second, courts are assumed to have the ļ¬nal say in preventing the abuse of
power by keeping the branches of government horizontally accountable and hence protecting the citizensā€™
rights. These assumptions and their errors will help us understand what makes a court fall short of issuing
a good judgement so we can work to ameliorate it.
Constitutional Limitations & Judgement
	 Letā€™s look at the ļ¬rst piece: the idea that judges are bound by the text of the constitution. Because
a courtā€™s decision relies on well reasoned arguments, polities desire that a court references some sort of
legal base for their decisions ā€” the constitution. However, because constitutional drafting has high costs
of agreement for a ļ¬nal, enumerated decision, the ļ¬nal document tends to be too ambiguous and
inadequate to handle all constitutional disputes. Sweet observes how ā€œdifļ¬culties associated with
negotiating rules for all possible contingencies, and given that, as time passes, conditions will change and
the interests of the parties to the agreement will evolve, all contracts [constitutions] are incomplete in
some signiļ¬cant wayā€ (ā€œConstitutional Courts and Parliamentary Democracyā€ 86). Because judges are
!3
reliant on an incomplete document for the basis of their decisions, they must to some extent rely on their
judgement and interpretation of law or fall victim to the inherit limitations of a constitutional text. This
judgement leads to a gray-area where cases are no longer strictly law-based. There is now another salient
variable to consider: ā€œconstitutional courts are understood as institutions whose function is fundamentally
politicalā€ (Hilbink 230). In order to best handle this variable, courts must build legitimacy by being
independent, professional, and impartial. These variables will be deļ¬ned in the ā€œHow Can Judiciary
Legitimacy Be Enhancedā€ section ahead. However, the underlying understanding is that even though
judgesā€™ decisions can no longer be grounded in strictly legal terms, by bolstering the legitimacy of the
court the decision can still be considered credible.
Now Let the Court Enforce It
	 Another issue with the currently pervading understanding of the judiciary is the errant
assumption that a courtā€™s decision is binding. This assumption is incorrect because the courts generally
have no way of enforcing their decision. Hamilton indicated that ā€œthe judiciary, [ā€¦] has no inļ¬‚uence over
either the sword or the purse; no direction either of the strength or of the wealth of the society; and can
take no active resolution whatever. ā€œIt may truly be said to have neither force nor will, but merely
judgment; and must ultimately depend upon the aid of the executive arm even for the efļ¬cacy of its
judgmentsā€ (Hamilton). In fact, in the current model, if congress wanted to, they could overturn the
decisions of the court by amenfding the rigid constitution. This may not be very evident because in many
nations, and especially western nations, courtsā€™ opinions seem binding. This is because the judiciary is
viewed as a legitimate institution across the polity. As stated before, courts can be designed to build
legitimacy by being independent, professional, and impartial; moreover, their behavior as an actor can
also serve to enhance their legitimacy. As is the case for the US judiciary. Another reason, speciļ¬c to the
US, for perceived bindingness of the decision is that ā€œrigidity of the constitution enhances judicial
supremacyā€ (Hilbink 234).
!4
Conclusion
	 This overview determined that a court exists in order to issue judgements. These judgements
prevent the abuse of power from other branches of government, as well as simultaneously protecting the
rights of the citizen. The more likely the parties involved in a decision are to follow along, the ā€œbetterā€ the
decision. Following this, two issues arose damaging the quality of a decision ā€” what makes these
judgements valuable, and how can the courtā€™s decisions be enforced? Because these two issues are
interrelated, so is their solution. By building legitimacy in its institution, the court can issue ā€œlegitimate
judgementsā€ that secure compliance and respect from the parties involved.
How Can Judiciary Legitimacy Be Enhanced?
	 The courtā€™s main end is to issue legitimate judgements, which will secure compliance and respect
from the parties involved. How this end of a legitimate judgement can be persevered is through ensuring
the court is a legitimate institution. A legitimate court will lead to all actors in the polity accepting these
legitimate judgements, regardless of how much they disagree. A less legitimate court can lead to situations
like Andrew Jackson saying ā€œJohn Marshall has made his decision, now let him enforce it,ā€ the Russian
Constitutional Court getting initially dissolved, or simply a decision getting ignored. Legitimacy for the
court exists across a spectrum ā€” upon which I would argue it is difļ¬cult to predetermine a point where a
court starts to be considered ā€œlegitimate.ā€ Therefore, this section will look at how legitimacy is assessed and
maximized. The courts, and in turn their decisions, gain legitimacy in two ways. First, through the
conception and design of a societyā€™s institutions; and second, through its behavior as an institutional actor.
Institutional Design
	 Smilov provides a good model to start understanding legitimacy, arguing that ā€œin contemporary
constitutional regimes, courts and the judiciary draw their legitimacy and their normative power from at
least four different sourcesā€ (862). These ā€œfour sources, [he argues], form a universally valid (for
!5
constitutional regimes) set of values, which modelsā€”institutionally very different from each otherā€”try to
optimize, although they may balance the basic values in different ways. Societies have speciļ¬cā€”sometimes
uniqueā€”histories and experiences, which explain the stronger emphasis on one value or anotherā€ (Smilov
862). To better understand what Smilov is saying, know that he holds a very loose ā€œinterpretiveā€ point of
view which rejects the premise of ā€œpluralistsā€ who claim ā€œthere is no overall best solutionā€ (862). He
loosely believes ā€œall legal systems follow basically the same (or very similar) sets of normative principles or
valuesā€ (862). So, his loose interpretive model creates four fundamental and interrelated variables which
can vary in importance across polities: ā€œseparation of powers; the rule of law; adjudication as a mark of
sovereignty; and the need for independent arbiters in disputes between two partiesā€ (862). In order to
maximizes these variables, we must ļ¬rst seek to understand them.
	 Let us begin by looking at the separation of powers. Smilov argues that ā€œit prevents the
concentration of powers in the hands of one holder, and ensures a minimum degree of pluralism at the
highest level of governmentā€ (864). The primary ancillary for ensuring separation of powers is judicial
independence, which ā€œguarantees that there is at least one other branch of power, different from the other
(political) holders of powerā€ that ā€œcheck[s] the political branches of power through some sort of judicial
reviewā€ (Smilov 864). Not only do judicial independence and review enhance the separation of powers,
but through a quantitative analysis, La Porta demonstrates that these principles succeed in achieving both
political and economic freedom across the polity through their guarantees of various rights (La Porta 1-3).
	 Because judicial review depends on judicial independence, let us take a closer look at judicial
independence. As Macdonald and Kong outline, ā€œbecause empirical evidence demonstrates that judges do
not make decisions based exclusively on existing formal legal considerations, the notion of judicial
independence is a mythā€ (Macdonald and Kong 837). In a way, absolute judicial independence is not
possible. However, Macdonald and Kong make sure to note that ā€œone can accept the empirical claim and
still have productive discussions about judicial independenceā€ (837). Even though judicial independence is
!6
ultimately unattainable, society can decrease external inļ¬‚uences in many ways, enhancing independence
and thereby judicial review and separation of powers. The three mechanisms which improve legitimacy
through independence by decreasing external inļ¬‚uence are appointment procedures that decrease bias
towards any party/group, an age limit introduced to judicial tenure, and incentives to improve culture.
	 The second variable for enhancing legitimacy is the rule of law. The rule of law is an important
value to uphold in a society because it is ā€œimportant to guarantee law-governed and rule-bound behavior
in societyā€ (Smilov 866). Because judges are ā€œprofessional experts on rules and following the law,ā€ they are
the ultimate gate keepers of stability in a rule of law system (Smilov 866). The assumption made in
Smilovā€™s argument is that judges are regarded as professionals. Therefore the appearance of
professionalism is the route to maximize legitimacy through rule of law. This appearance can be cultivated
in two ways: the independence of judges and the right to judicial review..
	 The ļ¬rst component, independence, is so fundamental that Epstein et. al argues ā€œwithout judicial
independence, there is no rule of law, and without rule of law the conditions are not in place for the
efļ¬cient operation of an open economyā€ (Epstein et al. 119). Judicial independence is signiļ¬cant because,
as seen in the last paragraph, it also guarantees separation of powers and gives way to judicial review ā€”
the second component of professionalism. Macdonold and Kongā€™s analysis highlights this interconnection
between judicial independence and review, also showing their contribution to the rule of law. They argue
that a ā€œjudge makes appropriate use of her independence when she properly fulļ¬lls her role as a judge
[ā€¦] One might say that judges most fully occupy their institutional role when they engage in principled
reasoningā€ (Macdonald and Kong 837). When thinking about review, remember that courts occupy a
unique ā€˜constitutional space,ā€™ which means ā€œthose governed must accept that constitutional meaning is (at
least partly) constructed through judgeā€™s interoperation and rule makingā€ (Sweet 825). Because decision
making power lies with these individuals and their judgments, the legitimacy of their decision must be
!7
enhanced. This can be done by modifying appointment procedures to get judges whose decisions we
respect, adjusting structure to improve professionalism, and lastly incentivizing cultural improvements.
	 Now let us turn to another piece of legitimacy: the need for impartial arbiters in disputes between
two parties. There is no way to absolutely measure or prevent bias; in a way a court can only work to
improve the degree to which it is considered impartial. A court that is impartial will generate trust and
thereby compliance. This legitimacy claim is the closest to the understanding of why courts exists ā€” to
issue respected and complied judgements. Smilov acknowledges the court fulļ¬lls this end as he indicates
ā€œcourts generate trust when they become instrumental to broad sections of society in series of concrete
disputes between two parties,ā€ or in other words is impartial (Smilov 870). He says impartiality has three
grounds of legitimation. First, ā€œattempt to limit the exposure of the judiciary to partisanship and open
politicization in order to make it attractive as a neutral arbiter,ā€ or in other words, make the judicial
branch independent. Second, because courts are ā€œhandicapped as endorsers of comprehensive political
programs and doctrines,ā€ they must rely on the rule of law. Third, courts must ā€œcorrectly balance the
competing values of accessible justice and manageable caseload,ā€ both of which enhance legitimacy in
different respects (870). Because impartiality is so reliant on the other two principles, improving their
instruments of legitimacy through appointment, structure, and culture will improve this one as well.
Moreover, balancing accessibility and caseload is a structural issue that can be addressed through an
analysis of review procedures, and a change in appointment with regards to diversity as well.
	 Lastly, we explore adjudication as a mark of sovereignty. Sovereignty is an odd concept because
ā€œhistorically, the claim of resolution of disputes through adjudication has been the mark of
sovereigntyā€ (Smilov 869). On this simple understanding, ā€œcourts normally claim exclusive and ļ¬nal
authority over the resolution of legal disputesā€ (Smilov 869). This principle is a circular argument that
essentially says the court is sovereign because it is sovereign ā€” it also stands separate from the
interconnection between all the previous concepts. Furthermore, this principle is very weak because its
!8
only possible argument for existence is historical context ā€” which the same author warns about when he
claims that history makes a standard normative design difļ¬cult. Lastly, Smilovā€™s length of this section in
comparison to its counterparts showed the lack of care and justiļ¬cation that was put into this principle.
Earlier this paper it was determined that sovereignty actually does not even exist insofar that a courtā€™s
decision can be ignored and not implemented, or that legislature can pass an amendment nullifying the
decision of a judiciary. So for this last principle, we will instead seek to understand what the courtā€™s place
in the balance of powers should be. Should it be reliant on this old model of assumed supremacy? Or
should we look to a more modern system, one that creates an open dialogue of constitutionalism between
the judiciary and the legislature? Rather than see adjudication as a mark of sovereignty, we can see it as an
important, and in many ways, essential members of a cooperative discussion of constitutional issues. This
claim is legitimized through structural changes.
Institutional Design ā€” The Takeaways
	 In this segment of the paper we looked at Smilovā€™s arguments of how a court system draws its
legitimacy and normative power from at least four different sources: the separation of powers, the rule of
law, impartiality of the court, and a cooperative discussion of constitutional issues (a rejection of Smilovā€™s
argument of judicial sovereignty). The exploration of these four variables identiļ¬ed an interrelation of
many of the concepts and variables, so inļ¬‚uencing one area can impact many; this helps standardize
mechanisms for improving legitimacy into categories of appointment, structure, and culture. What we will
do to execute upon these mechanisms is outlined more extensively in the ļ¬nal section but an overview is
given now.
	 We will begin with the hardest to encapsulate, yet in many ways the most broadly inļ¬‚uential of
the three mechanisms: culture. Culture is the most can be enhanced if we focus on the importance of
values like judicial independence, judicial impartiality, and rule of law in the dialogue across all
institutions related with the judicial branch, both internally and externally. This isnā€™t something that can
!9
be directly inļ¬‚uenced, but can be incentivized. As for structural changes, we will seek to redeļ¬ne the
traditional notion of judicial sovereignty into one of open discussion, meaning compliance with the courts
is only as strong as their general legitimacy ā€” because the change acknowledges this reality, it will force
courts to focus on building it. The remaining structural changes are then: enhancing judicial tenure to
improve impartiality and independence; and professionalizing the court by specializing the appellate
jurisdiction. In terms of appointment, an independent commission with various stakeholders from the
political, judicial, professional, and academic ļ¬elds will be utilized to increase consensus for for the
supreme court judges, enhancing all sources of legitimacy. Furthermore, appointment should ensure
judges should in some way be demographically representative of the nation to build impartiality.
Behavior as an Actor
	 The institutional mechanisms that have so far been discussed are only one piece of the puzzle ā€”
they give courts an initial step of legitimacy. The ļ¬nal impact of a court, to some extent, is determined by
its behavior after creation. Building legitimacy through behavior is done over time and to some extent it is
done so well that modern jurists cannot even conceive of a model where their decisions would be ignored.
This can be seen ā€œwhen members of the Russian Constitutional Court asked their U.S. counterparts
about how they ensured compliance with their decisions, they were taken aback with the American
Justices' response: ā€˜They simply did not understand us,ā€™ the Russians bemoaned. ā€˜It simply had not entered
their heads that the decisions of the Court would not be implementedā€™ā€ (Epstein et. al 126). However, the
US model was not always like this. Through his leadership, Marshallā€™s court established the principle of
judicial review overturning law. He further worked in many ways to enhance the courtā€™s legitimacy though
behavior: unanimity, enumerating decisions that wouldnā€™t upset the parties involved, etc. Behavior can be
improved by enhancing culture. Ultimately, this section will explore behavior because it is a key part of
our constitutional history as well as an important factor to consider in many emerging nations.
!10
Generally, courts are understood to have binding decisions (sovereignty). However, in reality, they
are ā€œconstrained actors,ā€ meaning they consider other actors to ā€œlend force to their decisionsā€ (Epstein et.
al 125). The more effectively they make these considerations and limit their decisions within the scope of
other actors per decision, the further they broaden their scope of acceptable decisions in the future,
ultimately becoming ā€œunconstrained actorsā€ (125). This scope of decision is otherwise known as the area
where tolerance intervals of institutional actors overlap. A ā€œtolerance intervalā€ is an interval that exists for
every actor (branch of government) and is the extent,
ideologically, of decisions upon which the respective actor
would not challenge the court. This is modeled to the right.
ā€œThose intervals [ā€¦] represent the elected actors' ex ante
assessment of the relative costs and beneļ¬ts of attempting an ā€˜attackā€™ on the Courtā€, for which ā€œthese
actors take into account four factorsā€ (129). Case salience, the extent to which this issue involves or is
relevant to the actor. Case authoritativeness, which is simply the weight of the precedent (have there been
multiple decisions, has the court been unanimous, etc.). Policy-speciļ¬c public support, what the general
public thinks about the issue at hand. Lastly, diffuse public support, the legitimacy the court has built up
across society (129).
	 The Russian court demonstrates this model perfectly. The only notable drawback is that the
analysis utilizes mainly qualitative data. However, I would argue that for this model qualitative analysis is
in a way beneļ¬cial because it is most similar to the ways actors would make their assessment. During
Russiaā€™s tumultuous start as a nation its court was suspended, the constitution rewritten, and a new court
took its place. These two courts behaved very differently, resulting in different levels of legitimacy and
permanence. The Russian court had three large categories of decisions: separation of powers, federalism,
and individual rights. On cases of separation of powers and federalism, tolerance intervals of the actors
rarely coincided; however, they were almost always in agreement on the individual rights of the branches.
!11
Pres.
Senate
House
Scope
In its ļ¬rst court era, over 62% of decisions were not considered ā€œsafe.ā€ BY issuing unsafe decisions they
opened themselves to conļ¬‚ict from the other branches and also increased the chance this conļ¬‚ict would
occur in the future by decreasing tolerance intervals. In its second era, the court seemed to learn from its
mistakes as judges claimed they sought to avoid ā€œacute political questionsā€ (Epstein et. al 153). In this
period we saw that 90% of the courtā€™s decisions were in the safe area of overlap in tolerance intervals.
Judges ruled mainly on topics of individual rights, broadening all tolerance intervals and creating an area
of overlap in federalism decisions, which the court then ruled on. Ultimately the court was able to increase
its legitimacy across the polity.
Conclusion
	 This section outlined two complex, interrelated models for achieving judiciary legitimacy. The
ā€œbasic framework for the democratic system is initially established by the enactment of a constitution,ā€
which through consideration of cultural, structural, and appointment factors can be institutionally
designed to enhance legitimacy. Second, ā€œthe ļ¬ne-grained institutional structure evolves over time as the
product of the legal and political interactions among various political actors" ā€” being aware of this can
impact the courtā€™s role in those interactions (Epstein et. al 155). Although establishing a stable, effective,
democratic state is a complex process that takes a long time, the judiciary is a very important piece of this
establishment. In summary, the purpose of the judiciary is to produce complied and respected
judgements, and it can do this by maximizing legitimacy through various design changes and behaviors.
Let us now look to what exactly these changes will be.
What Will Changes to US Normative Model Look Like?
	 In the previous section, we conclusively indicated the three areas for improving legitimacy:
culture, structure, and appointment. In this section we will investigate what changes will cause these
!12
mechanisms to generate more judicial legitimacy. Let us begin by looking more speciļ¬cally at culture, in
many ways the most crucial of the three but also the hardest to capture.
Culture
	 Culture is a unique mechanism as many scholars seem to mention the need for changes in culture,
but usually as part of a broader set of suggestions. It tends to be under-deļ¬ned; however, it can be roughly
understood as ā€œvirtueā€ or ā€œgood understanding.ā€ Culture relates to how the judiciary and related
institutions understand the nature of the judicial branch. Macdonald and Kong really give the best
understanding of culture when they outline that ideas like judicial independence should be a judicial
virtue. A virtue is something we strive towards, an ideal, a ļ¬nal understanding. Throughout the paper they
explain it as something that justices, society, and other institutions should acknowledge. For instance, they
argue ā€œwhether the rule of law thrives is dependent on a range of factors, including a culture of public
commitment to the institutions that support the rule of law and a system of separation of
powersā€ (Macdonald and Kong 845). This same thought applies to all the various ideals and members
involved. However, only incentives can improve culture. How can we incentivize thinking about these
ideals? By structuring the institutions in such a way that judges consider these virtues, as we will see in
some of the changes in the section. By bringing these issues to the forefront for judges, they can diffuse
into other areas of society like academia, public discussion, and other branches. Thereby further
enhancing the understanding and quality of these virtues, again strengthening the judiciary and its
legitimacy ā€” creating a self-enforcing feedback loop. In the end, culture is an important part of ensuring
courts have longevity and behave properly.
Structure
	 To make changes in structure, we must start with its core. This means replacing the traditional
notion of judicial sovereignty with one of open discussion. Because courts will no longer have this circular
!13
sovereignty claim to legitimacy, and instead are a part of an open discussion between the legislature and
judiciary, judges are consciously and constantly reminded that their opinions are only as strong as their
legitimacy. This structural change not only reļ¬‚ects the reality of the system, as we had seen earlier judges
have no way of enforcing their decisions; it also bolsters culture in the most direct way. Because the society
is now consistently and consciously aware that judiciary power stems from the institutionā€™s legitimacy,
culture improves. They will have to keep in mind the goals of enhancing impartiality, independence, and
the rule of law when structuring the branch. With this frame of mind the following structural changes will
be with implemented: reworking judicial tenure, and specializing the appellate jurisdiction. Judges more
speciļ¬cally will be culturally aware of behavior, as it is their most direct way of increasing legitimacy. Let
us understand this structural change by looking at the debates around it.
	 The debates for structuring of power among institutions have two extremes ā€” legislative and
judicial supremacy, argued by Waldron and Dworkin respectively. Dworkin argues that courts have
sovereignty because they can guarantee rights protection impartially ā€œwith equal concern and
respect" (Dworkin 17). As we saw earlier in the paper, this claim is false. We can strive for these virtues;
however, when it comes to meeting them and building a model off it, this is somewhat unrealistic. We then
look to Waldron, who says the opposite. Essentially because judges will never be impartial, it is
ā€œunpleasantly condescendingā€ that these unelected ofļ¬cials are then given sovereignty. Waldron instead
proposes a model of legislative supremacy (Waldron 303). The main ļ¬‚aw with this model is that it relies
heavily on society understanding debates that of a constitutional nature, such as rights, are inherently
different from simple discussions of what law to pass. They should be discussions grounded in a ā€œpolitical
culture of mutual respectā€ (310). He essentially makes the same mistake as Dworkin here, assuming that
his proposed justiļ¬cation will be inherently true and that the society will instantly and holistically adjust
political culture to one that Waldron describes.
!14
Gardbaum on the other hand provides an alternative to either model of supremacy, solving the
issues with both and curing ā€œthe over-legalization or judicialization of principled public discourseā€ and
preventing ā€œthe legislative and popular debilitation that has long been identiļ¬ed as a major institutional
cost of constitutionalizationā€ (Gardbaum 173). This model gives the legislature power to overturn a
courtā€™s constitutional decision, in effect opening and enhancing a culture and dialogue of rights and
constitutional issues. Hilbink outlines that this model rejects ā€œa strict distinction between law and politics,
[which] grants supreme authority to the judiciary in constitutional decision making and sets up the
relationship between the judiciary and legislature in binary and oppositional termsā€ (Hilbink 233). If the
courts are restructured this way, we can more consciously think about mechanisms of achieving legitimacy.
Especially with instruments that are based on merit and theory rather than based off a circular
assumption.
	 The next structural implement we will explore is judicial tenure. Judicial tenure is an important
factor to achieve independence and, in turn, impartiality. If a justice is tenured they donā€™t have to worry
about political pressures to those who appointed them, and they also donā€™t have to worry about losing a
position because of a ruling. Furthermore, ā€œcommitment theorists predict an inverse relationship between
legislative tenure and judicial tenureā€ (Macdonald and Kong 845). However, tenure canā€™t be indeļ¬nite like
it is currently in the US model ā€” this can lead to a judgeā€™s opinions being ā€œgrossly out-of-step with the
rest of the political system,ā€ in other words, unprofessional (Hilbink 231). Instead, judges should be
tenured until age 75, as in the Canadian and UK models, ensuring a wholly legitimate term. This allows
them to behave freely, professionally, and in accordance to the principles reinforced by their surrounding
culture.
	 Now weā€™ll look to change the structure of the appellate courts to enhance the rule of law and
impartiality. The appellate courtā€™s judges should be specialized in a model similar to that of Germanyā€™s
constitutional court. The German model of specialization splits the supreme court into two ā€œsenatesā€ that
!15
pick issues from various legal subjects at the start of the session based on caseload (Damle 1297).
Furthermore, based on the issues their senate selects, each judge becomes a ā€œrapporteur,ā€ with an
expertise in a speciļ¬c area of law (1298). These judges are then responsible for creating ā€œvotum[s]ā€ for
cases in their legal area ā€” a votum is essentially a ā€œmajor research report. [The judge] describes the
background and facts of the dispute, surveys the courtā€™s own precedent and the legal literature, presents
fully documented arguments advanced on both sides of the question, and concludes with the personal
view of how the case should be decidedā€ (1299). The reason we look to the German constitutional courtā€™s
specialization is that in the Kelsenian legal system, the constitutional court most closely resembles a court
in the US jurisdiction. Also, since the US supreme court hears at most 1% of cases appealed to it, we seek
to apply the specialization at an appellate level to have a more immediate impact on the law. Moreover,
the precedent and values of this more precise decision making will simply diffuse upwards.
	 Fusing this model into the US system is very straightforward ā€” at the start of a legal term justices
can pick a few topics based off caseload. Then when an issue comes to the court and a panel of three is
chosen to adjudicate, it can be formed based on the issues involved and then justices randomly chosen
from other, non-related, topics; the most relevant justice(s) will be tasked with preparing a votum for the
panel which will ultimately adjudicate. This approach is interesting because it capitalizes upon the beneļ¬ts
of both a generalist and specialized court. The more specialized justice(s) get to voice their opinion and
expertise, while the ultimate decision is more generalist because there are multiple judges involved.
Additionally, because the way topics are chosen helps manage caseload, this model also improves the
perception of impartiality because it allows the courts to remain efļ¬cient and low-cost, hearing every case.
Ultimately through this model, decision making will be more legitimate because law is more uniform and
professional across the polity, caseload is managed effectively, and the ļ¬nal opinions tend to be more
unanimous.
!16
Appointment
	 Appointment is speciļ¬cally covered last because it enhances all claims of legitimacy, and in many
ways draws upon the impacts of the mechanisms proposed in this section. Akkas argues the ā€Ø
ā€œappointment system has a direct bearing on the impartiality, integrity and independence of
judgesā€ (Akkas 200). This ā€œdirect bearingā€ is because as much as a society structures institutions and
enhances culture ā€” if they pick the wrong people, decisions will suffer. Judicial appointment can be
improved if judges are selected by an independent commission that accounts for the various stakeholders
we have discussed so far. A pluralist approach similar to South Africaā€™s will be taken, their commission
ā€œconsists of judges, the Minister of Justice, practicing and academic lawyers, members of the National
Assembly including a substantial number of opposition members, members of the Provincial parliaments,
persons nominated by the President of South Africa after consulting leaders of all political parties
represented in the National Assembly and in some cases the Premier of the Province or the Premierā€™s
nomineeā€ (Akkas 209). The independent commission increases the number and background of
stakeholders. The political, judicial, professional, and academic ļ¬elds will be utilized to increase consensus
for for the supreme court judges: enhancing independence and in turn impartiality, and the rule of law. It
is important to keep in mind that culture will in many ways inļ¬‚uence the decisions this commission makes.
For instance, if the commission wants to strive towards creating an impartial court and is much more
culturally aware of the value, they would try to make the court roughly representative of the
demographics in the nation. In the end, similarly to the South African model, the commission would slate
three more appointees than are needed. Following the idea that judiciary is inherently political, and
constitutional courts will represent a back-and-forth dialogue between the judicial and the political, the
appointees are ultimately proposed by the executive and voted in by the legislature. This political portion
of appointment will further enhance legitimacy of the courts by giving them more credibility in the open
dialogue system.
!17
Conclusion
	 To ļ¬nish off this section, we went through three areas to improve ā€” culture, structure, and
appointment. Through these we were able to create a ļ¬nal normative model that captured the reality of
the judicial branch by replacing sovereignty with a model of open discussion. This underlying framework
enhances culture by making the judiciary and society more aware of how to improve judicial legitimacy.
Judicial tenure, which enhances independence and impartiality, was reformed to include a retirement age
of 75 to also ensure professionalism and thereby rule of law. Legitimacy through rule of law and
impartiality were further built upon by specializing the US appellate jurisdiction, making it more
professional and efļ¬cient. Lastly, appointment was redesigned to enhance all the scores of legitimacy. By
increasing the stakeholders, justices become more independent and impartial, and more professional. The
changes proposed to institutions in this section only capture one portion of our normative model ā€” to
fully enhance legitimacy in the judicial system we must understand and advance the culture in recognition
of these values.
Conclusion
	 A normative model was designed that started with understanding that the purpose of a court is to
create complied and respected decisions. This can be done by increasing legitimacy. Legitimacy was
understood to be built institutionally, and behaviorally. Through investigating legitimacy, three areas of
improvement were determined: culture, structure, and appointment. By focusing on these areas of
improvement, a comprehensive normative model grounded in the US system that enhanced legitimacy
was created. ā€©
!18
Works Cited
Akkas, Sarkar Ali. "Appointment of Judges: A Key Issue of Judicial Independence." Bond Law Review 16.2
	 (2004): 200-210. Web. 18 Dec. 2015
Damle, Sarang Vijay. ā€œSpecialize the Judge, Not the Court: A Lesson from the German Constitutional 	
	 Courtā€. Virginia Law Review 91.5 (2005): 1267ā€“1311. Web. 18 Dec. 2015.ā€™
Dworkin, Ronald. Freedom's Law: The Moral Reading of the American Constitution. Cambridge, MA: 	 	
	 Harvard UP, 1996. Print.
Epstein, Lee, Jack Knight, and Olga Epstein et. al. "The Role of Constitutional Courts in the 	 	
	 Establishment and Maintenance of Democratic Systems of Government." Law & Society Review 	
	 35.1 (2001): 117. Web. 18 Dec. 2015.
Gardbaum, Stephen. "Reassessing the New Commonwealth Model of Constitutionalism." International 	
	 Journal of Constitutional Law 8.2 (2010): 167-206. Print.
Hamilton, Alexander. The Federalist: A Collection of Essays. New York: n.p., 1788. The Federalist #78. 	
	 Web. 18 Dec. 2015.
Hilbink, Lisa. "Assessing the New Constitutionalism." Comparative Politics 40.2 (2008): 227-45. Print.
Jacob, Herbert et. al. Courts, Law, and Politics in Comparative Perspective. New Haven: Yale UP, 1996. Print
La Porta, Rafael, Florencio LĆ³pezā€deā€Silanes, Cristian Popā€Eleches, and Andrei Shleifer. "Judicial Checks
	 and Balances." Journal of Political Economy 112.2 (2004): 445-70. Web. 18 Dec. 2015.
Laski, Harold J.. ā€œThe Technique of Judicial Appointmentā€. Michigan Law Review 24.6 (1926): 529ā€“543. 	
	 Web. 18 Dec. 2015
!19
Macdonald, Roderick A., and Hoi Kong. "Judicial Independence as a Constitutional Virtue." Oxford 	
	 Handbooks Online. 2012-11-21. Oxford University Press. Web. 18 Dec. 2015.
Smilov, Daniel. "The Judiciary: The Least Dangerous Branch?." Oxford Handbooks Online. 2012-11-21. 	
	 Oxford University Press.
Sweet, Alec Stone. "Constitutional Courts." Oxford Handbooks Online. 2012-11-21. Oxford University 	
	 Press. Web. 18 Dec. 2015.
Sweet, Alec Stone. "Constitutional Courts and Parliamentary Democracy." West European Politics 25.1 	
	 (2002): 77-100. Print.
Waldron, Jeremy. Law and Disagreement. Oxford: Oxford UP, 2001. Print
!20

More Related Content

What's hot

Govt 2305-Ch_13
Govt 2305-Ch_13Govt 2305-Ch_13
Govt 2305-Ch_13
Rick Fair
Ā 
British and american legal system
British and american legal systemBritish and american legal system
British and american legal system
KhanhHoa Tran
Ā 
American realism- Legal Theory
American realism- Legal TheoryAmerican realism- Legal Theory
American realism- Legal Theory
Vaishnavi Kanduri
Ā 
Constitutional Interpretation Paper
Constitutional Interpretation PaperConstitutional Interpretation Paper
Constitutional Interpretation Paper
Diana Sherrard-Nichols
Ā 
Judicialbranchslideshareversion 091213105049-phpapp02
Judicialbranchslideshareversion 091213105049-phpapp02Judicialbranchslideshareversion 091213105049-phpapp02
Judicialbranchslideshareversion 091213105049-phpapp02
gmurillo305
Ā 

What's hot (19)

Govt 2305-Ch_13
Govt 2305-Ch_13Govt 2305-Ch_13
Govt 2305-Ch_13
Ā 
Jurisprudence - Dworkin Theory of Adjudication
Jurisprudence - Dworkin Theory of AdjudicationJurisprudence - Dworkin Theory of Adjudication
Jurisprudence - Dworkin Theory of Adjudication
Ā 
Ch01
Ch01Ch01
Ch01
Ā 
Karl N. Llewellyn 0503 Intro
Karl N. Llewellyn 0503 IntroKarl N. Llewellyn 0503 Intro
Karl N. Llewellyn 0503 Intro
Ā 
British and american legal system
British and american legal systemBritish and american legal system
British and american legal system
Ā 
American realism- Legal Theory
American realism- Legal TheoryAmerican realism- Legal Theory
American realism- Legal Theory
Ā 
Constitutional Interpretation Paper
Constitutional Interpretation PaperConstitutional Interpretation Paper
Constitutional Interpretation Paper
Ā 
Judge Posner on Legislation
Judge Posner on LegislationJudge Posner on Legislation
Judge Posner on Legislation
Ā 
Bodenheimer and the theories of adjudication
Bodenheimer and the theories of adjudicationBodenheimer and the theories of adjudication
Bodenheimer and the theories of adjudication
Ā 
Precedents concept and kinds
Precedents concept and kindsPrecedents concept and kinds
Precedents concept and kinds
Ā 
Proclem and cencern in comparision of constitution
Proclem and cencern in comparision of constitution Proclem and cencern in comparision of constitution
Proclem and cencern in comparision of constitution
Ā 
Difference between legal logic and legal rhetoric
Difference between legal logic and legal rhetoricDifference between legal logic and legal rhetoric
Difference between legal logic and legal rhetoric
Ā 
Precedent
PrecedentPrecedent
Precedent
Ā 
Doctrine of Precedent - India, U.S and U.K
Doctrine of Precedent - India, U.S and U.KDoctrine of Precedent - India, U.S and U.K
Doctrine of Precedent - India, U.S and U.K
Ā 
Judicialbranchslideshareversion 091213105049-phpapp02
Judicialbranchslideshareversion 091213105049-phpapp02Judicialbranchslideshareversion 091213105049-phpapp02
Judicialbranchslideshareversion 091213105049-phpapp02
Ā 
Justiciability
JusticiabilityJusticiability
Justiciability
Ā 
God and the rule of law From a biblical prospective
God and the rule of law From a biblical prospectiveGod and the rule of law From a biblical prospective
God and the rule of law From a biblical prospective
Ā 
Hart's Concept of Law
Hart's Concept of LawHart's Concept of Law
Hart's Concept of Law
Ā 
Legal realism
Legal realismLegal realism
Legal realism
Ā 

Viewers also liked

Law-Exchange.co.uk Powerpoint
Law-Exchange.co.uk PowerpointLaw-Exchange.co.uk Powerpoint
Law-Exchange.co.uk Powerpoint
lawexchange.co.uk
Ā 
Š² сŠµŠ³Š¾Š“Š½ŃŃˆŠ½ŠµŠ¼ Š¼ŠøрŠµ
Š² сŠµŠ³Š¾Š“Š½ŃŃˆŠ½ŠµŠ¼ Š¼ŠøрŠµŠ² сŠµŠ³Š¾Š“Š½ŃŃˆŠ½ŠµŠ¼ Š¼ŠøрŠµ
Š² сŠµŠ³Š¾Š“Š½ŃŃˆŠ½ŠµŠ¼ Š¼ŠøрŠµ
Anjelikakasakian
Ā 
21 Cost efficient QM in microbreweries agk
21 Cost efficient QM in microbreweries agk21 Cost efficient QM in microbreweries agk
21 Cost efficient QM in microbreweries agk
Axel Kristiansen
Ā 
Grid Tech Corporate Presentation- Final
Grid Tech Corporate Presentation- FinalGrid Tech Corporate Presentation- Final
Grid Tech Corporate Presentation- Final
Harvinder Singh
Ā 
Judicial roles
Judicial rolesJudicial roles
Judicial roles
venusrice
Ā 
All final
All finalAll final
All final
Helen Bass
Ā 
Model essay: Should the UK adopt a codified constitution
Model essay: Should the UK adopt a codified constitutionModel essay: Should the UK adopt a codified constitution
Model essay: Should the UK adopt a codified constitution
mattbentley34
Ā 
The relationship between the separation of powers
The relationship between the separation of powersThe relationship between the separation of powers
The relationship between the separation of powers
Ratnesh Dwivedi
Ā 

Viewers also liked (20)

Racial diversity power point (boys)
Racial diversity power point (boys)Racial diversity power point (boys)
Racial diversity power point (boys)
Ā 
Diversity
DiversityDiversity
Diversity
Ā 
Law-Exchange.co.uk Powerpoint
Law-Exchange.co.uk PowerpointLaw-Exchange.co.uk Powerpoint
Law-Exchange.co.uk Powerpoint
Ā 
2079899_BL
2079899_BL2079899_BL
2079899_BL
Ā 
Hypothesis
Hypothesis Hypothesis
Hypothesis
Ā 
Š² сŠµŠ³Š¾Š“Š½ŃŃˆŠ½ŠµŠ¼ Š¼ŠøрŠµ
Š² сŠµŠ³Š¾Š“Š½ŃŃˆŠ½ŠµŠ¼ Š¼ŠøрŠµŠ² сŠµŠ³Š¾Š“Š½ŃŃˆŠ½ŠµŠ¼ Š¼ŠøрŠµ
Š² сŠµŠ³Š¾Š“Š½ŃŃˆŠ½ŠµŠ¼ Š¼ŠøрŠµ
Ā 
Dinobandhu Ghosh CV
Dinobandhu Ghosh CVDinobandhu Ghosh CV
Dinobandhu Ghosh CV
Ā 
EDUCACION EN TECNOLOGIA
EDUCACION EN TECNOLOGIAEDUCACION EN TECNOLOGIA
EDUCACION EN TECNOLOGIA
Ā 
naturaleza
naturalezanaturaleza
naturaleza
Ā 
Europe Iconography - Laboratorio del cittadino
Europe Iconography - Laboratorio del cittadinoEurope Iconography - Laboratorio del cittadino
Europe Iconography - Laboratorio del cittadino
Ā 
Kant
Kant Kant
Kant
Ā 
21 Cost efficient QM in microbreweries agk
21 Cost efficient QM in microbreweries agk21 Cost efficient QM in microbreweries agk
21 Cost efficient QM in microbreweries agk
Ā 
Grid Tech Corporate Presentation- Final
Grid Tech Corporate Presentation- FinalGrid Tech Corporate Presentation- Final
Grid Tech Corporate Presentation- Final
Ā 
Chį»©ng minh hai đoįŗ”n thįŗ³ng bįŗ±ng nhau
Chį»©ng minh hai đoįŗ”n thįŗ³ng bįŗ±ng nhauChį»©ng minh hai đoįŗ”n thįŗ³ng bįŗ±ng nhau
Chį»©ng minh hai đoįŗ”n thįŗ³ng bįŗ±ng nhau
Ā 
Trac nghiem-hat-nhan-nguyen-tu
Trac nghiem-hat-nhan-nguyen-tuTrac nghiem-hat-nhan-nguyen-tu
Trac nghiem-hat-nhan-nguyen-tu
Ā 
Judicial roles
Judicial rolesJudicial roles
Judicial roles
Ā 
All final
All finalAll final
All final
Ā 
Understanding our Criminal Justice System
Understanding our Criminal  Justice SystemUnderstanding our Criminal  Justice System
Understanding our Criminal Justice System
Ā 
Model essay: Should the UK adopt a codified constitution
Model essay: Should the UK adopt a codified constitutionModel essay: Should the UK adopt a codified constitution
Model essay: Should the UK adopt a codified constitution
Ā 
The relationship between the separation of powers
The relationship between the separation of powersThe relationship between the separation of powers
The relationship between the separation of powers
Ā 

Similar to Enhancing Judicial Legitimacy

Page 55 BUSINESS AND THE CONSTITUTIONA federal statute and.docx
Page 55 BUSINESS AND THE CONSTITUTIONA federal statute and.docxPage 55 BUSINESS AND THE CONSTITUTIONA federal statute and.docx
Page 55 BUSINESS AND THE CONSTITUTIONA federal statute and.docx
alfred4lewis58146
Ā 
Business Law I Introduction to LawHello class and welcome to t.docx
Business Law I Introduction to LawHello class and welcome to t.docxBusiness Law I Introduction to LawHello class and welcome to t.docx
Business Law I Introduction to LawHello class and welcome to t.docx
RAHUL126667
Ā 
15INTRODUCTION TO AMERICAN LEGAL SYSTEMINTRODUCTION.docx
15INTRODUCTION TO AMERICAN LEGAL SYSTEMINTRODUCTION.docx15INTRODUCTION TO AMERICAN LEGAL SYSTEMINTRODUCTION.docx
15INTRODUCTION TO AMERICAN LEGAL SYSTEMINTRODUCTION.docx
drennanmicah
Ā 
Assignment 2 Social Structure and Social Interacti.docx
Assignment 2 Social Structure and Social Interacti.docxAssignment 2 Social Structure and Social Interacti.docx
Assignment 2 Social Structure and Social Interacti.docx
braycarissa250
Ā 
Judge Posner on 'The Constitution as an Economic Document'
Judge Posner  on 'The Constitution as an Economic Document'Judge Posner  on 'The Constitution as an Economic Document'
Judge Posner on 'The Constitution as an Economic Document'
Shiva Kumar Srinivasan
Ā 
Chapter 22Ā THE LAW AND TALENT MANAGEMENTWayne F. Cascio, H
Chapter 22Ā THE LAW AND TALENT MANAGEMENTWayne F. Cascio, HChapter 22Ā THE LAW AND TALENT MANAGEMENTWayne F. Cascio, H
Chapter 22Ā THE LAW AND TALENT MANAGEMENTWayne F. Cascio, H
EstelaJeffery653
Ā 
1Chapter 2 LEGAL RIGHTS AND RESPONSIBILITIES(Laws Governi.docx
1Chapter 2 LEGAL RIGHTS AND RESPONSIBILITIES(Laws Governi.docx1Chapter 2 LEGAL RIGHTS AND RESPONSIBILITIES(Laws Governi.docx
1Chapter 2 LEGAL RIGHTS AND RESPONSIBILITIES(Laws Governi.docx
hyacinthshackley2629
Ā 
final sections of judicial branch
final sections of judicial branchfinal sections of judicial branch
final sections of judicial branch
adutcher
Ā 
# 151053 Cust Cengage Au Hall Pg. No. iii Title Cri.docx
# 151053   Cust Cengage   Au Hall  Pg. No. iii Title  Cri.docx# 151053   Cust Cengage   Au Hall  Pg. No. iii Title  Cri.docx
# 151053 Cust Cengage Au Hall Pg. No. iii Title Cri.docx
AASTHA76
Ā 

Similar to Enhancing Judicial Legitimacy (10)

Essay brief 20172018 module titlethe criminal justice process
Essay brief 20172018 module titlethe criminal justice processEssay brief 20172018 module titlethe criminal justice process
Essay brief 20172018 module titlethe criminal justice process
Ā 
Page 55 BUSINESS AND THE CONSTITUTIONA federal statute and.docx
Page 55 BUSINESS AND THE CONSTITUTIONA federal statute and.docxPage 55 BUSINESS AND THE CONSTITUTIONA federal statute and.docx
Page 55 BUSINESS AND THE CONSTITUTIONA federal statute and.docx
Ā 
Business Law I Introduction to LawHello class and welcome to t.docx
Business Law I Introduction to LawHello class and welcome to t.docxBusiness Law I Introduction to LawHello class and welcome to t.docx
Business Law I Introduction to LawHello class and welcome to t.docx
Ā 
15INTRODUCTION TO AMERICAN LEGAL SYSTEMINTRODUCTION.docx
15INTRODUCTION TO AMERICAN LEGAL SYSTEMINTRODUCTION.docx15INTRODUCTION TO AMERICAN LEGAL SYSTEMINTRODUCTION.docx
15INTRODUCTION TO AMERICAN LEGAL SYSTEMINTRODUCTION.docx
Ā 
Assignment 2 Social Structure and Social Interacti.docx
Assignment 2 Social Structure and Social Interacti.docxAssignment 2 Social Structure and Social Interacti.docx
Assignment 2 Social Structure and Social Interacti.docx
Ā 
Judge Posner on 'The Constitution as an Economic Document'
Judge Posner  on 'The Constitution as an Economic Document'Judge Posner  on 'The Constitution as an Economic Document'
Judge Posner on 'The Constitution as an Economic Document'
Ā 
Chapter 22Ā THE LAW AND TALENT MANAGEMENTWayne F. Cascio, H
Chapter 22Ā THE LAW AND TALENT MANAGEMENTWayne F. Cascio, HChapter 22Ā THE LAW AND TALENT MANAGEMENTWayne F. Cascio, H
Chapter 22Ā THE LAW AND TALENT MANAGEMENTWayne F. Cascio, H
Ā 
1Chapter 2 LEGAL RIGHTS AND RESPONSIBILITIES(Laws Governi.docx
1Chapter 2 LEGAL RIGHTS AND RESPONSIBILITIES(Laws Governi.docx1Chapter 2 LEGAL RIGHTS AND RESPONSIBILITIES(Laws Governi.docx
1Chapter 2 LEGAL RIGHTS AND RESPONSIBILITIES(Laws Governi.docx
Ā 
final sections of judicial branch
final sections of judicial branchfinal sections of judicial branch
final sections of judicial branch
Ā 
# 151053 Cust Cengage Au Hall Pg. No. iii Title Cri.docx
# 151053   Cust Cengage   Au Hall  Pg. No. iii Title  Cri.docx# 151053   Cust Cengage   Au Hall  Pg. No. iii Title  Cri.docx
# 151053 Cust Cengage Au Hall Pg. No. iii Title Cri.docx
Ā 

Recently uploaded

THE OBSTACLES THAT IMPEDE THE DEVELOPMENT OF BRAZIL IN THE CONTEMPORARY ERA A...
THE OBSTACLES THAT IMPEDE THE DEVELOPMENT OF BRAZIL IN THE CONTEMPORARY ERA A...THE OBSTACLES THAT IMPEDE THE DEVELOPMENT OF BRAZIL IN THE CONTEMPORARY ERA A...
THE OBSTACLES THAT IMPEDE THE DEVELOPMENT OF BRAZIL IN THE CONTEMPORARY ERA A...
Faga1939
Ā 
{Qatar{^šŸš€^(+971558539980**}})Abortion Pills for Sale in Dubai. .abu dhabi, sh...
{Qatar{^šŸš€^(+971558539980**}})Abortion Pills for Sale in Dubai. .abu dhabi, sh...{Qatar{^šŸš€^(+971558539980**}})Abortion Pills for Sale in Dubai. .abu dhabi, sh...
{Qatar{^šŸš€^(+971558539980**}})Abortion Pills for Sale in Dubai. .abu dhabi, sh...
hyt3577
Ā 
9953056974 Call Girls In Pratap Nagar, Escorts (Delhi) NCR
9953056974 Call Girls In Pratap Nagar, Escorts (Delhi) NCR9953056974 Call Girls In Pratap Nagar, Escorts (Delhi) NCR
9953056974 Call Girls In Pratap Nagar, Escorts (Delhi) NCR
9953056974 Low Rate Call Girls In Saket, Delhi NCR
Ā 
The political system of the united kingdom
The political system of the united kingdomThe political system of the united kingdom
The political system of the united kingdom
lunadelior
Ā 
call girls inMahavir Nagar (delhi) call me [šŸ”9953056974šŸ”] escort service 24X7
call girls inMahavir Nagar  (delhi) call me [šŸ”9953056974šŸ”] escort service 24X7call girls inMahavir Nagar  (delhi) call me [šŸ”9953056974šŸ”] escort service 24X7
call girls inMahavir Nagar (delhi) call me [šŸ”9953056974šŸ”] escort service 24X7
9953056974 Low Rate Call Girls In Saket, Delhi NCR
Ā 

Recently uploaded (20)

Dubai Call Girls Pinky O525547819 Call Girl's In Dubai
Dubai Call Girls Pinky O525547819 Call Girl's In DubaiDubai Call Girls Pinky O525547819 Call Girl's In Dubai
Dubai Call Girls Pinky O525547819 Call Girl's In Dubai
Ā 
Job-OriŠµntŠµd Courses That Will Boost Your Career in 2024
Job-OriŠµntŠµd Courses That Will Boost Your Career in 2024Job-OriŠµntŠµd Courses That Will Boost Your Career in 2024
Job-OriŠµntŠµd Courses That Will Boost Your Career in 2024
Ā 
06052024_First India Newspaper Jaipur.pdf
06052024_First India Newspaper Jaipur.pdf06052024_First India Newspaper Jaipur.pdf
06052024_First India Newspaper Jaipur.pdf
Ā 
10052024_First India Newspaper Jaipur.pdf
10052024_First India Newspaper Jaipur.pdf10052024_First India Newspaper Jaipur.pdf
10052024_First India Newspaper Jaipur.pdf
Ā 
THE OBSTACLES THAT IMPEDE THE DEVELOPMENT OF BRAZIL IN THE CONTEMPORARY ERA A...
THE OBSTACLES THAT IMPEDE THE DEVELOPMENT OF BRAZIL IN THE CONTEMPORARY ERA A...THE OBSTACLES THAT IMPEDE THE DEVELOPMENT OF BRAZIL IN THE CONTEMPORARY ERA A...
THE OBSTACLES THAT IMPEDE THE DEVELOPMENT OF BRAZIL IN THE CONTEMPORARY ERA A...
Ā 
{Qatar{^šŸš€^(+971558539980**}})Abortion Pills for Sale in Dubai. .abu dhabi, sh...
{Qatar{^šŸš€^(+971558539980**}})Abortion Pills for Sale in Dubai. .abu dhabi, sh...{Qatar{^šŸš€^(+971558539980**}})Abortion Pills for Sale in Dubai. .abu dhabi, sh...
{Qatar{^šŸš€^(+971558539980**}})Abortion Pills for Sale in Dubai. .abu dhabi, sh...
Ā 
Unveiling the Characteristics of Political Institutions_ A Comprehensive Anal...
Unveiling the Characteristics of Political Institutions_ A Comprehensive Anal...Unveiling the Characteristics of Political Institutions_ A Comprehensive Anal...
Unveiling the Characteristics of Political Institutions_ A Comprehensive Anal...
Ā 
Politician uddhav thackeray biography- Full Details
Politician uddhav thackeray biography- Full DetailsPolitician uddhav thackeray biography- Full Details
Politician uddhav thackeray biography- Full Details
Ā 
America Is the Target; Israel Is the Front Line _ Andy Blumenthal _ The Blogs...
America Is the Target; Israel Is the Front Line _ Andy Blumenthal _ The Blogs...America Is the Target; Israel Is the Front Line _ Andy Blumenthal _ The Blogs...
America Is the Target; Israel Is the Front Line _ Andy Blumenthal _ The Blogs...
Ā 
9953056974 Call Girls In Pratap Nagar, Escorts (Delhi) NCR
9953056974 Call Girls In Pratap Nagar, Escorts (Delhi) NCR9953056974 Call Girls In Pratap Nagar, Escorts (Delhi) NCR
9953056974 Call Girls In Pratap Nagar, Escorts (Delhi) NCR
Ā 
05052024_First India Newspaper Jaipur.pdf
05052024_First India Newspaper Jaipur.pdf05052024_First India Newspaper Jaipur.pdf
05052024_First India Newspaper Jaipur.pdf
Ā 
Transformative Leadership: N Chandrababu Naidu and TDP's Vision for Innovatio...
Transformative Leadership: N Chandrababu Naidu and TDP's Vision for Innovatio...Transformative Leadership: N Chandrababu Naidu and TDP's Vision for Innovatio...
Transformative Leadership: N Chandrababu Naidu and TDP's Vision for Innovatio...
Ā 
04052024_First India Newspaper Jaipur.pdf
04052024_First India Newspaper Jaipur.pdf04052024_First India Newspaper Jaipur.pdf
04052024_First India Newspaper Jaipur.pdf
Ā 
The political system of the united kingdom
The political system of the united kingdomThe political system of the united kingdom
The political system of the united kingdom
Ā 
*Navigating Electoral Terrain: TDP's Performance under N Chandrababu Naidu's ...
*Navigating Electoral Terrain: TDP's Performance under N Chandrababu Naidu's ...*Navigating Electoral Terrain: TDP's Performance under N Chandrababu Naidu's ...
*Navigating Electoral Terrain: TDP's Performance under N Chandrababu Naidu's ...
Ā 
422524114-Patriarchy-Kamla-Bhasin gg.pdf
422524114-Patriarchy-Kamla-Bhasin gg.pdf422524114-Patriarchy-Kamla-Bhasin gg.pdf
422524114-Patriarchy-Kamla-Bhasin gg.pdf
Ā 
call girls inMahavir Nagar (delhi) call me [šŸ”9953056974šŸ”] escort service 24X7
call girls inMahavir Nagar  (delhi) call me [šŸ”9953056974šŸ”] escort service 24X7call girls inMahavir Nagar  (delhi) call me [šŸ”9953056974šŸ”] escort service 24X7
call girls inMahavir Nagar (delhi) call me [šŸ”9953056974šŸ”] escort service 24X7
Ā 
China's soft power in 21st century .pptx
China's soft power in 21st century   .pptxChina's soft power in 21st century   .pptx
China's soft power in 21st century .pptx
Ā 
KING VISHNU BHAGWANON KA BHAGWAN PARAMATMONKA PARATOMIC PARAMANU KASARVAMANVA...
KING VISHNU BHAGWANON KA BHAGWAN PARAMATMONKA PARATOMIC PARAMANU KASARVAMANVA...KING VISHNU BHAGWANON KA BHAGWAN PARAMATMONKA PARATOMIC PARAMANU KASARVAMANVA...
KING VISHNU BHAGWANON KA BHAGWAN PARAMATMONKA PARATOMIC PARAMANU KASARVAMANVA...
Ā 
declarationleaders_sd_re_greens_theleft_5.pdf
declarationleaders_sd_re_greens_theleft_5.pdfdeclarationleaders_sd_re_greens_theleft_5.pdf
declarationleaders_sd_re_greens_theleft_5.pdf
Ā 

Enhancing Judicial Legitimacy

  • 1. Judicial Legitimacy Creating a constitution is an imposing task. There are many components to consider, and even then, a constitution cannot fully account for the stability of a nation. The constitution can only set the fundamental groundwork. That is why in some countries, like the US, components may exist completely outside the mainstream understanding of what works today. Nonetheless, it is worth attempting to improve these elements as they are fundamental to the existence of the state. The US judicial branch is one of these components. As Jacobs indicates, ā€œmany students remain unaware that the American legal system is an exception to what prevails in most of the rest of the worldā€ (vii). Although the US constitution has stood the test of time, its ideals with regards to the judiciary are in no way a model for the modern world. This paper will comparatively analyze the US judicial system with various nations such as Russia, Germany, and South Africa to create a normative design of the American judicial branch. This normative model will address the inherit ļ¬‚aws that exist within the American judicial branch, which make a constitutional nation less sustainable. In order to address these issues, one must ļ¬rst understand why the judicial branch exists; then how it can best fulļ¬ll these ends; and lastly what cultural, structural, and appointment mechanisms in a normative US model would look like. A Brief Introduction to the US Model Th4e American Paradox The American model is paradoxical in many ways; although its conception made it seem as though it was the weakest of the three branches, time has proven it to be a major part of the American polity. The constitution itself, the establishment of judicial review, and the Federalist Papers led to this initial perception of weakness. In the US constitution, articles I, II, and III outline the three branches. The legislative and executive branch are the topic of the ļ¬rst two articles; both have more sections, clearly enumerated powers/responsibilities, and speciļ¬c outlines of who can occupy the position(s). The judiciary !1
  • 2. on the other hand is the last of the three articles, has the least sections, is written vaguely, and does not even outline who is able to be a justice. It seems that the judicial was simply thrown on as an afterthought. Even the concept of judicial review, an underpinning of how we understand courts today, was established by the court itself (not the constitution). This further highlights the vagueness and weakness of the judicial branch as written in the constitution. Moreover, in the famous Federalist 78 , Hamilton outlined that the court is the weakest of the three branches, because it does not have the power of ā€œthe sword or the purseā€ (ā€œFederalist no. 78ā€). How then does this courtā€™s decision have ā€œpowerā€ in the checks and balances system? Through legitimacy. Legitimacy will be deļ¬ned more extensively later in the paper ā€” however, it is achieved both from the branchā€™s conception and its behavior as an actor in the constitutional system. Common Law Conundrum As one looks to the US model, it is hard to avoid the elephant in the room: the comparatively rare common law system. Although an entirely different paper could be written on the various merits of the common law and Kelsenian system in structuring of the courts, both methods are sustainable. Regardless of these disputes, even if the US changed to a civil law system, the institutional and structural costs would outweigh the net beneļ¬ts from the new system. Therefore, this paper will assume efļ¬cacy of the common law system. Furthermore, another detail to consider is the simple principle that constitutional courts, judges, and decisions occupy a ā€˜constitutional spaceā€™ that is neither ā€˜judicialā€™ nor ā€˜politicalā€™ (Sweet, ā€œConstitutional Courts and Parliamentary Democracyā€ 80; ā€œConstitutional Courtsā€ 818). This framing of a somewhat ambiguous nature of a judicial branch will be an important theme to note throughout this paper and will be, in part, justiļ¬cation for use of the common law system. For these reasons, this paper will aim to solve the problems of the judicial branch in the lens of US common law system. If these issues are going to be addressed, let us start by simply understanding why courts exist. !2
  • 3. Why Do Courts Exist? At their very core, courts exist to interpret the law and issue judgements. Since WWII, in judicial models around the world, courts interpret the law by checking it against the constitution ā€” the document which underpins all legal texts. It is through this interpretation of the law that they can then check the powers of the other two branches. This is because of the way balance of powers is conceptualized with the constitution. Because the polity ā€œagreedā€ on the constitution, they created two agents: the executive and legislative, both with positive lawmaking capabilities of whom ā€œthe peopleā€ are the principals. The courts in a way keep those agents honest to the principles of their creation enumerated in the constitution ā€” behaving as a trustee. Their nature as overseers of the system leads to a simultaneous responsibility for protecting citizenā€™s rights. There are two ļ¬‚awed assumptions to note with this traditional model. First, because the courts adjudicate based off the constitution, their decisions are assumed to be bound by the breadth of the constitution. Second, courts are assumed to have the ļ¬nal say in preventing the abuse of power by keeping the branches of government horizontally accountable and hence protecting the citizensā€™ rights. These assumptions and their errors will help us understand what makes a court fall short of issuing a good judgement so we can work to ameliorate it. Constitutional Limitations & Judgement Letā€™s look at the ļ¬rst piece: the idea that judges are bound by the text of the constitution. Because a courtā€™s decision relies on well reasoned arguments, polities desire that a court references some sort of legal base for their decisions ā€” the constitution. However, because constitutional drafting has high costs of agreement for a ļ¬nal, enumerated decision, the ļ¬nal document tends to be too ambiguous and inadequate to handle all constitutional disputes. Sweet observes how ā€œdifļ¬culties associated with negotiating rules for all possible contingencies, and given that, as time passes, conditions will change and the interests of the parties to the agreement will evolve, all contracts [constitutions] are incomplete in some signiļ¬cant wayā€ (ā€œConstitutional Courts and Parliamentary Democracyā€ 86). Because judges are !3
  • 4. reliant on an incomplete document for the basis of their decisions, they must to some extent rely on their judgement and interpretation of law or fall victim to the inherit limitations of a constitutional text. This judgement leads to a gray-area where cases are no longer strictly law-based. There is now another salient variable to consider: ā€œconstitutional courts are understood as institutions whose function is fundamentally politicalā€ (Hilbink 230). In order to best handle this variable, courts must build legitimacy by being independent, professional, and impartial. These variables will be deļ¬ned in the ā€œHow Can Judiciary Legitimacy Be Enhancedā€ section ahead. However, the underlying understanding is that even though judgesā€™ decisions can no longer be grounded in strictly legal terms, by bolstering the legitimacy of the court the decision can still be considered credible. Now Let the Court Enforce It Another issue with the currently pervading understanding of the judiciary is the errant assumption that a courtā€™s decision is binding. This assumption is incorrect because the courts generally have no way of enforcing their decision. Hamilton indicated that ā€œthe judiciary, [ā€¦] has no inļ¬‚uence over either the sword or the purse; no direction either of the strength or of the wealth of the society; and can take no active resolution whatever. ā€œIt may truly be said to have neither force nor will, but merely judgment; and must ultimately depend upon the aid of the executive arm even for the efļ¬cacy of its judgmentsā€ (Hamilton). In fact, in the current model, if congress wanted to, they could overturn the decisions of the court by amenfding the rigid constitution. This may not be very evident because in many nations, and especially western nations, courtsā€™ opinions seem binding. This is because the judiciary is viewed as a legitimate institution across the polity. As stated before, courts can be designed to build legitimacy by being independent, professional, and impartial; moreover, their behavior as an actor can also serve to enhance their legitimacy. As is the case for the US judiciary. Another reason, speciļ¬c to the US, for perceived bindingness of the decision is that ā€œrigidity of the constitution enhances judicial supremacyā€ (Hilbink 234). !4
  • 5. Conclusion This overview determined that a court exists in order to issue judgements. These judgements prevent the abuse of power from other branches of government, as well as simultaneously protecting the rights of the citizen. The more likely the parties involved in a decision are to follow along, the ā€œbetterā€ the decision. Following this, two issues arose damaging the quality of a decision ā€” what makes these judgements valuable, and how can the courtā€™s decisions be enforced? Because these two issues are interrelated, so is their solution. By building legitimacy in its institution, the court can issue ā€œlegitimate judgementsā€ that secure compliance and respect from the parties involved. How Can Judiciary Legitimacy Be Enhanced? The courtā€™s main end is to issue legitimate judgements, which will secure compliance and respect from the parties involved. How this end of a legitimate judgement can be persevered is through ensuring the court is a legitimate institution. A legitimate court will lead to all actors in the polity accepting these legitimate judgements, regardless of how much they disagree. A less legitimate court can lead to situations like Andrew Jackson saying ā€œJohn Marshall has made his decision, now let him enforce it,ā€ the Russian Constitutional Court getting initially dissolved, or simply a decision getting ignored. Legitimacy for the court exists across a spectrum ā€” upon which I would argue it is difļ¬cult to predetermine a point where a court starts to be considered ā€œlegitimate.ā€ Therefore, this section will look at how legitimacy is assessed and maximized. The courts, and in turn their decisions, gain legitimacy in two ways. First, through the conception and design of a societyā€™s institutions; and second, through its behavior as an institutional actor. Institutional Design Smilov provides a good model to start understanding legitimacy, arguing that ā€œin contemporary constitutional regimes, courts and the judiciary draw their legitimacy and their normative power from at least four different sourcesā€ (862). These ā€œfour sources, [he argues], form a universally valid (for !5
  • 6. constitutional regimes) set of values, which modelsā€”institutionally very different from each otherā€”try to optimize, although they may balance the basic values in different ways. Societies have speciļ¬cā€”sometimes uniqueā€”histories and experiences, which explain the stronger emphasis on one value or anotherā€ (Smilov 862). To better understand what Smilov is saying, know that he holds a very loose ā€œinterpretiveā€ point of view which rejects the premise of ā€œpluralistsā€ who claim ā€œthere is no overall best solutionā€ (862). He loosely believes ā€œall legal systems follow basically the same (or very similar) sets of normative principles or valuesā€ (862). So, his loose interpretive model creates four fundamental and interrelated variables which can vary in importance across polities: ā€œseparation of powers; the rule of law; adjudication as a mark of sovereignty; and the need for independent arbiters in disputes between two partiesā€ (862). In order to maximizes these variables, we must ļ¬rst seek to understand them. Let us begin by looking at the separation of powers. Smilov argues that ā€œit prevents the concentration of powers in the hands of one holder, and ensures a minimum degree of pluralism at the highest level of governmentā€ (864). The primary ancillary for ensuring separation of powers is judicial independence, which ā€œguarantees that there is at least one other branch of power, different from the other (political) holders of powerā€ that ā€œcheck[s] the political branches of power through some sort of judicial reviewā€ (Smilov 864). Not only do judicial independence and review enhance the separation of powers, but through a quantitative analysis, La Porta demonstrates that these principles succeed in achieving both political and economic freedom across the polity through their guarantees of various rights (La Porta 1-3). Because judicial review depends on judicial independence, let us take a closer look at judicial independence. As Macdonald and Kong outline, ā€œbecause empirical evidence demonstrates that judges do not make decisions based exclusively on existing formal legal considerations, the notion of judicial independence is a mythā€ (Macdonald and Kong 837). In a way, absolute judicial independence is not possible. However, Macdonald and Kong make sure to note that ā€œone can accept the empirical claim and still have productive discussions about judicial independenceā€ (837). Even though judicial independence is !6
  • 7. ultimately unattainable, society can decrease external inļ¬‚uences in many ways, enhancing independence and thereby judicial review and separation of powers. The three mechanisms which improve legitimacy through independence by decreasing external inļ¬‚uence are appointment procedures that decrease bias towards any party/group, an age limit introduced to judicial tenure, and incentives to improve culture. The second variable for enhancing legitimacy is the rule of law. The rule of law is an important value to uphold in a society because it is ā€œimportant to guarantee law-governed and rule-bound behavior in societyā€ (Smilov 866). Because judges are ā€œprofessional experts on rules and following the law,ā€ they are the ultimate gate keepers of stability in a rule of law system (Smilov 866). The assumption made in Smilovā€™s argument is that judges are regarded as professionals. Therefore the appearance of professionalism is the route to maximize legitimacy through rule of law. This appearance can be cultivated in two ways: the independence of judges and the right to judicial review.. The ļ¬rst component, independence, is so fundamental that Epstein et. al argues ā€œwithout judicial independence, there is no rule of law, and without rule of law the conditions are not in place for the efļ¬cient operation of an open economyā€ (Epstein et al. 119). Judicial independence is signiļ¬cant because, as seen in the last paragraph, it also guarantees separation of powers and gives way to judicial review ā€” the second component of professionalism. Macdonold and Kongā€™s analysis highlights this interconnection between judicial independence and review, also showing their contribution to the rule of law. They argue that a ā€œjudge makes appropriate use of her independence when she properly fulļ¬lls her role as a judge [ā€¦] One might say that judges most fully occupy their institutional role when they engage in principled reasoningā€ (Macdonald and Kong 837). When thinking about review, remember that courts occupy a unique ā€˜constitutional space,ā€™ which means ā€œthose governed must accept that constitutional meaning is (at least partly) constructed through judgeā€™s interoperation and rule makingā€ (Sweet 825). Because decision making power lies with these individuals and their judgments, the legitimacy of their decision must be !7
  • 8. enhanced. This can be done by modifying appointment procedures to get judges whose decisions we respect, adjusting structure to improve professionalism, and lastly incentivizing cultural improvements. Now let us turn to another piece of legitimacy: the need for impartial arbiters in disputes between two parties. There is no way to absolutely measure or prevent bias; in a way a court can only work to improve the degree to which it is considered impartial. A court that is impartial will generate trust and thereby compliance. This legitimacy claim is the closest to the understanding of why courts exists ā€” to issue respected and complied judgements. Smilov acknowledges the court fulļ¬lls this end as he indicates ā€œcourts generate trust when they become instrumental to broad sections of society in series of concrete disputes between two parties,ā€ or in other words is impartial (Smilov 870). He says impartiality has three grounds of legitimation. First, ā€œattempt to limit the exposure of the judiciary to partisanship and open politicization in order to make it attractive as a neutral arbiter,ā€ or in other words, make the judicial branch independent. Second, because courts are ā€œhandicapped as endorsers of comprehensive political programs and doctrines,ā€ they must rely on the rule of law. Third, courts must ā€œcorrectly balance the competing values of accessible justice and manageable caseload,ā€ both of which enhance legitimacy in different respects (870). Because impartiality is so reliant on the other two principles, improving their instruments of legitimacy through appointment, structure, and culture will improve this one as well. Moreover, balancing accessibility and caseload is a structural issue that can be addressed through an analysis of review procedures, and a change in appointment with regards to diversity as well. Lastly, we explore adjudication as a mark of sovereignty. Sovereignty is an odd concept because ā€œhistorically, the claim of resolution of disputes through adjudication has been the mark of sovereigntyā€ (Smilov 869). On this simple understanding, ā€œcourts normally claim exclusive and ļ¬nal authority over the resolution of legal disputesā€ (Smilov 869). This principle is a circular argument that essentially says the court is sovereign because it is sovereign ā€” it also stands separate from the interconnection between all the previous concepts. Furthermore, this principle is very weak because its !8
  • 9. only possible argument for existence is historical context ā€” which the same author warns about when he claims that history makes a standard normative design difļ¬cult. Lastly, Smilovā€™s length of this section in comparison to its counterparts showed the lack of care and justiļ¬cation that was put into this principle. Earlier this paper it was determined that sovereignty actually does not even exist insofar that a courtā€™s decision can be ignored and not implemented, or that legislature can pass an amendment nullifying the decision of a judiciary. So for this last principle, we will instead seek to understand what the courtā€™s place in the balance of powers should be. Should it be reliant on this old model of assumed supremacy? Or should we look to a more modern system, one that creates an open dialogue of constitutionalism between the judiciary and the legislature? Rather than see adjudication as a mark of sovereignty, we can see it as an important, and in many ways, essential members of a cooperative discussion of constitutional issues. This claim is legitimized through structural changes. Institutional Design ā€” The Takeaways In this segment of the paper we looked at Smilovā€™s arguments of how a court system draws its legitimacy and normative power from at least four different sources: the separation of powers, the rule of law, impartiality of the court, and a cooperative discussion of constitutional issues (a rejection of Smilovā€™s argument of judicial sovereignty). The exploration of these four variables identiļ¬ed an interrelation of many of the concepts and variables, so inļ¬‚uencing one area can impact many; this helps standardize mechanisms for improving legitimacy into categories of appointment, structure, and culture. What we will do to execute upon these mechanisms is outlined more extensively in the ļ¬nal section but an overview is given now. We will begin with the hardest to encapsulate, yet in many ways the most broadly inļ¬‚uential of the three mechanisms: culture. Culture is the most can be enhanced if we focus on the importance of values like judicial independence, judicial impartiality, and rule of law in the dialogue across all institutions related with the judicial branch, both internally and externally. This isnā€™t something that can !9
  • 10. be directly inļ¬‚uenced, but can be incentivized. As for structural changes, we will seek to redeļ¬ne the traditional notion of judicial sovereignty into one of open discussion, meaning compliance with the courts is only as strong as their general legitimacy ā€” because the change acknowledges this reality, it will force courts to focus on building it. The remaining structural changes are then: enhancing judicial tenure to improve impartiality and independence; and professionalizing the court by specializing the appellate jurisdiction. In terms of appointment, an independent commission with various stakeholders from the political, judicial, professional, and academic ļ¬elds will be utilized to increase consensus for for the supreme court judges, enhancing all sources of legitimacy. Furthermore, appointment should ensure judges should in some way be demographically representative of the nation to build impartiality. Behavior as an Actor The institutional mechanisms that have so far been discussed are only one piece of the puzzle ā€” they give courts an initial step of legitimacy. The ļ¬nal impact of a court, to some extent, is determined by its behavior after creation. Building legitimacy through behavior is done over time and to some extent it is done so well that modern jurists cannot even conceive of a model where their decisions would be ignored. This can be seen ā€œwhen members of the Russian Constitutional Court asked their U.S. counterparts about how they ensured compliance with their decisions, they were taken aback with the American Justices' response: ā€˜They simply did not understand us,ā€™ the Russians bemoaned. ā€˜It simply had not entered their heads that the decisions of the Court would not be implementedā€™ā€ (Epstein et. al 126). However, the US model was not always like this. Through his leadership, Marshallā€™s court established the principle of judicial review overturning law. He further worked in many ways to enhance the courtā€™s legitimacy though behavior: unanimity, enumerating decisions that wouldnā€™t upset the parties involved, etc. Behavior can be improved by enhancing culture. Ultimately, this section will explore behavior because it is a key part of our constitutional history as well as an important factor to consider in many emerging nations. !10
  • 11. Generally, courts are understood to have binding decisions (sovereignty). However, in reality, they are ā€œconstrained actors,ā€ meaning they consider other actors to ā€œlend force to their decisionsā€ (Epstein et. al 125). The more effectively they make these considerations and limit their decisions within the scope of other actors per decision, the further they broaden their scope of acceptable decisions in the future, ultimately becoming ā€œunconstrained actorsā€ (125). This scope of decision is otherwise known as the area where tolerance intervals of institutional actors overlap. A ā€œtolerance intervalā€ is an interval that exists for every actor (branch of government) and is the extent, ideologically, of decisions upon which the respective actor would not challenge the court. This is modeled to the right. ā€œThose intervals [ā€¦] represent the elected actors' ex ante assessment of the relative costs and beneļ¬ts of attempting an ā€˜attackā€™ on the Courtā€, for which ā€œthese actors take into account four factorsā€ (129). Case salience, the extent to which this issue involves or is relevant to the actor. Case authoritativeness, which is simply the weight of the precedent (have there been multiple decisions, has the court been unanimous, etc.). Policy-speciļ¬c public support, what the general public thinks about the issue at hand. Lastly, diffuse public support, the legitimacy the court has built up across society (129). The Russian court demonstrates this model perfectly. The only notable drawback is that the analysis utilizes mainly qualitative data. However, I would argue that for this model qualitative analysis is in a way beneļ¬cial because it is most similar to the ways actors would make their assessment. During Russiaā€™s tumultuous start as a nation its court was suspended, the constitution rewritten, and a new court took its place. These two courts behaved very differently, resulting in different levels of legitimacy and permanence. The Russian court had three large categories of decisions: separation of powers, federalism, and individual rights. On cases of separation of powers and federalism, tolerance intervals of the actors rarely coincided; however, they were almost always in agreement on the individual rights of the branches. !11 Pres. Senate House Scope
  • 12. In its ļ¬rst court era, over 62% of decisions were not considered ā€œsafe.ā€ BY issuing unsafe decisions they opened themselves to conļ¬‚ict from the other branches and also increased the chance this conļ¬‚ict would occur in the future by decreasing tolerance intervals. In its second era, the court seemed to learn from its mistakes as judges claimed they sought to avoid ā€œacute political questionsā€ (Epstein et. al 153). In this period we saw that 90% of the courtā€™s decisions were in the safe area of overlap in tolerance intervals. Judges ruled mainly on topics of individual rights, broadening all tolerance intervals and creating an area of overlap in federalism decisions, which the court then ruled on. Ultimately the court was able to increase its legitimacy across the polity. Conclusion This section outlined two complex, interrelated models for achieving judiciary legitimacy. The ā€œbasic framework for the democratic system is initially established by the enactment of a constitution,ā€ which through consideration of cultural, structural, and appointment factors can be institutionally designed to enhance legitimacy. Second, ā€œthe ļ¬ne-grained institutional structure evolves over time as the product of the legal and political interactions among various political actors" ā€” being aware of this can impact the courtā€™s role in those interactions (Epstein et. al 155). Although establishing a stable, effective, democratic state is a complex process that takes a long time, the judiciary is a very important piece of this establishment. In summary, the purpose of the judiciary is to produce complied and respected judgements, and it can do this by maximizing legitimacy through various design changes and behaviors. Let us now look to what exactly these changes will be. What Will Changes to US Normative Model Look Like? In the previous section, we conclusively indicated the three areas for improving legitimacy: culture, structure, and appointment. In this section we will investigate what changes will cause these !12
  • 13. mechanisms to generate more judicial legitimacy. Let us begin by looking more speciļ¬cally at culture, in many ways the most crucial of the three but also the hardest to capture. Culture Culture is a unique mechanism as many scholars seem to mention the need for changes in culture, but usually as part of a broader set of suggestions. It tends to be under-deļ¬ned; however, it can be roughly understood as ā€œvirtueā€ or ā€œgood understanding.ā€ Culture relates to how the judiciary and related institutions understand the nature of the judicial branch. Macdonald and Kong really give the best understanding of culture when they outline that ideas like judicial independence should be a judicial virtue. A virtue is something we strive towards, an ideal, a ļ¬nal understanding. Throughout the paper they explain it as something that justices, society, and other institutions should acknowledge. For instance, they argue ā€œwhether the rule of law thrives is dependent on a range of factors, including a culture of public commitment to the institutions that support the rule of law and a system of separation of powersā€ (Macdonald and Kong 845). This same thought applies to all the various ideals and members involved. However, only incentives can improve culture. How can we incentivize thinking about these ideals? By structuring the institutions in such a way that judges consider these virtues, as we will see in some of the changes in the section. By bringing these issues to the forefront for judges, they can diffuse into other areas of society like academia, public discussion, and other branches. Thereby further enhancing the understanding and quality of these virtues, again strengthening the judiciary and its legitimacy ā€” creating a self-enforcing feedback loop. In the end, culture is an important part of ensuring courts have longevity and behave properly. Structure To make changes in structure, we must start with its core. This means replacing the traditional notion of judicial sovereignty with one of open discussion. Because courts will no longer have this circular !13
  • 14. sovereignty claim to legitimacy, and instead are a part of an open discussion between the legislature and judiciary, judges are consciously and constantly reminded that their opinions are only as strong as their legitimacy. This structural change not only reļ¬‚ects the reality of the system, as we had seen earlier judges have no way of enforcing their decisions; it also bolsters culture in the most direct way. Because the society is now consistently and consciously aware that judiciary power stems from the institutionā€™s legitimacy, culture improves. They will have to keep in mind the goals of enhancing impartiality, independence, and the rule of law when structuring the branch. With this frame of mind the following structural changes will be with implemented: reworking judicial tenure, and specializing the appellate jurisdiction. Judges more speciļ¬cally will be culturally aware of behavior, as it is their most direct way of increasing legitimacy. Let us understand this structural change by looking at the debates around it. The debates for structuring of power among institutions have two extremes ā€” legislative and judicial supremacy, argued by Waldron and Dworkin respectively. Dworkin argues that courts have sovereignty because they can guarantee rights protection impartially ā€œwith equal concern and respect" (Dworkin 17). As we saw earlier in the paper, this claim is false. We can strive for these virtues; however, when it comes to meeting them and building a model off it, this is somewhat unrealistic. We then look to Waldron, who says the opposite. Essentially because judges will never be impartial, it is ā€œunpleasantly condescendingā€ that these unelected ofļ¬cials are then given sovereignty. Waldron instead proposes a model of legislative supremacy (Waldron 303). The main ļ¬‚aw with this model is that it relies heavily on society understanding debates that of a constitutional nature, such as rights, are inherently different from simple discussions of what law to pass. They should be discussions grounded in a ā€œpolitical culture of mutual respectā€ (310). He essentially makes the same mistake as Dworkin here, assuming that his proposed justiļ¬cation will be inherently true and that the society will instantly and holistically adjust political culture to one that Waldron describes. !14
  • 15. Gardbaum on the other hand provides an alternative to either model of supremacy, solving the issues with both and curing ā€œthe over-legalization or judicialization of principled public discourseā€ and preventing ā€œthe legislative and popular debilitation that has long been identiļ¬ed as a major institutional cost of constitutionalizationā€ (Gardbaum 173). This model gives the legislature power to overturn a courtā€™s constitutional decision, in effect opening and enhancing a culture and dialogue of rights and constitutional issues. Hilbink outlines that this model rejects ā€œa strict distinction between law and politics, [which] grants supreme authority to the judiciary in constitutional decision making and sets up the relationship between the judiciary and legislature in binary and oppositional termsā€ (Hilbink 233). If the courts are restructured this way, we can more consciously think about mechanisms of achieving legitimacy. Especially with instruments that are based on merit and theory rather than based off a circular assumption. The next structural implement we will explore is judicial tenure. Judicial tenure is an important factor to achieve independence and, in turn, impartiality. If a justice is tenured they donā€™t have to worry about political pressures to those who appointed them, and they also donā€™t have to worry about losing a position because of a ruling. Furthermore, ā€œcommitment theorists predict an inverse relationship between legislative tenure and judicial tenureā€ (Macdonald and Kong 845). However, tenure canā€™t be indeļ¬nite like it is currently in the US model ā€” this can lead to a judgeā€™s opinions being ā€œgrossly out-of-step with the rest of the political system,ā€ in other words, unprofessional (Hilbink 231). Instead, judges should be tenured until age 75, as in the Canadian and UK models, ensuring a wholly legitimate term. This allows them to behave freely, professionally, and in accordance to the principles reinforced by their surrounding culture. Now weā€™ll look to change the structure of the appellate courts to enhance the rule of law and impartiality. The appellate courtā€™s judges should be specialized in a model similar to that of Germanyā€™s constitutional court. The German model of specialization splits the supreme court into two ā€œsenatesā€ that !15
  • 16. pick issues from various legal subjects at the start of the session based on caseload (Damle 1297). Furthermore, based on the issues their senate selects, each judge becomes a ā€œrapporteur,ā€ with an expertise in a speciļ¬c area of law (1298). These judges are then responsible for creating ā€œvotum[s]ā€ for cases in their legal area ā€” a votum is essentially a ā€œmajor research report. [The judge] describes the background and facts of the dispute, surveys the courtā€™s own precedent and the legal literature, presents fully documented arguments advanced on both sides of the question, and concludes with the personal view of how the case should be decidedā€ (1299). The reason we look to the German constitutional courtā€™s specialization is that in the Kelsenian legal system, the constitutional court most closely resembles a court in the US jurisdiction. Also, since the US supreme court hears at most 1% of cases appealed to it, we seek to apply the specialization at an appellate level to have a more immediate impact on the law. Moreover, the precedent and values of this more precise decision making will simply diffuse upwards. Fusing this model into the US system is very straightforward ā€” at the start of a legal term justices can pick a few topics based off caseload. Then when an issue comes to the court and a panel of three is chosen to adjudicate, it can be formed based on the issues involved and then justices randomly chosen from other, non-related, topics; the most relevant justice(s) will be tasked with preparing a votum for the panel which will ultimately adjudicate. This approach is interesting because it capitalizes upon the beneļ¬ts of both a generalist and specialized court. The more specialized justice(s) get to voice their opinion and expertise, while the ultimate decision is more generalist because there are multiple judges involved. Additionally, because the way topics are chosen helps manage caseload, this model also improves the perception of impartiality because it allows the courts to remain efļ¬cient and low-cost, hearing every case. Ultimately through this model, decision making will be more legitimate because law is more uniform and professional across the polity, caseload is managed effectively, and the ļ¬nal opinions tend to be more unanimous. !16
  • 17. Appointment Appointment is speciļ¬cally covered last because it enhances all claims of legitimacy, and in many ways draws upon the impacts of the mechanisms proposed in this section. Akkas argues the ā€Ø ā€œappointment system has a direct bearing on the impartiality, integrity and independence of judgesā€ (Akkas 200). This ā€œdirect bearingā€ is because as much as a society structures institutions and enhances culture ā€” if they pick the wrong people, decisions will suffer. Judicial appointment can be improved if judges are selected by an independent commission that accounts for the various stakeholders we have discussed so far. A pluralist approach similar to South Africaā€™s will be taken, their commission ā€œconsists of judges, the Minister of Justice, practicing and academic lawyers, members of the National Assembly including a substantial number of opposition members, members of the Provincial parliaments, persons nominated by the President of South Africa after consulting leaders of all political parties represented in the National Assembly and in some cases the Premier of the Province or the Premierā€™s nomineeā€ (Akkas 209). The independent commission increases the number and background of stakeholders. The political, judicial, professional, and academic ļ¬elds will be utilized to increase consensus for for the supreme court judges: enhancing independence and in turn impartiality, and the rule of law. It is important to keep in mind that culture will in many ways inļ¬‚uence the decisions this commission makes. For instance, if the commission wants to strive towards creating an impartial court and is much more culturally aware of the value, they would try to make the court roughly representative of the demographics in the nation. In the end, similarly to the South African model, the commission would slate three more appointees than are needed. Following the idea that judiciary is inherently political, and constitutional courts will represent a back-and-forth dialogue between the judicial and the political, the appointees are ultimately proposed by the executive and voted in by the legislature. This political portion of appointment will further enhance legitimacy of the courts by giving them more credibility in the open dialogue system. !17
  • 18. Conclusion To ļ¬nish off this section, we went through three areas to improve ā€” culture, structure, and appointment. Through these we were able to create a ļ¬nal normative model that captured the reality of the judicial branch by replacing sovereignty with a model of open discussion. This underlying framework enhances culture by making the judiciary and society more aware of how to improve judicial legitimacy. Judicial tenure, which enhances independence and impartiality, was reformed to include a retirement age of 75 to also ensure professionalism and thereby rule of law. Legitimacy through rule of law and impartiality were further built upon by specializing the US appellate jurisdiction, making it more professional and efļ¬cient. Lastly, appointment was redesigned to enhance all the scores of legitimacy. By increasing the stakeholders, justices become more independent and impartial, and more professional. The changes proposed to institutions in this section only capture one portion of our normative model ā€” to fully enhance legitimacy in the judicial system we must understand and advance the culture in recognition of these values. Conclusion A normative model was designed that started with understanding that the purpose of a court is to create complied and respected decisions. This can be done by increasing legitimacy. Legitimacy was understood to be built institutionally, and behaviorally. Through investigating legitimacy, three areas of improvement were determined: culture, structure, and appointment. By focusing on these areas of improvement, a comprehensive normative model grounded in the US system that enhanced legitimacy was created. ā€© !18
  • 19. Works Cited Akkas, Sarkar Ali. "Appointment of Judges: A Key Issue of Judicial Independence." Bond Law Review 16.2 (2004): 200-210. Web. 18 Dec. 2015 Damle, Sarang Vijay. ā€œSpecialize the Judge, Not the Court: A Lesson from the German Constitutional Courtā€. Virginia Law Review 91.5 (2005): 1267ā€“1311. Web. 18 Dec. 2015.ā€™ Dworkin, Ronald. Freedom's Law: The Moral Reading of the American Constitution. Cambridge, MA: Harvard UP, 1996. Print. Epstein, Lee, Jack Knight, and Olga Epstein et. al. "The Role of Constitutional Courts in the Establishment and Maintenance of Democratic Systems of Government." Law & Society Review 35.1 (2001): 117. Web. 18 Dec. 2015. Gardbaum, Stephen. "Reassessing the New Commonwealth Model of Constitutionalism." International Journal of Constitutional Law 8.2 (2010): 167-206. Print. Hamilton, Alexander. The Federalist: A Collection of Essays. New York: n.p., 1788. The Federalist #78. Web. 18 Dec. 2015. Hilbink, Lisa. "Assessing the New Constitutionalism." Comparative Politics 40.2 (2008): 227-45. Print. Jacob, Herbert et. al. Courts, Law, and Politics in Comparative Perspective. New Haven: Yale UP, 1996. Print La Porta, Rafael, Florencio LĆ³pezā€deā€Silanes, Cristian Popā€Eleches, and Andrei Shleifer. "Judicial Checks and Balances." Journal of Political Economy 112.2 (2004): 445-70. Web. 18 Dec. 2015. Laski, Harold J.. ā€œThe Technique of Judicial Appointmentā€. Michigan Law Review 24.6 (1926): 529ā€“543. Web. 18 Dec. 2015 !19
  • 20. Macdonald, Roderick A., and Hoi Kong. "Judicial Independence as a Constitutional Virtue." Oxford Handbooks Online. 2012-11-21. Oxford University Press. Web. 18 Dec. 2015. Smilov, Daniel. "The Judiciary: The Least Dangerous Branch?." Oxford Handbooks Online. 2012-11-21. Oxford University Press. Sweet, Alec Stone. "Constitutional Courts." Oxford Handbooks Online. 2012-11-21. Oxford University Press. Web. 18 Dec. 2015. Sweet, Alec Stone. "Constitutional Courts and Parliamentary Democracy." West European Politics 25.1 (2002): 77-100. Print. Waldron, Jeremy. Law and Disagreement. Oxford: Oxford UP, 2001. Print !20