Your SlideShare is downloading. ×
Hofstede and globe  the ecological fallacy
Upcoming SlideShare
Loading in...5
×

Thanks for flagging this SlideShare!

Oops! An error has occurred.

×

Saving this for later?

Get the SlideShare app to save on your phone or tablet. Read anywhere, anytime - even offline.

Text the download link to your phone

Standard text messaging rates apply

Hofstede and globe the ecological fallacy

484
views

Published on

Published in: Technology

0 Comments
1 Like
Statistics
Notes
  • Be the first to comment

No Downloads
Views
Total Views
484
On Slideshare
0
From Embeds
0
Number of Embeds
1
Actions
Shares
0
Downloads
11
Comments
0
Likes
1
Embeds 0
No embeds

Report content
Flagged as inappropriate Flag as inappropriate
Flag as inappropriate

Select your reason for flagging this presentation as inappropriate.

Cancel
No notes for slide

Transcript

  • 1. FASHION FOUNDED ON A FLAW: THEECOLOGICAL M0N0-DETERMINISTICFALLACY OFHOFSTEDE, GLOBE, TROMPENAARS, ET AL.For presentation at the IACCM AnnualConferenceRotterdam School ofManagement, Erasmus University, 20—22 June, 2013Brendan McSweeneyRoyal Holloway, University of Londonand
  • 2. What, I guess, we commonly believe• The world is not ‗flat‘ (but how might wepartition populations?)• The past matters (but we should notoverstate lock-in due to initial conditions)• Culture matters (but what is ‗it‘ and howdoes it operate?)
  • 3. Summary• The popularity of the notion of ‗nationalculture‘ largely rely on the fallacious beliefthat one or other of its depictions depictlevels lower than the national: alliances,organizations, individuals, or whatever.• But to suppose that it does is a fallacy: theecological fallacy.
  • 4. • The idea of ‗culture‘ is more easilyinvoked that defined.• I focus on one notion of culture:‗national culture‘ and as definedas ‗values‘
  • 5. • The ontological status of ‗national culture‘; itsdepiction as bi-polar value ‗dimensions‘; thevalidity of measurements of thosedimensions; and the representativeness ofsamples, have been the object ofconsiderable debate.• Here I addresses a different issue: a relianceon the ecological fallacy (Selvin, 1958).• The fallacious inference that thecharacteristics (concepts and/or metrics) ofan aggregate (historically called ‗ecological‘)level also describe those at a lowerhierarchical level or levels.
  • 6. The Ecological Fallacy
  • 7. Supposed: What is true at one sub-national space isnecessarily true at all other sub-national spaces.• Brothel (in the samecountry)• Convent
  • 8. • The objection here is not the generation of hypotheses fromecological comparisons.• Some of the recent discoveries of the causes of cancer (e.g.dietary factors) have their origin in the generation of suchhypothesis from systematic international comparisons whichwere then investigated in lower level studies (Pearce, 2000).• The objection is to the doctrinaire (and invalid) transfer ofaggregate results to lower levels i.e. to the fallaciousassumption that what characterizes, or is believed tocharacterize, entire national populations is also representativeof each sub-national population.
  • 9. • The fallacy is also sometimes called the―disaggregation error‖ (Van de Vijver &Poortinga, 2002); or ―the fallacy ofdivision‖ (Aristotle, 350BC).• An illustrative example is: the falsederivation that any Japanese is collectivistbecause Japan, it is supposed, is culturallya collectivist country.
  • 10. • The other cross level extreme is the‗atomistic fallacy‘ (also called the ‗fallacy ofcomposition‘ or the ‗reverse ecologicalfallacy‘), that is, generalizing from individualor small n data.• For a national culture example of thisfallacy, see Kets de Vries, 2001. For adiscussion of the fallacy see, Liberson, 1991.
  • 11. Generalizing from small-n’s.• Thomas beats hiswife, therefore allhusbands beat theirwives.• Hofstede‘s example ofTwelve Angry Men.
  • 12. • Across the social sciences, deductive depictions of lowerlevels have been speculatively based on a host of higherecological representations, not just the national.• For example, characteristics of lower levels have beeninferred not only from nations (aka countries) but alsofrom regions (the West; ‗Anglo-Saxon‘ countries;Asia, and so forth); religions, time periods, and―civilizations‖ (Huntington, 1996; cf. Said, 2001).• The level lower whose features are deduced from ahigher national level may be an individual, a group ofindividuals, an organization, a sector, a segment, a classor other social categorisation, a generation, a locality, aneighbourhood, an occupational or other work
  • 13. • Although the term ―ecological fallacy‖ itselfwas coined later by Selvin (1958) in hiscritique of Durkheim‘s research onsuicide, awareness of the methodologicalcrime of assuming that results derived fromaggregate data are the same as, andtherefore can be substituted for, those whichwould be obtained from individual leveldata, had been popularized earlier byRobinson who in a seminal paperdemonstrated a striking discrepancy betweenecological and individual correlation (1950).
  • 14. • For example, he showed that, the correlationbetween illiteracy and nativity (foreign-bornvs domestically born) at the individual levelwas positive (r = 0.12) while at the state levelit was negative (r = -0.53).• In short, he showed that correlationscomputed with aggregate data bear noconsistent relationship to correlations basedupon individuals (Subramanian, et al., 2009).
  • 15. • Correlation computed at the individuallevel can differ substantially not only inmagnitude but also in direction (i.e.whether positive or negative) from thosecalculated using the correspondingstatistics based on geographic areas orgroups.
  • 16. • Bond (2002) illustrates that the cross levelconflation error applies not only to culturedimension scores and directions but also to thecultural concepts or dimension labels in that the―same labels‖ are inappropriately and inaccuratelyused for ―constructs at different levels ofanalysis, individual and national, and thusconfound the two‖ (2012, p. 678).• As Firebaugh states ―The demystification of cross-level bias begins with the recognition that anaggregate variable often measures a differentconstruct at the individual level (1978, p. 560)
  • 17. • Clearly, aggregation/disaggregation leads tomisrepresentation whenever populations arenot wholly homogeneous. That point isillustrated by the joke about the statisticianwho drowned in the river whose averagedepth was 5 centimeters.• But population homogeneity does not debarthe fallacy
  • 18. Decisive or indecisive?• Schwartz (1994), citing, Zito(1975), gives the illustrativeexample of the discrepancybetween a hung jury at twolevels. As a group, a hungjury is an indecisivejury, unable to decide theguilt or innocence of theaccused.• However, attributing thatcharacteristic to theindividual members of thejury would be incorrect asthe jury is hung because theindividual members (or amajority) are very decisive –not indecisive.• So, indecisive at onelevel, decisive at another.
  • 19. • Both Hofstede and GLOBE explicitly warn against theecological fallacy (Hofstede, 2001;House, Hanges, Javidan, Dorfman & Gutpta, 2004, forinstance).• ―Hofstede‘s dimensions of national culture wereconstructed at the national level. They were underpinnedby variables that correlated across nations, not acrossindividuals or organizations. In fact, his dimensions aremeaningless as descriptors of individuals or aspredictors of individual differences because thevariables that define them do not correlatemeaningfully across individuals.‖Minkov &Hofstede, 2011: 12)(emphasis added).• House & Hanges (2004, p. 99) say that it isinappropriate to assume that ―cultural-levelcharacterizations and relationships apply to individualswithin those cultures‖
  • 20. • Gerhard & Fang (2005), and others, have demonstrated thatHofstede‘s depictions of national culture do not apply at theindividual level.• Recalculating Hofstede‘s data, they show that only a tinyfraction (approximately 2 to 4 per cent) of differences inindividuals‘ ‗values‘ is explained by national differences.• Hofstede himself acknowledges the low explanatory power atthe level of individuals noting that ―of the total variance … only4.2% is accounted for‖ by nationality (1980, p. 71; 2001, p.50).• Oyserman, Coon and Kemmelmeier‘s analysis of all cross-national empirical research studies published in English onindividualism and/or collectivism (the ‗dimension‘ of nationalculture which has received the most empirical attention) foundthat country explains only 1.2 per cent of the variance inindividual-level individualism scores, that is 98.8% of variancein individualism is unexplained by country (2002)
  • 21. • Whilst it is appropriate to acknowledge theseadmissions, both Hofstede and GLOBE, and not just manyof their followers, also apply their national level dimensionsto the level of individuals and other sub-national levels.• Earley points to Hofstede‘s and GLOBE‘s ―entangle[ment]‖ oflevels (2006, p. 923).• Brewer & Vanaik state that the ―confounding of the levels ofanalysis permeates through the Hofstede and GLOBE booksand publications on national culture dimensions …. both in thedefinitions of their dimensions and the discussion of theirfindings‖ (2012, p. 678).• I don‘t pursue this ‗not-walking-the-talk‘ here (see my paper).
  • 22. • Employment of the fallacy is not onlyillogical, but it also usually leads to false results.• As Robinson observes, whilst it is theoretically possible forecological and individual correlations to be equal, theconditions under which it can happen are far removed fromthose ordinarily encountered in data (1950, p. 341).• There is no way of predicting in advance the degree ofseverity of divergence.• Almost any theory will generate some correct results butanalysis which relies on the fallacy cannot demonstrate thevalidity even of correct results.• Relationships identified at one level may be true of a lowerlevel but alternatively they may be stronger or weaker at thelower level; they may not exist they may be different; or theymay even be in the reverse direction (Klein andKozlowski, 2000; Ostroff, 1993, for instance).
  • 23. • The ecological fallacy has been addressedquite extensively in studies of epidemiologyand electoral behaviour. It has not beenwidely considered in the management andbusiness literature.• And it appears to have largely been ignoredin popular research methods textbooks in thatarena (see Saunders et al., 2012, forinstance).
  • 24. • The error is extensive in practitioner literature, in trainingprogrammes, and in everyday stereotyping.• An example from practice is given by Breidenbach and Nyíri(2009, p. 262), who report that the Chairman of Daimler-Chrysler decided not to appoint a Japanese person as amanager of plant in India because he was convinced that―Shinto culture‖ and ―Hindu culture‖ ―do not go together‖. ABuddhist Japanese manager, with a US MBA, would, it wasassumed, be totally and irrevocably ‗programmed‘ by auniform Shinto culture and all Indians programmed with acommon Hindu one. A national notion of culture wassupposed to have programmed each individual within thepopulation. A mythical singularity - Hindu culture – wasassumed to be carried by all workers in the Indianfactory, who incidentally were mainly Muslims.• The Muslim population of India (16.4 million) is onlymarginally smaller than the Muslim population of Pakistan(18.6 million) (CIA, 2013).
  • 25. Untrue and Implausible• Generalising about lower levels within acountry on the basis of ecological datarelies on the fallacy and is thereforeillogical.• But it can also be demonstrated thatdownward determination of behaviour bynational culture is untrue and implausible.• That argument is now explored.
  • 26. • The empirical evidence against theoverdetermining notion of national cultureis of two types.1. The absence of evidence supportingdetermination2. The counter-evidence
  • 27. Absence of Evidence• There is zero empirical evidence in either Hofstede‘s or GLOBE‘squestionnaire based calculations that national culture (as values), orstatistical representations of those cultures, influences individuals‘behaviour (Gerhard & Fang, 2005).• GLOBE‘s descriptions of ―practices‖ are bizarrely not practices in thesense of action or artifacts but merely another depiction of values(Earley, 2006).• The possibility of identifying a national culture on the basis ofresponses to questionnaires is highly contested. But that debateaside, analysis of those responses no matter how statisticallysophisticated, not only does not, but cannot, demonstrate acausal link between a national culture (or its representation)and an individual’s behaviour because the data analysed doesnot include observations of such behaviour.• An a priori belief in that link must be imposed. It cannot be derivedfrom the data.
  • 28. Counter-Evidence• Secondly, there is a vast body of empiricaldata depicting considerable behaviouralvariation within countries (see, forexample, Camelo et al., 2004;Campbell, et al., 1991; Crouch, 2005;Goold and Cambell, 1987; Kondo, 1990;Law and Mol, 2002; Lenartowicz etal., 2003; O‘Sullivan, 2000; Streeck andThelen, 2005; Thompson and Phua, 2005;Tsurumi, 1988; Weiss and Delbecq, 1987;Yanagisako, 2002).
  • 29. That is not to say that there are nouniformities• Try driving on the left-hand side of the road in Germany orpublically drinking alcohol in Saudi Arabia, for example.• But that should not blind us to diversities within countries. Norare the uniformities evidence of the causal influence ofnational cultural values.• ―Social action has many ingredients.Laws, institutions, monarchs, the invisiblehand, rituals, coercion, social contracts are amongst theexplanations for uniform social practices. It is empiricallyincontestable that under certain conditions it is possible todetect common social action without reference to a unifiedand commonly accepted cultural system‖(McSweeney, 2009, p. 938).
  • 30. I now consider reasons why claims based on the ecologicalfallacy are implausible, including:1. Causal complexity2. Varieties of culture3. Varieties of psychological features4. Values are not invariant5. Relationship between values and behaviour is uncertain6. Cultural incoherence7. The opaque, slippery and elusive ontological status of‗culture‘8. Nations as ―imagined communities‘9. Individuals are not cultural ‗dopes‘
  • 31. 1. Causal Complexity• Social phenomena are complex not only becausethey are almost always the outcome of multipleinfluences but also because those influences cancombine in a variety of ways and at different times.• The combinatorial, often complexly combinatorial,nature of social causation makes identification ofcausation (or prediction) highly challenging andusually far beyond the capability of unilevelanalysis even when the latter is well executed.
  • 32. • Attributing ‗lower‘ level behaviour toexclusively national culture ignores themultiplicity of potential influences – othercultures active within a country and non-cultural factors.• There may be several microlevel independentvariables and several (not just one)ecological variables. These may be clearlyseparated, nested, overlapping, orintermingled. They may be influential atdifferent times, some continuously and othersintermittently.
  • 33. If causal influences other than, or additional to, a‘national culture’ exists there must be intra-country variation.Only making culture the causal force - not just a causalforce - can intra-country diversity be denied.Although a variety of within-country ‘sub’-culturesare often acknowledged in the psycho-nationalculture literature - they are not incorporated intothe explanation of action and thusacknowledgement is an empty gesture.
  • 34. Conflating Culture And Values• Even if causal complexity is ignored, theattribution of determinate power to cultureas values is problematic for the followingreasons:-
  • 35. Varieties of CultureFirst, one can distinguish between at least five differentconceptions (and locations) of culture:1. Psychological (incl. culture as subjective values)2. Mentalism (or cognition)3. Textualism4. Intersubjectivism5. PracticeIf we attribute causal influence to some or all of these, inaddition to culture as values, then some diversity at leastmust be the deduced.
  • 36. • Second, the values notion of nationalculture focuses on just a subset of thepsychological, that is values. The possibleroles of a host of other psychologicalconstructs(desires, goals, motives, needs, traits, aversions, tastes, interests, likes, attractions,dispositions, valences, attitudes, preferences, cathexes, sentiments, and so forth) areignored
  • 37. • Third, there are a great many definitions ofvalues, not just the singularity implied inthe national culture literature. As a resultan implicit or explicit definition iscontestable and ―definitional inconsistencyhas been epidemic in values theory andresearch‖ (Rohan, 2000, p. 255)
  • 38. • Fourth, the assumption that values areunaffected by context, that they areinvariant transituational preferences, is atodds with an immense amount of contraryevidence (Ewing, 1990; Shweder, 1999).
  • 39. • Fifth, a strong and direct influence of values onbehaviour is treated as a given. Values are takenas cultural imperatives that lead to distinct action.But this is at best a highly contested view (Joas,2000; Rohan, 2000; Swidler, 1986).• ―Current theories give little guidance forunderstanding how values shape behavior‖ (Hitlin& Piliavin, 2004, p. 360).• That is not to say that values may not have aninfluence on behaviour, but what we know aboutthe highly mediated relationship is limited andvalues are but one type of a host of possibledeterminants (Williams, 1979).
  • 40. The assumption of coherence• Sixth, the assumption of causal primacy ofculture (values or whatever) is logicallynecessary, but not sufficient, to imply uniformityof social action.• The culture must also be assumed to becoherent: that is, that it contains nocontradictory elements so that it is impossible toconstruct incompatible, ambivalent, orcontradictory propositions within that culture.
  • 41. The assumption of coherence• ‗Look before you leap‘ vs. ‗he who hesitates is lost‘• Clifford Geertz, in harmony with what has become theaccepted view in anthropology, dismissed thecoherence view of culture which he ridiculed as a―seamless superorganic unity within whose collectiveembrace the individual simply disappears into a cloudof mystic harmony‖ (1965).• Cultural coherence allows no room for individuals toexploit – it is a theory of cultural automatons/dopes.―Click, whirr, act‖ Cialdini, (2001). We are social butnot entirely socialized (Wrong, 1961) and it excludesthe possibility of endogenous change (Archer, 1988).
  • 42. Cultural impurityWinslow Homer‘s Eight Bells held outto be an example of distinctly Americanart. But …Cross-Atlantic influences can readilybe discerned.Tempura, regarded as an example ofunique Japanese cuisine. But …A cooking method copied fromPortuguese missionaries in Japan.
  • 43. What has causal force?• Seventh, in the national culture literatureemploying the ecological fallacy, theontological status of culture is opaque,slippery, and elusive. Poorly specifiedconceptions slide unclearly and inconsistentlybetween each other (Knight, 1982; Taras, etal., 2010).• Is national culture a statistical average?Something real? Or what?
  • 44. • The attribution of constitutive power to a statisticalaverage, distribution, or whatever relies on two errors.• The first is the metaphysical fallacy of ‗misplacedconcreteness‘ (Whitehead, 1925) erroneously viewingsummary statistics as hard realities,• The second related error is ―statistical fatalism‖(Hacking, 1990) attributing deterministic power to a statisticalcalculation.• The idea that statistical distributions are ‗laws‘ was briefly veryfashionable in 1870s. It was mocked by Charles Dickens inHard Times (1854)(Hacking, 1983, 1990). Some averagesmay have predictive power (Friedman, 1953) – but that is adifferent type of claim. Averages are not causes. We do notmeet, compete, negotiate or form friendships with averages(Bidney, 1944; Duncan, 1980).
  • 45. • The notion of national culture as real is similar to whatHegel, for instance, called Geist (an essential andimmutable objective spirit). As White (1968) puts it: ―Ifthe behavior of a people is determined by itsculture, what determines the culture? The answer isthat it determines itself. Culture may be regarded as aprocess sui generis‖ (in Duncan, 1980, p.185).• There are similarities between this doctrinalholism, the depiction of culture as a superorganic factstanding above individuals, responding to laws of itsown, and the historic biological notion of ‗vitalism‘which treated life as the product of a mysterious visvitalis or life force.
  • 46. Try this test• When some event – positive or negative – is attributed to‗culture‘, or when the basis of improvement is said be a‗change of culture‘, replace ‗culture‘ with a made-up word, forexample, ‗bagabanga‘.• Is your understanding any the less? What is lumped togetheras culture – national or other - needs to be unbundled.• As Adam Kuper observes: ―unless we separate out thevarious processes that are lumped together under theheading of culture, and then look beyond the field of culture toother processes, we will not get very far in understanding anyof it‖ (1999, p. 247).
  • 47. • The objection here to the notion of a distinct and enduringcausal national culture is an objection to the attribution ofontological status and autonomous and regulatory power to asupra-individual abstraction (Bourdieu, 1977; Murdock, 1972;Radcliffe-Brown, 1940).• It is individuals who act. The notion of culture as a macro oremergent social force might however seem to be supportedby the apparent evidence of collective or aggregateeffects, for example, by the apparent effects of ‗financialmarkets‘ on interest rates on government borrowing. But‗markets‘ are composed of the opinions, actions, orwhatever, of individuals – they are not real in the sense ofhaving autonomous social force.
  • 48. • Contrary to a ―core nationalist doctrine‖(Smith, 1983, p. 21) that humanity is naturallydivided into nations, no country is trulyprimordial - most are of quite recent originfounded in the nineteenth or twentiethcenturies.• But nations are ―mental constructs sustainedin being by imaginative labour and discursivehabit‖ (Cubitt, 1998, p.3). Through whatAnnette Ching calls the ―social construction ofprimordiality‖ (in Yelvington 1991, p. 165).
  • 49. • State boundaries may be unstable. Poland, for instance, as anation-state ceased to exist in the late eighteenth century and wasonly reconstituted with quite different borders at the Treaty ofVersailles in 1919 when the borders of many other Europeancountries were radically altered. After World War II, the borders ofPoland and many other countries were again changed.• Land and people formerly in one state may be re-designated aspart of another state. For example, Alsace-Lorraine was returned toFrance most recently in 1945 (having yo-yoed back and forth over theprevious century).• Whole states or parts of states may be annexed (or re-claimed)as the north of Cyprus was by Turkey.• New states may be formed by seceding from other states (e.g.Bangladesh). States may be formed by the voluntary or involuntarycombination of multiple states (for instance, Germany in the latenineteenth century and again in the late twentieth century).• States may fragment into multiple states, violently (forexample, the break-up of Pakistan into [West] Pakistan andBangladesh) or peacefully (for example, the separation ofCzechoslovakia into the Czech Republic and Slovakia). Writing aboutthe determination of national boundaries at the Versailles PeaceConference in 1919, Arthur Balfour, the UK‘s Foreign Secretaryangrily observed the spectacle of ―all powerful, all ignorant men sittingthere and partitioning continents‖
  • 50. • Ninth, Of course, each individual is not an‗island‘. Individual choice requires theemployment of a somehow socially sharedframework or rather frameworks(Hodgson, 2007).• But ‗share‘ is a very imprecise notion. Towhat extent is it shared?
  • 51. • Even if the exclusive causal force is assumed tobe culture, nationally unique and commonbehaviour can only be deduced if the degree ofsharedness is assumed to be total. The fallacyfollowers make that assumption. Nationalbehaviour patterns are seen as having beeninternalized by individuals. Thus, Hofstede,Hofstede & Minkov refer to culture as the ―mentalprogramming‖ (2010, p.4) – culture as the centralprocessing mechanism common to each nationalcitizens‘ mind.• This is what Wrong (1961) rejects as an―oversocialized‖ notion of individuals. The potentialfor individual agency is effectively denied byreducing a person to what Garfinkel critically callsa passive ―cultural dope‖ (1967, p. 66) –dependent and impotent.
  • 52. More than the standard fallacy• Treating national culture as causal of behaviourwithin countries makes claims even beyond that inthe standard ―ecological fallacy‖ of supposingconceptual and/or empirical equivalence betweenhierarchial levels.• Where determinism of national culture issupposed, the ―misuse‖ (Brewer & Venaik, 2012)may more fittingly be called the ecological mono-deterministic fallacy. I have described andchallenged a series illogical arguments and invalidsuppositions on which that fallacy relies.
  • 53. • What is to be done? In short, the mainpolicy implication of the arguments here is:don‘t suppose that descriptions of nationalcultures are a multilevel ‗answeringmachine‘.