SlideShare a Scribd company logo
1 of 26
Bollant 1
Gabriel Bollant 7115
Paul Boling
CT 491
2/21/2015
Nietzsche's Insistence upon Suffering Unto Resignation
Tracing Nietzsche's ideas is a topic of understanding that has defined a large portion of
modern philosophy. His ambiguity due to his parabolic nature combined with his revolutionary
ideas has mystified the postmodern generation, captivating their interest. Books have been
written clarifying his ideals, and more have been written denouncing his ideas. Not only did
Nietzsche capture the imaginations of the modern generation, but since the first decades
following his writings, philosophers, psychologists, philologists, and many other scholarly
schools have been captivated in the same way. Influential thinkers and political leaders such as
Freud, Marx, Derrida, Foucault, and even Hitler have all been large proponents of his writings.
In this thesis I wish to draw out an ascetic ideal within Nietzsche's philosophy, and trace
it back to Eastern ideologies. The hinge that completes the trace will be the philosophy of
Schopenhauer and the influence that he had over Nietzsche at a young age. I wish to show that
while Nietzsche was still young and malleable, he was significantly influenced by Schopenhauer,
and that that influence never left him. Particularly, I wish to show it in the area of his insistence
upon suffering unto resignation. I claim that Nietzsche's insistence upon suffering unto
resignation was originally an Eastern idea traceable to the Upanishads through Schopenhauer.
The meaning of insistence upon suffering unto resignation is of great importance. In
tracing the argument, all of these philosophies positively affirmed that resignation from desire—
denial of the will—was accomplished through suffering. I will show that they all affirmed this
Bollant 2
ascetic idea, and that it encouraged a resignation from desire. Moreover, I will show that
Nietzsche, Schopenhauer, and Eastern philosophy encouraged suffering as an ideal show of
piety.
Such a trace will clarify the interpretation of Nietzsche's ideologies, but it will also reveal
their possible origin. Within this thesis, I will trace the potential of the idea to Eastern thought,
but not to finding origins of the ascetic idea. This would require another thesis. The focus of this
essay is upon Nietzsche himself, and the origin of his idea for his own thought. This thesis will
shed further light upon his philosophy influenced by the Eastern perspective. It could also lead to
further studies being done, including a study of Schopenhauer's specific influence and the
potential origin of the idea in Eastern thought. However, the focus of this essay is on Nietzsche.
Nietzsche was born in Rocken, a small town in Saxony, Prussia. His father was a
Lutheran minister coming from a generational line of ministers. He was christened with the name
Friedrich Wilhelm after the name of the Prussian king. Nietzsche would later shed this name
along with nationalism and religion, but not before both the king and Nietzsche’s father went
insane; an uncanny foreshadowing of his own insanity to come. Most experts, however, agree
that his illness was not inherited. ((Kaufmann 21-22)).
Nietzsche’s father died when he was five years old and his mother moved the family to
Naumburg. He began attending a renowned boarding school on full scholarship, which was a
significant scholastic achievement. After graduation, he attended the University of Bonn, initially
studying theology and classical philosophy. It would not be long before he would give up
theology and follow his teacher Friedrich Ritschl to Leipzig. This relationship proved to be a
victory for Nietzsche, as it would be on Ritschl's glowing recommendation that he would begin
teaching philology at the University of Basel (Kaufmann 23-24).
Bollant 3
Wilkens and Padgett interpret Nietzsche's work as a reaction against his childhood. They
point out that Nietzsche had not yet fulfilled the requirements for a doctorate when he began
teaching (Wilkens & Padgett). This shows that it was clearly on recommendation alone that
Nietzsche was awarded the position. His time at Basel would not be long, as he retired ten years
later at thirty-four years old due to poor health. He spent the last eleven years of his life
struggling with insanity, commonly attributed to syphilis.
Before beginning my particular argument, it is important to note Nietzsche's contradictory
nature. While it might be simple and apparent to argue Schopenhauer's insistence upon suffering
unto resignation, it is not simple to argue Nietzsche's. His philosophy is parabolic by nature, and
he is at constant contradiction with himself. Karl Jaspers, a prominent translator and scholar of
Nietzsche, affirms "All statements seem to be annulled by other statements. Self-contradiction is
the fundamental ingredient in Nietzsche's thought. For nearly every single one of Nietzsche's
judgments, one can also find an opposite” (Jaspers 10). Due to this contradictory nature, it is
either gratuitously simple or overly impossible to make claims about Nietzsche's ideas. I will
argue his insistence upon suffering unto resignation by outlining it within his philosophy, and
showing his dependence on Schopenhauer.
Given the outcome of Nietzsche's own life, his philosophy inevitably would deal with
suffering. Eleven years took him from the prime of his life into excruciating pain. Days when he
was free from the debilitating pain were spent in writing. In the final years of his life the illness
began destroying his mind. His final works were written while racing against his own destruction
(Melchert 533). As he struggled with illness disintegrating his body and mind, he would seek to
understand his own suffering.
Bollant 4
To understand Nietzsche's view of suffering, there is need to first understand his view of
religion. Religion to Nietzsche, particularly Christianity and Buddhism, was the possibility of
minimizing or abolishing suffering. Nietzsche understood religion to be merely a means to
alleviate personal suffering.
God created man happy, idle, innocent, and immortal: our actual life is a
false, decayed, sinful existence, an existence of punishment— Suffering,
struggle, work, death are considered as objections and question marks against life,
as something that ought not to last; for which one requires a cure—and has a
cure!—
From the time of Adam until now, man has been in an abnormal state:
God himself has sacrificed his son for the guilt of Adam, in order to put an end to
this abnormal state: the natural character of life is a curse; Christ gives back the
state of normality to him who believes in him: he makes him happy, idle and
innocent. (The Will to Power 224)
Nietzsche here critiques the ethic of Christianity as a means of solace from suffering. By looking
towards the next life as reward for actions in this life, Christianity escapes. Redemption will ease
the pain of suffering in this world by providing hope for a future.
This same concern with suffering is reflective in many religions. Kogen Mizuno, in his
explication of basic Buddhist concepts, writes, “The major purpose of all religions is to cure the
illness of the spirit and create a wholesome, integrated psychological condition . . . [their] major
task is the essential improvement of the psychological being to ensure spiritual health and
immunity to spiritual illness” (105). In the traditional story of Buddha's discovery of the path to
enlightenment, he is shaken from his ignorance by observing the suffering of sickness, old age,
Bollant 5
and death: “that life is suffering, that ignorance is the cause of suffering, that suffering can be
eliminated, and that the Eightfold Path is the way to eliminate suffering” (106). Buddhism views
suffering as a hindrance from experiencing happiness; that through the path to enlightenment,
there is freedom from suffering through its cessation. This view of religion, as a means to
freedom from suffering, may not be universally accepted; it actually tends more towards an
Eastern concept. Schopenhauer also reflected on these same ideas, as we will see further on. For
now, we need to note Nietzsche's ascetic ideal.
In the third essay of the Geneology of Morals, Nietzsche describes the ascetic ideal.
Essentially, it is a means through religion that provides meaning to suffering (Genealogy of
Morals, III 28). This is important, because it is Nietzsche's understanding of the pathway to
enlightenment. This is his freedom from suffering. The significance of Nietzsche defining his
means of freedom from suffering through the ascetic ideal is that it connects to his views of
religion. More importantly, it connects to his views of Buddhism. It is in this view of Buddhism
that I wish to connect Nietzsche's thought to Eastern philosophy, particularly by connecting him
to Schopenhauer. It is also in this view of suffering that I wish to connect Nietzsche's thought to
the idea of suffering unto resignation. I affirm that Nietzsche states such an ascetic view of
suffering leading to the ascetic ideal.
The ascetic ideal is achieved by means of the ascetic priest, a shepherd who guides the
herd to freedom from suffering. The wretched are guided by the ascetic priest, as he has
dominion over suffering (Genealogy of Morals, III 15). Nietzsche says that the priest is “a tool
for the creation of more favorable conditions for being here and being man—it is precisely this
power that enables him to persuade to existence the whole herd of the ill-constituted, disgruntled,
underprivileged, unfortunate, and all who suffer of themselves” (Genealogy of Morals, III 11).
Bollant 6
The wretched, the “. . . ill-constituted, disgruntled, underprivileged, unfortunate . . .” are guided
to freedom from suffering. Nietzsche understands that this is done in many ways. He divides
these ways into two categories: the ‘innocent’ and the ‘guilty.’
The first way, the innocent, is carried out by reducing life to avoid suffering: “If possible,
will and desire are abolished altogether . . . no love; no hate; indifference; no revenge; no wealth;
no work; one begs; if possible, no women, or as little as possible; in spiritual matters . . .”
(Genealogy of Morals, III 17). Such a cessation will produce a kind of euphoria. Nietzsche
provides the example of the Buddhist doctrine of becoming one with Brahma (Genealogy of
Morals, III 17). By denying oneself all desire, one achieves freedom from suffering.
The second way of the ascetic priest is through the guilty. Suffering and envy of the
healthy accumulate a resentment, which can have an explosive effect on the wretched individual.
The priest shepherds the wretched away from this resentment by providing a cause, a culprit to
which the wretched can vent their feelings. Even out of friends and family, the sufferer makes
culprits for himself to ease the pain of his suffering (Genealogy of Morals, III 15).
The ascetic priest redirects resentment by means of a lie. By informing the wretched that
they are their own cause for suffering, the priest provides the sufferer with a means to deaden the
pain, and more importantly he provides a meaning to suffering. Nietzsche determines the
problem of suffering is not in the pain of suffering, but in the lack of meaning in it: “[Man's]
problem was not suffering itself, but that there was no answer to the crying question, ‘why do I
suffer?’” (Genealogy of Morals, III 28).
Therefore, the ascetic ideal is self-denial: “The three great slogans of the ascetic ideal are
familiar: poverty, humility, chastity” (Genealogy of Morals, III 8). Humans naturally desire, they
crave and want, and these go against the ascetic ideal. Seeing this, the ascetic priest provides
Bollant 7
meaning for suffering either in an afterlife or in some reward, or more importantly as punishment
for going against the ascetic ideal: “He should look for it within himself, in guilt, in a piece of
the past, he should understand his suffering itself as a condition of punishment” (Genealogy of
Morals, III 20). In this, the ascetic ideal is complete. There is freedom from suffering, and even
more suffering is encouraged: “one no longer protested against pain, one thirsted for pain; ‘more
pain! more pain!’ the desire of his disciples and initiates has cried for centuries” (Genealogy of
Morals, III 20).
The ascetic ideal is key in showing Nietzsche's view of religion and suffering, and while
he has some harsh words to say about religion, his view of the ascetic ideal shapes the creation of
his own alternative ideal. Nietzsche is living in the post-Darwin world. Darwin's Origin of
Species, published in 1859, set forth a new era. His publication resulted in the development of
evolution, which gave means to some of the first cosmological models which did not necessitate
the existence of a god. Nietzsche finds in it the reality that God could no longer exist (“Human
All Too Human” This is the documentary).
To Nietzsche, science had developed past the need for God, and the ability to even
believe in God. The truth of science eradicated belief in God, and the realization of this
discovery was dramatic. Observe in Nietzsche's publication, The Gay Science, the scene
portrayed by his parable of the madman:
Have you not heard of that madman who lit a lantern in the bright morning hours,
ran to the market place, and cried incessantly: "I seek God! I seek God!"—As
many of those who did not believe in God were standing around just then, he
provoked much laughter. . . . Is there still any up or down? Are we not straying, as
through an infinite nothing? Do we not feel the breath of empty space? Has it not
Bollant 8
become colder? Is not night continually closing in on us? Do we not need to light
lanterns in the morning? Do we hear nothing as yet of the noise of the
gravediggers who are burying God? Do we smell nothing as yet of the divine
decomposition? Gods, too, decompose. God is dead. God remains dead. And we
have killed him. (sect. 125; 119)
This realization left Nietzsche with a task to create a new ascetic ideal, one which did not
necessitate the existence of God.
“Dead are all Gods: now do we desire the superman to live” (Thus Spake Zarathustra 1,
sect. 22, 83). Nietzsche's alternative ideal comes under the title of ubermensch, translated
‘superman’ or ‘overman.’ The ubermensch describes a character, an ascetic priest, who shepherds
the herd, and gives a new ascetic ideal. This new ideal does not rely upon the lies of God or
‘guilty.’ He is a character who can provide meaning to the herd by giving them the ascetic ideal.
Essentially, he is a new era in evolution, and he will guide man as a “bridge” in the process of
evolving higher (Thus Spake Zarathustra sect. 4, 8). There are many different characteristics of
the ubermensch, but the two we need to dwell on are the doctrines of faithfulness to the earth and
affirmation of eternal recurrence.
These two characteristics show Nietzsche's insistence upon suffering unto resignation.
Nietzsche's demands to remain “faithful to the earth” are going to show his insistence upon
resigning from desire, and eternal recurrence will show that suffering is going to be the key to
this resignation.
The first characteristic, faithfulness to the earth, is a matter of remaining firm on the
limited nature of life. An ubermensch has no business looking beyond this life to define his
meaning. It is not the true world Nietzsche is describing. The true world1
, a term referring to the
1 For further understanding on the true world, see Kant’s ideas on Phenomena as described in Critique of Pure
Bollant 9
way the world empirically represents itself to man, is just as much of a metaphysical theory as
belief in gods. For in Twilight of the Idols Nietzsche proclaims “How the 'True World' Finally
Became a Fable.” Here he describes it as “useless and superfluous” (“How the 'True World'
Finally Became a Fable”). Instead, Nietzsche is speaking about remaining faithful to non-
metaphysical ideas. The ubermensch should have no desires for otherworldly lies (Thus Spake
Zarathustra sect. 4, 9-10).
It is here in this doctrine that Nietzsche is espousing resignation. The ‘true world' is
something to be resigned to. It is an empty, cold shell that can never be grasped. Nietzsche's early
works, particularly The Birth of Tragedy attempted to reconcile a Schopenhauerian metaphysical
theory. Nietzsche has thrown off the reigns of metaphysical ideas, and has labeled them
worthless. The ubermensch must resign to such ideas, including the idea of the true world.
Nietzsche provided a test to measure a true ubermensch: the affirmation of eternal
recurrence. If a man could affirm an existence of perfect repetition, then he would be an
ubermensch. In other words, if life repeated itself over-and-over again without change or
anything new, the same sufferings and the same joys, and if a man could embrace it, even “love”
it, then he would be an ubermensch. Nietzsche calls it “my formula for greatness in a human
being: amor fati” (Ecce Homo 258). Amor fati means the love of fate; to embrace the
completeness of fate is, in essence, the new ideal. The test proves whether or not one truly
embraces all of fate, because despairing at the idea of repetition would reveal a desire for more.
It is desire, desire for more than what is, desire for an afterlife and higher calling, that the
ubermensch resigns from. These desires are the lies of metaphysical ideas, and they are not
worthy of an ubermensch. It is not only these grand desires that one resigns from. He resigns
from desire of all things: from pride, from comfort, from the things of weakness (Thus Spake
Reason.
Bollant 10
Zarathustra 1, sect. 1 23). He becomes an ascetic priest, free from the desires of this world, and
completely accepting of fate.
And how does the ubermensch resign from such desires? By none other than suffering.
Observe in Thus Spake Zarathustra Nietzsche's description of the first stage of the three
metamorphoses. The ubermensch must undergo the stages of three metamorphoses to become the
true ubermensch. The first stage is that of the camel. The picture here is that he must embrace
suffering and hardship in order to become strong and resign from desire. As a camel is strong, so
must the ubermensch be strong, carrying as much burden and hardship that is physically
possible. He must always take the hard way, assuming the “heavy.” But “what is heavy?”
Nietzsche says, “To humiliate oneself in order to mortify one's pride. . . . To exhibit one's folly in
order to mock at one's wisdom. . . . To desert our cause when it celebrateth its triumph. . . . To be
sick and dismiss comforters, and make friends of the deaf, who never hear thy request” (Thus
Spake Zarathustra 1, sect. 1 23).
It is here that Nietzsche is proclaiming the endurance of suffering in order to resign from
desire. Amor fati, love of fate: one must love what is immediately in front of him, and not desire
things beyond himself, just as Nietzsche says, “in order to mortify one's pride.” The ubermensch,
the new ascetic priest, Nietzsche's alternative ideal, must be someone who does not feel pride,
accept comfort, or celebrate triumph. Instead, he must seek hardship for himself in order to
achieve resignation.
Soren Kierkegaard, a Christian Existentialist philosopher, encourages a very similar
philosophy. As a Christian, Kierkegaard encourages it for very different reasons. However, in his
book, Fear and Trembling, he describes an ideal character. This character, the knight of faith, is a
man entirely resigned from the desires of the world. Even as a stepping stone, the knight of faith
Bollant 11
must first become the knight of infinite resignation. At that moment the knight has completely
resigned from all the desires of the world. However, he only becomes the knight of faith when he
can graciously accept the things of the world, while still maintaining a resignation of desire for
them. Observe this passage where Kierkegaard describes such a knight:
One can discover nothing of that aloof and superior nature whereby one
recognizes the knight of the infinite. He takes delight in everything, and whenever
one sees him taking part in a particular pleasure, he does it with the persistence
which is the mark of the earthly man whose soul is absorbed in such things...
Toward evening he walks home, his gait is as indefatigable as that of the postman.
On his way he reflects that his wife has surely a special little warm dish prepared
for him, e.g. a calf's head roasted, garnished with vegetables. If he were to meet a
man like-minded, he could continue as far as East Gate to discourse with him
about that dish, with a passion befitting a hotel chef. As it happens, he hasn't four
pence to his name, and yet he fully and firmly believes that his wife has that
dainty dish for him. If she had it, it would then be an invidious sight for superior
people and an inspiring one for the plain man, to see him eat; for his appetite is
greater than Esau's. His wife hasn't it–strangely enough, it is quite the same to
him. (Kierkegaard 82-83)
Nietzsche, sharing much of existentialist philosophy, is describing his ideal in terms of these
same qualities. His ubermensch is resigning from the desires of the world, as well as any
afterlife, and remaining faithful to the earth, or fate. This is accomplished by assuming suffering,
as a camel assumes a “heavy” load.
Bollant 12
Brian Leiter, in his Nietzsche on Morality, argues that eternal recurrence necessitates a
rejection of suffering and any meaning behind it. Such a claim stands in opposition to my thesis.
The acceptance of a repetitive eternity, Lieter says, “is to recognize that there is no such
meaning” (Leiter 288). However, coming from Nietzsche, such a claim is arguable. Even in Thus
Spake Zarathustra he says, “It was suffering and incapacity that created the afterworlds” (Thus
Spake Zarathustra 1, 143-145). Metaphysical ideas, which need to be thrown off, are the result of
suffering and those who suffer (Nietzsche on Morality, 287-8).2
George Wrisley does not agree with Leiter; he refutes Leiter on the grounds that
Nietzsche encouraged suffering. First of all, Nietzsche claimed that joy necessitates suffering.
The two are intimately tied. Secondly, he said suffering makes one strong, in a “what doesn't kill
me, makes me stronger” type fashion. Wrisley uses these points to argue Nietzsche's
encouragement of suffering, refuting Leiter's claims (Wrisley 13-21).3
Thus far it has been established that Nietzsche affirmed suffering unto resignation. Now
in order to show that such an idea is in fact an Eastern philosophy derived from Schopenhauer, I
will begin by drawing out Nietzsche's connections to Buddhism.
There have not been many studies drawing Nietzsche's connection to Buddhism. In a
paper connecting Nietzsche to Paul Duessen, Hans Rollman, a professor in the Department of
Religious Studies at the Memorial University of Newfoundland, states, “No monograph dealing
with the lifelong friendship between Friedrich Nietzsche and the German indologist Paul
Deussen has yet appeared” (125). This is significant because Paul Deussen was famed for
translating Eastern philosophy and was a lifelong friend of Nietzsche's. If such connections
establishing Eastern philosophy's impact over Nietzsche were well researched, such a monograph
2 For more on Leiter’s argument see Nietzsche on Morality.
3 For more on Wrisley's refutation see Nietzsche and the Value of Human Suffering - Two Alternative Ideals
Bollant 13
would surely be needed. However, there have been a handful of studies drawing the similarities
between Buddhism and Nietzsche, and a pool of research exists that draws his connection to
Schopenhauer.
Many Nietzschean scholars connect Nietzsche to nihilism, against the philosopher's
perspective of himself. Such a contradiction between his writings and scholarly claims
surrounding them is characteristic of Nietzsche. For this reason, it is plausible to look to
establishments beyond his own words to justify his philosophy. Establishing this idea—that
Nietzsche had Buddhist influence over his philosophy—is significant as it would connect him to
Buddhism and show his contradictory nature.
Guy Richard Welbon has researched the potential connections between Nietzsche and
Buddhism. Observing Nietzsche's life, Welbon points out that he likely studied Sanskrit while at
Leipzig, under Hermann Brockhaus. Welbon even suggests that due to his training Nietzsche
would have been one of the most well read and firmly grounded scholars on Eastern philosophy
for his time period. This is significant, as it might suggest a large influence from these
philosophies upon Nietzsche's own writings.
Welbon draws parallels between Nietzsche's doctrine of eternal recurrence and the
Buddhist vale of Samsara existence, Nietzche's Zarathustra and the Buddhist bodhisttava, his
program for transvaluation of values and Nirvana.4
Welbon further concludes, “I am insisting
that there is no basic conflict between Nietzsche and Buddhism on several important issues, and
that there is sufficient evidence to indicate that Nietzsche's presentations do witness Buddhist
influences” (Welbon 185-89).
Another author who draws a similar Buddhist influence over Nietzsche, Benjamin Elman,
suggests that Nietzsche was against many scholarly claims, in fact a nihilist, and that the nihilist
4 For more on these doctrines and Welbon's connection see Buddhist Nirvana and Its Western Interpreters.
Bollant 14
tendencies of Eastern thought show his connection to them. Elman concludes this by shifting the
understanding of Nietzsche's thought away from the traditional understanding of the Western
intellectual milieu defined by men such as G.W.F. Hegel (1770-1831), Karl Marx (1818-1883),
and Charles Darwin (1809-1882). In this traditional view, Nietzsche greatly influenced these
men. Elman suggests such a view introduces philosophic blinders due to Western interpretive
bias. Instead, he proposes viewing Nietzsche's philosophy in light of the vistas of Eastern
influence where, according to Elman, Nietzsche explicitly attacked Buddhism as a nihilistic
religion; Elman remains insistent upon this connection (671-673).
If the ideas of Welbon and Elman are correct, this would reveal not only significant
Eastern philosophic influence on Nietzsche, but also the legitimacy of his contradictory nature
when attacking Buddhism. This idea provides a stepping stone, establishing Buddhist influence,
which will lead into his connections with Eastern philosophy. In order to connect Nietzsche's
idea of suffering unto resignation to Eastern philosophy, I will draw out the same idea in Eastern
philosophy, first by drawing the connection of the idea to Schopenhauer. The next step in this
process is connecting Nietzsche to Schopenhauer himself.
Bollant 15
While Nietzsche was a university student at Leipzig, Schopenhauer left his mark upon
him. At that time, Nietzsche picked up a book at an antiquarian shop and was beguiled instantly.
He later wrote about the experience in Untimely Meditations. “I belong to the readers of
Schopenhauer,' Nietzsche says, 'who after they have read the first page of him know with
certainty that they will read all his pages, and they will listen to every word that he has said”
(Dolson 241-242). Nietzsche became a professed follower of Schopenhauer.
Neal Dolson, a professor of Philosophy at Wells College, describes Nietzsche's encounter
with Schopenhauer as a highly influential one. Once a proselyte, Nietzsche began making
converts of his friends. They began a circle of disciples, committed to the philosopher as
worshipers to a deity. When one among them would struggle, the other offered appropriate
passages from the works of Schopenhauer. He was to them the incarnation of an ideal
philosopher. Later, when Nietzsche accepted the position at Basel, he expressed his intention of
specifically infusing Schopenhauerian philosophy with the philology program. In an essay in
which Nietzsche attempted to express the meaning Schopenhauer had over him, instead of
repeating Schopenhauer's philosophic principles, he discussed the “physiological influence,” as
Nietzsche called it. In the essay he describes Schopenhauer as fulfilling the test of a true
philosopher by being genuine and true to his principles. He not only spoke his philosophy, but
Nietzsche says that he expressed it in his life (Dolson 241-246). Ironically, Schopenhauer was
known for many things, but fulfilling his own philosophy was not one of them. Nietzsche was
without a doubt infatuated with the philosopher.
Nietzsche's divorce from Schopenhauer comes resolutely. In his own words, he passes
from referring to himself as a follower and speaking highly of him to denouncing him and
Bollant 16
comparing him to the lowest order: Christianity. Observe this passage from one of Nietzsche's
early works, Schopenhauer as Educator:
I judge a philosopher by whether he is able to serve as an example. . . .
[Schopenhauer's] greatness is the fact that he faces the picture of life as a whole in
order to interpret it as a whole. . . . Schopenhauer's philosophy should be
interpreted . . . by the individual . . . in order to gain insight into his own misery,
needs and limitations and to know the antidotes and consolations; namely,
sacrifice of the ego, submission to the noblest intentions, and above all, justice
and mercy. He teaches us how to distinguish between real and apparent
advancements of human happiness, how neither becoming rich, nor being
respected, nor being learned can raise the individual above his disgust as the
valuelessness of his existence, and how the struggle for all these good things is
given meaning only by a high and transfiguring goal: to win power in order to
come to the help of nature, and to correct her foolishness and clumsiness a little
— at first, admittedly, solely for oneself, but eventually for everybody. . . . This is
a struggle which in its deepest and innermost nature leads to resignation. (25-26)
In this passage, the adoration that Nietzsche had for Schopenhauer is clearly felt. His expression
of high esteem is vividly evident. However, fifteen years later, with the publication of Twilight of
the Idols, Nietzsche would express a different tune. His adoration for Schopenhauer has waned
with his maturity by the time he composes this passage:
Schopenhauer . . . is for a psychologist a case of the first order: namely, a
mendacious attempt of genius to marshal, in aid of a nihilistic total devaluation of
life, the very counter-instances, the great self-affirmations of the 'will to live', the
Bollant 17
exuberant forms of life. He interpreted in turn art, heroism, genius, beauty, grand
sympathy, knowledge, the will to truth, tragedy, as phenomena consequent upon
the 'denial' of or the thirst to deny the 'will' — the greatest piece of false-coinage
in history, Christianity alone excepted. Looked at more closely he is in this merely
the heir of the Christian interpretation: but with this difference, that he knew how
to take what Christianity had rejected, the great cultural facts of mankind, and
approve of them from a Christian, that is to say nihilistic, point of view (- namely,
as roads to 'redemption', as preliminary forms of 'redemption', as stimulants of the
thirst for 'redemption'). (79-80)
The comparison to Christianity is one of the lowest degradations that could from Nietzsche. For
him, the Christian ethic was a disgust to all of society, and he described it as “life's nausea” ((The
Birth of Tragedy 23). To compare Schopenhauer to Christianity was in itself the greatest insult.
By the time he wrote this second passage, Nietzsche, in his own perspective, had completely
thrown off the influence of Schopenhauer. The change in perspective over these years shows a
reverse in his opinion.
Despite Nietzsche's insistence upon having thrown off the reigns of his previous master,
the evidence of the influence was still apparent. Nietzsche could not stand the idea of having
been accountable to someone else's philosophy. He loved the idea that he had carved his own
ideas out of the untouched rock face. Even as a young boy this same mentality was in his mind.
This mentality can be observed in a letter from his mother, when he was at boarding school. His
mother was concerned that his growing rebellious nature was derived from school peers, young
Nietzsche responded with, “There is no question of anybody exercising any influence over me,
for in order for that to happen I must first get to know people whom I feel to be my superiors”
Bollant 18
(Reyburn 22). This same mentality of superiority carried over into his later years, as he took on
almost no mentors outside of Schopenhauer and Richard Wagner. However, his philosophy
continued to bear resemblance to Schopenhauer after his alleged separation. Understanding the
world as will, and fashioning titles like the Will to Power after clear Schopenhauerian ideas, such
as the will to live, would remain permanently in his works.
Dolson agrees, Nietzsche never truly separated from Schopenhauer. He believes that even
after Nietzsche had divorced his allegiance, he continued to fill Schopenhauer's forms with ideas
of his own. Doubting that this position was merely a result of Nietzsche's youth, he argues that
Nietzsche never appreciated the idea that he had once been subject to another philosopher's
views. Dolson concludes that the evidence from Nietzsche's books is against his claims of
divorce, and that “it is safe to assume Schopenhauer's influence was a real and important one”
(Dolson 242).
Schopenhauer's influence over Nietzsche is thus established. While Nietzsche was still
young, and easily malleable, Schopenhauer left a significant mark upon him. Now in order to
reveal the connection between Schopenhauer and Nietzsche’s insistence upon suffering unto
resignation, it is necessary to reveal Schopenhauer's affirmation of the same idea.
Schopenhauer, in the preface of his master work, The World as Will and Representation,
encourages the reader to read three things before reading any further in this work. First of all, the
reader should read an earlier work by Schopenhauer that he describes as the introduction to this
work, On the Fourfold Root of the Principle of Sufficient Reason: A Philosophical Essay (x). The
second thing Schopenhauer encourages to be read are the writings of Kant. Schopenhauer
describes him in a glorious light, even referring to him as “the great Kant” (xii). The last thing
Schopenhauer makes reference to, and which is most important for this essay, are the writings of
Bollant 19
the Upanishads (xi-xiii). Throughout this master work, Schopenhauer will draw connections
between the ideas of Kant and the ideas of Vedanta philosophy. Schopenhauer’s influence from
Eastern philosophy is clear and self-proposed, and his own insistence upon suffering unto
resignation is starkly locatable. In fact, the conclusion of his master work is essentially affirming
asceticism through denial of the will.
The reason for these prerequisites is that Schopenhauer is going to marry the philosophies
of Kant and the Upanishads together into his own philosophy. John David Ebert gives a summary
of this work, The World as Will and Representation, and describes this marriage. Ebert describes
how Schopenhauer used Kant's philosophy of the noumenal world and the phenomenal world5
,
and proposed a relationship between them and the Upanishad philosophies of Maya and Brahma.
Together, these philosophies influenced Schopenhauer's own idea: that all things existed in a
cosmic will-to-live (“On Nietzsche's Birth of Tragedy 1/3”).
Schopenhauer's cosmic will-to-live essentially can be described as a cognitive apparatus
that consumes all of nature. Space, time, and causality determine all of existence, and even
animals have the presuppositional understanding for how to interpret reality. The only separation
between human beings and animals is their cognitive function for reason. Humans can reason,
which to Schopenhauer is merely abstractions upon the cognitive apparatus that interprets reality.
Ebert describes Schopenhauer's philosophy of ideas as, “the metaphysical substratum by means
of which the will pours itself forth and manifests itself in space and time” (John David Ebert on
Nietzsche's Birth of Tragedy 2/3).
Most important to this essay is Schopenhauer's ascetic freedom from the will. Since the
will is constantly driving both humans and animals, the whole world is in never-ending
5 These terns are initially introduced in Kant's Critique of Pure Reason. For simple explanations of these terms see
alternate sources.
Bollant 20
enslavement to the will. The only lasting freedom from it is by means of asceticism, or denial of
the will. From Schopenhauer's own words:
We therefore find in the lives of saintly persons that peace and bliss we have
described, only as the blossom resulting from the constant overcoming of the will;
and we see the constant struggle with the will-to-live as the soil from which it
shoots up; for on earth no one can have lasting peace . . . Therefore we see also
those who have once attained to the denial of the will, strive with all their might
to keep to this path by self-imposed renunciation of every kind, by a penitent and
hard life . . . Indeed, we may assume that most men can reach it only in this way,
and that it is the suffering personally felt, not the suffering merely known, which
most frequently produces complete resignation, often only at the approach of
death. (World as Will and Idea I 506-507)
Schopenhauer, in this statement, is affirming my thesis. To summarize according to
Schopenhauer's philosophy leading up to this quote, everything is will. Will is a presuppositional
cognitive interpretation of reality. To will is to suffer. Willing must inevitably lead to desire, and
any unfulfilled desire is suffering. Therefore, the lasting escape from suffering is to deny the will.
In the quote above, Schopenhauer states that the only lasting freedom from suffering is to deny
the will, and that those who have attained such a denial, strive with everything to maintain “self-
imposed renunciation.” And finally, Schopenhauer affirms my thesis by stating the pathway to
complete resignation is “by a penitent and hard life” through suffering unto resignation.
“If I were to take the results of my philosophy as the standard of truth, I would have to
consider Buddhism the finest of all religion” (The World as Will and Representation II 186).
Schopenhauer himself had clear Eastern influences and He traced his own ideas to Eastern
Bollant 21
influence. He found certain schools of Indian philosophy to nearly reflect his originally Western
philosophy.
Most importantly, it is necessary to recognize that no matter how much Schopenhauer's
philosophy might have strayed from Eastern thought, the purpose of suffering as a pathway to
resignation is cemented in both his ideas and in Eastern Buddhist philosophies from which he
derived his own philosophy. The Upanishads were old philosophies that Schopenhauer relied
upon, and these ideas were forged from many ascetic practices. The practice of yoga was
inspired by the idea that austerity killed sin. This view of such practices was embedded in
Brahamic religion in the Upanishads, and it gained a prominent role in the practices of the Yogas
and the Jainas. According to Jainism, liberation is only possible when all passion has been
exterminated, and a key pathway to that extermination is through suffering.
("Religious Asceticism"). Suffering unto resignation is an easily recognizable idea in the
philosophies and practices of many Eastern religions, and especially in those which
Schopenhauer relied upon.
It is here that the argument finds its rest. Insistence upon suffering unto resignation has
been traced through the philosophies of Nietzsche and Schopenhauer and into Eastern thought.
Nietzsche insisted upon it both in his understanding of an ascetic priest and in his own ascetic
ideal, the ubermensch. Schopenhauer heavily insisted upon it, and he noted that it was a
derivative of Eastern philosophy. His master work concluded this, and in it he clearly stated the
pathway to such resignation.
On the part of Nietzsche and Schopenhauer, this thesis is largely complete. Due to the
nature of Nietzsche's contradictory writings, the argument for his insistence upon suffering unto
resignation cannot be taken much further. On the part of Schopenhauer, it is obvious that it is not
Bollant 22
necessary to take it further. However, further extension of this idea in the area of Eastern
philosophy would not be unmerited. The origin of the ascetic idea could potentially be traced to
specific Eastern ideologies, and this evidence could solidify Nietzsche's original influence by
Schopenhauer and his Eastern philosophies.
It is most important to recognize the immediate influences on Nietzsche and the fact that
Schopenhauer's influence over him never died. As mentioned earlier, Paul Deussen was a
lifelong friend of Nietzsche's, and no monograph on their relationship is in existence. Such a
monograph could have importance in tracing this idea and similar ideas to Eastern thought as
well. Furthermore, Paul Deussen could potentially be traced to significant Eastern Philosophical
influences upon Nietzsche.
In conclusion, Nietzsche insisted upon suffering unto resignation. He espoused this in his
own works, and is shown through his philosophy. Nietzsche had significant connections to
Buddhism, and this stepping stone provides the path to describing his Eastern influences. This
path, however, is mainly through the influence of Schopenhauer. The German philosopher
clearly stated his own connections to Eastern thought in his philosophy. Most importantly,
Schopenhauer established his own insistence upon suffering unto resignation, and its origins in
Eastern thought. Eastern thought affirms the truth that the idea can be expressly found within its
philosophies. Therefore, it is sufficient to say that the idea of insistence upon suffering unto
resignation is traceable from Nietzsche to the Upanishads through Schopenhauer.
Bollant 23
Bibliography
"Forms of Religious Asceticism." Encyclopedia Britannica Online. Encyclopedia Britannica, n.d.
Web. 28 Apr. 2015.
"Human All Too Human, Part 1: Beyond Good and Evil - Friedrich Nietzsche". Streaming
Media. University of Southampton. 1999. "The first of a three-part documentary series on
philosophers whose work explored the nature of human freedom beginning with
Friedrich Nietzsche"
"Nietzsche and Buddhism." Journal of the History of Ideas 44.4 (1983): 671-86. JSTOR
[JSTOR]. Web. 27 Apr. 2015
Abelsen, Peter. "Schopenhauer and Buddhism." Philosophy East & West 43.2 (1993): 255-78.
JSTOR [JSTOR]. Web. 28 Apr. 2015.
Dolson, Grace N. "The Influence of Schopenhauer upon Friedrich Nietzsche."The Philosophical
Review 10.3 (1901): 241-50. JSTOR [JSTOR]. Web. 27 Apr. 2015
Frankl, Viktor Emil. The Doctor and the Soul: From Psychotherapy to Logotherapy. New York:
Vintage, 1986. Print.
Hillesheim, J. W., and Malcolm R. Simpson. Schopenhauer as Educator. Southbed, IN:
Gateway, 1965. Print.
Jaspers, Karl. Nietzsche: An Introduction to the Understanding of His Philosophical Activity.
Tucson, AZ: U of Arizona, 1965. Print.
John D. Ebert. “John David Ebert on Nietzsche's Birth of Tragedy 1/3.” YouTube. John David
Ebert Channel, 20 Oct. 2011. Web. 28 Apr. 2015.
John D. Ebert. “John David Ebert on Nietzsche's Birth of Tragedy 2/3.” YouTube. John David
Bollant 24
Ebert Channel, 20 Oct. 2011. Web. 28 Apr. 2015.
John D. Ebert. “John David Ebert on Nietzsche's Birth of Tragedy 3/3.YouTube.” John David
Ebert Channel, 20 Oct. 2011. Web. 28 Apr. 2015.
Kaufmann, Walter Arnold. Nietzsche, Philosopher, Psychologist, Antichrist. Princeton, NJ:
Princeton UP, 1974. Print.
Kierkegaard, Soren. Fear and Trembling and the Sickness Unto Death. Trans. Walter Lowrie.
Princeton, NJ: Princeton UP, 1941. Print.
Leiter, Brian. Routledge Philosophy Guidebook to Nietzsche on Morality. London: Routledge,
2002. Print.
Melchert, Norman.The Great Conversation: A Historical Introduction to Philosophy. 5th ed.
New York: Oxford UP, 2007. Print.
Basic Buddhist Concepts. Tokyo: Kosei Pub., 1987. Print.
Nietzsche, Friedrich Wilhelm. The Antichrist: A Criticism of Christianity. Trans. Anthony M.
Ludovici. New York: Barnes and Noble, 2006. Print.
Nietzsche, Friedrich Wilhelm. The Birth of Tragedy, and the Case of Wagner. Trans. Walter
Kaufmann. New York: Vintage, 1967. Print.
Nietzsche, Friedrich Wilhelm. Ecce Homo. Trans. W. Kaufmann. New York: Vintage, 1990.
Nietzsche, Friedrich Wilhelm. The Gay Science. Trans. Walter Arnold Kaufmann. New York:
Vintage, 1974. Print.
Nietzsche, Friedrich Wilhelm. The Will to Power. Ed. Walter Arnold Kaufmann. Trans. R. J.
Hollingdale. New York: Vintage, 1967. Print.
Bollant 25
Nietzsche, Friedrich Wilhelm. Thus Spake Zarathustra. Trans. Thomas Common. New York:
Modern Library, n.d. Print.
Nietzsche, Friedrich Wilhelm. Twilight of the Idols ; And, the Anti-Christ. Trans. R. J.
Hollingdale. London, England: Penguin, 1990. Print.
Nietzsche, Friedrich. On the Genealogy of Morals. In Basic Writings of Nietzsche. Tanslated and
Ed. Walter Kaufman. The Modern Library, New York, 1992.
Reyburn, H. A., H. E. Hinderks, and James Garden Taylor. Nietzsche; the Story of a Human
Philosopher. London: Macmillan, 1948. Print.
Rollman, Hans. "Deussen, Nietzsche, and Vendanta." Journal of the History of Ideas 39.1
(1978): 125-32. JSTOR [JSTOR]. Web. 27 Apr. 2015
Schopenhauer, Arthur. Die Welt als Wille und Vorstellung II (Erganzungsband), Schopenhauer
Samtliche Werke. Trans. Peter Abelsen. Vol. 2. Munchen: Piper Verlag, 1911. Print.
Schopenhauer, Arthur. The World as Will and Idea I. Trans. R. B. Haldane Haldane and J. Kemp.
Vol. 1. Boston: Ticknor, 1888. Print.
Welbon, Guy R. Buddhist Nirvana and Its Western Interpreters. Chicago: U of Chicago, 1968.
Print.
Wilkens, Steven, and Alan G. Padgett. Christianity and Western Thought: A History of
Philosophers, Ideas and Movements. Leicester: Inter-Varsity, 2000. Print
Williams, Bernard Arthur Owen. Nietzsche: The Gay Science. Trans. Josefine Nauckhoff.
Cambridge: Cambridge UP, 2001. Print.
Bollant 26
Wrisley, George. Nietzsche and the Value of Human Suffering - Two Alternative Ideals. George
Wrisley. Web.

More Related Content

What's hot

Philman orga report
Philman orga reportPhilman orga report
Philman orga report
Fedie Orga
 
Encyclopediaofpsychologyandreligion 110225130507-phpapp01
Encyclopediaofpsychologyandreligion 110225130507-phpapp01Encyclopediaofpsychologyandreligion 110225130507-phpapp01
Encyclopediaofpsychologyandreligion 110225130507-phpapp01
derryck100
 
Lecture 00 history of the psychology of religion
Lecture 00   history of the psychology of religionLecture 00   history of the psychology of religion
Lecture 00 history of the psychology of religion
Paweł Socha
 
From Pythagoras To Max Planck
From Pythagoras To Max PlanckFrom Pythagoras To Max Planck
From Pythagoras To Max Planck
Wesley F Revels
 

What's hot (20)

ASTROLOGY’S UNIVERSAL PARADIGM: The One Universal Language (Part 2)
ASTROLOGY’S UNIVERSAL PARADIGM: The One Universal Language (Part 2)ASTROLOGY’S UNIVERSAL PARADIGM: The One Universal Language (Part 2)
ASTROLOGY’S UNIVERSAL PARADIGM: The One Universal Language (Part 2)
 
Psychology and the Humanities
Psychology and the HumanitiesPsychology and the Humanities
Psychology and the Humanities
 
Philman orga report
Philman orga reportPhilman orga report
Philman orga report
 
Viktor Frankl's Philosophical Theory on Man's Search for Meaning
Viktor Frankl's Philosophical Theory on Man's Search for MeaningViktor Frankl's Philosophical Theory on Man's Search for Meaning
Viktor Frankl's Philosophical Theory on Man's Search for Meaning
 
Encyclopediaofpsychologyandreligion 110225130507-phpapp01
Encyclopediaofpsychologyandreligion 110225130507-phpapp01Encyclopediaofpsychologyandreligion 110225130507-phpapp01
Encyclopediaofpsychologyandreligion 110225130507-phpapp01
 
History and Background Of Psychology - Basic Introduction
History and Background Of Psychology - Basic IntroductionHistory and Background Of Psychology - Basic Introduction
History and Background Of Psychology - Basic Introduction
 
Lecture 00 history of the psychology of religion
Lecture 00   history of the psychology of religionLecture 00   history of the psychology of religion
Lecture 00 history of the psychology of religion
 
Eternity of man new
Eternity of man newEternity of man new
Eternity of man new
 
Mysticism by Aldous Huxley
Mysticism by Aldous HuxleyMysticism by Aldous Huxley
Mysticism by Aldous Huxley
 
Easternphilo
EasternphiloEasternphilo
Easternphilo
 
Historical background of psychology
Historical background of psychologyHistorical background of psychology
Historical background of psychology
 
A history of psychology section 3
A history of psychology section 3 A history of psychology section 3
A history of psychology section 3
 
Philosophy of man 6
Philosophy of man 6Philosophy of man 6
Philosophy of man 6
 
On the eternal of man(m.scheler)
On the eternal of man(m.scheler)On the eternal of man(m.scheler)
On the eternal of man(m.scheler)
 
From Pythagoras To Max Planck
From Pythagoras To Max PlanckFrom Pythagoras To Max Planck
From Pythagoras To Max Planck
 
Human Nature: An Islamic Perspective(Journal paper)
Human Nature: An Islamic Perspective(Journal paper)Human Nature: An Islamic Perspective(Journal paper)
Human Nature: An Islamic Perspective(Journal paper)
 
Introduction to History of Psychology
Introduction to History of PsychologyIntroduction to History of Psychology
Introduction to History of Psychology
 
Philosophy of Man
Philosophy of ManPhilosophy of Man
Philosophy of Man
 
Eastern Philosophy Perspective
Eastern Philosophy PerspectiveEastern Philosophy Perspective
Eastern Philosophy Perspective
 
Philosophy of man 9
Philosophy of man 9Philosophy of man 9
Philosophy of man 9
 

Viewers also liked (20)

Estrella
EstrellaEstrella
Estrella
 
LetterMckeon
LetterMckeonLetterMckeon
LetterMckeon
 
Mobil arbetsplatsform
Mobil arbetsplatsformMobil arbetsplatsform
Mobil arbetsplatsform
 
NEBOSH Certificate
NEBOSH CertificateNEBOSH Certificate
NEBOSH Certificate
 
Carlino, por que no se completan, educere aã±o 9 n⺠30, 2005
Carlino, por que no se completan, educere aã±o 9 n⺠30, 2005Carlino, por que no se completan, educere aã±o 9 n⺠30, 2005
Carlino, por que no se completan, educere aã±o 9 n⺠30, 2005
 
Descritores mat 2_bim_ 2014
Descritores mat 2_bim_ 2014Descritores mat 2_bim_ 2014
Descritores mat 2_bim_ 2014
 
C5 4 bim_aluno
C5 4 bim_alunoC5 4 bim_aluno
C5 4 bim_aluno
 
Contra la diabetes
Contra la diabetesContra la diabetes
Contra la diabetes
 
Eclipse
EclipseEclipse
Eclipse
 
Fahrenheit 451; Censorship vs. Freedom
Fahrenheit 451; Censorship vs. FreedomFahrenheit 451; Censorship vs. Freedom
Fahrenheit 451; Censorship vs. Freedom
 
Soundslide
SoundslideSoundslide
Soundslide
 
Los ojos de Celina
Los ojos de CelinaLos ojos de Celina
Los ojos de Celina
 
Pg
PgPg
Pg
 
COBRA
COBRACOBRA
COBRA
 
Natura ciclo 08 maio 2013
Natura ciclo 08 maio 2013Natura ciclo 08 maio 2013
Natura ciclo 08 maio 2013
 
Blog
BlogBlog
Blog
 
Present continuous
Present continuousPresent continuous
Present continuous
 
Projet carriere
Projet carriereProjet carriere
Projet carriere
 
N.º 32 jornal da e.s.g.s julho de 2004 ano vii
N.º 32 jornal da e.s.g.s   julho de 2004 ano viiN.º 32 jornal da e.s.g.s   julho de 2004 ano vii
N.º 32 jornal da e.s.g.s julho de 2004 ano vii
 
Bo 04 05-2012-30
Bo 04 05-2012-30Bo 04 05-2012-30
Bo 04 05-2012-30
 

Similar to Gabe's thesis (7)

Nietzsche's prominent works and God is dead.
Nietzsche's prominent works and God is dead. Nietzsche's prominent works and God is dead.
Nietzsche's prominent works and God is dead.
 
Nietzsche Essay
Nietzsche EssayNietzsche Essay
Nietzsche Essay
 
NEW THOUGHT---BUDDHIST STYLE
NEW THOUGHT---BUDDHIST STYLENEW THOUGHT---BUDDHIST STYLE
NEW THOUGHT---BUDDHIST STYLE
 
Nietzsche and Foucault on Historical Change
Nietzsche and Foucault on Historical ChangeNietzsche and Foucault on Historical Change
Nietzsche and Foucault on Historical Change
 
Christ Hymn
Christ HymnChrist Hymn
Christ Hymn
 
Optimism and Pessimism.pptx
Optimism and Pessimism.pptxOptimism and Pessimism.pptx
Optimism and Pessimism.pptx
 
Nietzschefinal.docx
Nietzschefinal.docxNietzschefinal.docx
Nietzschefinal.docx
 

Gabe's thesis

  • 1. Bollant 1 Gabriel Bollant 7115 Paul Boling CT 491 2/21/2015 Nietzsche's Insistence upon Suffering Unto Resignation Tracing Nietzsche's ideas is a topic of understanding that has defined a large portion of modern philosophy. His ambiguity due to his parabolic nature combined with his revolutionary ideas has mystified the postmodern generation, captivating their interest. Books have been written clarifying his ideals, and more have been written denouncing his ideas. Not only did Nietzsche capture the imaginations of the modern generation, but since the first decades following his writings, philosophers, psychologists, philologists, and many other scholarly schools have been captivated in the same way. Influential thinkers and political leaders such as Freud, Marx, Derrida, Foucault, and even Hitler have all been large proponents of his writings. In this thesis I wish to draw out an ascetic ideal within Nietzsche's philosophy, and trace it back to Eastern ideologies. The hinge that completes the trace will be the philosophy of Schopenhauer and the influence that he had over Nietzsche at a young age. I wish to show that while Nietzsche was still young and malleable, he was significantly influenced by Schopenhauer, and that that influence never left him. Particularly, I wish to show it in the area of his insistence upon suffering unto resignation. I claim that Nietzsche's insistence upon suffering unto resignation was originally an Eastern idea traceable to the Upanishads through Schopenhauer. The meaning of insistence upon suffering unto resignation is of great importance. In tracing the argument, all of these philosophies positively affirmed that resignation from desire— denial of the will—was accomplished through suffering. I will show that they all affirmed this
  • 2. Bollant 2 ascetic idea, and that it encouraged a resignation from desire. Moreover, I will show that Nietzsche, Schopenhauer, and Eastern philosophy encouraged suffering as an ideal show of piety. Such a trace will clarify the interpretation of Nietzsche's ideologies, but it will also reveal their possible origin. Within this thesis, I will trace the potential of the idea to Eastern thought, but not to finding origins of the ascetic idea. This would require another thesis. The focus of this essay is upon Nietzsche himself, and the origin of his idea for his own thought. This thesis will shed further light upon his philosophy influenced by the Eastern perspective. It could also lead to further studies being done, including a study of Schopenhauer's specific influence and the potential origin of the idea in Eastern thought. However, the focus of this essay is on Nietzsche. Nietzsche was born in Rocken, a small town in Saxony, Prussia. His father was a Lutheran minister coming from a generational line of ministers. He was christened with the name Friedrich Wilhelm after the name of the Prussian king. Nietzsche would later shed this name along with nationalism and religion, but not before both the king and Nietzsche’s father went insane; an uncanny foreshadowing of his own insanity to come. Most experts, however, agree that his illness was not inherited. ((Kaufmann 21-22)). Nietzsche’s father died when he was five years old and his mother moved the family to Naumburg. He began attending a renowned boarding school on full scholarship, which was a significant scholastic achievement. After graduation, he attended the University of Bonn, initially studying theology and classical philosophy. It would not be long before he would give up theology and follow his teacher Friedrich Ritschl to Leipzig. This relationship proved to be a victory for Nietzsche, as it would be on Ritschl's glowing recommendation that he would begin teaching philology at the University of Basel (Kaufmann 23-24).
  • 3. Bollant 3 Wilkens and Padgett interpret Nietzsche's work as a reaction against his childhood. They point out that Nietzsche had not yet fulfilled the requirements for a doctorate when he began teaching (Wilkens & Padgett). This shows that it was clearly on recommendation alone that Nietzsche was awarded the position. His time at Basel would not be long, as he retired ten years later at thirty-four years old due to poor health. He spent the last eleven years of his life struggling with insanity, commonly attributed to syphilis. Before beginning my particular argument, it is important to note Nietzsche's contradictory nature. While it might be simple and apparent to argue Schopenhauer's insistence upon suffering unto resignation, it is not simple to argue Nietzsche's. His philosophy is parabolic by nature, and he is at constant contradiction with himself. Karl Jaspers, a prominent translator and scholar of Nietzsche, affirms "All statements seem to be annulled by other statements. Self-contradiction is the fundamental ingredient in Nietzsche's thought. For nearly every single one of Nietzsche's judgments, one can also find an opposite” (Jaspers 10). Due to this contradictory nature, it is either gratuitously simple or overly impossible to make claims about Nietzsche's ideas. I will argue his insistence upon suffering unto resignation by outlining it within his philosophy, and showing his dependence on Schopenhauer. Given the outcome of Nietzsche's own life, his philosophy inevitably would deal with suffering. Eleven years took him from the prime of his life into excruciating pain. Days when he was free from the debilitating pain were spent in writing. In the final years of his life the illness began destroying his mind. His final works were written while racing against his own destruction (Melchert 533). As he struggled with illness disintegrating his body and mind, he would seek to understand his own suffering.
  • 4. Bollant 4 To understand Nietzsche's view of suffering, there is need to first understand his view of religion. Religion to Nietzsche, particularly Christianity and Buddhism, was the possibility of minimizing or abolishing suffering. Nietzsche understood religion to be merely a means to alleviate personal suffering. God created man happy, idle, innocent, and immortal: our actual life is a false, decayed, sinful existence, an existence of punishment— Suffering, struggle, work, death are considered as objections and question marks against life, as something that ought not to last; for which one requires a cure—and has a cure!— From the time of Adam until now, man has been in an abnormal state: God himself has sacrificed his son for the guilt of Adam, in order to put an end to this abnormal state: the natural character of life is a curse; Christ gives back the state of normality to him who believes in him: he makes him happy, idle and innocent. (The Will to Power 224) Nietzsche here critiques the ethic of Christianity as a means of solace from suffering. By looking towards the next life as reward for actions in this life, Christianity escapes. Redemption will ease the pain of suffering in this world by providing hope for a future. This same concern with suffering is reflective in many religions. Kogen Mizuno, in his explication of basic Buddhist concepts, writes, “The major purpose of all religions is to cure the illness of the spirit and create a wholesome, integrated psychological condition . . . [their] major task is the essential improvement of the psychological being to ensure spiritual health and immunity to spiritual illness” (105). In the traditional story of Buddha's discovery of the path to enlightenment, he is shaken from his ignorance by observing the suffering of sickness, old age,
  • 5. Bollant 5 and death: “that life is suffering, that ignorance is the cause of suffering, that suffering can be eliminated, and that the Eightfold Path is the way to eliminate suffering” (106). Buddhism views suffering as a hindrance from experiencing happiness; that through the path to enlightenment, there is freedom from suffering through its cessation. This view of religion, as a means to freedom from suffering, may not be universally accepted; it actually tends more towards an Eastern concept. Schopenhauer also reflected on these same ideas, as we will see further on. For now, we need to note Nietzsche's ascetic ideal. In the third essay of the Geneology of Morals, Nietzsche describes the ascetic ideal. Essentially, it is a means through religion that provides meaning to suffering (Genealogy of Morals, III 28). This is important, because it is Nietzsche's understanding of the pathway to enlightenment. This is his freedom from suffering. The significance of Nietzsche defining his means of freedom from suffering through the ascetic ideal is that it connects to his views of religion. More importantly, it connects to his views of Buddhism. It is in this view of Buddhism that I wish to connect Nietzsche's thought to Eastern philosophy, particularly by connecting him to Schopenhauer. It is also in this view of suffering that I wish to connect Nietzsche's thought to the idea of suffering unto resignation. I affirm that Nietzsche states such an ascetic view of suffering leading to the ascetic ideal. The ascetic ideal is achieved by means of the ascetic priest, a shepherd who guides the herd to freedom from suffering. The wretched are guided by the ascetic priest, as he has dominion over suffering (Genealogy of Morals, III 15). Nietzsche says that the priest is “a tool for the creation of more favorable conditions for being here and being man—it is precisely this power that enables him to persuade to existence the whole herd of the ill-constituted, disgruntled, underprivileged, unfortunate, and all who suffer of themselves” (Genealogy of Morals, III 11).
  • 6. Bollant 6 The wretched, the “. . . ill-constituted, disgruntled, underprivileged, unfortunate . . .” are guided to freedom from suffering. Nietzsche understands that this is done in many ways. He divides these ways into two categories: the ‘innocent’ and the ‘guilty.’ The first way, the innocent, is carried out by reducing life to avoid suffering: “If possible, will and desire are abolished altogether . . . no love; no hate; indifference; no revenge; no wealth; no work; one begs; if possible, no women, or as little as possible; in spiritual matters . . .” (Genealogy of Morals, III 17). Such a cessation will produce a kind of euphoria. Nietzsche provides the example of the Buddhist doctrine of becoming one with Brahma (Genealogy of Morals, III 17). By denying oneself all desire, one achieves freedom from suffering. The second way of the ascetic priest is through the guilty. Suffering and envy of the healthy accumulate a resentment, which can have an explosive effect on the wretched individual. The priest shepherds the wretched away from this resentment by providing a cause, a culprit to which the wretched can vent their feelings. Even out of friends and family, the sufferer makes culprits for himself to ease the pain of his suffering (Genealogy of Morals, III 15). The ascetic priest redirects resentment by means of a lie. By informing the wretched that they are their own cause for suffering, the priest provides the sufferer with a means to deaden the pain, and more importantly he provides a meaning to suffering. Nietzsche determines the problem of suffering is not in the pain of suffering, but in the lack of meaning in it: “[Man's] problem was not suffering itself, but that there was no answer to the crying question, ‘why do I suffer?’” (Genealogy of Morals, III 28). Therefore, the ascetic ideal is self-denial: “The three great slogans of the ascetic ideal are familiar: poverty, humility, chastity” (Genealogy of Morals, III 8). Humans naturally desire, they crave and want, and these go against the ascetic ideal. Seeing this, the ascetic priest provides
  • 7. Bollant 7 meaning for suffering either in an afterlife or in some reward, or more importantly as punishment for going against the ascetic ideal: “He should look for it within himself, in guilt, in a piece of the past, he should understand his suffering itself as a condition of punishment” (Genealogy of Morals, III 20). In this, the ascetic ideal is complete. There is freedom from suffering, and even more suffering is encouraged: “one no longer protested against pain, one thirsted for pain; ‘more pain! more pain!’ the desire of his disciples and initiates has cried for centuries” (Genealogy of Morals, III 20). The ascetic ideal is key in showing Nietzsche's view of religion and suffering, and while he has some harsh words to say about religion, his view of the ascetic ideal shapes the creation of his own alternative ideal. Nietzsche is living in the post-Darwin world. Darwin's Origin of Species, published in 1859, set forth a new era. His publication resulted in the development of evolution, which gave means to some of the first cosmological models which did not necessitate the existence of a god. Nietzsche finds in it the reality that God could no longer exist (“Human All Too Human” This is the documentary). To Nietzsche, science had developed past the need for God, and the ability to even believe in God. The truth of science eradicated belief in God, and the realization of this discovery was dramatic. Observe in Nietzsche's publication, The Gay Science, the scene portrayed by his parable of the madman: Have you not heard of that madman who lit a lantern in the bright morning hours, ran to the market place, and cried incessantly: "I seek God! I seek God!"—As many of those who did not believe in God were standing around just then, he provoked much laughter. . . . Is there still any up or down? Are we not straying, as through an infinite nothing? Do we not feel the breath of empty space? Has it not
  • 8. Bollant 8 become colder? Is not night continually closing in on us? Do we not need to light lanterns in the morning? Do we hear nothing as yet of the noise of the gravediggers who are burying God? Do we smell nothing as yet of the divine decomposition? Gods, too, decompose. God is dead. God remains dead. And we have killed him. (sect. 125; 119) This realization left Nietzsche with a task to create a new ascetic ideal, one which did not necessitate the existence of God. “Dead are all Gods: now do we desire the superman to live” (Thus Spake Zarathustra 1, sect. 22, 83). Nietzsche's alternative ideal comes under the title of ubermensch, translated ‘superman’ or ‘overman.’ The ubermensch describes a character, an ascetic priest, who shepherds the herd, and gives a new ascetic ideal. This new ideal does not rely upon the lies of God or ‘guilty.’ He is a character who can provide meaning to the herd by giving them the ascetic ideal. Essentially, he is a new era in evolution, and he will guide man as a “bridge” in the process of evolving higher (Thus Spake Zarathustra sect. 4, 8). There are many different characteristics of the ubermensch, but the two we need to dwell on are the doctrines of faithfulness to the earth and affirmation of eternal recurrence. These two characteristics show Nietzsche's insistence upon suffering unto resignation. Nietzsche's demands to remain “faithful to the earth” are going to show his insistence upon resigning from desire, and eternal recurrence will show that suffering is going to be the key to this resignation. The first characteristic, faithfulness to the earth, is a matter of remaining firm on the limited nature of life. An ubermensch has no business looking beyond this life to define his meaning. It is not the true world Nietzsche is describing. The true world1 , a term referring to the 1 For further understanding on the true world, see Kant’s ideas on Phenomena as described in Critique of Pure
  • 9. Bollant 9 way the world empirically represents itself to man, is just as much of a metaphysical theory as belief in gods. For in Twilight of the Idols Nietzsche proclaims “How the 'True World' Finally Became a Fable.” Here he describes it as “useless and superfluous” (“How the 'True World' Finally Became a Fable”). Instead, Nietzsche is speaking about remaining faithful to non- metaphysical ideas. The ubermensch should have no desires for otherworldly lies (Thus Spake Zarathustra sect. 4, 9-10). It is here in this doctrine that Nietzsche is espousing resignation. The ‘true world' is something to be resigned to. It is an empty, cold shell that can never be grasped. Nietzsche's early works, particularly The Birth of Tragedy attempted to reconcile a Schopenhauerian metaphysical theory. Nietzsche has thrown off the reigns of metaphysical ideas, and has labeled them worthless. The ubermensch must resign to such ideas, including the idea of the true world. Nietzsche provided a test to measure a true ubermensch: the affirmation of eternal recurrence. If a man could affirm an existence of perfect repetition, then he would be an ubermensch. In other words, if life repeated itself over-and-over again without change or anything new, the same sufferings and the same joys, and if a man could embrace it, even “love” it, then he would be an ubermensch. Nietzsche calls it “my formula for greatness in a human being: amor fati” (Ecce Homo 258). Amor fati means the love of fate; to embrace the completeness of fate is, in essence, the new ideal. The test proves whether or not one truly embraces all of fate, because despairing at the idea of repetition would reveal a desire for more. It is desire, desire for more than what is, desire for an afterlife and higher calling, that the ubermensch resigns from. These desires are the lies of metaphysical ideas, and they are not worthy of an ubermensch. It is not only these grand desires that one resigns from. He resigns from desire of all things: from pride, from comfort, from the things of weakness (Thus Spake Reason.
  • 10. Bollant 10 Zarathustra 1, sect. 1 23). He becomes an ascetic priest, free from the desires of this world, and completely accepting of fate. And how does the ubermensch resign from such desires? By none other than suffering. Observe in Thus Spake Zarathustra Nietzsche's description of the first stage of the three metamorphoses. The ubermensch must undergo the stages of three metamorphoses to become the true ubermensch. The first stage is that of the camel. The picture here is that he must embrace suffering and hardship in order to become strong and resign from desire. As a camel is strong, so must the ubermensch be strong, carrying as much burden and hardship that is physically possible. He must always take the hard way, assuming the “heavy.” But “what is heavy?” Nietzsche says, “To humiliate oneself in order to mortify one's pride. . . . To exhibit one's folly in order to mock at one's wisdom. . . . To desert our cause when it celebrateth its triumph. . . . To be sick and dismiss comforters, and make friends of the deaf, who never hear thy request” (Thus Spake Zarathustra 1, sect. 1 23). It is here that Nietzsche is proclaiming the endurance of suffering in order to resign from desire. Amor fati, love of fate: one must love what is immediately in front of him, and not desire things beyond himself, just as Nietzsche says, “in order to mortify one's pride.” The ubermensch, the new ascetic priest, Nietzsche's alternative ideal, must be someone who does not feel pride, accept comfort, or celebrate triumph. Instead, he must seek hardship for himself in order to achieve resignation. Soren Kierkegaard, a Christian Existentialist philosopher, encourages a very similar philosophy. As a Christian, Kierkegaard encourages it for very different reasons. However, in his book, Fear and Trembling, he describes an ideal character. This character, the knight of faith, is a man entirely resigned from the desires of the world. Even as a stepping stone, the knight of faith
  • 11. Bollant 11 must first become the knight of infinite resignation. At that moment the knight has completely resigned from all the desires of the world. However, he only becomes the knight of faith when he can graciously accept the things of the world, while still maintaining a resignation of desire for them. Observe this passage where Kierkegaard describes such a knight: One can discover nothing of that aloof and superior nature whereby one recognizes the knight of the infinite. He takes delight in everything, and whenever one sees him taking part in a particular pleasure, he does it with the persistence which is the mark of the earthly man whose soul is absorbed in such things... Toward evening he walks home, his gait is as indefatigable as that of the postman. On his way he reflects that his wife has surely a special little warm dish prepared for him, e.g. a calf's head roasted, garnished with vegetables. If he were to meet a man like-minded, he could continue as far as East Gate to discourse with him about that dish, with a passion befitting a hotel chef. As it happens, he hasn't four pence to his name, and yet he fully and firmly believes that his wife has that dainty dish for him. If she had it, it would then be an invidious sight for superior people and an inspiring one for the plain man, to see him eat; for his appetite is greater than Esau's. His wife hasn't it–strangely enough, it is quite the same to him. (Kierkegaard 82-83) Nietzsche, sharing much of existentialist philosophy, is describing his ideal in terms of these same qualities. His ubermensch is resigning from the desires of the world, as well as any afterlife, and remaining faithful to the earth, or fate. This is accomplished by assuming suffering, as a camel assumes a “heavy” load.
  • 12. Bollant 12 Brian Leiter, in his Nietzsche on Morality, argues that eternal recurrence necessitates a rejection of suffering and any meaning behind it. Such a claim stands in opposition to my thesis. The acceptance of a repetitive eternity, Lieter says, “is to recognize that there is no such meaning” (Leiter 288). However, coming from Nietzsche, such a claim is arguable. Even in Thus Spake Zarathustra he says, “It was suffering and incapacity that created the afterworlds” (Thus Spake Zarathustra 1, 143-145). Metaphysical ideas, which need to be thrown off, are the result of suffering and those who suffer (Nietzsche on Morality, 287-8).2 George Wrisley does not agree with Leiter; he refutes Leiter on the grounds that Nietzsche encouraged suffering. First of all, Nietzsche claimed that joy necessitates suffering. The two are intimately tied. Secondly, he said suffering makes one strong, in a “what doesn't kill me, makes me stronger” type fashion. Wrisley uses these points to argue Nietzsche's encouragement of suffering, refuting Leiter's claims (Wrisley 13-21).3 Thus far it has been established that Nietzsche affirmed suffering unto resignation. Now in order to show that such an idea is in fact an Eastern philosophy derived from Schopenhauer, I will begin by drawing out Nietzsche's connections to Buddhism. There have not been many studies drawing Nietzsche's connection to Buddhism. In a paper connecting Nietzsche to Paul Duessen, Hans Rollman, a professor in the Department of Religious Studies at the Memorial University of Newfoundland, states, “No monograph dealing with the lifelong friendship between Friedrich Nietzsche and the German indologist Paul Deussen has yet appeared” (125). This is significant because Paul Deussen was famed for translating Eastern philosophy and was a lifelong friend of Nietzsche's. If such connections establishing Eastern philosophy's impact over Nietzsche were well researched, such a monograph 2 For more on Leiter’s argument see Nietzsche on Morality. 3 For more on Wrisley's refutation see Nietzsche and the Value of Human Suffering - Two Alternative Ideals
  • 13. Bollant 13 would surely be needed. However, there have been a handful of studies drawing the similarities between Buddhism and Nietzsche, and a pool of research exists that draws his connection to Schopenhauer. Many Nietzschean scholars connect Nietzsche to nihilism, against the philosopher's perspective of himself. Such a contradiction between his writings and scholarly claims surrounding them is characteristic of Nietzsche. For this reason, it is plausible to look to establishments beyond his own words to justify his philosophy. Establishing this idea—that Nietzsche had Buddhist influence over his philosophy—is significant as it would connect him to Buddhism and show his contradictory nature. Guy Richard Welbon has researched the potential connections between Nietzsche and Buddhism. Observing Nietzsche's life, Welbon points out that he likely studied Sanskrit while at Leipzig, under Hermann Brockhaus. Welbon even suggests that due to his training Nietzsche would have been one of the most well read and firmly grounded scholars on Eastern philosophy for his time period. This is significant, as it might suggest a large influence from these philosophies upon Nietzsche's own writings. Welbon draws parallels between Nietzsche's doctrine of eternal recurrence and the Buddhist vale of Samsara existence, Nietzche's Zarathustra and the Buddhist bodhisttava, his program for transvaluation of values and Nirvana.4 Welbon further concludes, “I am insisting that there is no basic conflict between Nietzsche and Buddhism on several important issues, and that there is sufficient evidence to indicate that Nietzsche's presentations do witness Buddhist influences” (Welbon 185-89). Another author who draws a similar Buddhist influence over Nietzsche, Benjamin Elman, suggests that Nietzsche was against many scholarly claims, in fact a nihilist, and that the nihilist 4 For more on these doctrines and Welbon's connection see Buddhist Nirvana and Its Western Interpreters.
  • 14. Bollant 14 tendencies of Eastern thought show his connection to them. Elman concludes this by shifting the understanding of Nietzsche's thought away from the traditional understanding of the Western intellectual milieu defined by men such as G.W.F. Hegel (1770-1831), Karl Marx (1818-1883), and Charles Darwin (1809-1882). In this traditional view, Nietzsche greatly influenced these men. Elman suggests such a view introduces philosophic blinders due to Western interpretive bias. Instead, he proposes viewing Nietzsche's philosophy in light of the vistas of Eastern influence where, according to Elman, Nietzsche explicitly attacked Buddhism as a nihilistic religion; Elman remains insistent upon this connection (671-673). If the ideas of Welbon and Elman are correct, this would reveal not only significant Eastern philosophic influence on Nietzsche, but also the legitimacy of his contradictory nature when attacking Buddhism. This idea provides a stepping stone, establishing Buddhist influence, which will lead into his connections with Eastern philosophy. In order to connect Nietzsche's idea of suffering unto resignation to Eastern philosophy, I will draw out the same idea in Eastern philosophy, first by drawing the connection of the idea to Schopenhauer. The next step in this process is connecting Nietzsche to Schopenhauer himself.
  • 15. Bollant 15 While Nietzsche was a university student at Leipzig, Schopenhauer left his mark upon him. At that time, Nietzsche picked up a book at an antiquarian shop and was beguiled instantly. He later wrote about the experience in Untimely Meditations. “I belong to the readers of Schopenhauer,' Nietzsche says, 'who after they have read the first page of him know with certainty that they will read all his pages, and they will listen to every word that he has said” (Dolson 241-242). Nietzsche became a professed follower of Schopenhauer. Neal Dolson, a professor of Philosophy at Wells College, describes Nietzsche's encounter with Schopenhauer as a highly influential one. Once a proselyte, Nietzsche began making converts of his friends. They began a circle of disciples, committed to the philosopher as worshipers to a deity. When one among them would struggle, the other offered appropriate passages from the works of Schopenhauer. He was to them the incarnation of an ideal philosopher. Later, when Nietzsche accepted the position at Basel, he expressed his intention of specifically infusing Schopenhauerian philosophy with the philology program. In an essay in which Nietzsche attempted to express the meaning Schopenhauer had over him, instead of repeating Schopenhauer's philosophic principles, he discussed the “physiological influence,” as Nietzsche called it. In the essay he describes Schopenhauer as fulfilling the test of a true philosopher by being genuine and true to his principles. He not only spoke his philosophy, but Nietzsche says that he expressed it in his life (Dolson 241-246). Ironically, Schopenhauer was known for many things, but fulfilling his own philosophy was not one of them. Nietzsche was without a doubt infatuated with the philosopher. Nietzsche's divorce from Schopenhauer comes resolutely. In his own words, he passes from referring to himself as a follower and speaking highly of him to denouncing him and
  • 16. Bollant 16 comparing him to the lowest order: Christianity. Observe this passage from one of Nietzsche's early works, Schopenhauer as Educator: I judge a philosopher by whether he is able to serve as an example. . . . [Schopenhauer's] greatness is the fact that he faces the picture of life as a whole in order to interpret it as a whole. . . . Schopenhauer's philosophy should be interpreted . . . by the individual . . . in order to gain insight into his own misery, needs and limitations and to know the antidotes and consolations; namely, sacrifice of the ego, submission to the noblest intentions, and above all, justice and mercy. He teaches us how to distinguish between real and apparent advancements of human happiness, how neither becoming rich, nor being respected, nor being learned can raise the individual above his disgust as the valuelessness of his existence, and how the struggle for all these good things is given meaning only by a high and transfiguring goal: to win power in order to come to the help of nature, and to correct her foolishness and clumsiness a little — at first, admittedly, solely for oneself, but eventually for everybody. . . . This is a struggle which in its deepest and innermost nature leads to resignation. (25-26) In this passage, the adoration that Nietzsche had for Schopenhauer is clearly felt. His expression of high esteem is vividly evident. However, fifteen years later, with the publication of Twilight of the Idols, Nietzsche would express a different tune. His adoration for Schopenhauer has waned with his maturity by the time he composes this passage: Schopenhauer . . . is for a psychologist a case of the first order: namely, a mendacious attempt of genius to marshal, in aid of a nihilistic total devaluation of life, the very counter-instances, the great self-affirmations of the 'will to live', the
  • 17. Bollant 17 exuberant forms of life. He interpreted in turn art, heroism, genius, beauty, grand sympathy, knowledge, the will to truth, tragedy, as phenomena consequent upon the 'denial' of or the thirst to deny the 'will' — the greatest piece of false-coinage in history, Christianity alone excepted. Looked at more closely he is in this merely the heir of the Christian interpretation: but with this difference, that he knew how to take what Christianity had rejected, the great cultural facts of mankind, and approve of them from a Christian, that is to say nihilistic, point of view (- namely, as roads to 'redemption', as preliminary forms of 'redemption', as stimulants of the thirst for 'redemption'). (79-80) The comparison to Christianity is one of the lowest degradations that could from Nietzsche. For him, the Christian ethic was a disgust to all of society, and he described it as “life's nausea” ((The Birth of Tragedy 23). To compare Schopenhauer to Christianity was in itself the greatest insult. By the time he wrote this second passage, Nietzsche, in his own perspective, had completely thrown off the influence of Schopenhauer. The change in perspective over these years shows a reverse in his opinion. Despite Nietzsche's insistence upon having thrown off the reigns of his previous master, the evidence of the influence was still apparent. Nietzsche could not stand the idea of having been accountable to someone else's philosophy. He loved the idea that he had carved his own ideas out of the untouched rock face. Even as a young boy this same mentality was in his mind. This mentality can be observed in a letter from his mother, when he was at boarding school. His mother was concerned that his growing rebellious nature was derived from school peers, young Nietzsche responded with, “There is no question of anybody exercising any influence over me, for in order for that to happen I must first get to know people whom I feel to be my superiors”
  • 18. Bollant 18 (Reyburn 22). This same mentality of superiority carried over into his later years, as he took on almost no mentors outside of Schopenhauer and Richard Wagner. However, his philosophy continued to bear resemblance to Schopenhauer after his alleged separation. Understanding the world as will, and fashioning titles like the Will to Power after clear Schopenhauerian ideas, such as the will to live, would remain permanently in his works. Dolson agrees, Nietzsche never truly separated from Schopenhauer. He believes that even after Nietzsche had divorced his allegiance, he continued to fill Schopenhauer's forms with ideas of his own. Doubting that this position was merely a result of Nietzsche's youth, he argues that Nietzsche never appreciated the idea that he had once been subject to another philosopher's views. Dolson concludes that the evidence from Nietzsche's books is against his claims of divorce, and that “it is safe to assume Schopenhauer's influence was a real and important one” (Dolson 242). Schopenhauer's influence over Nietzsche is thus established. While Nietzsche was still young, and easily malleable, Schopenhauer left a significant mark upon him. Now in order to reveal the connection between Schopenhauer and Nietzsche’s insistence upon suffering unto resignation, it is necessary to reveal Schopenhauer's affirmation of the same idea. Schopenhauer, in the preface of his master work, The World as Will and Representation, encourages the reader to read three things before reading any further in this work. First of all, the reader should read an earlier work by Schopenhauer that he describes as the introduction to this work, On the Fourfold Root of the Principle of Sufficient Reason: A Philosophical Essay (x). The second thing Schopenhauer encourages to be read are the writings of Kant. Schopenhauer describes him in a glorious light, even referring to him as “the great Kant” (xii). The last thing Schopenhauer makes reference to, and which is most important for this essay, are the writings of
  • 19. Bollant 19 the Upanishads (xi-xiii). Throughout this master work, Schopenhauer will draw connections between the ideas of Kant and the ideas of Vedanta philosophy. Schopenhauer’s influence from Eastern philosophy is clear and self-proposed, and his own insistence upon suffering unto resignation is starkly locatable. In fact, the conclusion of his master work is essentially affirming asceticism through denial of the will. The reason for these prerequisites is that Schopenhauer is going to marry the philosophies of Kant and the Upanishads together into his own philosophy. John David Ebert gives a summary of this work, The World as Will and Representation, and describes this marriage. Ebert describes how Schopenhauer used Kant's philosophy of the noumenal world and the phenomenal world5 , and proposed a relationship between them and the Upanishad philosophies of Maya and Brahma. Together, these philosophies influenced Schopenhauer's own idea: that all things existed in a cosmic will-to-live (“On Nietzsche's Birth of Tragedy 1/3”). Schopenhauer's cosmic will-to-live essentially can be described as a cognitive apparatus that consumes all of nature. Space, time, and causality determine all of existence, and even animals have the presuppositional understanding for how to interpret reality. The only separation between human beings and animals is their cognitive function for reason. Humans can reason, which to Schopenhauer is merely abstractions upon the cognitive apparatus that interprets reality. Ebert describes Schopenhauer's philosophy of ideas as, “the metaphysical substratum by means of which the will pours itself forth and manifests itself in space and time” (John David Ebert on Nietzsche's Birth of Tragedy 2/3). Most important to this essay is Schopenhauer's ascetic freedom from the will. Since the will is constantly driving both humans and animals, the whole world is in never-ending 5 These terns are initially introduced in Kant's Critique of Pure Reason. For simple explanations of these terms see alternate sources.
  • 20. Bollant 20 enslavement to the will. The only lasting freedom from it is by means of asceticism, or denial of the will. From Schopenhauer's own words: We therefore find in the lives of saintly persons that peace and bliss we have described, only as the blossom resulting from the constant overcoming of the will; and we see the constant struggle with the will-to-live as the soil from which it shoots up; for on earth no one can have lasting peace . . . Therefore we see also those who have once attained to the denial of the will, strive with all their might to keep to this path by self-imposed renunciation of every kind, by a penitent and hard life . . . Indeed, we may assume that most men can reach it only in this way, and that it is the suffering personally felt, not the suffering merely known, which most frequently produces complete resignation, often only at the approach of death. (World as Will and Idea I 506-507) Schopenhauer, in this statement, is affirming my thesis. To summarize according to Schopenhauer's philosophy leading up to this quote, everything is will. Will is a presuppositional cognitive interpretation of reality. To will is to suffer. Willing must inevitably lead to desire, and any unfulfilled desire is suffering. Therefore, the lasting escape from suffering is to deny the will. In the quote above, Schopenhauer states that the only lasting freedom from suffering is to deny the will, and that those who have attained such a denial, strive with everything to maintain “self- imposed renunciation.” And finally, Schopenhauer affirms my thesis by stating the pathway to complete resignation is “by a penitent and hard life” through suffering unto resignation. “If I were to take the results of my philosophy as the standard of truth, I would have to consider Buddhism the finest of all religion” (The World as Will and Representation II 186). Schopenhauer himself had clear Eastern influences and He traced his own ideas to Eastern
  • 21. Bollant 21 influence. He found certain schools of Indian philosophy to nearly reflect his originally Western philosophy. Most importantly, it is necessary to recognize that no matter how much Schopenhauer's philosophy might have strayed from Eastern thought, the purpose of suffering as a pathway to resignation is cemented in both his ideas and in Eastern Buddhist philosophies from which he derived his own philosophy. The Upanishads were old philosophies that Schopenhauer relied upon, and these ideas were forged from many ascetic practices. The practice of yoga was inspired by the idea that austerity killed sin. This view of such practices was embedded in Brahamic religion in the Upanishads, and it gained a prominent role in the practices of the Yogas and the Jainas. According to Jainism, liberation is only possible when all passion has been exterminated, and a key pathway to that extermination is through suffering. ("Religious Asceticism"). Suffering unto resignation is an easily recognizable idea in the philosophies and practices of many Eastern religions, and especially in those which Schopenhauer relied upon. It is here that the argument finds its rest. Insistence upon suffering unto resignation has been traced through the philosophies of Nietzsche and Schopenhauer and into Eastern thought. Nietzsche insisted upon it both in his understanding of an ascetic priest and in his own ascetic ideal, the ubermensch. Schopenhauer heavily insisted upon it, and he noted that it was a derivative of Eastern philosophy. His master work concluded this, and in it he clearly stated the pathway to such resignation. On the part of Nietzsche and Schopenhauer, this thesis is largely complete. Due to the nature of Nietzsche's contradictory writings, the argument for his insistence upon suffering unto resignation cannot be taken much further. On the part of Schopenhauer, it is obvious that it is not
  • 22. Bollant 22 necessary to take it further. However, further extension of this idea in the area of Eastern philosophy would not be unmerited. The origin of the ascetic idea could potentially be traced to specific Eastern ideologies, and this evidence could solidify Nietzsche's original influence by Schopenhauer and his Eastern philosophies. It is most important to recognize the immediate influences on Nietzsche and the fact that Schopenhauer's influence over him never died. As mentioned earlier, Paul Deussen was a lifelong friend of Nietzsche's, and no monograph on their relationship is in existence. Such a monograph could have importance in tracing this idea and similar ideas to Eastern thought as well. Furthermore, Paul Deussen could potentially be traced to significant Eastern Philosophical influences upon Nietzsche. In conclusion, Nietzsche insisted upon suffering unto resignation. He espoused this in his own works, and is shown through his philosophy. Nietzsche had significant connections to Buddhism, and this stepping stone provides the path to describing his Eastern influences. This path, however, is mainly through the influence of Schopenhauer. The German philosopher clearly stated his own connections to Eastern thought in his philosophy. Most importantly, Schopenhauer established his own insistence upon suffering unto resignation, and its origins in Eastern thought. Eastern thought affirms the truth that the idea can be expressly found within its philosophies. Therefore, it is sufficient to say that the idea of insistence upon suffering unto resignation is traceable from Nietzsche to the Upanishads through Schopenhauer.
  • 23. Bollant 23 Bibliography "Forms of Religious Asceticism." Encyclopedia Britannica Online. Encyclopedia Britannica, n.d. Web. 28 Apr. 2015. "Human All Too Human, Part 1: Beyond Good and Evil - Friedrich Nietzsche". Streaming Media. University of Southampton. 1999. "The first of a three-part documentary series on philosophers whose work explored the nature of human freedom beginning with Friedrich Nietzsche" "Nietzsche and Buddhism." Journal of the History of Ideas 44.4 (1983): 671-86. JSTOR [JSTOR]. Web. 27 Apr. 2015 Abelsen, Peter. "Schopenhauer and Buddhism." Philosophy East & West 43.2 (1993): 255-78. JSTOR [JSTOR]. Web. 28 Apr. 2015. Dolson, Grace N. "The Influence of Schopenhauer upon Friedrich Nietzsche."The Philosophical Review 10.3 (1901): 241-50. JSTOR [JSTOR]. Web. 27 Apr. 2015 Frankl, Viktor Emil. The Doctor and the Soul: From Psychotherapy to Logotherapy. New York: Vintage, 1986. Print. Hillesheim, J. W., and Malcolm R. Simpson. Schopenhauer as Educator. Southbed, IN: Gateway, 1965. Print. Jaspers, Karl. Nietzsche: An Introduction to the Understanding of His Philosophical Activity. Tucson, AZ: U of Arizona, 1965. Print. John D. Ebert. “John David Ebert on Nietzsche's Birth of Tragedy 1/3.” YouTube. John David Ebert Channel, 20 Oct. 2011. Web. 28 Apr. 2015. John D. Ebert. “John David Ebert on Nietzsche's Birth of Tragedy 2/3.” YouTube. John David
  • 24. Bollant 24 Ebert Channel, 20 Oct. 2011. Web. 28 Apr. 2015. John D. Ebert. “John David Ebert on Nietzsche's Birth of Tragedy 3/3.YouTube.” John David Ebert Channel, 20 Oct. 2011. Web. 28 Apr. 2015. Kaufmann, Walter Arnold. Nietzsche, Philosopher, Psychologist, Antichrist. Princeton, NJ: Princeton UP, 1974. Print. Kierkegaard, Soren. Fear and Trembling and the Sickness Unto Death. Trans. Walter Lowrie. Princeton, NJ: Princeton UP, 1941. Print. Leiter, Brian. Routledge Philosophy Guidebook to Nietzsche on Morality. London: Routledge, 2002. Print. Melchert, Norman.The Great Conversation: A Historical Introduction to Philosophy. 5th ed. New York: Oxford UP, 2007. Print. Basic Buddhist Concepts. Tokyo: Kosei Pub., 1987. Print. Nietzsche, Friedrich Wilhelm. The Antichrist: A Criticism of Christianity. Trans. Anthony M. Ludovici. New York: Barnes and Noble, 2006. Print. Nietzsche, Friedrich Wilhelm. The Birth of Tragedy, and the Case of Wagner. Trans. Walter Kaufmann. New York: Vintage, 1967. Print. Nietzsche, Friedrich Wilhelm. Ecce Homo. Trans. W. Kaufmann. New York: Vintage, 1990. Nietzsche, Friedrich Wilhelm. The Gay Science. Trans. Walter Arnold Kaufmann. New York: Vintage, 1974. Print. Nietzsche, Friedrich Wilhelm. The Will to Power. Ed. Walter Arnold Kaufmann. Trans. R. J. Hollingdale. New York: Vintage, 1967. Print.
  • 25. Bollant 25 Nietzsche, Friedrich Wilhelm. Thus Spake Zarathustra. Trans. Thomas Common. New York: Modern Library, n.d. Print. Nietzsche, Friedrich Wilhelm. Twilight of the Idols ; And, the Anti-Christ. Trans. R. J. Hollingdale. London, England: Penguin, 1990. Print. Nietzsche, Friedrich. On the Genealogy of Morals. In Basic Writings of Nietzsche. Tanslated and Ed. Walter Kaufman. The Modern Library, New York, 1992. Reyburn, H. A., H. E. Hinderks, and James Garden Taylor. Nietzsche; the Story of a Human Philosopher. London: Macmillan, 1948. Print. Rollman, Hans. "Deussen, Nietzsche, and Vendanta." Journal of the History of Ideas 39.1 (1978): 125-32. JSTOR [JSTOR]. Web. 27 Apr. 2015 Schopenhauer, Arthur. Die Welt als Wille und Vorstellung II (Erganzungsband), Schopenhauer Samtliche Werke. Trans. Peter Abelsen. Vol. 2. Munchen: Piper Verlag, 1911. Print. Schopenhauer, Arthur. The World as Will and Idea I. Trans. R. B. Haldane Haldane and J. Kemp. Vol. 1. Boston: Ticknor, 1888. Print. Welbon, Guy R. Buddhist Nirvana and Its Western Interpreters. Chicago: U of Chicago, 1968. Print. Wilkens, Steven, and Alan G. Padgett. Christianity and Western Thought: A History of Philosophers, Ideas and Movements. Leicester: Inter-Varsity, 2000. Print Williams, Bernard Arthur Owen. Nietzsche: The Gay Science. Trans. Josefine Nauckhoff. Cambridge: Cambridge UP, 2001. Print.
  • 26. Bollant 26 Wrisley, George. Nietzsche and the Value of Human Suffering - Two Alternative Ideals. George Wrisley. Web.