SlideShare a Scribd company logo
1 of 13
Download to read offline
A Rights-Based Model of Governance: 
The Case of Human Enhancement and the 
Role of Ethics in Europe 
Daniele RUGGIU 
CIGA, University of Padova 
Abstract: In Europe, the current model of governance is characterized by the cen-trality 
of ethics, which has led (at national and supranational levels) to both the in-stitutionalization 
of ethics (the bureaucratic expression of ethics) and to the 
‘ethicization of technoscience’ (the tendency to frame the governance of emerging 
technologies in ethical terms). This model is unique in the world and, due to the 
overlapping of the above-mentioned phenomena, has generated a process of blur-ring 
the boundary between ethics and law, which weakens the action of the regula-tory 
and ethical tools of governance, especially with regard to human rights. The 
analysis of the case of human enhancement, with particular regard to stem cell re-search, 
shows instead how a clearer distinction of the role and functions of ethics 
and law, as well as the development of mechanisms of self-coordination, can 
strengthen the current model of governance as a rights-oriented one.1 
Keywords: Models of governance; enhancement technologies; metagovernance; 
human rights; ethics. 
Introduction 
The current development of technology and scientific research may give rise to several 
applications on human beings. In this context, emerging technologies can further foster 
the applications on human beings and pave the way for new and incisive research to-wards 
human enhancement (HE).2 Thanks to emerging technologies, HE can be more 
effective and represent a concrete challenge for present societies, also in Europe. Scien-tists 
of the Northwestern University Feinberg School of Medicine, for instance, re-cently 
created a brain-synthesized estrogen that influences the synaptic structure, 
function and cognitive processes by augmenting the networks among neurons (Svriva-stava 
et al. 2010). Thus it could be a case of future brain-doping. The use of emerging 
1 This work was done with the support of the European Commission FP7 Science in Society funded 
project, ‘Ethics in Public Policy Making: The Case of Human Enhancement’ (EPOCH), grant number 
SIS-CT-2010-266660, http://epochproject.com. The views expressed in this article are the sole respon-sibility 
of the author and do not reflect the opinion of the European Commission or of any partner of the 
project. 
2 For HE I refer to any “modification aimed at improving individual human performance and brought 
about by science-based or technology-based interventions in the human body”. As it has been under-lined, 
this definition includes “strong”, “second-stage” forms of human enhancement with long-term ef-fective 
or permanent results (e.g., genetic enhancements and invasive brain-computer interfaces) as well 
as “temporary” enhancements (e.g. alleged ”pharmacological cognitive enhancers” with low addiction 
potential or none at all”). See http://epochproject.com.
104 A Rights-Based Model of Governance 
technologies can also meliorate the biological defense mechanisms of the human body. 
With synthetic biology, it could be possible to create beneficial bacterial infections 
programmed to augment immunity, or even synth-cells engineered to circulate in the 
body to extend the human immune system, making the human body resistant to normal 
illness and infections. The potential of synthetic biology might also lead to inserting 
artificial chromosomes in the genome of complex organisms, including humans, open-ing 
the door to the gene-enhancement (EGE 2010, 23). The field of nanotechnology 
offers new opportunities by designing artificial muscles (Shahinpoor 2011) or contact 
lens that can lead us toward augmented reality, a dimension where we can experience 
material reality and immersive computer data simultaneously (Lengley and Parviz 
2008). Nanotechnology, synthetic biology, and stem cell research can concretely boost 
the possible applications of HE both for healthy and disabled people. In this context we 
should wonder whether the structures of technological governance we built in Europe 
are capable to face the societal changes that HE entails. 
The model of governance, affirmed in Europe over the last thirty years in the con-text 
of both biotechnologies (Busby et al. 2008) and nanotechnologies (Ruggiu 2012b), 
shows the centrality of ethics and its participative character. This relevance of ethics 
can be observed even in the field of the enhancement technologies, such as in the case 
of stem cell research. The role assumed by ethics in Europe implies several phenomena 
such as the ‘institutionalization of ethics’ (Tallacchini 2009), the ‘ethicization of tech-noscience’ 
(MASIS 2009, 32, 38) and the tendency of ethics to incorporate legal tools 
by blurring boundaries between law and ethics (Plomer 2008). These phenomena are 
tightly intertwined and the last one, in particular, involves human rights that can play a 
relevant part in face of HE through two clashing principles: personal dignity and au-tonomy. 
In this chapter, I will provide a rights-based model of governance and I will 
argue that governance can be more effective only if we build mechanisms of coordina-tion 
among all governmental tools, both regulatory and ethical. In this regard, the phe-nomenon 
of the ‘ethicization of technoscience’, with its blurring of ethical and legal 
norms, risks weakening the efficacy of human rights in the governance of emerging 
technologies, especially enhancement technologies. Therefore, I will conclude that a 
clear division of roles, functions, and structures of law and ethics could strengthen both 
the human rights penetration into the grammar of the EU governance and the efficacy 
of technological governance itself. 
1. Governance and Metagovernance 
By governance I mean the ensemble of processes with reticular character, diffuse 
among public and private actors both at national and supranational levels made up by 
norms of soft and hard law, somehow coordinated and aimed to solve conflicts and to 
make decisions in a particular technological, economic, or financial field (Ruggiu 
2012b, 156).3 Scholars increasingly distinguish the concept of governance from that of 
metagovernance. Metagovernance refers to the organizations, structures, and processes 
that produce (the conditions of) governance (Jessop 2003) through the arrangement of 
normative tools (of legal, ethical, technical nature). At the metagovernance level, the 
relations among organizations and governance structures are characterized by heter- 
3 On governance, with special attention to the ‘new governance turn’, see Stokes 1998; Scott and Tru-beck 
2002; Lyall and Tait 2005; with regard to emerging technologies, see Roco 2006.
A Rights-Based Model of Governance 105 
archy instead of a kind of framing of hierarchical type. This fact deprives the processes 
of governance of a centre that can determine all relations of the system, giving a merely 
eccentric and diffuse character. In this regard the governance appears de facto distri-buted 
among several subjects and, thus, to be effective any model of governance should 
be able to involve a wide range of stakeholders (Stokes 1998; Pariotti and Ruggiu 
2012). Consider the role of transnational corporations, or the action of NGOs within the 
worldwide governance (Pariotti 2007; 2013), or, again, the increasing importance of 
organs without legislative power but absolutely central in Europe, such as ethical 
committees especially at the Community level (Salter and Jones 2002). 
In this context we can distinguish the formalized structures and processes produc-ing 
governance from the informal ones. Those of the first type encompass the soft and 
hard law instruments such as EU directives, recommendations, self-regulatory tools 
(including codes of conduct), third-party certification systems that can nevertheless 
have legal effects, and human rights. Those of the second type can be, for example, 
reports and opinions of ethical advisory boards (EABs) such as the EGE, internal 
documents of corporations without any legal effect, or acts of NGOs that might influ-ence 
policy making. In other words, the first category of governance structures and 
processes, with respect to formal procedures and norms of competence, produces legal 
norms with binding force (hard law norms) or legal norms without binding force but 
capable of having legal effects (soft law norms); the latter category produces norms 
(moral, technical etc.) without any legal effects but capable of influencing decision-making 
processes. 
In the great puzzle of governance, any tool, even EU directives and resolutions, 
represents only a piece of the whole framework and coexists with a plurality of diverse 
tools with different goals and scope. Thus, to assess the pros and cons of a model, we 
need to enlarge our sight. In this chapter, I will focus on only two kinds of tools that are 
tightly intertwined—human rights and the ethical advisements of EGE—and their 
interplay with regard to HE. 
2. A Legal Analysis of Human Rights 
As a small piece of the picture of governance, human rights can represent a governance 
tool in two ways. Due to their dual nature as both moral and legal, they are referred to 
by legal documents on human rights and by acts of EABs (especially at supranational 
level).4 From the legal standpoint, human rights are considered by the documents of 
hard and soft law (for example, the European Convention of Human Rights or ECHR5, 
the Oviedo Convention6, and the EU Charter7), and, in this latter instance, especially by 
4 Human rights can be considered both as legal rights and as moral rights. In the Anglo-Saxon world, 
their consideration as moral rights prevails (e.g. Raz 2010; Brownsword 2008), whereas in continental 
Europe, their consideration as legal rights is consolidated (e.g. Jacobs et al. 2002; Bultrini 2004). These 
two perspectives are rooted in the different constitutional traditions characterizing the old continent. In 
this chapter, I will consider both perspectives as legitimate; but I will produce some brief arguments in 
favor of the legal consideration of human rights. 
5 Council of Europe, Convention for the Protection on Human Rights and Fundamental Freedoms 
(ECHR) (CETS n. 5), adopted in Rome on November 11, 1950 (entered into force on September 3, 
1953). 
6 Council of Europe, Convention for the Protection of Human Rights and Dignity of the Human Being 
with regard to the Application of Biology and Medicine (Convention on Human Rights and Biomedicine
106 A Rights-Based Model of Governance 
self-regulatory documents (codes of conduct, guidelines, and so forth). In order to ex-press 
their legal dimension, I will use the following definition: human rights are those 
rights recognized by the international law rules listed in documents like the Universal 
Declaration, the Covenants of '66, and the ECHR pertaining to individuals, groups and 
associations against the state and enforceable in the face of judicial or quasi-judicial 
organs at a supranational level (the European Court of Human Rights or ECtHR, UN 
committees on human rights) (Ruggiu 2012a, 337 n. 4; 2012b, 7 n. 1). This definition 
sees the normativity of human rights as the result of legal texts (e.g. the ECHR) and the 
supranational courts case law (e.g. the ECtHR decisions) and permits human rights to 
have both a definite semantic content (e.g. what autonomy means) and a concrete effi-cacy 
(i.e. any violation is punished). In this regard, despite the common opinion that 
sees human rights as indeterminate norms (MacIntyre 1981), thanks to the case law of 
the two main European courts (the ECtHR and the Court of Justice of the EU or CJEU), 
their semantic content (their meaning) is determinate and complete, at any rate in Eu-rope 
where there are binding treaties on human rights (the ECHR), as well as an effec-tive 
system of enforcement able to punish a state’s human rights violations (the 
ECtHR) and to offer a wide set of decisions in several fields, with regard to scientific 
and technological developments (Ruggiu 2012b). 
In Europe, there are two competing systems of protection of human rights that con-tribute 
to their enforcement: that of the Council of Europe and that provided by EU 
(Bultrini 2004). These two protection systems are centred around a couple of hard law 
instruments (the ECHR with regard to the Council of Europe and the EU Charter) and 
around the activity of two supranational judicial organs (the ECtHR and the CJEU), 
which create an efficient and self-coordinated mechanism of enforcement able to 
strengthen the respect of human rights in the old continent (Spielmann 1999; Bultrini 
2004).8 In the case of HE, where we could face (and we actually face) permanent or 
temporary modifications of the human body, there are two key aspects, in addition to 
the general theme of the protection of the individual good of health (the right to health): 
the possibility to exert individual consent to treatment (the self-determination principle), 
and the protection of human nature, which belongs to every individual (human dignity). 
2.1. Human Dignity 
In a context characterized by the intertwining of a plurality of actors, jurisprudence is 
per se a governance factor, alongside the academic world, which is so engaged within 
the ethical reflection on the implications of technological development. This conclusion 
is true especially with regard to HE. Indeed, in this field we find some decisions of the 
European courts of capital importance that will affect the governance of enhancement 
technologies in future, especially with regard to personal dignity and stem cell research. 
or the Oviedo Convention) (CETS n. 164), adopted in Oviedo on April 4, 1997 (entered into force on 
December 1, 1999). 
7 The Charter of Fundamental Rights of the European Union, adopted in Nice on December 7, 2000. 
8 Nevertheless, human rights and fundamental rights of the EU cannot be deemed as coincident since 
they differ for content (there are some Community rights, such as freedom of research, that are not also 
human rights in the ECHR), structure (fundamental rights are balanceable with other public interests of 
the EU, such as free circulation of goods that can predominate) and trait (human dignity is an autono-mous 
right, whilst personal dignity is the basic value supporting the whole human rights architecture), 
the spontaneous mechanism of self-coordination between the two courts represents a resource for hu-man 
rights themselves (Pariotti and Ruggiu 2012).
A Rights-Based Model of Governance 107 
When the human being is handled as a means and not as an end, human dignity 
may be called in question (Jacobson 2007, 293, 298). Within human rights law, human 
dignity is the most pregnant with ethical significance among the other legal concepts 
(Andorno 2009). This makes hard to give it a legal meaning. Dignity is recalled by 
several documents at a supranational (e.g. the Universal Declaration on Human Rights9, 
the Oviedo Convention, the EU Charter etc.) and a national level (e.g. the German 
Constitution) (Francioni 2007; Jacobson 2007). 
From the legal standpoint we can distinguish two basic conceptions of dignity: one 
conceives dignity as the hidden concept, the architrave, of the whole of human rights 
law, being implied in several rights and freedoms (Andorno 2009; Jacobson 2007, 
296); the latter interprets it as a right as such, which can be exercised by individuals or 
groups in the face of violations of human dignity (EGE 2000). The first model is proper 
to the Universal Declaration, the International Covenants of the 1966, and above all 
the system of the ECHR of the Council of Europe, which, paradoxically, does not men-tion 
it, not even in its preamble (Beyleveld and Brownsword 2004, 12).10 In this in-stance, 
individual dignity is protected directly by the state, which arrogates the power 
of making the trade-off among the opposite interests on behalf of the entire community, 
or indirectly by individuals that claim the protection of other freedoms and rights 
(mainly personal integrity, equality, and prohibition of inhuman, degrading treatments). 
Here, in this latter instance, dignity maintains the right structure (with an individual as 
right holder and a subject responsible for its protection, i.e. the state) but having a 
merely accessory character of the other rights. Thus, its legal content is nearly empty 
since the case law is too limited in this matter. Instead, in the first instance dignity has 
no right structure (no individual can claim it) and it is a mere public interest protected 
by the state and, in this sense, it might conflict with other individual interests that can 
be recognized as legal rights (e.g. autonomy). In order to build dignity as an ‘autono-mous 
(individual) right’ we could only resort to another model. This latter model, in-deed, 
is typical of the EU Charter where human dignity is affirmed as an autonomous 
right, and, as a right, it is protected by the CJEU jurisprudence. Here, the right holders 
are groups or associations that exercise the right of petition against the state in front of 
the court on behalf of the community. 
What is meaningful is that the jurisprudence of the CJEU on personal dignity is 
fundamental especially with regard to HE. Extremely relevant is, in fact, the Brüstle 
Case of the CJEU, because it has provided a definition of human embryo and deter-mined 
the conditions of patentability of some uses of human embryos.11 In 1997, Mr. 
Oliver Brüstle, a stem cell researcher, filed a patent related to isolated and purified 
neural progenitor cells for the treatment of neural defects. The transplantation of brain 
cells into the nervous system can be a promising method of treatment for numerous 
neurological diseases. The same techniques could be used also in brain enhancement. 
Greenpeace filed an appeal before the Bundespatentgericht (the Federal Patent Court in 
Germany) seeking a ruling of invalidity of the above-mentioned patent. The Bundes-patentgericht 
decided to stay the proceeding and to refer the question of stem cells 
patentability to the CJEU. First of all, lacking a uniform definition of human embryo, 
9 The Universal Declaration on Human Rights (UDHR) adopted in New York on December 10, 1948 by 
the General Assembly of the United Nations. 
10 It is expressly embodied in the preamble of the Protocol n. 13 concerning the abolition of death penalty 
in all circumstances adopted in Vilnius on May 3, 2002. 
11 Judgment of the Court of Justice (Grand Chamber), Oliver Brüstle v. Greenpeace eV (Case C-34/10), 
18 October 2011, not yet published.
108 A Rights-Based Model of Governance 
the CJEU provided one including: a) any human ovum as soon as fertilized; b) any 
non-fertilized human ovum into which the cell nucleus from a mature human cell has 
been transplanted; c) any non-fertilized human ovum whose division and further devel-opment 
have been stimulated by parthenogenesis, including stem cells obtained from a 
human embryo at the blastocyst stage. Then, it excluded from patentability some uses 
of human embryos (with industrial, commercial purposes, or for scientific research). 
Although the aim of the scientific research must be distinguished from industrial and 
commercial purposes, the use of human embryos for purposes of scientific research 
cannot be separated from the patent itself and the rights attached to it.12 According to 
the court, techniques for producing stem cells that require the prior destruction of hu-man 
embryos are also unpatentable.13 
Outside of all those limits, the patentability of stem cells is admitted and it does 
not infringe human dignity. This decision will also act as landmark for the ECtHR 
jurisprudence, which can follow its statements in the future thanks to the process of 
self-coordination existing between the two courts. 
2.2. Self-Determination Principle 
Autonomy, and the freedom of choice, is one of the pillars of human rights law. The 
question of the limits of our personal choice in non-medical treatments is one of the 
most controversial issues at stake (Beghé-Loreti and Marin 1999), especially with re-gard 
to HE. 
In the future, thanks to emerging technologies, the opportunity to use ICT implants, 
brain-computer interface devices, or artificial limbs could be really advantageous, giv-ing 
rise to a form of ‘permanent enhancement’.14 In these cases, what will be the judi-cial 
limits of a treatment as such? It is clear that human dignity and the self-determination 
principle are in a situation of potential conflict (EGE 2000). No case has 
(obviously) yet emerged, although nowadays many practices aimed to modify the body, 
if not directly enhancing it, are already very common. 
Within liberal-democratic societies some very invasive treatments such as gender 
re-assignment surgery are widely recognised.15 Re-assignment surgery can be deemed a 
kind of ‘irreversible human enhancement’. The ECtHR, for example, recognised that 
‘there has been an unmistakable trend in the member States of the Council of Europe 
towards giving full legal recognition to gender re-assignment’.16 Within the ECHR 
system, the personal autonomy falls under the provision of Article 8 (respect of private 
life), which guarantees the personal sphere of each individual, including the right to 
12 See Brüstle case, 43. 
13 According to Goran Hermerén (2009), if a court has settled the ethical issue of the meaning and scope 
of the application of the principle of human dignity (for example, whether the destruction of the blasto-cysts 
in stem cell research is or not compatible with human dignity) that would seem to be a clear case 
of blurring normative and legal issues. There are reasons not to agree with this opinion. Indeed, with 
regard to human rights practice in Europe, it is important to bear into mind that the regulatory frame-work 
of human rights is the result of the joined work of the regulator (e.g. the Council of Europe or the 
EU) and judges (mainly the ECtHR and the CJEU). Accordingly the judges’ work is fully normative (it 
produce norms and therefore it is ‘normogenetic’), even if within the framework of rights set forth by 
the regulator (i.e. Council of Europe, EU) (Viola and Zaccaria 2001). 
14 HE can be temporary or permanent and irreversible (Allhoff et al. 2010). 
15 See Christine Goodwin v. The United Kingdom (App. 28957/95), judgment of 11 July 2002, Reports of 
Judgments and Decisions 2002-VI. 
16 See ibid., 55.
A Rights-Based Model of Governance 109 
establish details of their identity as individual human beings.17 Can such applications of 
enhancement technologies be considered forms of reshaping individual identity? This 
is the question I would like to address here. It is clear that sexual identity is a particular 
aspect of personal identity, and it is difficult to build an analogical relationship with 
other medical treatments of the human body. But the delicacy of this issue is that it has 
a societal basis, and the common consideration of what is the core of our identity is 
strictly connected to societal development. According to the ECtHR, the matter of 
gender re-assignment cannot be left to the states’ margin of appreciation. The only 
limit which the court affirmed is that the treatment, even if painful, must be not ‘arbi-trary 
or capricious’.18 In this regard we could ask whether a HE intervention, which has 
by definition no therapeutic character, falls outside or inside those limits. It is necessary 
to remember that the ECHR is interpreted ‘in the light of the present-day conditions’ 
with a strong attention to societal evolution. Here the public order and morality clauses 
could take place. The question of the choice itself to undergo to surgical treatment has 
not been directly dealt with yet. The cases that dealt with the gender re-assignment in 
the light of the non-discrimination principle presuppose the legitimacy of the choice to 
undergo surgical treatment. A currently pending case will now directly deal with this 
issue and will probably determine limits and conditions of personal choice in its wider 
meaning.19 
In sum, while the EU system of protecting fundamental rights seems to be stronger 
with regard to the matter of personal dignity, that of the Council of Europe can offer a 
higher level of protection with regard to the self-determination principle; but the cur-rent 
mechanism of self-coordination between the two courts permits integrating them in 
one efficient model (Pariotti and Ruggiu 2012). 
3. The Activity of the Ethical Advisory Boards in Europe 
In biotechnological matters, the EU has developed a model of governance whose ex-perience 
represents a benchmark in other fields, as well. In particular, within the Euro-pean 
governance of emerging technologies, ethics has taken a leading role, which has 
no equal in the world.20 This fact led to building a bureaucratic apparatus able to sup-port 
and formally include ethical reflection into EU institutions, giving rise to the phe-nomenon 
of the progressive ‘institutionalization of ethics’, namely, the integration of 
ethical reflexivity into public institutions (Talacchini 2009). Tightly connected to this, 
the phenomenon of the ‘ethicization of technoscience’, that is, the tendency to frame 
technological innovation merely in ethical terms, has been unavoidably produced 
within the Union (MASIS 2009; Pariotti 2011). I would like to show that these over-lapping 
phenomena can be a weakening element in the governance of biotechnological 
applications on human beings, in particular those that can lead towards enhancement 
technologies. 
The processes of the ‘institutionalization of ethics’ and of the ‘ethicization of tech-noscientific 
governance’ began in the 1970s and 80s when the lack of acceptable regu- 
17 See ibid., 90. 
18 See ibid., 81. 
19 Y.Y. c. Turquie (Requête no 14793/08), pending case, available at http://hudoc.echr.coe.int/sites/eng/ 
pages/search.aspx?i=001-114422 (accessed on 4 April 2013). 
20 For example, with regard to nanotechnologies, see Kearnes and Rip 2009.
110 A Rights-Based Model of Governance 
latory capacity of the European Commission led to the adoption of committees, agen-cies, 
and EABs (Busby et al. 2008). In front of the challenges of biotechnologies the 
Community authorities addressed the issues of the increasing distrust of the public on 
the European policies and the legitimacy of the decision-making processes. For this 
reason, they instituted an organ with ethical competence able to steer the innovation 
processes among the member states. This body, which aimed to foster public confi-dence, 
took the name, first, of GAIEB and, then, of EGE.21 Its role and its increasing 
influence made it a strategic pole within the EU framework and the possible target of a 
process of instrumentalisation by politics (Plomer 2008). 
The route towards a model of governance characterized by the centrality of ethics 
goes through three fundamental steps. First of all the EGE legal basis was shaped with-out 
any datum point in the treaties, augmenting de facto its autonomy, especially from 
the European Parliament. Then, the scope of its remit was enlarged and subsequently 
posed under the control of the Presidency of the European Commission, weakening 
thus the requirements of its independency from political power. Finally, the activity of 
the EAB played a part in determining the European policies in the biotechnological 
field, in particular in stem cell research, in order to forge a common European identity 
in those matters among member states. 
With regard to the first aspect it is to notice that the Union EAB has benefited from 
the lack of a clear legal basis. In fact, none of the Treaty on functioning of the Euro-pean 
Union articles that are usually recalled (Article 168 – public health, Article 169 – 
consumer protection, Article 114) refer to either GAIEB or EGE activity (Busby et al. 
2008, 837). For example, Article 168 on public health provides that the European 
Commission shall take any useful initiative to promote the coordination among mem-ber 
states, particularly initiatives aiming at the establishment of guidelines and indica-tors. 
There is no reference to any EAB such as EGE. Thus, its legal basis seems to rest 
only on the two EC Decisions of 1998 and 200022 related to its mandate and on the EC 
Decision of 2005, which directly provide the EGE remit.23 And it is astonishing that no 
article of the EU Treaties mentions a so strategic organ of the EU. This uncertainty 
reduces de facto the possibilities of control on its activity, giving the EGE and the EU 
institutions responsible for it (i.e. the President of the Commission) an extensive au-tonomy 
(Busby et al. 2008, 838). 
As the requirements of its transparency and independency were so fragile, the EGE 
remit was changed several times by enlarging tasks24, members’ competences25, and 
membership26, and by introducing tighter dependency relations with the EU institutions 
(Plomer 2008, 843-844). These changes hide the existing conflict between the Euro-pean 
Parliament and the Commission on the role and functions of a key committee of 
21 The group was instituted in 1991 with the name of Group of Advisers on the Ethical Implications of 
Biotechnology to the European Commission. In 1998, it took the name of the European Group on Eth-ics 
in Science and New Technologies (EGE). 
22 Commission Decision dated 16 December 1997 (SEC(97) 2404) creating the European Group on Ethics 
in Science and New Technologies (EGE); Commission Decision dated 26 March 2001 (C(2001) 691) 
concerning the amendment to the remit of the European Group on Ethics in Science and New Tech-nologies. 
23 Criticisms on the legal basis of the EGE are also in Plomer 2008, 853. 
24 In 1998, its mandate was modified by including the tasks of consulting and reporting back to European 
Parliament. 
25 In 1998, the disciplines of sociology and informatics were included. 
26 With this last modification, the members went from six to twelve.
A Rights-Based Model of Governance 111 
the Union. The main modification occurred with the 2000 mandate (subsequently con-firmed 
in 200527) when the EGE secretariat was integrated in the Bureau of the Euro-pean 
Policy Advisors reporting directly to the President of the Commission and acting 
under his authority. In this moment a weighty legacy, in terms of independency and 
transparency of the work of the ethical committee of EU, was created. 
When the presupposition of its action was set under the control of the Presidency 
of the Commission, the increasing influence acquired by EGE was thus tightly inter-twined 
with its vulnerability in front of improper pressures of given political lobbies. 
Leaving aside the instance of the 1998 Directive28, wherein the clause of ordre public 
has been created by following two precedent EGE opinions29, the case of the stem cell 
research is emblematic. In March 2005, an EP resolution30 intervened, calling for the 
principle of subsidiarity to be applied also to the funding of embryonic stem cell re-search, 
leaving instead to the member states the responsibility of deciding which re-search 
should be funded. Immediately after, in September 2005, some members of the 
Parliament requested in a letter that the President of the Commission should exercise 
his influence to ensure that funding for research on human embryos would not take 
place under the Seventh Framework Programme (FP7) (Plomer 2008, 847). In 2007, 
the EGE adopted the opinion n. 22 on ethical aspects of FP731, drafting a set ethical 
indications that, then, were consequently included in the FP7. Accordingly, the FP7 
prescribed that the research funded should comply with the fundamental ethical princi-ples 
as reflected in the Charter of fundamental rights of the EU (Plomer 2008, 850)32, 
taking, then, into account also the opinions of the EGE nearby the other sources of law. 
Thus legal and ethical norms contribute de facto directly to the EU regulation.33 Ac-cording 
to FP7 the research aiming at the cloning for reproductive purposes, those 
intending to modify the genetic heritage of human beings, those intending to create 
human embryos solely for the purpose of research or for the purpose of stem cell pro-curement, 
including by means of somatic cell nuclear transfer, should not be funded. 
Moreover, in regard to the derivation of human embryonic stem cells, institutions, 
organizations, and researchers are subject to strict licensing and control by members 
states involved. Thus, the ethical control was further implemented by the legal frame-work 
of the member states. 
27 Commission Decision dated 11 May 2005 (2005/383/EC) on the renewal of the mandate of the Euro-pean 
Group on Ethics in Science and New Technologies. 
28 Article 37 of Directive 98/44 on the legal protection of biotechnological inventions [1998] OJ L213/13 
excludes from patentability those inventions ‘where their commercial exploitation offends ordre public 
or morality’. 
29 Opinion n° 3 - 30/09/1993 - Opinion on ethical questions arising from the Commission proposal for a 
Council directive for legal protection of biotechnological inventions; opinion n° 8 - 25/09/1996 - Ethi-cal 
aspects of patenting inventions involving elements of human origin. See Busby, Hervey, and Mohr 
2008. 
30 Resolution of the European Parliament on the trade in of human egg cells RC B6-0199/2005 of 10 
March 2005, para. 10. 
31 Opinion n° 22 - 13/07/2007 – Recommendation on the ethical review of hESC FP7 research projects. 
32 See also Opinion n° 22, II.4.2. 
33 With regard to an analogous influence of EGE on FP5, see Salter and Jones 2002, 812.
112 A Rights-Based Model of Governance 
4. The Blurring of Ethics and Law 
The process of shaping and designing the current scientific and technological develop-ments 
in ethical terms made the EGE a decisive tool of allocating research funding, 
giving it an extraordinary political power under the sole control of the President of the 
Commission. This strategic role assumed by ethics at the Community level has in-creased 
by the tendency of blurring ethical and legal matters (Plomer 2008, 845-846; 
Mohr et al. 2012, 106). The beginning of the process of blurring of ethics and law can 
be located in the opinion n° 8 wherein GAIEB draws the concept of ‘ethics’ widely, 
including technical legal concerns. Indeed, with regard to the question of the patent-ability 
of human gene sequences, it added to the legal reasons of non-patentability 
some ethical concerns relating the non-commercialization of the human body (Busby et 
al. 2008, 812). The above-mentioned Directive 98/44 with its ordre public clause is, in 
this framework, a clear sign of this process. This phenomenon is also enlarged by the 
semantic structuring of the EGE opinions that may contain a mixture of ethical and 
legal principles in a variety of sources (both at regional and universal level) often with-out 
detailed analysis of their legal status, contents, attending jurisprudence, and critical 
literature (Plomer 2008, 845-846). 
This approach, which makes human rights balanceable with other pubic interests 
of the state, appears questionable from the standpoint of the human rights law.34 In this 
regard, an example could be the opinion n° 20 on ICT implants35, where the ethical 
principles to be considered are drawn from legal texts of international law mixing hu-man 
rights (freedom, equality, privacy etc.), basic concepts of human rights law (dig-nity), 
and other legal principles of international law (precautionary principle), 
considered indifferently at the same level without any study of their ethical background, 
attending jurisprudence, and implications.36 An analogous tendency can be also seen in 
its opinion on nanomedicine, which appears more mature but with the same confusion 
between ethical and legal fields.37 This weakness in framing the texture of its opinions 
also risks blurring the roles of ethics and law, whereas they should be distinct to be 
more efficacious. 
This phenomenon leads progressively to imposing ethics as a parallel source of 
law within the EU, weakening the efficacy of the regulatory tools and eroding the base 
of the public trust. In this regard, the ‘ethicization’ phenomenon risks compromising 
the participatory characteristic of EU governance. In this framework, human rights see 
their forces ineffectively dispersed while they could be used differently, inasmuch as 
they are a strong pole of motivation. No content, except that given by the ethical reflec-tion, 
can be found in them. They are semantically empty and therefore only ethics can 
fill them. The action of the European courts on human rights is, in this conceptual 
34 In fact, within the ECHR human rights are derogable only in time of war and other public emergence 
(Article 15) and can be restricted only in the cases permitted by the Convention (Article 18). 
35 Opinion n° 20 - 16/03/2005 - Ethical aspects of ICT Implants in the Human Body. A different approach 
we can find in its Draft Charter on Fundamental Rights of European Union, Brussels, June 15, 2000, 
available at http://www.europarl.europa.eu/charter/civil/pdf/con233_en.pdf [accessed May 17, 2012]. In 
this document, the ethical implication of the legal shaping of the rights of the EU is considered with at-tention. 
36 Ibid., para. 4: Legal background. On this criticism, see Plomer 2008, 845-846. On the contrary, an 
excellent examination of fundamental rights from the legal standpoint can be found in the EGE’s draft 
of the EU Charter. See EGE 2000. 
37 Opinion n° 21 - 17/01/2007 - Ethical aspects of nanomedicine.
A Rights-Based Model of Governance 113 
framework, only a sign that, from the legal standpoint, would have no sense (i.e. it is 
totally discretional). Their normativity is reduced only to the texts affirming them and, 
therefore, separated from their practice and application, human rights are completely 
indeterminate (MacIntyre 1981). What does human dignity mean? Only ethics can say, 
not the law. Enclosed into mere ethical reflection, human rights lose the possibility of 
affecting the European governance with the strength of individuals’ positions and inter-ests, 
becoming a mere moral argument of an opaque (and unfortunately weak) rhetoric 
(Ruggiu 2012b, 172).38 
Conclusions 
The model of governance of the EU has elected ethics as the engine for boosting inno-vation 
(Kearnes and Rip 2009). The virtue of ethics should permit, in fact, thanks to its 
elasticity, facing the challenges of innovation on a case-by-case basis and involving 
more stakeholders in the governance processes, augmenting its efficacy. Yet instead, 
this fact weakens the efficacy of some regulatory instruments such as human rights, by 
empting them and letting them being absorbed into ethical reflexivity. This overflow-ing 
role is also witnessed by the process of blurring of ethics and law that characterizes 
the EGE activity (Plomer 2008). In the current model, we can notice that there are 
already antibodies to face these impairments. In fact, within the EU model there are 
some principles that anticipate the choices of decision makers. Those principles are the 
fundamental rights and they correspond substantially to human rights. They are largely 
implemented by some regulatory texts (e.g. the EU Charter and the ECHR) and the 
jurisprudence that is, at the metagovernance level, an actor operating in the framework 
of other governmental structures. 
Fundamental rights work as ‘normative anchor points’ by setting in advance the 
goals on which governance should be inspired (von Schomberg 2011; 2013). In other 
words, they work in an anticipatory dimension within European governance. With the 
entry into force of the EU Charter in the beginning of 2010, these ‘anchor points’ have 
acquired binding force and have become the ‘polar star’ of the EU governance. They 
are present both in the hard law instruments (i.e. the EU Charter as implemented by the 
CJEU) and in the soft law instruments (e.g. declarations, recommendations, the codes 
of conduct, guidelines, and so forth) and they also contribute to involving stakeholders 
(Pariotti and Ruggiu 2012). They are the fulcrum of this participatory model that, in-deed, 
uses them to shape both soft law and self-regulatory tools of governance (mainly 
guidelines and codes of conduct). In this context, the mechanism of self-coordination 
between the Council of Europe judicial body (i.e. the Strasbourg Court) and that of the 
EU (i.e. the CJEU) can help to strengthen the effective penetration of fundamental 
rights into EU law (Spielmann 1999; Bultrini 2004), especially with regard to emerging 
technologies aimed at HE wherein the pros and cons of the two systems are equivalent 
(Pariotti and Ruggiu 2012, 162). It is the case with personal dignity and the self-determination 
principle, which have great importance in the discourse on HE. 
38 An example of this rhetorical use of human rights can be seen in the EU code of conduct for responsible 
nanosciences and nanotechnologies research, wherein human rights are referred to only in generic man-ner, 
as a whole (e.g. point 4.1.17 of the guidelines), without focusing the specific individual positions 
singularly affected by technological development (e.g. the right to health, self-determination principle, 
integrity, and so forth). See Ruggiu 2012b, 170.
114 A Rights-Based Model of Governance 
For this reason, within the great puzzle of European governance, ethical tools 
should also address the interconnections existing in the composite framework that con-tributes 
to producing the whole system of governance. In this framework, human rights 
are certainly interesting tools that will play an increasing role within European govern-ance, 
and, in part, also thanks to the jurisprudence of the main two European courts (i.e. 
ECtHR and CJEU), they are already doing so. But they need to be correctly framed, 
alongside ethics, in order to avoid any overlapping between the two fields. A clearer 
vision of the roles and functions of law and ethics could empower the respective tools 
and would permit the development of a model of governance more coordinated and 
aware of the productive dimension of human rights in building governance in Europe. 
In other words, this model, already implemented by existing regulation in Europe, in 
the EU and in the Council of Europe, is the rights-based model of governance. 
References 
Allhoff, F., Lin, P., Moor, J. and Weckert, J. (2010) ‘Ethics of Human Enhancement: 25 Questions & An-swers’, 
Studies in Ethics, Law, and Technology 4 (1): 1-39. 
Andorno, R. (2009) ‘Human Dignity and Human Rights as a Common Ground of Bioethics’, Journal of 
Medicine and Philosophy, 34(3): 223-240. 
Beghé-Loreti, A. and Marin, L. (1999) ‘La tutela della persona umana nella sperimentazione clinica dei 
farmaci e il ruolo dei comitati etici tra regole internazionali di disciplina e normativa italiana’, Rivista 
internazionale dei diritti dell’uomo. Atti del Seminario internazionale Diritti dell’uomo e profili etnico-religiosi: 
una prospettiva globale (Milano, 3-4, dicembre 1998) 12: 641-675. 
Beyleveld, D. and Brownsword, R. (2004) Human Dignity in Bioethics and Biolaw, Oxford: Oxford Univer-sity 
Press. 
Brownsword, R. (2008) Rights, Regulation and the Technological Revolution, Oxford: Oxford University 
Press. 
Bultrini, A. (2004) La pluralità dei meccanismi di tutela dei diritti dell’uomo in Europa. Torino: Giappichelli. 
Busby, H., Hervey, T. and Mohr, A. (2008) ‘Ethical EU Law ? The Influence of the European Group on 
Ethics in Science and Technologies’, European Law Review 33: 803-832 
Francioni, F. (2007) ‘Genetic Resources, Biotechnology and Human Rights’. In F. Francioni (ed.) Biotech-nologies 
and International Human Rights, Oxford: Hart Publishing. 
EGE (2000) Citizens’ Rights and New Technologies: A European Challenge. Report of the European Group 
on Ethics in Sciences and New Technologies on the Charter on Fundamental Rights Related to Techno-logical 
Innovation as Requested by President Prodi on February 3, 2000, Brussels, May 23, 2000. 
Available at: http://www.europarl.europa.eu/charter/civil/pdf/con233_en.pdf (accessed August 28, 
2013). 
EGE (2009) Ethics of Synthetic Biology, Opinion n° 25, Brussels, 17 November 2009. Available at http://ec. 
europa.eu/bepa/european-group-ethics/docs/opinion25_en.pdf. 
Hermerén, G. (2009) Accountability, Democracy and Ethics Committee, Law, Innovation and Technology 
1(2): 153-170. 
Jacobs, F., White, R., and Ovey, C. (2002) The European Convention on Human Rights, 3rd ed., Oxford: 
Oxford University Press. 
Jacobson (2007) ‘Human Dignity and Health: A Review’, Social Science and Medicine 64: 292-302. 
Jessop, B. (2003) ‘Governance and Meta-governance: On Reflexivety, Requisite Variety and Requisite 
Irony’. In H. P. Bang (ed.) Governance as Social and Political Communication, Manchester: Manches-ter 
University Press. 
Kearnes, M.B. and Rip, A. (2009) ‘The Emerging Governance Landscape of Nanotechnolog’. In S. Gammel, 
S. Losch, A. Nordmann, (eds.) Jenseits Von Regulierung: Zum Politischen Umgang Mit Der Nanotech-nologie, 
Berlin: Akademische Verlagsgesellschaft. 
Lengley, A. and Parviz, B., (2008) ‘Multipurpose Integrated Active Contact Lenses’, The Neuromorphic 
Engineer, http://www.ine-news.org/pdf/0056/0056.pdf 
Lyall, C. and Tait, J. (2005) ‘Shifting Policy Debates and the Implications for Governance’. In C. Lyall and J. 
Tait (eds) New Modes of Governance: Developing an Integrated Policy Approach to Science, Technol-ogy, 
Risk and the Environment, Aldershot: Ashgate.MacIntyre, A. (1981) After Virtue: A Study in Mo-ral 
Theory, Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.
A Rights-Based Model of Governance 115 
MASIS (Monitoring Activities of Science in Society in Europe Experts Group) (2009) Challenging Futures 
of Science in Society. Emerging Trends and Cutting-Edge Issues, Luxembourg: European Commission, 
Directorate-General for Research. 
Mohr, A., Busby, H., Hervey, T. and Dingwall, R. (2012) ‘Mapping the Role of Official Bioethics Advice in 
the Governance of Biotechnologies in the EU: the European Group on Ethics’ Opinion on Commercial 
Cord Blood Banking’, Science and Public Studies 39: 105-117. 
Pariotti, E., (2007) ‘”Effetto orizzontale” dei diritti umani e imprese transnazionali nello spazio europeo’. In I. 
Trujillo, F. Viola (eds.), Identità, diritti, ragione pubblica in Europa, Bologna: Il Mulino. 
Pariotti, E. (2011) Normatività giuridica e governance delle tecnologie emergenti. In G. Guerra, A. Muratorio, 
M. Piccinni, E. Pariotti and D. Ruggiu (eds.) Forme di responsabilità, regolazione e nanotecnologie, 
Bologna: Il Mulino. 
Pariotti, E. (2013) Diritti umani: concetto, teoria, evoluzione, Padova: CEDAM. 
Pariotti, E. and Ruggiu, D. (2012) ‘Governing Nanotechnologies in Europe: Human Rights, Soft Law, and 
Corporate Social Responsibility’. In H. Van Lente, C. Coenen, K. Konrad, L. Krabbenborg, C. Milburn, 
F. Seifert, F. Thoreau and B. Zülsdorf (eds.) Little by Little: Expansions of Nanoscience and Emerging 
Technologies, Heidelberg: IOS Press/AKA-Verlag.. 
Plomer, A. (2008) ‘The European Group on Ethics: Law, Politics, and the Limits of Moral Integration in 
Europe’, European Law Journal 14(6): 839-859. 
Raz, J. (2010) ‘Human Rights in the Emerging World Order’, Transnational Legal Theory 1: 37-47. 
Roco, M. (2006) ‘Progress in Governance of Converging Technologies Integrated from the Nanoscale’, 
Annals of the New York Academy of Science 1093: 1-23 
Ruggiu, D. (2012a) ‘Synthetic Biology and Human Rights in the European Context: Health and Environment 
in Comparison of the EU and the Council of Europe Regulatory Framework’, Biotechnology Law Re-port 
31(4): 337-355. 
Ruggiu, D. (2012b) Diritti e temporalità. I diritti umani nell’era delle tecnologie emergenti, Bologna: Il 
Mulino. 
Salter, B. and Jones, M. (2002) ‘Human Genetic Technologies, European Governance and the Politics of 
Bioethics’, Nature Reviews Genetics 3(10): 808-814. 
Schummer, J. (2007) ‘Identifying Ethical Issues in Nanotechnologies’. In A. M. J. Hanke ten Have (ed.) 
Nanotechnologies, Ethics and Politics, Paris: UNESCO. 
Scott, J. and Trubek, D.M. (2002) ‘Mind the Gap: Law and New Approaches to Governance in the European 
Union’, European Law Journal 8(1): 1-18. 
Shahinpoor, M. (2011) ‘Biomimetic Robotic Venus Flytrap (Dionaea muscipula Ellis) Made with Ionic 
Polymer Metal Composites’, Bioinspiration & Biomimetics 6: 046004. 
Spielmann D. (1999) ‘Human Rights Case Law in the Strasbourg and Luxembourg Courts: Conflitcs, Incon-sistencies, 
and Complementarities’. In P. Alston (ed.), The EU and Human Rights, Oxford, Oxford 
University Press. 
Stoke, G. (1998) ‘Governance as Theory: Five Propositions’ JSSJ 155: 17-28. 
Svrivastava, D. P., Woolfrey, K. M., Feng, L., Brandon, N. J. and Penzes, P. (2010) ‘Estrogen Receptor ! 
Activity Modulates Synaptic Signalling and Structure’, The Journal of Neuroscience 30(40): 13454- 
13460. 
Tallacchini, M. (2009) ‘Governing by Values. EU Ethics: Soft Tool, Hard Effects’, Minerva 47: 281-306. 
Viola, F. and Zaccaria, G. (2001) Diritto e interpretazione. Lineamenti di teoria ermeneutica del diritto, 
Roma- Bari: Laterza. 
von Schomberg, R. (2011) ‘Prospects for Technology Assessment in a Framework of Responsible Research 
and Innovation. In M. Susseldorp and R. Beecrift (eds.) Technikfolgen abschätzen lehren: Bildungspo-tenziale 
transdisziplinärer Methoden, Wiesbaden: Vs Verlag. 
von Schonberg, R. (2013, forthcoming) A vision of Responsible Innovation. in R. Owen, M. Heintz, and J. 
Bessant (eds.) Responsible Innovation: Managing the Responsible Emergence of Science and Innova-tion 
in Society, London: John Wiley.

More Related Content

Similar to A rights based model of governance - the case of human enhancement

Debate on the Responsibilities of Stakeholders in Justice (from Theory to Pra...
Debate on the Responsibilities of Stakeholders in Justice (from Theory to Pra...Debate on the Responsibilities of Stakeholders in Justice (from Theory to Pra...
Debate on the Responsibilities of Stakeholders in Justice (from Theory to Pra...AJHSSR Journal
 
Nudging Legally on the Checks and Balances of Behavioural Regulation - Albert...
Nudging Legally on the Checks and Balances of Behavioural Regulation - Albert...Nudging Legally on the Checks and Balances of Behavioural Regulation - Albert...
Nudging Legally on the Checks and Balances of Behavioural Regulation - Albert...OECD Governance
 
Aare Kasemets (2018) Institutionalisation of Knowledge-Based Policy & Better ...
Aare Kasemets (2018) Institutionalisation of Knowledge-Based Policy & Better ...Aare Kasemets (2018) Institutionalisation of Knowledge-Based Policy & Better ...
Aare Kasemets (2018) Institutionalisation of Knowledge-Based Policy & Better ...Aare Kasemets
 
Aare Kasemets "Institutionalisation of Knowledge-Based Policy Design and Bett...
Aare Kasemets "Institutionalisation of Knowledge-Based Policy Design and Bett...Aare Kasemets "Institutionalisation of Knowledge-Based Policy Design and Bett...
Aare Kasemets "Institutionalisation of Knowledge-Based Policy Design and Bett...Aare Kasemets
 
OntoSOC: S ociocultural K nowledge O ntology
OntoSOC:  S ociocultural  K nowledge  O ntology OntoSOC:  S ociocultural  K nowledge  O ntology
OntoSOC: S ociocultural K nowledge O ntology IJwest
 
Application Of The Hardy-Weinberg Law In The Theory Of Social Management
Application Of The Hardy-Weinberg Law In The Theory Of Social ManagementApplication Of The Hardy-Weinberg Law In The Theory Of Social Management
Application Of The Hardy-Weinberg Law In The Theory Of Social ManagementLinda Garcia
 
Comp Econ&Institution
Comp Econ&InstitutionComp Econ&Institution
Comp Econ&Institutionbhamori
 
Debate on Artificial Intelligence in Justice, in the Democracy of the Future,...
Debate on Artificial Intelligence in Justice, in the Democracy of the Future,...Debate on Artificial Intelligence in Justice, in the Democracy of the Future,...
Debate on Artificial Intelligence in Justice, in the Democracy of the Future,...AJHSSR Journal
 
Models and Concepts for Socio-technical Complex Systems: Towards Fractal Soci...
Models and Concepts for Socio-technical Complex Systems: Towards Fractal Soci...Models and Concepts for Socio-technical Complex Systems: Towards Fractal Soci...
Models and Concepts for Socio-technical Complex Systems: Towards Fractal Soci...Vincenzo De Florio
 
Chapter 4 Administration Responsibility The Key to Administrativ.docx
Chapter 4 Administration Responsibility The Key to Administrativ.docxChapter 4 Administration Responsibility The Key to Administrativ.docx
Chapter 4 Administration Responsibility The Key to Administrativ.docxketurahhazelhurst
 
Criteria and procedures for selection of civil society organizations in cross...
Criteria and procedures for selection of civil society organizations in cross...Criteria and procedures for selection of civil society organizations in cross...
Criteria and procedures for selection of civil society organizations in cross...МЦМС | MCIC
 
Map making and analysis of the main international initiative on development i...
Map making and analysis of the main international initiative on development i...Map making and analysis of the main international initiative on development i...
Map making and analysis of the main international initiative on development i...Dr Lendy Spires
 
• Papeles El tiempo de los derechos “What were we going to evaluate, exactly?...
•	Papeles El tiempo de los derechos “What were we going to evaluate, exactly?...•	Papeles El tiempo de los derechos “What were we going to evaluate, exactly?...
• Papeles El tiempo de los derechos “What were we going to evaluate, exactly?...IDHBC
 
Techno-government networks: Actor-Network Theory in electronic government res...
Techno-government networks: Actor-Network Theory in electronic government res...Techno-government networks: Actor-Network Theory in electronic government res...
Techno-government networks: Actor-Network Theory in electronic government res...FGV Brazil
 
,QVWLWXWLRQDOL]HG2UJDQL]DWLRQV)RUPDO6WUXFWXUHDV0WKDQG
,QVWLWXWLRQDOL]HG2UJDQL]DWLRQV)RUPDO6WUXFWXUHDV0WKDQG,QVWLWXWLRQDOL]HG2UJDQL]DWLRQV)RUPDO6WUXFWXUHDV0WKDQG
,QVWLWXWLRQDOL]HG2UJDQL]DWLRQV)RUPDO6WUXFWXUHDV0WKDQGRayleneAndre399
 
Plan, Do, Check, Act - Safety Science
Plan, Do, Check, Act - Safety SciencePlan, Do, Check, Act - Safety Science
Plan, Do, Check, Act - Safety ScienceJules Arntz-Gray
 
Institutions and economic development
Institutions and economic developmentInstitutions and economic development
Institutions and economic developmentMajd Zghayar
 
Tensions and antagonistic interactions of risks and ethics of using robotics ...
Tensions and antagonistic interactions of risks and ethics of using robotics ...Tensions and antagonistic interactions of risks and ethics of using robotics ...
Tensions and antagonistic interactions of risks and ethics of using robotics ...Araz Taeihagh
 

Similar to A rights based model of governance - the case of human enhancement (20)

Debate on the Responsibilities of Stakeholders in Justice (from Theory to Pra...
Debate on the Responsibilities of Stakeholders in Justice (from Theory to Pra...Debate on the Responsibilities of Stakeholders in Justice (from Theory to Pra...
Debate on the Responsibilities of Stakeholders in Justice (from Theory to Pra...
 
Nudging Legally on the Checks and Balances of Behavioural Regulation - Albert...
Nudging Legally on the Checks and Balances of Behavioural Regulation - Albert...Nudging Legally on the Checks and Balances of Behavioural Regulation - Albert...
Nudging Legally on the Checks and Balances of Behavioural Regulation - Albert...
 
Aare Kasemets (2018) Institutionalisation of Knowledge-Based Policy & Better ...
Aare Kasemets (2018) Institutionalisation of Knowledge-Based Policy & Better ...Aare Kasemets (2018) Institutionalisation of Knowledge-Based Policy & Better ...
Aare Kasemets (2018) Institutionalisation of Knowledge-Based Policy & Better ...
 
Aare Kasemets "Institutionalisation of Knowledge-Based Policy Design and Bett...
Aare Kasemets "Institutionalisation of Knowledge-Based Policy Design and Bett...Aare Kasemets "Institutionalisation of Knowledge-Based Policy Design and Bett...
Aare Kasemets "Institutionalisation of Knowledge-Based Policy Design and Bett...
 
OntoSOC: S ociocultural K nowledge O ntology
OntoSOC:  S ociocultural  K nowledge  O ntology OntoSOC:  S ociocultural  K nowledge  O ntology
OntoSOC: S ociocultural K nowledge O ntology
 
Application Of The Hardy-Weinberg Law In The Theory Of Social Management
Application Of The Hardy-Weinberg Law In The Theory Of Social ManagementApplication Of The Hardy-Weinberg Law In The Theory Of Social Management
Application Of The Hardy-Weinberg Law In The Theory Of Social Management
 
Comp Econ&Institution
Comp Econ&InstitutionComp Econ&Institution
Comp Econ&Institution
 
Debate on Artificial Intelligence in Justice, in the Democracy of the Future,...
Debate on Artificial Intelligence in Justice, in the Democracy of the Future,...Debate on Artificial Intelligence in Justice, in the Democracy of the Future,...
Debate on Artificial Intelligence in Justice, in the Democracy of the Future,...
 
Models and Concepts for Socio-technical Complex Systems: Towards Fractal Soci...
Models and Concepts for Socio-technical Complex Systems: Towards Fractal Soci...Models and Concepts for Socio-technical Complex Systems: Towards Fractal Soci...
Models and Concepts for Socio-technical Complex Systems: Towards Fractal Soci...
 
E soc13
E soc13E soc13
E soc13
 
Chapter 4 Administration Responsibility The Key to Administrativ.docx
Chapter 4 Administration Responsibility The Key to Administrativ.docxChapter 4 Administration Responsibility The Key to Administrativ.docx
Chapter 4 Administration Responsibility The Key to Administrativ.docx
 
Criteria and procedures for selection of civil society organizations in cross...
Criteria and procedures for selection of civil society organizations in cross...Criteria and procedures for selection of civil society organizations in cross...
Criteria and procedures for selection of civil society organizations in cross...
 
Map making and analysis of the main international initiative on development i...
Map making and analysis of the main international initiative on development i...Map making and analysis of the main international initiative on development i...
Map making and analysis of the main international initiative on development i...
 
• Papeles El tiempo de los derechos “What were we going to evaluate, exactly?...
•	Papeles El tiempo de los derechos “What were we going to evaluate, exactly?...•	Papeles El tiempo de los derechos “What were we going to evaluate, exactly?...
• Papeles El tiempo de los derechos “What were we going to evaluate, exactly?...
 
Techno-government networks: Actor-Network Theory in electronic government res...
Techno-government networks: Actor-Network Theory in electronic government res...Techno-government networks: Actor-Network Theory in electronic government res...
Techno-government networks: Actor-Network Theory in electronic government res...
 
,QVWLWXWLRQDOL]HG2UJDQL]DWLRQV)RUPDO6WUXFWXUHDV0WKDQG
,QVWLWXWLRQDOL]HG2UJDQL]DWLRQV)RUPDO6WUXFWXUHDV0WKDQG,QVWLWXWLRQDOL]HG2UJDQL]DWLRQV)RUPDO6WUXFWXUHDV0WKDQG
,QVWLWXWLRQDOL]HG2UJDQL]DWLRQV)RUPDO6WUXFWXUHDV0WKDQG
 
Plan, Do, Check, Act - Safety Science
Plan, Do, Check, Act - Safety SciencePlan, Do, Check, Act - Safety Science
Plan, Do, Check, Act - Safety Science
 
Institutions and economic development
Institutions and economic developmentInstitutions and economic development
Institutions and economic development
 
The Rule of Law and its Social Reception as Determinants of Economic Developm...
The Rule of Law and its Social Reception as Determinants of Economic Developm...The Rule of Law and its Social Reception as Determinants of Economic Developm...
The Rule of Law and its Social Reception as Determinants of Economic Developm...
 
Tensions and antagonistic interactions of risks and ethics of using robotics ...
Tensions and antagonistic interactions of risks and ethics of using robotics ...Tensions and antagonistic interactions of risks and ethics of using robotics ...
Tensions and antagonistic interactions of risks and ethics of using robotics ...
 

More from Karlos Svoboda

Human vs and part machine - TVP magazine
Human vs and part machine - TVP magazineHuman vs and part machine - TVP magazine
Human vs and part machine - TVP magazineKarlos Svoboda
 
Moral science - Human subjects
Moral science - Human subjectsMoral science - Human subjects
Moral science - Human subjectsKarlos Svoboda
 
Existential Risk Prevention as Global Priority
Existential Risk Prevention as Global PriorityExistential Risk Prevention as Global Priority
Existential Risk Prevention as Global PriorityKarlos Svoboda
 
A taxonomy for descriptive research in law and technology
A taxonomy for descriptive research in law and technologyA taxonomy for descriptive research in law and technology
A taxonomy for descriptive research in law and technologyKarlos Svoboda
 
Evropská dohoda o ochraně obratlovců
Evropská dohoda o ochraně obratlovcůEvropská dohoda o ochraně obratlovců
Evropská dohoda o ochraně obratlovcůKarlos Svoboda
 
Ethics of security and surveillance technologies opinion 28
Ethics of security and surveillance technologies opinion 28Ethics of security and surveillance technologies opinion 28
Ethics of security and surveillance technologies opinion 28Karlos Svoboda
 
Ethical aspect of ICT Implants in the Human body
Ethical aspect of ICT Implants in the Human bodyEthical aspect of ICT Implants in the Human body
Ethical aspect of ICT Implants in the Human bodyKarlos Svoboda
 
Emerging Technoethics of Human Interaction with Communication, Bionic and Rob...
Emerging Technoethics of Human Interaction with Communication, Bionic and Rob...Emerging Technoethics of Human Interaction with Communication, Bionic and Rob...
Emerging Technoethics of Human Interaction with Communication, Bionic and Rob...Karlos Svoboda
 
Neural devices will change humankind
Neural devices will change humankindNeural devices will change humankind
Neural devices will change humankindKarlos Svoboda
 
Nanotechnology, ubiquitous computing and the internet of things
Nanotechnology, ubiquitous computing and the internet of thingsNanotechnology, ubiquitous computing and the internet of things
Nanotechnology, ubiquitous computing and the internet of thingsKarlos Svoboda
 
Identity REvolution multi disciplinary perspectives
Identity REvolution   multi disciplinary perspectivesIdentity REvolution   multi disciplinary perspectives
Identity REvolution multi disciplinary perspectivesKarlos Svoboda
 
MBAN medical body area network - first report and order
MBAN   medical body area network - first report and orderMBAN   medical body area network - first report and order
MBAN medical body area network - first report and orderKarlos Svoboda
 
Intimate technology - the battle for our body and behaviour
Intimate technology - the battle for our body and behaviourIntimate technology - the battle for our body and behaviour
Intimate technology - the battle for our body and behaviourKarlos Svoboda
 
Making perfect life european governance challenges in 21st Century Bio-engine...
Making perfect life european governance challenges in 21st Century Bio-engine...Making perfect life european governance challenges in 21st Century Bio-engine...
Making perfect life european governance challenges in 21st Century Bio-engine...Karlos Svoboda
 
GRAY MATTERS Integrative Approaches for Neuroscience, Ethics, and Society
GRAY MATTERS Integrative Approaches for  Neuroscience, Ethics, and SocietyGRAY MATTERS Integrative Approaches for  Neuroscience, Ethics, and Society
GRAY MATTERS Integrative Approaches for Neuroscience, Ethics, and SocietyKarlos Svoboda
 
Neuroscience, mental privacy and the law
Neuroscience, mental privacy and the lawNeuroscience, mental privacy and the law
Neuroscience, mental privacy and the lawKarlos Svoboda
 
Biotechnology and science probing the mind
Biotechnology and science   probing the mindBiotechnology and science   probing the mind
Biotechnology and science probing the mindKarlos Svoboda
 

More from Karlos Svoboda (20)

Human vs and part machine - TVP magazine
Human vs and part machine - TVP magazineHuman vs and part machine - TVP magazine
Human vs and part machine - TVP magazine
 
Jan Hus De ecclesia
Jan Hus De ecclesia Jan Hus De ecclesia
Jan Hus De ecclesia
 
Moral science - Human subjects
Moral science - Human subjectsMoral science - Human subjects
Moral science - Human subjects
 
Existential Risk Prevention as Global Priority
Existential Risk Prevention as Global PriorityExistential Risk Prevention as Global Priority
Existential Risk Prevention as Global Priority
 
A taxonomy for descriptive research in law and technology
A taxonomy for descriptive research in law and technologyA taxonomy for descriptive research in law and technology
A taxonomy for descriptive research in law and technology
 
Evropská dohoda o ochraně obratlovců
Evropská dohoda o ochraně obratlovcůEvropská dohoda o ochraně obratlovců
Evropská dohoda o ochraně obratlovců
 
Ethics of security and surveillance technologies opinion 28
Ethics of security and surveillance technologies opinion 28Ethics of security and surveillance technologies opinion 28
Ethics of security and surveillance technologies opinion 28
 
Ethical aspect of ICT Implants in the Human body
Ethical aspect of ICT Implants in the Human bodyEthical aspect of ICT Implants in the Human body
Ethical aspect of ICT Implants in the Human body
 
Emerging Technoethics of Human Interaction with Communication, Bionic and Rob...
Emerging Technoethics of Human Interaction with Communication, Bionic and Rob...Emerging Technoethics of Human Interaction with Communication, Bionic and Rob...
Emerging Technoethics of Human Interaction with Communication, Bionic and Rob...
 
Neural devices will change humankind
Neural devices will change humankindNeural devices will change humankind
Neural devices will change humankind
 
Nanotechnology, ubiquitous computing and the internet of things
Nanotechnology, ubiquitous computing and the internet of thingsNanotechnology, ubiquitous computing and the internet of things
Nanotechnology, ubiquitous computing and the internet of things
 
Identity REvolution multi disciplinary perspectives
Identity REvolution   multi disciplinary perspectivesIdentity REvolution   multi disciplinary perspectives
Identity REvolution multi disciplinary perspectives
 
MBAN medical body area network - first report and order
MBAN   medical body area network - first report and orderMBAN   medical body area network - first report and order
MBAN medical body area network - first report and order
 
Intimate technology - the battle for our body and behaviour
Intimate technology - the battle for our body and behaviourIntimate technology - the battle for our body and behaviour
Intimate technology - the battle for our body and behaviour
 
Human enhancement
Human enhancementHuman enhancement
Human enhancement
 
Making perfect life european governance challenges in 21st Century Bio-engine...
Making perfect life european governance challenges in 21st Century Bio-engine...Making perfect life european governance challenges in 21st Century Bio-engine...
Making perfect life european governance challenges in 21st Century Bio-engine...
 
Ambient intelligence
Ambient intelligenceAmbient intelligence
Ambient intelligence
 
GRAY MATTERS Integrative Approaches for Neuroscience, Ethics, and Society
GRAY MATTERS Integrative Approaches for  Neuroscience, Ethics, and SocietyGRAY MATTERS Integrative Approaches for  Neuroscience, Ethics, and Society
GRAY MATTERS Integrative Approaches for Neuroscience, Ethics, and Society
 
Neuroscience, mental privacy and the law
Neuroscience, mental privacy and the lawNeuroscience, mental privacy and the law
Neuroscience, mental privacy and the law
 
Biotechnology and science probing the mind
Biotechnology and science   probing the mindBiotechnology and science   probing the mind
Biotechnology and science probing the mind
 

Recently uploaded

Finance strategies for adaptation. Presentation for CANCC
Finance strategies for adaptation. Presentation for CANCCFinance strategies for adaptation. Presentation for CANCC
Finance strategies for adaptation. Presentation for CANCCNAP Global Network
 
74th Amendment of India PPT by Piyush(IC).pptx
74th Amendment of India PPT by Piyush(IC).pptx74th Amendment of India PPT by Piyush(IC).pptx
74th Amendment of India PPT by Piyush(IC).pptxpiyushsinghrajput913
 
NAP Expo - Delivering effective and adequate adaptation.pptx
NAP Expo - Delivering effective and adequate adaptation.pptxNAP Expo - Delivering effective and adequate adaptation.pptx
NAP Expo - Delivering effective and adequate adaptation.pptxNAP Global Network
 
The NAP process & South-South peer learning
The NAP process & South-South peer learningThe NAP process & South-South peer learning
The NAP process & South-South peer learningNAP Global Network
 
sponsor for poor old age person food.pdf
sponsor for poor old age person food.pdfsponsor for poor old age person food.pdf
sponsor for poor old age person food.pdfSERUDS INDIA
 
Scaling up coastal adaptation in Maldives through the NAP process
Scaling up coastal adaptation in Maldives through the NAP processScaling up coastal adaptation in Maldives through the NAP process
Scaling up coastal adaptation in Maldives through the NAP processNAP Global Network
 
2024 UN Civil Society Conference in Support of the Summit of the Future.
2024 UN Civil Society Conference in Support of the Summit of the Future.2024 UN Civil Society Conference in Support of the Summit of the Future.
2024 UN Civil Society Conference in Support of the Summit of the Future.Christina Parmionova
 
2024: The FAR, Federal Acquisition Regulations, Part 32
2024: The FAR, Federal Acquisition Regulations, Part 322024: The FAR, Federal Acquisition Regulations, Part 32
2024: The FAR, Federal Acquisition Regulations, Part 32JSchaus & Associates
 
Call Girls in Moti Bagh (delhi) call me [8448380779] escort service 24X7
Call Girls in Moti Bagh (delhi) call me [8448380779] escort service 24X7Call Girls in Moti Bagh (delhi) call me [8448380779] escort service 24X7
Call Girls in Moti Bagh (delhi) call me [8448380779] escort service 24X7Delhi Call girls
 
2024: The FAR, Federal Acquisition Regulations, Part 31
2024: The FAR, Federal Acquisition Regulations, Part 312024: The FAR, Federal Acquisition Regulations, Part 31
2024: The FAR, Federal Acquisition Regulations, Part 31JSchaus & Associates
 
Dating Call Girls inBaloda Bazar Bhatapara 9332606886Call Girls Advance Cash...
Dating Call Girls inBaloda Bazar Bhatapara  9332606886Call Girls Advance Cash...Dating Call Girls inBaloda Bazar Bhatapara  9332606886Call Girls Advance Cash...
Dating Call Girls inBaloda Bazar Bhatapara 9332606886Call Girls Advance Cash...kumargunjan9515
 
Election 2024 Presiding Duty Keypoints_01.pdf
Election 2024 Presiding Duty Keypoints_01.pdfElection 2024 Presiding Duty Keypoints_01.pdf
Election 2024 Presiding Duty Keypoints_01.pdfSamirsinh Parmar
 
31st World Press Freedom Day Conference in Santiago.
31st World Press Freedom Day Conference in Santiago.31st World Press Freedom Day Conference in Santiago.
31st World Press Freedom Day Conference in Santiago.Christina Parmionova
 
3 May, Journalism in the face of the Environmental Crisis.
3 May, Journalism in the face of the Environmental Crisis.3 May, Journalism in the face of the Environmental Crisis.
3 May, Journalism in the face of the Environmental Crisis.Christina Parmionova
 
Cheap Call Girls In Hyderabad Phone No 📞 9352988975 📞 Elite Escort Service Av...
Cheap Call Girls In Hyderabad Phone No 📞 9352988975 📞 Elite Escort Service Av...Cheap Call Girls In Hyderabad Phone No 📞 9352988975 📞 Elite Escort Service Av...
Cheap Call Girls In Hyderabad Phone No 📞 9352988975 📞 Elite Escort Service Av...kajalverma014
 
2024: The FAR, Federal Acquisition Regulations, Part 30
2024: The FAR, Federal Acquisition Regulations, Part 302024: The FAR, Federal Acquisition Regulations, Part 30
2024: The FAR, Federal Acquisition Regulations, Part 30JSchaus & Associates
 
Honasa Consumer Limited Impact Report 2024.pdf
Honasa Consumer Limited Impact Report 2024.pdfHonasa Consumer Limited Impact Report 2024.pdf
Honasa Consumer Limited Impact Report 2024.pdfSocial Samosa
 
2024 asthma jkdjkfjsdklfjsdlkfjskldfgdsgerg
2024 asthma jkdjkfjsdklfjsdlkfjskldfgdsgerg2024 asthma jkdjkfjsdklfjsdlkfjskldfgdsgerg
2024 asthma jkdjkfjsdklfjsdlkfjskldfgdsgergMadhuKothuru
 
Make a difference in a girl's life by donating to her education!
Make a difference in a girl's life by donating to her education!Make a difference in a girl's life by donating to her education!
Make a difference in a girl's life by donating to her education!SERUDS INDIA
 

Recently uploaded (20)

Finance strategies for adaptation. Presentation for CANCC
Finance strategies for adaptation. Presentation for CANCCFinance strategies for adaptation. Presentation for CANCC
Finance strategies for adaptation. Presentation for CANCC
 
74th Amendment of India PPT by Piyush(IC).pptx
74th Amendment of India PPT by Piyush(IC).pptx74th Amendment of India PPT by Piyush(IC).pptx
74th Amendment of India PPT by Piyush(IC).pptx
 
NAP Expo - Delivering effective and adequate adaptation.pptx
NAP Expo - Delivering effective and adequate adaptation.pptxNAP Expo - Delivering effective and adequate adaptation.pptx
NAP Expo - Delivering effective and adequate adaptation.pptx
 
The NAP process & South-South peer learning
The NAP process & South-South peer learningThe NAP process & South-South peer learning
The NAP process & South-South peer learning
 
sponsor for poor old age person food.pdf
sponsor for poor old age person food.pdfsponsor for poor old age person food.pdf
sponsor for poor old age person food.pdf
 
Scaling up coastal adaptation in Maldives through the NAP process
Scaling up coastal adaptation in Maldives through the NAP processScaling up coastal adaptation in Maldives through the NAP process
Scaling up coastal adaptation in Maldives through the NAP process
 
2024 UN Civil Society Conference in Support of the Summit of the Future.
2024 UN Civil Society Conference in Support of the Summit of the Future.2024 UN Civil Society Conference in Support of the Summit of the Future.
2024 UN Civil Society Conference in Support of the Summit of the Future.
 
2024: The FAR, Federal Acquisition Regulations, Part 32
2024: The FAR, Federal Acquisition Regulations, Part 322024: The FAR, Federal Acquisition Regulations, Part 32
2024: The FAR, Federal Acquisition Regulations, Part 32
 
Call Girls in Moti Bagh (delhi) call me [8448380779] escort service 24X7
Call Girls in Moti Bagh (delhi) call me [8448380779] escort service 24X7Call Girls in Moti Bagh (delhi) call me [8448380779] escort service 24X7
Call Girls in Moti Bagh (delhi) call me [8448380779] escort service 24X7
 
AHMR volume 10 number 1 January-April 2024
AHMR volume 10 number 1 January-April 2024AHMR volume 10 number 1 January-April 2024
AHMR volume 10 number 1 January-April 2024
 
2024: The FAR, Federal Acquisition Regulations, Part 31
2024: The FAR, Federal Acquisition Regulations, Part 312024: The FAR, Federal Acquisition Regulations, Part 31
2024: The FAR, Federal Acquisition Regulations, Part 31
 
Dating Call Girls inBaloda Bazar Bhatapara 9332606886Call Girls Advance Cash...
Dating Call Girls inBaloda Bazar Bhatapara  9332606886Call Girls Advance Cash...Dating Call Girls inBaloda Bazar Bhatapara  9332606886Call Girls Advance Cash...
Dating Call Girls inBaloda Bazar Bhatapara 9332606886Call Girls Advance Cash...
 
Election 2024 Presiding Duty Keypoints_01.pdf
Election 2024 Presiding Duty Keypoints_01.pdfElection 2024 Presiding Duty Keypoints_01.pdf
Election 2024 Presiding Duty Keypoints_01.pdf
 
31st World Press Freedom Day Conference in Santiago.
31st World Press Freedom Day Conference in Santiago.31st World Press Freedom Day Conference in Santiago.
31st World Press Freedom Day Conference in Santiago.
 
3 May, Journalism in the face of the Environmental Crisis.
3 May, Journalism in the face of the Environmental Crisis.3 May, Journalism in the face of the Environmental Crisis.
3 May, Journalism in the face of the Environmental Crisis.
 
Cheap Call Girls In Hyderabad Phone No 📞 9352988975 📞 Elite Escort Service Av...
Cheap Call Girls In Hyderabad Phone No 📞 9352988975 📞 Elite Escort Service Av...Cheap Call Girls In Hyderabad Phone No 📞 9352988975 📞 Elite Escort Service Av...
Cheap Call Girls In Hyderabad Phone No 📞 9352988975 📞 Elite Escort Service Av...
 
2024: The FAR, Federal Acquisition Regulations, Part 30
2024: The FAR, Federal Acquisition Regulations, Part 302024: The FAR, Federal Acquisition Regulations, Part 30
2024: The FAR, Federal Acquisition Regulations, Part 30
 
Honasa Consumer Limited Impact Report 2024.pdf
Honasa Consumer Limited Impact Report 2024.pdfHonasa Consumer Limited Impact Report 2024.pdf
Honasa Consumer Limited Impact Report 2024.pdf
 
2024 asthma jkdjkfjsdklfjsdlkfjskldfgdsgerg
2024 asthma jkdjkfjsdklfjsdlkfjskldfgdsgerg2024 asthma jkdjkfjsdklfjsdlkfjskldfgdsgerg
2024 asthma jkdjkfjsdklfjsdlkfjskldfgdsgerg
 
Make a difference in a girl's life by donating to her education!
Make a difference in a girl's life by donating to her education!Make a difference in a girl's life by donating to her education!
Make a difference in a girl's life by donating to her education!
 

A rights based model of governance - the case of human enhancement

  • 1. A Rights-Based Model of Governance: The Case of Human Enhancement and the Role of Ethics in Europe Daniele RUGGIU CIGA, University of Padova Abstract: In Europe, the current model of governance is characterized by the cen-trality of ethics, which has led (at national and supranational levels) to both the in-stitutionalization of ethics (the bureaucratic expression of ethics) and to the ‘ethicization of technoscience’ (the tendency to frame the governance of emerging technologies in ethical terms). This model is unique in the world and, due to the overlapping of the above-mentioned phenomena, has generated a process of blur-ring the boundary between ethics and law, which weakens the action of the regula-tory and ethical tools of governance, especially with regard to human rights. The analysis of the case of human enhancement, with particular regard to stem cell re-search, shows instead how a clearer distinction of the role and functions of ethics and law, as well as the development of mechanisms of self-coordination, can strengthen the current model of governance as a rights-oriented one.1 Keywords: Models of governance; enhancement technologies; metagovernance; human rights; ethics. Introduction The current development of technology and scientific research may give rise to several applications on human beings. In this context, emerging technologies can further foster the applications on human beings and pave the way for new and incisive research to-wards human enhancement (HE).2 Thanks to emerging technologies, HE can be more effective and represent a concrete challenge for present societies, also in Europe. Scien-tists of the Northwestern University Feinberg School of Medicine, for instance, re-cently created a brain-synthesized estrogen that influences the synaptic structure, function and cognitive processes by augmenting the networks among neurons (Svriva-stava et al. 2010). Thus it could be a case of future brain-doping. The use of emerging 1 This work was done with the support of the European Commission FP7 Science in Society funded project, ‘Ethics in Public Policy Making: The Case of Human Enhancement’ (EPOCH), grant number SIS-CT-2010-266660, http://epochproject.com. The views expressed in this article are the sole respon-sibility of the author and do not reflect the opinion of the European Commission or of any partner of the project. 2 For HE I refer to any “modification aimed at improving individual human performance and brought about by science-based or technology-based interventions in the human body”. As it has been under-lined, this definition includes “strong”, “second-stage” forms of human enhancement with long-term ef-fective or permanent results (e.g., genetic enhancements and invasive brain-computer interfaces) as well as “temporary” enhancements (e.g. alleged ”pharmacological cognitive enhancers” with low addiction potential or none at all”). See http://epochproject.com.
  • 2. 104 A Rights-Based Model of Governance technologies can also meliorate the biological defense mechanisms of the human body. With synthetic biology, it could be possible to create beneficial bacterial infections programmed to augment immunity, or even synth-cells engineered to circulate in the body to extend the human immune system, making the human body resistant to normal illness and infections. The potential of synthetic biology might also lead to inserting artificial chromosomes in the genome of complex organisms, including humans, open-ing the door to the gene-enhancement (EGE 2010, 23). The field of nanotechnology offers new opportunities by designing artificial muscles (Shahinpoor 2011) or contact lens that can lead us toward augmented reality, a dimension where we can experience material reality and immersive computer data simultaneously (Lengley and Parviz 2008). Nanotechnology, synthetic biology, and stem cell research can concretely boost the possible applications of HE both for healthy and disabled people. In this context we should wonder whether the structures of technological governance we built in Europe are capable to face the societal changes that HE entails. The model of governance, affirmed in Europe over the last thirty years in the con-text of both biotechnologies (Busby et al. 2008) and nanotechnologies (Ruggiu 2012b), shows the centrality of ethics and its participative character. This relevance of ethics can be observed even in the field of the enhancement technologies, such as in the case of stem cell research. The role assumed by ethics in Europe implies several phenomena such as the ‘institutionalization of ethics’ (Tallacchini 2009), the ‘ethicization of tech-noscience’ (MASIS 2009, 32, 38) and the tendency of ethics to incorporate legal tools by blurring boundaries between law and ethics (Plomer 2008). These phenomena are tightly intertwined and the last one, in particular, involves human rights that can play a relevant part in face of HE through two clashing principles: personal dignity and au-tonomy. In this chapter, I will provide a rights-based model of governance and I will argue that governance can be more effective only if we build mechanisms of coordina-tion among all governmental tools, both regulatory and ethical. In this regard, the phe-nomenon of the ‘ethicization of technoscience’, with its blurring of ethical and legal norms, risks weakening the efficacy of human rights in the governance of emerging technologies, especially enhancement technologies. Therefore, I will conclude that a clear division of roles, functions, and structures of law and ethics could strengthen both the human rights penetration into the grammar of the EU governance and the efficacy of technological governance itself. 1. Governance and Metagovernance By governance I mean the ensemble of processes with reticular character, diffuse among public and private actors both at national and supranational levels made up by norms of soft and hard law, somehow coordinated and aimed to solve conflicts and to make decisions in a particular technological, economic, or financial field (Ruggiu 2012b, 156).3 Scholars increasingly distinguish the concept of governance from that of metagovernance. Metagovernance refers to the organizations, structures, and processes that produce (the conditions of) governance (Jessop 2003) through the arrangement of normative tools (of legal, ethical, technical nature). At the metagovernance level, the relations among organizations and governance structures are characterized by heter- 3 On governance, with special attention to the ‘new governance turn’, see Stokes 1998; Scott and Tru-beck 2002; Lyall and Tait 2005; with regard to emerging technologies, see Roco 2006.
  • 3. A Rights-Based Model of Governance 105 archy instead of a kind of framing of hierarchical type. This fact deprives the processes of governance of a centre that can determine all relations of the system, giving a merely eccentric and diffuse character. In this regard the governance appears de facto distri-buted among several subjects and, thus, to be effective any model of governance should be able to involve a wide range of stakeholders (Stokes 1998; Pariotti and Ruggiu 2012). Consider the role of transnational corporations, or the action of NGOs within the worldwide governance (Pariotti 2007; 2013), or, again, the increasing importance of organs without legislative power but absolutely central in Europe, such as ethical committees especially at the Community level (Salter and Jones 2002). In this context we can distinguish the formalized structures and processes produc-ing governance from the informal ones. Those of the first type encompass the soft and hard law instruments such as EU directives, recommendations, self-regulatory tools (including codes of conduct), third-party certification systems that can nevertheless have legal effects, and human rights. Those of the second type can be, for example, reports and opinions of ethical advisory boards (EABs) such as the EGE, internal documents of corporations without any legal effect, or acts of NGOs that might influ-ence policy making. In other words, the first category of governance structures and processes, with respect to formal procedures and norms of competence, produces legal norms with binding force (hard law norms) or legal norms without binding force but capable of having legal effects (soft law norms); the latter category produces norms (moral, technical etc.) without any legal effects but capable of influencing decision-making processes. In the great puzzle of governance, any tool, even EU directives and resolutions, represents only a piece of the whole framework and coexists with a plurality of diverse tools with different goals and scope. Thus, to assess the pros and cons of a model, we need to enlarge our sight. In this chapter, I will focus on only two kinds of tools that are tightly intertwined—human rights and the ethical advisements of EGE—and their interplay with regard to HE. 2. A Legal Analysis of Human Rights As a small piece of the picture of governance, human rights can represent a governance tool in two ways. Due to their dual nature as both moral and legal, they are referred to by legal documents on human rights and by acts of EABs (especially at supranational level).4 From the legal standpoint, human rights are considered by the documents of hard and soft law (for example, the European Convention of Human Rights or ECHR5, the Oviedo Convention6, and the EU Charter7), and, in this latter instance, especially by 4 Human rights can be considered both as legal rights and as moral rights. In the Anglo-Saxon world, their consideration as moral rights prevails (e.g. Raz 2010; Brownsword 2008), whereas in continental Europe, their consideration as legal rights is consolidated (e.g. Jacobs et al. 2002; Bultrini 2004). These two perspectives are rooted in the different constitutional traditions characterizing the old continent. In this chapter, I will consider both perspectives as legitimate; but I will produce some brief arguments in favor of the legal consideration of human rights. 5 Council of Europe, Convention for the Protection on Human Rights and Fundamental Freedoms (ECHR) (CETS n. 5), adopted in Rome on November 11, 1950 (entered into force on September 3, 1953). 6 Council of Europe, Convention for the Protection of Human Rights and Dignity of the Human Being with regard to the Application of Biology and Medicine (Convention on Human Rights and Biomedicine
  • 4. 106 A Rights-Based Model of Governance self-regulatory documents (codes of conduct, guidelines, and so forth). In order to ex-press their legal dimension, I will use the following definition: human rights are those rights recognized by the international law rules listed in documents like the Universal Declaration, the Covenants of '66, and the ECHR pertaining to individuals, groups and associations against the state and enforceable in the face of judicial or quasi-judicial organs at a supranational level (the European Court of Human Rights or ECtHR, UN committees on human rights) (Ruggiu 2012a, 337 n. 4; 2012b, 7 n. 1). This definition sees the normativity of human rights as the result of legal texts (e.g. the ECHR) and the supranational courts case law (e.g. the ECtHR decisions) and permits human rights to have both a definite semantic content (e.g. what autonomy means) and a concrete effi-cacy (i.e. any violation is punished). In this regard, despite the common opinion that sees human rights as indeterminate norms (MacIntyre 1981), thanks to the case law of the two main European courts (the ECtHR and the Court of Justice of the EU or CJEU), their semantic content (their meaning) is determinate and complete, at any rate in Eu-rope where there are binding treaties on human rights (the ECHR), as well as an effec-tive system of enforcement able to punish a state’s human rights violations (the ECtHR) and to offer a wide set of decisions in several fields, with regard to scientific and technological developments (Ruggiu 2012b). In Europe, there are two competing systems of protection of human rights that con-tribute to their enforcement: that of the Council of Europe and that provided by EU (Bultrini 2004). These two protection systems are centred around a couple of hard law instruments (the ECHR with regard to the Council of Europe and the EU Charter) and around the activity of two supranational judicial organs (the ECtHR and the CJEU), which create an efficient and self-coordinated mechanism of enforcement able to strengthen the respect of human rights in the old continent (Spielmann 1999; Bultrini 2004).8 In the case of HE, where we could face (and we actually face) permanent or temporary modifications of the human body, there are two key aspects, in addition to the general theme of the protection of the individual good of health (the right to health): the possibility to exert individual consent to treatment (the self-determination principle), and the protection of human nature, which belongs to every individual (human dignity). 2.1. Human Dignity In a context characterized by the intertwining of a plurality of actors, jurisprudence is per se a governance factor, alongside the academic world, which is so engaged within the ethical reflection on the implications of technological development. This conclusion is true especially with regard to HE. Indeed, in this field we find some decisions of the European courts of capital importance that will affect the governance of enhancement technologies in future, especially with regard to personal dignity and stem cell research. or the Oviedo Convention) (CETS n. 164), adopted in Oviedo on April 4, 1997 (entered into force on December 1, 1999). 7 The Charter of Fundamental Rights of the European Union, adopted in Nice on December 7, 2000. 8 Nevertheless, human rights and fundamental rights of the EU cannot be deemed as coincident since they differ for content (there are some Community rights, such as freedom of research, that are not also human rights in the ECHR), structure (fundamental rights are balanceable with other public interests of the EU, such as free circulation of goods that can predominate) and trait (human dignity is an autono-mous right, whilst personal dignity is the basic value supporting the whole human rights architecture), the spontaneous mechanism of self-coordination between the two courts represents a resource for hu-man rights themselves (Pariotti and Ruggiu 2012).
  • 5. A Rights-Based Model of Governance 107 When the human being is handled as a means and not as an end, human dignity may be called in question (Jacobson 2007, 293, 298). Within human rights law, human dignity is the most pregnant with ethical significance among the other legal concepts (Andorno 2009). This makes hard to give it a legal meaning. Dignity is recalled by several documents at a supranational (e.g. the Universal Declaration on Human Rights9, the Oviedo Convention, the EU Charter etc.) and a national level (e.g. the German Constitution) (Francioni 2007; Jacobson 2007). From the legal standpoint we can distinguish two basic conceptions of dignity: one conceives dignity as the hidden concept, the architrave, of the whole of human rights law, being implied in several rights and freedoms (Andorno 2009; Jacobson 2007, 296); the latter interprets it as a right as such, which can be exercised by individuals or groups in the face of violations of human dignity (EGE 2000). The first model is proper to the Universal Declaration, the International Covenants of the 1966, and above all the system of the ECHR of the Council of Europe, which, paradoxically, does not men-tion it, not even in its preamble (Beyleveld and Brownsword 2004, 12).10 In this in-stance, individual dignity is protected directly by the state, which arrogates the power of making the trade-off among the opposite interests on behalf of the entire community, or indirectly by individuals that claim the protection of other freedoms and rights (mainly personal integrity, equality, and prohibition of inhuman, degrading treatments). Here, in this latter instance, dignity maintains the right structure (with an individual as right holder and a subject responsible for its protection, i.e. the state) but having a merely accessory character of the other rights. Thus, its legal content is nearly empty since the case law is too limited in this matter. Instead, in the first instance dignity has no right structure (no individual can claim it) and it is a mere public interest protected by the state and, in this sense, it might conflict with other individual interests that can be recognized as legal rights (e.g. autonomy). In order to build dignity as an ‘autono-mous (individual) right’ we could only resort to another model. This latter model, in-deed, is typical of the EU Charter where human dignity is affirmed as an autonomous right, and, as a right, it is protected by the CJEU jurisprudence. Here, the right holders are groups or associations that exercise the right of petition against the state in front of the court on behalf of the community. What is meaningful is that the jurisprudence of the CJEU on personal dignity is fundamental especially with regard to HE. Extremely relevant is, in fact, the Brüstle Case of the CJEU, because it has provided a definition of human embryo and deter-mined the conditions of patentability of some uses of human embryos.11 In 1997, Mr. Oliver Brüstle, a stem cell researcher, filed a patent related to isolated and purified neural progenitor cells for the treatment of neural defects. The transplantation of brain cells into the nervous system can be a promising method of treatment for numerous neurological diseases. The same techniques could be used also in brain enhancement. Greenpeace filed an appeal before the Bundespatentgericht (the Federal Patent Court in Germany) seeking a ruling of invalidity of the above-mentioned patent. The Bundes-patentgericht decided to stay the proceeding and to refer the question of stem cells patentability to the CJEU. First of all, lacking a uniform definition of human embryo, 9 The Universal Declaration on Human Rights (UDHR) adopted in New York on December 10, 1948 by the General Assembly of the United Nations. 10 It is expressly embodied in the preamble of the Protocol n. 13 concerning the abolition of death penalty in all circumstances adopted in Vilnius on May 3, 2002. 11 Judgment of the Court of Justice (Grand Chamber), Oliver Brüstle v. Greenpeace eV (Case C-34/10), 18 October 2011, not yet published.
  • 6. 108 A Rights-Based Model of Governance the CJEU provided one including: a) any human ovum as soon as fertilized; b) any non-fertilized human ovum into which the cell nucleus from a mature human cell has been transplanted; c) any non-fertilized human ovum whose division and further devel-opment have been stimulated by parthenogenesis, including stem cells obtained from a human embryo at the blastocyst stage. Then, it excluded from patentability some uses of human embryos (with industrial, commercial purposes, or for scientific research). Although the aim of the scientific research must be distinguished from industrial and commercial purposes, the use of human embryos for purposes of scientific research cannot be separated from the patent itself and the rights attached to it.12 According to the court, techniques for producing stem cells that require the prior destruction of hu-man embryos are also unpatentable.13 Outside of all those limits, the patentability of stem cells is admitted and it does not infringe human dignity. This decision will also act as landmark for the ECtHR jurisprudence, which can follow its statements in the future thanks to the process of self-coordination existing between the two courts. 2.2. Self-Determination Principle Autonomy, and the freedom of choice, is one of the pillars of human rights law. The question of the limits of our personal choice in non-medical treatments is one of the most controversial issues at stake (Beghé-Loreti and Marin 1999), especially with re-gard to HE. In the future, thanks to emerging technologies, the opportunity to use ICT implants, brain-computer interface devices, or artificial limbs could be really advantageous, giv-ing rise to a form of ‘permanent enhancement’.14 In these cases, what will be the judi-cial limits of a treatment as such? It is clear that human dignity and the self-determination principle are in a situation of potential conflict (EGE 2000). No case has (obviously) yet emerged, although nowadays many practices aimed to modify the body, if not directly enhancing it, are already very common. Within liberal-democratic societies some very invasive treatments such as gender re-assignment surgery are widely recognised.15 Re-assignment surgery can be deemed a kind of ‘irreversible human enhancement’. The ECtHR, for example, recognised that ‘there has been an unmistakable trend in the member States of the Council of Europe towards giving full legal recognition to gender re-assignment’.16 Within the ECHR system, the personal autonomy falls under the provision of Article 8 (respect of private life), which guarantees the personal sphere of each individual, including the right to 12 See Brüstle case, 43. 13 According to Goran Hermerén (2009), if a court has settled the ethical issue of the meaning and scope of the application of the principle of human dignity (for example, whether the destruction of the blasto-cysts in stem cell research is or not compatible with human dignity) that would seem to be a clear case of blurring normative and legal issues. There are reasons not to agree with this opinion. Indeed, with regard to human rights practice in Europe, it is important to bear into mind that the regulatory frame-work of human rights is the result of the joined work of the regulator (e.g. the Council of Europe or the EU) and judges (mainly the ECtHR and the CJEU). Accordingly the judges’ work is fully normative (it produce norms and therefore it is ‘normogenetic’), even if within the framework of rights set forth by the regulator (i.e. Council of Europe, EU) (Viola and Zaccaria 2001). 14 HE can be temporary or permanent and irreversible (Allhoff et al. 2010). 15 See Christine Goodwin v. The United Kingdom (App. 28957/95), judgment of 11 July 2002, Reports of Judgments and Decisions 2002-VI. 16 See ibid., 55.
  • 7. A Rights-Based Model of Governance 109 establish details of their identity as individual human beings.17 Can such applications of enhancement technologies be considered forms of reshaping individual identity? This is the question I would like to address here. It is clear that sexual identity is a particular aspect of personal identity, and it is difficult to build an analogical relationship with other medical treatments of the human body. But the delicacy of this issue is that it has a societal basis, and the common consideration of what is the core of our identity is strictly connected to societal development. According to the ECtHR, the matter of gender re-assignment cannot be left to the states’ margin of appreciation. The only limit which the court affirmed is that the treatment, even if painful, must be not ‘arbi-trary or capricious’.18 In this regard we could ask whether a HE intervention, which has by definition no therapeutic character, falls outside or inside those limits. It is necessary to remember that the ECHR is interpreted ‘in the light of the present-day conditions’ with a strong attention to societal evolution. Here the public order and morality clauses could take place. The question of the choice itself to undergo to surgical treatment has not been directly dealt with yet. The cases that dealt with the gender re-assignment in the light of the non-discrimination principle presuppose the legitimacy of the choice to undergo surgical treatment. A currently pending case will now directly deal with this issue and will probably determine limits and conditions of personal choice in its wider meaning.19 In sum, while the EU system of protecting fundamental rights seems to be stronger with regard to the matter of personal dignity, that of the Council of Europe can offer a higher level of protection with regard to the self-determination principle; but the cur-rent mechanism of self-coordination between the two courts permits integrating them in one efficient model (Pariotti and Ruggiu 2012). 3. The Activity of the Ethical Advisory Boards in Europe In biotechnological matters, the EU has developed a model of governance whose ex-perience represents a benchmark in other fields, as well. In particular, within the Euro-pean governance of emerging technologies, ethics has taken a leading role, which has no equal in the world.20 This fact led to building a bureaucratic apparatus able to sup-port and formally include ethical reflection into EU institutions, giving rise to the phe-nomenon of the progressive ‘institutionalization of ethics’, namely, the integration of ethical reflexivity into public institutions (Talacchini 2009). Tightly connected to this, the phenomenon of the ‘ethicization of technoscience’, that is, the tendency to frame technological innovation merely in ethical terms, has been unavoidably produced within the Union (MASIS 2009; Pariotti 2011). I would like to show that these over-lapping phenomena can be a weakening element in the governance of biotechnological applications on human beings, in particular those that can lead towards enhancement technologies. The processes of the ‘institutionalization of ethics’ and of the ‘ethicization of tech-noscientific governance’ began in the 1970s and 80s when the lack of acceptable regu- 17 See ibid., 90. 18 See ibid., 81. 19 Y.Y. c. Turquie (Requête no 14793/08), pending case, available at http://hudoc.echr.coe.int/sites/eng/ pages/search.aspx?i=001-114422 (accessed on 4 April 2013). 20 For example, with regard to nanotechnologies, see Kearnes and Rip 2009.
  • 8. 110 A Rights-Based Model of Governance latory capacity of the European Commission led to the adoption of committees, agen-cies, and EABs (Busby et al. 2008). In front of the challenges of biotechnologies the Community authorities addressed the issues of the increasing distrust of the public on the European policies and the legitimacy of the decision-making processes. For this reason, they instituted an organ with ethical competence able to steer the innovation processes among the member states. This body, which aimed to foster public confi-dence, took the name, first, of GAIEB and, then, of EGE.21 Its role and its increasing influence made it a strategic pole within the EU framework and the possible target of a process of instrumentalisation by politics (Plomer 2008). The route towards a model of governance characterized by the centrality of ethics goes through three fundamental steps. First of all the EGE legal basis was shaped with-out any datum point in the treaties, augmenting de facto its autonomy, especially from the European Parliament. Then, the scope of its remit was enlarged and subsequently posed under the control of the Presidency of the European Commission, weakening thus the requirements of its independency from political power. Finally, the activity of the EAB played a part in determining the European policies in the biotechnological field, in particular in stem cell research, in order to forge a common European identity in those matters among member states. With regard to the first aspect it is to notice that the Union EAB has benefited from the lack of a clear legal basis. In fact, none of the Treaty on functioning of the Euro-pean Union articles that are usually recalled (Article 168 – public health, Article 169 – consumer protection, Article 114) refer to either GAIEB or EGE activity (Busby et al. 2008, 837). For example, Article 168 on public health provides that the European Commission shall take any useful initiative to promote the coordination among mem-ber states, particularly initiatives aiming at the establishment of guidelines and indica-tors. There is no reference to any EAB such as EGE. Thus, its legal basis seems to rest only on the two EC Decisions of 1998 and 200022 related to its mandate and on the EC Decision of 2005, which directly provide the EGE remit.23 And it is astonishing that no article of the EU Treaties mentions a so strategic organ of the EU. This uncertainty reduces de facto the possibilities of control on its activity, giving the EGE and the EU institutions responsible for it (i.e. the President of the Commission) an extensive au-tonomy (Busby et al. 2008, 838). As the requirements of its transparency and independency were so fragile, the EGE remit was changed several times by enlarging tasks24, members’ competences25, and membership26, and by introducing tighter dependency relations with the EU institutions (Plomer 2008, 843-844). These changes hide the existing conflict between the Euro-pean Parliament and the Commission on the role and functions of a key committee of 21 The group was instituted in 1991 with the name of Group of Advisers on the Ethical Implications of Biotechnology to the European Commission. In 1998, it took the name of the European Group on Eth-ics in Science and New Technologies (EGE). 22 Commission Decision dated 16 December 1997 (SEC(97) 2404) creating the European Group on Ethics in Science and New Technologies (EGE); Commission Decision dated 26 March 2001 (C(2001) 691) concerning the amendment to the remit of the European Group on Ethics in Science and New Tech-nologies. 23 Criticisms on the legal basis of the EGE are also in Plomer 2008, 853. 24 In 1998, its mandate was modified by including the tasks of consulting and reporting back to European Parliament. 25 In 1998, the disciplines of sociology and informatics were included. 26 With this last modification, the members went from six to twelve.
  • 9. A Rights-Based Model of Governance 111 the Union. The main modification occurred with the 2000 mandate (subsequently con-firmed in 200527) when the EGE secretariat was integrated in the Bureau of the Euro-pean Policy Advisors reporting directly to the President of the Commission and acting under his authority. In this moment a weighty legacy, in terms of independency and transparency of the work of the ethical committee of EU, was created. When the presupposition of its action was set under the control of the Presidency of the Commission, the increasing influence acquired by EGE was thus tightly inter-twined with its vulnerability in front of improper pressures of given political lobbies. Leaving aside the instance of the 1998 Directive28, wherein the clause of ordre public has been created by following two precedent EGE opinions29, the case of the stem cell research is emblematic. In March 2005, an EP resolution30 intervened, calling for the principle of subsidiarity to be applied also to the funding of embryonic stem cell re-search, leaving instead to the member states the responsibility of deciding which re-search should be funded. Immediately after, in September 2005, some members of the Parliament requested in a letter that the President of the Commission should exercise his influence to ensure that funding for research on human embryos would not take place under the Seventh Framework Programme (FP7) (Plomer 2008, 847). In 2007, the EGE adopted the opinion n. 22 on ethical aspects of FP731, drafting a set ethical indications that, then, were consequently included in the FP7. Accordingly, the FP7 prescribed that the research funded should comply with the fundamental ethical princi-ples as reflected in the Charter of fundamental rights of the EU (Plomer 2008, 850)32, taking, then, into account also the opinions of the EGE nearby the other sources of law. Thus legal and ethical norms contribute de facto directly to the EU regulation.33 Ac-cording to FP7 the research aiming at the cloning for reproductive purposes, those intending to modify the genetic heritage of human beings, those intending to create human embryos solely for the purpose of research or for the purpose of stem cell pro-curement, including by means of somatic cell nuclear transfer, should not be funded. Moreover, in regard to the derivation of human embryonic stem cells, institutions, organizations, and researchers are subject to strict licensing and control by members states involved. Thus, the ethical control was further implemented by the legal frame-work of the member states. 27 Commission Decision dated 11 May 2005 (2005/383/EC) on the renewal of the mandate of the Euro-pean Group on Ethics in Science and New Technologies. 28 Article 37 of Directive 98/44 on the legal protection of biotechnological inventions [1998] OJ L213/13 excludes from patentability those inventions ‘where their commercial exploitation offends ordre public or morality’. 29 Opinion n° 3 - 30/09/1993 - Opinion on ethical questions arising from the Commission proposal for a Council directive for legal protection of biotechnological inventions; opinion n° 8 - 25/09/1996 - Ethi-cal aspects of patenting inventions involving elements of human origin. See Busby, Hervey, and Mohr 2008. 30 Resolution of the European Parliament on the trade in of human egg cells RC B6-0199/2005 of 10 March 2005, para. 10. 31 Opinion n° 22 - 13/07/2007 – Recommendation on the ethical review of hESC FP7 research projects. 32 See also Opinion n° 22, II.4.2. 33 With regard to an analogous influence of EGE on FP5, see Salter and Jones 2002, 812.
  • 10. 112 A Rights-Based Model of Governance 4. The Blurring of Ethics and Law The process of shaping and designing the current scientific and technological develop-ments in ethical terms made the EGE a decisive tool of allocating research funding, giving it an extraordinary political power under the sole control of the President of the Commission. This strategic role assumed by ethics at the Community level has in-creased by the tendency of blurring ethical and legal matters (Plomer 2008, 845-846; Mohr et al. 2012, 106). The beginning of the process of blurring of ethics and law can be located in the opinion n° 8 wherein GAIEB draws the concept of ‘ethics’ widely, including technical legal concerns. Indeed, with regard to the question of the patent-ability of human gene sequences, it added to the legal reasons of non-patentability some ethical concerns relating the non-commercialization of the human body (Busby et al. 2008, 812). The above-mentioned Directive 98/44 with its ordre public clause is, in this framework, a clear sign of this process. This phenomenon is also enlarged by the semantic structuring of the EGE opinions that may contain a mixture of ethical and legal principles in a variety of sources (both at regional and universal level) often with-out detailed analysis of their legal status, contents, attending jurisprudence, and critical literature (Plomer 2008, 845-846). This approach, which makes human rights balanceable with other pubic interests of the state, appears questionable from the standpoint of the human rights law.34 In this regard, an example could be the opinion n° 20 on ICT implants35, where the ethical principles to be considered are drawn from legal texts of international law mixing hu-man rights (freedom, equality, privacy etc.), basic concepts of human rights law (dig-nity), and other legal principles of international law (precautionary principle), considered indifferently at the same level without any study of their ethical background, attending jurisprudence, and implications.36 An analogous tendency can be also seen in its opinion on nanomedicine, which appears more mature but with the same confusion between ethical and legal fields.37 This weakness in framing the texture of its opinions also risks blurring the roles of ethics and law, whereas they should be distinct to be more efficacious. This phenomenon leads progressively to imposing ethics as a parallel source of law within the EU, weakening the efficacy of the regulatory tools and eroding the base of the public trust. In this regard, the ‘ethicization’ phenomenon risks compromising the participatory characteristic of EU governance. In this framework, human rights see their forces ineffectively dispersed while they could be used differently, inasmuch as they are a strong pole of motivation. No content, except that given by the ethical reflec-tion, can be found in them. They are semantically empty and therefore only ethics can fill them. The action of the European courts on human rights is, in this conceptual 34 In fact, within the ECHR human rights are derogable only in time of war and other public emergence (Article 15) and can be restricted only in the cases permitted by the Convention (Article 18). 35 Opinion n° 20 - 16/03/2005 - Ethical aspects of ICT Implants in the Human Body. A different approach we can find in its Draft Charter on Fundamental Rights of European Union, Brussels, June 15, 2000, available at http://www.europarl.europa.eu/charter/civil/pdf/con233_en.pdf [accessed May 17, 2012]. In this document, the ethical implication of the legal shaping of the rights of the EU is considered with at-tention. 36 Ibid., para. 4: Legal background. On this criticism, see Plomer 2008, 845-846. On the contrary, an excellent examination of fundamental rights from the legal standpoint can be found in the EGE’s draft of the EU Charter. See EGE 2000. 37 Opinion n° 21 - 17/01/2007 - Ethical aspects of nanomedicine.
  • 11. A Rights-Based Model of Governance 113 framework, only a sign that, from the legal standpoint, would have no sense (i.e. it is totally discretional). Their normativity is reduced only to the texts affirming them and, therefore, separated from their practice and application, human rights are completely indeterminate (MacIntyre 1981). What does human dignity mean? Only ethics can say, not the law. Enclosed into mere ethical reflection, human rights lose the possibility of affecting the European governance with the strength of individuals’ positions and inter-ests, becoming a mere moral argument of an opaque (and unfortunately weak) rhetoric (Ruggiu 2012b, 172).38 Conclusions The model of governance of the EU has elected ethics as the engine for boosting inno-vation (Kearnes and Rip 2009). The virtue of ethics should permit, in fact, thanks to its elasticity, facing the challenges of innovation on a case-by-case basis and involving more stakeholders in the governance processes, augmenting its efficacy. Yet instead, this fact weakens the efficacy of some regulatory instruments such as human rights, by empting them and letting them being absorbed into ethical reflexivity. This overflow-ing role is also witnessed by the process of blurring of ethics and law that characterizes the EGE activity (Plomer 2008). In the current model, we can notice that there are already antibodies to face these impairments. In fact, within the EU model there are some principles that anticipate the choices of decision makers. Those principles are the fundamental rights and they correspond substantially to human rights. They are largely implemented by some regulatory texts (e.g. the EU Charter and the ECHR) and the jurisprudence that is, at the metagovernance level, an actor operating in the framework of other governmental structures. Fundamental rights work as ‘normative anchor points’ by setting in advance the goals on which governance should be inspired (von Schomberg 2011; 2013). In other words, they work in an anticipatory dimension within European governance. With the entry into force of the EU Charter in the beginning of 2010, these ‘anchor points’ have acquired binding force and have become the ‘polar star’ of the EU governance. They are present both in the hard law instruments (i.e. the EU Charter as implemented by the CJEU) and in the soft law instruments (e.g. declarations, recommendations, the codes of conduct, guidelines, and so forth) and they also contribute to involving stakeholders (Pariotti and Ruggiu 2012). They are the fulcrum of this participatory model that, in-deed, uses them to shape both soft law and self-regulatory tools of governance (mainly guidelines and codes of conduct). In this context, the mechanism of self-coordination between the Council of Europe judicial body (i.e. the Strasbourg Court) and that of the EU (i.e. the CJEU) can help to strengthen the effective penetration of fundamental rights into EU law (Spielmann 1999; Bultrini 2004), especially with regard to emerging technologies aimed at HE wherein the pros and cons of the two systems are equivalent (Pariotti and Ruggiu 2012, 162). It is the case with personal dignity and the self-determination principle, which have great importance in the discourse on HE. 38 An example of this rhetorical use of human rights can be seen in the EU code of conduct for responsible nanosciences and nanotechnologies research, wherein human rights are referred to only in generic man-ner, as a whole (e.g. point 4.1.17 of the guidelines), without focusing the specific individual positions singularly affected by technological development (e.g. the right to health, self-determination principle, integrity, and so forth). See Ruggiu 2012b, 170.
  • 12. 114 A Rights-Based Model of Governance For this reason, within the great puzzle of European governance, ethical tools should also address the interconnections existing in the composite framework that con-tributes to producing the whole system of governance. In this framework, human rights are certainly interesting tools that will play an increasing role within European govern-ance, and, in part, also thanks to the jurisprudence of the main two European courts (i.e. ECtHR and CJEU), they are already doing so. But they need to be correctly framed, alongside ethics, in order to avoid any overlapping between the two fields. A clearer vision of the roles and functions of law and ethics could empower the respective tools and would permit the development of a model of governance more coordinated and aware of the productive dimension of human rights in building governance in Europe. In other words, this model, already implemented by existing regulation in Europe, in the EU and in the Council of Europe, is the rights-based model of governance. References Allhoff, F., Lin, P., Moor, J. and Weckert, J. (2010) ‘Ethics of Human Enhancement: 25 Questions & An-swers’, Studies in Ethics, Law, and Technology 4 (1): 1-39. Andorno, R. (2009) ‘Human Dignity and Human Rights as a Common Ground of Bioethics’, Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, 34(3): 223-240. Beghé-Loreti, A. and Marin, L. (1999) ‘La tutela della persona umana nella sperimentazione clinica dei farmaci e il ruolo dei comitati etici tra regole internazionali di disciplina e normativa italiana’, Rivista internazionale dei diritti dell’uomo. Atti del Seminario internazionale Diritti dell’uomo e profili etnico-religiosi: una prospettiva globale (Milano, 3-4, dicembre 1998) 12: 641-675. Beyleveld, D. and Brownsword, R. (2004) Human Dignity in Bioethics and Biolaw, Oxford: Oxford Univer-sity Press. Brownsword, R. (2008) Rights, Regulation and the Technological Revolution, Oxford: Oxford University Press. Bultrini, A. (2004) La pluralità dei meccanismi di tutela dei diritti dell’uomo in Europa. Torino: Giappichelli. Busby, H., Hervey, T. and Mohr, A. (2008) ‘Ethical EU Law ? The Influence of the European Group on Ethics in Science and Technologies’, European Law Review 33: 803-832 Francioni, F. (2007) ‘Genetic Resources, Biotechnology and Human Rights’. In F. Francioni (ed.) Biotech-nologies and International Human Rights, Oxford: Hart Publishing. EGE (2000) Citizens’ Rights and New Technologies: A European Challenge. Report of the European Group on Ethics in Sciences and New Technologies on the Charter on Fundamental Rights Related to Techno-logical Innovation as Requested by President Prodi on February 3, 2000, Brussels, May 23, 2000. Available at: http://www.europarl.europa.eu/charter/civil/pdf/con233_en.pdf (accessed August 28, 2013). EGE (2009) Ethics of Synthetic Biology, Opinion n° 25, Brussels, 17 November 2009. Available at http://ec. europa.eu/bepa/european-group-ethics/docs/opinion25_en.pdf. Hermerén, G. (2009) Accountability, Democracy and Ethics Committee, Law, Innovation and Technology 1(2): 153-170. Jacobs, F., White, R., and Ovey, C. (2002) The European Convention on Human Rights, 3rd ed., Oxford: Oxford University Press. Jacobson (2007) ‘Human Dignity and Health: A Review’, Social Science and Medicine 64: 292-302. Jessop, B. (2003) ‘Governance and Meta-governance: On Reflexivety, Requisite Variety and Requisite Irony’. In H. P. Bang (ed.) Governance as Social and Political Communication, Manchester: Manches-ter University Press. Kearnes, M.B. and Rip, A. (2009) ‘The Emerging Governance Landscape of Nanotechnolog’. In S. Gammel, S. Losch, A. Nordmann, (eds.) Jenseits Von Regulierung: Zum Politischen Umgang Mit Der Nanotech-nologie, Berlin: Akademische Verlagsgesellschaft. Lengley, A. and Parviz, B., (2008) ‘Multipurpose Integrated Active Contact Lenses’, The Neuromorphic Engineer, http://www.ine-news.org/pdf/0056/0056.pdf Lyall, C. and Tait, J. (2005) ‘Shifting Policy Debates and the Implications for Governance’. In C. Lyall and J. Tait (eds) New Modes of Governance: Developing an Integrated Policy Approach to Science, Technol-ogy, Risk and the Environment, Aldershot: Ashgate.MacIntyre, A. (1981) After Virtue: A Study in Mo-ral Theory, Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.
  • 13. A Rights-Based Model of Governance 115 MASIS (Monitoring Activities of Science in Society in Europe Experts Group) (2009) Challenging Futures of Science in Society. Emerging Trends and Cutting-Edge Issues, Luxembourg: European Commission, Directorate-General for Research. Mohr, A., Busby, H., Hervey, T. and Dingwall, R. (2012) ‘Mapping the Role of Official Bioethics Advice in the Governance of Biotechnologies in the EU: the European Group on Ethics’ Opinion on Commercial Cord Blood Banking’, Science and Public Studies 39: 105-117. Pariotti, E., (2007) ‘”Effetto orizzontale” dei diritti umani e imprese transnazionali nello spazio europeo’. In I. Trujillo, F. Viola (eds.), Identità, diritti, ragione pubblica in Europa, Bologna: Il Mulino. Pariotti, E. (2011) Normatività giuridica e governance delle tecnologie emergenti. In G. Guerra, A. Muratorio, M. Piccinni, E. Pariotti and D. Ruggiu (eds.) Forme di responsabilità, regolazione e nanotecnologie, Bologna: Il Mulino. Pariotti, E. (2013) Diritti umani: concetto, teoria, evoluzione, Padova: CEDAM. Pariotti, E. and Ruggiu, D. (2012) ‘Governing Nanotechnologies in Europe: Human Rights, Soft Law, and Corporate Social Responsibility’. In H. Van Lente, C. Coenen, K. Konrad, L. Krabbenborg, C. Milburn, F. Seifert, F. Thoreau and B. Zülsdorf (eds.) Little by Little: Expansions of Nanoscience and Emerging Technologies, Heidelberg: IOS Press/AKA-Verlag.. Plomer, A. (2008) ‘The European Group on Ethics: Law, Politics, and the Limits of Moral Integration in Europe’, European Law Journal 14(6): 839-859. Raz, J. (2010) ‘Human Rights in the Emerging World Order’, Transnational Legal Theory 1: 37-47. Roco, M. (2006) ‘Progress in Governance of Converging Technologies Integrated from the Nanoscale’, Annals of the New York Academy of Science 1093: 1-23 Ruggiu, D. (2012a) ‘Synthetic Biology and Human Rights in the European Context: Health and Environment in Comparison of the EU and the Council of Europe Regulatory Framework’, Biotechnology Law Re-port 31(4): 337-355. Ruggiu, D. (2012b) Diritti e temporalità. I diritti umani nell’era delle tecnologie emergenti, Bologna: Il Mulino. Salter, B. and Jones, M. (2002) ‘Human Genetic Technologies, European Governance and the Politics of Bioethics’, Nature Reviews Genetics 3(10): 808-814. Schummer, J. (2007) ‘Identifying Ethical Issues in Nanotechnologies’. In A. M. J. Hanke ten Have (ed.) Nanotechnologies, Ethics and Politics, Paris: UNESCO. Scott, J. and Trubek, D.M. (2002) ‘Mind the Gap: Law and New Approaches to Governance in the European Union’, European Law Journal 8(1): 1-18. Shahinpoor, M. (2011) ‘Biomimetic Robotic Venus Flytrap (Dionaea muscipula Ellis) Made with Ionic Polymer Metal Composites’, Bioinspiration & Biomimetics 6: 046004. Spielmann D. (1999) ‘Human Rights Case Law in the Strasbourg and Luxembourg Courts: Conflitcs, Incon-sistencies, and Complementarities’. In P. Alston (ed.), The EU and Human Rights, Oxford, Oxford University Press. Stoke, G. (1998) ‘Governance as Theory: Five Propositions’ JSSJ 155: 17-28. Svrivastava, D. P., Woolfrey, K. M., Feng, L., Brandon, N. J. and Penzes, P. (2010) ‘Estrogen Receptor ! Activity Modulates Synaptic Signalling and Structure’, The Journal of Neuroscience 30(40): 13454- 13460. Tallacchini, M. (2009) ‘Governing by Values. EU Ethics: Soft Tool, Hard Effects’, Minerva 47: 281-306. Viola, F. and Zaccaria, G. (2001) Diritto e interpretazione. Lineamenti di teoria ermeneutica del diritto, Roma- Bari: Laterza. von Schomberg, R. (2011) ‘Prospects for Technology Assessment in a Framework of Responsible Research and Innovation. In M. Susseldorp and R. Beecrift (eds.) Technikfolgen abschätzen lehren: Bildungspo-tenziale transdisziplinärer Methoden, Wiesbaden: Vs Verlag. von Schonberg, R. (2013, forthcoming) A vision of Responsible Innovation. in R. Owen, M. Heintz, and J. Bessant (eds.) Responsible Innovation: Managing the Responsible Emergence of Science and Innova-tion in Society, London: John Wiley.