Programming modulo representations
Correctness by Construction Research Project
Dr M Benini
Università degli Studi dell’Insubria
marco.benini@uninsubria.it
1st October 2014
A bizarre idea to discuss
The aim of this talk is to show, through an elementary example, how one
can change the point of view on (functional) programming.
The idea has a philosophical motivation: is it possible to conceive a
programming system which does not allow to inspect its output and, at the
same time, is able to ensure that the result of a computation is correct?
This talk will provide a positive answer, but its consequences are still
work-in-progress.
(2 of 18)
Concrete and abstract lists
Usually, lists are defined as the elements of the free algebra over the
signature h{E,L} , {nil :L,cons :E £L!L}i.
And, in the standard practice of traditional programming, they are
represented as follows:
ç a cell is a record in the computer memory which contains two fields:
ä the head which is an element in E;
ä the tail of the list which is a list;
ç in turn, a list is a pointer (memory address) to a cell;
ç the empty list, nil, becomes the null pointer.
Thus, cons is a procedure that allocates a cell, fills the head with its first
parameter, and the tail with the second one, finally returning its address.
Evidently, up to the ability to read computer memory, the result of any
computation on lists can be inspected.
(3 of 18)
Concrete manipulation of a list
As an example of program, we consider the concatenate function.
Its specification is: “Given the lists [x1, . . . ,xn] and [y1, . . . ,ym], concatenate
has to return the list [x1, . . . ,xn,y1, . . . ,ym]”.
Usually, it is implemented as
concatenate(x,y) ´
if x Æ nil then return y
else q :Æ x
while q6Æ nil do
p :Æ q
q :Æ q!tail
p!tail :Æ y
return x
(4 of 18)
Correctness
The previous algorithm is correct. In fact, when x Æ nil, it returns y,
satisfying the specification.
When x6Æ nil, x Æ [x1, . . . ,xn]. So, at the end of the i-th iteration step,
p Æ [xi , . . . ,xn] and q Æ [xiÅ1, . . . ,xn], as it is immediate to prove by induction.
Also, the cycle terminates after n iterations, and p Æ [xn].
But, in the concrete representation of x, p!tail must be nil and the
assignment p!tail :Æ y substitutes nil with y. So x becomes
[x1, . . . ,xn,y1, . . . ,ym], as required.
The proof sketched above uses in an essential way the concrete
representation of the x list, because the algorithm uses “list surgery”.
The algorithm, as one deduces from the correctness proof, computes in
O(jxj) steps, and uses a constant amount of memory, apart the one used to
represent the input.
(5 of 18)
A functional derivation
Dropping list surgery, we can use the abstract formalisation of lists directly:
concatenate(x,y) ´
if x Æ nil then return y
else return cons (hdx) (concatenate(tl x,y))
where hd and tl return the head and the tail of its argument, respectively.
Of course, this is a functional program, and it is justified by the following
reasoning, which can be immediately converted into a formal correctness
proof by induction on the structure of x:
1. we want that concatenate([x1, . . . ,xn], [y1, . . . ,ym]) Æ [x1, . . . ,xn,y1, . . . ,ym],
2. as before, if x Æ nil, the result is just y
3. when x6Æ nil, concatenate([x1, . . . ,xn], [y1, . . . ,ym]) yields the same result
as cons x1 (concatenate([x2, . . . ,xn], [y1, . . . ,ym]));
4. in the line above, the recursive application decreases the length of the
first argument, so recursion terminates after n steps, yielding the result.
(6 of 18)
Recursion versus induction
In the functional implementation of concatenate, we may interpret the
recursive schema as the computational counterpart of an inductive schema.
It is immediate to see that such an inductive schema becomes the skeleton
of the correctness proof. So, the functional program “carries” with itself its
proof of correctness, in some sense.
Usually, the functional implementation of concatenate is regarded as
inefficient because it recursively constructs a number of intermediate lists
before yielding the final results. ¡
¢ That is, the functional program computes in
O(jxj) steps, but it uses O2jxjmemory cells in a plain implementation of
the language.
To inspect the result, we need to know that nil and cons are the
constructors of the data type of lists, a piece of knowledge that is shared
between the user and the programmer.
(7 of 18)
Abstracting over lists
We formalised a list [x1, . . . ,xm] as cons x1 (cons x2 (. . . (cons xm nil) . . . )). We
can use a slightly different representation1:
¸n,c. c x1 (c x2 (. . . (c xm n) . . . )) .
The key idea is to abstract over the structure of the data type, making it
part of the representation of the datum.
Alternatively, we can interpret this representation A as the abstract datum,
and the concrete one, C can be obtained by passing the instances of the
constructors to A.
For example, the standard formalisation is obtained by (Anil cons).
1As far as I know, the general algorithm to derive such a representation is due to
Böhm and Berarducci, and it can be traced back to Church. But the paper of Böhm and
Berarducci is subtle as it relies on a typed ¸-system.
(8 of 18)
Abstracting one step further
In fact, it is possible, by assuming that the ¸-calculus (type theory) we are
using has pairs, to abstract a bit further, so to completely hide the data
type. Instead of writing [x1, . . . ,xm] as
¸n,c. c x1 (c x2 (. . . (c xm n) . . . )) ,
we may substitute the constructors with the data type a, which is a 2-tuple,
the first element being the concrete representation for nil, the second being
the concrete representation for cons:
¸a. ¼2 a x1 (¼2 a x2 (. . . (¼2 a xm (¼1 a)) . . . )) ,
where ¼1 and ¼2 are the standard projections.
In this way, the programmer does not know how the list is concretely
represented, but simply that the first element of a is how to interpret nil and
the second element of a is how to represent cons.
(9 of 18)
Interpreting abstract lists
An abstract list can be thought of as representing a term in the first-order
logical language with the equality relation symbol, and the signature of the
data type of lists.
The ¸-term standing for the abstract list realises the mapping from the
logical term — the list, the body of the abstraction — into some model,
which is specified when we apply to the ¸-term the way to interpret the
function symbols, which, in turn, are not specified.
If we fix this point of view, we can write a “correct by construction”
implementation of concatenate:
concatenate ´ ¸x,y,a. x
®
.
(y a) , (¼2 a)
(10 of 18)
Correctness by construction I
concatenate ´ ¸x,y,a. x
(y a) , (¼2 a)
®
It is worth explaining the construction of this program:
1. it is a function, which takes two argument x and y;
2. it returns an abstract list, so a ¸-term of the form ¸a. L, with L a logical
term in the language of lists, the constructors represented as projections
from the signature a;
3. the y abstract list gets interpreted in the same model as the result of
concatenate — and this is rendered by (y a);
4. the x abstract list gets interpreted in a model which has the same
interpretation for cons, (¼2 a), but it interprets nil as the ‘concrete’ y.
We should remark that, in fact, this abstract implementation is, in essence,
the very same algorithm we have shown in the beginning, deprived from the
irrelevant details about the concrete data structure of lists. So, it is an
efficient functional implementation.
(11 of 18)
Correctness by construction II
concatenate ´ ¸x,y,a. x
(y a) , (¼2 a)
®
The above definition is a direct coding of the explanation. In turn, the
explanation can be converted into a correctness proof by observing that
ç the structure depicted in point (4) is a model for the theory of lists;
ç there is a mapping that preserves the meaning between the standard term
model and the model above;
ç this mapping is just the function concatenate.
The idea behind this proof is that the function concatenate, intended as a
program, is nothing but a morphism between models of the same theory.
A non-evident aspect of the explanation of concatenate is that it correctly
operates in any model for the theory of lists.
(12 of 18)
One program, many meanings
For example, natural numbers, described as the structure generated by zero
and successor, are a model for lists: cons ´ ¸e, l. suc l and nil ´ 0. And
concatenate becomes just the usual addition.
For example, interpreting cons as the Cartesian product and nil as the
terminal object in a category with products, we get another model for lists.
And concatenate becomes just the Cartesian product of two products.
For example, interpreting cons as function application and nil as the identity
function, we get another model for lists. And concatenate becomes function
composition.
And, in all these cases, the programmer is not aware of what his program is
actually computing. But, still, as far as he assumes that there is morphism
between the standard representation of lists and the intended concrete
structure the program will operate on, he will be able to prove that his
program is correct.
(13 of 18)
Interpretations and computing
Suppose to have three actors: the real user of the program; the programmer;
and a malicious user of the program.
Since the real user can invoke the program by providing the inputs x and y,
but not the concrete interpretation, he will obtain an abstract result which is
a program that takes as input just the concrete representation a, something
he can use locally and privately.
The programmer knows that the purpose of the program is to concatenate
lists, and he is able to write a correct implementation, even if he does not
know how lists are concretely represented. So, he cannot inspect the output
of the user, but he is able to test the program in the usual way by employing
a standard representation for lists.
The malicious user, who wants to steal the result of the real user, can
inspect x and y, as well as the program, but he does not know a, as the real
user does not provide it. So he can inspect the abstract result, but he will be
unable to understand its meaning in the world of the real user.
(14 of 18)
Generalising
ç Does it work only for lists?
The theory behind the abstract representation for data types has been
developed by Böhm and Berarducci, and it directly applies to all the data
structures that can be formalised as free algebras of terms over a
first-order signature. This holds for a large number of the elementary
structures which are used in the current practice of programming. In a
similar way, co-inductive data structures can be modelled as well.
For data structures which are not free (co-)algebras, there are still some
open problems, but, to some extent, they can be modelled in the same
spirit — essentially, most data types used in programming are quotients
of free (co-)algebras, so the inductive pattern still works, that is,
recursion on the structure of the free (co-)algebra is a correct way to
perform computation, even if not necessarily efficient.
ç Does it work in a “real” programming language?
As far as the programming language supports the dynamic creation of
functions, e.g., by providing abstraction, the technique can be
immediately used. This is the case for any functional language.
(15 of 18)
A philosophical remark
Any program which takes as input the description of the data types it uses,
in the abstract sense we introduced earlier, automatically computes modulo
a concrete representation.
Nothing prevents to use arbitrary representations: as far as one can provide
a morphism from the free (co-)algebra of terms to the intended model, the
result will be correctly computed.
Using a bizarre representation hides the result to the programmer and to any
other user who does not know the morphism that maps the abstract result
into its concrete representation. So, this technique, in principle, may provide
a way to perform anonymous correct computations.
On another side, nothing prevents from using a non-computable concrete
representation: in this way, the result cannot be inspected even by the user,
although he perfectly knows, by means of a mathematical proof, that it is
correct. So, inspectability and computability are distinct concepts and, in
particular, the latter does not imply the former.
(16 of 18)
Conclusions
In the previous slide there is a hidden assumption: that the logical theory
has a canonical model which can be transformed into a any other model via
a suitable mapping.
This is not true in general. So the presented point of view can be stretched
only when considering logical theories having such a classifying model —
which is the case for free (co-)algebras of terms, for example.
In my work started here, in Leeds, I’ve shown a semantics for first-order
intuitionistic logical theories, based on a categorical setting, which has
classifying models. So, every such a theory could, in principle, be regarded
as a “data type” in the sense of this talk.
Of course, much work has to be done... so any hint, suggestion, critique,
question is mostly welcome!
(17 of 18)