Your SlideShare is downloading. ×
0
Bassham3 powerpoint lecturenotes_ch08
Bassham3 powerpoint lecturenotes_ch08
Bassham3 powerpoint lecturenotes_ch08
Bassham3 powerpoint lecturenotes_ch08
Bassham3 powerpoint lecturenotes_ch08
Bassham3 powerpoint lecturenotes_ch08
Bassham3 powerpoint lecturenotes_ch08
Bassham3 powerpoint lecturenotes_ch08
Bassham3 powerpoint lecturenotes_ch08
Bassham3 powerpoint lecturenotes_ch08
Bassham3 powerpoint lecturenotes_ch08
Bassham3 powerpoint lecturenotes_ch08
Bassham3 powerpoint lecturenotes_ch08
Bassham3 powerpoint lecturenotes_ch08
Bassham3 powerpoint lecturenotes_ch08
Upcoming SlideShare
Loading in...5
×

Thanks for flagging this SlideShare!

Oops! An error has occurred.

×
Saving this for later? Get the SlideShare app to save on your phone or tablet. Read anywhere, anytime – even offline.
Text the download link to your phone
Standard text messaging rates apply

Bassham3 powerpoint lecturenotes_ch08

1,548

Published on

Published in: Education, Technology, Spiritual
0 Comments
0 Likes
Statistics
Notes
  • Be the first to comment

  • Be the first to like this

No Downloads
Views
Total Views
1,548
On Slideshare
0
From Embeds
0
Number of Embeds
1
Actions
Shares
0
Downloads
39
Comments
0
Likes
0
Embeds 0
No embeds

Report content
Flagged as inappropriate Flag as inappropriate
Flag as inappropriate

Select your reason for flagging this presentation as inappropriate.

Cancel
No notes for slide

Transcript

  • 1. Critical Thinking Ch 8 Evaluating Arguments
  • 2. Evaluating Arguments <ul><li>Once you have an argument summarized/standardized, you need to evaluate it to see if you are forced to accept the conclusion. </li></ul><ul><li>There are two main questions to ask when doing so: </li></ul><ul><ul><li>Is the argument a “good argument”? </li></ul></ul><ul><ul><li>Are the premises acceptable? </li></ul></ul>
  • 3. When is an argument a good argument? <ul><li>What “good argument” does not mean: </li></ul><ul><li>“ agrees with my views” </li></ul><ul><ul><li>The attitude that only arguments that agree with your viewpoints are good is extremely close-minded. </li></ul></ul><ul><li>“ persuasive argument” </li></ul><ul><ul><li>People aren’t always smart and can be persuaded by “eloquent speech” (and be confused by solid reasoning). </li></ul></ul><ul><ul><li>Hitler was more persuasive than Churchill, but that doesn’t mean that Hitler’s arguments were better. </li></ul></ul><ul><li>“ well-written/spoken” </li></ul><ul><ul><li>Although it’s easier to tell whether an argument is good if it is well written, being well written doesn’t make it good. Clarity, eloquence and organization can all occur in the presence of logical mistakes. </li></ul></ul>
  • 4. When is an argument a good argument? <ul><li>What “good argument” does mean. </li></ul><ul><li>It must, at the least, be either deductively sound (valid with true premises) or inductively cogent (strong with true premises). </li></ul><ul><li>But it will also need to be clear… </li></ul><ul><ul><li>An argument isn’t good unless it is understandable. </li></ul></ul><ul><li>… precise… </li></ul><ul><ul><li>One needs to avoid equivocation and use exact language. </li></ul></ul><ul><li>… the premises need to be relevant… </li></ul><ul><ul><li>Arguments with a lot of irrelevant material can’t be said to be good arguments. </li></ul></ul><ul><li>… consistent… </li></ul><ul><ul><li>Arguments that contain logical contradictions commit the fallacy of inconsistency. </li></ul></ul><ul><li>… complete… </li></ul><ul><ul><li>If an arguer ignores facts relevant to the conclusion at hand, we can’t say the argument is good (it doesn’t account for relevant objections). </li></ul></ul><ul><li>… and fair. </li></ul><ul><ul><li>An argument can’t be good if it hastily dismissed objections. </li></ul></ul><ul><li>In a nut shell, a good argument embodies all the good qualities of critical thinking. (See guidelines on p. 206.) </li></ul>
  • 5. When is it reasonable to accept a premise? <ul><li>Arguments always contain premises, and—while some premises will have support from other premises—there will always be some premises that are mere assumptions (claims made by the arguer). If the argument is valid/ strong, its soundness/cogency will turn on whether these assumptions are true. So how can we tell if we should accept them? </li></ul><ul><li>The Principle of Rational Acceptance : It is reasonable to accept a claim if… </li></ul><ul><li>(1) The claim does not conflict with personal experience that we have no good reason to doubt it. </li></ul><ul><li>(2) The claim does not conflict with background beliefs that we have no good reason to doubt. </li></ul><ul><li>(3) The claim comes from a credible source. </li></ul>
  • 6. Does the claim conflict with your experience? <ul><li>In general, you should favor the testimony of your own sight (and other senses) over the testimony of others. </li></ul><ul><li>If someone tells you her Doberman is gentle as a kitten, but you’ve seen him attack many people, you should probably not believe that the Doberman is gentle. </li></ul><ul><li>But it should be noted that your senses are not indubitable (un-doubtable). They can be mistaken for any number of reasons. </li></ul><ul><ul><li>Bad physical conditions ( e.g., poor lighting) </li></ul></ul><ul><ul><li>Sensory impairment ( e.g., poor vision) </li></ul></ul><ul><ul><li>Observer impairment ( e.g., drunk) </li></ul></ul><ul><ul><li>Unreliable measuring instruments </li></ul></ul><ul><ul><li>Bad memory </li></ul></ul>
  • 7. How reliable are your senses?
  • 8. How reliable are your senses?
  • 9. How reliable are your senses? <ul><li>Just how are </li></ul><ul><li>are you supposed to </li></ul><ul><li>to count how many times </li></ul><ul><li>“are” appears in this quote? </li></ul>
  • 10. Does the claim conflict with background beliefs <ul><li>Background beliefs: convictions held—usually assumed without question—that inform most of the other beliefs that we have. </li></ul><ul><ul><li>e.g., It snowed in Las Vegas last July 4 th . </li></ul></ul><ul><ul><ul><li>This seems to contradict our background belief that it doesn’t snow in deserts during the summer. </li></ul></ul></ul><ul><ul><li>e.g., George W. Bush is a robot. </li></ul></ul><ul><ul><ul><li>This contradicts our background belief that people aren’t robots. </li></ul></ul></ul><ul><li>But it is important to note that even background beliefs should be subject to revision if sufficient evidence is presented against them (don’t be dogmatic about any beliefs you have). </li></ul>
  • 11. Does the claim come from a credible source? <ul><li>Much of what we believe is based on the testimony of sources. </li></ul><ul><li>We saw a lot about this in chapter 6 (more is in chapter 12). </li></ul><ul><li>To reiterate: questions to ask to determine source credibility: </li></ul><ul><ul><li>Genuine expert? Are they outside their area? Are they biased? Do they have a reason to lie? Questionable senses (were they drunk)? Are they generally reliable (is it The Enquirer? ) Right context? Can expert opinion settle the issue ( e.g., is this a moral issue)? Is it improbable? </li></ul></ul>
  • 12. Refuting Arguments <ul><li>There are two ways to refute an argument: </li></ul><ul><ul><li>Show that a premise—or a critical group of premises—is false or dubious. </li></ul></ul><ul><ul><li>Show that the conclusion does not follow from the premises. </li></ul></ul>
  • 13. Showing Premises False <ul><li>If a premise is critical to an argument, showing it false will refute the argument. </li></ul><ul><ul><li>(1) All presidents live in the White House. (2) Paris Hilton is President. So, (3) Paris Hilton lives in the White House. </li></ul></ul><ul><ul><li>Showing (2) to be false is sufficient to refute the argument. </li></ul></ul><ul><li>However, showing false an irrelevant premise will not refute the argument. </li></ul><ul><ul><li>(1) All circles are squares. (2) All squares are rectangles. (3) All rectangles are geometrical figures. (4) So, all squares are geometrical figures. </li></ul></ul><ul><ul><li>Showing (1) is false won’t keep (2) and (3) from proving (4). </li></ul></ul><ul><li>Additionally, for refutation, the premise must be necessary (critical) </li></ul><ul><ul><li>(1) TJ is a bachelor. (2) TJ is an uncle. (3) So, TJ is a Male. </li></ul></ul><ul><ul><li>Since both (1) and (2) provide independent support for (3) falsifying only one of them will not refute the argument. </li></ul></ul>
  • 14. Showing Premises to be Dubious and other Techniques <ul><li>If one shows a critical premise to be doubtable, then one has refuted the argument (by showing it to be unconvincing). </li></ul><ul><li>Demonstrating doubt: </li></ul><ul><ul><li>Appeal to personal experience, common knowledge, or reputable source. </li></ul></ul><ul><ul><li>Note a self-contradiction (either in a single premise or between premises). </li></ul></ul><ul><ul><li>Show the premises is based on an unwarranted assumption. </li></ul></ul><ul><ul><li>Personally demonstrate its falsity or dubiousness. </li></ul></ul><ul><li>Other refutation Techniques: </li></ul><ul><ul><li>Reducing to the absurd : Show the truth of a premise would entail something clearly false (absurd). </li></ul></ul><ul><ul><li>Present a counter-example : present an exception that shows a premise false. </li></ul></ul><ul><ul><ul><li>(arguer): All 20 th Century presidents were rich. </li></ul></ul></ul><ul><ul><ul><li>(you): Harry Truman wasn’t! </li></ul></ul></ul>
  • 15. Showing That the Conclusion does Not Follow from the Premises. <ul><li>To do this, you need to show that the argument is either (a) deductively invalid or (b) inductively weak. </li></ul><ul><li>Most important questions: </li></ul><ul><ul><li>If deductive, does the conclusion follow necessarily from the premises? </li></ul></ul><ul><ul><li>Are the premises relevant (is there a fallacy)? </li></ul></ul><ul><ul><li>Are the premises sufficient to support the conclusion? </li></ul></ul><ul><ul><li>Does the argument omit any crucial countervailing evidence? </li></ul></ul>

×